Pi ct ure s of th e B od y
L o gi c an d Af f ect
James Elkins
Revised January 2021
Preface, Introduction
2
This book is dedicated to Barbara Stafford.
Preface, Introduction
3
Table of Contents
Preface
Introduction
PART ONE • AFFECT
CHAPTER 1 Membranes
CHAPTER 2 Psychomachia
CHAPTER 3 Cut flesh
PART TWO • LOGIC
CHAPTER 4 By Looking Alone
CHAPTER 5 Analogic Seeing
CHAPTER 6 Dry Schemata
Preface, Introduction
4
Preface: On the History of this Subject
In the last half century, beginning more or less in the mid-1980s, there has been a
renascence of writing on the depicted body. Loosely following phenomenological
accounts by Jean–Paul Sartre and Maurice Merleau-Ponty, and taking up threads from
Robert Vischer’s theory of empathy and Jacques Lacan’s descriptions of the web of vision,
writers have woven a more reflective understanding of what happens when a viewer
encounters a represented body.1 The pictured body is no longer imagined as an immobile
shape on paper or canvas—as a modernist problem in form or volume, or an opportunity
for divine or historical narrative—but as a counterpart and figure for the observer. As my
body moves, or as I think of moving, the body I behold also shifts, and as I look, I see
myself being seen, and I return the represented gaze. My thoughts are entangled in what I
imagine as the depicted figure’s thoughts, and my image of myself is mingled with the
way I respond to the pictured body. Because the body intromits thought, important
aspects of my responses to a picture of a body may not even be cognized: I may feel taller
looking at an attenuated figure, or be thrown into a frustrated mood upon seeing a figure
that is twisted or cramped. My own identity shifts subtly, and sometimes drastically, as I
contemplate a represented body. The nature of my thought, my very capacity to form
judgments, is in question: as Elaine Scarry emphasized in 1985, the act of beholding a
1 The relevant texts are Sartre, Being and Nothingness, translated by Hazel E. Barnes
(New York: Washington Square Press, 1966); Merleau–Ponty, The Visible and the
Invisible, translated by Alphonso Lingis (Evanston: Northwestern University Press,
1968), and Merleau–Ponty, Phenomenology of Perception, translated by Colin Smith
(London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1962); Lacan, The Four Fundamental Concepts of
Psycho–Analysis, translated by Alan Sheridan (New York: W. W. Norton, 1964), 91–
104; and Robert Vischer, Das optische Formgefühl (1872), in Drei Schriften zum
ästhetischen Formproblem (Halle, 1927), and Empathy, Form, and Space: Problems in
German Aesthetics 1873–1893, translated by Harry Francis Mallgrave and Eleftherios
Ikonomu (Santa Monica, CA: Getty Center for the History of Art and Humanities, 1994).
For Sartre see also Hubert L. Dreyfus and Piotr Hoffman, “Sartre’s Changed Conception
of Consciousness: From Lucidity to Opacity,” The Philosophy of Jean–Paul Sartre,
edited by Paul Arthur Schilpp. The Library of Living Philosophers, vol. 16. (La Salle, Ill:
Open Court, 1981), 233 ff.
Preface, Introduction
5
body affects my ability to form propositions and to use language, and depending on the
physical or ideological force of the image I see, my capacity to situate myself in relation to
the image may be eroded.2 It was also in the 1980s that Mark Johnson suggested that
thinking about the body is also thinking by means of the body, because the very structure
of propositional logic follows in part from the experience of the body.3
At the same time, the represented body is taken as a sign of the real: it denotes
identity, ethnicity, sexuality, and gender, and it invites the viewer to consider their own
identity in relation to the body that is depicted, and to think of both their identity and the
represented body in relation to the imagined or represented body of the artist. That
entanglement of projected identities reaches through the work to the world, and back
again.
A large number of disciplines and methods have been converging on these ideas:
at the least there is art history, feminism, gender studies, queer theory, varieties of
psychoanalysis, phenomenology, studies of popular culture, histories of science and
medicine, anthropology, contemporary scientific imaging, advertising, and contemporary
art from performance to video games.
Given this historically recent awareness it is worth bearing in mind that questions
of embodied seeing were not an innovation of the late twentieth century, and that
corporeal responses to pictures of the body go back to the origins of Western art
criticism. Philostratus’s Imagines, written around 220 A.C.E., is a ready example. It
presents itself as the record of a lecture tour of the paintings in a house outside Naples. As
Scarry, The Body in Pain (New York: Oxford University Press, 1985), 279. Scarry
makes her comments in reference to “concussive experiences” of pain and torture, but as
I will argue, her observations have force in regard to many bodily representations.
3
See Johnson, The Body in the Mind: The Bodily Basis of Meaning, Imagination and
Reason (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987), whose account I will not be
following here because it is too general—and too rational—to be of much help in
accounting for pictures. Johnson does not cite Spinoza or the Stoics, and his book also
has unacknowledged affinities with existentialism; see Alphonso Lingis, Libido, The
French Existentialist Theories (Bloomington, Indiana: Indiana University Press, 1985),
50–51. For Spinoza see Gilles Deleuze, Spinoza, Practical Philosophy, translated by
Robert Hurley (San Francisco: City Lights, 1988). See also Drew Leder, The Absent Body
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990); Jane Gallop, Thinking Through the Body
(New York, 1988); Naomi Goldenberg, Returning Words to Flesh: Feminism, Psycho–
analysis, and the Resurrection of the Body (Boston, 1992); and George Lakoff, Women,
Fire, and Dangerous Things: What Categories Reveal about the Mind (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1987).
2
Preface, Introduction
6
Philostratus describes each painting for the benefit of his admirers, he addresses himself
to a ten–year–old boy, the son of his host. Stopping in front of a painting depicting the
death of Menoeceus outside the walls of Thebes, Philostratus
praises the wonderful way the painter has shown Menoeceus
pulling the sword from his body. Philostratus would have been
standing to one side of the painting, with the boy next to him
and the spectators ringed around. “Let us catch the blood, my
boy,” Philostratus says, “holding it under a fold of our
garments; for it is flowing out, and the soul is already about to
take its leave, and in a moment you will hear its gibbering cry.”4
To Philostratus, the Menoeceus is a painting that speaks, that
bleeds, that is about to give up a soul. I imagine Philostratus
making a gesture, as if to receive the blood, and if his rhetoric
was strong enough his audience would have felt the boundary between painting and
public begin to weaken.5
Strains of this kind of bodily response echo throughout the history of art and art
criticism, and so does interest in what we now call constructions of gender.
(Philostratus’s choice of a ten–year–old boy is not chance, and it has its effect on his
monologue as well.) Yet it could be argued that the contemporary mixture of ideas has
produced a new configuration of problems. The sometimes narcissistic “infatuation with
different modes of body consciousness” has coalesced into a field of extraordinary
conceptual complexity, and on some occasions the new amalgam of interests has almost
become a discipline in its own right.6
Philostratus, Imagines, translated by Arthur Fairbanks (Cambridge: Harvard University
Press, 1960), I.4, p. 19.
5
This awareness of the corporeal link between actual and painted body has been
intermittent in Western history and criticism. In most illustrated versions of Philostratus,
more conventional alignments of beholder and beheld forbid the possibility of blood
flowing beyond the frame, and the blood spurts into a pool, or drips down Menoeceus’s
body—in which case he becomes a figure for Christ. See for example Philostratus, Les
Images, translated by Blaise de Vigenère (Paris, 1614), reprinted in the series The
Renaissance and the Gods, edited by Stephen Orgel (New York: Garland, 1976), 24.
6
The quotation is from Jean Starobinski, “A Short History of Bodily Sensation,”
translated by Sarah Matthews, in Fragments for a History of the Human Body, edited by
Michel Feher, 3 vols. (Cambridge, Mass.: Zone Books, MIT Press, 1989), vol. 2, 369.
4
Preface, Introduction
7
If the conceptual groundwork for the study of represented bodies goes back to
phenomenology and pschoanalysis in the first half of the 20th century, and if the first
conceptualizations of the feld date to the mid-1980s, then the field was consolidated into
a recognizable academic subject in the late 1980s and early 1990s. For its first
retrospective collection, the journal October created a heading for “The Body” alongside
more conventional topics. Rosalind Krauss, Leo
Steinberg, Georges Didi-Huberman, and Michael
Fried were among the writers who theorized and
practiced the new concerns.7 At the end of the
1980s, a three-volume collection of essays on the
body edited by Michel Feher, Fragments for a
History of the Human Body, demonstrated this
near-absolute lack of order. Feher’s contributors
represent many disciplines and deploy
incommensurate interpretive methods (Feher
himself favored a Plotinian approach), and they
make use of contradictory notions of such key
terms as body and representation.8 The resulting
disarray proclaimed the impossibility of a unified
sense of bodily representations, as if to say that
the body cannot be directly addressed because it is both more and less than a philosophic
or physical object. The exhilaration of the better essays in Fragments for a History of the
Human Body came in part from their newness: there was a certain joy in contemplating
Krauss’s book The Optical Unconscious (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1993) can be
read as an account of somatic involvements in the crucial moments of modernism. For
Michael Fried see especially Courbet’s Realism (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1990). Steinberg’s engagement with questions of the body is especially eloquent not in
the book on Christ’s sexuality, which has a specific interpretive purpose, but in the
meditations on Picasso’s Les Demoiselles d’Avignon; see the reprint, “The Philosophical
Brothel,” October 44 (1988), 8–74, with a preface on somatic criticism by Krauss. For
Didi–Huberman see first Devant l’image: question posée aux fins d’une histoire de l’art
(Paris: Minuit, 1990).
8
Fragments for a History of the Human Body, op. cit. Feher suggests that the genealogy
of the “ethical and aesthetic conceptions of the psychosomatic link” that I have been
adumbrating in this Preface are to be found in Plotinus. See Eric Alliez and Michel Feher,
“Reflections of a Soul,” ibid., vol. 2, 46–84.
7
Preface, Introduction
8
Tibetan medical manuals, African images of the afterlife, or medieval notions of the
wandering womb.
