THE XVII CONFERENCE ON FAMEMS AND THE III WORKSHOP ON THE HILBERT’S SIXTH PROBLEM, KRASNOYARSK, SIBERIA, RUSSIA, 2018
Co∼eventum mechanics
Oleg Yu. Vorobyev
Institute of mathematics and computer science
Siberian Federal University
Krasnoyarsk
mailto:
[email protected]
http://www.sfu-kras.academia.edu/OlegVorobyev
http://olegvorobyev.academia.edu
Abstract:
For a long time, one of my dreams was to describe the nature of uncertainty axiomatically, and it looks
like I’ve finally done it in my co∼eventum mechanics! Now it remains for me to explain to everyone
the co∼ventum mechanics in the most approachable way. The main objective of co∼eventum mechanics
and eventology [1] is the penetration of a new event-based language into all scientific and technological
spheres and the development of the ability of the eventological potential of science and technology to
transform the objects of study by event-based way, the formation of an interdisciplinary eventological
paradigm that unifies, in the first place, socio-humanitarian, ecological, psycho-economic and other
spheres, where scientific and technological research is difficult to imagine without including the observer
in the subject of research, as well as the natural sciences in which the understanding of the impossibility
of completely separating the subject of research from the observer has long been maturing. This is what
I’m trying to do in this work. You yourself, or what is the same, your experience is such “coin” that, while
you aren’t questioned, it rotates all the time in “free light”. And only when you answer the question the
“coin” falls on one of the sides: “Yes” or “No” with the believability that your experience tells you.
Eventology, probability theory, event, probability, entropy, negentropy, matter, life, mind, Kolmogorov’s
axiomatics, co∼event, believability, certainty, believability theory, certainty theory, co∼events theory,
Keywords:
theory of experience and chance, co∼eventum mechanics, co∼eventum mechanistic approach, co∼event
dualism, co∼event axiomatics, experienced-random experiment.
MSC:
60A05, 60A10, 60A86, 62A01, 62A86, 62H10, 62H11, 62H12, 68T01, 68T27, 81P05, 81P10, 91B08, 91B10,
91B12, 91B14, 91B30, 91B42, 91B80, 93B07, 94D05
1 Milestones that discovered the path to co∼eventum mechanics
I think that both mind and matter are merely convenient ways of grouping events.
Bertrand Russel [2, 1946].
Die Welt ist alles, was der Fall ist.1 .
Ludwig Wittgenstein [3, 1921].
An event is always co∼being, co∼event.
Mikhail Bakhtin [4, 1920].
The co∼eventum mechanics is the science of co∼events.
[2018].
The co∼eventum mechanics is a science of co∼events that grew out of the eventology [1] which in turn arose on
the event-based “verge” of probability theory as a synthesis of unusually easy observations by several attentive
observers:
∙ “an event is always co∼being, co∼event” [4, Bakhtin, 1920]2
∙ “an event is a set of alternative outcomes; happens when one of them happens”. “... certain real numbers (probabilities) are aligned with events
that may or may not happen ...” [6, Kolmogorov, 1933]3 ;
c 2018 O.Yu.Vorobyev
○
This is an open-access article distributed under the Creative Commons Attribution License, which permits
unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium provided the original work is properly cited.
Oleg Vorobyev (ed.), Proc. of the XVII FAMEMS’2018, Krasnoyarsk: SFU, ISBN 978-5-9903358-7-5
1 “The
world is all that is the case.”
Mikhail Mikhailovich, 1895–1975, was a Russian philosopher, literary critic, semiotician and scholar who worked on
literary theory, ethics, and the philosophy of language; he holds such literary concepts as polyphony, laughter culture, chronotop,
carnivalization; believed (1920) that “an event is always co∼being, co∼event” [4] (see also [5]). His writings, on a variety of subjects,
inspired scholars working in a number of different traditions (semiotics, structuralism, religious criticism) and in disciplines as
diverse as literary criticism, history, philosophy, sociology, anthropology, and psychology.
3 Kolmogorov, Andrei Nikolaevich, 1903–1987, was a Russian mathematician; the founder of modern probability theory, within
the framework of which he gave a mathematical definition of event and probability; basic works in the field of probability theory
and mathematical statistics, topology, logic, theory of turbulence, theory of algorithm complexity.
2 Bakhtin,
60
THE XVII FAMEMS’2018 AND THE III H’S6P WORKSHOP
∙ “... we can identify that quantity which is usually called entropy, with the probability of the state in question ...” [7, Boltzmann, 1866]4 ;
∙ “every process, event, happening ..., everything that is going on in Nature means an increase of the entropy ... ; what an organism feeds upon while
alive is negative entropy ...” “... consciousness is associated with the training of living substance ... its know-how is unconscious ... consciousness
is a teacher of the unconscious ...” [8, Schrödinger, 1943], [9, 1958], [10, 1964]5 ;
∙ “... both mind and matter are merely convenient ways of grouping events” [2, Russel, 1946]6 ;
∙ “Die Welt ist alles, was der Fall ist7 ” [3, Wittgenstein, 1921]8 ;
∙ “a mind is born there and then, where and when the ability of living matter originates to make a probabilistic choice” is a paraphrase of the
Lefebvre’ hypothesis [11, Lefebvre, 2001]9 ;
∙ “an event and a probability are two mutually related concepts, like two poles of a magnet that lose meaning in isolation from each other” [1, 2001];
∙ “the world is all that occurs, when that is experienced, what happens” [12, 2016].
The main objective of co∼eventum mechanics and eventology [1] is the penetration of a new event-based language
into all scientific and technological spheres and the development of the ability of the eventological potential of
science and technology to transform the objects of study by event-based way, the formation of an interdisciplinary
eventological paradigm that unifies, in the first place, socio-humanitarian, ecological, psycho-economic and other
spheres, where scientific and technological research is difficult to imagine without including the observer in the
subject of research, as well as the natural sciences in which the understanding of the impossibility of completely
separating the subject of research from the observer has long been maturing. This work in a lot is more of a reference
only: I just wanted to collect the arguments of different sciences and subject them to eventological transduction in
order to later to link of their aggregate in a single picture of evolution:
Matter — Life — Mind
where Nature knows itself with the help of the co∼eventum mechanics it has created. I refer the scientists–pioneers
to my supporters and opponents, who at various times made an indispensable contribution to the creation of this
event-based picture, and throughout the whole work with pleasure and gratitude I refer to their statements.
1.1 Bakhtin about the event and co∼event
Virtually the entire 20th century, the work of the philosopher and linguist Bakhtin was inaccessible to the scientific
community. Today its scientific heritage is studied all over the world, especially in England, where the Bakhtin Center
was created at Shefield University10 . So now, with the works of this remarkable scientist, it’s faster to get acquainted
in English. For many years the American literary scholar Holquist dedicated the study of Bakhtin’s heritage11 :
“The Russian word used, “sobytie”, is the normal word Russian would use in most contexts to mean what we call in
English an “event”. In Russian, “event” is a word having both a root and a stem; it is formed from the word for being —
4 Boltzmann, Ludwig Eduard, 1844–1906, is generally acknowledged as one of the most important physicists of the nineteenth
century. Particularly famous is his statistical explanation of the second law of thermodynamics. The celebrated formula S = kB ·
ln W , expressing a relation between entropy S and probability W has been engraved on his tombstone (even though he never
actually wrote this formula down which was written down in this form by Plank, 1906). Boltzmann’s views on statistical physics
continue to play an important role in contemporary debates on the foundations of that theory.
5 Schrödinger, Erwin Rudolf Josef Alexander, 1887–1961, was an Austrian theoretical physicist, one of the creators of quantum
mechanics and the wave theory of matter; Nobel Prize in physics (1933); author of many works on statistical mechanics and
thermodynamics, dielectric physics, color theory, electrodynamics, general theory of relativity and cosmology, unified field theory;
philosopher and scholar; introduced the concept of negative entropy (negentropy) to describe living systems; radically changed the
foundations of our modern world view, modern biology, philosophy of science, philosophy of reason and epistemology; his theory of
life and self-organization of matter anticipated the current fusion of natural, social and human sciences, influenced the philosophy
of nature and the modern view of the world, creating an evolutionary picture of the continuing synthesis of nature and culture:
one of the most interesting events of modern thought.
6 Russell, Bertrand Arthur William, 1872–1970, was an English mathematician and philosopher; Nobel Prize in literature (1950).
7 “The world is all that is the case.”
8 Wittgenstein, Ludwig Josef Johann, 1889–1951, was an Austrian-British philosopher who worked primarily in logic, the
philosophy of mathematics, the philosophy of mind, and the philosophy of language. During his lifetime he published just one slim
book, the 75-page Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus [3, 1921]. His manuscript were edited and published posthumously in 1953, and
has since come to be recognised as one of the most important works of philosophy in the twentieth century. His teacher, Bertrand
Russell, described Wittgenstein as “the most perfect example I have ever known of genius as traditionally conceived; passionate,
profound, intense, and dominating”.
9 Lefebvre, Vladimir Alexandrivich (b. 1936) is a Russian and American psychologist and mathematician; the founder of the theory
of reflection, located at the junction of many sciences: psychology, philosophy, mathematics, sociology, ethics, etc.; determines the
mind as the ability to make a probabilistic choice.
