A Merleau‐Pontian Account
of Embodied Perceptual Norms
Corinne Lajoie*
Abstract
Although philosophers may first find it odd to speak of norms in the context of
perception, the argument for normativity finds support in the writings of some of
the spearheads of the phenomenological tradition, amongst them Edmund Husserl
and Maurice Merleau-Ponty. As Maren Wehrle argues however, a
phenomenological analysis of perception’s normative claim requires that we redefine
our traditional conception of norms as authoritative standards or prescriptive
moral guidelines. To this end, as she points out, the origin of the concept of norm
in architecture can be illuminating because it refers to a measure or guideline which
emerges out of “practical motivations”1 and serves to “facilitate cooperative and
intersubjective communication.”2 In her view, prior to any theoretical or moral
engagement with the world, certain sets of norms already play a role at an
embodied, pre-reflexive level and account for our ability to orientate ourselves in the
intersubjective lifeworld. My interest in the concept of norms stems from such a
comprehension, and attempts to unfold and clarify some of its implications for
perception in general. My goal in this paper is thus to address one of the key
interpretations of perceptual norms in Merleau-Pontian scholarship and to suggest
______________
* L’auteure est étudiante à la maîtrise en philosophie (Université de
Montréal).
1 Maren Wehrle, “Normality and Normativity in Experience”, in Normativity
in Perception, ed. Breyer, T. and Doyon, (Basingstoke : Palgrave Macmillan,
2015), pp. 128-140, here p. 1.
2 Ibid.
Ithaque 22 – Printemps 2018, p. 1‐19
Handle: 1866/19891
Corinne Lajoie
a new reading of their role in the Phenomenology of Perception (1945),
through the lense of interest and temporality.
A growing number of works in recent scholarship address the
topic of normativity in perception and its relevance for
phenomenology3. Although philosophers may first find it odd to
speak of norms in the context of perception, the argument for
normativity finds support in the writings of some of the spearheads
of the phenomenological tradition, amongst them Edmund Husserl
and Maurice Merleau-Ponty. The question of how normativity gets a
foothold in perception finds different responses in the philosophical
litterature, but phenomenologists have generally attempted to show
how perceptual behaviors are beholden to norms below the treshold
of reflective activity. As Maren Wehrle argues, a phenomenological
analysis of perception’s normative claim however requires that we
redefine our traditional conception of norms as authoritative
standards or prescriptive moral guidelines. To this end, as she points
out, the origin of the concept of norm in architecture can be
illuminating because it refers to a measure or guideline which emerges
out of “practical motivations”4 and serves to “facilitate cooperative
and intersubjective communication.”5 In her view, prior to any
theoretical or moral engagement with the world, certain sets of norms
already play a role at an embodied, pre-reflexive level and account for
our ability to orientate ourselves in the intersubjective lifeworld. My
interest in the concept of norms stems from such a comprehension,
______________
3 See for example Steven Crowell, Normativity and Phenomenology in Husserl and
Heidegger (Cambridge, MA : Cambridge University Press, 2013) ; Sean Kelly,
“Seeing Things in Merleau-Ponty.” In The Cambridge Companion to MerleauPonty, ed. Taylor Carman, (Cambridge, MA : Cambridge University Press,
2006), pp.74-110; “The Normative Nature of Perceptual Experience.” In
Perceiving the World, ed. Bence Nanay, (Oxford : Oxford University Press,
2010), pp.146-158 ; Erik Rietveld, “Situated Normativity : The Normative
Aspect of Embodied Cognition in Unreflective Action.” Mind, vol. 117,
no. 468 (October 2008) : pp. 973-1001 ; Maxime Doyon et Timo Meyer,
Normativity in Perception, (Basingstoke : Palgrave Macmillan, 2015).
4 Wehrle, “Normality and Normativity in Experience”, p. 1.
5 Ibid.
2
A Merleau‐Pontian Account of Embodied Perceptual Norms
and attempts to unfold and clarify some of its implications for
embodied perception in general.
My goal in this paper is to address one of the key interpretations
of perceptual norms in contemporary merleau-pontian scholarship
and to suggest a new reading of their role in the Phenomenology of
Perception (1945), through the lense of interest and temporality. A first
section of this paper will thus provide a close reading of Sean Kelly’s
argument in “Seeing Things In Merleau-Ponty” (2005) and outline his
understanding of normativity in perception. Section 2 introduces
criticisms raised by Samantha Matherne, in addition to my own, and
opens up onto Section 3, which proposes a two-fold reading of
perceptual norms in both Merleau-Ponty and Husserl’s writings. This
last section introduces the concept of (practical) interest and argues in
favor of the temporal emergence of perceptual norms and their
embeddedness in living temporality.
