Chapter 2
55
Psychomachia
Chapter 2
P s y c h om a c hi a
In brief, always and everywhere, the normal blond has
positive, dynamic, driving, aggressive, domineering,
impatient, active, quick, hopeful, speculative, changeable,
and variety-loving characteristics; while the normal
brunette has negative, static, conservative, imitative,
submissive, cautious, painstaking, patient, plodding, slow,
deliberate, serious, thoughtful, specializing characteristics.
— The Job, the Man, the Boss 1
Before it became popular in the humanities, semiology was a branch of medicine,
concerned with the ways that the body could be read. Like contemporary semiotics in art history,
medical semiology finds itself bound up with the impossible task of reading a seamless, organic
object in terms of discrete linguistic units. To the extent that art historical semiotics remains
within a narrow conception of semiotic operation, involving the search for certain kinds of
symbols and significant marks in pictures, it might find the wider variety of medical practices a
fruitful model. In a short list, the body has been read in at least a half–dozen methodologically
distinct ways:2
Katherine Blackford, The Job, the Man, the Boss (Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday, Page and Co.,
1914), quoted in William Armand Lessa, Landmarks in the Study of Human Types (New York:
Brooklyn College Press, 1942), 141.
2
The table is adapted from Lessa, Landmarks, op. cit., table I, pp. iv-vi. Semiotics in art history is
reviewed in my “Marks, Traces, Traits, Contours, Orli, and Splendores: Nonsemiotic Elements in
Pictures,” Critical Inquiry 21 (1995): 822–60.
1
Chapter 2
Doctrine
Humoralism
Physiognomy
Phrenology
Physiology
Anatomy
Somatotypology
Encyclopedic
semiology
56
Psychomachia
Typological key
Examples
The four humors: sanguine,
Hippocrates, Galen, Avicenna,
melancholic, phlegmatic, choleric
Sennert, Rivière, Laycock
Movements of the face
Polemo, Adamantius, Della Porta,
Lombroso, Morel
Cranial topography
Gall, Spurzheim, Combe, Fowler
Body systems: digestive, muscular,
Cabanis, Troisvèvre, Rostan,
Chaillou
respiratory, cerebral
Intestinal length, scapular form,
embryonic layers
Weight and dimensions of the
body
Syntheses of the above
Spiegel, Treves, Huter, Graves,
Beneke, Bean, Swaim
Näcke, Bauer, Kretschmer, Sheldon
Lichtenberg, Blackford, BurgerVillingen, Lessa
Table 3. Systems of medical semiology.3
Some sources, in order (the full list is in the original edition of this book, Stanford University
Press; the software will not permit a footnote this long): Hippocrates, The Genuine Works of
Hippocrates, translated by Francis Adams (London: Sydenham Society, 1849); R. E. Siegel, Galen
on Psychology, Psychopathology, and Function and Diseases of the Nervous System (Basel, 1973),
and Galen on the Passions and Errors of the Soul, trans. P. W. Harkings (Columbus, 1963);
Avicenna, A Treatise on the Canon of Medicine in Avicenna, translated by O. C. Gruner
(London, 1930); D. Sennert, Nine Books of Physick and Chirurgy Written by the Great and
Learned Physician Dr. Sonnertius (London, 1658); Lazaro Rivière, Opera medica universa. Editio
novissima; cui praeter Jacobi Grandii (Geneva: De Tournes, 1737); T. Laycock, “Clinical Lectures
on the Physiognomic Diagnosis of Disease,” Medical Times and Gazette 1 (1862): 1-3, 51-54, 101103, 151-54, 185, 205-208, 287-89, 341-44, 449-51, 499-502, 551-54, 635-37.
Antonius Polemo (c. 88–145 C.E.) Physiognomics, in Scriptores Physiognomici Graeci et Latini,
edited by Richard Förster (Leipzig: B. G. Teubner, 1893); Adamantius (4th c. A.D.),
3
Chapter 2
Psychomachia
57
It would not be difficult to augment and subdivide this chart, adding disciplines such as
dermatoglyphics (the study of skin folds), palmistry, and dactyloscopy (fingerprinting).
Metoposcopy (or metoscopy, or mesoposcopy), which began in the sixteenth century, is the
study of lines in the forehead.4 Iridology, the diagnosis of ailments by study of the patterns of the
iris, continues to be popular. (The illustration here is from Iridology Simplified, by Bernard
Physiognomics, in Ibid.; Giovan Battista Della Porta, De humana physiognomonia libri III (Vici
Aequensis, 1586); C. Lombroso, Le Crime: causes et remèdes (Paris, 1899), translated by H. P.
Horton as Crime: Its Causes and Remedies (Boston, 1912); Bénédict Auguste Morel, Traité des
dégénérescences physiques, intellectuelles et morales de l’espèce humaine (Paris: J. B. Baillière,
1857).
F. J. Gall, Philosophisch-medicinische Untersuchungen über Natur und Kunst im kranken und
gesunden Zustand des Menschen (Vienna, 1791); Johann Gaspar Spurzheim, Phrenology, third
Amercan edition (Boston: Marsh, Capeu, and Lyon, 1834); George Combe, Essays on Phrenology
(Edinburgh, 1819) andThe Constitution of Man (Edinburgh, 1828); O.S. and L. N. Fowler,
Phrenology—Proved, Illustrated, and Applied (New York, 1836).
4
The principal source is Girolamo Cardano, Metoscopia (1558); see also Giovan Battista Della
Porta, Metoposcopia, edited by Giovanni Aquilecchia (Naples: Istituto Suor Orsola Benincasa,
1990); Cavaliere Spontini, La metoposcopia (Venice, 1637); Philip Phinella, De metoposcopia
(Antwerp, 1648). For plates see Kurt Seligman, The Mirror of Magic (New York: Pantheon: 1948),
figs. 176–95; a plate from a 17th century manuscript on “mesoposcopy” is reproduced in Patrizia
Magli, “The Face and the Soul,” translated by Ughetta Lubin, in Fragments for a History of the
Human Body, op. cit., vol. 2, 112.
Chapter 2
58
Psychomachia
Jensen.) Symbolic gestures, such as
the right hand raised in benediction,
are another partial system that has
varied across cultures.5 Many of the
systems are incomplete or
specialized. In metoposcopy, for
example, folds above the eyebrows
are significant, but Venus’s necklaces
(folds in the neck), crow’s feet, and
other facial lines are not. (In this
picture, Mercury ☿ is the creases
between the eyebrows; the Sun ☉and
Moon ☽ are the first lines above the
eyebrows, and then some Venus ♀,
Mars ♂, Jupiter ♃, and Saturn ♄.)
Part of the face becomes a
text, and most remains a cipher—or
more exactly, a meaningless pattern.
Manuals of fingerprint analysis are
very precise about the “delta” the “loop,” the “core,” and other features, but say next to nothing
about palmprints.6 (Fingerprint classification is interesting and can be learned in an afternoon.)
Symbolic gestures are common in some settings, such as Roman reliefs and late medieval
narratives, but they are often omitted or ambiguous. Since all interpretations of pictured bodies
must employ some semiotic system, the this book might have been cast as a matter of negotiating
these and other ways of reading. But I would resist that because the most interesting and
Moshe Barash, Giotto and the Language of Gesture (New York: Cambridge University Press,
1987); Michael Baxandall, Painting and Experience in Fifteenth–Century Italy (London: Oxford
University Press, 1974); and Die Beredsamkeit der Liebes, Zur Körpersprache in der Kunst, edited
by Ilsebill Barta Fliedl and Christoph Giessmar, Veröffentlichung der Albertina no. 31 (Salzburg:
Residenz Verlag, 1992).
6
See the wonderful analysis of fingerprints in The Science of Fingerprints: Classification and Uses,
printed for the United States Department of Justice, Federal Bureau of Investigation
(Washington, DC: U. S. Government Printing Office, 1984), which includes instructions for
taking fingerprints from dead and decaying hands. Palm prints are mentioned last, pp. 207-11.
5
Chapter 2
59
Psychomachia
widespread systems are also the least amenable to rational exposition: metoposcopy and
fingerprint analysis are precise in their limited realms, but “expressive dermatology” is both
general and semiotically elusive: skin appears to have the capacity to express specific meaning,
even though it normally eludes any exact interpretation.
The subject this chapter is
another general semiotic system I
am calling psychomachia, by which I
mean expressive twistings and
turnings of the body—as opposed to
the expressive existence of the body,
which was part of my subject in the
first chapter. I take it that the two
principal examples, physiognomy
and contrapposto, together
constitute a basic field of
possibilities for meaningful motions
and positions of the depicted body. Physiognomy is an attempt at a semiotics of the face, and
contrapposto is a language of bodily motion. Deleuze marks the difference by calling the face a
“faciality machine,” capable only of generating facial effects, but I would hesitate to make a clear–
cut division, because there are so many other ways of reading the body that depend on divisions
within the body or the face.7 The existence of practices such as metoposcopy, which does not
apprehend the face as a single visual or linguistic field, shows the limitations of a general (and
largely non–visual) account such as Deleuze’s. Palmistry reads some lines, and metoposcopy and
dermatoglyphics read others, and none of them depends on the distinction between a “faciality
machine” and other mechanisms of meaning.
