Political Political Science: A Phronetic Approach
By
Sanford F. Schram
Bryn Mawr College
Bent Flyvbjerg
Oxford University
Todd Landman
University of Essex
Full reference: Schram, Sanford F., Bent Flyvbjerg, and Todd Landman, 2013, "Political
Political Science: A Phronetic Approach," New Political Science, vol. 35, no. 3, pp. 359372, DOI:10.1080/07393148.2013.813687, URL: http://bit.ly/15A0kEL.
Abstract: For over fifty years, successive waves of critique have underscored that the
apolitical character of much of Political Science research betrays the founding mission of
the discipline to have science serve democracy. The Caucus for a New Political Science
was originally based on such a critique, and the Perestroika movement in the discipline
included a call for more problem-driven as opposed to theory- or method-driven work
that would better connect Political Science research to ongoing political struggles. In
recent years, movements for a public Sociology and public Anthropology as well as
dissonant movements in Economics and related fields have added to the insistence that
social science research was too often disconnected from the real world. Phronetic Social
Science has emerged out of the ferment for change in the social sciences, starting with the
much-debated book by Bent Flyvbjerg, Making Social Science Matter (Cambridge 2001).
Flyvbjerg critiqued the social sciences for mimicking the natural sciences while
proposing an alternative approach that focuses research on helping people address the
problems they are facing in the context they are facing them. Today, Phronetic Social
Science goes beyond the call for an alternative approach to social inquiry and its growing
adherents are providing evidence that this alternative approach to doing research can
enrich the social sciences by more effectively connecting research to efforts to address
real world problems as people experience them. This essay provides a genealogy of
efforts to connect Political Science to politics, a review of the major critiques of
mainstream research, an explication of the rationale for more problem-driven, mixed
methods research, a specification of the key principles of the phronetic approach, and
examples of its application in the public realm. The essay concludes with implications for
realizing a more political Political Science by way of taking a phronetic approach.
1
Political Science research has remained a contested terrain from its first beginnings with
the formation of the discipline in the late 19th Century, the subsequent development as
Political Science as a distinct profession, and right down to this very day. As a result, the
quest for a unitary paradigm for structuring research about politics has remained
unfulfilled.1 But the battle lines are being redrawn as we speak.
In recent decades, the issue of how to best conduct research in Political Science
has been shadowed by a debate between positivists who champion emulating the natural
sciences and interpretivists who side with approaching the study of politics along the
lines of more humanistic forms of inquiry. Competing positivist and interpretivist
epistemologies have spawned distinctive methodologies with separate logics of inquiry,
varying preferences for different methods of data collection, and debates about a number
of other issues including, most commonly, the value of quantitative versus qualitative
data. Most recently, debates between positivists and interpretivists have been complicated
by interventions by others who do not situate their investigations in either camp. This
group has included a growing number of scholars who refuse to accept that they must
limit their research to either a positivist or interpretivist methodology. Mixed-methods
researchers have been joined by others who stress the importance of problem-driven over
theory-driven research. These researchers want to focus on problems in the real world of
politics and then use whatever many different methods of study and forms of data
collection necessary to study those topics as best they can. The debates about Political
1
On the idea of a unitary paradigm for Political Science, see David D. Laitin,
“Disciplining Political Science,” American Political Science Review 89, 2 (June 1995),
pp. 454-456.
2
Science research ultimately raise issues about the relationship of Political Science to
politics.
This essay examines the major points of contention about Political Science
research today by focusing on what some are calling a “practical turn” as manifested in
the development of “phronetic social science” originating in Bent Flyvbjerg’s critique of
a social science that mimics the methods of the natural sciences.2 The phronetic social
science, as practiced by a growing number of researchers, features a problem-driven
approach that mixes methods to address issues of power involved in specific public
problems people are struggling to address.3 In what follows, we demonstrate how the
phronetic approach provides a way of addressing effectively the enduring issue of the
discipline's relationship to the issues of power in politics.
Researching the Discipline/Disciplining Research
Beginning with its origins in the late 19th Century, the American incarnation of Political
Science as an academic discipline has always been a work in progress, dedicated to the
idea of progress. That chiasmus points to the hope the discipline’s early leaders had that
Political Science could develop as the scientific study of politics that would redound to
2
See Bent Flyvbjerg, Making Social Science Matter: Why Social Inquiry Fails and How
it Can Succeed Again (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2001). Also see Sanford
F. Schram and Brian Caterino, eds., Making Political Science Matter: Debating
Knowledge, Research and Method (New York: New York University Press, 2006).
3
Bent Flyvbjerg, Todd Landman, and Sanford Schram, eds., Real Social Science: Applied
Phronesis (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2012).
