The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
1
This is the pre-edited version of the article published as:
“The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay,” in: Monism: Science, Philosophy,
Religion, and the History of a Worldview, ed. Todd Weir. Palgrave Series in
Intellectual and Cultural History (Palgrave: New York, 2012), pp. 1-44.
The Riddles of Monism: An introductory essay
Todd Weir1
Recent developments in the cognitive sciences point to a convergence, for some a
clash, of the humanities and natural science. In 2004 a group of leading neurobiologists
published a manifesto in the German journal Gehirn und Geist (Brain and Mind),
claiming that their discipline had succeeded in explaining and predicting many
psychological processes and would now tackle the problem of free will. A parallel
advance can be observed in the growing field of evolutionary psychology, where the
leading research question “what is the evolutionary good of God?” indicates that religion
has already been subsumed under the explanatory framework of Darwinian natural
selection.2 In the humanities, meanwhile, some scholars are looking to the physiology of
affective response to support new theories of emotions, subjectivity and cognition, while
others have argued that historians need to expand their inquiry beyond written and
archaeological sources and examine the brain itself as a historically evolving social
product, where the “features of culture” have been “wired in human physiology.”3 In
addition to crossing over the disciplinary boundaries of natural science and the
humanities, these varied scholarly endeavors represent a common challenge to the
Cartesian conception of mind and body as essentially separate domains. Rejecting the
dualistic understanding of human reality, they seek to analyze nature and culture from a
single disciplinary vantage point based on the assumption that mind and matter as parallel
but conjoined manifestations of a single substance. This philosophical stance is monism.4
The cognitive scientists and evolutionary psychologists, who believe that they are
on the verge of solving key philosophical problems such as the origin of free will,
consciousness, and religion premise their claims on extrapolations into the future of
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
2
current scientific trends. This makes their monism appear novel. Yet over a century ago
the German biologist Ernst Haeckel (1837-1919) argued that natural science had
essentially already solved these problems, which he called the “world riddles” and
thereby provided empirical verification of Baruch Spinoza’s (1632-1677) philosophical
proposition that mind and matter, or thought and extension, were but two modes of a
single substance. Darwinian evolution provided, in Haeckel’s interpretation, a master
theory linking the multiplicity of biological life to the development of human
consciousness and civilization as a single meaningful totality. For Haeckel, the unity of
matter and spirit in substance was mirrored by the unity of knowledge in natural science.
Haeckel had begun to use the term monism in 1866 and his efforts to propagate monism
as the sole viable modern worldview culminated in his international best-selling monist
manifesto The Riddle of the Universe in 1899 and the formation of the German Monist
League in 1906.
Today’s monists appear largely unaware of the monist movement of a century and
more ago, despite the many similarities. Both have featured struggles between natural
science and philosophy over jurisdiction and method, and both have been allied to
sometimes latent, sometimes overt attacks on revealed religion. Then as now, the popular
scientific media have provided the chief arena in which monists have staked their claims.
Yet the differences are striking. Whereas today’s monism largely lacks overt political
connotations, between the mid-nineteenth and the mid-twentieth century naturalistic
monism provided an important epistemological foundation to actors in host of social and
political movements. It was an undercurrent in the history of international socialism that
had a formative influence on more than one generation of socialist leaders from August
Bebel and Karl Kautsky to Walter Ulbricht and Mao Zedong. Whereas today’s feminist
movement has remained suspicious of socio-biological thought, naturalistic monism was
a source of inspiration for the early women’s movement and for pioneers of the
homosexual rights movement, who made it into the foundation of an inclusive humanism.
Other monists argued that history was driven forward by those races who had evolved
more advanced cultures. Their monism served as an ideology of imperialism.
Monists like Haeckel promised to clear up the “world riddles” created by dualistic
thinking with a good dose of empiricism and common sense, yet in science, culture and
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
3
religion, monism presented itself as a philosophy with its own riddles. While anticlerical,
monism developed a clear religious project of immanent transcendence. This took on a
scientistic hue in Haeckel’s definition of God as the summation of the laws of causation
or in the “monist Sunday sermons” delivered by chemist Wilhelm Ostwald during his
tenure as chairman of the Monist League. In the theosophical visions of Annie Besant
and Rudolf Steiner, by contrast, monism proved capable of providing the foundation for
an anti-materialist spiritualism that identified itself nonetheless with scientific research.
Spiritualistic and naturalistic monism intermingled in the manifestoes of avantgarde
aesthetic movements and in the creative works of artists like Isadora Duncan and Wassily
Kandinsky, George Eliot and Rainer Maria Rilke.
The political and religious valence of monism has shown strong geographic
variation. Whereas the “culture wars” of the United States provide a ready market for the
monistically minded “new atheists” of today, a century ago naturalistic monism proved
most radical in Germany and Russia, where monarchical rule was inseparable from the
power of the state churches.
Following the Second World War, the passions surrounding monism cooled. The
term itself largely vanished from public usage and returned to the marginal vocabulary of
philosophy from whence it had come. Not only was the monist movement largely absent
from popular memory in the postwar period, scholars working in historical disciplines
also paid it scant attention. Given developments in science and scholarship during the
Cold War, it is easy to understand why monism became hard to see. Its holistic,
spiritualized understanding of science ran counter to methodological trends within the
natural sciences and contradicted the functional differentiation that was assumed to
govern the relationships between the disciplines. As the certitudes of modernization have
eroded, however, phenomena like naturalistic monism have become increasingly visible
to the historical gaze.
Scholars are now interested in historical monism, not as a dry branch on the tree of
scientific evolution, but rather as a symptomatic expression of an age that was marked by
secularism but was not yet secular. Following the cultural turn in the history of science,
that discipline in particular has found in the monist movement an exemplary case for
investigating how late nineteenth-century natural science spilled over into religion,
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
4
philosophy, politics and culture. We now have some excellent studies on what might be
termed the “narrow” history of monism, i.e. on the activities and philosophy of Ernst
Haeckel and the Monist League between the late nineteenth century and the First World
War.
It was with the aim of extending this research and mapping out the contours of
naturalistic monism in a wider chronological, disciplinary and geographic framework that
a colloquium was convened on October 2 and 3, 2009 at Queen’s University Belfast
under the auspices of the Wiles Trust. The essays in this volume represent the fruits of
the discussion in Belfast between scholars from history of science, intellectual and
cultural history, religion, geography, political science and literary studies.
By way of framing these their essays, my own introductory essay will take a step
back and provide an overview and evaluation of the broad trends in research into
monism. In so doing, I want to make the case that study of monism places in a new light
some of the chief intellectual, cultural, religious and political questions and conflicts in
the period between the 1840s and 1940s, making this in many ways a “monist century.” I
will pursue two lines of argument. The first is that we have in monism a peculiar type of
socially-embodied knowledge that is little understood and yet which illuminates one of
the important ways in which religion, science and philosophy coalesced in social and
political movements in this period. I approach this task through an analysis of two key
terms in The Riddle of the Universe. In the term “world riddles,” i.e. those points of
conflict between dualistic and monist philosophical system, I find the nodal points upon
which the entire monist edifice was erected. Viewed from the perspective of these
riddles, modern monism did not belong to a sole discipline, be it science, philosophy or
religion. Turning to the social embodiment of monism, I will argue that monism was
linked to too many movements and social interests to be usefully analyzed an ideology.
Rather than approaching it as philosophy, religion, scientific paradigm or ideology,
monism is best understood as a novel formation of knowledge captured in the second key
term “worldview.” Indeed, in many ways the German concept of Weltanschauung
developed in tandem with and through the history of monism, so that monism offers a
particularly rich avenue for exploring what made the monist century also an age of
worldviews.
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
5
The second approach this essay takes to expanding our understanding of monism is
to sketch out a map of the monist century by surveying the many temporal, social and
geographic locations in which monism manifested itself outside of the realms of science
and philosophy. Here, I begin by looking at some of the qualitative changes in the
articulation of monism in the 1840s and 1850s, when it went from being an esoteric
philosophical position to a worldview that organized a host of dissenting movements. As
two examples of late nineteenth century dissent, I delve briefly into the role of monism in
the early women’s and homosexual rights movements. The essay then charts some of the
public controversies that surrounded monism in the field of ethics before turning to
aesthetics. Artists and writers revealed an important aspect of monism, namely the
coexistence and ongoing competition of Haeckel’s naturalistic monism with other forms
of monism, whether idealistic, spiritualistic or neutral. Finally, I consider the
international fate of monism in the competing worldview regimes of twentieth-century
Germany and the USSR before ending with some preliminary conclusions about what the
changes wrought by the end Second World War tell us about the conditions that had
sustained the culture of popular monism over the previous century.
The “narrow” history of monism
Because the other contributors explore border zones, chart out new areas of
research, and engage in comparative study, it falls to this introduction to first outline the
“narrow” history of monism, which has focused justifiably on the figure of Ernst
Haeckel.5 Although he did not invent the term monism, he did most to popularize it. It is
generally agreed that the term first appeared in German in a 1721 treatise by the early
Enlightenment philosopher Christian Wolff. Monism remained, however, an obscure
philosophical term that came to be used increasingly, but still infrequently, in the first
half of the nineteenth century by theologians and philosophers to describe or decry
aspects of contemporary pantheism, spiritualism or Hegelian speculation.6 Having
discovered the word monism in the work of philologist August Schleicher, a friend and
colleague in Jena, Haeckel applied it to a naturalistic worldview based chiefly on the
theory of biological evolution. In 1866, five years before the publication of Darwin’s
Descent of Man, Haeckel argued in his General Morphology that natural selection
accounted for the development of humans from lower life forms. As proof, Haeckel
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
6
showed how the human embryo passed through stages of development recapitulating the
lower life forms from which it had evolved. 7 The book culminated in a description of
“the unity of nature and the unity of science” in a “system of monism.” Monism not only
encapsulated Haeckel’s faith that the universe was united in a single substance and
governed by a single set of laws. By linking mind and body, matter and spirit, naturalistic
monism allowed Haeckel to make claims in the realms of philosophy and religion. In his
Natural Stories of Creation (1868) Haeckel spoke simply of his natural scientific
worldview as “a monistic religion.”8
Although other scholars employed the term monism in the 1870s and thereafter,
Haeckel’s definition remained the dominant one, particularly in the German-speaking
world. A further testament to Haeckel’s centrality was the role he played in the formation
of monist organizations. When he began to withdraw from active research and devote
himself to propagating monism in the 1890s, Haeckel’s philosophy found an enthusiastic
audience among the secularists, freemasons and republicans, who had united in 1880 in
the International Congress of Freethinkers to oppose clerical influence in public life.9
Haeckel turned down an offer to assume the helm of German Freethought League in
1899. Instead, he called for the formation of a new organization at the International
Congress of Freethinkers in Rome in 1904. A German Monist League (DMB) was duly
formed under Haeckel’s aegis in 1906. Led by a handful of prominent scientists and
philosophers, this organization attracted a membership of around 5,500, composed
primarily of university trained professionals: physicians, secondary-school teachers,
writers, and engineers.10
The Monist League, like its founder, displayed what today might be considered
contradictory tendencies towards emancipation and social control. This contradiction
reflects, in part, the predicament of bourgeois liberals in Germany, whose cultural
hegemony had not translated into political dominance. The prominence of racial hygiene
and anticatholicism in the League’s early public work coincided loosely with the 1906
government coalition that brought liberals together with conservatives under a program
of imperialism and confessional antagonism.11 The collapse of this coalition in 1909 cut
liberals adrift and contributed to the leftward turn of the Monist League. A public debate
sponsored by the League in Berlin in 1910 on the question “Did Jesus live?” signaled a
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
7
shift from anticatholicism towards a broad anti-Christian campaign. In December 1910
Haeckel announced his withdrawal from the Protestant Church and the following year the
League became the chief sponsor of the Committee of the Confessionless, a secularist
alliance of liberal monists and social democratic freethinkers who waged a three-year
campaign to encourage mass desertion from the state churches. The high point of this
campaign came in 1913, when the League’s chairman, Wilhelm Ostwald, and the future
founder of the Communist Party, Karl Liebknecht, jointly denounced the state churches
before a crowd of thousands at an open-air rally in Berlin. 12
When Ostwald, a Nobel laureate in chemistry, assumed leadership of the Monist
League in 1911, he brought along his own monistic system of “energetics”. Whereas
Haeckel’s monism proposed biological evolution as the central framework for the
progressive organization of substance, Ostwald described different manifestations of
energy. Where Haeckel sought the unity of all science under the umbrella of Darwinian
theory, Ostwald developed a hierarchical model of the sciences, allocating to each
discipline responsibility for explaining a different level in the organization of energy. As
a placeholder for the discipline that would study the highest level of complexity in human
society, Ostwald proposed the neologism “culturology.”13
Ostwald also sought to redefine the ethical and political program of Monist League
according to his energetics. Haeckel based ethical judgments on the health of the species,
making eugenics his ultimate ethical system. Ostwald proposed a monist ethics based on
what he called the “energetic imperative” which was “waste no energy, utilize it.” He
promoted an array of practical applications of monism, such as international
standardization of industrial norms and artificial language (he favored Ido over
Esperanto). In 1913 the League named as its chief areas of operation: natural science and
medicine, technology, school reform, the protection of mothers and sexual reform, land
reform, the peace movement, the abstinence movement, and the cooperative movement.14
Presiding over the International Monist Congress in Hamburg in May 1911,
Ostwald outlined the promise of monism as the key to “world-organization.” This was to
be a technocratic solution of world problems. Ostwald summed up this global ambition
by declaring the opening of a “monist century.” The monist heyday under Ostwald’s
leadership was, however, very short-lived. As an organizational form, German and
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
8
international monism broke up on the reefs of the First World War. The majority of the
Monist League opposed the war, causing Haeckel and Ostwald, the former champions of
pacifism now turned expansionist nationalists, to resign in 1915. Ostwald’s replacement
was the psychiatrist and sociologist Franz Müller-Lyer, who offered evolutionary
sociology as yet another principle for unifying all science in a single worldview.