10 The Bakhtin Center, The University of Sheffield: http://www.sheffield.ac.uk/bakhtin.
11 Holquist, J. Michael, 1935–2016, was an American literary critic; scholar of scientific heritage of Bakhtin.
OLEG YU VOROBYEV. CO∼EVENTUM MECHANICS
61
“bytie” — with the addition of the prefix implying sharedness, “so-”, (or, as we should say in English, “co-” as co-operate
or co-habit), giving “sobytie”, event as co-being. “Being” for Bakhtin then is, not just an event, but an event that is shared.
Being is a simultaneity; it is always co∼being”. [13, Holquist, p. 25].
The co∼eventum mechanistic point of view.
Bakhtin’s verbal formula “an event is always co∼being” is his brilliant anticipation and vision of the duality of being. The given
idea underlies all his philosophy of language and his other writings on a variety of subjects. In the co∼eventum mechanics,
his verbal formula acquires a strict mathematical meaning: “an event is always co∼event” that is a binary relation defined
on the Cartesian product of the space of experience and the space of chance.
1.2 Kolmogorov about the event and probability
“They assume a certain set of conditions, allowing an unlimited number of repetitions. They are studying a certain
range of events that can happen as a result of the implementation of this set of conditions. In some alternative
outcomes, these events may or may not happen in different combinations. In the set Ω they include all possible
alternative outcomes of occurrence or non-occurrence of the events under study. If, after the next realization of this
set of conditions, the alternative outcome that has happened in practice turns out to be part of the subset x ⊆ Ω, then
it is said that the event x happened. Thus, each event they consider as a set of alternative outcomes” [6, Kolmogorov,
1933].
“... it can be assumed that certain events that may happen, or not happen after the implementation of this set of
conditions, are associated with certain real numbers possessing axiomatic properties ... and called probabilities of
events” [6, Kolmogorov, 1933].
The co∼eventum mechanistic point of view.
Since Kolmogorov’s probability theory is one of the dual halves of the co∼eventum mechanics, and Kolmogorov’s axiomatics
is a part of co∼eventum mechanistic axiomatics, Kolmogorov’s ideas about the event and its probabilities remain unchanged.
Except for forced changes in terminology: Kolmogorov’s events, which are measured by probability, are called ket-events in
the co∼eventum mechanics, which can only happen or not happen. Therefore, quotations from Kolmogorov can be translated
into the co∼eventum mechanistic language as follows:
“They assume a certain set of conditions, allowing an unlimited number of repetitions. They are studying a certain range of
ket-events that can happen as a result of the implementation of this set of conditions. In some alternative outcomes, these
ket-events may or may not happen in different combinations. In the set |Ω⟩, they include all possible alternative outcomes of
happening or non-happening of the ket-events under study. If, after the next realization of this set of conditions, the alternative
outcome that has happened in practice turns out to be part of the subset |x⟩ ⊆ |Ω⟩, then it is said that the ket-event |x⟩ happened.
Thus, each ket-event they consider as a set of alternative outcomes” [12, 2016]. “... it can be assumed that certain ket-events
that may happen, or not happen after the implementation of this set of conditions, are associated with certain real numbers
possessing axiomatic properties ... and called probabilities of ket-events” [12, 2016].
This is a co∼eventum logic of the future chance. Since all those ket-events, that will happen, can serve as the possible future
consequences of the present outcome of the chance observation.
As for the other half of the co∼eventum mechanics, called the believability theory, the dual idea underlying it can be
formulated in the same Kolmogorov style as follows:
“They assume a certain set of conditions, allowing an unlimited number of repetitions. They are studying a certain range of
bra-events that can be accumulated as a result of observations of ket-events that can happen as a result of the implementation
of this set of conditions. In some joint incomes, these bra-events may be accumulated or not accumulated in different
combinations. In the set ⟨Ω|, they include all accumulable joint incomes of accumulating or non-accumulating of the braevents under study. If, after the next realization of this set of conditions, the set of joint incomes all of which are accumulated
in practice turns out to contain the subset ⟨x| ⊆ ⟨Ω|, then it is said that the bra-event ⟨x| was accumulated. Thus, each bra-event
they consider as a set of joint accumulated incomes” [12, 2016]. “... it can be assumed that certain bra-events that may be
accumulated, or not accumulated after the implementation of this set of conditions, are associated with certain real numbers
possessing axiomatic properties ... and called believabilities of bra-events” [12, 2016].
This is a co∼eventum logic of the past experience. Since all those bra-events, that are accumulating in the observer’s
experience at present, can serve as the past causes of the set of joint present incomes.
1.3 Feynman about the event and probability
There’s a big difference between
knowing the name of event and knowing event.
Richard Feynman.
“Other problems which may be further analyzed are those dealing with the theory of knowledge. For example, there
seems to be a lack of symmetry in time in our knowledge. Our knowledge of the past is qualitatively different than
that of the future. In what way is only the probability of a future event accessible to us while the certainty of a past
62
THE XVII FAMEMS’2018 AND THE III H’S6P WORKSHOP
event can often apparently be asserted? These matters again have been analyzed to a great extent. I believe however
a little more can be said to clarify the situation. Obviously, we are again involved in the consequences of the large size
of ourselves and of our measuring equipment. The usual separation of observer and observed which is now needed
in analyzing measurements in quantum mechanics should not really be necessary, or at least should be even more
thoroughly analyzed. What seems to be needed is the statistical mechanics of amplifying apparatus.” [14, Feynman,
1951]
The co∼eventum mechanistic point of view.
The logic of the theory of experience and chance is the union of the co∼eventum logic of the future chance and the
co∼eventum logic of the past experience. Since all those ket-events, that will happen, can serve as the possible future
consequences of the present outcome of the chance observation. And because all those bra-events, that are accumulating
in the observer’s experience at present, can serve as the past causes of the set of joint present incomes.
In co∼eventum mechanics, a co∼event is defined as a binary relation between the observer’s experience and the chance
of observation. Bra-events serve as models of the observer’s experience, and ket-events — as a model of the chance of
observation. Any co∼event generates an element-set labelling of the Cartesian product of the space of observers and the space
of observations. In this labelling, the accumulated bra-events play the role of the names of the happening ket-events. That
is why Feynman’s quotation to this section has the following form in the language of co∼eventum mechanics: “There’s a big
difference between knowing the bra-events and knowing the ket-events.” “The statistical mechanics of amplifying apparatus”,
which Feynman lacked, is nothing more than the co∼event mechanics of bra-events. Because the result of the work of any
amplifying apparatus is always a “some name” of what is observed with its help, in other words, it is a bra-event of observed
ket-event.
“If all the difficulties of quantum mechanics are gathered into one point, then it will be called “negative
probabilities”.” [15, Feynman, 1982], [16, Feynman, 1987].
The co∼eventum mechanistic point of view.
The paradox of negative probabilities in quantum mechanics is naturally formulated in the theory of co∼events as a paradox
of phantom distributions of sets of co∼events (see [17]). However, the solution of this paradox is still to be discovered in the
framework of the co∼eventum mechanics.
1.4 Boltzmann about the probability and entropy
The foundation of all statistical physics is the statistical interpretation by Boltzmann of the second law of
thermodynamics. The famous Boltzmann H-theorem justifies the second principle in application in an ideal gas.
Boltzmann showed [7, 1866] that he discovered the connection of entropy and probability12 defines a measure for the
entropy of systems of atoms and molecules in the gas phase, thereby providing a measure for entropy in classical
thermodynamics. The logical completion of Boltzmann’s ideas was the statistical mechanics of Gibbs13 , which formed
the basis of statistical thermodynamics. And the logical continuation of his ideas is quantum mechanics, born out of
the quantum Planck hypothesis14 on the discreteness of the energy to which Planck came based on the assumption
of the same Boltzmann on the discrete energy of molecules.
The co∼eventum mechanistic point of view.
In the most usual present sense, the Boltzmann entropy is interpreted as a measure of the observer’s uncertainty in the
microstate of the system. The macrostate of the equilibrium of the system maximizes its entropy because then the observer
loses a maximum of information about the microstates of the system except for its fixed macro variables. The maximization
of entropy maximizes ignorance of the observer about the microscopic details of the system. It is commonly “believed” that
this uncertainty is not everyday subjective uncertainty but rather the uncertainty that is inherent in its experimental method
and interpretation model. In the co∼eventum mechanics this observer’ everyday subjective uncertainty is the uncertainty
that is generated by observer’ experience and measured by the believability measure. However, in co∼eventum mechanics,
the observer’s experience is understood in the broadest sense in such a way that it, of course, includes the experimental
methods and interpretation models that the observer can use for her/his observations. It can be said that in co∼eventum
mechanics both models and methods of observation are just a continuation or strengthening of the means of observation that
the observer possesses.
12 See.
the footnote 7 on page 60.
Josiah Willard, 1839-1903 was an American mathematician, physicist, chemist and mechanic; one of the founders,
statistical physics, mathematical theory of thermodynamics, vector analysis; established the fundamental law of statistical
mechanics, the Gibbs distribution, generalized the entropy principle, applying the second law of thermodynamics to a wide range
of physical processes; in many respects predetermined the development of modern exact sciences and natural science in general.
14 Plank, Max Karl Ernst Ludwig, 1858-1947, was a German theoretical physicist, founder of quantum physics; Nobel laureate in
physics (1918); Basic works on thermodynamics, theory of thermal radiation, quantum theory, special theory of relativity, optics;
formulated the second law of thermodynamics in the form of the principle of increasing entropy and used it to solve various
problems of physical chemistry.