1. Perceptual norms in Merleau-Ponty : the ‘view from
everywhere’ hypothesis
In a section from the Phenomenology of Perception titled ‘The Thing
and the Natural World’, Merleau-Ponty writes : “For each object, just
as for each painting in an art gallery, there is an optimal distance from
which it asks to be seen -an orientation through which it presents
more of itself- beneath or beyond which we merely have a confused
perception due to excess or lack.”6 With these words, Merleau-Ponty
suggests that the subject’s perceptual field is experienced normatively
rather than simply descriptively. On this view, the optimal range I
establish between me and a painting in a museum is neither
formulated as an explicitly laid-out rule, nor is it a distance I could
measure objectively. Rather, we might say that the optimal distance
Merleau-Ponty refers to is the stance that feels ‘just right’ or
‘appropriate’ in a given situation. What’s more, the establishment of
this distance serves more than the reception of sense-data on my
retina : customary phenomenological examples suggest that when the
embodied subject sees a painting in a museum or reaches for her
glasses on the bedside table, she immediately knows how to optimally
______________
6
Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology of Perception, trans. D. Landes
(London : Routledge, 2012), p. 315-316.
3
Corinne Lajoie
navigate her surroundings in order to accomplish the task at hand. As
Maria Talero puts it, a subject can be said to be “behaviorally
attuned”7 to her environment when she is adequately responsive to
the optimal interplay of action and perception it requires.
Hubert Dreyfus’s distinction between success conditions and
conditions of improvement works along similar lines to account for
normativity in perception. Through this distinction, Dreyfus suggests
that our context-dependent sensitivity to conditions of improvement
allows us to constantly discriminate between better or worse ways to
see things “without the agent needing in any way to anticipate what
would count as success.”8 Although it might first seem peculiar to
suggest that agents are driven towards improvement through their
bodies, Dreyfus’ view echoes a variety of colloquial sayings that
express how our bodies ‘take us here and there’ in everyday action,
without prior deliberation. As such, phenomenologists would argue
that our encounters with objects and others are bent upon implicitly
acquired perceptual norms which shape our perceptual field and play
an important part in facilitating our general orientations in the world.
This is not to say that deontic norms are not equally important in
many areas of our lives, but phenomenologists generally hold that
codified or logical norms presuppose an elementary ground of
intentional activity that is rooted in our experience of our own bodies.
A central outcrop of the Phenomenology of Perception lies precisely in
Merleau-Ponty’s detailed articulation of this specific type of motor
intentionality and the author explores the subject’s openness to the
world, conceived as a norm-sensitive space of (practical) meaning. To
this end, as Sean Kelly rightly observes in “Seeing Things in MerleauPonty”, Merleau-Ponty’s Phenomenology of Perception is uniquely relevant
to adress the question of normativity. In his paper, Kelly makes use
of Merleau-Ponty’s account of perceptual norms to answer a classic
problem in philosophy of perception. Put briefly, while Kelly argues
that Merleau-Ponty’s analysis of object-perception provides clear
answers to the problem of property constancy, he is adamant in
______________
7
Maria Talero, “The Experiential Workspace and the Limits of Empirical
Investigation”, International Journal of Philosophical Studies 16, no. 4 (Fall 2017),
p. 453-472, here p. 456.
8 Hubert Dreyfus, “The Primacy of Phenomenology over Logical Analysis”,
Philosophical Topics 27, no. 2 (Fall 1999), p. 3-24, here p. 6.
4
A Merleau‐Pontian Account of Embodied Perceptual Norms
defending that it does not provide clear answers to the problems of
perceptual presence and object constancy9. In an attempt to provide
answers to these problems, Kelly draws what he takes to be implicit
conclusions on Merleau-Ponty’s part and argues for a normative
account of perceptual experience. The first strokes of Kelly’s
argument are largely in accordance with Merleau-Ponty’s own view in
the Phenomenology and suggest that the perceptual field is experienced
normatively by the embodied subject when perceived affordances
render perceptually salient the ways in which indeterminate aspects,
elements and profiles (Abschattungen) of a perceived object could be
better determined and enrich our present view. Kelly’s general
argument thus relies on the following two claims : (i) perception
always involves an awareness of indeterminate aspects and (ii) our
perceptions are always experienced as deviations from an optimal
perception which would include these aspects and provide us with the
richest, fullest view.
Kelly explains : “Merleau-Ponty’s view of perception depends on
the idea that the background of our perception of objects and their
properties [...] must recede from view and yet functions everywhere
to guide what is focally articulate.”10 In short, that which recedes
from view and is indeterminate plays a normative role in my
perception of things. The indeterminate horizon of experience serves
as an orientation device of sorts, against which perceptual figures
emerge. This partial indetermination (or absence) at the heart of any
perception points to a possibility of fulfillment which hinges on the
differential structure of perceptual experience. On Kelly’s view,
perceptual norms thus manifest themselves through the
(kinesthetically) experienced gap left open by the alternance of
determination and indetermination in experience.