Most studies of the “narrow” history of monism have ended with the First World
War. After the war, the estranged nationalists did not rejoin the Monist League, though
some took their monist theorizing into völkisch circles.15 Some of the better-known
leftwing monists, like the editor of the Weltbühne Carl von Ossietzky, the feminist
Helene Stöcker, and the sexologist Magnus Hirschfeld, did not remain active. Although it
continued to operate until it was banned by the new regime in 1933, the Monist League
failed to recapture the public imagination during the Weimar Republic.16
Two methodological approaches to the riddles of monism
The title of my essay alludes to Haeckel’s monist manifesto The Riddle of the
Universe (published in 1899 in German with the title Die Welträtsel). This book was, by
some accounts, the most popular work of science hitherto published in Germany.17 By
1914 it had sold three hundred thousand copies in German and by 1931 it had been
translated into twenty languages. Haeckel’s archive contains thousands of letters received
from inspired readers. Asserting that monism could crack the key problems of science
and philosophy—the “world riddles”—the book heralded a coming age when natural
science would solve modernity’s most vexing issues. Like many monist tracts, its popular
appeal rested on the ability of a scientific authority to assure readers that its philosophical
claims were really self-evident and easily verifiable by simple empirical observation and
the use of common-sense. Today these claims appear anything but self-evident. They
throw up a host of paradoxes. Here was a scientific philosophy that resisted falsification
and an anticlerical movement associated with a mix of religious innovations. Here was a
movement that advocated technocratic social control as a means to emancipation, the
leaders of which have been tarred with the brush of ethical nihilism and yet saw
themselves as the genuine inheritors of humanism. These are some of the “riddles” of
naturalistic monism that make it a challenging subject for historical analysis.
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
9
The riddles of monism are best approached through the joint consideration of the
two aspects that gave the naturalistic monism of Haeckel’s era its particular historical
signature and showed it to be quite different from monisms that preceded and succeeded
it. First, naturalistic monism was a totalizing philosophy bent on eradicating the
boundaries between other forms of knowledge in the name of science. Second, it was
mobilized within sharp social, religious and institutional conflicts and even developed
autonomous organizational forms, of which the Monist League was the most prominent. I
would now like to link these two aspects in an exploration of two key concepts used by
monists: “world riddle” and “worldview”. A brief conceptual historical treatment of each
can demonstrate in an exemplary fashion the intimate connection between philosophical
claims and dissent. Moreover, once contextualized, these terms can provide a vocabulary
for the interdisciplinary analysis of monism. For the “world riddles” and “worldview”
reveal some of the paradoxes or riddles at the heart of naturalistic monism as a peculiar
form of knowledge.
The “world riddles”
The term “world riddle” and its centrality to monism emerged out of a dispute
between two eminent German scientists over the proper boundaries of natural science.
Speaking to an audience of several thousand gathered at Germany’s largest annual
conference of scientists and physicians in 1872, the Berlin physiologist Emil du BoisReymond compared natural science to “a world-conqueror of ancient times.” Just as his
imagined warrior chief might pause “in the midst of his victorious career” and survey the
“boundaries of the vast territories he has subjugated” to discern whether some “natural
barrier that cannot be overcome by his horsemen” might “constitute the true limits of his
power,” du Bois-Reymond told his listeners that it was fitting “if Natural Science, the
world-conqueror of our times, resting as on a festive occasion from her labor, should
strive to define the true boundaries of her immense domain.”18
As one of the best-known and most powerful scientists in the capital of recently
unified Germany, Du Bois-Reymond was well placed to speak on behalf of the empire of
science. He pinpointed two “two widely-diffused errors with regard to the limits of
natural science” that threatened its legitimacy. The origin of movements (first causes) and
the origin of consciousness were two questions not open to empirically verifiable,
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
10
quantitative, mechanical explanations, hence their investigation did not belong to the
realm of natural science. These marked the limits of natural knowledge and he named
them “world riddles.” To illustrate the folly of any attempt to cross these limits, he
argued that even a scientist with a perfect understanding of neural chemical processes
could no more explain the brain’s thoughts than a balloonist could reach the moon.
Whereas scientists were used to saying “ignoramus”—we do not know—in the face of
presently inexplicable scientific problems of a mechanical nature, when faced with
“world riddles”, they must turn back and utter “ignorabimus”—we will not know.19
In a second major speech on the subject given eight years later, du Bois-Reymond
expanded the number of “world riddles” to seven, some of which science could not
presently solve and some of which could never be solved and were hence “transcendent.”
The seven riddles were: the relationship of matter and force, the origins of motion, of life,
of sensation, of consciousness and of free will, as well as the apparently purposeful order
of nature. He also noted the wide public echo of his earlier “ignorabimus.” Rather than
leading to the acceptance of his riddles as boundary stones, the word had become “a type
of natural philosophical shibboleth.” As in the biblical story, where shibboleth was the
word used to weed out the members of a hostile tribe who could not pronounce it, du
Bois-Reymond’s “ignorabimus” had succeeded in flushing out enemies, most particularly
Ernst Haeckel.20
Haeckel responded with speeches and essays, countering Bois-Reymond’s
“ignorabimus” with his own Latin slogan “impavidi progrediamur!” (we must proceed
without fear).21 When Haeckel finally published a complete system of naturalistic
monism in 1899, he took du Bois-Reymond’s Welträtsel as the title of his book.
Haeckel’s book also opened with an imaginary map, a survey of the transformations of
“the whole of our modern civilization, not only by our astounding theoretical progress in
sound knowledge of nature, but also by the remarkably fertile practical application of that
knowledge in technical science, industry, commerce, and so forth.” Haeckel’s map too
was drawn to characterize a threat to modern civilization, albeit a threat arising from a
lack rather than an excess of scientific zeal. Insufficient progress in “moral and social
life” threatened “grave catastrophes in the political and social world” that could be
averted only through the spread and application of a scientific “natural worldview.” This
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
11
worldview was monism. Haeckel claimed that the theory of substance and evolutionary
biology could solve all of the riddles that du Bois-Reymond had posed. In successive
chapters, Haeckel offered clear and simple examples from scientific research to prove
these points. 22
Haeckel and du Bois-Reymond represented two competing conclusions about the
meaning of modern science for culture. Each claimed that his was a “mechanical
worldview” derived entirely from empirical observation. However, where du BoisReymond’s map of science halted by an act of “manly renunciation” at the boundary of
the world riddles, Haeckel’s map was unbounded, whole and total.
In a narrow sense, this was a debate about what constituted good scientific method,
however, it was also a debate over the relationship between disciplines. Du BoisReymond rejected Haeckel’s claim that he was a “dualist” and in league with Kantian
philosophy and religious orthodoxy. However, by calling some of the world riddles
“transcendent,” Du Bois-Reymond was indeed setting up an argument for separate
spheres of influence for science and theology, something Stephen Jay Gould (with similar
anti-monistic intent) would later call “non-overlapping magisteria.” Parallel conclusions
were being reached by Neo-Kantian philosophers, who developed clear methodological
boundaries between the empirical sciences, which sought general laws, and the cultural
sciences, which were concerned with historical explanation.23
The proposed inviolability of the “world riddles” allowed room for a transcendent
sphere outside of the natural world, and for a human subject outside of natural scientific
determinism. It also strengthened the disciplinary boundaries of theology, philosophy and
science thereby preventing the “pollution” of science by religion and philosophy.
Conversely, Haeckel quite consciously saw that the eradication of these barriers was
essential, if monism was to act as a religion and philosophy of immanent transcendence.
Monism was, as Haeckel declared in a major speech of 1892, “a link between religion
and science.”24
The debate between du Bois-Reymond and Haeckel demonstrates paradigmatically
how two versions of scientific secularity defined one another through conflict. On the one
hand, out of opposition to monism, du Bois-Reymond developed an argument for a
secular order based on scientific self-restraint and disciplinary differentiation. Haeckel’s
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
12
position, by contrast, might be called secularist rather than secular, as it sought to replace
religion with a new universal creed based in empirical natural science.
The “world riddles” marked the key points of friction between monism and
dualistic systems; they also formed the epistemological and spiritual nodal points of the
monist system. Thus both as a social formation and as a philosophical system, the
scientific, social and religious struggles over these boundaries were what made monism
operational. Exploration of the world riddles naturally formed a research agenda for
monist science. Because monist philosophy posited that the universe was an
interconnected and unitary order of being raised to self-consciousness through human
culture and crowned finally by monist worldview, it fell to natural science to prove that
the “world riddles” were merely points of transition and not boundaries between the
domains of this order.
Two of these points of transition stand out as key targets of monist science. The
first was the transition from inorganic matter to organic life. Following Spinoza’s dictum
that “all things have souls,” Haeckel argued that crystals were matter striving for life. His
last book Crystal Souls of 1917 put forward the theory that the universal substance
consisted not only of matter and motion, but also of psychic energy, or “psychom.”25
According to Haeckel, the highest form of psychic organization was human selfconsciousness. This connection of consciousness to biology was the second and more
central question in the work of monist scientists. In psychology, the reigning Kantian
model of cognition separated off the operations of the mind from the perceived world
outside. This model enticed monist mediation. One line of monist thought led into
psychophysics, as proposed theoretically by physiologist Gustav Fechner and pursued in
experimental science by Ernst Mach and Wilhelm Wundt. Psychophysical parallelism
was considered on the philosophical side by the likes of William James and Bertrand
Russell.26 The desire to connect the cultural products of the human mind with biology
also informed the dogged defense by naturalistic monists of Neo-Lamarckianism.
Whereas the germ plasma theory of August Weissmann rejected biological learning and
thereby erected a wall of separation between biology and culture, monists favored the
theory of the “inheritance of acquired characteristics” that allowed communication
between the organism and the environment.27
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
13
Monism as worldview
Unpacking the term “worldview” is necessary if one wants to understand how
monists dealt with one of the chief paradoxes of their philosophy, namely how
unbounded scientific explanation remained curiously resistant to scientific criticism. A
window into the relationship of worldview and monism is offered by the monist
philosopher Arthur Drews. In his 1908 essay on the varieties of monism, Drews
demonstrated the shortcomings not only of Haeckel’s hylozoism (from the Greek
“matter” + “life”), but of at least eight other contemporary and historic varieties of
monism as well. At the end, Drews offered Eduard von Hartmann’s philosophy of the
unconscious as the only successful monist system. Yet Drews’s summary of this older
philosophical work was so limp and so brief that the reader must conclude that Drews did
not find Hartmann necessary to support the claim that “the world belongs to the monist
idea.” Indeed, in his preface Drews argued that critics who focused on the weakness of
each system were missing the point. Monists, he wrote, have many perspectives
(betrachtungsweise) they have only one view (anschauungsweise). In other words,
perspectives could be wrong without invalidating the view. The varieties of monism were
just passing forms, giving way to a higher worldview.28 “Worldview” thus paradoxically
preceded the science that supposedly produced it.
On a basic level, most monists understood the relationship of worldview to science
within a positivist cognitive model, which held that free reason and empirical observation
would lead to a uniform understanding of the world as a whole. If theories were
erroneous that was not the fault of nature, it simply meant that monists had to learn to
listen better to nature’s symphony.29 This was a correspondence theory of knowledge that
saw the mind’s function as the mirroring of the laws of nature. Hence Frederick Gregory
terms monism a nineteenth century mode of knowing.30 However, if we leave the realm
of academic knowledge and consider monism as a popular knowledge in the form of
worldview, we find that it was compatible, indeed paradigmatic, of trends in the first half
of the twentieth century as well. Here it is worth considering the specific meanings of the
German term “Weltanschauung” which was ubiquitously used not just by monists, but by
many other political, cultural and religious groups to describe their respective
philosophies. When Germans invoked the term in the period between the 1840s and
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
14
1940s, they understood Weltanschauung to be more than just a shared cultural-cognitive
framework of perception, which is how social scientists often use the English term
“worldview” today. Weltanschauung was understood to be a systematic understanding of
the world as a meaningful totality that formed the basis of a community. It was a form of
knowledge that not only explained the present state of the social and physical world, but
was expected to contain a normative system and a program of salvation on many fronts.31
In order to meet these expectations, secular worldviews such as monism used
structuring paradoxes to reconcile science, which promised a rational explanation of the
world, with potentially irrational plans of salvation. Whereas monotheistic religions offer
redemption in a transcendent sphere accessed in an afterlife, secular worldviews placed
redemption in history at the end of a period of intentional struggle. Of the two bestknown twentieth century worldviews, Marxism posited a universal class that required
revolution to become truly universal, while National Socialism was premised on the
belief that an act of purification through violence would restore the German people to
health and power. Monists ascribed to the belief that Nature and Humanity already
existed as totalities, yet were paradoxically denied to the faithful at present. These
universal subjects would be redeemed and achieve self-consciousness through a two-fold
struggle: a political struggle against dualist reactionaries in the public sphere and an
intellectual struggle through scientific discovery and education. In the former case,
worldview was the banner of secularism, in the latter, worldview was the draft sketch for
the edifice of unified knowledge that science would construct. Scientific worldview thus
carried the promise of redemption and the explanation of why this redemption had not yet
occurred. Always on the cusp of being solved, the world riddles were both the neuralgic
points and the central pillars of this worldview. By retaining the tension between solution
and the “not yet,” the riddles functioned as paradoxes that allowed the monist worldview
to be an object of faith that could be reconciled with the rational principle of scientific
modernity.
