Monism as Connecting Religion and Science
Ernst Haeckel (trans. J. Gilchrist)
Preface
The following lecture on Monism is an informal address delivered extemporaneously on
October 9, 1892, at Altenburg, on the seventy-fifth anniversary of the ‘Naturforschende
Gesellschaft des Osterlandes.’ The immediate occasion of it was a previous address
delivered by Professor Schlesinger of Vienna on ‘Scientific Articles of Faith.’ This
philosophical discourse contained, with reference to the weightiest and most important
problems of scientific investigation, much that was indisputable; but it also contained some
assertions that challenged immediate rejoinder and a statement of the opposite view. As I
had for thirty years been very closely occupied with these problems of the philosophy of
nature, and had set forth my convictions with respect to them in a number of writings, a
wish was expressed by several members of the Congress that on this occasion I should give
a summary account of these. It was in compliance with this wish that the following
‘Scientific Confession of Faith’ was uttered. The substance of it, as written from
recollection on the day after its delivery, first appeared in the Altenburger Zeitung of 19th
October 1892. This was reproduced, with one or two philosophical additions, in the
November number of the Freie Buehne fuer den Entwickelungskampf der Zeit (Berlin). In
its present form the Altenburg address is considerably enlarged, and some parts have been
more fully worked out. In the notes several burning questions of the present day have been
dealt with from the monistic point of view.
The purpose of this candid confession of monistic faith is twofold. First, it is my desire
to give expression to that rational view of the world which is being forced upon us with
such logical rigour by the modern advancements in our knowledge of nature as a unity, a
view in reality held by almost all unprejudiced and thinking men of science, although but
few have the courage (or the need) to declare it openly. Secondly, I would fain establish
thereby a bond between religion and science, and thus contribute to the adjustment of the
antithesis so needlessly maintained between these, the two highest spheres in which the
mind of man can exercise itself; in monism the ethical demands of the soul are satisfied, as
well as the logical necessities of the understanding.
The rising flood of pamphlets and books published on this subject, demonstrates that
such a natural union of faith and knowledge, such a reasonable reconciliation of the
feelings and the reason, are daily becoming a more pressing necessity for the educated
classes. In North America (in Chicago), there has been published for several years a weekly
journal devoted to this purpose: The Open Court: A Weekly Journal devoted to the Work of
Conciliating Religion and Science. Its worthy editor, Dr. Paul Carus (author of The Soul of
Man, 1891), devotes also to the same task a quarterly journal under the title The Monist. It
is in the highest degree desirable that so worthy endeavours to draw together the empirical
and speculative views of nature, realism and idealism, should have more attention and
encouragement than they have hitherto received, for it is only through a natural union of the
two that we can approach a realisation of the highest aim of mental activity-the blending of
religion and science in monism.
ERNST HAECKEL. JENA, October 31, 1892
MONISM
A society for investigating nature and ascertaining truth cannot celebrate its
commemoration day more fittingly than by a discussion of its highest general problems. It
must be regarded, therefore, with satisfaction that the speaker on such an august occasion as
this—the seventy-fifth anniversary of your Society—has selected as the subject of his
address a theme of the highest general importance. Unfortunately, it is becoming more and
more the custom on such occasions, and even at the general meetings of the great
‘Association of German Naturalists and Physicians,’ to take the subject of address from a
narrow and specialised territory of restricted interest. If this growing custom is to be
excused on the grounds of increasing division of labour and of diverging specialisation in
all departments of work, it becomes all the more necessary that, on such anniversaries as
the present, the attention of the audience should be invited to larger matters of common
interest.