It may be that as the represented body has become a subject art historians talk
about alongside the other subjects of the discipline, it has also become less coherent as a
concept: it has turned into an amorphous repository for whatever escapes current
methods and systems. That which is unassimilable, vague, without category or quality, is
now diverted into the realm of the somatic. The rise of affect theory from c. 2000 to the
present has contributed to the idea that bodily sensations and experiences are outside of
rational representation. Performative gender and identity have themselves become the
subject matter of art, overwhelming other sources of meaning. In all these ways the
represented body has become the one place in art where no fixed order is possible. It takes
on the interconceptual function of the region where, as Freud said, the demands of the
body become ideas in the mind: the very spot where flesh becomes intelligible, where
mute drives become signs. It appears that the represented body exists in a contaminated
zone between the two, so it cannot properly be in full possession of its meaning. That, at
least, is my understanding of the literature that has been produced on the subject of
pictured bodies and viewer’s bodily reactions. Writers are drawn to the subject in part as
the remaining refuge of deep affect—embodied perception, uncognized somatic
reactions— unbridgeable interdisciplinarity, and inexpressible subjectivity in a discipline
that can seem constricted by the harsh demands of philosophic methodologies.
One purpose of this book is to resist that dispersion of ideas. I am interested in the
conditions of representation of bodies in general—the ways bodies have been given
pictorial form, and their varying relations to viewers—and I believe it is possible to find
some order in the welter of images. This book is an aerial view of the subject, an attempt
to gather works, terms, and theories, and to give some clarity to a field that is nearly
incoherent. My grounding thesis is that pictured bodies are expressive in two largely
opposite modes: some act principally on the beholder’s body, forcing thoughts about
sensation, affect, pain, and ultimately death; and others act more on the beholder’s mind,
conjuring thoughts of painless projection, transformation, and metamorphosis. I propose
this framework as a way of bringing provisional order to a literature that grows less
coherent with each passing year.
Another thesis of this book runs counter to the opposition of what I will call
“affect” and “logic,” undercutting it at every point: and that is the conviction—and
perhaps, the structural necessity—that the depicted body must be intractable, that it must
Preface, Introduction
9
escape all categories, all systems, all imposed orders, all systematic logic. I hope the
general accounts of depicted bodies that I develop in these pages might find uses in the
production, history, theory, and criticism of bodily images of all kinds—even while the
particular explanations labor and finally break under the pressure of the conviction that
the body is the most powerfully unsystematic object that we can know. The sense that I
am wrong, and that the body is unencompassably strange and irretrievably unruly, will be
a constant accompaniment to my ordered exposition: it could not be otherwise.
This is an incarnation of the book Pictures of the Body: Pain and Metamorphosis
(Stanford University Press, 1999). It was a latecomer to the academic conversations about
represented bodies, and it had a different origin: it developed from classes I taught to art
students at the School of the Art Institute in Chicago. The idea was to show how
contemporary art practice has deep roots in medical literature, and to give artists a
resource for thinking about metaphors and leading concepts in current art that addresses
the body. But the book I ended up writing had only a few references to contemporary art,
and so it never quite found its public. It was read, instead, by historians of science, and to
them it must have often seemed disconnected from their own current interests.
This is the third rewriting of that book. A “second edition” is posted on
academia.edu. This version is an attempt to remake those earlier incarnations into
something more like what they should have been: a conceptual analysis of late twentiethand early twenty-first century visual art about the body.
Underlined words are for the class at the School of the Art Institute. (Underlined
words may appear on quizzes.)
Grey text boxes are assignments for the class.
Preface, Introduction
10
Preface, Introduction
11
I n t r od u c t i o n
But how it abuses our senses and their “dictionary,”
this pain that turns their pages!
—Rilke’s last words9
Every picture is a picture of the body.
Every work of visual art is a representation of the body.
To say this is to say that we see bodies, even where there are none, and that the
creation of a form is to some degree also the creation of a body. And if a splash of paint or
a ruled grid can be a picture of the body—or the denial of a body—then there must be a
desire at work, perhaps among the most primal desires of all: we prefer to have bodies in
front of us, or in our hands, and if we cannot have them, we continue to see them, as after
images or ghosts. This is a beautiful and complicated subject, the way our eyes continue
to look out at the most diverse kinds of things and bring back echoes of bodies.10
According to the Stoic philosophy as it is given voice by Lucretius and Epicurus,
we see objects because they shed “films” or “membranes” (membranae) that come
floating continuously toward us through the ether.11 The skins are not abstract markers of
a body’s limits, as in Leon Battista Alberti’s Renaissance perspective, with its geometric
9
Modified from B. Conrad, Famous Last Words (New York, 1961), 171.
Portions of this book are distilled in chapter 4 of The Object Stares Back: On The
Nature of Seeing (New York: Harcourt Brace, 1997). The approach there is less
historically specific, and more geared to the phenomenology of sight in general. I think
that bodies are both the primary objects of seeing, and the principal conditions for the
possibility of seeing; The Object Stares Back puts those possibilities to work in a general
account of vision and blindness.
11
Lucretius Carus, De rerum natura IV.28–96.
10
Preface, Introduction
12
forms defined by centric rays and polygonal outlines (circumscriptiones).12 They are not
the theoretical apparatus of some geometry, or the equations of modern physiological
optics. They are the echoes, the ripples, of bodies, and they carry the sense of body
toward us together with the details of form.
Writing in the 1st c. B.C.E., Lucretius says he is
thinking of “something like skin,” and he
compares the membranes to the “brittle summer
jackets” of cicadas, the cauls or allantoides
shaken off by newborn calves, and the shed
skins of snakes.13 As Diskin Clay puts it, in
Lucretius’s imagination the atmosphere is “fluid
with films or cauls.”14
Lucretius is concerned that clouds,
unlike all other mundane objects, are not solid
enough to be able to shed those skins, and that
point of difficulty in his theory shows his need
to begin from bodies, and not just objects. A
cloud can be rounded and discrete like a body,
but it lacks two primordial attributes of bodies,
firmness and skin. So Lucretius puzzled over clouds, which are visible and yet impalpable.
The theory of vision that he shares with Epicurus reveals itself as a theory of bodies by the
way it pauses over the idea of a body that is also weightless. Vision, in its deepest source
and impetus—in its somatic origin (Quelle) and its rooted force (Drang), as Freud might
12
Circonscrizione in the Italian; see Alberti, Della pittura e della statua (Milan: Classici
Italiani, 1804), 45.
13
Lucretius, The Way Things Are, The De Rerum Natura of Titus Lucretius Carus,
translated by Rolfe Humphries (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1968), 120.
Humphries also renders “films,” as do the editors of Lucretius, De rerum natura, edited
by William Ellery Leonard and Stanley Barney Smith (Madson: University of Wisconsin
Press, 1942), 526 n. 31. See further Karl Konrad Friedrich Wilhelm Lachmann, In T.
Lucretii Cari De Rerum Natura libros commentarius (New York:Garland, 1979
[originally Berlin, 1855]), and note effugias for effigies, p. 215 n. 42. For a general
introduction to the passage see John Masson, Lucretius, Epicurean and Poet (New York:
E. P. Dutton, 1907), chapter 11.
14
Clay, Lucretius and Epicurus (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1983), 119.
Preface, Introduction
13
have said—may be the determined search for bodies.15 If I choose Greek and Roman Stoic
philosophy as an antecedent for this idea instead of the 20th c. phenomenology of
Merleau–Ponty, it is because Merleau–Ponty puts things in terms of “flesh” and “carnal
being”: he is concerned with the identity of the body as a whole, while I am interested in
its parts and particularities, and above all its appearance as a body, with a shape as well as
a feel.16 Visual existence, in the account I will be developing, has to do with the apparition
of specific bodies—skins in the shape of objects, or bodies, or parts. Epicurus is more
exacting about the body than Merleau–Ponty (he is more aware of pain, and the body’s
insistent complaints), and Lucretius is more precise than either. A picture of a body can
never be anything other than specific: it cannot stand for touching, or fleshly existence, or
identity, or any other general term of experience, unless it does so in its specific skin.
15
Freud, Instincts and their Vicissitudes, in Standard Edition, edited by James Strachey
(London: Hogarth Press, 1962), vol. 14, 122–23. See further Jean Laplanche and J.-B.
Pontalis, The Language of Psycho-analysis, translated by Donald Nicholson-Smith
(London: Hogarth Press, 1973). In a talk at the Johns Hopkins University (April 1994),
Laplanche emphasized that his book is not intended as a dictionary, but as a way of
raising questions about the Freudian corpus.
16
Martin C. Dillon, “Merleau–Ponty and the Reversibility Thesis,” in Merleau–Ponty,
Critical Essays ([ ]), 86, quoting Merleau–Ponty, The Visible and the Invisible, op. cit.,
136; Eliot Deutsch, “The Concept of the Body,” in Phenomenology East and West,
Essays in Honor of J. N. Mohanty, edited by Frank Kirkland and D. P. Chattopadhyaya
(Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1993).
Preface, Introduction
Here is a particular body, or part of one: a portrait of the Japanese philosopher
Isaku Yanaihara, by Alberto Giacometti.17 It is part of the record of an obsession
Giacometti had with this particular face and body—he painted Yanaihara over fifteen
times, and paid for his airfare from Tokyo to Paris in the summers of 1957, 1959, 1960,
and 1961—and because of that obsession, it is an exemplary portrait. It is labored,
14
Preface, Introduction
15
anxious, and uneasy: a half–gray halo rises up to the middle of the picture, marking the
place where Yanaihara’s figure was once painted; but then he shrank, compressed by the
intensity of Giacometti’s gaze, to the puny location where Giacometti left him. The little
Yanaihara is a house of cards—a stack of black and white streaks, washed in pale white,
and topped by a smudged brown nose that almost succeeds in looking solid. The
painting’s surface is shiny and gently undulating, like the wood of a cult statue that has
been caressed until it is smooth. Manifestly, the painting is a failure. Giacometti
abandoned it, as he abandoned the other fourteen paintings in the series and the many
drawings that he made at the same time. Nothing went wrong, exactly—but the body’s
force failed to impress itself on the canvas, and what the canvas found could not hold the
body.
Something about this picture—and I mean to say by extension, all portraits—
makes me pause, throws me into a state of intensified, unsatisfied looking. Part of what I
want from any face is a speaking, moving response, and I can’t get it from a face that is
painted. But is that enough to account for my restlessness? In another sense, perhaps
more fundamental or prior to the demand for a living face, I want a face to behave as a
face: to be complete, to be unified and distinct from what is around it, to be there before
me without any uncertainty, to be clear enough to interpret, to keep some sensible
distance from my own face. Yanaihara’s face fails on each of those counts. Despite
Giacometti’s compulsion about distance and size (he insisted Yanaihara place his chair on
red spots marked on the floor, and he moved his canvas up and down in small increments
using pieces of clay), the face is neither near nor far, high nor low.18 The looming soft
halo is the memory of a larger or closer Yanaihara, and the delicate armature of lines
encloses echoes of smaller or more distant Yanaiharas. The figure emerges from its white
background, and then melts back into it. There is no firm surface, no hard skull, no
17
See Thomas Minner, “Portraits of a Relationship: Alberto Giacometti and Isaku
Yanaihara,” MA Thesis, School of the Art Institute of Chicago, 1990, unpublished.