Still, the face as a whole is often separated from the (headless or faceless) body, and the
two subjects of this chapter are the places where theorization on those two regions has been most
acute and systematic. In accord with the different ways that the face and the body are said to
convey meaning, the semiotics of contrapposto and physiognomy are incompatible. In particular,
they reach their limits in different ways: physiognomy suffers because it tends to become too
Deleuze and Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus, op. cit., and Deleuze and Guattari, The Anti–
Oedipus, translated by Robert Hurley et al. (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1983).
For the concept of the face in China see Angela Zito, “Silk and Skin,” op. cit., 119–20. The
concept of the face in general is explored in my Object Stares Back, op. cit., chapter 5.
7
Chapter 2
Psychomachia
60
precise, too much like a language, and contrapposto fails because it is too vague—the body can
never quite convey determinate meaning without the support of narratives and symbols. Their
failures provide two models for art historical semiotics as it seeks to read the visual; in a larger
book, each of the other semiotic systems could also provide lessons in the ways that linguistic
constructions are bent, and finally broken, on the illegible surface of the body.
Assignment 1: create or find an artwork that analyzes the body according to iridology,
metoposcopy, dactyloscopy, or some other system. (We will come back to humoralism,
phrenology, and somatotypology, so don’t choose those.)
On the disconnection of
physiognomy and modernism
Although physiognomy (and its later sister
science, phrenology) is a dead issue in modernism
and postmodernism, it may be better to describe
the 20th and 21st centuries as anti-physiognomic
rather than non-physiognomic. Modern artists
were generally uninterested in what became known
as psychological poetraiture—or to put it in
premodern terms, telling the story of the soul on
the face—and even those few portraitists who can
be regarded as central to 20th century art (for
example Bacon, Picasso, and Beckmann) typically
do not belong to the tradition of psychological
portraiture that begins in the fifteenth century and
reaches a high water mark with Rembrandt.
Instead they are anti-psychological. Beckmann
gives us mask after mask, and never reveals
himself, as Rembrandt does even under his
theatrical costumes. Picasso quickly abandoned his
early experiments in using analytic cubism to express psychological nuance. The pschologically
odd portraits he attempted around 1910–11 are enough to show that cubism and this tradition of
portraiture are an unhappy mixture, and that fact, apart from any other, may be decisive for the
Chapter 2
61
Psychomachia
twentieth century’s rejection of
psychological portraiture.8 Our
distance from psychological
portraiture can be brought out by a
look at an artist who believed in it,
and founded his practice on
physiognomic criteria.
As Rudolf Wittkower
emphasized, Gian Lorenzo Bernini
was once “the brightest star” of the
constellation of seventeenth
century artists that also includes
Caravaggio, Rembrandt, Velázquez
and Poussin.9 Given the immense
industry that art history has
become, it is always risky to call an
artist underappreciated, but at least
for undergraduate courses Bernini
gets perhaps a little less than the
usual summary appreciation.
Students hear of his
accomplishments as a litany of formal breakthroughs: in Wittkower’s words the “choice of a
transitory moment, the breaking down of restrictions imposed by the block, the elimination of
different spheres for sculpture and spectator, and intense realism and subtle differentiation of
texture”—but somehow he does not often come alive to contemporary students or contemporary
artists. Yet his is certainly not an instance of that slow, gentle slide into oblivion that is the fate of
lesser artists—for example his near-contemporary, the elegant, taciturn Du Quesnoy, who was
also once ranked with Michelangelo.
I suggest that Bernini’s physiognomic practices can help account for his current absence
from some lists of essential artists. The majority of his portraits adhere to the physiognomic
Hans Dieter Junker, “Picassos Kunsthändlerporträts von 1910,” in “Was sind wir Menschen
doch!…” Menschen im Bild. Analysen, Hermann Hinkel zum 60. Geburtstag, edited by Dietrich
Grünewald (Weimar: Verlag und Datenbank für Geisteswissenschaften, 1995), 41-50.
9
Wittkower, Gian Lorenzo Bernini, third edition (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1981), 7.
8
Chapter 2
Psychomachia
62
tradition, which enjoins artists to depict
expressions in the mid-range of human beauty and
emotion, avoiding ugliness and caricature.
Relatively little of Bernini’s work has the kind of
physiognomic excess we tend to find congenial.
When he wants to depict a violent emotion, he
tends to explore formulaically contorted facial
expressions: the Condemned Soul (Anima dannata,
c. 1619) grimaces wildly, and the Neptune (1620)
has a raggedly determined face. Bernini had a few
precedents for these distorted faces—he was
thinking of Hellenistic sculpture, the Carracci, and
early Caravaggio—but he tempered the excesses of
Hellenistic and Caravaggesque work by adhering to
the ideals of physiognomic balance and decorum
that are so much forgotten in the twentieth–
century.
It may be that we do not respond as strongly as we might because to a late modern
sensibility, truly extreme emotions—those that express what we take to be the greater horrors of
the 20th century—cannot be conveyed by tragic masks or
simple grimaces.10 Just as the Laocöon no longer moves us
(even though it shows a man and his two sons being killed
by enormous snakes), so Bernini’s efforts at emotional
extremes seem more contrived than passionate.11 Since
German expressionism, the most intense suffering has not
been directly represented; instead it has been conceived as
something entirely off the scale of possibilities that facial
muscles afford: beyond the classical woe of the Laocöon are
10
See Moshe Barash, “The Tragic Face: The Classical Mask of the Tragic Hero, and Expression of
Character and Emotion in Renaissance Art,” and “‘Pathos Formulae’: Some Reflections on the
Structure of a Concept,” Imago Hominis, Studies in the Language of Art, Bibliotheca Artibus et
Historiae (Vienna: IRSA, 1991) 59–77 and 119–27 respectively.
11
Simon Richter, Laocoon’s Body and the Aesthetics of Pain: Winckelmann, Lessing, Herder,
Moritz, Goethe (Detroit, Mich.: Wayne State University Press, 1992).
Chapter 2
Psychomachia
63
the desolate blank masks of Kirchner’s
young girls. We have come to expect
great suffering to be shown to us by
bodily distortions and not silly
grimaces. After all, a wince may be the
same whether it is in reaction to a
stubbed toe or an amputated leg. I
think we have developed a triple
distrust of Baroque physiognomy: we
don’t feel that emotions come in
measured varieties; we wouldn’t risk
depicting a strong emotion by a
grimace that might look trivial; and we
are rarely satisified to remain in the
gray areas between the extremes, where
passions are muted, mixed, and calmed
by reflection and a sense of balance. A
fourth obstacle is Bernini’s idea, which
he held in common with
physiognomists of the time, that faces should exhibit emotions that can be interpreted as “anger,”
“frustration,” “sorrow,” and other common states. It is not an accident that the recent scholarship
on seventeenth-century portraiture almost entirely
eschews affective description in favor of economic,
biographical, or formal questions. We prefer illegible
complexity in faces, even though we have lost all
confidence in our ability to put even a little of that
complexity into words.
As a science, physiognomy has entirely vanished:
not only do current art historians and artists not believe it,
they do not care about it, and contemporary artworks that
concern the face avoid implying recoverable or specific
psychological meaning. The 20th century was immoderate
and skeptical. Yet physiognomy remains central to
figurative painting despite these differences, because no
Chapter 2
Psychomachia
64
one can entirely disbelieve that the face is a text for what lies behind it. In order to carry on even
the most rudimentary conversation, I have to be able to look at a person and make a rough guess
about what that person is like. And because physiognomics in this general sense remains
necessary, it stands to reason that the fund of ideas we apply to our informal decryptions comes
from traditions of interpretation that are already in place: that is, from physiognomics. The old
doctrines are arguably more important than ever because they are only half known. When
physiognomy flourished, at least it was possible to question a given reading, and to come to a
working agreement about what some expressions mean. Contemporary artists read and create
faces without noticing that the potential and the limitations of psychological portraiture are
largely inherited from the Renaissance and Baroque physiognomists.
Physiognomic awkwardnesses
Like the other semiological systems, physiognomy
and phrenology raise fundamental questions: Since the face is
not inscribed with letters, how can it be read as if it were a
text? In what way does it exhibit signs or propositions about
the soul beneath? To ask these questions is to inquire about
physiognomy from the inside: that is, to ask the kinds of
questions that the eighteenth century doctors asked
themselves. Johann Caspar Lavater’s admittedly fragmentary
Essays on Physiognomy (originally called the Physiognomische
Fragmente) is the principal document in this history, the
closest the science came to producing a standard reference.12
As with so much of physiognomy, an initial problem with reading Lavater is that he is
difficult to take seriously. I do not say this carelessly: even the physiognomists had their doubts
Lavater, Essays on Physiognomy, edited by Thomas Holloway, translated by Henry Hunter
(London: John Murray, 1792). The Faces of Physiognomy: Interdisciplinary Approaches to Johann
Caspar Lavater, edited by Ellis Shookman (Columbia, South Carolina: Camden House, 1983);
Flavio Caroli, Storia della Fisiognomica: Arte e psicologia da Leonardo a Freud (Milan: Arnoldo
Mondadori, 1995); and Norbert Borrmann, Kunst und Physiognomik: Menschendeutung und
Menschendarstellung im Abendland (Cologne: DuMont, 1994), are helpful studies. For the
history of reception see John Graham, Lavater’s Essays on Physiognomy, A Study in the History of
Ideas. European University Studies, series 18, Comparative Literature, vol. 18. (Berne: Peter
Lang, 1979).