13 Gibbs,
OLEG YU VOROBYEV. CO∼EVENTUM MECHANICS
63
So, the co∼eventum mechanics has more sophisticated means of describing and measuring entropy as a measure of disorder.
First, it is the usual Boltzmann entropy, which I call the entropy of the observation’s chance, i.e. entropy of the set of ketevents. Secondly, this is the entropy of the observer’s experience, i.e. the entropy of the set of bra-events. And, finally, it is the
entropy of experience and chance, or the entropy of the co∼event, which is simply equal to the sum of these two entropies.
1.5 Schrödinger about the matter, life, and mind evolution
In his book “What is life?”15 Schrödinger introduced [8, 1943] the concept of negative entropy (most likely ascending to
Boltzmann) which living organisms must receive from the surrounding world in order to compensate for the growth
of entropy that leads them to thermodynamic equilibrium and, consequently, to of death. According to Schrödinger
an import of negentropy, or export of entropy by living organisms is one of the main differences of life from inanimate
nature:
“Every process, event, happening — call it what you will; in a word, everything that is going on in Nature means an
increase of the entropy of the part of the world where it is going on. Thus a living organism continually increases its
entropy — or, as you may say, produces positive entropy — and thus tends to approach the dangerous state of maximum
entropy, which is of death. It can only keep aloof from it, i.e. alive, by continually drawing from its environment negative
entropy — which is something very positive as we shall immediately see. What an organism feeds upon is negative
entropy. Or, to put it less paradoxically, the essential thing in metabolism is that the organism succeeds in freeing itself
from all the entropy it cannot help producing while alive”. [8]
The origin and evolution of life and mind Schrödinger also examines in detail in two other of his equally famous
books “Mind and matter”[9, 1958]16 and “My view of the world”[10, 1963]17 .
The co∼eventum mechanistic point of view.
I would like to think that what Schrödinger called negative entropy is nothing else than the entropy of the observer’s
experience in the co∼eventum mechanics. In my fairly long-ago paper [18], the first wording and the proof of the eventological
H-theorem (the eventological generalization of Boltzmann H-theorem) is presented, which relates the entropy of experience
and the entropy of chance. This is a very promising direction in the co∼eventum mechanics, which promises many discoveries
and will require rigorous proofs.
1.6 Russell about the mind and matter as the events in “History of Western Philosophy”
“Einstein substituted events for particles; each event had to each other a relation called interval, which could be
analyzed in various ways into a time-element and a space-element. ... From all this it seems to follow that events, not
particles, must be the stuff of physics. What has been thought of as a particle will have to be thought of as a series of
events. The series of events that replaces a particle has certain important physical properties, and therefore demands
our attention; but it has no more substantiality than any other series of events that we might arbitrarily single out. ...
Thus matter is not part of the ultimate material of the world, but merely a convenient way of collecting events into
bundles. ... While physics has been making matter less material, psychology has been making mind less mental. ...
Thus from both ends physics and psychology have been approaching each other, and making more possible a neutral
doctrine. ... I think that both mind and matter are merely convenient ways of grouping events. ... Some single events,
I should admit, belong only to material groups, but others belong to both kinds of groups, and are therefore at once
mental and material. ... This doctrine effects a great simplification in our picture of the structure of the world.”
15 “What Is Life? The Physical Aspect of the Living Cell” is a 1944 science book written for the lay reader by physicist Erwin
Schrödinger in which he expounds his views of the physicist on the problems of biological life and for the first time introduces
into science the concept of negentropy (negative entropy); written on the basis of three popular lectures, read by him in Dublin in
February 1943 on the basis of the “Green Notebook”.
16 “Mind and Matter” is Schrödinger’s book (1958), in which he analyzes the physical principles of consciousness and the
unconscious: “Consciousness is the teacher of the unconscious”, and examines issues that are traditionally considered the
prerogative of philosophers, theologians , psychoanalysts and politicians: are the mind and matter, the subject and the object,
the inner self and the external world completely different things or are they the same thing; what place does consciousness take in
the evolution of life, which is the basis of morality; can one still expect the biological development of modern man and how will his
intellectual development take place.
17 “My view of the world” is the Schrödinger’s book (1963), where he analyzes the philosophical problem of spatio-temporal
multiplicity and the unity of observing and thinking subjects in whom no thought can arise, not a continuation of the thought
of their ancestors, and also — the problem of the birth and evolution of the mind in the living, where consciousness plays the role
of an instrument for the evolutionary learning of organic life, and the organic abilities of the living are unconscious: consciousness
is something becoming ( this is the point of application of evolution), the unconscious is something that exists.
64
THE XVII FAMEMS’2018 AND THE III H’S6P WORKSHOP
The co∼eventum mechanistic point of view.
Following Bertrand Russell, the co∼eventum mechanic says with a “little clarification” that both mind and matter are merely
convenient ways of grouping co∼events. Therefore, the theory of sets of co∼events, i.e. the co∼eventum mechanics can serve
as the axiomatic basis of what can be called a unified theory of mind and matter.
1.7 Wittgenstein about events, mind and world
By defining the world as all that occurs [3, 1921] and by showing the application of modern logic to metaphysics, via
language, Wittgenstein provided new insights into the event-based relations between world, mind and language and
thereby into the nature of philosophy.
If in the initial items 1, 1.1, 1.11, 1.12, 1.13, 1.2, 1.21, and 2 of the English version [19, 1966] of the main Wittgenstein’s
book, the term “a fact” we will naturally translate as “an event” then we will learn the description of the event-based
picture of Wittgenstein’s world:
“The world is all that occurs. The world is the totality of events, not of things. The world is determined by the events,
and by their being all the events. For the totality of events determines what occurs, and also whatever doesn’t
occur. The events in logical space are the world. The world divides into events. Each event can occur or can don’t
occur while everything else remains the same. That what does occur, an event is the existence of states of the world”.
The co∼eventum mechanistic point of view.
Following Ludwig Wittgenstein, the co∼eventum mechanics says with a “little clarification” that the world is everything
that occurs, i.e. what accumulates when something happens. In co∼eventum mechanics language this means that the world
is everything that is co∼events. This means that the co∼eventum mechanistic generalizations of the ideas of Russell and
Wittgenstein completely coincide, which again indicates a successful choice of the co∼eventum axiomatics for the theory of
experience and chance.
1.8 Lefebvre about the origin of the mind
You will not find in Lefebvre’s works literally the same utterance as on page 60, but having become better acquainted
with his works [11], you will come with him, namely, to this conclusion: “a mind is born there and then, where and
when the ability of living matter originates to make a probabilistic choice”. This event-probabilistic
18
hypothesis
about the origin of the mind, which Lefebvre put forward, based on the results of experimental psychology [20],
immediately follows from the fundamental Bakhtin definition of the event as co∼being, co∼event, [4] and the basic
eventological idea [1]: “an event and a probability are two mutually related concepts, like two poles of a magnet that
lose meaning in isolation from each other”.
The co∼eventum mechanistic point of view.
Following Lefebvre, the co∼eventum mechanics says with a “little clarification” that “a mind is born there and then, where
and when the ability of living matter originates to make a believabilistic choice on the basis of its experience”. This assertion
is based on the dual co∼eventum mechanistic idea: “a bra-event and a believability are two mutually related concepts, like two
poles of a magnet that lose meaning in isolation from each other”.
2 What is the co∼eventum mechanics?
“The world is all that occurs, when that is experienced, what happens”
[12, 2016]
“The co∼eventum mechanics is a science of co∼events
that occurs, when that is experienced, what happens”
[2018]
“A man is the ability of living matter to co∼be,
to group co∼events and to make a believabilistic choice of them”
[2018]
For a long time, one of my dreams was to describe the nature of uncertainty axiomatically, and it looks like I’ve finally
done it in my co∼eventum mechanics19 ! Now it remains for me to explain to everyone the co∼eventum mechanics in
18 One can not but admit that Lefebvre in his works, operates only with probabilities, without using the concept of an event
explicitly, although he always silently assumes it.
19 See [12, 21, 22], for example.
OLEG YU VOROBYEV. CO∼EVENTUM MECHANICS
65
the most approachable way. This is what I’m trying to do in this work.
In the modern theories of uncertainty a “belief” is usually defined as a measure in the space of probability
distributions [23, 24]. In other words, this is a “probability of probability”, i.e., a probability of the second order. The
co∼eventum mechanics approach is fundamentally different. It is grown from eventology [1], the science of the sets
of Kolmogorov events. It can be said that random sets of “names” of Kolmogorov events are studied in eventology.
The co∼eventum mechanics [12, 21, 22, 25, 26, 27, 28, 29] appears as a natural mathematical consequence of the
eventological theory and the theory of random sets [30] only after the dual character of probability description of a
set of events has been discovered [12, 21]. The concept of co∼event appeared that is defined as a measurable binary
relation on the Cartesian product of a space of “names” (of bra-events) and a space of Kolmogorov events (of ketevents). A measure defined on this Cartesian product is defined as a product of a “probability measure of ket-events”
and a “believability measure of bra-events”. This new measure is called the “certainty of co∼events”.