Among published sources see Isaku Yanaihara, “Pages de journal,” Derriere le miroir
127 (May 1961): 18–25, and James Lord, Giacometti, A Biography (New York: Farrar
Strauss Giroux, 1985). Yanaihara’s name is pronounced with the accent on the antepenultimate syllable.
18
Yanaihara, “Pages,” op. cit., 21. Compare the parallel studies of bodies and space in
Helmut Oehlers, Figur und Raum in den Werken von Max Ernst, René Magritte, Salvador
Dalí und Paul Delvaux zwischen 1925 und 1938. Europäische Hochschulschriften, Reihe
XXVIII, Kunstgeschichte, vol. 54. (Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang, 1986).
Preface, Introduction
16
resistance. Even the brown nose, the most firmly finished passage, is spongy and damp.
And the painting is fascinating because of those failures: I want it to be whole and
articulated, I want it to occupy a reasonable place in its setting—and what are those
demands, if not desires I have in regard to all depicted bodies, and finally to all form?
Isn’t there a deep resonance between the desire for a tangible head and the desire for clear
shapes of any kind? I would like to say that we prize distinctness and clarity, in objects as
well as in philosophy, ultimately because we need distinct and clear bodies and faces.
Looking at Yanaihara, I want a sureness about his form that I know the painting
does not want to give, and Giacometti is successful to the extent that his work persuades
me to give up that desire, and entrances me with uncertainties. It is not a pleasant kind of
seeing, but a demanding and imbalanced experience, a kind of vertigo. The skull
contracts into an uncertain flat grayish envelope of space. It shrinks—it continues to
shrink as I look, like an afterimage slipping from my field of vision—and it trembles, like
a tree flushed by a breeze. What problems, however provisional, are solved here? What
impasse has been reached here that is not reached, or that is avoided, in some other more
conventional portrait? We know from Yanaihara’s journal that an intense emotional
drama ran alongside the demanding all–day posing sessions: Yanaihara had an affair with
Giacometti’s wife beginning the first year that he posed. We know, too, that the artist and
his model talked continuously during the posing, and then again afterwards in cafés,
about existentialism and phenomenology, about the identity of the Other and the
unsettling slight difference between one male and another, between a Westerner and a
Japanese. But finally, even if the biographical details cannot find their places in the
portrait itself, even if we can’t find a way to understand them as signs, say, of the
disruption of the face, the portrait continues its incessant self–destruction. And it is that
motion, the unremitting denial of the security of the body, that accounts for the
queasiness, the trace of nausea, that the portrait elicits. I would read it as compelling
evidence of a basic need for the face and the body.
Assignment 1: portraiture. Either talk about your own work, or show another
artist’s work, to explore these themes of instability.
Preface, Introduction
17
First and second seeing
When there is a body to be
seen, we may focus on it with a
particular relaxed concentration, a
determined sinuous insistent gaze
we reserve for bodies and faces.
When the body in question is as
fugitive as Yanaihara’s, we may
sense that peaceful seeing on
account of its relative absence: I
am anxious when I try to see
Yanaihara because I know and
need the peace and the pleasure
that can come from seeing a body.
Let me call this first seeing,
denoting the way we may look
when there is a body to be seen, or
part of one. In everyday
conversation, first seeing is
relaxed, or even languorous: my
eyes rest in the eyes of the person I
see, and my gaze slides and caresses their skin as it moves from place to place. Even if the
face I see is frightening or repulsive—like some I considered in another book, The Object
Stares Back—there is a certain repose in my way of looking.19 (In that book, I used these
examples from a Polish book on cosmetics, where interrupted lines show the motions that
are to be used in applying makeup: I thought that those lines also suggest the ways we
look at faces, in repetitive, smooth, lingering, sometimes caressing, motions of our eyes.)
19
The Object Stares Back, op. cit., 186-93, 210-15.
Preface, Introduction
18
A face, and perhaps especially a
naked body, is a place of rest and
meaning in a setting that
commonly also contains boredom
and meaninglessness. Everything—
from chairs to light switches,
landscapes to asphalt—is partly
empty and dissatisfying in contrast
to the repletion I feel when I see a
body. Even if I am embarrassed or
tense or if I am compelled to look
against my will, I can still sense the
relaxation, the correctness of my
gaze when it falls on a body. The
Portrait of Yanaihara is on the far
edge of that experience, because it
refuses to congeal into a firm
continuous face, and because like
all pictures it cannot move or reveal
its true distance, shape, or size.
Even so, the anxious irregular
shifting in my gaze is not enough to annul the conviction that this is a face, and therefore
my way of looking is fundamentally satisfied and reposeful.
The world is full of scenes and patterns that contain no bodies. This is the more
complicated, and more common, occurrence of second seeing: a restless, nomadic way of
looking that begins when I fail to find bodies or body parts.20 Even the most narcotic
20
First and second seeing have affinities with the psychoanalytic concept of anaclisis, the
misplaced desire for the pleasure associated with an original instinct of self–preservation;
but there is an important difference, because in the anaclitic model desire seeks
something that is irretrievably lost (i.e., the original scenario, in which the instinct for
self–preservation created the first pleasure), whereas in this model the sight of the body
must be considered as the aim (in the Freudian sense) of the desire. See Jean Laplanche,
Life and Death in Psychoanalysis, translated by Jeffrey Mehlman (Baltimore: The Johns
Preface, Introduction
19
objects—a deep twilight, the sight of a freshly made bed, a well–designed garden—
provoke something of this more restless seeing. I do not mean that my eyes must flit from
place to place, or that second seeing needs to have any determinate physical symptom.
But I think that whatever is not a body inaugurates a restive intermittent search for bodily
forms or metaphors. If I am alone in a garden, I will look around, meaning I will look at
things in turn, at nothing in particular, at one thing after another. My eyes may be restive
in both senses of that word: unruly, or else static and fixated. If a person or an animal (a
non–human body) strays into my field of vision, I will immediately fix on it, by an
unconscious reflex that cannot be denied.
In the absence of bodies, I think we embark on a search for body metaphors—for
bodily lengths, weights, colors, textures, shapes, and movements—and in that second
search we tend to be easily satisfied, and content with the most obvious choices. A
psychoanalyst tells a story about a little boy and his father, out for a walk in the woods.
The boy squats down, shits, and notices that his excrement stands up “straight on end in
the underbrush.” He is evidently amused and
satisfied, and he proclaims, “Look, I made the
Chrysler building.” The analyst wonders whether
“such a joke uttered by a naïve child provides any
hint as to what may be meant when a man in
soberer and politer years dreams of making a tall
building.”21 I have no argument with this line of
reasoning, and I am not sure that we usually do
much better with our metaphors. This is the sense
in which upright buildings can be said to resemble
upright people, or erections, or arms or noses or
fingers. These rudimentary metaphorics do not
usually occupy the conscious mind, but they are more than just reflexes: they are
conditions for the comprehension of the world in general. Within second seeing, the
Hopkins University Press, 1976). “Nomadic” is intended as an echo of Gilles Deleuze’s
concept; see for example Deleuze, “Nomad Thought,” in The New Nietzsche:
Contemporary Styles of Interpretation, edited by David Allison (New York: Dell, 1977),
142-49.
21
L. Kubie, “Body Symbolization and the Development of Language,” Psychoanalytic
Quarterly 3 (1934): 433.
Preface, Introduction
20
moments when we locate body metaphors are secondary moments of rest, but they can
never be entirely satisfying. Body metaphors are evanescent in our consciousness, and
they dissolve under the slightest pressure of thought. That is why efforts to list them, such
as Elaine Scarry’s list of the “bodily sources of culture,” are unsatisfying: they are true, but
also too well articulated.22 The Chrysler building isn’t really much like a pile of shit,
because it has a metallic surface and geometric arcs—but then when I seek to understand
those arcs, they seem to require more body metaphors. They might recall, or (to put it
more gently, since these phenomena are scarcely conscious) gain some of their meaning
from the sweep of a forearm, or the arc of an iris. The metallic sheathing is like a perfect
skin, and so on. Even to mention these kinds of metaphors is to think far too coarsely and
literally about what it is to see a form like the Chrysler building, but they are normative
examples of the continuous and swift search for body metaphors that constitutes the
more mobile second seeing.
Second seeing animates and directs everyday sight, and it is made explicit in
painting. To D. H. Lawrence, Cézanne “terribly wanted to paint the real existence of the
body,” and Meyer Schapiro has said as much by observing the figural disposition of
Cézanne’s apples on their cloths and plates.23 The peculiar anxiousness of second seeing
is a constant source of expressive power in the still lifes and landscapes. Stephen Bann
praises Lawrence’s “deeper” realization that “it was the body that was in question,” and
adds that “embodiment resided in the translation of the movements of the painter’s hand
into the weave of interconnected brush marks.”24 That kind of equation, moreover, is
only a surface residuum, a trace of the deeper dialogue between the painter’s body and the
inhuman bodies of the objects he watched. As Merleau–Ponty knew, the object is in
question throughout Cézanne’s work.25 In a sense he saw bodies as apples, but he also saw
bodies as scraped impasto, as modulating earth tones, and as collections of fractured
fields; it is difficult to begin to write a longer list of such terms or to reconstruct the bodily
22
Scarry, The Body in Pain, op. cit., 282.
D. H. Lawrence, On Hardy and Painting, ed. J. V. Davies (London, 1973), 146, and
Meyer Schapiro, “The Apples of Cézanne,” in Modern Art—Selected Papers (New
York, 1978), 2 ff.
24
Stephen Bann, The True Vine, On Visual Representation and the Western Tradition
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989), 91.
25
The Merleau–Ponty Reader: Philosophy and Painting, edited by Galen A. Johnson
(Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press, 1993).