______________
9
As Samantha Matherne, “Merleau-Ponty on Style as the Key to Perceptual
Presence and Constancy.” Journal of the History of Philosophy, vol. 55, no. 4 (Fall
2017) : p.693-727, argues, and although this question will not concern us,
such a failure on Merleau-Ponty’s part would prove problematic for the
coherence and consistency of his account of perception. My main concern in
what follows, however, does not touch directly on this question.
10 Sean Kelly, « Seeing Things in Merleau-Ponty », in The Cambridge Companion
to Merleau-Ponty, ed. Taylor Carman (Cambridge, MA : Cambridge University
Press), p. 74-110, here p. 76.
5
Corinne Lajoie
Although the author himself does not acknowledge it, reading as
he does Husserl’s position largely inaccurately throughout this paper,
Kelly’s preliminary outline of the normative structure of perception
maps onto Husserl’s own descriptions of the normative tension
constitutive of object-perception. In what follows, however, it is
Kelly’s explanation for the way in which this experienced gap is
cashed out in experience that should interest us. At first sight, I am
very favorable to Kelly’s insistence on the essential articulation
between indetermination, embodiment and normativity in MerleauPonty’s account. As both Husserl and Merleau-Ponty have
convincingly shown, embodied perception is situated and thus
necessarily entails a limited perspective on the world. Moreover, as
Kelly argues, some perspectives are more relevant than others, in
proportion to their ability to disclose an object’s relevant features in a
better or worse way. Following Merleau-Ponty, Kelly holds that these
different perspectives do not stand indiscriminately in everyday
perception, and thus seeing things is always implicitly knowing how I
could see them better. However, the problem with Kelly’s view, as I
take it, lies in his explanation of this normative dimension of
perception. Although I agree with some of Kelly’s claims, I take issue
with what I consider to be the core argument of his paper and with
the manner in which he proceeds to draw conclusions from MerleauPonty’s text.
Let us go back, for now, to Kelly’s sketching out of a merleaupontian answer to the problem of property constancy. Put coarsely,
the problem of property constancy concerns our ability to perceive a
property as one and the same in spite of a variation in its system of
appearances. In his explanation, Kelly first suggests we consider the
specific role played by lighting in perception. As Kelly puts it, an
object’s ‘real’ colour, such as the constant colour of the table on
which I write, is experienced “in a direct bodily manner”11 as the
norm from which my current perception is felt to deviate. However
much the light I cast on this table varies, (e.g. when I open the blinds
in the morning, or when I close my desk lamp at night), my various
perceptions of its shade “necessarily [make] an implicit reference to
[...] the colour as it would be better revealed if the lighting context
______________
11
6
Ibid., p. 85.
A Merleau‐Pontian Account of Embodied Perceptual Norms
were changed in the direction of the norm.”12 The ‘real colour’, in this
case, is thus an indeterminately given optimal perception, which
nonetheless serves to establish the perceptual norm against which my
current view stands. It is part of my perception of the table on which
I work, argues Kelly, that I implicitly know “in a direct bodily
manner”13 how the light should vary, how my body should move or
how “the context should change”14 to allow me to see its ‘real’ colour.
This explanation, however, proves insufficient to account for the
problems of perceptual presence and object constancy. The first asks
how we can perceive aspects of objects that are not immediately
present in our perceptual field (i.e. when I perceive my laptop as
having a backside when I am typing), while the second is a variation
on the problem of property constancy as it applies to our perception
of the unity of the perceptual flow of an object’s various profiles (i.e.
knowing that my laptop is one and the same object as I move it
around before my eyes). As Kelly explains, while I could
hypothetically cast the optimal light on my table and see its ‘real’
colour, “there is no single point of view on the object that I could
have that would reveal it maximally.”15 (Kelly 2006 : 90) Put
otherwise, while the norm that served to explain the phenomena of
property constancy was intuitively experiencable in ideal viewing
conditions, the same does not seem to hold for three-dimensional
objects in perception. The fundamentally embodied nature of
perception foils any attempt to escape my point of view, and I can
only ever see one of the object’s profiles at once. Kelly formulates the
resulting problem in terms of access : given that our perceptions are
always limited and indeterminate, what optimal perspective could give
me a maximal grip on three-dimensional objects ? If the background
features of experience really do play a normative role in our current
perception, how are we to understand, in this case, the norm from
which our perception is felt to deviate ?
______________
12
Ibid., p. 86.
Sean Kelly, « Seeing Things in Merleau-Ponty », in The Cambridge Companion
to Merleau-Ponty, ed. Taylor Carman (Cambridge, MA : Cambridge University
Press).