Such a topic, supreme in its importance, is that concerning ‘Scientific Articles of Faith,’
upon which Professor Schlesinger has already expounded his views.1 I am glad to be able to
agree with him in many important points, but as to others I should like to express some
hesitation, and to ask consideration for some views which do not coincide with his. At the
outset, I am entirely at one with him as to that unifying conception of nature as a whole
which we designate in a single word as Monism. By this we unambiguously express our
conviction that there lives ‘one spirit in all things,’ and that the whole cognisable world is
constituted, and has been developed, in accordance with one common fundamental law. We
emphasise by it, in particular, the essential unity of inorganic and organic nature, the latter
having been evolved from the former only at a relatively late period.2 We cannot draw a
1
In Professor Schlesinger's address (delivered on 9th October at Altenburg) on this subject he rightly called
attention to the limits of knowledge of nature (in Kant's sense of the terms) imposed upon us by the
imperfection of our perceptive organs. The gaps which the empirical investigation of nature must thus leave in
science, can, however, be filled up by hypotheses, by conjectures of more or less probability. These we cannot
indeed for the time establish on a secure basis; and yet we may make use of them in the way of explaining
phenomena, in so far as they are not inconsistent with a rational knowledge of nature. Such rational
hypotheses are scientific articles of faith, and therefore very different from ecclesiastical articles of faith or
religious dogmas, which are either pure fictions (resting on no empirical evidence), or simply irrational
(contradicting the law of causality). As instances of rational hypotheses of first-rate importance may be
mentioned our belief in the oneness of matter (the building up of the elements from primary atoms), our belief
in equivocal generation, our belief in the essential unity of all natural phenomena, as maintained by monism
(on which compare my General Morphology, vol 1 pp. 105, 164, etc., also my Natural History of Creation,
8th ed., 1889, pp. 21, 360, 795). As the simpler occurrences of inorganic nature and the more complicated
phenomena of organic life are alike reducible to the same natural forces, and as, further, these in their turn
have their common foundation in a simple primal principle pervading infinite space, we can regard this last
(the cosmic ether) as all-comprehending divinity, and upon this found the thesis: ‘Belief in God is
reconcilable with science.’ In this pantheistic view, and also in his criticism of a one-sided materialism, I
entirely agree with Professor Schlesinger, though unable to concur with him in some of his biological, and
especially of his anthropological, conclusions (cf. his article on ‘Facts and Deductions derived from the
Action of Universal Space’ Mittheilungen aus dem Osterlande, Bd. 5, Altenburg, 1892).
2
I consider the fundamental unity of inorganic and organic nature, as well as their genetic relation, to be an
essential axiom of monism. I particularly emphasise this ‘article of faith’ here, as there are still scientists of
repute who contest it. Not only is the old mystical ‘vital power’ brought back upon the stage again from time
to time, but even the ‘miraculous’ origin of organic life out of ‘dead’ inorganic nature is often brought up still
2
sharp line of distinction between these two great divisions of nature, any more than we can
recognise an absolute distinction between the animal and the vegetable kingdom, or
between the lower animals and man. Similarly, we regard the whole of human knowledge
as a structural unity; in this sphere we refuse to accept the distinction usually drawn
between the natural and the spiritual. The latter is only a part of the former (or vice versa);
both are one. Our monistic view of the world belongs, therefore, to that group of
philosophical systems which from other points of view have been designated also as
mechanical or as pantheistic. However differently expressed in the philosophical systems of
an Empedocles or a Lucretius, a Spinoza or a Giordano Bruno, a Lamarck or a David
Strauss, the fundamental thought common to them all is ever that of the oneness of the
cosmos, of the indissoluble connection between energy and matter, between mind and
embodiment—or, as we may also say, between God and the world—to which Goethe,
Germany's greatest poet and thinker, has given poetical expression in his Faust and in the
wonderful series of poems entitled Gott und Welt.
That we may rightly appreciate what this Monism is, let us now, from a philosophicohistorical point of view cast a comprehensive glance over the development in time of man's
knowledge of nature. A long series of varied conceptions and stages of human culture here
passes before our mental vision. At the lowest stage, the rude—we may say animal—phase
of prehistoric primitive man, is the ‘ape-man,’ who, in the course of the tertiary period, has
only to a limited degree raised himself above his immediate pithecoid ancestors, the
anthropoid apes. Next come successive stages of the lowest and simplest kind of culture,
such as only the rudest of still existing primitive peoples enable us in some measure to
conceive. These ‘savages’ are succeeded by peoples of a low civilisation, and from these
again, by a long series of intermediate steps, we rise little by little to the more highly
civilised nations. To these alone—of the twelve races of mankind only to the Mediterranean
and Mongolian—are we indebted for what is usually called ‘universal history.’ This last,
extending over somewhat less than six thousand years, represents a period of infinitesimal
duration in the long millions of years of the organic world's development.