12
Chapter 2
65
Psychomachia
about their enterprise—they realized it was unreliable, potentially misleading, and “fragmentary.”
Despite its voluminousness, Lavater’s work is repeatedly silly. He tries to read parts of bodies
other than faces, and he even interprets the emotions of snakes, queen bees and worker bees,
flies, mosquitoes, and fish. Of fish number three at the upper right, for example, he comments
dryly, “what stupidity in the
mouth… and particularly in
its relation to the eye.”
Lavater does not credit the
“Sea-horse” or “monster” at
the bottom—a hippo—with
much intelligence. He finds it
“destitute” of gentleness and
tenderness, and says its
mouth and teeth are “stupid,
ignoble, [and] insensible,
made for devouring without the pleasure of enjoying,” and in sum “the throat of the Sea-horse is
a profound and horrible gulph, formed only to crush and swallow.”13
Lavater also studied parts of the face, including birthmarks and even warts, and he warns
that women with hairy warts on their chins are industrious but also “amorous to [the point of]
folly.” He recommends that the right way to treat them is with “a mildly cold dignity of
demeanor.”14 Physiognomy is always cousin to caricature: it is inseparable from inadvertent
humor, even when the physiognomists try to use humor to make their points.15 Vaught’s
Lavater, Essays on Physiognomy, op. cit., vol. 2, p. 126. The hippopotamus comes in for an even
harsher attack in the unabridged original: “Die entsetzliche gleichfortgehende Breite der Stirn
und Nase—oder vielmehr der Nasenlöcher und des Mauls—welch ein Ausdruck von
dummwilder Unerbittlichkeit—und dann die Unregelmäßigkeit in der Positur und Figur der
Zähne—welch eigentlicher Charakter, teuflischer doch planloser, sich selbst zerstörender
Bosheit!” Lavater, Physiognomische Fragmente (Leipzig: Weidmanns Erben und Reich, 1777), vol.
3, p. 76.
14
Lavater, quoted by Lessa, Landmarks in the Science of Human Types, op. cit., 6.
15
On caricature see E. H. Gombrich, [ ]; Devin Burnell, “Art and Ambiguity: The Aesthetics of
Caricature Considered in Relation to Nineteenth Century Romanticism and to the Work of
Daumier,” PhD dissertation, University of Chicago, 1976, unpublished; and Maren Gröning,
“Groteske Kopfe,” in Die Beredsamkeit des Leibes: Zur Körpersprache in der Kunst, edited by
Ilsebill Barta Fliedl and Christoph Geissmar, Veröffentlichung der Albertina no. 31 (Salzburg:
Residenz Verlag, 1992), 100-12.
13
Chapter 2
Psychomachia
66
Practical Character Reader, published in Chicago in 1902,
is full of inventive phrenological and physiognomical
caricatures. The drawings are humorous mnemonics,
serving the very serious purpose of inculcating awareness
of the significance of skull contours. “The psychological
railway” helps readers remember that a bump on the
forehead indicates good powers of thought, because
Boston is “the thought center of the country.” A lump in
back of the head indicates “Amativeness”; and because
Salt Lake City is the center of Mormonism, the text urges:
“What faculty better represents polygamy?” Other cities
are identified by their economic specialties. “Chicago’s
two dominant characteristics are pig–sticking and
money–making. She is well represented by the two elements, Destructiveness and
Acquisitiveness.” By similar logic, Milwaukee represents “Alimentiveness,” and Pittsburgh
“Constructiveness.”16 The author is joking, but also bringing out the unintentional, and
unavoidable, humor of the phrenological enterprise itself. Both Lavater and the early
phrenologists are ironic at certain moments, and their apparent naïveté may be partly a strategy
for stifling the corrosive silliness of the new sciences.
On the other hand, physiognomy balances this comedy with a desire of great moment—
the daily necessity of reading peoples’ souls on their faces. Physiognomy has a universal purpose,
but beyond the most basic, self-evident propositions, it becomes counter–intuitive. Why did the
physiognomists compound the passions into unlikely concatenations—such as Lavater’s faces
denoting “violence, tempered by cowardice and malice aforethought” or “candor, innocence and
weakness”? At one point Lavater considers a series of nearly indistinguishable faces, and reads
“an insufferable countenance, an absurd mixture of foolish terror and factitious rage,” a man who
is “furious, passionate, vulgar, and ungovernable,” another whose face exhibits “the excess of rage
of a low man, suffering, and divested of energy,” one who shows “the fury of a fool under
flagellation,” and one who displays “a mixture of greatness and triviality—the grimace of a fool
L. A. Vaught, Vaught’s Practical Character Reader, revised edition, with a preface by Emily
Vaught (Chicago: Vaught–Rocind, 1902), 171–72.
16
Chapter 2
67
Psychomachia
and an idiot.” It is no wonder that Mirabeau thought Lavater was a “bizarre mixture of dementia
and wit, ignorance and knowledge”—itself a very Lavaterian diagnosis.17
Part of the reason for physiognomy’s eclipse may have to do with the way that the
emotions were imagined in the late seventeenth and early eighteenth centuries, as discrete
faculties and “passions” rather than subtle moods. In this respect it is significant that in
eighteenth–century novels, passions were still perceived as types, and the mercurial moods of the
Sturm und Drang movement had not yet surfaced. But another way to answer the question has to
do with the face itself, and its difference from writing. The signs of writing must be clearly
separate from one another: they depend on what Jean–François Lyotard and others have called
oppositionality or distinctness.
The conviction that the face may
be a different kind of sign, one
capable of holding a number of
signs in fluid suspension, may
derive from our habits of
associating peoples’ names (as
distinct signifiers) with their
faces (as indistinct signifiers).
When I think of a person’s name
as I look at her face, the face
seems to express a great deal of
what that person has come to
mean, without my being able to
condense any of it to a single
phrase or description. But
physiognomy cannot
comprehend such an unspecific
interpretation. If a face contains
an encrypted lexeme, and its corresponding meaning—its sememe—is more intricate than an
emotion such as violence or candor, physiognomy cannot dissect the sign into the wider range of
emotions we might expect. There is no warrant for it in the face.
Honoré-Gabriel-Victor de Riquetti, Comte de Mirabeau, Lettre du comte de Mirabeau à M…
sur M. M. Cagliostro et Lavater (Berlin, 1786), quoted in J. Baltrusaitis, Aberrations, An Essay on
the Legend of Forms, translated by Richard Miller (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1989), 49.
17
Chapter 2
68
Psychomachia
Physiognomy failed because it couldn’t suppress its unintended humor, and because the
physiognomists clung to a simple model of namable emotions, avoiding the real complexity of
even the most ordinary states of
mind. A deeper reason for its demise
may have to do with the pictorial
nature of the face itself. A face that
blends too many emotions is
palimpsestic and unreadable. It is not
longer a text, but—in an exemplary
way—a picture, a portrait that has no
verbal equivalent. The coherence we
demand of faces and people may be a
model for the coherence we ask of
artistic styles: all are holistic forms
that retain a sense of structure and an
inconsistent aura of individual
elements.18 I tend to accept the
features of a person’s face as signs of
a single personality without being
entirely conscious of what forms I am
counting as elements, or what
principles govern their coherence.
What matters is the sliding sense that
there is a structure or a set of
elements, and that the elements do
not need to be experienced
separately. The same kind of partly illogical apprehension governs the experience of artistic style,
where the elements of the work are present and yet blurred, and their principle of coherence is
partly articulable and partly not. In this way style, personality, and the construction of the face
meet on a common ground of incomplete clarity and coherence.
This is argued, partly following E. H. Gombrich, in my “Style,” The Dictionary of Art (New
York, Grove Dictionaries, 1996).
18
Chapter 2
Psychomachia
69
Physiognomy also encounters the kinds of problems any reading finds when it does not
know how or when to stop.19 Are noses and ears significant? Are they texts in the same sense as
the mouth, or the eyes? And if not, by what
metalanguage do we understand that we
should cease reading the face at a certain
point, and begin seeing it as a meaningless
pattern of forms? Lavater thought features
like noses and ears are meaningful, but he
said that it would not be appropriate to put
much weight on their interpretation.20
Many physiognomists have been less
circumspect. In the images of noses very
large nostrils (top) are said to denote
insatiable sensuality, small nostrils (middle)
are the sign of a volatile sensuality, while
those that are broad in back and narrow
toward the front (bottom) signify a capacity
to compensate for sensuality. (Lessing, the
authors add, possessed this third and best
type of nostril, and Mme. de Staël had
unusually large nostrils.)21
A fourth problem with physiognomy, aside from its unintentional humor, its mechanical
model of the emotions, and its misguided hope that the face works like a text, is its dependence
on departures from a mean. Since physiognomy is the study of passions, it equates expression
with facial forms that are not normal. In order to be meaningful, a feature has to stand out (like a
hairy eyebrow) or move (like a furrowed, hairy eyebrow). A zero-degree face, one that is average
in all respects and at rest, becomes unreadable by definition. Pierre Klossowski echoes this
Stafford, “‘Peculiar Marks’: Lavater and the Countenance of Blemished Thought,” Art Journal
46 (1987): 185–92.