14 Ibid., p. 87.
15 Ibid., p. 90.
7
13
Corinne Lajoie
Kelly’s answer to these questions is supported by a beautiful, and
yet intricate passage from the Phenomenology of Perception. In the
introduction to Part One, Merleau-Ponty is reflecting on perception’s
ability to “come about from somewhere, without thereby being
locked within its perspective.”16 Put coarsely, and following his
illustration, his reflection amounts to the following interrogation :
how can we take our perception of the house as we are walking up
the street towards it to be a perception of the ‘real’ house ? Is it not
the case that every one of these situated perceptions as I am walking
up the street cannot give me “the house itself”17, but rather only
always one of its profiles at once ? After rejecting the claim that “the
house itself is the house seen from nowhere”18, given its blatant
disavowal of the situatedness of embodied perception, Merleau-Ponty
entertains a second proposition. As quoted by Kelly, Merleau-Ponty
writes :
[To] see an object is to come to inhabit it and to thereby
grasp all things according to the sides these other things
turn toward this object. [...] Each object, then, is the mirror
of all the others. When I see the lamp on my table, I
attribute to it not merely the qualities that are visible from
my location, but also those that the fireplace, the walls, and
the table can “see”. The back of my lamp is merely the face
that it “shows” to the fireplace. [...] Thus, our formula
above must be modified : the house itself is not the house
seen from nowhere, but rather the house seen from
everywhere. The fully realized object is translucent, it is
shot through from all sides by an infinity of present gazes,
intersecting in its depth and leaving nothing there hidden.19
Kelly’s explanation of object constancy and perceptual presence
follows from just this passage and gives great weight to the idea of an
optimal “view from everywhere”20. Although this was never made
______________
16
Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology of Perception, p. 69.
Ibid.
18 Ibid.
19 Ibid., p. 71.
20 Kelly, “Seeing Things in Merleau-Ponty”, p. 92.
8
17
A Merleau‐Pontian Account of Embodied Perceptual Norms
explicit by Merleau-Ponty himself, Kelly argues that this passage from
the Phenomenology of Perception is the key to understanding the two
problems previously left unsolved. Moreover, although the ‘house
seen from everywhere’ is in no way “a view that I can have”21, its
virtual possibility sets the norm against which my current perception
of the house is measured. The view from everywhere is further
defined by Kelly as that which “would give me a better grip on the
object than any single point of view could”22, even though this grip is
not a grip my body actually could have, but rather a view virtually
constituted by the various objects that stand over and against the
central object I am perceiving. Lastly, Kelly concludes that the real or
constant thing in perception is the “maximally articulate norm against
which every particular presentation is felt to deviate”23 and “the
background against which my perspectival presentation makes
sense”24. In view of these conclusions, I take it that Kelly’s account of
perceptual normativity suggests a notion of norms as set by
experientially inaccessible optimal viewpoints, which our current
perceptions can asymptomatically strive towards, without however
ever reaching them.
2. Some problems with this view
In her response to Sean Kelly’s text, Samantha Matherne raises
two main lines of criticism. For the purpose of my argument, I will
leave aside her convincing defense of the role of style in MerleauPonty’s account of object constancy and perceptual presence, and
concentrate on the second aspect of her critique. As Matherne argues,
one of the main concerns with Kelly’s argument is exegetical. I largely
agree with Matherne that the passage on which Kelly’s argument
relies, and which I have quoted at lenght above, is simply not meant
to express Merleau-Ponty’s view. In true Merleau-Ponty fashion, the
author’s argument in this section emerges through a discursive
encounter with the pitfalls of both empiricist and intellectualist
positions. Although Merleau-Ponty does rhetorically entertain the
______________
21
Kelly, “Seeing Things in Merleau-Ponty”, p. 91.
Ibid., p. 92.
23 Ibid., p. 97.
24 Ibid., p. 98.
22
9
Corinne Lajoie
thought that the house itself could be the house “shot through from
all sides by an infinity of present gazes”25, this hypothesis is rejected
in its turn by the end of the chapter and the passage on which Kelly’s
argument turns is eventually debunked.
Most surprising, however, is the inconsistency between Kelly’s
aknowledgement of the constitutive role of an interplay between
determination and indetermination in perception, and his reliance on
a passage defending the possibility of a ‘fully realized’ and ‘translucent
object’. Such a conception of the object, it appears, would amount to
the objectivist’s ‘absolute positing’ of an object, which Merleau-Ponty
equates with “the death of consciousness, since it congeals all of
experience [...].”26 In positing its objects as things that exist inthemselves, the objectivist loses “the origin of the object at the very
core of our experience”27 and causes us to “ignore the contribution
we make through our embodied perspective.”28
Notwithstanding these factors, my main concern with Kelly’s
argument is not primarily exegetical. After all, it could be that Kelly’s
reading of this passage is accurate, in which case I would still argue
that it provides us with an incoherent view on perceptual norms. The
problem I thus take to be more important than defending MerleauPonty’s text is that of providing a phenomenologically sound account
of embodied norms, as they emerge in the course of experience. As I
hope to show, although perception strives towards richness and
clarity, it does not do so aimlessly. On the one hand, I am only
required a minimal awareness of my perceptual surroundings to find
my glasses on the kitchen counter, for example. On the other, it
seems clear that “more differentiation and more information is not
necessarily positive or helpful [...] as it can turn the visible into
something invisible.”29 This point is made very clearly by MerleauPonty himself, as he explicitly harmonizes his claims regarding our
striving for a maximum of visibility with a basic gestaltist principle of
______________
25
Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology of Perception, p. 71.