Neither of the primitive men we have spoken of, nor of those who immediately
succeeded them, can we rightly predicate any knowledge of nature. The rude primitive
child of nature at this lowest stage of development is as yet far from being the restless
Ursachenthier (cause-seeking animal) of Lichtenberg; his demand for causes has not yet
risen above that of apes and dogs; his curiosity has not yet mounted to pure desire of
knowledge. If we must speak of ‘reason’ in connection with pithecoid primitive man, it can
only be in the same sense as that in which we use the expression with reference to those
against the doctrines of evolution, as an insoluble riddle—as one of Du Bois-Reymond's ‘seven riddles of the
world’ (see his Discourse on Leibnitz, 1880). The solution of this ‘transcendent’ riddle of the world, and of
the allied question of archigony (equivocal generation, in a strictly defined meaning of the term), can only be
reached by a critical analysis and unprejudiced comparison of matter, form, and energy in inorganic and
organic nature. This I have already done (1866) in the second book of my General Morphology (vol 1 pp.
109-238): ‘General Researches as to the Nature and First Beginning of Organisms, their Relation to things
Inorganic, and their Division into Plants and Animals.’
A short resume of this is contained in Lecture XV of my Natural History of Creation (8th ed., pp. 340370). The most serious difficulties which formerly beset the monistic view there given may now be held to
have been taken out of the way by recent discoveries concerning the nature of protoplasm, the discovery of
the Monera, the more accurate study of the closely-related single-celled Protista, their comparison with the
ancestral cell (or fertilised egg-cell), and also by the chemical carbon-theory. (See my ‘Studies on Monera and
other Protista,’ in the Jenaische Zeitschrift fuer Naturwissenschaft, vols 4 and 5, 1868-1870; also Carl
Naegeli, Mechanisch-physiologische Begruendung der Abstammungslehre, 1884.)
3
other most highly developed Mammals, and the same remark holds true of the first
beginnings of religion.3
It is indeed still not infrequently the custom to deny absolutely to the lower animals
reason and religion. An unprejudiced comparison, however, convinces us that this is wrong.
The slow and gradual process towards completeness which, in the course of thousands of
years, civilised life has been working in the soul of man, has not passed away without
leaving some trace on the soul of our highest domestic animals also (above all, of dogs and
horses). Constant association with man, and the steady influence of his training, have
gradually, and by heredity, developed in their brain higher associations of ideas and a more
perfect judgment. Drill has become instinct, an undeniable example of ‘the transmission of
acquired characters.’4
Comparative psychology teaches us to recognise a very long series of successive steps in
the development of soul in the animal kingdom. But it is only in the most highly developed
vertebrates—birds and mammals—that we discern the first beginnings of reason, the first
traces of religious and ethical conduct. In them we find not only the social virtues common
to all the higher socially-living animals,—neighbourly love, friendship, fidelity, selfsacrifice, etc.,—but also consciousness, sense of duty, and conscience; in relation to man
their lord, the same obedience, the same submissiveness, and the same craving for
protection, which primitive man in his turn shows towards his ‘gods.’ But in him, as in
them, there is yet wanting that higher degree of consciousness and of reason, which strives
after a knowledge of the surrounding world, and which marks the first beginning of
philosophy or ‘wisdom.’ This last is the much later attainment of civilised races; slowly and
gradually has it been built up from lower religious conceptions.
At all stages of primitive religion and early philosophy, man is as yet far removed from
monistic ideas. In searching out the causes of phenomena, and exercising his understanding
thereon, he is in the first instance prone in every case to regard personal beings—in fact,
anthropomorphic deities—as the agents at work. In thunder and lightning, in storm and
earthquake, in the circling of sun and moon, in every striking meteorological and geological
occurrence, he sees the direct activity of a personal god or spirit, who is usually thought of
3
We cannot fail to recognise in the more highly developed of our domestic animals (especially in dogs,
horses, and elephants) some first beginnings of those higher brain-functions which we designate as reason and
consciousness, religion and morality; they differ only in degree, not in kind, from the corresponding mental
activities of the lowest human races. If, like the dogs, the apes, and especially the anthropoids, had been for
thousands of years domesticated and brought up in close relation with civilised man, the similarity of their
mental activities to those of man would undoubtedly have been much more striking than it is. The apparently
deep gulf which separates man from these most highly-developed mammals ‘is mainly founded on the fact
that in man several conspicuous attributes are united, which in the other animals occur only separately, viz.