3
the improvement of American democracy and vise versa.4 The push for
professionalization that came with the initiation of the American Political Science
Association (APSA) in the first years of the 20th Century represented an attempt to
transform the discipline to more explicitly and successfully address the relationship of
science to democracy. John Gunnell has written:
Between the institution of the APSA and the appearance of the first
issue of the American Political Science Review, Max Weber published his
1904 essay on “The ‘Objectivity’ of Knowledge in Social Science and
Social Policy” in the newly created Archiv für Sozialwissenschaft und
Sozialpolitik, which he shared in editing. There is little to suggest any
direct relationship between Weber’s essay and the ideas of American
political scientists, but in both theme and context there were a distinct
family resemblance and mediated intellectual connections. Weber’s
argument was in part a response to the failure of the Verein [für
Sozialpolitik] and the ideological and methodological disputes that had
characterized its history. Although he presented his essay as an
intervention in controversies about the nature of social scientific
explanation, he also explicitly addressed it to a wider public audience with
the aim of vouchsafing the cognitive authority of academic social science.
He stressed the commitment of the journal was to the scientific pursuit of
the “the facts of social life,” but it was also concerned with “social policy”
4
See John G. Gunnell, “The Founding of the American Political Science Association:
Discipline, Profession, Political Theory, and Politics,” American Political Science Review
100, 4 (November 2006), pp. 479-486.
4
and “the training of judgment in respect of practical problems arising from
these social circumstances.”…Weber…emphasized various ways in which
social scientific knowledge could, in principle, constrain and direct policy
decisions as well as the extent to which scientific investigation necessarily
proceeded from the perspective of value-laden premises. The authority of
social science nevertheless depended, he argued, on acceptance of the
autonomy of empirical claims and on the professional status and
independence of those who made such claims. The dilemma and solution
Weber articulated bore remarkable similarities to the situation attending
the founding of the APSA.5
Frank Goodnow, W. W. Willoughby, Woodrow Wilson, and others formed the
APSA based on concerns consistent with Weber's thinking about the connections
between science and politics. Goodnow was an especially poignant participant due to his
prior involvement in both politics and academic administration, much like Wilson, but
also because he helped educate leaders of the next generation who sought to develop a
science of politics for the betterment of democracy, including most prominently Charles
Merriam.
With time, a number of exemplars of the attempt to fuse science and democracy
to their mutual benefit appear in the histories of the profession. Prominent among them
was Merriam’s colleague at Chicago Harold Lasswell who would eventually turn to
5
Gunnell, “The Founding of the American Political Science Association,” pp. 480-481.
5
attempting to forge what he called a “policy science.”6 Perhaps because the promise of
these efforts has seemed forever deferred, periodic challenges to the idea that a science of
politics could serve democracy have occurred throughout the discipline’s history.7
Yet, it was in the 1960s with the rise of what came to be called behavioralism that
the push for a scientific Political Science reached its zenith. At this time, explicit
discussion of methodology, as in an underlying logic of inquiry, overtook debates about
the value of specific methods, as in particular forms of empirical observation and data
collection. The behavioral movement very much sought to deliver on the longstanding
promise that Political Science could become a scientific discipline if research in the field
were conducted by emulating the natural sciences. Yet, in spite of desire to emulate the
natural sciences, proponents of behavioralism (like Robert Dahl, David Easton, Heinz
Eulau, and David Truman to name just a few of the most prominent behavioralists of the
time) turned not to natural science but to the philosophy of science for models of how to
conduct scientific research on politics.8
The philosophy of science provided an explanation of the logical structure of
scientific explanation known variously as logical positivism or logical empiricism and is
6
See James Farr, Jacob S. Hacker, and Nicole Kazee, “The Policy Scientist of
Democracy: The Discipline of Harold D. Lasswell,” American Political Science Review
100, 4 (November 2006), pp. 579-588.
7
See Bernard Crick, The American Science of Politics: Its Origins and Conditions
(London: Routledge & Keegan Paul, 1959); David M. Ricci, The Tragedy of Political
Science: Politics, Scholarship, and Democracy (New Haven: Yale University Press,
1984); and John G. Gunnell, Imagining the American Polity: Political Science and the
Discourse of Democracy (University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 2004).
8
John G. Gunnell, Philosophy, Science, and Political Inquiry (Morristown: General
Learning Press, 1975), pp. 11-28.
6
now commonly referred to as just plain “positivism.” Positivism served to create a
methodological foundation for Political Science as a science. Political scientists would be
doing science if they structured their research projects consistent with the positivistic
methodology. In other words, regardless of the specific methods of empirical observation
or data collection used, research needed to be framed to support explanations consistent
with the tenets of positivism. Research needed to produce the basis for testing causal
theories that could explain why political phenomena, relationships and processes were the
way they were.9 Various inductive and deductive approaches to empirical research in
Political Science eventually led to more a generalized understanding of how research was
organized to contribute to the scientific discipline of Political Science. We can specify a
consolidated model of this generic understanding to include the following hierarchy of
assumptions:
(1) Political Science exists to help promote understanding of the truth about
politics;
(2) Political Science research contributes to this quest by adding to the
accumulation of an expanding base of objective knowledge about politics;
(3) growth of this knowledge base is contingent upon the building of theory that
offers explanations of politics;
(4) building of theory is dependent on the development of universal
generalizations regarding the behavior of political actors;
(5) development of a growing body of generalizations occurs by testing
falsifiable, causal hypotheses that demonstrate their success in making predictions;
9
Carl G. Hempel, Philosophy of Natural Science (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall,
Inc., 1966).