20
For Lavater on noses, see Eleonora Louis, “Der beredte Leib, bilder aus der Sammlung Lavater,”
in Die Beredsamkeit des Leibes, op. cit., 113-55, especially 134.
21
R. Burger-Villingen and Walter Nöthling, Das Geheimnis der Menschenform, Lehrbuch der
Menschenkenntnis auf Grund der Anlagenfeststellung (Wuppertal: Barger–Verlag, 1958), 272–73.
See also Harold M. Holden, Noses (Cleveland and New York: World Publishing Company, 1950).
19
Chapter 2
Psychomachia
70
eighteenth–century quandary when he writes of the body in terms of its resemblance to a
“demonic” ideal outside all possible bodies.22 The problem of the zero–degree face accounts for
physiognomists’ anxiety about
depicting deception and
falsehood, and it suggests that
the semiotic system of
physiognomy wavers when it
comes to faces that are marked
by the absence of traits rather
than their presence. The
contemporary interest in these
zero-degree faces, mainly
associated with artists like Thomas Ruff and Jaume Plensa,
and poses the same problem: is an expressionless face
potentially a profound reservoir of many half-glimpsed
emotions, or is it a blank, registering only vacancy?
In principle, a physiognomist would have no problem
depicting a purely evil face, because it would have to possess
all manner of facial distortions, asymmetries, and tics. In
practice, it proved difficult to imagine what Judas (drawing on
the previous page), or the Devil, could have looked like, because each distorted feature could be
further distorted, ad infinitum. But even average faces presented difficulties. Usually Lavater
describes mediocrity in negative terms, concentrating on what it is not, as in his figures labeled as
“incapable of greatness,” and his gallery of less than noble people. Sometimes he waxes eloquent
on the defects of ordinary people. The text to this plate is a typical, inadvertently funny example:
22
Klossowski, La rassemblance (Paris: Ryôan–ji, 1984).
Chapter 2
Psychomachia
71
1 The physiognomy of a man of intensity and courage, in whom you may confide;
but at the same time an ordinary face, destitute of sagacity and elevation. The
want of greatness is particularly visible in the point of the nose.
2 The face of a groveling, sordid, cunning wretch. Though he be at present a very
contracted being, his natural dispositions rendered him abundantly capable of
instruction. Without being positively wicked, he is become contemptible through
weakness and want of cultivation; and, in his actual state, presents a total want of
honor and internal energy.
3 Impotent coquetry. The eye is strongly expressive of passion—the mouth, of
weakness bordering on folly.
4 This face is neither great nor energetic—but it indicates a man possessed of
considerable talents, susceptible of taste and instruction, capable of reflection,
without the power of profound investigation.
5 The forehead, if I may use the expression, has not yet arrived at full maturity;
and, considered with relation to the mouth, is not sufficiently furrowed, it is too
childish. It is unnecessary to observe, that this is the profile of a changeling,
indolent and good-natured: the imbecility is chiefly resident in the under lip,
which advances far too much.23
If normalcy is difficult for physiognomics, then pure, untainted goodness is nearly
impossible. What could mark could identify a face that is unstained by any thought of evil? The
face of the Savior, of an angel, of a naïve and pious boy, spell trouble for physiognomy. Lavater’s
plate of “Weakness Innocence and Goodness,” for instance, gives us something less than a real
person: the boy’s face is a little embryonic, as if something were missing. But Lavater loves it:
23
Lavater, Essays on Physiognomy, op. cit., vol. 2, p. 85.
Chapter 2
Psychomachia
72
“what heart,” he says, “does not feel itself moved and attracted?” Physiognomy forces the strange
equation of divinity—the culmination of all good qualities—and the tabula rasa.24
Assignment 2: physiognomics and the psychological portrait. Find a portrait, from any
culture, that you can interpret with the help of these concepts. It may be a psychological
portrait, in the European tradition, or a blank expressionless face in the postmodern
manner. If it’s a psychological portrait, try analyzing it the way Lavater might have: read
into the features whatever mindset you feel the person must have had.
Conceptual problems with reading the face
These four points are all questions that physiognomists put to themselves, and they
contributed to the gradual decay of the discipline at the end of the eighteenth century.
Lavater, Essays on Physiognomy, op. cit., vol. 1, p. 184. For the connection between this problem
and signs “incapable of being misunderstood,” see Stafford, Body Criticism, 92–93.
24
Chapter 2
Psychomachia
(Phrenology continued, mainly in
America, through the nineteenth
century.25) Physiognomy was always
a fragile science, doomed by its own
practitioners as much by its
sometimes brilliant critics.26 Lavater
was unsure from the very beginning:
the Physiognomische Fragmente
opens by quoting an anonymous
critic who says physiognomy is
unreliable. At the same time, we
know that there must be some
connection between thoughts (or
the soul, or the mind) and the face.
Haven’t we all looked at people and
decided they were “childish,”
“ordinary,” or even “wretches” or
“idiots”? If we are to reject all the
trappings of the Enlightenment
“science,” what are we left with?
What can a face say, if it cannot say
anything reliable or determinate?
Things only get more
slippery if the people we’re trying to
understand are putting on faces in
order to deceive us. A twentieth–
century physiognomic study of the
“mimetic diagnostic” of faked
emotions is a case in point.27 Since
See for example Philippe Sorel, “Le phrénologie et l’art,” in L’âme au corps: arts et sciences
1793-1993, exh. cat., edited by Jean Clair (Paris: Réunion des musées nationaux, 1993), 266-79.
26
Georg Christoph Lichtenberg, Über Physiognomik, wider die Physiognomen, op. cit.
27
Philipp Lersch, Gesischt und Seele, Grundlinien einer mimischen Diagnostik, third edition
(Munich and Basel: E. Reinhardt, 1951 [1932]).
25
73
Chapter 2
Psychomachia
74
the author is concerned with acting problems, he is acutely aware of the difficulty of reading
sincerity in expressions. But this is not merely a problem of coaching actors, since it casts doubt
on the entire possibility of interpreting faces. We can often tell insincere expressions in life—but
are there rules for that ability? The girl in the photo at the beginning of
this chapter is supposedly responding involuntarily to the sound of a
tuning fork—or is she play-acting, like some of Charcot’s patients? And
what about cases of pathological degeneration or psychosis, when the
facial expressions have broken free from their moorings in the mind?28
How can physiognomists determine when people aren’t sincere, so that
they can rescind their interpretive claims?
Certainly we have reason to be skeptical of systematic connections
between mind and face. In medieval epics, gestures were “psychophysical”: the gesture meant the
passion, and even though the heart was hidden—in accord with the doctrine of the occulta
cordis—“symbolical connections remained between the body and soul, and facial expressions
were a sign of this connection.”29 But the division between the “inner man” (homo exterior) and
“outer man” (homo interior) has been remarked since the Renaissance, and the fall of
physiognomy has only accentuated the difficulty of linking those two terms.30 It is interesting in
this respect that physiognomy does not only demand that there is a connection between the
motions of the mind and the movements of the face—it also requires that the homo exterior and
interior remain at some distance from one another. As long as the soul has strings that allow it to
move the body, and as long as the eyes remain windows to the soul, mind and skin are connected
but separate, and even when the body moves the soul—as when a deformity propels a man
toward evil—the two are still distinct. But physiognomy does not allow for a soul and body that
are inextricable, or are a single thing, or are unaccountably divorced. It seems to me that the
deepest criticism of physiognomy comes from this source. If the soul and face are taken to be
inseparable, then the cause and effect relation that physiognomy posits might be erased or
reversed.
28
See also H. Lamy, “Note sur les contractions «synergiques paradoxales» observées à la suite de
la paralysie faciale périphérique,” Nouvelle Iconographie de la Salpêtrière 18 (1905): 424-25.
29
L. J. Friedman, “Occulta Cordis,” Romance Philology 11 (1957–58): 103–19; C. Guillén, op. cit.,
306. “Psychophysical” comes from L. Spitzer, “Le vers 834 du Roland,” Romania 68 (1944–45):
471–77.
30
Claudio Guillén, “On the Concept and Metaphor of Perspective,” in Literature as System,
Essays Toward the Theory of Literary History (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1971), pp.
306-307.
Chapter 2
Psychomachia
75
To say that physiognomy reads the face is to conceive part of the skin of the face as a text,
and though that is a fruitful metaphor, is not entirely adequate. If we can continue to understand
peoples’ expressions with some confidence, and if we still feel we can interpret the subtle moods
and tendencies of mind depicted in the best psychological portraiture, it is not because
something inside is writing on something outside. The relation of the two is more intimate, and
physiognomics might ultimately be the name for a mechanical misunderstanding of the
inextricable relation between them.
The analytic of contrapposto
The plasticity of the physiognomic sign finds its general form in the expressive
movements of the body that are still properly known as contrapposto.31 Like physiognomics,
contrapposto remains centrally important for figural art, even though it is seldom taught outside
of Renaissance and Baroque art history. Beginning in the mid–15th century, and continuing
through the plurifacial figures of the late sixteenth century such as those by Ammannati and
Giovanni da Bologna, artists explored the possible motions of the human form, pushing it farther
and farther toward the thresholds of pain or fantasy. Taken together, those achievements still
provide a catalogue of possible bodily positions that can only be repeated or exaggerated by
contemporary artists. Even images made by pressing the body directly against the canvas or
paper, including Yves Klein’s sexist “anthropometries” to Jasper Johns’s self-impressions, stand
directly in the tradition of contrapposto.32 As the skin stretches and compresses to fit the flat
surface, and the body either twists and rolls (as in Yves Klein’s figures, which echo poses from
Renaissance painting) or it pushes straight onto the canvas, the floor, or the paper (as in Jasper
John’s images).33 Even Annie Sprinkle’s Tit Prints are the unpredictable progeny of frontal poses,
Two principal sources are John Pope-Hennessey, The Study and Criticism of Italian Sculpture
(New York: Metropolitan Museum of Art, 1980), and David Summers, “Contrapposto [ ],” The
Art Bulletin 59 (1977): 336-61.