The co∼eventum mechanics is another name for the co∼event theory, i.e., for the theory of experience and chance
which I axiomatized in 2016 [12, 21]. In my opinion, this name best reflects the co∼event-based idea of the new
dual theory of uncertainty, which combines the probability theory as a theory of chance, with its dual half, the
believability theory as a theory of experience. In addition, I like this new name indicates a direct connection between
the co∼event theory and quantum mechanics, which is intended for the physical explanation and description of the
conflict between quantum observers and quantum observations [31]. Since my theory of uncertainty satisfies the
Kolmogorov axioms of probability theory, to explain this co∼eventum mechanics I will use a way analogous to the
already tested one, which explains the theory of probability as a theory of chance describing the results of a random
experiment. The simplest example of a random experiment in probability theory is the “tossing a coin”. Therefore, I
decided to use this the simplest random experiment itself, as well as the two its analogies: the “scrolling a coin” and
the “spinning a coin” to explain the co∼eventum mechanics, which describes the results of a combined experiencedrandom experiment.
I would like to resort to the usual for the probability theory “coin-based” analogy to explain (and first of all for
myself) the logic of the co∼eventum mechanics as a logic of experience and chance. Of course, this analogy one
may seem strange if not crazy. But I did not come up with a better way of tying the explanations of the logic of
the co∼eventum mechanics to the coin-based explanations that are commonly used in probability theory to explain
at least for myself the logic of the chance through a simple visual “coin-based” model that clarifies what occurs as
a result of a combined experienced-random experiment in which the experience of observer faces the chance of
observation. I hope this analogy can be useful not only for me in understanding the co∼eventum mechanics [12].
In the probability theory, the terms “throwing a coin”, “tossing a coin”, “scrolling a coin”, “rotating a coin”, “spinning
a coin” and so on are used as classical synonymous for the name of a typical example of a random experiment.
So at first I thought the co∼event theory [12] requires three different terms that distinguish similar experiments
with a “coin”, but which are implemented within the framework of probability theory, believability theory [12], and
co∼event theory correspondingly. Therefore, at first sight it seemed to me in the co∼eventum mechanics these usual
synonymous are forced to get strictly different mathematical meanings. And I would have to choose the three terms
to define for them the different meanings:
∙ “tossing a random coin”20
for the random experiment in the probability theory,
∙ “flipping all the experienced coins,” or in detail:
“flipping all the experienced coins accumulated by an observer relevant to the observed outcome of some random
coin” for the experienced experiment in the believability theory, and
∙ “spinning the experienced-random coins”, or in detail:
“tossing a random coin and then flipping all the experienced-random coins accumulated by an observer relevant to
20 You can find an interesting attempt to construct a quantum model of “a random coin” in [32, 33]. I only note that in this paper I
use a different co∼event approach and I am only interested in co∼event models, the construction of which does not go beyond the
co∼eventum mechanics.
66
THE XVII FAMEMS’2018 AND THE III H’S6P WORKSHOP
the observed outcome of this random coin” for the experienced-random experiment in the co∼event theory.
However, everything turned out to be much more complicated than I expected. As a result, I was able to finally
recognize that neither a random experiment nor an experienced experiment can be determined separately, but only
together with each other, like the dual halves of a one experienced-random experiment. In this work, I’m going to
discuss the way of definition and the need to introduce this terms into the new theory to axiomatically describe the
co∼eventum mechanics in a conflict between an observer and an observation of co∼event. The author hopes this
co∼eventum axiomatics will be useful in the study of quantum entanglement, which characterizes the collision of
quantum observers and quantum observations.
2.1 The battle to find a satisfactory co∼eventum mechanistic ontology
2.1.1 “Coins in free rotation”
I’m sure you will not have much trouble imagining “a real coin in free rotation”. I would like to consider this image
as the “superposition state” of the real coin, as a natural state of the coin at a time when it is not observed by an
observer. In a random experiment of tossing a coin, the coin turns out to be in such a “superposition state” in order
to fall on one of its states/sides: “head” or “tail” at the moment of observation of the result of this experiment by an
observer. For example, it can be said that “the real coin in free rotation” is an ordinary real coin that has already
been tossed during a random experiment but has not yet fallen on one of its sides.
It is not difficult to imagine “a real coin in free rotation”. This visualization of reality, which often appeared before
your eyes, can be easily caused by your imagination. It is much more difficult to imagine what you have never seen.
I mean your accumulated experience, which is also always in a “superposition state” as “a real coin in free rotation”,
until the moment of an observation of the outcome of a random experiment that expands this your given experience.
Such a “superposition state” of your experience I will imagine as “an imaginary experienced coin in free rotation”.
What occurs at the moment of “a tossing a real coin” observation by an observer whose coin-based experience is in
a “superposition state”, i.e. whose “experienced coin is in free rotation”?
The emergent co∼event mechanics gives the completely clear answer:
“The result of this experienced-random experiment is a co∼event, i.e., a bra-ket-event that is defined as
the Cartesian product of a bra-event and a ket-event. The bra-event describes an accumulating the observer’
experience at the moment of observation, and the ket-event describes the chance of observation at the same
moment. In other words, the bra-event is accumulated and the ket-event happens at the moment of collision
between the observer’ experience and the chance of observation. This means that the bra-ket-event, i.e. the
co∼event occurs at the same moment.”
However, I continue to reasonably fear that the meaning of these theoretical explanations is understandable so far
only to me alone. Therefore, I will try to illustrate them with the help of my “coin-based model” or maybe “dice-based
model”.
But foreseeing the reader’s inadequacies, I want to emphasize in advance three principal statements that relate to
the observability properties of all three types of experiments, the strict definitions of which unusual for the reader
will be given below.
∙ The result of the random experiment is unobservable because there is no one to observe.
∙ The result of the experienced experiment is unobservable because there is nothing to observe.
∙ And only the result of the experienced-random experiment is observable because there is something to observe,
and there is one who observes.
OLEG YU VOROBYEV. CO∼EVENTUM MECHANICS
67
2.1.2 An experienced-random experiment
Neither a random experiment (see Definition 2) nor an experienced experiment (see Definition 3) exists separately.
They are like two poles of a magnet, or as on two sides of a coin, either as a mind and matter, or as a mental and
real, or as an experience and a chance, or as an observer and an observation. If you notice, each of them is defined
in connection with another. Both of these experiments are inseparable halves of what I call an experienced-random
experiment.
Definition 1 (an experienced-random experiment, a bra-ket-experiment, a bra-ket-trial). An experiencedrandom experiment (a bra-ket-experiment, a bra-ket-trial) is a pair of two inseparable experiments that are carried
out simultaneously. One of them is a random experiment, and the other is an experienced experiment21 . The result
of each experiment from this pair is unobservable separately. Only the overall result of the pair is observable
and indicates that some kind of co∼event has occurred, and what kind of co∼event it has been. At the time
of observation, the unobservable chance in a random experiment generates in the experienced experiment an
unobservable accumulation of the observer’s experience. This unobservable accumulated experience of the observer
in a pair with the unobservable chance, is the overall observable result of the given experienced-random experiment,
the observable co∼event.
Figures 1, 2, 3, and 4 illustrating some experienced experiments depict Venn diagrams of co∼events in the bra-ket
spaces ⟨Ω|Ω⟩ that occur as the results of appropriate experienced-random experiments, the dual halves of which are
the random experiments and experienced experiments, which I have discussed above (see details in figure captions).
2.1.3 A random experiment
Definition 2 (a random experiment, a ket-experiment, a ket-trial). A random experiment (a ket-experiment,
a ket-trial) is a dual half of experienced-random experiment the result of which is unobservable in the absence
of an observer, and in the presence of an observer its future result can not be predicted until its observation. In
other words, a random experiment (a ket-experiment) is an experiment whose future result becomes available to
the observer at the time of observation and can not be predicted until this moment of observation by the observer,
regardless of her/his past experience.
In the probability theory, the “tossing a random coin” is the typical example of a “random experiment”. However,
in this theory, a “random experiment” is defined differently than in the co∼event mechanics, since the role of an
observer in such a “random experiment” is completely ignored, and one can only guess at a tacitly existing abstract
observer with an indefinite experience. Below I will also consider and define two more examples of a random
experiment (”tossing a gray random dice” and “tossing a colored random dice”22 ), which, in my opinion, can most
transparently explain the meaning of definition of a random experiment in the co∼eventum mechanics and its
difference from a “random experiment” in probability theory.
Example 1 (tossing a random coin). Imagine an urn contains balls, well-mixed together, that are colored by black
or white in equal proportion23 . A ball is drawn at random from the urn, its color is observed by an observer, who
is characterized by her/his own experience. From the point of view of probability theory an observer observes a
value of the Boolean random variable, for example, the zero is “black” and the unit is “white”. The observer asks
her/himself a question: “Is this ball black or white?”, in other words, “Which side of the coin fell: black or white?”24
Example 2 (tossing a gray random dice, all shades of gray from black to white). Imagine an urn contains
balls, well-mixed together, that are colored by shades of gray from black to white. A ball is drawn at random from
21 See
Definitions 3 and 2 below.
a “random dice” I will understand as an ordinary random dice with six equiprobable faces, and a generalized random dice
that has infinitely many equiprobable faces.
23 An urn model in probability theory is an idealized mental exercise in which some events that occur with objects of real interest
(such as atoms, people, cars, etc.) are represented as a pulling/drawing/taking/dropping out colored balls from an urn.
24 The observer gives her/himself an answer based on her/his own experience The observer’s answer is the result of an
experienced-random experiment in which the given random experiment serves as one of two inseparable halves of it. The other
half of it is an experienced experiment, which consists in how the observer perceives and interprets this random experiment,
accumulating her/his own experience.
22 By
68
THE XVII FAMEMS’2018 AND THE III H’S6P WORKSHOP
the urn, its color is observed by an observer, who is characterized by her/his own experience. From the point of view
of probability theory an observer observes a value of random variable uniformly distributed in the unit interval.
