Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
2007, Nature
…
1 page
1 file
Had Keats lived long enough to read Ian Stewart's latest book, Why Beauty is Truth, he might have been inspired to write a sixth great ode, soft-piping sweet melodies in praise of symmetry. But what did Keats mean in Ode on a Grecian Urn when he wrote some of the most famous lines in English poetry: "Beauty is truth, truth beauty-that is all/ Ye know on earth, and all ye need to know"? Stewart is onto something deep, something mathematicians must have been keenly aware of since Greeks began turning urns. What is the underlying beauty of mathematics? Is it the artful way a proof is expressed? Or is it something deeper-something guiding pythagorean and platonist mathematicians to see better, something at the molecular structure of mathematics, some "unravish'd bride of quietness", some "Attic shape"-that enlightens and delights us. Stewart, a professor of mathematics at the University of Warwick, is renowned for his popular science books, but Why Beauty is Truth is without a doubt his finest. If it were just an authentic history of mathematics, it would be creditable. If it were only for its lively informal style, its historical characters, its intrigue ("The Galois group has a terrible secret"), its beautiful prose, it would be praiseworthy. Yet, its real uniqueness-its power-is in what it uncovers. It brings us the heart of why mathematicians pursue mathematics. Beauty is not always as visible as the iridescent butterfly on the cover of Stewart's book. We are aware that it is not the dazzling colour that makes such an insect beautiful, but rather its shape, in particular its symmetry. It is this kind of beauty that Stewart's book reveals. We encounter it most obviously when we perceive it in geometry, in the wings of a butterfly, the sections of a cone, or the appearance of regular solids. But Stewart wants us to 'see' the invisible symmetries of algebra. He starts with Évariste Galois, a young nineteenth-century French revolutionary who saw
Journal of Humanistic Mathematics, 2016
This special issue grew out of a wish to bring fresh voices to bear on the age-old question of what is the nature of beauty in mathematics. This question has a long history, rooted in philosophical discussions about aesthetics going back to Hutchenson, Kant, and even the ancient Pythagoreans. The goal was not to recapitulate this history, but rather to connect those discussions to contemporary work in aesthetics and philosophy of mathematics. We, that is Raman-Sundström andÖhman, began our exploration with the question of whether beauty and explanation might be related. Explanatory proofs are somehow privileged over non-explanatory proofs. Could this difference be aesthetic? Could there be some quality inherent to explanation that brings about the feeling that a proof is beautiful, or elegant, or cool, or pleasurable in some other positive way? The question is a natural one, but difficult to answer, particularly since aesthetic judgments are likely to be contextual and subjective, as Wells [13] and Burton [1] have suggested. Moreover, to make the question tractable we would need a model of mathematical explanation, and at present there is no such agreed upon model 1. 1 See Mancosu [7] as a starting point for the debate.
Mathematical Intelligencer, 2010
Humanistic Mathematics Network Journal, 1996
IJIRIS:: AM Publications, 2023
"Rightly viewed, mathematics possesses not only truth, but supreme beauty—a beauty cold and austere, like that of sculpture, devoid of appeal to any part of our weaker nature, devoid of the gorgeous trappings of painting or music, yet sublimely pure, and capable of a stern perfection such as only the greatest art can show." The true spirit of delight, exaltation, and the experience of being more than Man, which is the test of the highest excellence, can be discovered in mathematics just as easily as in poetry."
The Mathematical Intelligencer, 2017
The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this publication does not imply, even in the absence of a specific statement, that such names are exempt from the relevant protective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use. While the advice and information in this book are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication, neither the authors nor the editors nor the publisher can accept any legal responsibility for any errors or omissions that may be made. The publisher makes no warranty, express or implied, with respect to the material contained herein.
Journal of Humanistic Mathematics, 2015
The editorial staff of JHM works hard to make sure the scholarship disseminated in JHM is accurate and upholds professional ethical guidelines. However the views and opinions expressed in each published manuscript belong exclusively to the individual contributor(s). The publisher and the editors do not endorse or accept responsibility for them. See https://scholarship.claremont.edu/jhm/policies.html for more information.
Foundations of Science, vol. 20 (2015), pp. 339-355., 2015
In a very influential paper Rota stresses the relevance of mathematical beauty to mathematical research, and claims that a piece of mathematics is beautiful when it is enlightening. He stops short, however, of explaining what he means by ‘enlightening’. This paper proposes an alternative approach, according to which a mathematical demonstration or theorem is beautiful when it provides understanding. Mathematical beauty thus considered can have a role in mathematical discovery because it can guide the mathematician in selecting which hypothesis to consider and which to disregard. Thus aesthetic factors can have an epistemic role qua aesthetic factors in mathematical research.
This paper outlines the history of a famous school mathematics problem — originally formulated (we believe) by Isaac Newton. It appeared in a U.S. arithmetic text in 1834 and became the source of a controversy that lasted for at least 60 years. We offer two quite different solutions to the problem and provide details of the controversy that emerged. The concept of mathematical elegance, and the difficulty of specifying criteria for elegance, are discussed.
arXiv: History and Overview, 2013
We state the defining characteristic of mathematics as a type of symmetry where one can change the connotation of a mathematical statement in a certain way when the statement's truth value remains the same. This view of mathematics as satisfying such symmetry places mathematics as comparable with modern views of physics and science where, over the past century, symmetry also plays a defining role. We explore the very nature of mathematics and its relationship with natural science from this perspective. This point of view helps clarify some standard problems in the philosophy of mathematics.
Journal of Oriental Numismatic Society No. 239, 2020
La primera generación de republicanos de México, 2023
Salvador Allende: reflexiones a 50 años, después ¿Se abrieron las grandes alamedas?, 2024
Revista de Humanidades, 2023
ENDÜSTRİYEL ENERJİ İZLEME UYGULAMALARI VE SÜRDÜRÜLEBİLİRLİĞE ETKİSİ, 2024
Political Studies Review, 2015
International Review of Psychiatry, 2020
African Journal of Biological Sciences, 2024
J. Gender Race & Just., 1997
Journal of Travel Research
Human-Centered System Design for Electronic Governance
Journal of Cardiology, 2009
Scientific Reports, 2021
Journal of Dietitians Association of Nigeria
Spanish Economic Review, 2007
European Journal of Internal Medicine, 2003
Економіка та суспільство, 2022
Alicerces e Adversidades das Ciências da Saúde no Brasil 5, 2019
Somatic Cell and Molecular Genetics, 1991