7
(6) accumulation of a growing body of predictions about political behavior comes
from the study of variables in samples involving large numbers of cases; and
(7) a growing body of objective, causal knowledge can be put in service of
society, particularly by influencing public policy makers and the stewards of the state.
Critics from the time of behavioralism and since have been quick to note that this
paradigm excludes much valuable research. For instance, it assumes that the study of a
single case is “unscientific,” provides no basis for generalizing, does not build theory,
cannot contribute to the growth of political knowledge, and, as a result, is not even to be
considered for publication in the leading journals and is to be discouraged as a legitimate
doctoral dissertation project.10 This bias against case studies is quite surprising given the
very powerful essay in defense of case studies published by Harry Eckstein in 1975 in the
Handbook of Political Science, which to this day is one of the best essays on the value of
case studies to theory development.11 While there have always been dissenters to the drift
toward “large-n” quantitative research in service of objective, decontextualized and
universally generalizable truth about politics, there is a good case to be made that the
dissenters were for a long time increasingly been marginalized as the center of gravity of
10
For instance, one of the authors of this article was recently told that Comparative
Political Studies still to this day has a policy of not accepting case studies.
11
Harry Eckstein, ‘Case Study and Theory in Political Science’ in Fred I. Greenstein and
Nelson S. Polsby, eds., Handbook of Political Science, Volume 7, Strategies of Inquiry
(Reading, MA: Addison Wesley, 1975), pp. 79-137; and Bent Flyvbjerg, “Five
Misunderstandings about Case-Study Research,” Qualitative Inquiry, 12, 2 (April 2006),
pp. 219-245.
8
the discipline drifted more and more towards reflecting these core assumptions about
political knowledge.12
Nonetheless, dissent against this scientistic drift was there throughout. Even in the
1960s, criticisms could be heard of the failure to address the political turmoil overtaking
the U.S. at the time. Charles McCoy, as a founder member of the Caucus for a New
Political Science, was particularly eloquent in his critique of what he called the apolitical
politics of the push to make Political Science more scientific.13 The Caucus led the way
to a thorough-going debate about the failure of mainstream Political Science to speak to
the major political issues of the time: civil rights, poverty, the War in Vietnam, etc.14
By the turn of the 21st Century, the challenge came from the Perestroika
movement, which included arguments that the preoccupation with becoming a science
has led the discipline away from improving politics.15 Rogers Smith and Ian Shapiro led
the call to move away from method-driven research toward problem-driven research that
is framed around addressing fundamental political concerns in the real world of politics.16
12
The second-coming for positivism in Political Science was marked by the publication
of Gary King, Robert O. Keohane, and Sidney Verba’s Designing Social Inquiry:
Scientific Inference in Qualitative Research (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1994)
which argues for how qualitative research can be made to be consistent with the positivist
paradigm that tends more often to lead to large-n quantitative studies.
13
Charles A. McCoy and John Playford, Apolitical Politics: A Critique of Behavioralism
(New York: Thomas Y. Crowell, 1967).
14
Clyde W. Barrow, “The Intellectual Origins of New Political Science,” New Political
Science, 30, 2 (2008), pp. 215-244.
15
See Kristen Renwick Monroe, ed., Perestroika! The Raucous Rebellion in Political
Science (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2005).
16
Rogers M. Smith, “Should We Make Political Science More of a Science or More
about Politics?” PS: Political Science and Politics 35 (2002): 199-201; and Ian Shapiro,
9
For Smith and Shapiro, it was less important whether Political Science research is
grounded in one or another distinct methodology underwritten by a particular philosophy
of science and more important that it be premised first and foremost on addressing real
problems in the world of politics.
The Perestroika movement gained sustenance from allied movements in related
fields that served to underscore that the ongoing ferment within Political Science was
associated with broadly shared concerns about the social sciences which transcended
disciplinary boundaries. In recent years, movements for a public Sociology and public
Anthropology as well as dissonant movements in Economics and related fields have
added to the insistence that social science research was too often at risk of not helping
people address the public problems they confronted.17
It is important to note that as part of its problem-driven focus, the Perestroika
challenge also included a call for methodological pluralism.18 In fact, at times, this
dimension of the movement seemed to override the interest in problem driven work. Yet,
they are very much related. The call for methodological pluralism has often been couched
in terms of ending the supposed hegemony of positivistic approaches to the exclusion of
interpretive research, particularly in the leading journals, out of concern that positivistic
The Flight from Reality in the Human Sciences (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
2005).