(1) The higher degree of differentiation of the larynx (speech), (2) brain (mind), and (3) extremities; and (4)
the upright posture. It is merely the happy combination of these important animal organs and functions at a
higher stage of evolution that raises the majority of mankind so far above all lower animals’ (General
Morphology, 1866, vol 2 p. 430).
4
As the controversy on this important question is still unsettled, special attention may here be called to the
valuable data for arriving at a decision which are afforded precisely by the development of instincts among
the higher animals, and of speech and reason in man. ‘The inheritance of characters acquired during the life of
the individual, is an indispensable axiom of the monistic doctrine of evolution.’ ‘Those who, with Weismann
and Galton, deny this, entirely exclude thereby the possibility of any formative influence of the outer world
upon organic form’ (Anthropogenie, 4th ed., pp. xxiii, 836; see, further, the works there referred to of Eimer,
Weismann, Ray-Lankester, etc.; also Ludwig Wilser's Die Vererbung der geistigen Eigenschaften,
Heidelberg, 1892).
4
in a more or less anthropomorphic way. Gods are distinguished as good and bad, friendly
and hostile, preserving and destroying, angels and devils.
This becomes true in a yet higher degree when the advancing pursuit of knowledge
begins to take into consideration the more complicated phenomena of organic life also, the
appearance and disappearance of plants and animals, the life and death of man. The
constitution of organised life, so suggestive as it is of art and purpose, leads one at once to
compare it with the deliberately designed works of man, and thus the vague conception of a
personal god becomes transformed into that of a creator working according to plan. As we
know, this conception of organic creation as the artistic work of an anthropomorphic god—
of a divine mechanic—generally maintained its ground almost everywhere, down even to
the middle of our own century, in spite of the fact that eminent thinkers had demonstrated
its untenability more than two thousand years ago. The last noteworthy scientist to defend
and apply this idea was Louis Agassiz (died 1873). His notable Essay on Classification,
1857, developed that theosophy with logical vigour, and thereby reduced it to an absurdity.5
All these older religious and teleological conceptions, as well as the philosophical
systems (such as those of Plato and of the Church fathers) which sprang from them, are
antimonistic; they stand in direct antithesis to our monistic philosophy of nature. Most of
them are dualistic, regarding God and the world, creator and creature, spirit and matter, as
two completely separated substances. We find this express dualism also in most of the
purer church-religions, especially in the three most important forms of monotheism which
the three most renowned prophets of the eastern Mediterranean—Moses, Christ, and
Mohammed—founded. But soon, in a number of impure varieties of these three religions,
and yet more in the lower forms of paganism, the place of this dualism is taken by a
philosophical pluralism, and over against the good and world-sustaining deity (Osiris,
Ormuzd, Vishnu), there is placed a wicked and destroying god (Typhon, Ahriman, Siva).
Numerous demi-gods or saints, good and bad, sons and daughters of the gods, are
associated with these two chief deities, and take part with them in the administration and
government of the cosmos.
In all these dualistic and pluralistic systems the fundamental idea is that of
anthropomorphism, or the humanising of God; man himself, as godlike (or directly
descended from God), occupies a special position in the world, and is separated by a great
gulf from the rest of nature. Conjoined with this, for the most part, is the anthropocentric
idea, the conviction that man is the central point of the universe, the last and highest final
cause of creation, and that the rest of nature was created merely for the purpose of serving
man. In the Middle Ages there was associated at the same time with this last conception the
geocentric idea, according to which the earth as the abode of man was taken for the fixed
middle point of the universe, round which sun, moon, and stars revolve. As Copernicus
(1543) gave the death-blow to the geocentric dogma, so did Darwin (1859) to the
anthropocentric one closely associated with it.6 A broad historical and critical comparison
5
Of all the modern attempts of dualistic philosophy to establish the knowledge of nature on a theological
basis (that of Christian monotheism), the Essay on Classification of Louis Agassiz is by far the most
important,—in strictness, indeed, is the only one worthy of mention. (On this see my Natural History of
Creation, Lect. 3, also ‘Aims and Methods of the Modern Embryology,’ 1875, Jena Zeitschr. fuer Naturw.,
Bd. 10, Supplement.)