Ibid., p. 74.
27 Ibid.
28 Samantha Matherne, “Merleau-Ponty on Style as the Key to Perceptual
Presence and Constancy”, Journal of the History of Philosophy 55, no. 4, p. 693727, here p. 701.
29 Doyon, M. (manuscript).
10
26
A Merleau‐Pontian Account of Embodied Perceptual Norms
differentiation. That is to say, although “we seek, just as when using a
miscroscope, a better focus point”30 on the thing perceived,
perception is always a matter of equilibrium. Merleau-Ponty writes :
A living body seen from too close, and lacking any
background against which it would stand out, is no longer
a living body, but rather a material mass as strange as the
lunar landscape, as can be observed by looking at a
segment of skin with a magnifying glass ; and seen from
too far away, the living body again loses its living value,
and is no longer anything but a puppet or an automaton.31
The optimal perception, then, is to be found in the appropriate
balance between background and foreground, between determination
and indetermination or visibility and invisibility, where the perceived
is still caught up with its living value, somewhere between the lunar
landscape and the puppet.
In light of these preliminary shortcomings, another main concern
I have with Kelly’s claim that “[the] view from everywhere [...] is the
optimum perspective from which to view the object”32 is the
conclusions it might lead us to draw in regards to the limitations of
embodied experience. Both for Husserl and for Merleau-Ponty, the
situated character of perceptual experience does not hinder
perception’s claim to see things, rather than ‘parts of things’ or mere
‘aspects of things’. Both philosophers are committed to the view that
object-perception is not a conceptual reconstruction of singular
profiles and that the perceived object is given immediately and in the
flesh (Leibhaftig) through these profiles. The object’s hidden profiles
are neither known nor hypothesized : in largely compatible ways,
Husserl and Merleau-Ponty defend the view that these profiles form a
protentional horizon of possible experiences and are given to the
perceiving subject through the if-then structure of motor intentionality.
If I move my body to the left, then new aspects of the house I
perceive will be revealed.
______________
30
Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology of Perception, p. 355-356.
Ibid.
32 Kelly, “Seeing Things in Merleau-Ponty”, p. 91.
31
11
Corinne Lajoie
While Kelly does speak of the subject’s ability to “take up [other]
points of view”33 through a form of ‘bodily readiness’ near the end of
his paper, this section does not clearly impinge on his conception of
perceptual norms. Rather, Kelly maintains that our embodied
perception of objects deviates from the optimal givenness of a ‘view
from everywhere’. In my view, Kelly’s argument is misleading and
suggests that perception’s embodied nature still limits our grip on the
world in a problematic way, which calls for the hypothetical
resolution of an all-encompassing omniscient view. My concern is
that however much he stresses the importance of embodiment for
Merleau-Ponty, Kelly still gives credit to the view that embodied
perception in itself is constitutively insufficient to generate perceptual
norms and to account for our responsiveness to them. This view is
ultimately problematic from a phenomenological point of view, given
the centrality of embodiment for our being in the world. All things
considered, I worry that Kelly’s reading of normativity in MerleauPonty is phenomenologically intenable and operates with virtual
norms that lose their traction on lived experience.
I believe that Kelly’s omission of the essential role played by
interest and temporality is a good starting point to help explain some
of the serious difficulties his text amounts to. On the one hand, it
seems that norms are fundamentally contextual, and emerge out of
our practical engagement with specific projects. On the other, Kelly
offers no explicit description of the temporal emergence of norms
and speaks of the ‘real colour’, the ‘real size’ or the ‘real object’ as a
pre-determined and fixed exogenous norm standing outside the
course of experience, thus leaving aside a fundamental aspect of
Merleau-Ponty’s account of perception. In what remains of this
paper, I will attempt to briefly sketch out a merleau-pontian account
of embodied perceptual norms by way of the threefold significance of
embodiment, interest and temporality for perceptual life.