Although the argument has just been made that monism represents a quintessential
expression of the religious dimensions of modern worldview, it would be wrong to
assume that religion was the secret source of monism. Walter Benjamin famously likened
another worldview, historical materialism, to an invincible, chess-playing automaton,
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
15
operated by a hunchbacked dwarf called theology, who crouched hidden under the
table.32 This allegory fits the basic approach to worldview taken by theorists of “political
religion.”33 However, it does not apply as well to monism for two reasons. First, whereas
Soviet Marxism had erased its own religious origin in Feuerbach’s criticism, monism
made no secret of its desire to operate in the field of religion. Secondly, while Marxism
staked out its domain in the political and economic realms, naturalistic monism did not
have a privileged domain. If we use the term worldview, we can find a position for
monism that is, in some sense, outside of all the domains, transgressing each and seeking
to eradicate its boundaries. Monism is neither false ideology nor political religion,
because both of these terms presuppose a mask and an essence behind it.
What I am suggesting here is a perspectival shift in the analysis of monism.
Because critics have hitherto viewed monism from observer positions within one of the
domains of knowledge, be it science, philosophy or religion, they have interpreted
monism as an intrusion by an outside interest. Unmasking naturalistic monism as bad
philosophy prompted by scientific hubris has been a relatively easy game for
philosophers, like Habermas, who suggested that the neurobiologists who penned the
2004 declaration had succumbed to “metaphysical temptation” and been “pulled into the
undertow of philosophical speculation.” This is but a recent iteration of a long tradition of
teasing the emperor science for his new philosophical clothes. Responding to Haeckel’s
attempt to place his monism in the great tradition of German idealist systems,
feuilletonist Fritz Mauthner wrote that Haeckel’s writings revealed that “semi-educated”
minds were “nowhere more terrible than in the realm of philosophy.” In 1937 the
theologian Walter Nigg similarly discounted the turn to monism by some Protestant
dissenters as a devolution into “religious cretinism.” 34 These judgments may or may not
be correct but they are certainly incomplete, because monism was not just a scientific
intrusion into philosophy and religion. It was also a philosophical and religious intrusion
into science. Both as a development in the history of ideas and as a social movement,
monism cannot be adequately understood from a single perspective. To reduce it to one
of its component parts or disciplinary foundations would be to misrepresent it. Given that
all knowledge is produced in variegated discursive and social networks, this conclusion
will sound like a truism. However, what differentiated monism from many philosophical
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
16
or scientific movements is that its coherence as a worldview coincided with a marked
disciplinary homelessness.
The homelessness of worldview also helps account for monism’s position between
academic and popular science. In his classic study of popular science, the Polish
philosopher of science Ludwik Fleck concluded that “[t]he pinnacle, the goal of popular
knowledge is worldview.” Fleck explained worldview as a byproduct of the essential
processes of science popularization: simplification, valuation and visualization. He also
described the feedback loop between popular and academic science through which
worldview helps pre-form the “style of thought” of the scientific community.35
Fleck’s ahistorical, functional model of the relationship of worldview and popular
science has been enormously influential. Writing as he was in Central Europe of the
1930s, a society without worldview might have been inconceivable to Fleck. Since then
the concept of worldview has undergone massive transformations, so that we must look
beyond the processes of popularization to understand the audience’s hunger for
worldview in the first half of twentieth century. In particular, we should consider the
attachment of worldviews to the social and political movements of the period. Monism
was certainly an expression of the cultural power of natural science, but also a medium
through which social movements could claim scientific legitimacy for their positions. The
pressure exerted on science is revealed in the opening line of Drews’s essay: “At present
the need for a monistic understanding of reality is one that is generally felt and that seeks
expression through a variety of channels.”36 It would be more accurate to speak of
“needs” here, as monism responded to multiple needs. Some of these needs were widely
diffused and may be best approached through biographical and periodical literature, while
some needs were organized in discrete formations of social dissent.
Investigations that take such needs into account will go beyond the usual methods
of the history of scientific and philosophical ideas and view monism as a socially
embodied, novel form of knowledge, best captured in the term worldview, i.e. one that is
approached from any number of disciplinary systems, religious positions, social interests,
or biographical histories. This understanding of monism allows historians to consider the
conditions that accompanied the rise and survival not only of this particular worldview
but of the project of worldview overall.
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
17
From “narrow” monism to a monist century
Worldviews make universal claims but leave discrete historical imprints. In the
following, I survey the particular imprints of monism that have been revealed by recent
scholars, including the authors of this volume. The provisional map that emerges of the
various geographical, social, scientific or chronological locations of monism shows
provide some contours to what may be seen as a monist century.
The origins of modern monism
Where does the history of modern monism begin? Certainly there was a strong
monist current in German thought around 1800. Idealism, Naturphilosophie, and
Romanticism all questioned assumptions of Cartesian philosophy and Newtonian physics,
while contending with the epistemological dualism of Immanuel Kant’s model of human
cognition. Key thinkers like Schelling, Goethe and Hegel drew heavily on the early
modern monism of Baruch Spinoza and Giordano Bruno, but gave it a nineteenth-century
historicist twist by adding the dimension of becoming, of evolution.37 If dated from its
emergence as a popular worldview, however, we can identify the 1840s as the starting
point of what might be termed a “monist century.” It was then that a number of factors
converged, leading to a qualitatively different monism, one which reached a mature
expression in Haeckel’s first clear articulations of his monist theory in General
Morphology of 1866.
The qualitative shift at mid-century can best be explained with reference to an
antinomy identified already in 1721 by philosopher Christian Wolff. Whereas monists
generally purport to have overcome the terms of the mind-body dualism with a neutral
third term, Wolff noted that monists in fact tend to locate universal substance in one or
the other: either the mind or the body, the soul or matter. Historians of philosophy have
followed suit and generally differentiate between materialistic or naturalistic monism, on
the one hand, and idealistic or spiritualistic monism, on the other.38 According to Georgi
Plekhanov, the founder of Russian Marxism and Lenin’s mentor, monism was a central
aspect of all nineteenth century thought, but whereas the first half of the century “was
dominated by idealistic monism,” “in its second half there triumphed in science—with
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
18
which meanwhile philosophy had been completely fused—materialistic monism,
although far from always consistent and frank monism.”39
There is ample evidence from the 1840s and 1850s to support Plekhanov’s claim
that the turn from idealistic to materialist monism was accompanied by a second
qualitative change. The chief field of the production of monism shifted, as philosophers
and natural scientists alike looked to experimental science to answer philosophical
problems. When Ludwig Feuerbach called for a humanist anthropology to replace
Christian theology in The Essence of Christianity (1841), he not only reversed the
predication of God and man, he called for the integration of the sciences of man,
including biology, into philosophy. According to philosopher Friedrich Harms in 1845,
however, rather the opposite was happening. Whereas Hegel had swallowed all of the
sciences in his system, Harms feared that through Feuerbach’s anthropology “the
experiential sciences would devour philosophy.”40
Radical epistemological conclusions were also being drawn by empirical scientists.
In the mid 1840s, a group of physiologists in Berlin, including Hermann Helmholtz,
Rudolf Virchow and the young Emil du Bois-Reymond, demanded that scientists allow
only mechanical explanations of life processes and exclude reference to outside forces
inaccessible to the senses. This direct attack on the deductive methods of natural history
and natural philosophy had wider implications as Virchow noted in lecture in Berlin in
December 1846: “at a time when philosophy has turned to nature and to life, […]
medicine has discarded faith, quashed authority, and banned the hypothesis to domestic
inactivity.”41
Monism and dissent
If scientists and philosophers were both moving towards monism in the 1840s, the
real crucible of the formation of worldview was not in the halls of the university, but the
public sphere. Popular science emerged as one important vector, as shown the enormous
influence of Alexander von Humboldt’s Kosmos of 1845. As the world-famous Prussian
biologist and explorer put it in his introduction, his aim in this work was to provide the
reader with a “worldview” or a “general natural painting descending from the farthest
nebulae and rotating double stars of the universe to the telluric phenomena of the
geography of organisms (plants, animals and human races).”42
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
19
To understand the emergence of naturalistic monism as a historical force in the
1840s and 1850s one must also consider its rooting in the dissenting religion and politics.
In 1845 a significant number of Catholic, Protestant and Jewish dissenters broke off from
their respective churches in the name of an anti-confessional rationalism. Within the
space of ten years many came to embrace immanent conceptions of the divine and,
already in 1852, the preacher of the Hamburg Free Congregation Karl Kleinpaul had
described “our monist religion of nature” as the celebration of “the spirit in nature and the
spirit in history.”43 The key to understanding the adoption and dissemination of monism
by Free Religion lay, as I have argued elsewhere, in the dynamic tension produced by
religious schism and ecclesiastical and state persecution.44
Just as London’s South Place Chapel and its Unitarian dissent formed the seedbed
of British secularism, Free Religion lay the foundation for organized secularism in
Germany. Constitutive of Free Religion, Freethought and the Monist League was the
combination of anticlericalism and the propagation of a natural-scientific worldview.
Even the socialist freethinkers, who in the 1920s and 1930s complained bitterly about the
“bourgeois” monists and swore fealty to Marxism as the only legitimate socialist
worldview, remained indebted to monism in their cultural work. Likewise the Free
Religious groups that were allowed a niche existence in the anti-Christian German Faith
Movement during the Third Reich transformed their monism into an immanent Germanic
religion of blood.45
If it had remained confined to secularist organizations, monism would constitute a
footnote, however interesting, in German and European cultural and scientific history.
One finds, however, a similar constellation of secularism and natural-scientific monism
in a host of social and political movements that similarly took form in the 1840s. As
historian Peter Caldwell has noted, some of the key German theorists of the revolution of
1848, men and women such as Moses Hess, Louise Dittmar, Gustav von Struve and
Ludwig Feuerbach, took a keen interest in religious reform, natural scientific
investigation and even dietary regimens alongside politics. Whereas later observers often
found this combination to have been a deviation from true politics, the idea of a
revolutionary role for biology, either in the form of scientific popularization or dietary
praxis, makes perfect sense from a monist perspective.46 The history of monism reframes
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
20
some of the period’s better known intellectual movements of materialism and positivism.
In many ways, these were monisms avant la lettre.
The connection between monism and radical dissent also help explain the
centrality of monist rhetoric to social movements such as pacifism, early radical
feminism and the homosexual rights movement, as well as the so-called life-reform
movements.47 All of these groups had in common the conviction that a dualistic illusion
was being foisted on the unwitting population by the repressive forces of orthodoxy,
whether in the churches, the state, the urban social elite or the universities. The utility of
monism in dissent underscores the importance of understanding the role of sociological
factors in the evolution of this particular form of knowledge.
One entry point into the sociological articulation of monism is the outcome of the
debate between du Bois-Reymond and Haeckel, in which two scientific secularisms were
on offer. 1872 was perhaps the high point of acceptance of empiricism and monism
among German liberal circles, as witnessed by the popularity of that year’s bestseller The
Old Faith and the New. In this book the no longer young Hegelian David Friedrich
Strauss made the case for abandoning Christianity in favor of naturalistic monism.48
Despite the fact that monist thinkers like Haeckel and Strauss understood themselves to
be supporting the dominant spirit of modernity, their version of secularism ultimately did
not prevail. They won the heart of organized secularism but failed to define the secular
order. Thus monism became, in fact, a heterodox voice.49 In the defeat lay the key to its
success as an ideology of dissent.
One of the recurrent tropes in elite condemnations of monism and organized
secularism more generally, was that its leaders and followers were only “semi-educated”
(Halbgebildete). This charge obfuscated the social threat represented by monism, as a
systematic form of knowledge readily available to those with limited education. It is no
accident that the rising crescendo of liberal critiques of monism and liberalism from the
mid 1870s onwards coincided with the growing defection of the urban “half-educated,”
i.e. the ambitious lower-middle and working classes, from the liberal parties to Social
Democracy. They took with them their materialistic monism and anticlericalism.50
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
21
Monism, early feminism and the homosexual rights movement
Alongside the workers’ movement, early German feminism provides another
example of a dissenting movement of the “semi-educated” drawn to monism. In the
nineteenth century elite humanistic learning was largely monopolized by the men who
had access to the grammar schools (Gymnasien) and universities where the classics were
taught.51 Women were generally self educated or obtained their educations in vocational
colleges or lyceums, which often taught popular science. Monism offered women an
alternative form of educational capital with which they could challenge traditional forms
of learning, whether religious or humanistic.
In addition to the social leverage that empiricist knowledge offered the semieducated, we must also recognize the specific way in which monist theories were
appropriated by each form of dissent. Among the numerous letters of praise sent to Ernst
Haeckel, there is a photograph of a woman from Portland, Oregon, who had written on
the reverse: “One of the 1000’s of young Women, whose minds are being emancipated
by Haeckel’s works.”52 Here again is one of the surprises of monism. How could a
thinker associated with social Darwinism, like Haeckel, have inspired feminist theory?