The observer asks her/himself a question: “Is this ball rather black than white, or rather white than black?”, in other
words, “On which side did the coin fall, on white or black?”24
Example 3 (tossing a colored random dice, all shades of any colors). Imagine an urn contains balls, wellmixed together, that are colored by all shades of any colors. A ball is drawn at random from the urn, its color is
observed by an observer, who is characterized by her/his own experience. From the point of view of probability
theory an observer observes a value of random vector uniformly distributed in the unit three dimension cube. The
observer asks her/himself a question: ”Is this ball rather red, or orange, or yellow, or green, or blue, or violet than
another color of the six-color rainbow?”, in other words, “On which side did the dice fall: on red, or on orange, or on
yellow, or on green, or on blue, or on violet?”24
2.1.4 An experienced experiment
To define and understand what an experienced experiment is, I will need to define who and what is involved in
this experiment. Of course, and this has been said many times by me above, an indispensable participant in the
experienced experiment is the observer with her/his experience. What I still need here is to define the models of
the observer’s experience within the framework of my dice-based approach. These dice-based models I call a “gray
experienced dice” and a “colored experienced dice”25 .
Definition 3 (an experienced experiment, a bra-experiment, a bra-trial). An experienced experiment (a braexperiment, a bra-trial) is a dual half of experienced-random experiment the result of which is unobservable in
the absence of an observation, and in the presence of an observation its future result can not be predicted until
its observation. In other words, an experienced experiment (a bra-experiment) is an experiment whose future result
becomes available to the observer at the time of observation and can not be predicted until this moment of observation
by the observer, regardless of her/his past experience.
Definition 4 (a gray experienced dice). A gray experienced dice is a hypothetical dice, which is colored by the
observer’s experience in one shade of gray quite definite for the observer. This is a dice, which in each trial of the
observer’s experience can fall on either side: “black” or “white” with the observer’s believability, which are defined
by the observer’s experience of the degree of “grayness” of this hypothetical coin.
Definition 5 (the singular gray experienced dices). The “black experience dice” and the “white experienced
dice” are the two extreme singular cases of a gray experienced dice, which are defined by the observer’s experience
with full believability. These dices are called the singular gray experienced coins.
Definition 6 (a colored experienced dice). A colored experienced dice is a hypothetical dice, which is colored
by the observer’s experience in one color quite definite for the observer. This is a dice, which in each trial of the
observer’s experience can fall on either side: “violet”, “blue”, “green”, “yellow”, “orange”, or “red” with the observer’s
believability, which are defined by the observer’s experience of the degree of “rainbow color” of this hypothetical
dice.
Definition 7 (the singular colored experienced dices). The “violet, blue, green, yellow, orange, or red
experience dices” are the six extreme singular cases of a colored experienced dice, which are defined by the
observer’s experience with full believability. These dices are called the singular colored experienced dices.
“A flipping all the experienced dices”26 is the typical example of an experienced experiment in the believability
theory. Below I will consider and define such examples of an experienced experiment (“a flipping all the singular
gray experienced dices”, “a flipping all the gray experienced dices” and “a flipping all the colored experienced dices”)
which, in my opinion, can most transparently explain the meaning of definition of an experienced experiment in the
co∼eventum mechanics.
25 By an “experienced dice” I will understand as an ordinary experienced dice with six faces, and a generalized experienced dice
that has infinitely many faces.
26 see terms in detail on page 65.
OLEG YU VOROBYEV. CO∼EVENTUM MECHANICS
69
Example 4 (a flipping all the singular gray experienced dices). Imagine you are an observer and observe
outcomes of the random experiment a “tossing a black-white random coin” in which the outcome “a coin fell on
black side” happened. You observe this random outcome and, of course, come to the following conclusion. When
you are asked: “On which side did the coin fall?” you need to say with full believability that the coin fell on the black
side. Of course, this your conclusion is trivial here because this experienced experiment is singular.
|Ω⟩
⏟
⏞
∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘
|{x}⟩
|∅⟩
⎧ ⏞
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎨
⟨Ω| ⟨x|
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎩
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
⏟
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
⏞
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
⏟
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
Table 1: A tossing the random coin and a flipping all the singular gray experienced coins. Venn diagram illustrates an income-outcome of the 24×24
experienced-random experiment (the “black-white observer” is making 24 “black-white random coin observations”) as a result of which co∼event
R ⊆ ⟨Ω|Ω⟩ ( ○ ) occurs with the element-set labellings ⟨X|SX ⟩ = ⟨{x}|{∅, {x}}⟩.
However, ask yourself: “Why do I give this answer with full believability?” You can explain this in a variety of ways,
but all of them will, of course, be based on your own rich experience of observing the outcomes of this random
experiment. The co∼event theory gives the following exact answer, based on its axioms [12]. So, you are absolutely
right, the full believability is prompted by your experience of observing the outcomes of this random experiment. But
how is this your experienced mechanism that allows you to come to conclusions with some degree of believability?
The co∼event theory gives an axiomatic description of this experienced mechanism, which in a coin-dice-based
70
THE XVII FAMEMS’2018 AND THE III H’S6P WORKSHOP
language is interpreted as follows. For such an experienced experiment, your experience has accumulated two sets
of singular experienced dices. In one set, it has the black experienced dices, in the other it has the white experienced
dices. At the very moment when you observe that the random coin has fallen on the black side, your experience
begins its “experiment”: “a flipping all the black experienced dices accumulated by an observer relevant to the blackoutcome of the random coin”, which ends with all, without exception, black experienced dices falling on the black
face. Precisely, the fact that all the dices that have been without exception dropped on the black face, allows you
to give the answer with full believability. Otherwise, at the very moment when you observe that the random coin
has fallen on the white side, your experience begins its another “experiment”: “a flipping all the white experienced
dices accumulated by an observer relevant to the white-outcome of the random coin”, which ends with all, without
exception, white experienced dices falling on the white face. Precisely, the fact that all the dices that have been
without exception dropped on the white face, allows you to give the answer with full believability. (See Fig. 1)
|Ω⟩
⏟
⏞
∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘
|X1 ⟩ |X2 ⟩ |X3 ⟩ |X4 ⟩ |X5 ⟩ |X6 ⟩ |X7 ⟩ |X8 ⟩ |X9 ⟩ |X10⟩ |X11⟩ |X12⟩ |X13⟩ |X14⟩ |X15⟩ |X16⟩ |X17⟩ |X18⟩ |X19⟩ |X20⟩ |X21⟩ |X22⟩ |X23⟩ |X24⟩
⎧
⎪
⟨x1 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x2 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x3 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x4 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x5 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪⟨x6 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x7 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪⟨x8 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x9 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x10 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x11 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎨⟨x12 |
⟨Ω|
⎪
⟨x13 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x14 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x15 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x16 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x17 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x18 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x19 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪⟨x20 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪⟨x21 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x22 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x23 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎩⟨x |
24
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
Table 2: A tossing the gray random dice and flipping all the singular gray experienced coins. Venn diagram illustrates an income-outcome of the
24×24 experienced-random experiment (24 “black-white observers” are making 24 “all shades of gray random dice observations”) as a result of which
co∼event R ⊆ ⟨Ω|Ω⟩ ( ○ ) occurs with the element-set labellings ⟨X|SX ⟩ = ⟨{x1 , . . . , x24 }|{X1 , . . . , X24 }⟩.
OLEG YU VOROBYEV. CO∼EVENTUM MECHANICS
71
Example 5 (a flipping all the gray experienced dices). Imagine you are an observer and observe outcomes of
the random experiment a “tossing a gray random dice” in which the outcome “a dice fell on gray face” happened.
You observe this random outcome and come to the following conclusion. When you are asked: “What gray color is
the face on which the dice fell?” you need to say with some degree of believability that the dice fell on the black face
or on the white face. This your conclusion is not trivial here because this experienced experiment is not singular.
However, ask yourself: “Why do I give this answer with some degree of believability?” You can explain this in a
variety of ways, but all of them will, of course, be based on your own rich experience of observing the outcomes of
such random experiment. The co∼event theory gives the following exact answer, based on its axioms [12]. So, you
are absolutely right, the some degree of believability is prompted by your experience of observing the outcomes of
such random experiment. But how is this your experienced mechanism that allows you to come to conclusions with
some degree of believability? The co∼event theory gives an axiomatic description of this experienced mechanism,
which in a co∼eventum mechanistic language is interpreted as follows. For such an experienced experiment, your
experience has accumulated the set of gray experienced dices. At the very moment when you observe that the gray
random dice has fallen on the face of some degree of gray, your experience begins its own “experienced experiment”:
“a flipping all the gray experienced coins accumulated by her/his observer’s experience relevant to this gray-outcome
of the gray random dice”, which ends with some gray experienced dices falling on the black face and some gray
experienced dices falling on the white face. This allows you to give the answer: “the black face” with a degree of
believability equal to the share of gray experienced dices falling on the black face; and — the answer: “the white
face” with complementary degree of believability. (See Fig. 2)
Example 6 (a flipping all the singular colored experienced dices). Imagine you are an observer and observe
outcomes of the random experiment a “tossing a rainbow color random dice” in which the outcome “a dice fell on
red face” happened. You observe this random outcome and, of course, come to the following conclusion. When
you are asked: “On which face did the dice fall?” you need to say with full believability that the dice fell on the red
face. Of course, this your conclusion is trivial here because this experienced experiment is singular. However, ask
yourself: “Why do I give this answer with full believability?” You can explain this in a variety of ways, but all of
them will, of course, be based on your own rich experience of observing the outcomes of such random experiment.