______________
33
Kelly, “Seeing Things in Merleau-Ponty”, p. 100
12
A Merleau‐Pontian Account of Embodied Perceptual Norms
3. Drawing out a new concept of norms
3.1. Situated norms : the role of interest
Although Merleau-Ponty also draws on the notion of practical
interest in the Phenomenology of Perception, it should be noted that it was
Edmund Husserl who first suggested a conception of optimality as
relative to interest in §36 of the Thing & Space (1907) lectures, when
he attempts to define the criteria of adequate perception. In Husserl’s
theory of perception, the incomplete givenness of the perceived thing
always “refers to possibilities of fulfillment whereby the thing would
come, step by step, to full givenness.”34 In view of this aim of optimal
givenness, our body continuously makes sense of and optimizes the
intentional relations that stand between us and our experiential field.
However, while Kelly’s argument suggests that the optimal
perception against which my current perception is measured displays
the richness and clarity of a ‘view from everywhere’, Husserl’s
conception of “[the] circle of maximum givennesses”35 suggests
otherwise36. Following Husserl’s example, when I see a match box
nestled between books on a shelf, the slight variations that my
perception of it might undergo do not matter the least, in this
context, to optimally perceive the match box qua match box. As long
as it allows me to perceive “the thing precisely as an ordinary thing in
the sense of any common interest of practical life”37, a varying
number of appearances, regardless of the distance from which I stand
______________
34
Edmund Husserl, Thing and Space. Lectures of 1907, trans. R. Rojcewicz
(Dordrecht : Springer, 1997), p. 105.
35 Ibid.
36 Surprisingly, Kelly also quotes §36 of Thing & Space, but glosses over its
central argument regarding the importance of interest for defining
optimality. Instead, he quickly dismisses what he takes to be Husserl’s
intellectualism and writes : “This system of perspectival presentations, which
Husserl sometimes also calls the ‘circle of complete givenness,’ is the ‘real’
object to which each perspectival presentation refers but which none by
itself is able to present. It can be understood intellectually, although not
presented perceptually, by imagining yourself walking around the object or
by imagining it rotating before you. This cannot be Merleau-Ponty’s view.”
(Kelly, “Seeing Things in Merleau-Ponty”, p. 94-95)
37 Husserl, E. Thing and Space. Lectures of 1907, p. 106.
13
Corinne Lajoie
or the lighting in the room, successfully fulfill my intention. However,
Husserl adds :
If the interest changes, if perhaps some intimation in the
appearance that previously counted as complete gives the
interest a new direction, then the circle of completely
satisfying appearances is transformed into an unsatisfying
circle, and the differences in the appearance, which
previously were irrelevant, may possibly now become very
relevant.38
Husserl’s point is quite intuitive : since a perception is always the
situated perception of a subject shaped by habits, goals, expectations
and an experiential past, the optimal norm of perception simply
cannot be a fixed one. In perception, “a practical tendency toward the
optimum”39 moves us toward the satisfaction of these conditions,
with “the interest [terminating] in the optimal givenness.”40 As
Husserl would argue, the botanist’s interest in a flower is different
from my own when I pass a flower shop on my way to university. My
interest in getting to university in time for a class, the poor knowledge
I have of plant biology, or my sudden desire to coordinate a bouquet
of hydrangeas for a friend would all play constitutively different roles
in establishing the norm for an adequately meaningful perception of
the flowers. As Steven Crowell recently argued, the epistemic value of
perception hinges on its claim to provide us “access to the object as
something”41 and thus “it too must entail conditions of satisfaction
that ‘set up’ (posit ; setzen) its object as a norm.”42 Husserl’s important
claim, however, is that these conditions are constantly amenable to a
variety of practical interests.
In the Phenomenology of Perception, Merleau-Ponty offers his concept
of ‘situation’ to make a similar claim and assert the importance of
interests to account for normativity in perception. In distinguishing
______________
38
Husserl, E. Thing and Space. Lectures of 1907, p. 106.
Ibid., p. 321.
40 Ibid., p. 322.
41 Steven Crowell, Normativity and Phenomenology in Husserl and Heidegger
(Cambridge, MA : Cambridge University Press, 2013), p. 125.
42 Ibid.
14
39
A Merleau‐Pontian Account of Embodied Perceptual Norms
between a ‘spatiality of situation’ and ‘spatiality of position’43,
Merleau-Ponty emphasizes the essential role played by situatedness in
embodied experience and argues that the spatiality of the embodied
subject is largely defined by the intentional projects towards which
she gathers herself. The situation of her body, then, is marked by a
body “polarized by its tasks, insofar as it exists toward them, insofar
as it coils up upon itself in order to reach its goal.”44 While her
position determines the set of objective coordinates that a subject
occupies in space, it does not give us the breath and scope of her
intentional life, as it is defined by practical interests, bodily
imperatives, skills and habits, affective moorings, and the likes.
Through various forms of “bodily recognition”45, we attune ourselves
to the “practical significations”46 opened up by our situation and take
up their meaning into our own. This is what I take Merleau-Ponty to
suggest when he writes of the living value of things (be it a body
under a microscope, or the mat of a boat I glimpse in the distance),
and of the perceptual equilibrium it calls on us to reach.