Because biology is often invoked to fix sexual characteristics, many of today’s feminists
are critical of the role of popular biology and socio-biology in naturalizing relations of
sexual domination.53 In the late nineteenth century, however, monist biology provided
feminists with a new epistemological foundation for grounding their own identity in the
natural order and outside of moral-clerical discourse. The developmental, comparative
biology advocated by Haeckel gave feminists a socio-biological framework that
explained the commonly accepted constitutional inferiority of women as a consequence
of environmental factors, in particular the familial, economic and religious structures of
male domination. The same neo-Lamarckian theory of the inheritance of acquired
characteristics that explained the social roots of supposed female deformations also
offered a means to their amelioration. Hence we find that monist biology played a role in
the rethinking of sexual identity and ethics by a host of feminist theorists, including
Annie Besant and Constance Naden in Britain and the sexual reformers Helene Stöcker
and Grete Meisel-Hess in Germany. 54
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
22
Another prominent sexual reformer active in the Monist League was the Berlin
sexologist Magnus Hirschfeld, who is considered Germany’s most important pioneer of
homosexual rights. As Hirschfeld wrote to Haeckel in May 1912, he wished to place his
empirical studies of sexuality “into the great connections of natural life.”55 Specifically,
Hirschfeld placed homosexuality within a series of “intermediary sexual stages” that gave
it a natural and therefore legitimate place within the totality of human sexuality.56
A further incentive for the biologization of sexuality by dissidents was to remove it
from the sphere of religion. Where science governed, Hirschfeld argued, the churches no
longer had the right to impose moral edicts. In 1913 Hirschfeld celebrated that “the times
have finally passed, in which theologians and jurists were nearly alone in leading
discussion of questions of human sexual life,” and that doctors and scientists were now
stepping up who worked “on the only possible natural, biological-anthropological
foundation.”57
Monist ethics
These examples of dissenting interpretations should not lead to the conclusion that
monism had a single, leftwing political valence. Far from it. Adherents of naturalistic
monism often took sides against one another. A chief flashpoint of the controversy was
the implications of monism for ethics and Haeckel’s own stance, in particular, elicited
and continue to elicit great attention. His starting point bears some similarity to that of his
contemporary, the self-avowed “Free Spirit” Friedrich Nietzsche. Both men believed that
in the absence of a transcendental authority, ethics had to be refounded beyond Christian
notions of good and evil. And, like Nietzsche, Haeckel proposed that ethics be guided by
the question: what is good for life? However, where Nietzsche sought a “revaluation of
all values” from the perspective of the individual’s responsibility to his own life, Haeckel
judged life from the point of view of the species or the race. Hence his ethics was most
radical in its biological dimension, where it became tied up in the collective and eugenic
possibilities of directed reproduction.
The debate over Haeckel’s ethics has continued to dominate recent literature on
monism. On the one hand, as already mentioned, Haeckel offered early German feminist
and gay-rights movements a foundation for critiquing the traditional ethics of
reproduction and homosexuality. On the other hand, Haeckel was an advocate of
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
23
imperialism, who applied natural selection to race relations. He justified the ongoing
elimination of the Native Americans, by noting that those European settlers who bore
culture (Kulturvölker) had a higher “life value” (Lebenswert) for the human species than
the “natural races” (Naturvölker). Haeckel’s concept of “life value” was later picked up
and used as a rationale in the Nazi Euthanasia program to kill the mentally and physically
handicapped, whom they called “life unworthy of life.”58
To decide the ethical debate for or against Haeckel misses a key point. “Left” and
“right” eugenics rubbed shoulders, often quite literally, as shown, for example, in the
brief participation of leading eugenicist Alfred Ploetz in Helene Stöcker’s feminist
Mothers’ Protection Society. By applying scientific rationality to ethical decisions,
monists could devalue human life, while at the same time claiming the mantle of the
radical humanism from thinkers like Ludwig Feuerbach. Because the overall ethical
legacy of monism remains a riddle that reveals no single logic, contextualization is
crucial.59
Monist aesthetics
Aesthetics was another area of inquiry where interesting interactions of idealist,
spiritualist and materialist monisms manifested themselves. Alexander von Humboldt and
Haeckel considered natural beauty a guarantee that the universe was an ordered
meaningful totality, a cosmos. Hence they believed that the aesthetic faculty was crucial
for the subjective assimilation of a naturalistic worldview. Naturalistic monism began to
make a notable impact on literature in the 1880s, when the young English writer
Constance Naden sought to explore the “land where Science and Poetry meet.” Her
satirical poem “Scientific wooing” in the cycle “Evolutional Erotics” describes a young
scholar who drops his studies to pursue love, only to find in love – and in poetry – the
unity promised by science.60 Here the artist-scientist entered into Nature’s own play of
attraction. Typical of monists, Naden conceived of beauty as an integral part in the
evolutionary process guided by sexual selection. Similar ideas were being explored in
Germany by Naden’s contemporary Wilhelm Bölsche, a long-time confidant of Haeckel.
At the start of his writing career in 1886, Bölsche issued a naturalist manifesto, in which
he demanded that poetry subject itself to the new worldview provided by Darwin. 61
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
24
By the time he helped found Germany’s first monist club, the Giordano-Bruno
Society for Unified Worldview, in 1900, Bölsche had published his influential Lovelife of
Nature, a work linking the erotic life of animals with cosmic unity. He was also
popularizing Gustav Fechner’s psychophysical monism, through which he and other
artists found a bridge between their natural scientific worldview and mysticism,
spiritualism and other “irrational” practices. It was precisely in literary and life reform
circles that the more radical implications of the monistic unconscious were explored. The
naturalist avantgarde moved from the “spiritualization of the body” to the “incarnation of
the soul.”62
Writer Julius Hart argued that a “new” and “supersensory seeing” could expand the
“field of vision” of the mystical seer to reveal spiritual connections inaccessible to
“philosophical schools and systems,” which only saw only “half and quarter world
pictures.”63 Hart, like Bölsche and Naden, sought to break down the distance between
observer and the natural world through depictions of mystical unions based on the monist
identity of subject and object.64 Such unions were to be achieved, on the one hand,
through exercises in imagined empathy with animate and inanimate nature.65 On the
other, the fin-de-siècle avantgarde advocated sexual love between humans as a key
experiential means of awakening the panpsychic potential of the unconscious.
Psychologist and writer Lou Andreas-Salome found in sexuality a “bodily memory
(Gedächtnis)” and means of “reawakening” the “primeval.”66 Through pan-psychism and
“evolutional erotics,” monism could remain an underlying point of agreement between
symbolist and expressionist artists and the naturalists, whose “materialism” they rejected.
The geography of monism
Historical geography has an important role to play in expanding our understanding
of monism. International comparison is needed in order to reveal the geographic
distribution of the varieties of monism as well as to help explain the movement’s strength
in Germany.67 As the essays in this volume show, monism appeared in quite different
constellations in Britain, Russia and Germany in the first third of the twentieth century.
How are we to account for the weakness of naturalistic monism in the Britain and the
relatively greater interest in spiritualistic monism there points to different intellectual
traditions in Britain and Germany. Already in 1834 Heinrich Heine had claimed that
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
25
whereas materialism had pushed religion from philosophy in France and Britain, in
Germany materialism drove God underground, where he reappeared in all matter as
philosophical pantheism. Or, as Bertolt Brecht put it more succinctly, yet no less
humorously, a century later: “the Germans have a poor aptitude for materialism. Where
they get it, they immediately turn it into an idea.”68
Looking beyond the role played by differences in national intellectual culture, the
relative weakness of naturalistic monism in Britain and the US strengthens the argument
made above about the importance of secularism and the enterprise of worldview in
Germany. By the early 20th century, when monism was most popular in Germany,
religion was not a central political issue in Britain or the United States. One American
monist in 1913 lamented that because of the separation of church and state, American
freethinkers were too complacent to organize an effective monist movement.
69
By
contrast, there was an avid reception of German monism among the political left of
Tsarist Russia, which like Germany saw itself as a confessional state.70
Monism after 1918
Some studies have depicted the First World War as the abrupt endpoint of
naturalistic monism.71 While this catastrophe did mark the end of the type of unalloyed
monism championed by the likes of Haeckel and Ostwald and which has been aptly
described as a technocratic fantasy of scientific elites,72 it may be that in hybrid form
monism grew in importance after 1918. Of particular interest to scholars have been the
interactions of monism with two key political worldviews of the interwar period:
Marxism and National Socialism.73 These interactions form the subject of the final essays
in this volume, which, taken together, return us to the ambiguity, now in the political
sphere, of Haeckel’s monism. Despite Haeckel’s racism and support of German
imperialism, his own political views did not determine his intellectual legacy. The same
man who defended the Darwinian “struggle for life” as an aristocratic principle inimical
to social democracy could be eulogized as the “German Encyclopaedist” in the socialist
Vorwärts amidst the postwar revolutionary upheaval of 1919: “What Diderot,
d'Alembert, Voltaire once accomplished for the French, that should also be said to
Haeckel’s honor: he was a path breaker of the intellectual German revolution.”74
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
26
Two worldviews informed the radical socialist movement in Germany and Russia:
naturalistic monism and Marxism, or scientific and dialectical materialism. Their relation
was one of competition, but also of cooperation. The biographies of the leading German
socialists like August Bebel, Karl Kautsky, and Walter Ulbricht show that these men had
been exposed to naturalistic monism before they became Marxists.75 Although the social
democratic leadership rejected any official endorsement of monism or anticlericalism for
strategic reasons, these remained key elements of worker culture. The rank and file saw
no clear distinction between monistic materialism and what they called “socialist
worldview.”
At the height of the church-leaving campaign in October 1913, Ostwald informed
the German-American monist and professor of biology Jacques Loeb that the Monist
League had entered into “a type of cooperation” with Social Democracy. He hoped to
deliver the socialists “the theoretical underpinnings for the new content […] that they will
desperately need after the exhaustion of their Marxism.”76 With few exceptions, however,
socialists remained leery of the “bourgeois” monist movement and criticized Haeckel for
ignoring class struggle and thus supporting the “dualism” of the capitalist system. Little
enthusiasm was generated by the synthesis of Marxism and monism in the “dialectical
nature-monism” that was promoted in pre-war Germany by followers of Joseph Dietzgen,
an autodidact known as the great “worker-philosopher” of the German Socialist
movement.77
Quite a different constellation emerged in pre-war Russia. The “empirio-monism”
of Ernst Mach had become so influential amongst leading Bolshevik intellectuals that
Lenin devoted an extensive theoretical book to its refutation.78 Nonetheless, after 1917
natural-scientific monism was granted a wide berth in the new regime. Soviet monism
arguably reached its apogee when Trofim Lyssenko’s Neo-Lamarckian evolutionary
theory was made the cornerstone of official biology. Monism was even viewed positively
by Chinese communists, such as Mao Zedong, who told the visiting West German
chancellor Helmut Schmidt in 1975 that his views had been shaped by four great German
thinkers: Hegel, Marx, Engels and Haeckel.79
The relationship to National Socialism remains one of the most controversial issues
in the history of monism despite—and because of—the fact that relatively little research
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
27
has been undertaken on the subject. In one of the first major studies of naturalistic
monism, Historian Daniel Gasman argued the case in 1971 that Haeckel’s monism was a
“prelude to the doctrine of National Socialism.”80 Although Haeckel’s “guilt” for Hitler’s
worldview has been widely disputed, and despite the fact that the Nazis disbanded the
leftwing Monist League in 1933, it would be wrong to assume that monism was
irrelevant to the history of National Socialism.81 If a general definition of naturalistic
monism is applied, monistic elements of Hitler’s worldview can be identified. For despite
his frequent invocations of “the Almighty” and his “idealism” in speeches excoriating
contemporary Germany for its submission to myriad forms of “materialism,” when Hitler
spoke more systematically, his conception of worldview proved to be naturalistic and
monistic. At the height of the “Church Struggle” he stated: “Never before have the
spiritual aims and direction of the will of our nation been so identical with the natural
obligations to political self assertion as they are today. Never before for the German
people has worldview been so identical with the eternal laws of nature and thus with the
nation and its conditions of life.”82 Pope Pius XI condemned Nazi monism in his 1937
encyclical “mit brennender Sorge” with the warning that “[w]hoever identifies, by
pantheistic confusion, God and the universe, by either lowering God to the dimensions of
the world, or raising the world to the dimensions of God, is not a believer in God.”83
Isaiah Berlin and Tzvetan Todorov are two political philosophers, who have
employed monism as a synonym for totalitarianism to describe the antipluralistic and
organicist essence of both by National Socialism and Soviet Communism. Although
Todorov notes that both regimes shared a “cult of science,” he, like Berlin, has used
monism purely as an analytical category divorced from the tradition of naturalistic
monism that would have been familiar to Soviet and German scientists in the 1930s and
1940s.84 Clearly, the historical monism under consideration here could not be credited
with such tremendous influence. As the essays in this volume demonstrate, each regime
curtailed the development of overt monist movements. Nonetheless, National Socialism
and Stalinism were worldview dictatorships that operated under conceptions of
worldview that shared monistic assumptions. Under the umbrella of these assumptions,
individuals and groups continued to elaborate theories building on naturalistic and
spiritualistic monism more narrowly defined.85
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
28
1945: The end of a monist century?
One of the issues discussed at the conference in Belfast was when and if monism
ceased to be an intellectual, social and scientific movement of broad historical influence.
Depending on the aspect of monism under consideration, different endpoints or
transformations were put forward. Some forms of monism continued to evolve
throughout the twentieth century. One such example is offered by spiritualistic monism.