The co∼event theory gives the following exact answer, based on its axioms [12]. So, you are absolutely right, the
full believability is prompted by your experience of observing the outcomes of such random experiment. But how
is this your experienced mechanism that allows you to come to conclusions with some degree of believability? The
co∼event theory gives an axiomatic description of this experienced mechanism, which in a co∼eventum mechanics
language is interpreted as follows. For such an experienced experiment, your experience has accumulated six sets
of singular colored experienced dices: the set of violet experienced dices, the set of blue experienced dices, the set of
green experienced dices, the set of yellow experienced dices, the set of orange experienced dices, and the set of red
experienced dices. At the very moment when you observe that the rainbow color random dice has fallen on the red
face, your experience begins its own “experienced experiment”: “a flipping all the red experienced coins accumulated
by an observer relevant to the red-outcome of the rainbow color random dice”, which ends with all, without exception,
red experienced coins falling on the red face. Precisely, the fact that all the dices that have been without exception
dropped on the red face, allows you to give the answer with full believability. And so on for each random outcomes:
“the rainbow color random dice has fallen on the violet, blue, green, yellow, orange, red face”. (See Fig. 3)
Example 7 (a flipping all the colored experienced dices). Imagine you are an observer and observe outcomes
of the random experiment a “tossing a colored random dice” in which the outcome “a dice fell on colored face”
happened. You observe this random outcome and come to the following conclusion. When you are asked: “What
rainbow color is the face on which the dice fell?” you need to say with some degree of believability that the dice
fell on one of the six rainbow color faces: the violet, blue, green, yellow, orange, or red face. This your conclusion
is not trivial here because this experienced experiment is not singular. However, ask yourself: “Why do I give
this answer with some degree of believability?” You can explain this in a variety of ways, but all of them will, of
course, be based on your own rich experience of observing the outcomes of such random experiment. The co∼event
theory gives the following exact answer, based on its axioms [12]. So, you are absolutely right, the some degree of
believability is prompted by your experience of observing the outcomes of such random experiment. But how is this
72
THE XVII FAMEMS’2018 AND THE III H’S6P WORKSHOP
your experienced mechanism that allows you to come to conclusions with some degree of believability? The co∼event
theory gives an axiomatic description of this experienced mechanism, which in a co∼eventum mechanistic language
is interpreted as follows.
|Ω⟩
⏟
⏞
∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘
|X1 ⟩ |X2 ⟩ |X3 ⟩ |X4 ⟩ |X5 ⟩ |X6 ⟩ |X7 ⟩ |X8 ⟩ |X9 ⟩ |X10⟩ |X11⟩ |X12⟩ |X13⟩ |X14⟩ |X15⟩ |X16⟩ |X17⟩ |X18⟩ |X19⟩ |X20⟩ |X21⟩ |X22⟩ |X23⟩ |X24⟩
⎧
⎪
⎪⟨x1 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x2 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x3 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x4 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x5 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x6 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x7 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x8 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x9 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x10 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x11 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎨⟨x12 |
⟨Ω|
⎪
⟨x13 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪⟨x14 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x15 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x16 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x17 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x18 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪⟨x19 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x20 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪⟨x21 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x22 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪⟨x23 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎩⟨x |
24
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
Table 3: A tossing the six-rainbow colored random dice and flipping all the singular colored experienced dices. Venn diagram illustrates an incomeoutcome of the 24×24 experienced-random experiment (24 “six-rainbow observers” are making 24 “six-rainbow color random dice observations”) as
a result of which co∼events R1 ( ○ ) +R2 ( ○ ) +R3 ( ○ ) +R4 ( ○ ) +R5 ( ○ ) R6 ( ○ ) = ⟨Ω|Ω⟩ occur with the overall element-set labellings
⟨X|SX ⟩ = ⟨{x1 , . . . , x24 }|{X1 , . . . , X24 }⟩.
For such an experienced experiment, your experience has accumulated the set of rainbow colored experienced
coins each of which corresponds to one or another observable color on the face of the colored random dice. And
in each such set, the believabilities of falling out of one or another rainbow colored face, accumulated by your
experience, corresponds to the observed color of the fallen face of a colored random dice. At the very moment
when you observe that the colored random dice has fallen on the colored face, your experience begins its own
“experienced experiment”: “a flipping all the rainbow colored experienced coins accumulated by her/his observer’s
experience relevant to this color-outcome of the color random dice”, which ends with the six set of colored experienced
coins falling on the violet, blue, green, yellow, orange, and red face correspondingly. This allows you to give the
OLEG YU VOROBYEV. CO∼EVENTUM MECHANICS
73
answer: “the violet, blue, green, yellow, orange, and red face” with the corresponding degree of believability equal
to the share of this rainbow color coins falling on the corresponding rainbow color face. (See Fig. 4)
|Ω⟩
⏟
⏞
∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘∘
|X1 ⟩ |X2 ⟩ |X3 ⟩ |X4 ⟩ |X5 ⟩ |X6 ⟩ |X7 ⟩ |X8 ⟩ |X9 ⟩ |X10⟩ |X11⟩ |X12⟩ |X13⟩ |X14⟩ |X15⟩ |X16⟩ |X17⟩ |X18⟩ |X19⟩ |X20⟩ |X21⟩ |X22⟩ |X23⟩ |X24⟩
⎧
⎪
⟨x1 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x2 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x3 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x4 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x5 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x6 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x7 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x8 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x9 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪⟨x10 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x11 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎨⟨x12 |
⟨Ω|
⎪
⟨x13 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x14 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x15 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x16 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x17 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x18 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x19 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x20 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x21 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x22 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x23 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎩⟨x |
24
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
∘
Table 4: A tossing the all colored random dice and flipping all the singular colored experienced dices. Venn diagram illustrates an income-outcome
of the 24×24 experienced-random experiment (24 “six-rainbow observers” are making 24 “all color random dice observations”) as a result of which
co∼events R1 ( ○ ) +R2 ( ○ ) +R3 ( ○ ) +R4 ( ○ ) +R5 ( ○ ) R6 ( ○ ) = ⟨Ω|Ω⟩ occur with the overall element-set labellings ⟨X|SX ⟩ =
⟨{x1 , . . . , x24 }|{X1 , . . . , X24 }⟩.
3 A tossing, a flipping, and a spinning the “coins”, and ... organ pipes
Now I will allow myself to reformulate in the bra-ket-notations three principal statements that relate to the
observability properties of all three types of experiments, the strict definitions of which were given above.
∙ The ket-result of the random experiment is unobservable because there is no one to observe.
∙ The bra-result of the experienced experiment is unobservable because there is nothing to observe.
∙ And only the bra-ket-result of the experienced-random experiment is observable because there is something to
74
THE XVII FAMEMS’2018 AND THE III H’S6P WORKSHOP
⟨bra-success|
⏟
⟨b bra
ra -k
-fa et
ilu -fa
re ilu
|k re
et =
-r
es
ul
t⟩
⟨∅|
⎧
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎨
|∅⟩
⏞
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎩
=
⟨b bra
ra -k
-s et
uc -s
ce uc
ss ce
|k ss
et =
-r
es
ul
t⟩
R
|ket-result⟩
⏟
=
⎧ ⎧
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎨ ⎪
⎨
⟨Ω| ⟨x|
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪ ⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪ ⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪ ⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎩ ⎪
⎩
|{x}⟩
⏞
|Ω⟩
⏟
⏞
Rc
|ket-result⟩
|Ω⟩
⏟
⏞
⟨bra-failure|
Table 5: A Bernoulli bra-ket-trial. Venn diagrams for two accumulable-possible results of a Bernoulli bra-ket-trial of a co∼event R: R occurred
(“bra-ket-success”= ⟨“bra-success”|“ket-result”⟩, left), or R didn’t occur, i.e. the co∼event Rc = ⟨Ω|Ω⟩ − R occurred, or the co∼event R didn’t occur
(“bra-ket-failure”= ⟨“bra-failure”|“ket-result”⟩, right).
observe, and there is one who observes.
I will also note that in the bra-ket-terms a random experiment is a ket-experiment or a ket-trial, an experienced
experiment is a bra-experiment, or a bra-trial, and an experienced-random experiment is a bra-ket experiment, or
a bra-ket-trial. Thus, in the co∼eventum mechanics, only the results of the bra-ket-trial can be observed, and the
ket-trial result and the bra-trial result serve only as inseparable unobservable halves of the bra-ket-trial result.