17
For Sociology see Michael Burawoy, “2004 Presidential Address: For Public
Sociology,” American Sociological Review, 70 (February 2005): 4-28; and for
Economics, see the post-Autistic Economics journal Real-World Economics Review,
http://www.paecon.net/.
18
See Sanford F. Schram, “Return to Politics: Perestroika and Postparadigmatic Political
Science,” Political Theory 31 (December 2003), pp. 831-851.
10
research was disconnected from the lived experience and concerns of the people being
studied. Further, there was concern that positivistic approaches strove for an
advancement of scientific techniques in service of perfecting causal models, independent
of whether such research actually helped people address public problems. One response
was to encourage more problem-driven, mixed methods studies that allowed for
alternative methodologies that could better connect research to the people being studied
and to better help address their concerns.
John Dryzek however has encouraged a modification of the call for
methodological pluralism, arguing against an “empty pluralism” that allows for a
thoughtless “anything goes” attitude.19 Instead, Dryzek calls for a “critical pluralism” that
would involve critical engagement of competing research traditions so that they can
better learn from each other.20 Keith Topper has seconded that critique by emphasizing
the need for a critical pluralism that combines research methodologies to create a more
robust knowledge of politics.21 Topper joins Dryzek in pushing for a critical pluralism
within research projects so that the interpretive moments in all analyses can inform
positivistic ones and vise versa.
A critical pluralism highlights the important role of political judgment in the
selection of methods as well as the selection of topics. Political reflexive research is
sensitive to how all methods are not politically neutral and vary as to their relevance in
19
On oft cited example of the ‘anything goes’ approach to the philosophy of science is
found in Paul Feyerabend, Against Method (London: Verso Press, 1993).
20
John S. Dryzek, “A Pox on Perestroika, A Hex on Hegemony: Toward a Critical
Political Science,” In Kristen Renwick Monroe, ed., Perestroika! The Raucous Rebellion
in Political Science (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2005), pp. 509-525.
21
Keith Topper, The Disorder of Political Inquiry (Cambridge: Harvard University Press,
2005).
11
promoting insight into political problems. Not all research is equally good, not all
research methods are equally politically relevant and not all research conducted via
different methods will enable us to effectively pursue a problem-driven type of political
research that can help people address the major issues of politics. An empty pluralism
would allow all methods to be included just for the sake of inclusion. An empty pluralism
would encourage the study of all topics irrespective of whether they addressed
fundamental political problems. An empty pluralism would blindly study whatever
people in the public realm insisted was important whether they were right or not. The fact
of the matter is that a critical pluralism would recognize the importance of making and
defending political judgments about what should be studied and how.
That said, while Political Science research has as yet to achieve a critical
pluralism, it is now arguably increasingly post-paradigmatic in the sense of not being
confined to one perspective about what research ought to be like. The discipline is
moving away from the idea that research should be according to one overarching
philosophy of science, overall methodology or distinctive logic of inquiry. In fact, the
changing currents associated with Political Science research indicate that perhaps the
field was always best seen as non-paradigmatic both in terms of what it ideally should be
in theory as well as what it actually was in practice. It is perhaps only now with
Minerva’s Owl that we can look back to see the value of the diversity that was present in
Political Science research throughout its history.
Against Methodological Purity and for Methodological Pluralism
12
The current debate about methodological pluralism has been a long time coming, arriving
at the end of an arduous journey across the methodological minefields that have served as
the ground for Political Science research. The pressures for a unitary paradigm have been
a real and persistent temptation. There are understandable reasons to insist on
methodological purity as opposed to methodological pluralism. Political Science is an
academic discipline; and like all academic disciplines, it is organized to promote
scholarship according to the highest standards of what counts as good research. The
temptation to discipline research is therefore implicit in the very idea of organizing an
academic discipline. Gatekeeping to keep out bad research and include only good
research is an unavoidable corollary.
While the methodological purity of the positivist paradigm could be countered
with a call for a methodological pluralism, instead the most common response until most
recently has been to push for a more “interpretive” approach to the study of politics. The
interpretive approach is really a loose collection of many different approaches including
such disparate approaches as political ethnography, constructivism, discourse analysis,
thick description, narrative analysis and many others. What these approaches share in
common is an emphasis on the interpretive dimensions of political analysis, stressing the
importance of accounting for how political phenomena, relationships and processes are
not so much pre-existing objective facts of the social world as they are subjectively
experienced and interpreted phenomena.22 This distinction revisits the debates that
preoccupied Weber and his colleagues over whether social science ought to be more
22
See Dvora Yanow and Peregrine Schwartz-Shea, ed., Interpretation and Method:
Empirical Research Methods and the Interpretive Turn (Armonk: M.E. Sharpe, 2006).