In the 1945 publication Vedanta for the Western World, the British writers Aldous
Huxley and Christopher Isherwood invited Western intellectuals to embrace Indian
philosophy precisely because its monism provided the “minimum working hypothesis”
for spiritual research in a scientific age. This publication formed a bridge between earlier
spiritualistic monism and the future New Age movements that would emerge in the new
Californian home of two exiles.86
In the case of West Germany, however, it can be argued that the monist century
ended in the wake of the Second World War. Between 1945 and 1949 the framework
broke down that had sustained interest in worldview and secularism over the previous
century. National Socialism and Communism had discredited the political project of unity
around worldview and the broad appeal of the “Christian West” as a program of moral
rebuilding and European integration led to an end to political anticlericalism.
Furthermore, the British and Americans who occupied Western Germany were decidedly
hostile to worldview.
The situation in East Germany was quite different. The communist state
resuscitated elements of monism, when it reintroduced the Free Religious youth
confirmation ceremony or Jugendweihe as its central state rite. Yet, although it became
embedded in the cultural policies and popular science of East Germany, state monism,
like Marxism-Leninism, eventually fell victim to secularization. Long before the demise
of the post-Stalinist state, the aura faded from the project of worldview.87
Today was are experiencing something of a renewed monist convergence that
extends well beyond the interactions of neuroscience and the humanities mentioned at the
beginning of this essay. Monism appears resurgent in popular science, where Richard
Dawkins has captured the public spotlight with his raids from natural science across the
neo-Kantian firewall and into the realms of culture and religion. The New Age contains
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
29
many monistic elements. Spinoza and his concept of conatus, i.e. the drive for selfpreservation expressed in all life action whether thought or metabolism, are exerting a
powerful fascination on some radical social theorists, who find in them an immanent
ontological foundation that can serve as site of resistance to social construction.88
Arguably, dissent and the persuasive force of natural scientific metaphor, are again
presenting themselves as shared features of many of these articulations of monism.
However, despite the reappearance of some familiar combinations, contemporary
varieties of monism are no longer embedded in structures and assumptions about
worldview that sustained monism between 1845 and 1945.89 They appear rather as goods
in a secular marketplace of religious ideas. For not just religions but also worldviews
have become untethered in our ‘secular age’.
Summary
This introductory essay has sought to demonstrate how monism as a form of
knowledge connected natural science with the social tensions and religious questions of
its century. Haeckel was acutely aware of this connection. In Riddle of the Universe, he
described “an uneasy sense of dismemberment and falseness” felt by liberal intellectuals
as the signature of the age.90 He intended naturalistic monism as a solution to this
malaise. On the level of metaphysics, monism sought to eliminate the notion of
transcendent mind or deity but reclaim transcendence in the immanent material world by
declaring the unity of all being. In contrast to earlier philosophical monism, modern
naturalistic monism argued that this totality was not speculative supposition, but an
empirically verifiable scientific theory. On the level of epistemology, naturalistic monism
proposed the eradication of disciplinary boundaries and the unification of all branches of
knowledge, including the sciences of culture, under a sole natural-scientific theory. In
terms of social organization, monism stood for the amelioration of all social conflicts
through the application of scientific rationality.
In this light, monism offered itself as a solution to what Georg Lukács famously
termed the “transcendental homelessness” of modernity. However, when we shift
perspective and view monism relationally as a form of knowledge instantiated in specific
historic conflicts, it is monism itself that appears homeless. Rather than redefining
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
30
science, monism was defined by the enticements and resistances offered at the boundaries
it sought to transgress. Biographically, monism proved attractive to individuals with
mystical, heretical or antiauthoritarian dispositions, to ambitious individuals in marginal
positions, and to those subject to discrimination. It was carried into a myriad of dissenting
movements that were challenging social, religious and cultural boundaries, where the
transgressive, secularist aspects of monism could be leveraged. In the field of science, the
monist efforts to colonize other domains of knowledge contributed to a “conflict of the
faculties.” Although it provided a research agenda, monism developed an uncomfortable
relationship to natural science itself. Operating more in the realm of popular than
academic science, monism proved to be homeless in a disciplinary sense. It took the guise
of philosophy, religion, science without belonging properly to any one. It sometimes
eluded scientific rationality, in whose name it operated, in order serve as the basis for
worldview. The “world riddles” functioned simultaneously as foundational pillars of this
worldview and as shibboleths dividing it from its competitors. As such, the world riddles
are a fitting entry point for exploring the riddles of monism.
The essays in this volume
The naturalistic monism of Ernst Haeckel forms the central point of reference, but
also a common point of departure for the essays of this volume. They push our
understanding of monism beyond its “narrow” history as a development within late
nineteenth century natural science in Germany. The first two essays examine the
prehistory of Haeckel’s monism. Frederick Gregory opens up what he calls the
transition from idealistic to naturalistic monism that occurred in the second third of the
nineteenth century. His essay compares the proto-monism of philosopher F.W.J.
Schelling and theologian Friedrich Schleiermacher with the innovations of thinkers like
Ludwig Feuerbach and David Friedrich Strauss.
Nicolaas Rupke draws in the social context of the emergence of naturalistic
monism though his analysis of the reception of Alexander von Humboldt’s Kosmos
(1845), which was an immensely popular attempt to write a natural history of the
universe as a meaningful and organized unity. Though Kosmos was heralded as a
milestone in the formation of monist worldview, Rupke argues that it was largely
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
31
political leftists and pantheist preachers in the 1850s and 1860s who turned Humboldt
into a monist prophet and a Darwinist avant la lettre.
The next two essays show that, although dominant, Haeckel’s was not the only
monism on offer in the late nineteenth century. The development of eclectic spiritualistic
philosophies were one such monist alternative, and as Gauri Viswanathan shows in her
essay, leading theosophists were articulated their philosophy against naturalism. While
the movement’s leader Helene Blavatsky called scientific materialism “bastard monism,”
her follower Annie Besant reveals a more ambiguous relationship towards naturalism.
Besant had been England’s second most famous atheist after Charles Bradlaugh in the
1870s, and, had, like him, embraced naturalistic monism at that time. While her
conversion to theosophy in the 1880s represented an abrupt change in her position on
naturalism, Besant retained her monism. As an antimaterialist philosophy with a
secularist, immanent conception of the divine, theosophy merged monistic evolutionary
thinking with elements of Indian philosophy and esoteric sources. In her essay,
Viswanathan reveals how Besant and the other female writers and reformers articulated
an ethical critique of masculine materialist science through their theosophically informed
opposition to vivisection.91
The writings of Baruch Spinoza provided the essential philosophical foundation of
nineteenth-century monism, yet, as Tracie Matysik demonstrates in her essay, the
reception of the Dutch philosopher led to divergent forms of naturalism. Her point of
entry is Wilhelm Dilthey’s attempt to liberate Spinoza from interpolations that ascribed to
him a vitalistic understanding of nature more properly applicable to the monistic systems
of Giordano Bruno and Shaftesbury. The mechanistic and vitalistic variations had,
Matysik argues, important ethical implications that became apparent in the twentieth
century.
We cannot look to Haeckel if we wish to understand how monism impacted natural
scientific research during the heyday of monist organizing in the first decades of the
twentieth century. By the time The Riddle of the Universe appeared in 1899, Haeckel’s
days as an active scientist were essentially behind him and his hylozoistic philosophy had
changed little since its original formulation in 1866.92 To explore the impact of monism
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
32
on science in the first half of the twentieth century, the third pair of essays examines a
younger generation of scientists.
Sander Gliboff examines efforts by Haeckel’s acolytes—Paul Kammerer, Richard
Semon and Ludwig Plate—to defend and further substantiate Haeckel’s monistic
evolutionary theory in the early twentieth century. Kammerer’s work on the inheritance
of acquired characteristics and Semon’s theory of a biological memory have generally
been interpreted as prime examples of the overdetermination of Haeckelian biology by
worldview. Semon’s work was not widely accepted despite positive reviews by the
“neutral monist” Bertrand Russell, and Kammerer’s career ended in a more spectacular
fashion, when after being accused of manipulating his research data in 1926, he
committed suicide.93 Against the typical reading, Gliboff argues that adherence to monist
worldview and participation in monist organizations did not necessarily make monism
less “scientific” or more ideological than competing biological paradigms of its day. He
uses Ludwig Plate as a counter example. Plate’s Darwinian orthodoxy helped him
become Haeckel’s successor in Jena, though he later successfully jettisoned affiliation
with the monist movement, when it might have damaged his career.
Like Gliboff, Paul Ziche challenges the view of many historians of science that
commitment to worldview led monists to be out of touch with developments in twentieth
century science. Ziche focuses on one aspect of Wilhelm Ostwald’s wide monist oeuvre,
his work on the unification of the sciences. Against accounts that have correlated
Ostwald’s turn to monism to his marginalization as a scientist,94 Ziche shows that
Ostwald’s effort to reorganize the sciences was compatible with the much wider and
well-respected unity of science movement that continued into the 1930s to 1950s in the
work of Rudolf Carnap and Otto Neurath.95
Gliboff and Ziche open up new territory with their studies of the place of monism
in twentieth-century natural science by showing that monism could also form the
framework for research that was innovative despite, or because, of the worldview
interests of the scientists. In this vein, historian of science Robert Bud has argued that the
monist interests of his mentors provided the young Francis Crick with a research agenda
that started him on the path to the discovery of DNA in 1953.96 Similarly, the monist
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
33
commitments of physiologists and philosophers like Ernst Mach and Richard Avenarius
led to theoretical work on cognition that continues to be influential to this day.
The last three essays open up a subject in the history of monism about which we
know least, that is, how prewar monism developed further in 1920s and 1930s, the
decades in which the conflicts between rival worldview regimes reached their ideological
highpoint. Focusing on Britain, Russia and Germany respectively, the essays provide a
basis for comparative analysis.
In his essay on British popular science, Peter Bowler finds that the dissemination
of naturalistic monism concentrated, as it did in Germany, in the currents of leftist
dissent. The term monism itself failed, however, to be embraced by the workers’
education movement, in part due to the strength of idealistic and spiritualistic monisms in
Britain. One exception was the English geneticist and science popularizer J.B.S. Haldane,
who declared himself to be a monist in 1932, at a time when he came to embrace
communism as well.97
Igor Polianski charts the fate of two-fold monism in Tsarist Russia and the early
Soviet Union. First he revisits the heated polemic of 1908 between the leading
Bolsheviks Vladmir Lenin and Alexander Bogdanov. The latter’s empirio-monism stood
in stark contrast to the monism of most German socialists, who embraced Haeckel’s
materialism. Bogdanov and his allies argued that the unity of mind and matter led not just
to a rejection of idealism, but to a rejections of the simple empiricism underlying
Haeckel’s materialism as well. While Bogdanov was defeated and his philosophy
subordinated to Marxism, monism led a flourishing existence in various “niches” in the
Soviet Union, including the biological sciences and medicine, as well as anticlerical
action and popular science.98
Establishing the relationship between the general “monistic” thrust of National
Socialism and the specific tradition of monism proper presents a serious methodological
challenge, given the disparate origins of National Socialist thinking. In his essay, Heiner
Fangerau has found an elegant solution to this challenge through a comparative
examination of those biologists who identified with monism and those who developed the
field of racial hygiene. Fangerau shows that while the mechanistic predilections and
political commitments of its advocates made monistic biology unpalatable to National
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
34
Socialists, it nonetheless shared a common epistemological framework with racial
hygiene.
Taken together, the essays of this volume reveal some of the key tensions around
which modern monist positions were articulated. Thus the rivalry between idealistic and
naturalistic monisms in early nineteenth century Germany is relevant for understanding
the definition of the term in early twentieth century Britain. We gain a better
understanding of the varieties of naturalistic monism, if we consider how the mechanistic
and vitalistic interpretations of Spinoza resonate with mechanistic and organicist
preconceptions among German natural scientists. Bogdanov’s philosophy shows that
“neutral monism” had continuing appeal, but lacked popular articulation. Finally, among
both theosophists and the early popularizers of Humboldt, we see the dynamics created
when religious and political dissenters contest scientific authority and it monopoly on the
cultural interpretation of Nature.
The following essays will likely take the reader into unfamiliar areas of research.
Because the riddles of monism still have much to offer scholars interested in the history
of modern science, philosophy, religion and politics, this book is meant as an opening
rather than a culmination of this research.
1
This essay was composed during my sabbatical leave from Queen’s University Belfast,
while I was a fellow at the Simpson Center for the Humanities at the University of
Washington. I would like to thank Center’s director, Katherine Woodward, and my
interlocutors in Seattle, who have included Charles LaPorte, Michael Rosenthal and John
Toews. For useful comments on earlier versions of this paper, I would like to thank my
colleagues in the Queen’s research group “Religion in Modernity” Eric Morier-Genoud,
Veronique Altglas and Matthew Wood, as well as Tracie Matysik, Igor Polianski and
Andreas Daum, who joined me on conference panel on monism in 2009. Particularly
helpful suggestions were made by Suzanne Marchand.
2
“Das Manifest: Elf führende Neurowissenschaftler über Gegenwart und Zukunft der
Hirnforschung,” Gehirn und Geist, no. 6 (2004): 34. Daniel Dennett, “Appraising Grace:
What evolutionary good is God,” The Sciences. 37, no. 1 (1997): 39.
3
Two recent books linking affect theory and cultural studies are Patricia Ticineto Clough
with Jean Halley, The Affective Turn: Theorizing the Social (Durham: Duke UP, 2007)
and Brian Massumi, Parables for the Virtual: Movement, Affect, Sensation (Durham:
Duke UP, 2002). The quotation on the brain as an object of historical inquiry is taken
from Daniel L. Smail, On Deep History and the Brain (Berkeley, Los Angeles, London:
UC Press, 2008), 8. An insightful critique of the shortcomings of Smail’s approach is
provided by William H. Reddy, a leading scholar in the history of emotions, in his review
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
35
essay “Neuroscience and the Fallacies of Functionalism,” History and Theory 49
(October 2010): 412-425.