⏞
⎧
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎨
⟨Ω|
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎩
⟨x|
︁
⟨∅|
︁
︁
⟨∅|
︁
⟨x|
︁
⟨x|
︁
⟨∅|
︁
⟨x|
︁
⟨x|
︁
⟨x|
︁
⟨∅|
⏞
|Ω⟩
⏟
|{x}⟩
⏟
bra-ket-success= ⟨bra-success|ket-result⟩
bra-ket-failure= ⟨bra-failure|ket-result⟩
bra-ket-failure= ⟨bra-failure|ket-result⟩
bra-ket-success= ⟨bra-success|ket-result⟩
bra-ket-success= ⟨bra-success|ket-result⟩
bra-ket-failure= ⟨bra-failure|ket-result⟩
bra-ket-success= ⟨bra-success|ket-result⟩
bra-ket-success= ⟨bra-success|ket-result⟩
bra-ket-success= ⟨bra-success|ket-result⟩
bra-ket-failure= ⟨bra-failure|ket-result⟩
⏞
|Ω⟩
⏟
|{x}⟩
⏞
⏟
⎧
⎪
⎪
bra-ket-success= ⟨bra-success|ket-result⟩
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
bra-ket-success= ⟨bra-success|ket-result⟩
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎨ bra-ket-success= ⟨bra-success|ket-result⟩
⟨x|
⎪
⎪
⎪
bra-ket-success= ⟨bra-success|ket-result⟩
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
bra-ket-success= ⟨bra-success|ket-result⟩
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎩
bra-ket-success= ⟨bra-success|ket-result⟩
⎧
⎪
⎪
bra-ket-failure= ⟨bra-failure|ket-result⟩
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎨ bra-ket-failure= ⟨bra-failure|ket-result⟩
⟨∅|
⎪
⎪
⎪ bra-ket-failure= ⟨bra-failure|ket-result⟩
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎩ bra-ket-failure= ⟨bra-failure|ket-result⟩
Table 6: 10 Bernoulli “bra-trials”. Two equivalent Venn diagrams for accumulable results of the ten Bernoulli bra-trials of a co∼event R: R
accumulable (“bra-success”), or R didn’t accumulate, i.e. the co∼event Rc = ⟨Ω|Ω⟩ − R accumulable (“bra-failure”).
In conclusion, I would like to underline once again a difference what is usually meant by “tossing a random coin”
in probability theory, and what is meant by “flipping a set of experienced coins” and “spinning a set of experienced
OLEG YU VOROBYEV. CO∼EVENTUM MECHANICS
bra-ket-failure = ⟨bra-failure|ket-result⟩
⏟
bra-ket-failure = ⟨bra-failure|ket-result⟩
bra-ket-failure = ⟨bra-failure|ket-result⟩
|∅⟩
⏞
bra-ket-failure = ⟨bra-failure|ket-result⟩
⏟
bra-ket-success = ⟨bra-success|ket-result⟩
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎩
|{x}⟩
|Ω⟩
⏟
bra-ket-success = ⟨bra-success|ket-result⟩
bra-ket-success = ⟨bra-success|ket-result⟩
bra-ket-success = ⟨bra-success|ket-result⟩
bra-ket-success = ⟨bra-success|ket-result⟩
bra-ket-failure = ⟨bra-failure|ket-result⟩
bra-ket-success = ⟨bra-success|ket-result⟩
bra-ket-success = ⟨bra-success|ket-result⟩
bra-ket-failure = ⟨bra-failure|ket-result⟩
bra-ket-failure = ⟨bra-failure|ket-result⟩
bra-ket-failure = ⟨bra-failure|ket-result⟩
bra-ket-success = ⟨bra-success|ket-result⟩
⟨x|
⎧⏞
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎨
bra-ket-success = ⟨bra-success|ket-result⟩
|∅⟩ |{x}⟩ |{x}⟩ |∅⟩ |{x}⟩ |{x}⟩ |{x}⟩
⎧
⎧⏞ ⏟ ⏞ ⏟ ⏞ ⏟ ⏞ ⏟ ⏞ ⏟ ⏞ ⏟ ⏞ ⏟ ⏞ ⏟ ⏞ ⏟ ⏞ ⏟
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎨
⎨
⟨Ω|
⟨x|
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎩
⎩
bra-ket-success = ⟨bra-success|ket-result⟩
|∅⟩
⏞
bra-ket-success = ⟨bra-success|ket-result⟩
|{x}⟩ |∅⟩
|Ω⟩
⏟
bra-ket-success = ⟨bra-success|ket-result⟩
⏞
75
Table 7: 10 Bernoulli “ket-trials”. Two equivalent Venn diagrams for random results of the ten Bernoulli ket-trials of a co∼event R ⊆ ⟨Ω|Ω⟩
︁
︁
:
R happened (“bra-ket-success”), or R didn’t happen, i.e. the co∼event Rc = ⟨Ω|Ω⟩ − R happened (“bra-ket-failure”).
coins with a random coin” in the co∼eventology of experience and chance [12].
A coin toss has all the attributes of a “random experiment” in probability theory. There is more than one possible
ket-result. We can specify each possible outcome in advance — head (ket-success) or tail (ket-failure). And there is
an element of chance. We cannot know the ket-result until we actually toss the coin. At last, what is very important,
for this random experiment it is completely indifferent whether this experiment is observed by an observer or not.
An experienced coin flip has all the attributes of a “experienced experiment” in the co∼eventum mechanics. There is
more than one accumulable bra-result. We can specify each accumulable bra-result in advance — head (bra-success)
or tail (bra-failure). And there is an element of experience. We cannot know the bra-result until we actually flip the
experienced coin. At last, what is very important, for this experienced experiment it is very important who observed
it and what experience she/he has.
A set of experienced coins with a random coin spin has all the attributes of a “experienced-random experiment” in
the co∼eventum mechanics and the co∼eventology of experience and chance. There is more than one accumulablepossible bra-ket-result. We can specify each accumulable-possible bra-ket-result in advance — head (bra-ket-success,
the co∼event occur) or tail (bra-ket-failure, the co∼event doesn’t occur). And there is an element of experience.
We cannot know the bra-ket-result until we actually spin all coins. And, of course, what is very important, for this
experienced-random experiment it is very important who observed it and what experience she/he has.
At last, I will note the Venn diagram of any co∼event reminds me very much the organ with its pipes. Moreover,
in this organ analogy, the co∼event occurs whenever “only one of the organ pipes sounds”, i.e., the ket-event
corresponding to this pipe happens and the set of bra-events corresponding to this pipe are accumulated by the
observer’s experience (see Tab. 8 and ?? for comparing).
4 Milestones that the co∼eventum mechanics opens to us
We are all experienced observers in the world of chance observations. Nothing occurs with us except co∼events
which describe the conflict of our past experience with the future chance. Our being is always co∼being, which
occurs with us as a succession of sets of co∼events. Co∼eventum mechanics suggest that our world can be viewed
as the universal experienced-random experiment, and we are all participants of it without exception. At any
coincidence, each of us makes decisions based on her/his own past experience. Only our experience tells us what
76
THE XVII FAMEMS’2018 AND THE III H’S6P WORKSHOP
|Ω⟩
⏟
⏞
|X1 ⟩ |X2 ⟩ |X3 ⟩ |X4 ⟩ |X5 ⟩ |X6 ⟩ |X7 ⟩ |X8 ⟩ |X9 ⟩ |X10⟩ |X11⟩ |X12⟩ |X13⟩ |X14⟩ |X15⟩ |X16⟩ |X17⟩ |X18⟩ |X19⟩ |X20⟩ |X21⟩ |X22⟩ |X23⟩ |X24⟩
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
bra-ket-success
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
bra-ket-success
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
bra-ket-success
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
bra-ket-success
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
bra-ket-success
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
bra-ket-success
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
bra-ket-success
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
bra-ket-success
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
bra-ket-success
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
bra-ket-success
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
bra-ket-success
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
bra-ket-success
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
bra-ket-success
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
bra-ket-success
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
bra-ket-success
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
bra-ket-success
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
bra-ket-success
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
bra-ket-success
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
bra-ket-success
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
bra-ket-success
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
bra-ket-success
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
bra-ket-success
bra-ket-success
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
×
⟨x24 | ×
bra-ket-success
⎧
⎪
⎪
⎪⟨x1 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x2 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x3 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x4 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x5 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x6 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x7 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x8 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x9 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x10 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x11 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎨⟨x12 |
⟨Ω|
⎪
⟨x13 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x14 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪⟨x15 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x16 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪⟨x17 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x18 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪⟨x19 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x20 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪⟨x21 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⟨x22 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪⟨x23 |
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎩
Table 8: The bra-ket-trial and “organ analogy”. Venn diagram of the co∼event R ⊆ ⟨Ω|Ω⟩ ( bra-ket-success ) and the co∼event Rc = ⟨Ω|Ω⟩ − R
( bra-ket-failure ) with the element-set labellings ⟨X|SX ⟩ = ⟨{x1 , . . . , x24 }|S{x1 ,...,x24 } ⟩ and Φ(R) = 1/2 (see Tab. ??, left, for comparing with the
“organ analogy”).
decision should be chosen at the moment of chance observation with some degree of believability in the correctness
of this decision. From the point of view of the co∼eventum mechanistic approach, each of us represents a set of
her/his past experiences, and each of these experiences is a set of elementary experienced which are identified with
experienced coins in a free rotation ready for this or that random elementary observation. In turn, any random
observation is a set of elementary random observations which are identified with random coins in a free rotation
ready to be observed by some or other experienced observers. So, the co∼eventum mechanics sees our world filled
with only coins in a free rotation, experienced coins and random coins. The collision of these sets of coins creates
sets of co∼events, which is our co∼being.