13
about erklaren (explanation) or verstehen (understanding).23 The interpretive approaches
emphasize it is more important to try to arrive at understanding how the social world is
subjectively experienced and interpreted by people than it is to provide an explanation of
what caused social phenomena to happen. Most interpretive approaches therefore do not
look to the natural sciences for a model of how to conduct research on politics because
they see an asymmetry between social sciences and the natural sciences stemming from
what Anthony Giddens and others have called the double hermeneutic.24 From this
perspective, the natural sciences are interpretive in that natural science research is framed
through interpretive lenses for constructing the facts that are observed whether they are
quarks within atoms or the black holes in the cosmology; however, the social sciences are
doubly hermeneutic in that research on social phenomena involves interpreting the
interpretations social actors make of their experiences. Social science research is doubly
hermeneutic because it involves researchers’ interpretations of other people’s
interpretations.
The “interpretive turn,” as it came to be called in the social sciences, had many
sources, including, perhaps, most prominently Clifford Geertz and his leadership in the
School of Social Science at the Institute for Advanced Study in Princeton, New Jersey.25
Geertz, to be sure, saw interpretive approaches as providing important perspectives for
understanding whatever was being studied and famously argued that thick description
23
G. H. Von Wright, Explanation and Understanding (London: Routledge, 1971).
24
Anthony Giddens, New Rules of Sociological Method: A Positive Critique of
Interpretative Sociologies (London: Hutchinson, 1976).
25
See Joan W. Scott and Debra Keates, ed., Schools of Thought: Twenty-Five Years of
Interpretive Social Science (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2001).
14
comprised “piled up inferences and implication.”26 Yet, Geertz resisted the idea that
researchers had to choose either an interpretive or positivist approach as a distinct logic
of inquiry.27 Nonetheless, over time, the main thrust of the interpretive turn has been to
insist that interpretive social science implied a distinct logic of inquiry that prevented
mixing methodologies.28
Positivism and interpretivism became the oil and water of Political Science
research. While researchers might be able to mix different methods of data collection,
they increasingly were discouraged from mixing the methodologies on the grounds that
positivism and interpretivism implied distinct logics of inquiry that could not be sensibly
combined in the same analysis. Over time, the separate logic of inquiry argument has
undoubtedly contributed to the idea that Political Science is a fractured discipline where
different researchers employing different approaches talk less and less to each other.29
Yet, in recent years, the longstanding impasse between positivism and
interpretivism has begun to come undone by researchers who pursue more problemdriven, mixed methods research. Mixed methods research in particular has attracted a
26
Clifford Geertz, “Thick Description: Toward an Interpretative Theory of Culture,” in
The Interpretation of Cultures (New York: Basic Books, 1977).
27
Clifford Geertz, Available Light: Anthropological Reflections on Philosophical Topics
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2000).
28
Edward Schatz, “Methods are not Tools: Ethnography and the Limits of MultipleMethods Research,” Working Paper, Committee on Concepts and Methods, International
Studies Association, January 2007:
http://www.conceptsmethods.org/working_papers/20070123_26_PM%2012%20Schatz.p
df.
29
See Gabriel A. Almond, “Separate Tables: Schools and Sects in Political Science,” PS:
Political Science and Politics 21, 4 (Autumn, 1988), pp. 828-842.
15
growing number of proponents in Political Science as well as other social sciences. There
are books and whole journals dedicated to promoting the idea of mixing methods in the
name of engaging in problem-driven research.30 The idea of mixed-methods research
itself can be contained within either the positivist or interpretivist paradigm, and one can
find different versions of it in different instances in the social sciences. Yet, the ferment
associated with mixed methods research has come to Political Science with its more
critical versions crossing disciplinary boundaries and ending up appearing even in the
pages of the American Political Science Review (which for years has been roundly
criticized for featuring positivistic research focused on perfecting method at the expense
of connecting to ongoing politics).31
Further evidence of movement in this direction comes from debates in major
Political Science journals. In a recent series of articles in Perspectives on Politics,32 but
30
For books on mixed-methods research, see Abbas Tashakkori and Charles B. Teddlie,
Mixed Methodology: Combining Qualitative and Quantitative Approaches (Thousand
Oaks: Sage Publications, 1998).
31
For one example of problem-driven research that employs both interpretive and
positivistic approaches, see Joe Soss and Sanford F. Schram, “A Public Transformed:
Welfare Reform as Policy Feedback,” American Political Science Review 101, 1
(February 2006), pp. 111-127.
32
For essays in a symposium that debate the value of pursuing mixed-methods, problemdriven research on comparative and international politics, see Rudra Sil and Peter J.
Katzenstein, “Analytic Eclecticism in the Study of World Politics: Reconfiguring
Problems and Mechanisms across Research Traditions,” Perspectives on Politics 8, 2
(June 2010), pp. 411-431; Thomas C. Walker, “The Perils of Paradigm Mentalities:
Revisiting Kuhn, Lakatos, and Popper,” Perspectives on Politics 8, 2 (June 2010), pp.
433-451; and Andrew Rehfeld, “Offensive Political Theory,” Perspectives on Politics 8,
2 (June 2010), pp. 465-86.