32
Sidra Stich, Yves Klein, exh. cat. (Cologne: Ludwig Museum, 1995), especially
“Anthropometries,” pp. 171-91; for Johns’s “Studies for Skin” (1962) see Jasper Johns: A
Retrospective, edited by Kirk Varnedoe, with an essay by Roberta Bernstein (New York: Museum
of Modern Art, 1996), 23-24, pl. 91; I thank Roberta Bernstein for bringing Johns’s impressions
to my attention.
33
For the Mandylion and related images see Hans Belting, Likeness and Presence, A History of the
Image before the Era of Art, translated by Edmund Jephcott (Chicago: University of Chicago
31
Chapter 2
76
Psychomachia
portraits, and impressions. Even the most distorted figures, like some of Tracey Emin’s, rehearse
the range of poses found in European art. There is no escape from the repertoire of poses first
theorized in the Renaissance, and so
it becomes crucially important to
acknowledge and explore
contrapposto’s original meanings, in
order to see what they might
contribute to new explorations of
the figure.
The history of contrapposto
begins with an injunction about its
limits, defining it in terms of what it
is not. Leon Battista Alberti’s De
pictura enjoins that a figure should
not twist more than “shoulder over
navel,” both because it is impossible,
and because it is inappropriate (non
condicente).34 In another passage Alberti says that a figure should be balanced, and if it raises its
right leg, it should also raise its left arm. These simple definitions are the seeds of the later
Renaissance understanding of contrapposto, because they introduce contrapposto as something
that expresses both the normal limits of the body and of expressive decorum. At the same time,
we should not overlook the particular examples Alberti gives. The second is a matter of balance,
and it conjures dancing or marching figures; but the first is a strange exercise that pits the torso
against itself. As opposed to dancing or balancing, twisting can be futile and even unpleasant, and
it can express a body badly reconciled with itself. Contrapposto has these two strains throughout
Press, 1994), 208–24. Recent artists who have made body prints include Günter Brus and Doug
Prince. For Prince see William Ewing, The Body: Photographs of the Human Form (San
Francisco: Chronicle Books, 1994), 370-71; and for Brus in relation to Klein and others, see Silvia
Eiblmayr, Die Frau als Bild: Der weibliche Körper in der Kunst des 20. Jahrhunderts (Frankfurt am
Main: Reimer, 1993), especially “Von der symbolischen Bildzerstörung bis zur aktionistischen
Inszenierung des Körpers als Bild: Masson, Fontana, Wiener Aktionismus (Brus), pp. 97-105.
Body impressions are also discussed in Frauen Körper Kunst, exh. cat., Frankfurt am Main,
Hochschule für Musik und Darstellende Kunst, edited by Martina Peter-Bolaender (Kassel:
Furore, 1994).
34
Alberti, De Pictura
Chapter 2
Psychomachia
77
the Renaissance: one dances, and the other
deforms. The difference can be seen in a
stock-in-trade comparison from midtwentieth century art history: the two
competition reliefs for the doors of the
Florence Baptistery by Ghiberti and
Brunelleschi. Ghiberti (below) offers a
relaxed demonstration of his skill, close to
the dancing definition of contrapposto. His
Abraham sways gently in a C-curve.
Brunelleschi (left) offers several tautly
knotted contrapposti, including the
classical figure of the spinario (at the lower
left), the boy who removes a thorn from his
foot. The difference between the two is
sometimes put in terms of the two
competitors’ fidelity to the emerging Renaissance: Ghiberti’s slightly swaying contrapposti are
said to echo the late medieval International Style, and Brunelleschi’s are said to be more
normatively Roman (he also reproduces the
antique spinario, the boy pulling a thorn from his
foot). Those historical connections can also be
read as the poles of Alberti’s bifurcated definition
of contrapposto: the one denotes the pleasure of
dance and free movement, and the other
expresses the displeasure of the body turning
against itself.
It may be that Alberti did not want his
viewers to make a connection between the
figures’ turns and their implied mental states (or
the artists’ mental states), no matter how “overly
excited” (troppo fervente et furioso) they might
be.35 Various injunctions in De Pictura may be
35
D. Summers, “Contrapposto,” op. cit., 341.
Chapter 2
78
Psychomachia
read as further definitions of the limits of judicious contrapposto, including his reservations
about “panache,” speed, and facility of execution (sprezzatura) and of judicious variety (varietà).
But Alberti’s thoughts on the subject are less important than the ways they developed in the
following two centuries, where the connection became integral to the effect. The formal laws of
contrapposto may be read as an expressive vocabulary of the body, and for that reason they are
worth looking at in detail. What I am calling dancing contrapposto the Renaissance has three
canonical laws, which may be read as laws of balance, division, and constraint:
(1) Balance: Alberti’s law of equal and opposite motion. If the limbs respond to one
another in mirror reflection, so that when one arm is back the other is forward, then the body
becomes a balancing act. This is not the usual way we imagine our bodies: it has more to do with
artificial feats such as standing with one leg lifted high in the air. The fifteenth century examples
of these balancing acts are showpieces for the special properties of painting, which can represent
even the heaviest figures frozen in mid–
flight, or perching on a single toe. The
artificiality of this concept of balance
made it ineffective as a general strategy.
(2) Division: the rule of the Standbein
and Spielbein. A second law, which
meliorates the first, requires that one leg
bear the figure’s weight (the Standbein),
while another one trails ahead, behind,
or to one side (the Spielbein). (Shown
here in Andrea del Castagno’s portrait
of Dante.) This injunction has a
particular meaning in the language of
psychomachia. When part of a figure
bears weight, and part is nearly but not
completely weightless, the figure is
divided against itself in an especially
unstable manner. Renaissance
sculptures tend to exaggerate the
normal habit of standing that favors
one leg over the other, and the poses
they adopt involve a variable light touch
Chapter 2
Psychomachia
79
on the Spielbein. If I stand upright, and shift the majority of my weight onto one foot, while
letting the other just touch the ground, I can feel myself divide into two sets of muscles: one set
works hard to hold me upright,
and the other is kept subtly
tensed so that the Spielbein can
remain in place. I can feel the
muscles of the Spielbein pull and
relax as they attempt to
maintain the leg’s position. It is
much easier, but not in the
Renaissance spirit, either to have
the Standbein carry all the
weight and let the Spielbein rest
against it, toe down (as many
people naturally stand), or else
to stand symmetrically, so that
each foot has about half the
weight. (Only a few Renaissance
images opt for that very
common pose, for example
Castagno’s David in the
National Gallery, Washington,
who stands confidently, feet
apart and almost equally
weighted.) In Renaissance
sculpture the body is usually
hard at work maintaining a
difficult balance between those
two more reasonable
possibilities. Michelangelo’s David is one of the best examples: to hold the David’s pose, it is
necessary to plant the Standbein (the figure’s right foot), preferably by wedging the heel against a
support (in the David, the heel is clamped in the double trunk of a tree stump). Then with the
Standbein secured, extend the Spielbein, raise the heel slightly and curl the toes, pressing lightly
down onto the ground so that the body does not cant to the opposite site. The pose is remarkably
Chapter 2
Psychomachia
80
unnatural, taut, and uncomfortable,
and it brilliantly expresses the half–
rigid, tentative state of mind that
the figure appears to evince.
Donatello’s bronze David in the
Bargello (c. 1430) does the same
exquisite balancing act, this time
with less force and more obviously
sexual meaning. Both poses are
nearly impossible to hold: half the
body becomes exhausted
cantilevering the other half, and
then the body begins to tremble
with the effort of mingling forceful
tension and delicate balance.
(3) Constraint: the plumb
line rule. In some Renaissance
theory there is also a median or
plumb line that drops from the pit
of the neck, through the center of
gravity, and down to the weightbearing Standbein. From the second
law, we learn that a figure should
not stand straight up (to use the odd
modern expression, it should not stand “foursquare”), but at the same time it must employ this
geometric law of balance. For that reason figures that are disposed according to the plumb line
rule look tend to look constrained, if not off–balance, and it is rare that the pit of the neck is over
one ankle. In addition, the line tends not to bisect the figure, so that it looks lopsided in relation
to the figure’s outline. In pictures where the plumb line can still be seen, such as Masaccio’s
Tribute Money in the Brancacci Chapel (where plumb lines were scored in the wet intonaco
plaster) the effect—looking at the figure together with its plumb line—is unbalanced and
awkward. Standing farther back, so that the plumb line is invisible, the figures begin to appear
more natural. This disharmony between the plumb line and the figure is important because it
shows that contrapposto contains a principle of constraint, as well as of balance and division.