The reader is free to interpret this co∼eventum mechanistic view of the world of co∼events in terms of her/his
paradigm of the scientific world picture. In my humble opinion, in the co∼eventum mechanistic approach, every coin
in free rotation, both an experienced and random, is a superposition state, which in quantum mechanics is described
OLEG YU VOROBYEV. CO∼EVENTUM MECHANICS
|ket-result⟩
⟨b bra
ra -k
-s et
uc -s
ce uc
ss ce
|k ss
et =
-r
es
ul
t⟩
=
R
⟨bra-success|
⟨∅|
⎧
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎨
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎩
|∅⟩
⏞
⏟
⟨b bra
ra -k
-fa et
ilu -fa
re ilu
|k re
et =
-r
es
ul
t⟩
⏟
=
|{x}⟩
⏞
|Ω⟩
⏟
⏞
Rc
|ket-result⟩
|Ω⟩
⏟
⏞
⎧ ⎧
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎨ ⎪
⎨
⟨Ω| ⟨x|
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪ ⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪ ⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪ ⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎪
⎩ ⎪
⎩
77
⟨bra-failure|
Table 9: A Bernoulli bra-ket-trial. Venn diagrams for two accumulable-possible results of a Bernoulli bra-ket-trial of a co∼event R: R occurred
(“bra-ket-success”= ⟨“bra-success”|“ket-result”⟩, left), or R didn’t occur, i.e. the co∼event Rc = ⟨Ω|Ω⟩ − R occurred, or the co∼event R didn’t occur
(“bra-ket-failure”= ⟨“bra-failure”|“ket-result”⟩, right).
by the Schrödinger wave equation. And the entire co∼eventum world is described by the system of Schrödinger wave
equations. As a result, the next milestone in the knowledge of the world should be a theory that combines quantum
and co∼eventum mechanics.
References
[1] O. Yu. Vorobyev.
Eventology.
.
Siberian Federal University, Krasnoyarsk, Russia, 435p., 2007 (in Russian),
https://www.academia.edu/179393/
[2] B. A. W. Russell. History of Western Philosophy and its Connections with Political and Social Circumstances from the Earlist
Times to the Present Day. George Allen & Unwin, London, 1946.
[3] L. Wittgenstein. Logisch-philosophische abhandlung. Ostwalds Annalen der Naturphilosophie, 14:185–262, 1921.
[4] M. M. Bakhtin. Toward a Philosophy of the Act. University of Texas Press, Austin (1993), St.Petersburg, 1920.
[5] O. Yu. Vorobyev. Contemporary uncertainty theories: An eventological view. In. Proc. of the VIII Intern. FAM Conf. on Financial
and Actuarial Mathematics and Related Fields, Krasnoyarsk: SFU (Oleg Vorobyev ed.), 1:26–34, 2009.
[6] A. N. Kolmogorov. Grundbegriffe der Wahrscheinlichkeitrechnung. Ergebnisse der Mathematik, Berlin, 1933.
[7] L. Boltzmann. Über die mechanische bedeutung des zweiten hauptsatzes der wärmetheorie. Wiener Berichte, 53:195–220,
1866.
[8] E. Schrödinger. What is Life? The Physical Aspect of the Living Cell. Based on lectures delivered under the auspices of the Institute
at Trinity College, Dublin, in February 1943. At the University Press, Cambridge, UK, 1944.
[9] E. Schrödinger. Mind and Matter. The Tarner Lectures, delivered at Trinity College, Cambridge, in October 1956. At the University
Press, Cambridge, UK, 1958.
[10] E. Schrödinger. My View of the World. At the University Press, Cambridge, UK, 1964.
[11] V. A. Lefebvre. Algebra of Conscience. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Boston, 2001.
[12] O. Yu. Vorobyev. Postulating the theory of experience and chance as a theory of co∼events (co∼beings). In. Proc.
of the XV Intern. FAMEMS Conf. on Financial and Actuarial Mathematics and Eventology of Multivariate Statistics & the
Workshop on Hilbert’s Sixth Problem; Krasnoyarsk, SFU (Oleg Vorobyev ed.), pages 25–43, 2016, ISBN 978-5-9903358-6-8,
https://www.academia.edu/34373279; https://arxiv.org/abs/1801.07147.
[13] M. Holquist. Dialogism. Bakhtin and his World. 2nd edition. Routledge, Taylor & Francis Group, London and New York, 2002.
[14] R.P. Feynman. The concept of probability in quantum mechanics. Proc. Second Berkeley Symp. on Math. Statist. and Prob.,
pages 533–541, 1951.
[15] R.P. Feynman. Simulating physics with computers. International Journal of Theoretical Physics, 21(6/7):467–488, 1982.
[16] R.P. Feynman. Negative probability. In “Quantum implications”: Essays in honor of David Bohm, edited by B. J. Hiley and F. D.
Peat, (Chap. 13):235–248, 1987.
78
THE XVII FAMEMS’2018 AND THE III H’S6P WORKSHOP
[17] O. Yu. Vorobyev. Triangle room paradox of negative probabilities of events. In. Proc. of the XV Intern. FAMEMS Conf. on
Financial and Actuarial Mathematics and Eventology of Multivariate Statistics & the Workshop on Hilbert’s Sixth Problem;
Krasnoyarsk, SFU (Oleg Vorobyev ed.), pages 94–97, 2016, ISBN 978-5-9903358-6-8, https://www.academia.edu/32419497.
[18] O. Yu. Vorobyev. Eventological H-theorem. In. Proc. of the VII All-Russian FAM Conf. on Financial and Actuarial Mathematics
and Related Fields. Krasnoyarsk, KSU (Oleg Vorobyev ed.), 1:51–58, 2008, ISBN 978-5-7638-1001-1, https://www.academia.edu/37376751.
[19] L. Wittgenstein. Logish-philosophische Abhandlung — Tractatus logico-philosophicus. Routledge & Kegan Paul; The humanities
press, London; New York, 1966.
[20] R. J. Herrnstein. Relative and absolute strength of response as a function of frequency of reinforcement.
Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 4:267–272, 1961.
Journal of
[21] O. Yu. Vorobyev. An element-set labelling a Cartesian product by measurable binary relations which leads to postulates of
the theory of experience and chance as a theory of co∼events. In. Proc. of the XV Intern. FAMEMS Conf. on Financial and
Actuarial Mathematics and Eventology of Multivariate Statistics & the Workshop on Hilbert’s Sixth Problem; Krasnoyarsk, SFU
(Oleg Vorobyev ed.), pages 9–24, 2016, ISBN 978-5-9903358-6-8, https://www.academia.edu/34390291.
[22] O. Yu. Vorobyev. Theory of dual co∼event-based means. In. Proc. of the XV Intern. FAMEMS Conf. on Financial and Actuarial
Mathematics and Eventology of Multivariate Statistics & the Workshop on Hilbert’s Sixth Problem; Krasnoyarsk, SFU (Oleg
Vorobyev ed.), pages 44–93, 2016, ISBN 978-5-9903358-6-8, https://www.academia.edu/34357251.
[23] G. Shafer. A Mathematical Theory of Evidence. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ, 1976.
[24] F. Cuzzolin. Visions of a generalized probability theory. Lambert Academic Publishing, 2014.
[25] O. Yu. Vorobyev. The bra-ket-means of co∼events in the theory of experience and chance. In. Proc. of the XVI Intern. FAMEMS
Conf. on Financial and Actuarial Mathematics and Eventology of Multivariate Statistics & the II Workshop on Hilbert’s Sixth
Problem; Krasnoyarsk, SFU (Oleg Vorobyev ed.), pages 144–157, 2017, ISBN 978-5-9903358-7-5, https://www.academia.edu/36667769/.
[26] O. Yu. Vorobyev. Co∼event models of experts’ behavior in examples and problems. In. Proc. of the XVI Intern. FAMEMS Conf.
on Financial and Actuarial Mathematics and Eventology of Multivariate Statistics & the II Workshop on Hilbert’s Sixth Problem;
Krasnoyarsk, SFU (Oleg Vorobyev ed.), pages 111–133, 2017, ISBN 978-5-9903358-7-5, https://www.academia.edu/36661246.
[27] O. Yu. Vorobyev. Mathematical expectation, reflexion, and existence as numerical means of a co∼event in the theory of
experience and chance. In. Proc. of the XVI Intern. FAMEMS Conf. on Financial and Actuarial Mathematics and Eventology of
Multivariate Statistics & the II Workshop on Hilbert’s Sixth Problem; Krasnoyarsk, SFU (Oleg Vorobyev ed.), pages 139–143, 2017,
ISBN 978-5-9903358-7-5, https://www.academia.edu/35454045.
[28] O. Yu. Vorobyev. The theory of co∼events in brief questions and brief answers with illustrations. In. Proc. of the XVI Intern.
FAMEMS Conf. on Financial and Actuarial Mathematics and Eventology of Multivariate Statistics & the II Workshop on Hilbert’s
Sixth Problem; Krasnoyarsk, SFU (Oleg Vorobyev ed.), pages 134–138, 2017, ISBN 978-5-9903358-7-5, https://www.academia.edu/36663315.
[29] O. Yu. Vorobyev. The logic of uncertainty as a logic of experience and chance and the co∼event-based Bayes’ theorem. In.
Proc. of the XVI Intern. FAMEMS Conf. on Financial and Actuarial Mathematics and Eventology of Multivariate Statistics & the
II Workshop on Hilbert’s Sixth Problem; Krasnoyarsk, SFU (Oleg Vorobyev ed.), pages 92–110, 2017, https://www.academia.edu/36645361.
[30] I. Molchanov. Theory of Random Sets. Second Edition. Springer, 2017, 678pp.
[31] Shan Gao. What is it like to be a quantum observer? and what does it imply about the nature of consciousness? Preprint,
pages 1–13, 2018, 2 July, http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/14836/.
[32] A.M. Soiguine. A tossed coin as quantum mechanical object. Preprint, pages 1–14, 2013, https://www.academia.edu/8068825/.
[33] A.M. Soiguine. What quantum “state” really is? Preprint, pages 1–12, 2014, https://www.academia.edu/8068841/.