16
also, other journals, including the Journal of Social Policy,33 commentators have engaged
in debates that suggest a growing interest in getting beyond the positivist/interpretivist
divide in ways that include pursuing mixed-methods, problem-driven inquiry. In fact, a
number of scholars have for some time self-consciously and explicitly designed their
work as mixed-methods research that is focused in real political problems.34 Recovering
the insights of Geertz, Howard Becker and other leaders of the interpretive turn of the last
generation, Soss has joined with others in conducting work that takes a problem-driven
approach and mixes methodologies in research projects that strive to studying specific
topics as fully and thoroughly as possible so as to better inform public deliberation on
pressing social issues.35
Nonetheless, even though problem-driven, mixed-methods research is a growing
trend in Political Science and related fields, such research comprises still the minority of
projects and is even less represented in journal articles. Given the format and space
constraints of most academic journals, the tendency is to present findings associated with
33
For articles in a symposium that debates the value of mixed-methods, problem-driven
research as it relates to the study of social policy, see Paul Spicker, “Generalisation and
Phronesis: Rethinking the Methodology of Social Policy,” Journal of Social Policy 40, 1
(January 2011), pp. 1-19; Stephen McKay, “Response 1: Scientific Method in Social
Policy Research Is Not a Lost Cause,” Journal of Social Policy 40, 1 (January 2011), pp.
21-29; and Tony Fitzpatrick , “Response 2: Social Science as Phronesis? The Potential
Contradictions of a Phronetic Social Policy,” Journal of Social Policy 40, 1 (January
2011), pp. 31-39.
34
For example, see Joe Soss, “Lessons of Welfare: Policy Design, Political Learning, and
Political Action,” The American Political Science Review 93, 2 (June 1999), pp. 363-380.
35
The sociologist Howard Becker’s contributions to the interpretive turn rivaled Geertz’s
in importance for the social sciences. And like Geertz, he resisted the separate logics of
inquiry insistence that followed his path-breaking work. See Howard S. Becker, “The
Epistemology of Qualitative Research,” in Richard Jessor, Anne Colby, and Richard
Schweder, eds., Essays on Ethnography and Human Development (Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 1996), pp. 53-71.
17
one particular data collection effort even if it was part of a mixed-methods project. These
constraints may need to change if problem-driven, mixed-methods research reflective of
the phronetic approach is to get a full hearing. The possibilities that come with electronic
publishing of journals over the internet may well help in this regard.
Were the conditions to be made right, the possibilities increase for problem-driven
mixed methods research to flourish not just across Political Science research efforts but
within specific political science research projects. These would be projects that resist the
Manichean debates between positivists and interpretivists that pose the false choice of the
separate logics of inquiry. These would be projects that often find their frame as
primarily what Shapiro has called problem-driven research where a researcher starts with
a specific problem in the world of politics and then employs multiple approaches to study
it as best he or she can.36 Further, these are not simply mixed-methods, problem-driven
projects but instead are mixed-methods, problem-driven investigations that explicitly
practice a critical pluralism, specifically by seeking to gain an analytical advantage that
comes from highlighting the interpretive moments in their positivistic analyses and vise
versa. This, then, is more than triangulating findings by collecting several different types
of data about a particular topic. In joining Dryzek’s call for critical pluralism in research,
Topper provides the philosophical orientation for such Political Science research.37 His
argument can be summarized without too much violence as highlighting the analytical
power that comes with constructing a critical pluralism within specific Political Science
research investigations.
36
Shapiro, The Flight from Reality in the Human Sciences.
37
Topper, The Disorder of Political Inquiry.
18
The power of such combined approaches needs to be assessed by researchers on
both sides of the positivistic and interpretive divide. Should the claims made for a critical
pluralism within political science research hold up when evaluated by political
researchers of various stripes, we might start to see our way beyond some of the most
fractious and debilitating divisions that afflict the discipline. Then, mixed-methods,
problem-driven research might be able to better deliver on the founding promise of the
field to connect science and democracy, leading to the improvement of both, not just in
theory but in practice as well.
Phronetic Political Science is Political Political Science
The turn to problem-driven and mixed methods approaches is matched by another
turn. In recent years, debates over choosing between positivism and interpretivism are
being overtaken by a “practical turn” that is agnostic on methods if they are employed or
even combined in service of better connecting research to ongoing political struggle.38 As
with any movement, sometimes the agenda can be pushed too far, suggesting that all
research should have immediate practical relevance, eschew the use of abstract theories
that are not immediately digestible by public policy makers, or should be in service of the
state.39 Yet, many political scientists of various stripes, from empirical researchers to
theorists, have warmed to the idea that more efforts in the discipline should try to connect
38
Flora Cornish, “Social Science as Practical Wisdom: Here Come the Examples,” LSE
Review of Books, http://blogs.lse.ac.uk/lsereviewofbooks/2012/09/06/real-social-scienceapplied-phronesis-bent-flyvbjerg/.