Chapter 2
Psychomachia
81
The other contrapposto, which I will call the twisting contrapposto, also has several rules,
which were elaborated in the late sixteenth century:
(1) The taper: the rule of decreasing energy. The figura serpentinata is defined in two
passages in Lomazzo’s Ideal del tempo nella pittura, and in the first he uses four similes to
describe what he means.36 The figure, he says, is like a pyramid, or flames, or serpents, or Sshapes. Each is a tapering form, strong and wide at its base and attenuated near its tip. Lomazzo
also says that the pyramid can be upright or inverted, opening the way for figures that are
spindle-shaped and swell in the middle. What is important here is less the exact form of the
taper—Lomazzo is rather diffuse in his descriptions and metaphors—but the concept of tapering,
so that the body is imagined as possessing a relatively stable center of motion, with twists are
applied to give it motion. The “serpentinated figure” (figura serpentinata) is a stable form, the
figura, which has been attenuated into a flame or a serpent, serpentinata. The center is protected,
36
Lomazzo, Ideal del tempo nella pittura
Chapter 2
82
Psychomachia
and the unprotected margins of the body flail around it. Although the full figure is the normal
model for this structure, it can occur in limbs as well—for instance in the fingers of the Magdalen
in Grünewald’s Isenheim Altarpiece (previous page), or the feet of Jesus, whose toes almost twist
free even though the rest of the body is nearly rigid. (The taper ends with an inverted “flame” of
blood, which falls in ropes—themselves twisted—from the toes to the ground.)
(2) The helix: the law of turning.
The pyramid, flames, serpents, and Sshapes are names of things that spiral
against some center or weighted axis,
and in that they are different from the
helix, which turns endlessly and with no
resistance or diminution. When a
contrapposto is imagined as a helix, the
model is probably a twisted column,
whose turns are artificially terminated at
the top and bottom rather than
organically spent like a serpent’s coils,
or physically exhausted like a candle
flame. A column can spiral gently,
without the force or energy of snakes or
flames. Quintilian was thinking more of
helices in this sense than of tapering turns when he wrote about “that curve, I might almost call it
motion,” that “gives an impression of… animation… grace and charm.”37
(3) The multiplied twist: the rule of figures “multiplied by one, two, and three.” After he
mentions flames and S-shapes, Lomazzo says figures should be “multiplied by one, two, or
three.”38 Like much in Lomazzo, this is unclear; it has been taken to mean that there should be
more than one figure, or that the proportions in the figures should be 1:1, 1:2, and 1:3.39 It is also
“Flexus ille et, ut sic dixerim, motus…,” Quintilian, Institutio oratoria II.xiii.9, translation
quoted from The Institutio oratoria of Quintilian, translated by H. W. Butler (London: William
Heinemann, 1963), 293.
38
Lomazzo, Trattato dell’Arte de la Pittura (Milan, 1584), 22–24.
39
K. Birch-Hirschfeld, Die Lehre von der Malerei in Cinquecento (Rome, 1912), 36–43, and John
Shearman, Mannerism (Baltimore, 1967), 81–91, both cited in David Summers, “Maniera and
Movement,” op. cit., 296, and for the passage in Lomazzo see pp. 271–72.
37
Chapter 2
83
Psychomachia
possible that Lomazzo means twisting one, two, or three times, so that the figure turns once at
the hips, again at the shoulders, and once more at the head. In a second passage, Lomazzo speaks
of motions (moti) in addition to
twistings (ravvolgimenti).40 The
former are up and down, right
and left, backward and forward,
and he comments that there are
“probably” others. If this
passage is read together with the
obscure comment on
multiplying by “one, two, or
three,” it appears Lomazzo may
intend to evoke the idea of
multiple motions within a single
figure, and as evidence of that I
note it is also in this second
passage that Lomazzo
introduces the term figura
serpentinata by commenting
41
that “it is best to give such figures a serpentine form.” Triple turnings in single figures are
common in mannerist art. Michelangelo’s Victory turns three times, twisting at the hips (to the
left), shoulders (left), and neck (right). The Victory is not a helix because different parts turn in
different directions. The simple helix, taper, or spiral is an image of infinity, of transcendence
from the body and metamorphosis into flame; the multiplied twist is a figure of mortality, of a
body struggling uselessly against itself.
These two forms of contrapposto, together with their six more exact components, can be
used to help map the possibilities of the contorted figure from the Renaissance to the present. In
the twentieth century, for example, expressionist figures that seem initially to go beyond these
concepts can be shown to be applying them more thoroughly than the Renaissance dared. A
Lomazzo, L’Idea, op. cit., book VI, chapter 4.
The term is attributed to Michelangelo, and Lomazzo may have gotten it via Marco Pino, who
was in Rome in the late 1540’s, “precisely the years when Michelangelo was most concerned with
writing a treatise on human anatomy and movement.” See D. Summers, “Contrapposto,” op. cit.,
284.
40
41
Chapter 2
Psychomachia
84
figure by Max Beckmann that looks like a man dangling the broken bones of his legs, or a
scarecrow blown off its stays, is nevertheless an example of the rules of multiple twistings and of
equal and opposite motion. Here torsion
is not applied to the vertical sequence
from ankle to neck, but to individual
limbs from shoulder joint to wrist, and
from ankle to knee. The rule of equal and
opposite motion distinguishes not only
one arm from the other, but one wrist
from the other, and each finger from
every other, so that the figure looks
splayed and broken, and there is no clear
difference between the painfully
wrenched wrist and the feet that turn and
curl in sympathetic pain. Historically,
Beckmann’s figure suffers a double
torture: it is twisted and broken in itself,
and racked by history—by the need to show the pain that Renaissance figures first showed, but to
do it even more intensely.
Assignment 3: find a representation of a figure that can be analyzed in terms of these
possibilities of conteapposto, or a figure that breaks with those traditions.
The indelibility of contrapposto:
Lesson of the Dread Figure
Contrapposto is still with us because it encompasses the possibilities of normal human
movement, and because depicted bodies will often echo others made in very different contexts.
Twisting contrapposto in particular has become so densely woven into our sense of the human
figure that we probably cannot depict the body without it.
One of the common paradoxes of history is that ideas have often been critiqued most
effectively by the very people who first proposed them. Twisting contrapposto is an example of
that phenomenon, because the impossibility of escaping or overturning it was demonstrated
most conclusively by one of its best exponents, Michelangelo. Late in his life, beginning around
1550, Michelangelo attempted to erase the very repertoire of poses and movements that he had
Chapter 2
85
Psychomachia
been elaborating since the last
decade of the fifteenth century. In
the place of the conventionally
twisting figure of the crucified
Christ, Michelangelo tried to
draw what are now known as
“frontal” figures, in strictly
symmetrical poses. His attack on
contrapposto was motivated in
part by the same reasons that
prompted twentieth-century
expressionists to return to
“primitive,” hieratic and frontal
figures: he mistrusted the
ideological trappings of the
Renaissance and wanted to find
something that would not be
tarnished by what the
Renaissance had come to mean.
The drawings in which this
hopeless struggle take place are a
diary of his failed attempt to
extinguish, inch my inch, the last
vestiges of visible agony from the
Dread Figure. A close inspection
of the sequence of overlapping
marks reveals that the drawings
began with strongly twisted
poses, either in the Renaissance
modes of fully articulated contrapposto, or in one of the late medieval forms of S–shaped or C–
shaped figures. Michelangelo rubbed out his first efforts, or covered them in opaque white wash,
repeatedly trying to constrain the figure to a more directly upright pose; but even the final
drawings of the series preserve a faint but telling curve or turn of the body that recalls the entire
panoply of differentially weighted contrapposti. Charles de Tolnay first showed that
Chapter 2
Psychomachia
86
Michelangelo’s contemporaries would have associated the perpendicular pose he was after with
the holy “plague crosses” of the thirteenth century, which were carried in parades to ward off the
pestilence. The choice of the thirteenth century cannot be chance, and I read it as Michelangelo’s
attempt to take art backwards, past the corrupted
period that included his own lifetime, and toward
a more spiritually and artistically pure period
before the history of modern art had begun.42
Michelangelo’s failed assault on the
repertoire of contrapposto concentrated on the
the central figure of Christian art, and on the
most pained moment of his life. It is therefore an
exemplary case for the study of contrapposto in
general. Doctrinally, Jesus’s agony is our agony,
and his suffering is the type of all pain; even
outside Catholic art, the Dread Figure continues
to be central to the pictorial imagination. That is
why it makes sense to say that the limits of
contrapposto, and its grip on our sense of the
figure, turn on how the crucified Christ can be
imagined and depicted.
Formally, the possibilities are limited:
there are not very many ways of disposing a figure on the cross, short of abstraction or
anatomically impossible expressionism. One thing an exhausted body does naturally when it is
suspended by its arms is to bend at the knees. The L-shape that results is found throughout the
thirteenth century; in a drawing by Villard de Honnecourt’s, Christ is snapped at the knees,
frozen in a geometric schema. A second possibility is the Zig-Zag, in which the body bends at
In my Pictures and the Words That Fail Them, op. cit., this sequence is analyzed from a
different point of view, one that would ultimately undermine the iconographic reading I assay
here. In that book the point of the analysis is that in these drawings, iconographic and narrative
readings—that is, the usual readings—fail in an exemplary way, because the marks refuse to sort
themselves out into discrete meaningful stages. But just as Pictures and the Words That Fail
Them is not intended as a purely antisemiotic or antinarrative polemic, so the sequence of
permissible crucified figures I sketch here would have underlain Michelangelo’s project, even
when he was least concerned with identifiable poses and most enmeshed in the project of
envisioning sacrifice.