23
Preface, Introduction
21
relations between them. Cézanne concentrates on the centers of his pictures and lets the
margins fall away, in the manner of a portrait painter—almost as if each picture were the
premonition of a body, which then appears in another guise, as a human form or as a tree,
a boulder, a mountain, or even a principle of color or of fragmentation.26
Assignment 2: first and second seeing. Analyze your own work in terms of first
and second seeing, or find another art practice to interpret.
A way into these questions is provided by Balthasar Klossowski, known as
Balthus, a painter who thought a great deal about Cézanne. He is not an unproblematic
starting point for an inquiry like this one, because his best viewers are themselves often
outside of mainstream concerns about modernist painting, and because of the relentless
sexism of his subjects. (Balthus, Beckman, Schiele, and several other dissimilar twentiethcentury figural painters remain a common grouping in art schools and academies.
Outside those settings they are often bypassed in favor of other genealogies.) But
Balthus’s intensely and obviously sexual way of looking at the world is a helpful quality
for the kind of introduction I have in mind here. His interests are highly specific: despite
the protestations of his biographer Jean Lemayrie and his son Stanislas Klossowski de
Rola, it is almost meaningless to deny he was both initially and finally an observer of
adolescent girls.27 He saw them in ways that have to do with the exact demands of his
desire: the paintings focus on the underpants, the top inch of the inner thigh, the hem of
the skirt, the rounded forms of the vulva, the hair (especially when it is pulled or
brushed), and the double arc of the tops of the breasts. His paintings of domestic interiors
are precise demonstrations of the ways that it is possible—in imagination, or in a
26
For examples of Cézanne’s attention to the centers of pictures, see my “The Failed and
the Inadvertent: The Theory of the Unconscious in the History of Art” International
Journal of Psycho–Analysis 75 part 1 (1994): 119–32.
27
Lemayrie, Balthus, second edition (New York: Skira, 1982); Klossowski de Rola,
Balthus (New York: Abrams, 1996). I do not doubt that Stanislas is correct in what he
says about his father’s idea of women (basically, that they represent unattainable
perfection), or about his artistic project (that it was increasingly hermetic). For additional
material on Balthus, see Milton Gendel, “H. M. The King of Cats,” interview, Art News
61 no. 2 (April 1962): 36–38; Alice Rewald, “Interview with Balthus,” Gazette de
Lausanne (8 December 1962); Michel Legris, “Si Rome n’est plus Rome,” Le Monde (11
January 1967), and “Entretien avec Balthus,” Le Monde (12 January 1967). The account I
am developing here is parallel to Die weibliche und die männliche Linie: Das imaginäre
Geschlecht der modernen Kunst von Klimt bis Mondrian, edited by Susanne Deicher
(Berlin: Dietrich Reimer, 1993).
Preface, Introduction
22
painter’s studio—to look up, down, or obliquely in order to see around obstacles. That
kind of seeing is demonstrated in the most exhausting way whenever there are figures in
the paintings, and it is present just as insistently in the few still lifes he painted. The
obvious analogies are all here: the knife, thrust into the loaf of bread; the cloth draped in a
double curve over the chair (exactly mimicking the pose taken by models in several
paintings). And there are
old–fashioned vanitas
elements as well: the broken
pitcher recalling the
punctured hymen, as in
Jean–Baptiste Greuze’s 18th c.
paintings of lost innocence,
and several rounded forms
recalling hips, arms, and
breasts.
Balthus’s hot-house
dramas are luxuries that
Cézanne stifled, or rather
that he never controlled or
knew well enough to put in
such obvious forms, and they are ultimately less interesting than the specific angles and
encounters between objects. On the right, the stopper and a glass fragment nearly touch
one another; they are neither horizontal nor upright, and they are not quite disposed so
that we can see them clearly. Some of their curves are pointed toward us, and others away.
They perform the same kind of half-hidden, ambiguous and sexually charged meeting
that Balthus demanded of his models. The cloth bends forward, unfurling itself and
almost touching the mallet handle. An entire dynamics of the eye could be written about
Balthus’s still lifes, setting out the full range of conceivable orientations and views that
determine the shapes of his desire. This particular still life is more eloquent on that
account, because it resonates with the evidence of Balthus’s figure paintings: but any still
life partakes of the obvious sexual and bodily meaning of knives and fruits, as well as this
more hidden but precise geometry of the ways that the body can be seen.
Still lifes are a common example of a bodiless genre suffused with bodily
invitations and overtones, and landscape is another. Western landscape has long taken
Preface, Introduction
23
meaning from parallels between natural forms and bodily contours—so much so that
Chinese and other non–European landscapes are susceptible to specific kinds of
misreadings as scholars attempt to see them in terms of the bodies they do not possess.
John Hay made the provocative suggestion that Western pictured bodies (in the sense of
solid, naked, politically charged representations) may have their analogues in the
“convoluted, foraminate, complexly
textured” rocks so ubiquitous in Chinese
gardens and paintings.28 The rocks would
then indicate a particular sense of the
body largely foreign to Western
meanings: they would have to do with
shen, qi, and other Chinese concepts
(roughly, “spirit” and “energy”), and they
would evoke the body’s bulk, its gestures,
its orifices and proportions, in oblique
and unstable ways. Hay’s proposal opens a
risky interpretive field, since in accord
with Western habits of seeing it would be
tempting to extend his observation to
ordinary painted rocks and mountains
that seem to depend so much on erasing
the body’s specific forms.29 A painting by
Dong Qichang, for example, may have a
range of fractured and crumpled cliffs that
do not respond to bodily readings.
It could be argued that
interpretations that locate the body in
Chinese and other non–Western
landscapes will not make significant
28
John Hay, “The Body Invisible in Chinese Art?” in Body, Subject, and Power in China,
edited by Angela Zito and Tani Barlow (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994),
42–77, especially 68.
29
Hay says only that the rock is “the classical image of the Chinese tradition,” parallel to
“the Apollo or the Venus” (ibid., 68).
Preface, Introduction
24
progress until we can better understand how Western response depends on the body; and
for that reason I want to continue for the moment with the fundamental elements of the
Western perception of pictured bodies. Balthus is again a good introductory example; in
his painting The Cherry–Picker (1940), a woman is halfway up a ladder, provoking
thoughts of voyeurism—her legs
are together, and her skirt is lifted
just above her knees; but with
another few steps up the ladder,
she will be overhead. Thanks to
the hypereloquent sexuality of
Balthus’s vision, the landscape
itself expresses the same desire, so
accurately that the figure is almost
superfluous. Cherry–picking is
always a matter of peering upward
and craning the neck, and Balthus
places a few cherries in the leaves
just out of the girl’s reach. The
whole scene is set on a steep
hillside that accelerates into a cliff
that brushes the very top of the
picture—with a vertical Lombard
poplar for extra emphasis—so that
the viewer, or rather the voyeur, is
entirely absorbed in the act of
looking up. In other paintings
Balthus mobilizes a more common
convention, in which a woman lies in a landscape, and the hills undulate with echoes of
her hips. The effect can be obvious and also overwhelming, as if the landscape were an
ocean, and every hill a wave rehearsing the outlines of her body.
If Western landscapes are imbued with these structures, the exception that proves
the rule is the geometrized landscape. When Cézanne painted the curve of the Mont
Saint–Victoire he tended to cut it into architectonic fragments, and in general he made
sharp lines out of opportunities to represent gentle curves. In order to say that those
Preface, Introduction
25
decisions are moves made against the body, it is not necessary to invoke the history of
sexualized landscape back to Giorgione; it is enough to realize, as the pictorial logic itself
reveals, that the Mont Saint–Victoire has a curved back, and that Cézanne has broken it.
Balthus painted one extraordinary landscape according to these rules of negation: a view
of the small town of Larchent. The picture is unmoving and empty, and the town’s few
houses are regimented into an austere convocation of geometric planes. As in some of
Cézanne’s landscape, there is nothing nearby. A field leads down at an indeterminate
angle toward a quarry, and the town only begins in the far distance. The quarry has a pit
and a central mound of tailings, and it is not a coincidence that Cézanne was attracted to
the same two forms in his paintings of the Bibémus quarry. The heap is an attractive
obstacle: that is, a body, or the faint echo of one. It is soft and truncated (in Cézanne’s
paintings, the Bibémus quarry is more formidable, riven with impassable clefts and
overhangs), and in the distance the mound is completed by the even more strongly figural
shape of an old church. Larchent is painted in parsimonious late–winter colors,
smothering any strong chromatic effect and putting a chill on Balthus’s accustomed
Preface, Introduction
26
sexual heat. Since most of Balthus’s paintings are set in close, humid rooms, this is an
unexpected act of asceticism, and the whole performance may be read as a quiet, effective
silencing of the body.
Bodily forms in abstraction
These are some of the ways that a sense of body can be crucial even where there is
no body or obvious body metaphor. Abstraction is only farther from the body if we say a
body has to have certain naturalistic conventions such as a recognizable face, or an object
recognizable as a face, limbs in a determinate order (though that order might not be the
human one), opacity, adherence to gravity, or organic rather than sharp–edged contours.
In general it is difficult to reform the body so radically that its fragments begin to operate,
as Balthus’s brother Pierre Klossowski has said, somehow outside the circuit of possible
desire and possession.30 But the possibilities are variable and not easy to pin down.
Abstract pictures can resonate with a sense of the body more strongly and persuasively
even than photographs or academic studies of the nude. The second seeing they initiate
can be more engrossing than the obviously fruitless searches for a body in landscape or
interiors. Abstraction, it could be argued, is virtually a discourse on the represented body,
made all the more insistent by its obliquity.
There is gesture, first of all: the marks in Jackson Pollock’s Grayed Rainbow, for
example, are records of the exact bodily motions that made them, and they evoke the
affects a viewer may associate with those motions. The drip paintings are about leaning,
stooping, stretching, as well as all the things that Pollock’s contemporaries found amusing
about the new technique: drooling, peeing, and stomping around. When Pollock
discovered the drip technique in 1947 he was doing battle against his own Picassoid
figures, trying to enmesh and overwhelm them in new marks; as Rosalind Krauss has
emphasized, “what seemed consistently at stake was to do violence to the image.”31 The
horizontal surface, and the awkward bending and reaching (and crawling, and tip–toeing)
are all part of that purpose, and they leave their traces in the work. The all-over paintings
30
Pierre Klossowski, La rassemblance (Paris: Ryôan–ji, 1984), 83, discussed in Mario
Perniola, “Between Clothing and Nudity,” translated by Roger Friedman, in Fragments
for a History of the Human Body, op. cit., vol. 2, 236–65, especially 252. See further
Klossowski, “Balthus Beyond Realism,” Art News 55 no. 8 (1956): 26–31.