4
Jürgen Habermas, “The Language Game of Responsible Agency and the Problem of
Free Will: How Can Epistemic Dualism be Reconciled with Ontological Monism?”
Philosophical Explorations 10, no. 1 (2007): 13-50. Two recent avowals of a new
monism in the sciences have made by the socio-biologist E. O. Wilson and the
philosopher of biology Michael Ruse. In 2000, Wilson claimed that over the prior two
decades the gap between literary and scientific cultures had been closing and that the
neurosciences, genetics, and evolutionary psychology mark borderland disciplines that
were leading towards a unity of science. Edward O. Wilson, “How to Unify Knowledge,”
in Unity of Knowledge : the Convergence of Natural and Human Science, ed. Antonio
Damasio (New York: New York Academy of Sciences 2001), 13. Ruse stated that
“[m]ost philosophers and scientists today are inclined to monism rather than to dualism.”
Michael Ruse, The Evolution Wars (New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers UP, 2001), 200.
5
Four monographs on Haeckel have appeared between 2005 and 2008 alone. The most
important are Robert Richards, The tragic sense of life : Ernst Haeckel and the struggle
over evolutionary thought (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2008) and Sander
Gliboff, H. G. Bronn, Ernst Haeckel, and the Origins of German Darwinism (Cambridge,
Mass.: MIT Press, 2008).
6
The term monism was used in histories of religion, for instance to celebrate mankind’s
breakthrough to its first unified worldview via monotheism or to characterize the threat of
Gnosticism. The conservative Lutheran Friedrich Julius Stahl favorably compared the
“monism” of Protestantism to the “dualism” of Catholicism, while another advocate of
the “Christian State” argued that the Prussian unity of church and state was a “the proper
monism of our Christian national life” and superior to the dualism of a secular state.
Friedrich Julius Stahl, Die gegenwärtigen Parteien in Staat und Kirche, 2 ed. (Berlin:
Wilhelm Hertz, 1868), 363; August Petersen, “Zur Lehre von der Kirche. Eine Replik,”
Litterarischer Anzeiger für christliche Theologie und Wissenschaft überhaupt, no. 31 (18
May), 32 (23 May) (1844): 243. One of Hegel’s students, the legal scholar Karl Friedrich
Goeschel, published a work in 1832 entitled Der Monismus des Gedankens (The Monism
of Thought). On Hegel’s logic as a “monism” or better a “pantheism.” Johann Eduard
Erdmann, “Französische Werke über die Philosophie,” Allgemeine Literatur-Zeitung, no.
99 (May) (1849): 792.
7
Haeckel’s “biogenetic law” and recapitulation theory more generally came under
sustained attack in the twentieth century. However, recent interest in epigenetics and
evolutionary development have placed his work in a more positive light.
8
Ernst Haeckel, Generelle Morphologie der Organismen, vol. 2 (Berlin: Reimer, 1866),
vol. II, 450. Ernst Haeckel, Natürliche Schöpfungsgeschichte, 7th ed. (Berlin: G. Reimer,
1879).
9
On the European Freethought movements see: Jacqueline Lalouette, La Libre Pensée en
France, 1848-1940 (Paris: Albin Michel, 1997). Guido Verucci, L’Italia laica prima e
dopo l’Unita (Rome-Bari: Laterza, 1996); Jochen-Christoph Kaiser, Arbeiterbewegung
und organisierte Religionskritik: proletarische Freidenkerverbände in Kaiserreich und
Weimarer Republik (Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta, 1981).
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
10
36
The most comprehensive history of the Monist League has been written by Rosemarie
Nöthlich et al., “Weltbild oder Weltanschauung? Die Gründung und Entwicklung des
Deutschen Monistenbundes,” in Jahrbuch für Europäische Wissenschaftskultur, ed.
Heiko Weber and Maurizio Di Bartolo, vol. 3 (Stuttgart: Steiner, 2007), 19-68. See also,
Richard Weikart, “‘Evolutionäre Aufklärung’? Zur Geschichte des Monistenbundes,” in
Wissenschaft, Politik und Öffentlichkeit: von der Wiener Moderne bis zur Gegenwart, ed.
Mitchell Ash (Vienna: WUV Universitätsverlag, 2002), 131-148; Gangolf Hübinger,
“Die monistische Bewegung. Sozialingenieure und Kulturprediger,” in Kultur und
Kulturwissenschaften um 1900 (Stuttgart: Steiner, 1997), 246-259; Volker Drehsen and
Helmut Zander, “Rationale Weltveränderung durch “naturwissenschaftliche”
Weltinterpretation? Der Monistenbund - eine Religion der Fortschrittsgläubigkeit,” in
Vom Weltbildwandel zur Weltanschauungsanalyse. Krisenwahrnehmung und
Krisenbewältigung um 1900, ed. Volker Drehsen and Walter Sparn (Berlin: Akademie
Verlag, 1996).
11
One of the first major public events of the League was the 1907 debate in Berlin with
the Jesuit entomologist Erich Wasmann. See Prof. Dr. L. Plate, Ultramontane
Weltanschauung und moderne Lebenskunde Orthodoxie und Monismus. Die
Anschauungen des Jesuitenpaters Erich Wasmann und die gegen ihn in Berlin gehaltenen
Reden. (Jena: Fischer, 1907). On the resurgence of Kulturkampf in the period between
1906 and 1914, see Helmut Walser Smith, German Nationalism and Religious Conflict.
Culture, Ideology, Politics 1870-1914 (Princeton: Princeton UP, 1994).
12
Arthur Drews, Berliner Religionsgespräch: Hat Jesus gelebt? Reden über “Die
Christusmythe” gehalten am 31. Januar und 1. Februar von Prof. Dr. Arthur Drews
(Berlin: Verlag des Dt. Monistenbundes, 1910). On the Kirchenaustritt movement, see
Jochen-Christoph Kaiser, “Sozialdemokratie und ‘praktische’ Religionskritik. Das
Beispiel der Kirchenaustrittsbewegung 1878-1914,” Archiv für Sozialgeschichte XXII
(1982): 263-298. On the participation of monists in this movement, see Todd Weir, “The
Fourth Confession: Atheism, Monism and Politics in the ‘Freigeistig’ Movement in
Berlin 1859-1924” (PhD, Columbia University, 2005), 515-545.
13
A biting critique of Ostwald’s theory was penned by Max Weber, “‘Energetische’
Kulturtheorien,” in Gesammelte Aufsätze zur Wissenschaftslehre (Tübingen: Mohr,
1988): 400-426. For historical treatments of Ostwald’s monism, see Eckard Daser,
Ostwalds Energetischer Monismus (Constance: PhD Dissertation, 1980); Britta Görs,
Nikolaos Psarros, and Paul Ziche, eds., Wilhelm Ostwald at the Crossroads Between
Chemistry, Philosophy and Media Culture (Leipzig: Leipziger Universitätsverlag, 2005).
14
Das monistische Jahrhundert (The Monist Century), the League’s journal declared in
April 1913 that “[a]ccording to its understanding of monism not only as a method of
thought and life but also as a cultural goal,” the journal has “not limited itself to natural
science and natural philosophy—the basis of our worldview—by has systematically
attempted to incorporate one realm of life after another into its work. Monism appears
more and more as the organizing principle of all practical cultural work, even if the inner
connections between thought and action, between science and economics, between ethics,
technology and politics are not clear in the general consciousness, also not among all
monists.” Das monistische Jahrhundert. Zeitschrift für wissenschaftliche
Weltanschauung und Weltgestaltung, volume 1, 5 April 1913.
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
37
15
Two monists who drifted into völkisch circles were Max Maurenbrecher and Otto
Gramzow. Maurenbrecher was a Protestant pastor, who joined the SPD in 1903 and
became a Free Religious preacher and monist in 1907, only to reject these causes during
the war, when he joined the ultra-right Fatherland Party and reentered the Protestant
clergy. After the war he preached a Nietzschean-Christian synthesis and antisemitism.
Gramzow was a philosopher of worldview, who after conversion to völkisch nationalism
during the war became embroiled in a losing struggle in 1926 for control of Berlin’s
premier popular scientific institution, the Humboldt Hochschule. Gramzow was able to
assume control with the help of the National Socialists in 1933. On Maurenbrecher, see
Justus Ulbricht, “Kulturrevolution von Rechts. Das völkische Netzwerk 1900-1933,” in
Nationalsozialismus in Thüringen (Cologne: Böhlau, 1995), 29-48. On Gramzow, Dr.
Oskar Stillich, Die Humboldt-Hochschule am Scheideweg! Eine Denkschrift an die
Dozenten und Hörer (Berlin: Hensel & Co., 1926). Landesarchiv Berlin, B Rep. 042, Nr.
26111, nos. 186, 229, 243.
16
On Ossietzky’s monism, see Dieter Fricke, “Ossietzky und der Monismus,” in Carl von
Ossietzky und die politische Kultur der Weimarer Republik, ed. Gerhard Kraiker
(Oldenburg: Bibliotheks- und Informationssystem der Universität Oldenburg, 1991), 123146.
17
Alfred Kelly, The Descent of Darwin (Chapel Hill: UNC Press, 1981), 25.
18
Emil du Bois-Reymond, “The Limits of our Knowledge of Nature,” The Popular
Science Monthly V, no. May (1874): 17-32, quotation 17.
19
Emil du Bois-Reymond, “The Limits of our Knowledge of Nature.”
20
Emil Heinrich Du Bois-Reymond, “Die sieben Welträthsel,” in Reden von Emil Du
Bois-Reymond, vol. 1 (Leipzig: von Veit & Co., 1886): 381-411, on Haeckel as the
“Prophet of Jena” 388-389, 396. On the echo of the “Ignorabimus” in German science
and culture, see the essays in Kurt Bayertz, Weltanschauung, Philosophie und
Naturwissenschaft im 19. Jahrhundert: vol. 3, Der Ignorabimus-Streit (Hamburg:
Meiner, 2007) and Hermann Lübbe, “Wissenschaft und Weltanschauung: Ideenpolitische
Fronten im Streit um Emil Du Bois-Reymond,” in Die Aufdringlichkeit der Geschichte:
Herausforderung der Moderne vom Historismus bis zum Nationalsozialismus, ed.
Hermann Lübbe (Graz, Vienna and Cologne: Styria, 1989), 257-274.
21
Ernst Haeckel, with a preface by Thomas Henry Huxley, Freedom in Science and
Teaching (New York: Humboldt Pub. Co., 1888).
22
Ernst Haeckel, The Riddle of the Universe at the Close of the Nineteenth Century (New
York, London: Harper & Brothers, 1900).
23
In 1894 the philosopher Wilhelm Windelband developed the opposition of nomothetic
and idiographic science. The former pursue general laws, i.e. natural science, the latter
historical explanation, i.e. the “Geisteswissenschaften.” The philosopher Heinrich Rickert
further elaborated this idea, stating that cultural sciences were concerned with value,
while natural science was concerned with laws. Herbert Schnädelbach, Philosophie in
Deutschland 1831-1933 (Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp, 1983): 77-79. Stephen Gould, “This
View of Life: Nonoverlapping Magisteria,” Natural History 106, no. 2 (1997): 16-22.
24
Ernst Haeckel, Monism as Connecting Religion and Science: the Confession of Faith of
a Man of Science (London: A. and C. Black, 1895).
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
25
38
Ernst Haeckel, Kristallseelen: Studien über das anorganische Leben (Leipzig: Alfred
Kröner, 1917).
26
Katherine Arens, Structures of Knowing: Psychologies of the Nineteenth Century
(Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1988).
27
Haeckel’s monism was not an isolated development in biological thought. Vitalism,
Gestalt psychology, and other schools of thought also the sought holistic explanations of
discrete biological phenomena. Like Haeckel, who invented the work ecology, they
advanced environmental theories. See Anne Harrington, Reenchanted Science: Holism in
German Culture from Wilhelm II to Hitler (Princeton: Princeton UP, 1996).
28
Arthur Drews, “Vorwort” and “Die verschiedenen Arten des Monismus,” in Der
Monismus : dargestellt in Beiträgen seiner Vertreter (Jena: E. Diederichs, 1908), vi-vii,
1-46.
29
Ernst Troeltsch’s insightful commentary on freethinkers can be applied to monists as a
whole: “The characteristic feature of free-thought, as distinguished from modern science,
properly so called, is its pervading sense of an axiomatic unity amongst its adherents,
based upon the assumption of certain self-consistent, universally binding, and ‘natural’
truths. The sociological aspect of ethical and religious thought manifests itself here in the
assumption – ‘natural’ and self-evident’ that all independent thinkers will inevitably
arrive at the uniformity in their convictions and modes of thought. On the foundation of
natural religion arises, so to speak, a ‘natural’ Church of free-thinkers.” Ernst Troeltsch,
“Free-Thought,” in Encyclopaedia of Religion and Ethics (New York: Scribner and Sons,
1908): 120-124.
30
See Gregory’s essay in this volume.
31
Herbert Schnädelbach, “Weltanschauung,” in Lexikon zur Geschichte und Politik im
20. Jahrhundert (Cologne: Kiepenhauer & Witsch, 1971), 842-43; Andreas Daum, “Das
versöhnende Element in der neuen Weltanschauung: Entwicklungsoptimismus,
Naturästhetik und Harmoniedenken im populärwissenschaftlichen Diskurs der
Naturkunde um 1900,” in Vom Weltbildwandel zur Weltanschauungsanalyse.