Most importantly for the question that interests us, MerleauPonty’s insistence on the notion of situation sheds new light on
Kelly’s claim that “the view from everywhere, which is the optimal
spatial context, is the view that would give me the maximum grip on
the object (if I could have it).”47 Against Kelly, it seems that MerleauPonty would hold that the maximal grip on the object is the type of
grip on the world that allows me to walk down its streets, ride its
trains, hold the hand of a friend, reach for a cigarette in my
backpocket or distractedly skim through a book, as these situations all
call forth different types of bodily responses. Perceptual norms, then,
owe more to the subtle and dynamic coupling of our bodies with
experiential cues in the world, than they do to the ideal standpoint of
a view from everywhere.
More generally, this central aspect of Merleau-Ponty and Husserl’s
analysis holds great importance for the question of normativity
because it emphasizes the broad and narrow contexts in which
______________
43
Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology of Perception, p. 102.
Ibid., p. 103.
45 Ibid., p. 81.
46 Ibid.
47 Kelly, “The Normative Nature of Perceptual Experience”, p. 95.
44
15
Corinne Lajoie
perception unfolds, and the role they play in defining the quality of
our perceptions. Perceptual norms are not abstract optimas of
givenness which stand outside of the various horizons in which they
function. In what remains of this paper, I will show that these norms
are rather determined both by the unfolding of short term intentional
projects (i.e. selecting flowers for a bouquet, reaching for my
toothbrush, finding a missing sock) and by the fine-grained
experiential weight our body schemas carry through time, allowing for
a stable and coherent experience.
3.2. Emergent norms : the role of temporality
In addition to being determined in part by the subject’s practical
and situated interests, norms present specific temporal features which
Kelly’s argument does not clearly address. To a certain extent, Kelly’s
point that the optimal context of perception is determined by our
positing of a virtual ‘view from everywhere’ begs the question. In
holding that norms are exogenous standards against which our
perceptions are measured, one is still confronted to the problem and
how and why they come to be established. In Kelly’s view, norms are
posited independently of our specific engagement with them and hold
valid across different time scales. The house ‘seen from everywhere’
simply is what it is, independently of the constant ebbing and flowing
of experience. Such a conception, however, is clearly incompatible
with the conclusions I have drawn in the preceding section.
Drawing on Merleau-Ponty’s work in The Structure of Behaviour,
Maria Talero suggests we conceive of phenomenal settings as being
fundamentally ‘mercurial’ and ‘labile’ environments characterized by
their dynamic structure and emergent norms. In describing the
particular setting of a football game, for example, she writes : “The
‘workspace’ of football [...] is precisely this complex and intricate
experiential arena characterized by ‘lines of force’, ‘sectors’ and
‘zones’ that emerge as the play develops, which collectively function
as normative parameters guiding each player’s participation the flow
of play [...].”48 According to Talero, norms progressively emerge at
the intersection of the player’s intentions and the affordances of the
______________
48 Talero, “The Experiential Workspace and the Limits of Empirical
Investigation”, p. 456.
16
A Merleau‐Pontian Account of Embodied Perceptual Norms
experiential setting. They are “embedded in the very ‘flow’ of the
play”49 and constantly “vulnerable to reinscription.”50 In such a view,
perceptual norms are fundamentally permeable and are sensitive to
past perceptions we retain, our experience of the present and our
anticipation of the future unfolding of perceptual settings.
This mercurial aspect of perceptual norms is also what I take to be
David Morris’ point in his discussion of perceptual illusions, which
functions just as well to acknowledge the basic structure of our
everyday perceptions. Against a traditional conception of illusions as
‘mistakes’, Morris suggests that the standards which allow us to
conceive of some perceptions as illusions “[rely] on perspectives
unavailable within illusory experience.”51 As Morris argues, the
vocabulary of illusion is merely a retrospective characterization which
testifies to the ambiguous overlapping between past and present
perceptual norms. In the course of everyday perception, various
timescales and the perceptual norms they carry come into play.
Norms thus emerge both on the micro-timescale of experience (as
classic ruber hand illusions tellingly reveal), and on the larger
timescale of evolution, as “a past within living behavior.”52 They are
both something “the organism brings along with it”53 and a
normative complex “modulated, and instituted by presently ongoing
dynamics”54.
In the Phenomenology of Perception, Merleau-Ponty introduces the
famous case of the Muller-Lyer illusion, in which two segments of
equal lenght are respectively represented with inward-pointing and
outward-pointing arrows. In Merleau-Ponty’s view, saying that I am
perceiving the lenght of the segments in a right or a wrong way
defeats the purpose of accounting for our perceptual engagement
______________
49
Talero, “The Experiential Workspace and the Limits of Empirical
Investigation”.