31
Krauss, The Optical Unconscious, op. cit., 282, 284.
Preface, Introduction
27
are compelling, in this regard, because they exhibit specifiable degrees of anger against
the figure. Some continuous swoops are lazy, half-controlled gestures, and the kind of
motion that made them would have been something gentle but imprecise, like strewing
seeds. (In Greyed Rainbow, they are mostly white loops and strings.) That kind of motion,
in turn, conjures informal relaxation, both bodily and mental. Other marks are more
violent, and there are splatters, gobs of paint, and even hand– and footprints, that speak
about less comfortable motions.
It has been remarked that Pollock’s drips are perched between contours (that is,
outlines, which could contain figural shapes) and areas that would be enclosed between
contours.32 In one place they are a thin as lines, and in another as thick as color areas or
objects, but they neither catch the light nor throw shadows, and they neither confine nor
compose areas. At first glance, that modernist criticism might appear to be a recipe for
avoiding the apparition of the body, and concentrating on the pure play of abstraction.
With no way to be sure if a drip mark is an outline bounding a figure, or a thin figure
with its own outline, it would not be possible to be sure of the vocabulary of figural
metaphors. But the body has many voices and it can express itself through motions and
ambiguous contours as well as disambiguated forms. There is no need to roughen the
experience of the painting by trying to set out the bodily metaphors in any detail; it is
enough to note that there are many kinds of gestures and associated emotions in the
painting, and that the body is the vehicle of their meaning. If we do not think of the
body—no matter how faintly or quickly—the gestural language remains inaudible.
Abstract moments in all visual art also involve the body when they exhibit the
shapes, colors, and feel of the skin. Like all oil painting, Grayed Rainbow takes place on a
skin (the raw canvas is a skin, both in its thinness and its opacity), and the paint itself
forms another skin with its smooth dry surface and potentially, or originally, viscous
interior. It could be argued that Grayed Rainbow expresses more about skin than many
illusionistic paintings because it does not yield information about what lies beyond the
picture plane. Despite Clement Greenberg’s assertion of Pollock’s planarity, the painting’s
“cuts” and streaks are wounds to the skin of the canvas, and they make the skin metaphor
that much more insistent.
32
Michael Fried, Three American Painters (Cambridge: Fogg Art Museum, 1965), 10–
19. The theme is pursued from another perspective in my Pictures and the Words That
Fail Them (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, forthcoming).
Preface, Introduction
28
Gesture and skin are two modes by which the body is metaphorically present in
abstraction, and another is scale. As Robert Rosenblum observed, paintings such as
Grayed Rainbow can be ambiguously human-sized, microscopic (“atomic”) and
macroscopic (like “galaxies”).33 Those two alternatives are more dramatic than my own
experience of the painting—I’d rather say Greyed Rainbow offers an oscillating series of
scales, all roughly human–scaled. The largest forms in the painting aside from the surface
itself are the sweeping black curves that line up across the canvas. They are the painting’s
principal surrogate figures, not because we need to think of them as figures, but because
they are almost human–scaled and human–proportioned. I instinctively respond to them
in that way, as if my whole body is an appropriate echo to each one of the forms. Still,
Rosenblum’s observation is correct as a reminder that scale is an open question; and other
times I find myself responding to small portions of the painting, thinking of the finer
lines as plantlike shapes, or inadvertently constructing imaginary landscapes. Once again
33
R. Rosenblum, Modern Painting and the Northern Romantic Tradition, Friedrich to
Rothko (New York: Harper, 1975), 203.
Preface, Introduction
29
it does not matter in this context exactly how the scales operate (though it would be
essential for a more involved reading of the painting); what counts is that the body is also
immediately available through choices of scale.
Assignment 3: bodies in abstraction. If your own work is abstract, analyze how
bodies are conjured using scale, figure and ground, skin, and scale. Or choose an
abstract artwork to analyze in those terms.
Preface, Introduction
30
A fourth source of bodily metaphors in abstraction is provided by the distances at
which I situate myself when I am looking at a represented body. The ordinary choices can
be put schematically:
myopic positions
Deliberately overly close,
scanning or inspecting the
surface inch by inch.
2
figure mark
positions
The farthest positions from
which it is possible to see
individual painted marks on the
body.
3
ground mark
positions
The farthest positions from
which it is possible to see
individual painted marks on the
ground.
4
conversational
positions
The places where the painting
comfortably fills the visual field,
and possesses the same size–to–
distance ratio that I sense in
talking to people.
5
inferred center of
projection
The place where the perspective
schema or other structural clue
implies I should stand.
6
hyperopic
positions
Deliberately overly distant
positions, from which large
features of the painting cannot
be seen.
7
anamorphic
positions
Positions deliberately too far to
one side, so that the picture is
willfully distorted.
1
Table 1. Some positions in front of representations of the body.
Preface, Introduction
31
Normative distances are in the middle of the Table: if the representation strikes me as a
bodily shape and size, I may unthinkingly stand at the same distance I would stand from a
person when I am talking (number 4). The conversational distance is instinctive, and I
sometimes find myself drawn toward it even in front of abstract compositions. Often, too,
I may stand just close enough to see the marks that make the figure, or the (often larger)
marks that comprise the ground (numbers 2 and 3). In some Renaissance paintings, those
figure mark and ground mark positions are close to the panel or canvas, and they balance
the more distant inferred center of projection, which is frequently a little farther away
than I might care to stand (number 5). With painters like Raphael, the choices are quite
clear: either I can walk close up to one of his paintings, and try to see how it was done, or
I can stand back near the place specified by the perspectival or structural cues in the
picture. The figure and ground mark positions are usually close enough to touch the
painting, because they correspond with the distances from which the painting was made:
and therefore they are also the distances I might occupy if I mean to touch another
person. Piero di Cosimo is another typical example: there are implied positions from
myopic inspections to conversational overviews, and viewers are invited to move between
them.
Then there are “improper” positions, which I call myopic, hyperopic (farsighted)
and anamorphic (numbers 1, 6, and 7); each avoids the cluster of places that address the
picture. The normative positions afford more or less intimacy and naturalness, and the
improper positions are ways of spying on the painting, seeing it from places it does not
Preface, Introduction
32
sanction. Anamorphic positions are surreptitious, and in that respect Balthus’s paintings
are all anamorphic. Though I may position myself front and center before one of
Balthus’s paintings, in imagination, and in accord with the picture’s logic, I am bending
low, squatting, turning, or twisting myself to see something out of the corner of my eye.34
Hyperopic positions are essentially rejections, in that I refuse to be close enough to see (or
talk to, or hear) the figure or the painting; and myopic positions are pathological or
medical, and are beyond the bounds of common human intercourse. I can refuse a
painting either by staying away from it, or by approaching and examining so closely that I
do not take in the entire image.
Assignment four: positions of viewing. Analyze an artwork using some of these
categories of close and distant viewing.
Needless to say, this list is only a sample of the possibilities. It is too coarse to
explain what happens in front of an actual painting, and other media would require other
ideas, other positions. But the table illustrates another way that the body can reverberate
when it is absent, pushing me toward a picture, or pulling me away, in accord with rules
that are ultimately derived from my interaction with bodies. When a painting disrupts the
body as Pollock’s does, dispersing its forms to all parts of the canvas, cutting the work
loose “from any analogies with the gestalt of the body whole,” then it refers even more
insistently to the body’s lost wholeness, and to the “aggressivity and formlessness” of its
repression.35 And when, in addition to that violent dispersal, the painting declines to
observe the hierarchy of human scales, it provokes a vertigo of continuous unfocused
displacement—as I walk back and forth, up to the painting and away again—and I am
returned all the more insistently to the question of the absent body.
Certainly gesture, skin, scale and distance are sources of bodily meaning in
abstraction, and I might add a fifth term, the specific modes of looking that pertain to
bodies. Grayed Rainbow has its own rules of looking: staring along and around the large
black gestures, peering through and among the smaller ones, looking up and down, tying
visual knots and flourishes by following the curving paths of the dripping paint. Some of
those are modes of looking that I feel most strongly when I look at bodies: the caressing
34
In this respect the concept of anamorphosis need not be confined to viewing positions
that are literally skew. Lacan’s theory implies as much; for discussion and further
literature see my Poetics of Perspective (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1994),
248-52.
35
Krauss, The Optical Unconscious, op. cit., 308.
Preface, Introduction
33
motions are certainly bodily, and so is the motion of looking around or along, since it
names the curvilinear motions of the eye that I associate with organic forms, and
ultimately with the body. Other kinds of looking, such as the scattered surveys I make of
the painting as a whole, or the kaleidoscopic feel of its lack of center, do not pertain to the
body: they are the more anxious, less rooted kinds of second seeing, in which my eyes
rove in search of bodily forms or echoes.
Beyond these five categories I would not be sure where to go: Would it make sense
to say that heat, texture, growth, or hue, are body metaphors in the same way as gesture
or scale? Because I believe that the final source of visual meaning is the body, I would
have no a priori difficulty in accepting new categories of picturemaking as signs of the
body. But this is not an easy subject, and the relation between the terms is far from clear.
The operation of the eye, or of scale, or of position in any given work can quickly pass
beyond the power of analysis or descriptive language. For that reason it seems best to
remain aware of the multiplicity and nuance of second seeing, and of the resourcefulness
of the eye in locating body metaphors, rather than attempting to systematize the field into
a taxonomy of bodily responses. Part of the skittishness or anxiety of second seeing may
well be due to this exact conceptual disorganization: as we look from object to object in
search of bodies that are not there, we also look from metaphor to metaphor, hoping to
find one strong enough to rival an actual body in its solidity and permanence.
Representation as bodily distortion
With this extended prologue I arrive at the main subject of this book: an attempt
at a general account of the pictured body. I have tried to speak as specifically as I can
about individual images, in the hope of showing how general philosophic questions might
meet the exactitudes of the pictured body. To that end it has been necessary to find
guiding concepts and figures that could operate both as a philosophemes and as critical or
historical terms capable of describing specific images. The literature is replete with
general categories such as the ecstatic, grotesque, recessive, immaterial, or “dys–
appearing” body, and with broad concepts such as the “denigration of vision,”
scopophilia, visual culture, and “visibilization,” but they are more appropriate to surveys
Preface, Introduction
34
of philosophic positions and cultural trends than individual images.36 Hybrid concepts
that allow historical and critical nuance to play against philosophic clarity are more
promising, and I want to introduce a few here as a way of opening the argument of the
book.