Krisenwahrnehmung und Krisenbewältigung um 1900, ed. Volker Drehsen and Walter
Sparn (Berlin: Akademie Verlag, 1996), 203-216; Herbert Schnädelbach, “Der Blick aufs
Ganze. Zur Optik der Weltanschauung,” in Philosophie in der modernen Kultur,
Vorträge und Abhandlungen, ed. Herbert Schnädelbach (Frankfurt a.M., 2000), 150-162.
32
Walter Benjamin, “Theses on the Philosophy of History,” in Illuminations: Essays and
Reflections (New York: Schocken, 1969): 253-264.
33
Recent examples of work on “political religion” include: Hans Maier and Michael
Schäfer, Totalitarismus und Politische Religionen: Konzepten des Diktaturenvergleiches
(Paderborn: Schönigh, 1997); Michael Burleigh, Earthly Powers: The Clash of Religion
and Politics in Europe from the French Revolution to the Great War (New York:
HarperCollins, 2005). For a critical review of this literature: Wolfgang Hardtwig,
“Political Religion in Modern Germany: Reflections on Nationalism, Socialism and
National Socialism,” GHI Bulletin 28 (2001): 3-27.
34
Jürgen Habermas, “The Language Game of Responsible Agency"; Fritz Mauthner,
“Monismus,” in Wörterbuch der Philosophie: Neue Beiträge zu einer Kritik der Sprache,
vol. 2 (Leipzig: Felix Meiner, 1924): 338-357; Walter Nigg, Geschichte des religiösen
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
39
Liberalismus: Entstehung - Blütezeit - Ausklang (Zurich and Leipzig: Max Niehans,
1937), 367.
35
Ludwik Fleck, Entstehung und Entwicklung einer wissenschaftlichen Tatsache:
Einführung in die Lehre vom Denkstil und Denkkollektiv (Basel: Benno Schwabe, 1935),
121.
36
Drews, “Der Monismus,” 1.
37
Jakob Stern, a former rabbi who went on to become an influential monist in the Social
Democratic camp, noted that while Spinoza’s concept of the conatus, the drive for selfpreservation made his system dynamic, it was thinkers like Hegel and Schelling, who
made a significant correction by introducing the idea of “continual development” into the
picture. These statements were made in Stern’s additions to the book he edited: Albert
Schwegler, Geschichte der Philosophie im Umriss (Leipzig; Reclam, 1889), 470.
38
Christian Wolff, Vernünfftige Gedanken; Rudolf Eucken, “Monism,” in Encyclopaedia
of Religion and Ethics, ed. James Hastings (New York: Scribner and Sons, 1908-1926),
809; “Monismus” in Horst Robert Balz et al, eds. Theologische Realenzyklopädie, Vol.
23 (Berlin: W. de Gruyter, 1994), p. 213.
39
G. Plekhanov, The Development of the Monist View of History, trans. Andrew
Rothstein (Moscow: Foreign Languages Publishing House, 1956 [1895]), p. 15.
40
Friedrich Harms, Der Anthropologismus in der Entwicklung der Philosophie seit Kant
und Ludwig Feuerbachs Anthroposophie (Leipzig: Otto Wigand, 1845), 204, 10.
Confirming Harms’s predictions, in 1848 Feuerbach now claimed that theology was not
just anthropology, but “anthropology plus physiology.” Cited in Van Harvey, “Ludwig
Feuerbach and Karl Marx,” in Nineteenth Century Religious Thought in the West, Ninian
Smart, et al. eds., vol. 1 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press): 291-328, 314.
41
David Galaty, “The Philosophical Basis of Mid-Nineteenth Century German
Reductionism,” Journal of the History of Medicine 29, no. July (1974): 300. Virchow
cited in: Constantin Goschler, Rudolf Virchow: Mediziner, Anthropologe, Politiker
(Cologne: Böhlau, 2002), 46.
42
Alexander von Humboldt, Kosmos: Entwurf einer physischen Weltbeschreibung, vol. I
(Stuttgart, Tübingen: Cotta, 1845), xii, iv, xiii
43
Karl Kleinpaul, “Die philosophische Naturreligion,” Neue Reform (1852), 515. I would
like to thank Peter Ramberg for locating this early usage of “monism” by the Free
Religious.
44
Todd Weir, “Towards a History and Sociology of Atheist Religious Community: The
Berlin Free Religious Congregation 1845-1921,” in: Die Gegenwart Gottes in der
Modernen Gesellschaft, eds. Lucian Hölscher, Michael Geyer (Göttingen: Wallstein
2006): 197-229.
45
On the organized secularist movement in Germany, see Horst Groschopp, Dissidenten.
Freidenkerei und Kultur in Deutschland (Berlin: Dietz, 1997); Frank Simon-Ritz, Die
Organisation einer Weltanschauung: die freigeistige Bewegung im Wilhelminischen
Deutschland (Gütersloh: Kaiser, 1997); Todd Weir, “The Fourth Confession”. For the
legacy of secularism in the Nazi period, see the essays by Ulrich Nanko, “Das Spektrum
völkisch-religiöser Organisationen von der Jahrhundertwende bis ins ‘Dritte Reich’” and
Matthias Pilger-Strohl, “Eine deutsche Religion? Die freireligiöse Bewegung - Aspekte
ihrer Beziehung zum völkischen Milieu,” in Völkische Religion und Krisen der Moderne:
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
40
Entwürfe “arteigener” Glaubenssysteme seit der Jahrhundetwende (Würzburg:
Königshausen & Neumann, 2001): 208-226; 342-366.
46
Caldwell, by contrast, sees in the eclecticism of the Feuerbachian radicals the “birth of
politics neither from pure reason nor from theology, but from the contradictory, scattered
pieces of an antiliberal, antiformal counterculture.” Love, Death, and Revolution in
Central Europe: Ludwig Feuerbach, Moses Hess, Louise Dittmar, Richard Wagner (New
York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2009), 7.
47
Diethart Kerbs and Jürgen Reulecke, eds. Handbuch der deutschen
Reformbewegungen: 1880 - 1933 (Wuppertal: Hammer, 1998).
48
David Friedrich Strauss, The Old Faith and the New: A Confession, vol. 6 (New York:
Holt, 1873).
49
Gauri Viswanathan has challenged scholars to recover the heterodox voices that have
been occluded the assumption inherent in secularization thesis that the religious history of
modernity boils down to a conflict between secularism and orthodox religion. Gauri
Viswanathan, “Secularism in the Framework of Heterodoxy,” Publications of the Modern
Language Association of America. 123, no. 2 (2008): 466-476.
50
On Halbbildung and monism, see Weir, “Towards a History and Sociology of Atheist
Religious Community,” 215-224.
51
One of Berlin’s first women’s organizations Frauenwohl initially recruited from among
sales clerks, a typical occupational category of the modern middle classes, who tended
like Frauenwohl’s leaders to associate with left-liberalism. Minna Cauer, 25 Jahre Verein
Frauenwohl Groß-Berlin (Berlin: W. & S. Loewenthal, 1913), p. 25.
52
Schmidt, Ernst Haeckel: Denkmal eines großen Lebens, p. 91. The acclaimed
innovator in modern dance, Isadora Duncan was reportedly another American female
Haeckelianer. Otto Lehmann-Rußbüldt, one of the chief promoters of the monist
Giordano Bruno-Bund in Berlin wrote to Haeckel on 11 March 1903 that “Miss Isadora
Duncan […] in an enthusiastic adherent of monism,” who knows “Darwin’s works very
well and is an admirer especially of your activities in German and in the international
cultural world.” Ernst Haeckel Haus, Jena, Haeckel papers.
53
For a critique of socio-biology for its unscientific ideological affirmation of male
domination, see the chapter “Putting Woman in Her (Evolutionary) Place” in Anne
Fausto-Sterling, Myths of Gender: Biological Theories about Women and Men, 2 ed.
(New York: Basic Books, 1992): 156-204. See also Donna Haraway, Simians, Cyborgs,
and Women: the Reinvention of Nature (New York: Routledge, 1991).
54
A recent article points out the significance of monism to the women’s movement but
fails to examine why natural science was important: Edward Ross Dickenson,
“Reflections on Feminism and Monism in the Kaiserreich, 1900-1913,” Central
European History 34, no. 2 (2001): 191-230.
55
Letters from Magnus Hirschfeld to Haeckel, 21 Feb. 1912, 6 May 1912, Ernst Haeckel
Haus, Jena, Haeckel papers. Hirschfeld gave a course on monism and sexual reform at a
scientific retreat of the DMB in May 1914.
56
Hirschfeld pushed fellow monists to accept homosexuality as a central plank of the
monist project, arguing that anyone committed to overcoming “oppositions like force and
matter, God and nature, one and all, body and soul” also had to abandon the “dualism of
the sexes.” For the sexes existed in a “eternally present fusion of both in one.” Their
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
41
“infinitely variable ratio of mixture … begins [with the fact] that already the male sperm
and the female egg are male-female hermaphroditic formations, this monism of the sexes
is the center of the origin and essence of personality.” Cited in a review of Hirschfeld’s
book on transvestites in: Diskussion. Kultur-Parlament. Eine Monatsschrift für aktuelle
Kulturfragen. Herausgegeben von Hans Ostwald, (Berlin: Eberhard Frowein, 1910), no.
II, p. 83.
57
Magnus Hirschfeld, Die Homosexualität des Mannes und des Weibes: Nachdruck der
Erstauflage von 1914 mit einer kommentierenden Einleitung von E. J. Haeberle (Berlin,
New York: Walter de Gruyter, 1984 (1914)), pp. XI-XII, 973-1026. On Hirschfeld, see
Kevin Amidon “Sex on the brain: The rise and fall of German sexual science” in
Endeavour 32, no. 2 (2008): 64-69.
58
Ernst Haeckel, Die Lebenswunder: Gemeinverständliche Studien über biologische
Philosophie (Volks-Ausgabe) (Stuttgart: Alfred Kröner, 1906), 157-164. Richard Weikart,
“Darwinism and Death: Devaluing Human Life in Germany 1859-1920,” Journal of the
History of Ideas 63, no. 2 (2002): 323-344.
59
The Deutscher Bund für Mutterschutz was founded in 1905 by Helene Stöcker, who
gave the organization’s journal a name suggestive of its eugenic and emancipatory
orientation: Die Neue Generation. Whether women’s liberation or eugenics had a priority
in this organization remained a matter of ongoing debate. Grete Meisel-Hess argued in
1909 that the women’s movement would be replaced by Mothers’ Protection, which had
“adopted the goals of highest racial welfare.” Ursula Ferdinand, Das Malthusische Erbe:
Entwicklungsstränge der Bevölkerungstheorie im 19. Jahrhundert und deren Einfluß auf
die radikale Frauenbewegung in Deutschland (Münster: Lit-Verlag, 1999), 208, 257.
60
Constance Naden, The Complete Poetical Works of Constance Naden (Kessinger
Publishing, 2004), 84, 203; Marion Thain, “‘Scientific Wooing’: Constance Naden’s
Marriage of Science and Poetry,” Victorian Poetry 41, no. 1 (March 1, 2003): 151-169;
Charles LaPorte, “Atheist Prophecy: Mathilde Blind, Constance Naden, and the Victorian
Poetess,” Victorian Literature and Culture 34, no. 2 (2006): 427-442.
61
Wilhelm Bölsche, Die naturwissenschaftlichen Grundlagen der Poesie (Tübingen:
DTV, 1976); Wilhelm Bölsche, “Fechner,” in Hinter der Weltstadt (Leipzig: Eugen
Diederichs, 1901), 259-347.
62
Monika Fick, Sinnenwelt und Weltseele: der psychophysische Monismus in der
Literatur der Jahrhundertwende (Tübingen: Niemeyer, 1993), 128. Like Fick, Claudia
Bibo argued that the transformation of the literary naturalists of the 1880s into neoRomantics and symbolists of the fin-de-siècle occurred within the natural scientific and
monistic premises of naturalism. Claudia Bibo, Naturalismus als Weltanschauung?
biologistische, theosophische und deutsch-völkische Bildlichkeit in der von Fidus
illustrierten Lyrik (1893-1902): mit einem Anhang: Organisationen der
Deutschgläubigen Bewegung (Frankfurt a. M.: Peter Lang, 1995), 7-8.
63
Hart, Die neue Welterkenntnis, cited in: Fick, Sinnenwelt und Weltseele, 138.
64
Bölsche wrote in the preface to his “Weltblick” in 1904: “All depends on One,
connects in One. Through this whispering of the branches blows world-wind. World-eyes
peer large and deep through these gaps in the leaf work. Press your forehead on the moss,
close your eyes, there lies in you as deep as the abyss, surging shapes, questions, calls,-World. And there is no more two.” Quoted in Bibo, Naturalismus, 34.
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
65
42
The following statement shows both the cognitive assumptions of psycho-physical
parallelism and their potential for aesthetic mysticism: “The penetrating sympathy
(Einfühlen) of the Ego in the object is only possible, if components of the object lay
within the Ego. […] Just as the sound of the voice across an open piano only causes the
vibration of strings of the same pitch, thus in the cells of men only those strings vibrate
that are given to them by nature.” Wilhelm Liepmann, Weltschöpfung und
Weltanschauung (Berlin: Wegweiser-Verlag, 1923), 98.