6
This is the title of an address delivered by Du Bois-Reymond on 25th January 1883, in the Berlin Academy
of Sciences, and afterwards published in his Collected Addresses (vol 2 1887). As the author himself
mentions in a note (p. 500) that this gave rise, ‘most unmeritedly,’ to great excitement, and called down upon
him the violent attacks of the clerical press, I may be allowed to point out here that it contained nothing new, I
5
of religious and philosophical systems, as a whole, leads as a main result to the conclusion
that every great advance in the direction of profounder knowledge has meant a breaking
away from the traditional dualism (or pluralism) and an approach to monism. Ever more
clearly are we compelled by reflection to recognise that God is not to be placed over against
the material world as an external being, but must be placed as a ‘divine power’ or ‘moving
spirit’ within the cosmos itself. Ever clearer does it become that all the wonderful
phenomena of nature around us, organic as well as inorganic, are only various products of
one and the same original force, various combinations of one and the same primitive
matter. Ever more irresistibly is it borne in upon us that even the human soul is but an
insignificant part of the all-embracing ‘world-soul’; just as the human body is only a small
individual fraction of the great organised physical world.
The great general principles of theoretical physics and chemistry are now in a position to
afford to this unifying conception of nature an exact, to a certain extent, indeed, a
mathematical confirmation. In establishing the law of the ‘conservation of energy,’ Robert
Mayer and Helmholtz showed that the energy of the universe is a constant unchangeable
magnitude; if any energy whatever seems to vanish or to come anew into play, this is only
due to the transformation of one form of energy into another. In the same way Lavoisier's
law of the ‘conservation of matter’ shows us that the material of the cosmos is a constant
unchangeable magnitude; if any body seems to vanish (as, for example, by burning), or to
come anew into being (as, for example, by crystallisation), this also is simply due to change
of form or of combination. Both these great laws—in physics, the fundamental law of the
conservation of energy, and in chemistry, of the conservation of matter—may be brought
under one philosophical conception as the law of the conservation of substance; for,
according to our monistic conception, energy and matter are inseparable, being only
different inalienable manifestations of one single universal being-substance.7 In a certain
myself, fifteen years previously, in my lectures on ‘The Origin and Genealogy of the Human Race,’ having
carried out in detail the comparison between Darwin and Copernicus, and the service rendered by these two
heroes in putting an end to the anthropocentric and geocentric views of the world. (See the Third Series in
Virchow and Holtzendorff's Collection of Popular Scientific Lectures, Nos. 53 and 54, 1868, 4th ed., 1881.)
When Du Bois-Reymond says, ‘For me, Darwin is the Copernicus of the organic world,’ I am the more
pleased to find that he agrees (partly in identical words) with my way of thinking, as he himself, quite
unnecessarily, takes up an attitude of opposition towards me. The same is the case with regard to the
explanation of innate ideas by Darwinism, which he has attempted in his address (1870) on ‘Leibnitzian Ideas
in Modern Science’ (vol 1 of the Collected Addresses). Here also he is most agreeably at one with me in what,
four years before, I had elaborated in my General Morphology (vol 2 p. 446), and in my Natural History of
Creation (1868). ‘The laws of heredity and adaptation explain to us how it is that a priori ideas have been
developed out of what was originally a posteriori knowledge,’ etc. I cannot fail to be highly flattered in being
able in these last days to greet the renowned orator of the Berlin Academy as a friend and patron of the
Natural History of Creation, which he had previously designated a bad romance. But his winged words are
not on that account to be forgotten, that ‘the genealogical trees of phylogeny are about as much worth as, in
the eyes of the historical critic, are those of the Homeric heroes’ (Darwin versus Galiani, 1876).