39
See Robert Gallucci, “We Have to Talk: The Urgency of Dialogue Between
International Relations Scholarship and Policy” (Presentation at Bryn Mawr College,
September 20, 2012).
19
to ongoing political struggle.40 Moreover, at least in the context of the United Kingdom,
government assessment of political science research output now includes significant
attention (20%) to the ‘impact’ of research on practice, which in our terms creates new
incentives for problem-based research of the kind we advocate here.
Out of all the ferment, Bent Flyvbjerg’s call “phronetic social science” has led a
charge in the practical turn. Phronetic social science promotes mixed-methods problemdriven, contextualized studies that relate to specific issues political communities are
struggling to address.41 Flyvbjerg anticipated the two main complaints that the
Perestroika movement made about Political Science in his original critique of the social
sciences more generally: (1) mainstream research too often mistakenly sought to apply
the methods of the natural sciences to the study of social phenomena; and (2) as a result,
research too often was disconnected from helping people address the problems they were
confronting. Without the labels, Flyvbjerg called for problem-driven, mixed methods
research that offered contextually specific understanding of social problems in ways that
helped the people being studied better to address their problems.
By drawing on the Aristotelian categorization of types of knowledge, he called his
approach “phronetic social science.” For Aristotle, episteme was universal knowledge,
techné was essentially practical application of that knowledge in the form a technique and
phronesis was the practical wisdom that emerged from having an intimate familiarity of
40
For general arguments in favor of greater engagement by theorists, see Jason Frank and
John Tambornino, eds., Vocations of Political Theory (Minneapolis: University of
Minnesota Press, 2000).
41
Flyvbjerg, Making Social Science Matter, pp. 166-68.
20
what would work in particular settings and circumstances.42 For Flyvbjerg, while the
natural sciences studied a subject matter of the physical world that was amenable to
universal models of causal laws and such, the social sciences could not produce such
knowledge of the social world given its subject matter, i.e., people whose subjective
states of consciousness and shared understandings were not amenable to being modeled
by transcontextual, universal causal models. Instead, the social sciences were better
adapted to provide contextually specific knowledge that could help people address the
major problems they confront in their lives. Social science could conduct research that
would enhance phronesis, the practical wisdom born of an intimate familiarity with a
practice that could help people act effectively in particular situations. Flora Cornish
notes:
Phronesis can be understood as part of a “turn to practice” in the social
sciences. After the “linguistic” and “cultural” turns gave center-stage to symbols
and meanings in human affairs, attention to practice is one way of returning
materiality to social theory. Phronetic social researchers engage in detail in the
complexities of the phenomena which they study, examining why things are the
way they are, often uncovering undesirable workings of power, and asking how
things could be improved. In so doing, they develop both practical wisdom and
theoretical tools that provide lenses for problematizing and reconstructing
42
Aristotle, The Nicomachean Ethics, translated by J.A.K. Thomson, revised with notes
and appendices by Hugh Tredennick, introduction and bibliography by Jonathan Barnes
(Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1976).
21
practices in other settings. They explicitly do not strive to create general or
universal theories of human behavior.43
Flyvbjerg has argued that there is nothing new in linking political science with
phronesis.44 Aristotle explicitly did this more than two thousand years ago in his original
definition of phronesis, in the Nicomachean Ethics, which today is still foundational in
studies of phronesis. Aristotle here emphasized that “Political science and prudence
[phronesis] are the same state of mind” and that Political Science must deal both with
general legislation and particular circumstances and must be practical and deliberative.
“Prudence [phronesis] concerning the state [the object of political science, for Aristotle]
has two aspects: one, which is controlling and directive, is legislative science; the other . .
. deals with particular circumstances . . . [and] is practical and deliberative.”45
Two things are worth noting here. First is Aristotle’s assertion that political
science, as a consequence of the emphasis on the particular, on context, and on
experience, cannot be practiced as episteme. To be a knowledgeable researcher in an
epistemic sense is not enough when it comes to political science because “although
[people] develop ability in geometry and mathematics and become wise in such matters,
they are not thought to develop prudence [phronesis],” according to Aristotle.46 A wellfunctioning Political Science based on phronesis is imperative for a well-functioning
43
Cornish, “Social Science as Practical Wisdom: Here Come the Examples.”
44
Flyvbjerg, Making Political Science Matter, p. 59.
45
Aristotle, The Nicomachean Ethics, 1141b8–b27.
46
Aristotle, The Nicomachean Ethics, 1142a12–29.
22
society, says Aristotle, inasmuch as “it is impossible to secure one’s own good
independently of . . . political science.”47 Second, we may benefit from paying close
attention to Aristotle's emphasizes in his concept of phronetic political science of both the
collective (the state) and the particular, of control and circumstance, of directives and
deliberation, of sovereign power and individual power.
Since the time of Aristotle, an unfortunate division has developed in political
philosophy of two separate traditions, each representing one of the two sides stressed by
Aristotle. One tradition, the dominant one, has developed from Plato via Hobbes and
Kant to Habermas and other rationalist thinkers, emphasizing the first of the two sides.