66
Andreas-Salome quotations in Fick, Sinnenwelt und Weltseele, 133. Writer and
anarchist Gustav Landauer points to the impossibility of reaching the union promised by
the biogenetic principle through consciousness and offers self-actualization and erotic
love as alternatives: “I am the cause of myself, because I am the world. I am the world,
when I am entirely myself. The course of the evolutionary stream comes from the source
that originates in eternity; the chain has never been broken though the stream cannot of
course flow backwards, and the superficially thinking part of our human brain cannot
remember the origin upon which it developed, cannot perceive the source from outside,
as an object, which flows through it, in the eternal present. […] However, we find this
infinite in ourselves, when we become infinite, become entirely ourselves and draw our
deepest foundation out of ourselves. And there is a path to this feeling of infinity, […]
love. […] It is the deepest and most glowing form of perception of the world
(Welterkenntnis), […] when the fire spark penetrates two people.” Gustav Landauer,
“Durch Absonderung zur Gemeinschaft,” in Das Reich der Erfüllung: Flugschriften zur
Begründung einer neuen Weltanschauung, ed. Heinrich Hart and Julius Hart (Leipzig:
Eugen Diederichs, 1901): 65-66.
67
On monism in an international context, see the essays in Heiko Weber and Maurizio Di
Bartolo, eds., Jahrbuch für Europäische Wissenschaftskultur, vol. 3 (Stuttgart: Steiner,
2007).
68
Heinrich Heine, On the history of religion and philosophy in Germany and other
writings (Cambridg; New York: Cambridge University Press, 2007). Bertolt Brecht,
“Flüchtlingsgespräche,” in Bertolt Brecht Werke, ed. Werner Hecht et al. (Berlin: Aufbau
and Suhrkamp, 1995), 205.
69
James Morton, Jr., “Das Freidenkertum in den Vereinigten Staaten,” in: Das
monistische Jahrhundert, vol. 2 (1913), 983.
70
Robert Crews, “Empire and the Confessional State: Islam and Religious Politics in
Nineteenth-Century Russia,” American Historical Review 10, no. 1 (2003).
71
For example, Arens, Structures of Knowing: Psychologies of the Nineteenth Century.
Monika Fick, “Sinnstiftung durch Sinnlichkeit: Monistisches Denken um 1900” in:
Wolfgang Braungart/Gotthard Fuchs/Manfred Koch (eds.) Ästhetische und religiöse
Erfahrungen der Jahrhundertwenden. vol. 2 (Paderborn 1998): 69-83.
72
Hermann Lübbe, Säkularisierung. Geschichte eines ideenpolitischen Begriffs, 2 ed.
(Munich: Karl Alber, 1975), 45-46.
73
“Christian Monism” forms a third area of hybrid monism. German Protestants of the
Weimar era went much further than their Catholic counterparts in borrowing elements of
the monist worldview in order to combat it. During the mid 1920s the defensive agency
of the Protestant Church—the Apologetic Central—offered “worldview weeks” for the
educated laity on topics such as “Between Matter and Spirit” and sought out cooperation
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
43
with conservative völkisch circles, such as the Fichte Society. In 1926 the Church
sponsored the foundation of the Research Center for Worldview Studies in Wittenberg
under the leadership of theologian and ornithologist Otto Kleinschmidt. An ardent
opponent of Haeckel, Kleinschmidt sought to fuse biology and Protestant theology in a
unified worldview, which at the end of the Weimar Republic embraced racial science.
Given shared interest in a spiritualized concept of human biology and opposition to
secularism and socialism, National Socialists and Christian monists initially found much
common ground, however frictions between them grew following the consolidation of
Nazi power in Spring 1933, when the new regime began to turn on its erstwhile allies.
Matthias Pöhlmann, Kampf der Geister: Die Publizistik der “Apologetischen Centrale”
(1921-1937) (Stuttgart: Kohlhammer, 1998), 89.
74
Cited in: Franz Meffert, Ernst Häckel der Darwinist und Freidenker: Ein Beitrag zur
Charakteristik des modernen Freidenkertums (M. Gladbach: Volksverein-Verlag, 1920),
p. 245. The East German leader Walter Ulbricht, who was educated in an workers
education association, was probably recalling his own experiences when he declared in
1960, “Rarely has a book had more lasting impact than Haeckels Welträtsel.” From his
speech at the 15th anniversary of the refounding of the Friedrich-Schiller University in
Jena and cited in an advertising insert in the 1960 reprint of Ernst Haeckel, Die Welträtsel
(Berlin: Akademie, 1960 (1899)). V.I. Lenin approvingly cited Franz Mehring’s positive
review of the Welträtsel, that the book was important not for its veracity, but for its
political tendency, which made it, in Lenin’s words, “a weapon in the class struggle.”
Vladimir Lenin, Materialism and empirio-criticism. (New York: International Publishers,
1927), 362.
75
August Bebel began his career as a member of a workers’ education society Vorwärts
led by German Catholic preacher and monist Emil Roßmäßler. In 1882 Karl Kautsky
sounded out Haeckel on the possibility of submitting a dissertation to him, while the
future leader of East Germany, Walter Ulbricht had received religious education as a
child from Deutschkatholiken in Leipzig. On the role of Freethought and Free Religion in
early socialism, see Sebastian Prüfer, Sozialismus statt Religion: Die deutsche
Sozialdemokratie vor der religiösen Frage 1863-1890 (Göttingen: Vandenhoeck &
Ruprecht, 2002).
76
Ostwald to Loeb, 14 Oct. 1913, Ostwald papers, no. 1828, Berlin Brandenburg
Academy of Sciences.
77
In his attempt to ground a dialectical monism, the German-American socialist Ernest
Untermann criticized Haeckel for failing to account for class as a dualism requiring
liquidation. Ernest Untermann, Dialektisches. Volkstümliche Vorträge aus dem Gebiete
des proletarischen Monismus, (Stuttgart: J.H.W. Dietz, 1907). His book Science and
revolution (Chicago: C. H. Kerr & Company, 1905) contains a chapter entitled
“Materialist Monism: The Science And ‘Religion’ Of The Proletariat” with the passage:
“Only the universe is immortal, and it cannot be destroyed. If the human mind wishes to
share in this immortality, and avoid being hurled into the abyss of oblivion, it has only
one course open before it: The conscious promotion of an environment in which an organ
of understanding can develop which will succeed in controlling the universal process. It
is only the philosophy of the proletariat which furnishes a scientific basis for the
realization of the most daring dreams of the thinkers of all ages. The proletarian mind,
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
44
conscious of its origin, its present and future place in society and universe, its social,
terrestrial, and cosmic mission, can exclaim triumphantly: ‘I was, I am, and I shall be!’”
78
Vladimir Lenin, Materialism and empirio-criticism..
79
Klaus Mehnert, Twilight of the young : the radical movements of the 1960’s and their
legacy : a personal report (New York: Holt Rinehart and Winston, 1977).
80
Daniel Gasman, The Scientific Origins of National Socialism: Social Darwinism in
Ernst Haeckel and the German Monist League, xiv.
81
See the critiques of Gasman and Weikart in Richards, The Tragic Sense of Life, 506509.
82
Cited in T. Schirrmacher, Hitlers Kriegsreligion. (Bonn, Verlag für Kultur und
Wissenschaft, 2007) 108
83
“Mit brennender Sorge,” March 14, 1937. Taken from Papal Encyclicals Online.
http://www.papalencyclicals.net/Pius11/P11FAC.HTM.
84
In one of his last essays, Berlin wrote that “the enemy of pluralism is monism—the
ancient belief that there is a single harmony of truths into which everything, if it is
genuine, in the end must fit.” New York Review of Books, Vol. XLV, Number 8 (1998).
Several of the contributors to a commemorative volume considered “anti-monism” to be
Berlin’s chief political legacy. See, Mark Lilla, Ronald D. Dworkin, and Robert B.
Silvers, The Legacy of Isaiah Berlin (New York Review of Books, 2001).Tzvetan
Todorov, Hope and Memory (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton UP, 2003), 14, 20-22.
85
Todorov chose the term monism simply as an antonym for pluralism. His functional
explanation of monism is based on Eric Voegelin’s theory of political religion, whereby
monism ensues when a properly dualistic understanding of the relationship of the divine
and the secular breaks down. Ibid., 14-26.
86
In his essay, Huxley argued that the Vedantic idea that behind reality lay an
“unmanifested principle of all manifestations” “at once transcendent and immanent” was
the optimal “minimum working hypothesis” for personal religious research. Too little
hypothesis led to superficiality, while the problem of Western revealed religions is that
they had “too much working hypothesis” or “dogma.” “Catholics, Jews and Moslems,”
wrote Huxley, could only find what they “already know to be there.” This foreclosed
experimentation and rational inquiry, making these religions a scientific dead-end.
Aldous Huxley, “The Minimum Working Hypothesis,” in Vedanta for the Western World
(Hollywood: Vedanta Society of Southern California, 1945), 33-35.
87
On monist developments in postwar East Germany, see Igor J. Polianski, “Das Rätsel
DDR und die ‘Welträtsel’”, Deutschland Archiv 2/2007, 265-274. According to
geographer Mark Bassin, the ecological understanding of ethnicity in the tradition of
Haeckel and his student Friedrich Ratzel was sustained between the 1960s and 1990s by
the Soviet scholar Lev Gumilev: Mark Bassin, “Nurture Is Nature: Lev Gumilev and the
Ecology of Ethnicity,” Slavic Review 68, no. 4 (2009): 872-897.
88
Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri advocate a politics based on the Spinozan concept of
love as conatus articulated through reason. This love “is not only an ontological motor,
[…] but also an open field of battle.” Commonwealth (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard UP,
2009), 195. As similar approach to emotion is taken by Eve Kosofsky Sedgwick, who
seeks to correct a dualism in deconstruction and gender theory that stemmed from an
antiessentialist impulse that led scholars to separate physicality from linguistic or social
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
45
construction and privilege the latter. She proposes to no longer subsume “nonverbal
aspects of reality firmly under the aegis of the linguistic” and draws on affect theory to
investigate a nondualistic understanding of the emotions. Touching Feeling: Affect,
Pedagogy, Performativity (Durham: Duke UP, 2003), 6. These recent monistic tendencies
in critical theory were brought to my attention by Tracie Matysik, whom I would like to
thank for allowing me to read her unpublished paper “From Sexuality to Affect:
Reflections for the Intellectual History of Sexuality.”
89
Church historian Hugh McLeod specified the 1960s as the point at which
“Christendom” ended and the secular age began. Building on this periodization, we may
identify an age of secularism that opened around 1840 and ended with Christendom in the
secular age. That is a period in which secularist movements critiqued and competed with
Christianity in Europe. I have suggested two terms to sum up the specificity of these
secularist movements, those are worldview and monism. Hugh McLeod, “Introduction,”
in The Decline of Christendom in Western Europe, 1750-2000, ed. Hugh McLeod and
Werner Ustorf (Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 2003).
90
Haeckel, The riddle of the universe, 34.
91
A similar turn was taken by the Austrian Rudolf Steiner, who had been a Haeckelian
and taught workers in freethinking circles around 1900 before he founded his own
theosophical school of anthroposophy. Helmut Zander, Anthroposophie in Deutschland
(Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 2007), vol 1, 881-889. There are many other cases, which
suggest that problems raised by naturalistic monism and secularist dissent formed a key
context for the reception of Asian philosophy in Europe. For example, a leading monistfreethinking journal Das Freie Wort was launched in 1900 by the Free Religious preacher
of Frankfurt a. Main Carl Sänger, The Quran translator Max Henning and one of
Germany’s leading Buddhists Arthur Pfungst. Groschopp, Dissidenten, 28-41.
92
Against this interpretation, Niles Holt argued that Haeckel’s monism developed in four
stages. Niles Holt, “Ernst Haeckel´s Monistic Religion,” Journal of the History of Ideas,
no. 32 (1971).
93
A sympathetic portray of Kammerer is found in: Arthur Koestler, The Case of the
Midwife Toad (New York: Random House, 1971).
94
On Ostwald’s marginalization from the scientific community see Weir, “The Fourth
Confession: Atheism, Monism and Politics in the ‘Freigeistig’ Movement in Berlin 18591924,” 458-462.
95
A sign of the impact of Ostwald on young intellectuals can be taken from letters
addressed to him in 1912 and 1913 by the future economist and political theorist Karl
Polanyi, in his function as secretary of the Central Association of Hungarian
Freethinkers. On 19 May 1913, Polanyi wrote that their newspaper, Szabad Gondolat
(Free Thought) “strove to extend the monist worldview and, in particular, the ethical
world picture that this entails.” Ostwald papers, no. 4119, Berlin Brandenburg Academy
of Sciences.
96
Robert Bud, “A sword from the field of battle: The Double Helix and debates over the
secret of life,” conference paper presented on October 3, 2009 at Queen’s University
Belfast.
97
Haldane’s position paralleled that of many continental monists, such as Viktor Stern,
who had started out prior to the First World War as a monist philosopher and by the
The Riddles of Monism: An Introductory Essay
46
1920s become a functionary of the Czech communist party and leader of their
Freethought movement. For further details on Haldane, see Peter Bowler’s essay in this
volume.
98
A sign of the welcome German monism received in the early Soviet Union is shown by
the Russian part in the drama around Paul Kammerer. Following the revelations that he
had manipulated his research data, Soviet officials came to his rescue by offering him
directorship of an institute. Following his suicide, Anatoly Lunacharsky, one of the
prewar Bolshevik monists and now Minister of Enlightenment, wrote the script for a film
that portrayed Kammerer as the victim of clerical-conservative intrigue. Arthur Koestler,
The Case of the Midwife Toad (New York: Random House, 1971).