7
Strictly taken, this belongs also to ‘scientific articles of faith,’ and could stand as the first article of our
‘monistic religion.’ Physicists of the present day, it is true, generally (and correctly) regard their ‘law of the
conservation of energy’ as the immovable foundation of all their science (Robert Mayer, Helmholtz), just as
in like manner chemists so regard their fundamental law of the ‘conservation of matter’ (Lavoisier). Sceptical
philosophers could, however, raise certain objections to either of these fundamental laws with as much
success as against their combination into the single superior law of the ‘conservation of substance.’ As a
matter of fact, dualistic philosophy still attempts to raise such objections, often under the guise of cautious
criticism. The sceptical (in part also purely dogmatic) objections have a semblance of justification only in so
far as they relate to the fundamental problem of substance, the primary question as to the connection between
matter and energy. While freely recognising the presence of this real ‘boundary of natural knowledge,’ we can
6
sense we can regard the conception of ‘animated atoms’ as essentially partaking of the
nature of this pure monism—a very ancient idea which more than two thousand years ago
Empedocles enunciated in his doctrine of ‘hate and love of the elements.’ Modern physics
and chemistry have indeed in the main accepted the atomic hypothesis first enunciated by
Democritus, in so far as they regard all bodies as built up of atoms, and reduce all changes
to movements of these minutest-discrete particles. All these changes, however, in organic
as well as in inorganic nature, become truly intelligible to us only if we conceive these
atoms not as dead masses, but as living elementary particles endowed with the power of
attraction and repulsion. ‘Pleasure’ and ‘pain,’ and ‘love’ and ‘hate,’ as predicates of atoms
are only other expressions for this power of attraction and repulsion.
Although, however, monism is on the one hand for us an indispensable and fundamental
conception in science, and although, on the other hand, it strives to carry back all
phenomena, without exception, to the mechanism of the atom, we must nevertheless still
admit that as yet we are by no means in a position to form any satisfactory conception of
the exact nature of these atoms, and their relation to the general space-filling, universal
ether. Chemistry long ago succeeded in reducing all the various natural substances to
combinations of a relatively small number of elements; and the most recent advances of
that science have now made it in the highest degree probable that these elements or the (as
yet) irreducible primitive materials are themselves in turn only different combinations of a
varying number of atoms of one single original element. But in all this we have not as yet
obtained any further light as to the real nature of these original atoms or their primal
energies.
A number of the acutest thinkers have, so far in vain, endeavoured to grapple more
closely with this fundamental problem of the philosophy of nature, and to determine more
exactly the nature of atoms as well as their relation to the space-filling ether. And the idea
steadily gains ground that no such thing as empty space exists, and that everywhere the
primitive atoms of ponderable matter or heavy ‘mass’ are separated from each other by the
homogeneous ether which extends throughout all space. This extremely light and attenuated
(if not imponderable) ether causes, by its vibrations, all the phenomena of light and heat,
electricity and magnetism. We can imagine it either as a continuous substance occupying
the space between the mass-atoms, or as composed of separate particles; in the latter case
we might perhaps attribute to these ether-atoms an inherent power of repulsion in contrast
to the immanent attracting power of the heavy mass-atoms, and the whole mechanism of
cosmic life would then be reducible to the attraction of the latter and the repulsion of the
former. We might also place the ‘vibrations of the cosmic ether’ alongside of the ‘operation
of space in general,’ in the sense in which these words are used by Professor Schlesinger.
At any rate, theoretical physics has in recent years made an advance of fundamental
importance and widest reach in our knowledge of nature, in that it has come nearer to a
knowledge of this cosmic ether, and has forced the question of its essence, its structure, and
its motion into the foreground of monistic nature-philosophy. Only a few years ago the
cosmic ether was to the majority of scientists an imponderable something, of which, strictly
speaking, absolutely nothing was known, and which could be admitted provisionally only
as a precarious working hypothesis. All this was changed when Heinrich Hertz (1888)
yet, within this boundary, apply quite universally the ‘mechanical law of causality.’ The complicated
‘phenomena of mind,’ as they are called (more especially consciousness), fall under the ‘law of the
conservation of substance’ just as strictly as do the simpler mechanical processes of nature dealt with in
inorganic physics and chemistry. Compare note 16.
7
demonstrated the nature of electrical energy, by his beautiful experiments establishing the
conjecture of Faraday that light and heat, electricity and magnetism, are closely related
phenomena of one single set of forces, and depend on transverse vibrations of the ether.