The other, Aristotelian in origin, has developed via Machiavelli to Nietzsche, and to
Foucault in some interpretations.48 Today, the two traditions tend to live separate lives,
apart from occasional attacks from thinkers within one tradition on thinkers within the
other, the critique by Habermas of Foucault and Derrida, and vice versa, being cases in
point. However, Aristotle wisely insisted that what is interesting, for understanding and
for praxis, is what happens where the two now largely separate intellectual traditions
intersect--where particular circumstance and context meet general rules of governance
and conduct--and that this point of intersection is the locus of appropriate phronetic
activity.
Flyvbjerg’s call for a phronetic social science rejoins these competing
philosophical traditions, laying the basis for a more politically engaged approach to
research focused on the role of power in addressing specific public issues. In recent years,
47
48
Aristotle, The Nicomachean Ethics, 1141b27–1142a12.
Flyvbjerg, Making Political Science Matter, pp. 110-12.
23
his work has been joined by growing numbers of researchers who want to connect their
work to people’s efforts to address public problems and make change in the political
arena.49 There is now a growing interest in following Flyvbjerg by pursuing problemdriven, mixed-method research in the social sciences today. It is not difficult to see how
research into the politics of healthcare, climate change, airport expansions, human rights,
transitional justice, urban planning, poverty alleviation, conflict and other topics would
benefit from application of the phronetic approach. The knowledge community around
these and other significant issues is replete with the ‘unconsciously competent’ expertise
that ought to be part of the scholarly endeavour. Well-designed problem-driven research
that is informed by this knowledge community fortified with systematic research analysis
challenge many of the dominant understandings, framings, and hegemonic discourses of
these issues as well as the relations of power that sustain them.
The phronetic approach focuses specifically on the role of power in public
problem solving. Indeed, in our book Real Social Science, we identified a remarkable set
of common ‘tension points’ across eight case studies that form the core of the book.
Whether analyzing Native American people in Canada, women re-entering the workforce
in New York, or the New Labour government in the UK pursuing a policy of “sustainable
aviation,” the idea of “tension points” emerged as a critical theme across the case studies.
Such tension points consist of “power relations that are particularly susceptible to
problematization and thus change, because they are fraught with dubious practices,
contestable knowledge and potential conflict.”50 In fact, the identification and
49
See Flyvbjerg, Landman, and Schram, eds., Real Social Science.
50
Flyvbjerg, Landman, and Schram, Real Social Science, p. 288; emphasis added.
24
investigation of these tension points across whatever area of policy, can bring about
significant change, as these points are analogous to the tiny exploitable fissures in a rock
face that when hit often enough with a hammer can bring down a mountainside. For us,
tension points are “the fault lines phronetic researchers seek out.”51 In other words, the
tension points phronetic research identifies go to the heart of political analysis. Indeed,
our own research on megaprojects (Flyvbjerg), human rights (Landman), and poverty and
race (Schram) use social scientific analysis to challenge power relations and bring about
positive social change by focusing on tension points. In this way, we are engaged in
value-based, problem-driven research that in many ways sidesteps the whole problem of
positivism versus interpretivism.
Challenging power relations by doing phronetic political science focused on
tension points can be a conflictual and, in some instances, adversarial process. This is
particularly the case as scholars insert their research into the breaches they are studying in
order to affect change. People who stand to win from the change may applaud the
research, but people who stand to lose are likely to oppose it. Tension points "bite back,"
as observed in Real Social Science. If nobody cares about your research, positively or
negatively, perhaps it is time to reconsider its relevance. For some researchers, and
perhaps especially early-career scholars and graduate students, the level of public
attention and conflict that may ensue when tension points bite back can possibly be
intimidating.
Ultimately, what is the alternative? Do we really want the next generation of
political scientists to become conventional academics, concerned mainly about academic
51
Flyvbjerg, Landman, and Schram, Real Social Science, p. 290.
25
impact, that is, journal citations, instead of public, practical impact on policy and
politics? We suggest not. To make a difference to the communities and societies in which
we live and work, we need to be concerned about both types of impact, and the two are
equally important. From its founding as a social science discipline to now, Political
science has been first and foremost about political practice; its efforts to understand
politics have always focused on helping improve political practice and the expectation
has been that the empirical research political scientists engage in ought to as well. Today,
there is ferment in Political Science pushing past methodological debates, encouraging a
mixing of methods in order to better connect political science research to political
practice. Phronetic social science can contribute to this ferment. It provides a thoughtful
approach to better connect political science research to ongoing political struggle. Like
phronetic researchers in other fields, phronetic political scientists do not hide in the ivory
tower of academia; they have the courage and skills to enter into the fray of public debate
and policy with their research. They know that knowledge is power and that they have a
civic duty to use this power – and use it wisely, that is, phronetically – in the service of
the communities in which they live.