Distortion is such a term: it is connected to philosophic discourse on
representation in general, and it is both elemental and specific in body images of all kinds.
Claude Gandelman names one aspect of the equation between the represented body and
distortion when he says the “reality of the body qua represantatio [as representation] is its
essential distortion,” and I would argue that the opposite and correlative aspect is the
bodily form toward which all representation tends.37 Any representation of a body
involves distortion, because all representation is distortion, and conversely,
representation works within a logic of the body, so that representation is embodiment: it
produces and projects bodies.
Hence I would posit a series of increasingly large domains, that might be imagined
as concentric circles in a Venn diagram: innermost is pictures, which I am taking
throughout this text as a synecdoche for all visual artifacts. Larger than the sum total of
visual images is representations of the body, since there are also imaginary
representations—representations that are not metaphorically embodied in the outside
world, but remain literally embodied in the mind. Outside representations of the body are
representations in general, or representation in the philosophic sense, because there are
surely representations that do not involve the body—though I would be less certain that
there are representations that we would not attempt to read in terms of bodily metaphors.
And the largest category, the one I propose to elaborate, is distortion. As a logician would
say, even though all representation is distortion, some distortion is not representation—
36
Scopophilia is explored in Martin Jay, Downcast Eyes: The Deingration of Visition in
Twentieth–Century French Thought (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1993); it was coined
by Freud, Three Essays on Sexuality, in Standard Edition, edited by James Strachey
(London: Hogarth Press, 1962), vol. 17, 169. Most of the remaining terms are from Drew
Leder, The Absent Body, op. cit. The ecstatic body has been invoked most recently by
Gertrud Sandquist, describing Andres Searrano’s photographs. See “Body of Ecstasy,” in
Andres Serrano (Oslo: Galleri Riis, 1991).
37
Gandelman, Reading Pictures, Viewing Texts (Bloomington, IN: Indiana University
Press, 1991), 74. Unfortunately Gandelman ties this to a programmatic interpretation of
the map of cortical motor functions, which he says implies a “homunculus” in the brain;
recent research has distorted the homunculus beyond recognition, and extended
“humunculi” to other sense organs in other animals.
Preface, Introduction
35
for example a broken leg does not represent itself—and therefore distortion encompasses
all the other categories.
It is common to argue the inevitability of distortion in all representation by
appealing to the mathematical problem of projecting or otherwise mapping a sphere onto
a plane. No such projection or mapping is possible without distortion, but maps are not
simply distorted. Instead they are distorted in particular ways that are designed to
preserve useful properties of the globe. Azimuthal maps retain the sense of direction,
equal-area maps preserve areas, and conformal maps preserve angles and certain
distances. In the same way, pictures of the body normally work to preserve certain bodily
properties, so that distortion is usually local and specifiable. The danger is in generalizing
as Gandelman does, and implying everything in representations of the body is equally
within the field of distortion. Instead bodily distortion is both a condition and a property
of representation but not the whole of it—and that is what allows the analysis of
represented bodies to go forward without turning into an equation of holistic properties:
a body’s reality qua represantatio is some distortion.
Still more fundamentally, and not at all coincidentally, distortion is an attribute of
the body itself prior to representation. We are pressed through the birth canal, we swell to
Preface, Introduction
36
adult proportions, we shrink into old age. Our skin is elastic, and it is relevant that
elasticity is the essential non–mathematical metaphor of topology, which has itself
become a non–mathematical metaphor for conceptual distortions of all kinds. The skin is
not elastic like rubber, but pinched folds do return to place—quickly in younger people,
and then more sluggishly, until the skin appears to lose its elastic nature. Skin shrivels,
stretches, hangs and wiggles. When it comes to talk about representing the body,
distortion is the inescapable fact. Erwin Panofsky said perspective causes painters to
distort their experience in order to represent it, and that representation was the chief
purpose of perspective’s distortions.38 Like perspective, the histories of bodily canons and
schemata can be seen as distorting moves against the inevitable unrepresentable qualities
of bodily experience; and the histories of contrapposto, poses, gestures, physiognomy and
the passions can be read as attempts to embrace those same experiences while also
representing them. The vacillating attitudes toward distortion and the varying urges for
and against representation would be a fruitful way to organize the history of the body,
and this book could equally have been subtitled A General Theory of Distortion.
But there are other words that might serve better in place of distortion. The word
distortion comes from Latin torquere, to twist, and so the verb “to distort” means “to twist
out of shape.” Yet not all representation is twisting, specifically. Another term is
“deformation,” which comes from forma, beauty. The Latin deformis means ugly, and our
English word “deformed” also carries this connotation; hence to “deform” is to make
ugly. Much of what I will be considering has to do with this boundary between beauty
and ugliness, and between what has form in this sense and what does not. These words
are related to “disproportion,” “distention” (from distendere, to stretch), “dissolution”
(from solvere, to loosen), “dissection” (from secare, to cut), “disruption” (from rumpere,
to break), and “disjunction” (from jungere, to join). “Disfiguration” has some resonance
in literary criticism, where the word “figure” or “figure of thought” does much more
general duty as a near–synonym for “trope”; disfiguration is sometimes a good name for
what happens in pictures when bodies are divested of their forms by being impressed into
38
“Die Perspektive als ‘Symbolische Form’,” Vorträge der Bibliothek Warburg 4
(1927): 258–330.
Preface, Introduction
37
noncorporeal objects, dissolved into backgrounds, or shredded by broken light.39 Just as
every occurrence of a linguistic figure is both a usage and a partial effacement or
distortion of that figure, so each picture of the body is both a figure and its disfiguration.
Because it has so many forms, distortion is not a word that can provide a skeleton
key for questions of bodily representation. In the pages that follow it will appear as
schematization, analogy, anatomy, dissection, projection, inversion, metaphorization, and
many other names. But it is worth stressing the idea that a process that can sometimes
adequately be called distortion is so fundamental, so universal, that it governs
representation itself. In its guise as continual motion, distortion is the body’s quality of
liveness, and it is also the essential property of representation. (And this may be one of
the reasons why death, the state without distortion, is not easily susceptible to
representation.40) The two appearances of distortion, in the body and in pictures, are
related: they speak for the intimate relation between embodiment and representation.
Assignment five: terms for distortion and representation. Use some of these
terms, or others, to analyze what happens in your own artwork, or in someone
else’s.
Affect and logic
Although words such as “distortion” and “deformation” are indispensable general
categories, they lead to an unhelpful formalism. Instead of trying to create a topology of
failed representation, I am going to opt for a distinction that employs topology in the
service of a description of the bodily effects of bodily representations: the distinction
between distortions that are felt, and those that are thought. A headache or a broken bone
exist in two states: in one, we feel it, and often we cannot think of anything else; and in
another, we think of it, and feel nothing. These two possibilities, never entirely separate,
39
In Quintilian and classical rhetoric “figure of speech” and “trope” were disjunct, while
“figure of thought” coincided with some uses of “trope.” See Princeton Encyclopedia of
Poetics, edited by Alex Preminger (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1974), s. v.
“Trope” and “Figure.”
40
This is taken up in The Object Stares Back, op. cit., and in a different way, in the final
chapter of Mieke Bal, Reading “Rembrandt”: Beyond the Word–Image Opposition
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991).
Preface, Introduction
38
are ways that the self encounters the represented body, including our own body as we
sense it and represent it to ourselves. Either something that distorts the body feels, or it
means.
Affect in this book has a spercific meaning that is different from the one usuallt
assigned to it in affect theory as it is exemplified by Brian Massumi. In his account, affect
is the body’s innate response to the world, which takes place nearly instantly, before and
without cognition. In more general terms, and outside Massumi’s account, affect theory
has come to be the study of sensation, feeling, and emotion, as opposed to intellection. the
meaning I am after is closer to that looser sense of affect, and in particular to the way that
affect, when it is consciously experienced, is on the same spectrum as feeling and can
therefore sometimes be intense and literally painful. Affect is the opposite of something I
puzzle over, it’s the opposite of an intellectual engagement. At one end it is dully
perceived moods, and at the other it is pain. In art, affect in this sense does not usually
cross over into actual discomfort. Instead an affective artwork is one that elicits a
nonverbal experience, a sensation or mood, as opposed to a cognized experience of the
sort that I can articulate.41 Affect is a general state of sensation, a sensual monitoring of
the body and what it sees, a care or awareness of its health and its current state, an
attention to what are sometimes known as “raw feels.”
When it comes to the body’s sense of itself, there is a neurological concept that is
close to what I mean here, and that is proprioception (also known as cenesthesia and
tactus intimus): the body’s internal sense of itself.42 Proprioception is among the body’s
fundamental senses, even though it has not gained the canonical status of the five senses.
When I number the senses that seem independent of one another, I count at least eight:
there is sight, smell, taste, hearing, and touch, and there is also gravity (independent of
the five, since it does not require touch), heat (independent, for the same reason: I do not
41
For that reason I will not be considering images that have to do explicitly with the
theme of pain, but rather images whose sight causes pain (or some allied, but less intense,
reaction). For a feminist account of images about pain, see Paula Cooey, Religious
Imagination and the Body, A Feminist Analysis (New York: Oxford University Press,
1994), on Frida Kahlo.
42
For proprioception see Oliver Sacks, The Man who Mistook his Wife for a Hat (New
York: Summit, 1985). For cenesthesia and tactus intimus (the latter comes from Cicero’s
translation of Aristippus), see Jean Starobinski, “A Short History of Bodily Sensation,”
translated by Sarah Matthews, in Fragments for a History of the Human Body, op. cit.,
vol. 2, 350–70, especially 353.
Preface, Introduction
39
need to make contact to feel temperature), and proprioception. This last names the way
we know how our limbs are disposed without looking at them or touching them. It is the
body’s internal muscular and organic sense of itself. Proprioception is not equivalent to
the sense of touch, since the skin tells us about what happens in the outside world but
also, independently and without any act of touching, it tells us something about the
disposition of the limbs underneath. There have been medical cases in which
proprioception disappears, and such patients report a faint sensation on the skin (they
can feel the wind blowing against it, or the light brushing of objects), but there is a general
helplessness about the body. The patients have to learn to look at their limbs to remain
seated or to walk. If they lose sight of their bodies they tend to collapse, so that they can
only walk while looking down, and they have to learn to sit by the tedious expedient of
memorizing the motions and places of each limb. Grasping objects is difficult, since it is
not easy to monitor the strength of the grip by eye: either the knuckles grow white, or the
object slips from the fingers.