42
Chapter 2
Psychomachia
87
knees and waist. A third is the C-arc, best known in Cimabue’s Crucifixion in Arezzo—a sinuous
pose that Francis Bacon admired because when it is inverted it reminded him of a worm
“undulating” or “crawling down
the cross.”43 The rigid frontal
pose, the L-shape, the Zig-Zag,
and the C-arc were the principal
options for a hanging body before
the age of naturalism. In the
Renaissance those options were
adapted to the new ideals of
balance and contrapposto. A
tightened version of the L-shape
(straight axis for the torso, rotated at the hips, knees together, feet crossed) was used by
Mantegna and Northern artists such as Veit Stoss. Sinuous forms of the Zig-Zag, called “the
Gothic wave” (l’ondeggione gotico), found their way into Renaissance practice as versions of the
gravimetrically balanced contrapposto preferred by Brunelleschi.
From Rubens and Rembrandt (who painted slack–bellied figures slumping down towards
the Deposition) to Picasso, Graham Sutherland, and Francis Bacon, the Crucifixion has been an
opportunity for
meditation on the body’s
gross weight, its struggles
against itself, and its
weakness in death. The
literature on the ways that
the nails must have been
placed in order to avoid
ripping out of the hand
(supposedly they would
have had to be put
between the carpals rather
than the metacarpals) is
all modern. So too are
43
Francis Bacon Interviewed by David Sylvester (New York: Pantheon, 1975), 14.
Chapter 2
88
Psychomachia
attempts to verify Jesus’s most probable position; in at least one case a corpse has been crucified
to determine the most naturalistic pose. In this example, a Chelsea pensioner, one James Legg,
was crucified by the anatomist
Joseph Constantine Carpue shortly
after he had been shot in the chest.
The resulting pose was cast in
plaster, and then afterward the
corpse was flayed, and another cast
was made from the écorché. (Only
the écorché survives.) Benjamin
West, who was one of the artists
involved in the project, is said to
have remarked that he had “never
before seen the human hand”
before he realized the way it is
stretched under the pressure of the
crucifixion.44 The exercise shows
that a crucified body might hang
nearly vertically, with virtually no
contrapposto—at least no more
than the hint in Michelangelo’s last
drawings of the subject.
A full history of crucified
bodies would also have to include
the twentieth–century
representations of the crucified
Christ as a carcass, as a nearly
abstract net of lines, and as a
heterological assembly of wet rags,
joints and ligaments. Because this subject is so important to the history of representations of the
body, and so little studied, I append a working chart of the possibilities:
Ilaria Bignamini and Martin Postle, The Artist’s Model, Its Role in British Art from Lely to Etty
(Nottingham: University Art Gallery, 1991), cat. 91, pp. 96–97 (the quotation is p. 97); and see
Julius Bryant, “Banks’s Anatomical Crucifixion,” Apollo (June 1991).
44
Chapter 2
Period
Type
Frontal, rigid
I
Medieval
89
Psychomachia
L–shape
Zig–Zag:
Geometric
Examples
Anonymous images, from the 2nd to the 13th c.
Villard de Honnecourt
Examples from the 14th c.
Zig–Zag:
The Gothic wave
Examples from 12th to the 14th c.
(l’ondeggione gotico)
II
Gothic
C–arc:
Gentle curve
C–arc:
Strong segment
L–shape
III
Zig–Zag:
Examples from the 10th to the 14th c.
Cimabue, Crucifixion (Florence, Uffizi, 1280–85)
Masaccio, Trinity (Florence, S. M. Novella, 1428)
Giotto, Crucifixion (Florence, S. M. Novella, before
1312)
Renaissance
C–arc:
Figura serpentinata
Wet–rag body
IV
Carcass:
Modern
made of flesh
Grünewald, Isenheim Altarpiece (Colmar, 1510–15)
From the 17th c.:
Rembrandt, Rubens
Francis Bacon, Crucifixion (1965)
Carcass:
Picasso, Crucifixion drawings (1932)
made of bones, thorns, etc.
Graham Sutherland, Thorn Cross (1954)
Table 4. Positions of the crucified Christ.
Chapter 2
Psychomachia
90
Michelangelo knew the
Renaissance derivatives of the
Gothic C-arc, L-shape, and ZigZag. He reproduced the C-arc in
the Crucifixion for Vittoria
Colonna, easily the most dramatic
and least constrained of the series,
and he also adopted the L–shape
and Zig-Zag in several drawings,
progressively forcing it to move
less and less, until he ended with a
“sort of contrapposto”: the faintest
of turns to the torso, matched by
the faintest of motions in the
opposing leg.45 Yet even this
exercise in Counter-reformation
austerity does not silence the
echoes of contrapposto. The
reverberation of his former
interests in the moving figure can
be read by looking up and down
the body’s midline: the eye that
follows that line sways first to one
side, then to the other.
Michelangelo never managed to
erase the repertoire of off–center balances that he had himself invented over the previous five
decades, and so the series of Crucifixion drawings ends with a tremendously subtle, and nearly
perpendicular, figure of Christ that still betrays the curves of Renaissance contrapposto.
Michelangelo’s failure should be taken seriously, especially by modern artists who seek to move
beyond contrapposto by abstracting figures, or disassembling them, or taking them from outside
Western art. Contrapposto’s resistance to even the most concerted attack, launched by the person
45
For the C–arc see see also Tolnay 418, second state. It was copied in an especially detailed
ivory; see M. Auclais, Images du Christ (Paris, n.d.), 108. For other examples see also the initial
outlines—the first states—of Tolnay 418 and 416r, as well as T415, T417, and T419.
Chapter 2
Psychomachia
91
who knew it better than anyone since, is a sign of how deeply it has stained our imagination of
the figure.
Assignment 4: find a series of representations of the Crucifixion, and see if you can
determine where the poses come from. There are a number that are not listed here.
Telos, the winding sheet
Twisting contrapposto has been used to express many things, but it is normally taken as a
sign of psychomachia, of the mind’s struggle against itself. In that interpretation the body is just
an outward sign, and the soul is what matters. Just as physiognomy depends on distinguishing
the mind and the face, so contrapposto requires the soul (or mind) and body to be distinct. If the
face and the soul aren’t kept at arm’s length, the doctrines of physiognomy break down, and the
same can be said of contrapposto. What if the body doesn’t merely express the torment of the
soul: what if they are entangled in the same struggle? In that case, a twisted body might be trying
to get away from itself: the soul might be trying to pry itself out of its wrapping of skin, or—even
more hopelessly, and more carnally—the flesh might be at odds with itself, allergic to its own
weight, its own fluids and masses.
On this fundamental level, contrapposto expresses discontent with the ordinary condition
of the body. Figures who stretch and twist may be plagued by guilt or bad conscience, or they
may be aspiring to break the bonds of their sensual existence (as the Neoplatonic reading of
Michelangelo implies): but they are also more or less ill at ease with their normal resting bodies.
Turning pulls the skin taut, and makes limbs and joints twist against one other. Even in figures
with gently balanced poses, contrapposto conjures unrest: if one part of the body is extended,
raised, or turned, another part is forced to make a symmetrical movement in the opposite
direction. Violent contrapposto expresses alienation from the skin as well as from the mind, and
in doing so it evokes a more unsolvable unhappiness, and a long-term, disconsolate struggle.
The way to this wider meaning was opened in the Renaissance. In the sixteenth century
psychomachia, the battle within the soul, lost the special significance it had in Prudentius’s
original text The Battle of the Soul (late 4th century A.C.E.; an 11th c manuscript is shown on the
Chapter 2
Psychomachia
92
next page), or even in Marsilio
Ficino’s Neoplatonism (late 15th
c.), and became the site of a more
universal and indistinct sense of
unease or tension.46 As specifically
Christian meanings receded, the
body’s struggle became more
inward, more about itself; but
even in what Leo Steinberg calls
“modern oblivion,” where
Renaissance concepts are largely
forgotten, the twisting and turning
of contrapposti and the figura
serpentinata still signal both
bodily and spiritual discomfort.47
Writhing bodies can express
purely sexual tension, as in
advertisements and pornography,
or tortured self-hatred, as in some
German expressionism: either
way, the body is partly exhibiting
the motions of an unsatisfied mind, and partly turning against itself, as if it were trying to twist
free of itself.
The Greek word telos is interesting in this connnection. It is usually translated as “end” or
“consummation”; but in the Iliad and other early Greek sources, it has a more specific meaning,
something like “band,” “wrapping,” or “winding sheet,” depending on the passage.48 “The telos of
Moshe Barash, “Character and Physiognomy: Bocchi on Donatello’s St. George, A Renaissance
Text on Expression in Art,” Imago Hominis, Studies in the Language of Art, Bibliotheca Artibus et
Historiae (Vienna: IRSA, 1991), 36–46.
47
Steinberg, The Sexuality of Christ in Renaissance Art and in Modern Oblivion (New York:
Pantheon, 1989); David Summers, “Maniera and Movement: the figura serpentinata,” Art
Quarterly 35 (1972): 269-71.