50 Ibid.
51 David Morris, “Illusions and Perceptual Norms as Spandrels of the
Temporality of Living”, in Normativity in Perception, ed. Maxime Doyon
and Thiemo Breyer (Basingstoke : Palgrave Macmillan, 2015), p. 75-90, here
p. 75.
52 Ibid.
53 Ibid., p. 85
54 Ibid.
17
Corinne Lajoie
with the illusion itself. The alternative, as Merleau-Ponty argues,
belongs to a currently inoperable set of conceptual tools and thus
requires that we introduce norms that are exogenous to our
experience itself. Rather, the lines “are neither equal nor unequal”55
and they stand in this compelling ambiguity until I actively attempt to
resolve its tension. Of this ambiguity, Morris writes : “I have
perceptual access to the Muller-Lyer figure only through my
determinate body and habits, and that’s just the way it looks in virtue
of my bodily-habitual engagement with it.”56
The perceptual norms we operate with thus also heavily draw on
an experiential past of embodied skills and habits which open up the
world for us in differentiated and normatively attuned ways. Only
when we recognize the essential temporality of embodied perceptual
norms can we begin to understand how they emerge from a deeprunning engagement with the world rather than externally predetermine this encounter. Much like our experiences of the world are
in contact with the horizons of past, present and future interactions,
perceptual norms are established within “temporally thick”57 living
dynamics.
4. Conclusion
In this paper, I provided an analysis and criticism of Sean Kelly’s
argument for normativity in perception, through the lense of
Merleau-Ponty’s Phenomenology of Perception. I rejected both Kelly’s
insistance on the idea of an optimal all-encompassing view from
everywhere, and the impossible standards it sets for everyday
perception. Instead, I suggested that our perceptions are contextsensitive and emerge in dynamic and labile environments through
which our bodies attempt to find a proper equilibrium. To this end, I
complicated Kelly’s claims by turning to the central role of (practical)
interest and temporality at the most basic level of embodied
experience. Although much remains to be said to establish a fully
convincing account of perceptual norms, it should now be clear that
______________
55
Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology of Perception, p. 6.
Morris, “Illusions and Perceptual Norms as Spandrels of the Temporality
of Living”, p. 77.
57 Ibid., p. 85.
18
56
A Merleau‐Pontian Account of Embodied Perceptual Norms
my reading of Merleau-Ponty’s Phenomenology of Perception is
incompatible with Kelly’s argument for perceptual presence and
object constancy. While I agree with Kelly that perceptual norms play
an essential part in shaping our interaction with the world, I contend
that his view still lacks some key considerations to offer a convincing
account of both their emergence and their signifiance.
Bibliography
Crowell, Steven. Normativity and Phenomenology in Husserl and Heidegger,
Cambridge, MA : Cambridge University Press, 2013.
Doyon, Maxime, “Husserl on Perceptual Optimality” (manuscript of
the author).
Dreyfus, Hubert. “The Primacy of Phenomenology over Logical
Analysis.” Philosophical Topics, vol. 27, no. 2 (Fall 1999) : p. 3-24.
Husserl, Edmund. Thing and Space. Lectures of 1907. Translated by
R. Rojcewicz. Dordrecht : Springer, 1997.
Kelly, Sean. “The Normative Nature of Perceptual Experience.” In
Perceiving the World, edited by Bence Nanay. p. 146-158. Oxford :
Oxford University Press, 2010.
Kelly, Sean. “Seeing Things in Merleau-Ponty.” In The Cambridge
Companion to Merleau-Ponty, edited by Taylor Carman. p. 74-110.
Cambridge, MA : Cambridge University Press, 2006.
Matherne, Samantha. “Merleau-Ponty on Style as the Key to
Perceptual Presence and Constancy.” Journal of the History of
Philosophy, vol. 55, no. 4 (Fall 2017) : p. 693-727.
Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. Phenomenology of Perception. Translated by
Donald Landes. London : Routledge, 2012.
Morris, David. “Illusions and Perceptual Norms as Spandrels of the
Temporality of Living” in Normativity in Perception, edited by
Maxime Doyon and Thiemo Breyer, p. 75-90. Basingstoke :
Palgrave Macmillan, 2015.
Rietveld, Erik. “Situated Normativity : The Normative Aspect of
Embodied Cognition in Unreflective Action.” Mind, vol. 117, no.
468 (October 2008) : p. 973-1001.
Talero, Maria. “The Experiential Workspace and the Limits of
Empirical Investigation.” International Journal of Philosophical Studies,
vol. 16 no. 3 (Spring 2008) : p. 453-472.
19
Corinne Lajoie
Wehrle, Maren. “Normality and Normativity in Experience” in
Normativity in Perception, edited by Maxime Doyon and Thiemo
Breyer, p. 128-140. Basingstoke : Palgrave Macmillan, 2015.
20