The quality I am calling affect certainly has to do with this, though there is no
reason to exclude the senses of touch, heat, balance, or even smell and taste in the same
general category. Affect signifies that mode of awareness that listens to the body, and is
aware of its feeling—whether that feeling is the low-level muttering of a body in good
health, or the high pain of illness. Most of the time in looking at visual art I am concerned
with simple things like the feeling of a turn of the head, or an eye that moves and focuses.
Proprioception is apt because it denotes feeling that occurs in the body rather than bodily
movements. I may not actually move in responding to an artwork, but I often feel
something like moving—and proprioception names the sensation, or memory, or
incipience, of motion. As in other transcriptions of bodily responses, it is important to be
exact about these half–sensations. Looking for a long time at Balthus’s painting of the
cherry picker, I may become aware of a slight tenseness in my neck as I think of straining
to look upward. Those motions are mental: they don’t produce neckache or eyestrain, or
Preface, Introduction
40
even, usually, the thought of them. Affect here is
the delicate awareness of the thought of the
viewer’s body and its relation to the artwork.
Empathy is another term that may be
implicated in this sense of pain. It was originally
an Enlightenment term; Pierre-Louis Moreau de
Maupertuis used it to describe the effect of a
mother’s emotions on her developing fetus.
Moreau’s argument follows a medieval model
enjoining mothers to be careful of wayward
thoughts. Just as we feel pain when we see pain,
he claims, so the fetus can be malformed if its
mother sees disfigured bodies or conceives
disfigured thoughts.43 The Scottish philoospher
David Hume’s sense of “compassion” is also an empathetic doctrine. When Hume sought
to demonstrate the bodily origin of thought, he proposed the example of gout, which
ravages both the body and the mind.44 Given these sources in medieval associative magic,
medicine, and Enlightenment rationalism, it is curious that our current sense of empathy
was coined as a connoisseur’s term, to describe a viewer’s reaction to paintings. Robert
Vischer observed how formal arrangements in works of art elicited muscular and
emotional reactions, and concluded that we are deceived into attributing those reactions
to the object.45 This Einfühlung (“feeling-in,” empathy) is an “involuntary act of
transference” that causes the viewer to think something is true of the object rather than of
43
Maupertuis, The Earthly Venus, translated by Simone Brangier Boas, with an
introduction by George Boas (New York: Johnson Reprint Corp., 1966), 49–50.
Maupertuis is discussed in Barbara Stafford, Body Criticism, Imaging the Unseen in
Enlightenment Art and Medicine (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1991), 315; see also my
review in The Art Bulletin 74 no. 3 (1992): 517–20.
44
Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, edited by L. A. Selby-Bigge (Oxford, 1967), 276,
287, 319. This is discussed also in Stafford, Body Criticism, 188.
45
Vischer, Das optische Formgefühl, op. cit. Vischer’s doctrine, which is still
insufficiently studied, posits Einfühlung as one of a series of concepts that describe the
relation between felt reality and the mind.
Preface, Introduction
41
himself.46 (Theodor Lipps, who exposited the theory of empathy most thoroughly, also
used examples from the visual arts.47) Vischer noticed how the body “swells” when it
enters a wide hall, and how it “sways,” even in imagination, when it sees wind blowing in
a tree. Proprioception demonstrates that the body has sensation within and of itself, with
only minimal input from the outside world. But empathic reaction can also echo forms
and events in the outside world: the “swelling” elicited by the hall is felt inside my body,
not as a force on my body. In conjunction with proprioception, empathy can help us
understand how our bodies are partly our own, and partly owned by the objects we see.
I want to try to avoid calling the opposite of affect “thought” or “meaning,”
because I do not know how to place the moments when language begins to be attached to
objects of experience. Instead I will be using a polarity between affect and logic. Often
what is at stake in representations of the body that elicit thoughts, analysis, and logic,
rather than visceral reactions, is a metamorphosis of the body. I do not wince when
Picasso turns a face into a flower, as I do sometimes when Francis Bacon turns a head
into a bloody stump. Do even the most convoluted and violent of Picasso’s creations,
such as the ones T. J. Clark studied in his Mellon lectures, make me feel for the
46
C. E. Gauss, “Empathy,” Dictionary of the History of Ideas, edited by P. P. Wiener
(New York, 1973), vol. II, 86.
47
Lipps, Raumästhetik und geometrisch-optische Täuschungen (Leipzig, 1897), and
Lipps, Ästhetik, 2 vols. (Hamburg and Leipzig, 1903–06). Lipps’s text and his categories
seem to me to be confused, and I will not be following them here. He posits three levels
of empathy: one in which the viewer reacts viscerally to an object (feeling expansive
upon entering a large hall, swaying like a tree), a second in which objects elicit
intellectual reactions (as when I analyze the hall, and place it in a specific historical
period), and a third in which humans elicit specific readings (as in physiognomy and the
languages of gesture). (See C. E. Gauss, “Empathy,” op. cit., 86.)
Preface, Introduction
42
represented bodies? I do not think so. Instead viewing a picture like this is like solving a
puzzle. I see a cascade of hair at the upper left, and I deduce an arm must be supporting it;
I recognize a face at the upper right, and I conclude that it belongs to a lionlike man.
Gradually, the pieces fall into place: I see that the woman is holding up a mirror or
hairbrush, and then I notice the man’s hand on the guitar, his splayed feet, the long curve
of the woman’s body terminating in a tiny bundled foot, and two breasts (with hanging
shadows) in the form of a face. Gradually I come to understand that it’s a picture of a
man, playing a guitar while a woman listens while and brushes her hair. I do not feel
much when I encounter such images, because I am too concerned with deducing and
decoding—with solving a logical puzzle—and sometimes also too filled with admiration
for the artist’s clever inventions, what the sixteenth century would have called “conceits”
(concetti).48
48
In this respect Picasso’s drawing participates in the modernist equation between
pictures and puzzles; see my Why Are Our Pictures Puzzles? On the Modern Origins of
Pictorial Complexity (New York: Routledge, forthcoming).
Preface, Introduction
43
Images that elicit the analytic side of seeing are mostly those that analogize the
body, rearranging and substituting its parts for symbolic and allegorical purpose, and
otherwise toying with it intellectually. Here a
man is a lion, a woman’s abdomen is a face, her
head is a vacuum cleaner, his arm is a machine
part. Those changes are best called
metamorphoses, logical changes, as opposed to
the images I will associate with affect.
Metamorphosis effortlessly alters the body into
that which no living body can be. It is
significant, and often unremarked, that in the
classical literature metamorphosis is a painless
matter. The changes the Roman poet Ovid
describes in his Metamorphoses can be
unpleasant experiences (Daphne did not want to
become a laurel, as in this sculpture by Bernini),
but they are not painful (Daphne does not
scream in Ovid’s poem when she sees her fingers
tightening into twigs, but she feels “numb and
heavy”—the opposite of discomfort).49 The characters cry out because they are being
unjustly punished or delivered from rape or death, or else they cry because they are
leaving their lovers and the world of humanity. But they do not feel their transformations
at all, except as impartial observers at the wonder of the moment. Actaeon screams, we
assume, when he is turned into a stag and his dogs turn on him: but his pain, which we do
not feel, is not on account of his metamorphosis. In Titian’s painting we do not feel his
pain. Even the most extreme distortions can be painless if they are metamorphoses—a
woman into a tree, or a man into a mixture of lion, paper collage, and rubber band.
49
Ovid, Metamorphoses, translated by Rolfe Humphries (Bloomington, IN: Indiana
University Press, 1975), 19.
Preface, Introduction
44
I think this is an essential fact about the concept of metamorphosis: though it is
sensual, it does not present itself as a matter of feeling. The idea of metamorphosis is odd,
and it has never been clear to me what attracted Ovid to the theme apart from its poetic
and narrative opportunities. But the answer may be connected to the painlessness of it all.
Though every metamorphic distortion attracts our bodily sympathy to some degree, and
though no painful distortion is without intellectual meaning, the distinction between
affect and logic or metamorphosis holds because metamorphosis exists as an idea: we
have the clear notion that bodies can be either broken or merely metempsychosed, and
only one of those possibilities entails pain. In that sense the Metamorphoses is a poem of
escapes, of demonstrations that transcendence is painless and dazzling.
Preface, Introduction
45
It may be objected that this division is not the only organizational principle for the
distortion in bodily representation. A prominent alternate would be the distinction
between the organic in all its forms (the round, flexible, soft, wet, warm, asymmetric, and
living) and the inorganic in all its forms (the geometric, hard, cold, dry, symmetric and
dead). The two are Doppelgängers of each other. Joseph Wood Krutch has written
eloquently on the disturbing difference between an ice flower, growing on a frozen
windowpane, and the apparently similar frond of a fern.50 The ice flower is seductive
because it looks like it is alive,
though it also has the orderly
and inevitable aspect of
inorganic “death.” The
organic/inorganic polarity is a
generative force in many texts,
from the later Socratic dialogues,
where Plato’s love of
mathematics begins to infect the
Socratic moral questioning like
an “unliving” virus, to books on
chaos theory, where the newly
discovered “chaotic attractors”
appear as lifelike patterns found
in nonliving nature.51 I avoid
this way of ordering things
partly because too much of what
happens in visual art is organic,
and the result would be a lopsided exposition of organicity; but a history of the pictured
body could certainly begin with the opposition between life and inorganic “death.”
50
Joseph Wood Krutch, “The Colloid and the Crystal,” The Best Nature Writing of
Joseph Wood Krutch (New York: William Morrow, 1969), 309–20. I thank Paul
Hinchcliffe for this reference.
51
For Socrates as a virus see Gregory Vlastos, Socrates, Ironist and Moral Philosopher
(Ithaca, 1991), 107. For chaos theory see for example J. Gleich, Chaos Science (New
York, 1989).