48
Richard Broxton Onians, The Origins of European Thought about the Body, the Mind, the Soul,
the World, Time, and Fate (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988 [1951]), 426 ff.
46
Chapter 2
93
Psychomachia
death covered his eyes and nostrils as he was speaking,” Homer says of one soldier.49 According
to Richard Onians, “in sympathetic magic men used bands or wrappings to produce the effects
produced by the mystic bands or wrappings of fate.”50 I would take this archaic sense of telos as a
term as an essential quality of contrapposto that has so far gone unnamed: the sense that such
figures are wrapped, wound about and confined, by their own skins. Literal wrappings are a sign
of death and the grave or for
the struggle against whatever
is mortal or “lower” in
human nature (as in
Michelangelo’s so-called
“slaves,” who fight against
flimsy swaths). But in the
end the adversary is the skin
itself, the emblem of
mortality and decay, the
“filthy sack” of medieval
theologians.
Sometimes the body
presses against its skin, as if
it is trying to escape. That
happens, for example, in the
history of bandages, torture
devices, prostheses, traction
systems, death wrappings
and mummifications.51 It
also occurs when the body is
49
Iliad XVI, 502 f.
Onians, Origins of European Thought, op. cit., 427.
51
For 18th c. texts on bandages see Johann Gottlob Bernstein, Systematische Darstellung des
chirurgischen Verbandes, sowohl älterer als neuerer Zeiten (Jena: Akademischen Buchhandlung,
1798), 2 vols.; and Joseph Marie Achille Goffres, Précis iconographique de bandages, pansements
et appareils ([ ]); and Jean Baptiste Jacques Thillaye, Traité des bandages et appareils, third
edition (Paris: Crochard, 1815). A good modern history is William Bishop, A History of Surgical
Dressings (Chesterfield, England: Robinson, 1959).
50
Chapter 2
Psychomachia
94
pressed into a resistant medium like plaster, as in various contemporary body-molding
techniques. An ancestor of relief plaques by George Segal and others are fin-de-siècle occultists’
casts of astral beings, in which ghostly faces strain to impress themselves on the real world. In the
best of them, made by the medium Eusapia Paladino, the hands and faces look as if they are
trying to break through a skin separating their world from ours.52 Any forceful pressing of the
body against a mold will conjure the body’s hopeless struggle against its own skin. Twisting
contrapposto is one of the most eloquent forms of that desire because it is least dependent on
mechanical devices, plaster, and other props.
In the end, the twisting contrapposto wins against the dancing contrapposto, because a
body’s battle against itself means more than its tilt against gravity. The figure must turn against
itself, manacle itself, make movement impossible. In the words of another Renaissance theorist,
such a body will become forced, unnatural, mysterious, and difficult (“tutta sforciata, misteriosa e
52
See the attack in F. Moser, Der Okkultismus, Täuschungen und Tatsachen, 2 vols. (Munich,
1935), vol. 2, 832 ff., and the defense in Everard Fielding, Sittings with Eusapia Palladino and
Other Studies ([ ]: University Books, 1963).
Chapter 2
Psychomachia
95
difficile”).53 In Renaissance terms, figures struggling against themselves were bedeviled by loss of
faith or sin, and the more desperate the fight, the more evil the figure. There are grotesquely
contorted figures of Judas, writhing in agony at his imminent betrayal of Christ. In some
paintings, his figure is so twisted that it looks as if is literally broken by sin; such figures may well
have reminded viewers of bodies broken on the wheel and other torture devices. In less virulent
fights, the soul might still be saved (as in Michelangelo’s “slaves”). In the twentieth century,
specifically Christian and Neoplatonic thoughts have been dispersed, but the fundamental
meaning of the figures remains clear enough: contrapposto is still a matter of discontent,
excessive unease, and pain, and its formal vocabulary will remain in place as long as the human
anatomy remains constant.
In this respect contrapposto is not only a European invention, though certainly its more
specific meanings are Western. There are figural possibilities in non–European art that were
never explored in the West—for example, there are terms describing how corpses can be fit in
cramped graves (the Yamnaya posture, with knees up; the Lepinski Vir posture, with knees
splayed to either side and feet together), and many other examples in Indian dance and the
This is from Paolo Pino, quoted in David Summers, “Contrapposto,” op. cit., 278. See “Paolo
Pino’s Dialogo di Pittura,” translated by Mary Pardo, PhD dissertation, University of Pittsburg,
1984 (Ann Arbor, Mich.: U.M.I. Dissertation Serives, 1994).
53
Chapter 2
Psychomachia
96
asanas of Hatha Yoga.54 I would only claim that in each instance, the body’s discomfiture at itself,
or the figure’s mastery of its own rebellious body as it is expressed in the “lotus position” and
other yoga poses, will be part of its meaning. Contrapposto is a universal sign for unease, and it
can even be found outside of the human figure: in a dog that wrenches its body around in search
of a flea, or in the contortions of fetuses incorrectly aligned for delivery. These are not human
postures, but they express confinement even more directly because they are not. It would be
painful to twist into a position like number 6, with the feet almost touching the nose, and the
head pushed down and sideways: the inhuman shape speaks about compression and
claustrophobia in a way no human figure can. There is nothing beyond contrapposto, and no
way, I think, to leave it entirely behind: but there are new poses to be explored, and images like
this are the most promising places to look for new configurations of the body.
For postures in Neolithic graves, see L. V. Grinsell, Barrow, Pyramid, and Tomb, Ancient Burial
Customs in Egypt, the Mediterranean and the British Isles (London: Thames and Hudson, 1975),
17–23. For asanas see Gavin Flood, Body and Cosmology in Kashmir Saivism (San Francisco:
Mellen Research University Press, 1993). Classical Indian dance postures are classified in the
Visnudharmottara Purna, edited by Priyabala Shah (Baroda: Oriental Institute, 1958).
54
Chapter 2
Psychomachia
97
Assignment 5: find representations of the figure (in art, archaeology, veterinary
science…) that do not conform to the models of contrapposto, but still suggest a body
struggling in a confined space.
The very shape of our idea of bodily motion
The body doesn’t separate and arrange affective signs the way that language does. Signs of
emotion on the face are subject to blurring as one emotion clouds another, and they are prone to
disappear when the face becomes neutral. Signs on the body fail to communicate reliably because
they are indistinct, and even though it may be argued that the body has a larger repertoire of
positions than the face, those positions are not unambiguously correlated with individual
emotions, but collectively related to a small number of emotions that converge on thoughts of
unhappiness and torment.
Still, it does not make sense to abandon either physiognomics or contrapposto, because
each is the only available lexicon of expressive motions aside from the narrower systems of
medical semiotics, or the transient systems of symbolic gestures and expressions that each culture
reinvents for itself. Bodies can only be in contrapposto, and they must finally take their meanings
from the heritage of contrapposto, unless they choose one of five non– or anti–Western options:
attempting to return to the periods before the Renaissance or before classical Greece, where
frontal rigidity was the only available mode; trying to escape from Western modes altogether, by
adopting non-Western conventions; breaking the body itself, as Picasso and Beckmann have
done; exaggerating it in plastic or expressionist deformations, as Bacon has; or abandoning it for
abstract gestures. But how sure can we be that even those strategies can avoid contrapposto?
What about breaking the body, or pulling it into an outlandish shape?55 (I illustrate the “boneless
body” from a comic book to show how surrealist strategies diffused into popular culture, losing
their sexual edge while they gain in topological freedom. I wonder if the two have an inverse
relationship: sexual readings are most clearly articulated when the represented body remains
close to its possible shapes.) It seems to me that this strategy will also fail, because whatever
meanings are elided by the fantasy of bonelessness, it won’t be possible to evade the basic
The best discussions of surrealist distortions are in Rosalind Krauss, L’Amour Fou:
Photography and Surrealism, with an essay by Dawn Ades (Washington, DC: Corcoran Gallery of
Art, 1985).
55
Chapter 2
Psychomachia
98
possibilities of the normal body, and those possibilities will be circumscribed by Renaissance
explorations of contrapposto. The undistorted part of the standing figure in this cell is pure
Renaissance contrapposto, fleshed out with muscles that Michelangelo taught us to see, and
shaded with a twentieth-century version of academic hatching, which was itself practiced most
influentially by Michelangelo. When the battle is over, both these figures will snap back to their
art-world molds.
These strictures apply even more strongly to the face. What expressions have been
invented in the last five hundred years? Even though each individual face continues to differ
from every face that has appeared before it, the catalogue of expressions has not changed. And
for that reason even the most ridiculous publications of the physiognomists deserve study,
because they remain the closest inspections of the namable positions of the face. The correlations
between face and mind are made just as crudely now as they were then, and our current timidity
on the subject does not mean we understand faces more subtly than Lavater. Physiognomy,
contrapposto, and the more arcane repertoire of medical semiotics encompass our concept of the
motions of the depicted body: there is no depiction outside of their radically unreliable
discoveries. In later chapters we will see this motion repeated: a disused “science,” whose aims
and methods appear intellectually bankrupt, provides the best opportunity to study what is
Chapter 2
Psychomachia
99
possible in pictured bodies. In the next chapter I want to continue and conclude the investigation
of pain by asking what happens when the skin is not only twisted, but actually broken.
Assignment 6: find artworks in comics or manga that stretch or distort the body in new
ways. Are they independent of contrapposto?