Preface, Introduction
46
On the other hand, the pain/metamorphosis axis may also be the name of
something even older and even more common in the Western conversation on art and
visuality. It is, after all, the same problem that has also been written as the mind/body
problem, or the difference between language and feeling, or logic and affect, or reason
and instinctual drive. I choose logic and affect simply because they have more resonance
in art theory in the 21st century. The terms are, I think, general enough to be
interchangeable. From Empedocles and Pythagoras to Cambridge Neoplatonism and
beyond, the body has been understood as an object that is mediated by the mind (or the
psyche, or soul, or pneuma, or logos, or ratio). I am content in following that most
ingrained of constructions, and equating or reducing my polarity of affect and logic to
body and mind. My only contribution is the idea that reason, when it is transposed into
pictures of the body, takes the form of metamorphic change, and that a sense of the body,
when it is pictured, becomes a specifiable range of signifiers of sensation.
Assignment 6: logic and affect. Analyze an artwork in terms of what parts of it
make you feel something, and what parts make you think.
The argument dissected
In this book I have attempted to bring the enabling axis between affect (including
pain) and logic (often meaning metamorphosis) into a more articulate contact with
images by dividing the two realms into six categories. In doing this I am less interested in
defending a precise classification than I am in saying something orderly and clear enough
to be useful and susceptible to critique.52 The six categories are as follows:
52
A related classification (into twelve categories) is proposed in William Ewing, The
Body: Photographs of the Human Form (San Francisco: Chronicle Books, 1994), 31; and
a less similar taxonomy is used in L’âme au corps: arts et sciences 1793-1993, exh. cat.,
edited by Jean Clair (Paris: Réunion des musées nationaux, 1993). The latter
distinguishes “le thêatre d’anatomie,” “l’homme machine,” “l’homme électrique,” “le
temps de la phrénologie,” “évolution et symétrie,” “l’homme prosthétique,” and “la
drogue, les émotions, le rêve.”
Preface, Introduction
47
In membranes
(the concept of skin)
Affect
As psychomachia
(the movements of skin)
In cut flesh
(the tearing of skin)
Distortion
By looking alone
(bodies merely presented)
Logic
(Metamorphosis)
By analogy
(metaphoric
substitutions)
By schematization
(geometric reductions)
Table 2. Six categories of represented bodies.
By the affect of membranes (the subject of the first chapter) I mean sensation
evoked by certain ways of picturing the skin. Given its importance in images and in the
body, skin is remarkably under–theorized. Questions of visibility, sensation, the
dichotomy of inside and outside, smoothness, and identity all depend on skin. Chapter 1
explores the concept of pictured skin, extending it to a general theory of depicted
membranes by drawing parallels between psychoanalysis and dermatology. Pictured
bodies offer a range of solutions to the problem of skin: at one extreme there is nothing
but skin, and the body is pure visible surface; and at the other there is no skin, and the
body is surfaceless flesh. But skin metaphors, or their elisions, need to be present in order
for represented bodies to be perceived as living or intact figures. That is true whether the
artist is especially attracted to the skin (as in Lucien Freud, or Matthias Grünewald), or
avoids it in such a way as to make it seem that the very idea of skin is being denied (as I’ll
argue about Pontormo and Michelangelo). Between the two possibilities there are artists
who use a wide range of metaphors—wax, oil, paper, glue—to imagine the pictorial form
Preface, Introduction
48
of skin, and much of the first chapter is aimed at contemporary explorations of visual
equivalents for skin and membranes.
Skin is the starting place of the book and the fundamental possibility for images of
the body, since it is what is visible before and apart from any further meaning.
Psychomachia (Chapter 2) denotes sensation produced by the sight of bodily motion:
either in contorted faces (as in the practice of physiognomy) or in bodies that are twisted
and turned about themselves (as in the practice of contrapposto). It can be argued that
the 15th and 16th centuries explored the majority of configurations of the naturalistically
conceived human body, and that the Renaissance vocabulary of figural postures has
remained in place despite attempts to rescind it by imagining purely frontal and non–
Western figures. The same may be said of the abandoned discipline of physiognomy,
which is as close as the West came to systematically describing the meaning of
expressions. The two moth-eaten disciplines, physiognomy and contrapposto, are the
subject of Chapter 2, whose purpose is to demonstrate the richness of their possibilities,
and the futility of avoiding their histories.
Chapter 1 concerns skin itself, and Chapter 2 explores skin that is put under
tension. Last of the three classes in the general category of affect concerns skin that has
been cut open, revealing the flesh beneath. Flesh has a different constellation of meanings
than skin, some of them involving metaphors of liquidity, as if the body is a bag of skin
holding a fluid interior. In general the invisible inside of the body has been considered
too painful to represent, and few artists have made pictures of the opened body. Most of
the history of cut flesh, therefore, takes place in medical illustration, and it is the story of
an alternation between pictures that attempt to show the inner body in all its bewildering
specificity (sometimes revolting, and other times dangerously seductive), and those that
abstract what is found there in favor of comprehensible portions and simplified views.
The incomprehensibility of flesh, and its close proximity with the inconceivability of
death, bring the first half of the book to a close and raise the abstract question of the
relation between the inconceivable and the unrepresentable, which forms the epilogue to
this book as a whole.
Logical and metamorphic change, the subject of the second half of the book,
belongs to a different world of experience. Metamorphosis “by looking alone,” the subject
of Chapter 4, concerns the effect of some photographs and other pictures that are not
overt rearrangements or distortions of the body (that is, they are perceived as normative
in regard to conventions of naturalism), but at the same time work to change their
Preface, Introduction
49
subjects by turning them into types or specimens. What happens in such images can be as
violent as what occurs when the body is willfully twisted or cut. Pornography, sexism, and
racism belong here, among the representations that purport to be merely truthful, and I
propose a connection between those kinds of images and the simple frontal pose that has
long been central to Western picturemaking. Pictures such as Botticelli’s Birth of Venus,
Watteau’s Gilles, and Velázquez’s portraits of the Infanta all participate in the same visual
field as ethnological photographs used in racial research. The linking concept is the
possibility of mere presence—the simple thereness of the body, which seems to need no
narrative or other linguistic frame in order to express meaning. That assumption is a
dangerous one if only because it puts the image at the mercy of its ideological context.
The concept of mere presence opens the way to a revaluation of racist and pornographic
images, since they become examples of a more general phenomenon—the desire to
consolidate our sense of ourselves by comparison with a represented body. I suggest that
the daily assessment of our image in the mirror is not different in kind from the
comparisons afforded by fine art, by racist imagery and (in the realm of sexuality) of
pornography. Each of those kinds of images can be considered as an opportunity for
specific acts of self–definition, as well as a sometimes harmful reduction of the body for
racist or sexist purposes.
A second strategy that appeals more to the mind than to visceral reaction is
“Analogic Seeing” (Chapter 5), denoting representations that create analogies for the
body as a whole, or for its parts. Picasso’s drawing is an example when it turns a woman’s
body into a spoon, her head into a dustbrush, her breasts into a leering face, and her left
arm into jelly. It seems to me that analogic seeing is more than a formal game or a
surrealist strategy, and that it underwrites much of our ability to comprehend bodies in
general. Chapter 5 opens with a look at the workings of analogy in analytic cubism,
arguably the most important and fruitful bodily metamorphosis in modernism; and it
concludes with an attempt to describe what happens when analogies become difficult to
locate, and the comprehension of the body itself is in danger. The assembled monsters
that populate Greek myths and medieval bestiaries have probably seldom been
frightening, perhaps because their obvious principles of assembly (man + horse =
centaur) are screens that block out the greater terror, which is that monsters might have
no comprehensible organization. Bodies of animals found in the ocean abyss, in plankton,
in Cambrian fossils, and above all under the microscope provide the closest examples of
Preface, Introduction
50
truly disorderly bodies, where the ability to comprehend by finding analogies fails, and
the eye is thrown into a kind of confusion I call visual desperation.
In linguistic terms, Chapter 4 is about the notion that it is possible to merely
describe (that is, merely look) at a body, and Chapter 5 concerns metaphoric
substitutions. The final Chapter completes the possibilities by inquiring into the
reduction of writing to bare logic—or in visual terms, the attempt to deny the body its
basic organic chaos, and to substitute either the rigors of geometry or the labels of
language. In a way the ruleless or transgressive body that Bakhtin called “grotesque” is the
inverted reflection of the linear simplifications that have been imposed by proportional
systems from the Egyptians onward. In order to imagine a body as an object that can be
adequately represented on a grid, or as a scale of head heights, its grosser functions and
shapes have to be repressed; and for that reason the history of bodily schemata can be
understood in terms of what it is not: each grid and scale erases some specific unthinkable
bodily function by confining, repressing, and idealizing it in the name of an impossible
perfection. As in the reduction of writing to logic, there will always be an expressive
remnant that speaks, sometimes very strongly, about what is not being said. In the course
of reviewing the major systems of bodily schemata, the last chapter approaches and finally
opens a double question that runs throughout the book, and gives it much of its impetus:
the nature of the unrepresentable and the inconceivable.
What is unrepresentable might be so because it seems untoward, inappropriate, or
illicit; but it may also be that a bodily form has no graphic equivalent, and therefore
vanishes from pictures because it is taken to be out of the reach of representation. An
eighteenth–century medical illustrator, for example, might omit the textures of mercury
poisoning because he can find no way to represent them in a lithograph. Inconceivability,
on the other hand, signifies whatever is utterly absent from the expected forms of the
represented body, so that the body might appear complete to a certain set of viewers.
Leonardo’s figures seemed replete to some of his contemporaries, as if the paintings
contained the sum total of Renaissance artistic capabilities as well as a surplus—what
Vasari, in another context, called “grace”—but in terms of contemporary art they can
seem chained to a set of nearly immobile dogmas about proportion, motion, emotion,
light, and texture. It is reasonable to think that Freud’s idea that Leonardo fantasized a
penis shaken in his mouth would have been inconceivable to the artist, but the concept of
inconceivability works outside the assumptions of metapsychology. Both inconceivability
and unrepresentability are names for the necessary omissions—the blank stretches of
Preface, Introduction
51
paper between marks, the gaps and missing portions, the blind spots that the artist
doesn’t see—and as such they constitute all pictures. I have chosen to let them work
quietly throughout the book rather than making them explicit, in order to avoid
implying that the entire subject of pictured bodies can be reformulated as a negative
question of lack. The unpredictable peculiarities of pictures belie that. Yet if every picture
is a picture of the body, and if distortion is an adequate word for the means of
representation, then pictures are continuous refusals and repressions of the body: they are
ways of controlling the body by fixing an image of what it is not. The positive doctrines of
the pictured body, in that respect, are nothing more than shores against its ruins, and the
task of a history of the represented body is to say what has not been shown, and to explain
why it is absent.