Light itself—whatever else it be—is always and everywhere an electrical phenomenon. The
ether itself is no longer hypothetical; its existence can at any moment be demonstrated by
electrical and optical experiment. We know the length of the light wave and the electric
wave. Indeed, some physicists believe that they can even determine approximately the
density of ether. If by means of the airpump we remove from a bell-jar the atmospheric air
(except an insignificant residue), the quantity of light within it remains unchanged; it is the
vibrating ether we see.8 These advances in our knowledge of the ether mean an immense
gain for monistic philosophy. For they do away with the erroneous ideas of empty space
and actio in distans; the whole of infinite space, in so far as it is not occupied by massatoms (‘ponderable matter’), is filled by the ether. Our ideas of space and time are quite
other than those taught by Kant a hundred years ago; the ‘critical’ system of the great
Koenigsberg philosopher exhibits in this respect, as well as in his teleological view of the
organic world and in his metaphysics, dogmatic weaknesses of the most pronounced kind.9
8
In a thoughtful lecture on the relations between light and electricity at the sixty-second Congress of German
naturalists and physicians in Heidelberg in 1889, Heinrich Hertz explains the scope of his brilliant discovery:
‘Thus the domain of electricity extends over the whole of nature. It comes nearer to ourselves; we learn that
we actually possess an electric organ, the eye. Here we are brought face to face with the question as to
unmediated actio in distans. Is there such a thing? Not far off from this, in another direction, lies the question
of the nature of electricity. And immediately connected therewith arises the momentous and primary question
as to the nature of the ether, of the properties of the medium that fills all space, its structure, its rest or motion,
its infinitude or finitude. It becomes every day more manifest that this question rises above all others, that a
knowledge of what the ether is would reveal to us not only the nature of the old 'imponderables,' but also of
the old 'matter' itself and its most essential properties, weight and inertia. Modern physics is not far from the
question whether everything that exists is not created from the ether.’ This question is already being answered
in the affirmative by some monistic physicists, as, for example, by J. G. Vogt in his most suggestive work on
The Nature of Electricity and Magnetism, on The Basis of the Conception of a Single Substance (Leipsic,
1891). He regards the atoms of mass (the primal atoms of the kinetic theory of matter) as individualised
centres of concentration of the continuous substance that uninterruptedly fills all space; the mobile elastic part
of this substance between the atoms, and universally distributed, is—the ether. Georg Helm in Dresden, on
the basis of mathematico-physical experiments, had already at an earlier date arrived at the same conclusions;
in his treatise on ‘Influences at a Distance mediated by the Ether’ (Annalen der Physik und Chemie, 1881, Bd.
xiv.), he shows that it requires only the postulate of one particular kind of matter, the ether, to explain
influence at a distance and radiation; that is, as regards these phenomena, all the qualities ascribable to matter,
except that of motion, are of no account; in other words, that in thinking of the ether we simply require to
think of it as ‘the mobile.’
9
As recent German philosophy has in a large measure returned to Kant, and in some cases even deified as
‘infallible’ the great Koenigsberg philosopher, it may be well here to point out once more that his system of
critical philosophy is a mixture of monistic and dualistic ingredients. His critical principles of the theory of
knowledge will always remain of fundamental importance: his proof that we are unable to know the essential
and profoundest essence of substance, the ‘thing in itself’ (or ‘the combination of matter and energy’); that
our knowledge remains subjective in its nature; that it is conditioned by the organisation of our brain and
sensory organs, and can therefore only deal with the phenomena which our experience of the outer world
affords us. But within these ‘limits of human knowledge’ a positive monistic knowledge of nature is still
possible, in contrast to all dualistic and metaphysical fantasies. One such great fact of monistic knowledge
was the mechanical cosmogony of Kant and Laplace, the ‘Essay on the Constitution and Mechanical Origin of
the Universe, according to the Principles of Newton’ (1755). In the whole field of our knowledge of inorganic
nature, Kant held firmly to the monistic point of view, allowing mechanism alone as the real explanation of
the phenomena. In the science of organic nature also, on the other hand, he held monism to be valid indeed,
yet insufficient; here he considered it necessary to call in the aid of final as well as of efficient causes. (Cf. the
fifth lecture of my Natural History of Creation on ‘The Evolution-Theory of Kant and Lamarck’; also
Albrecht Rau's Kant und die Naturforschung: Eine Pruefung der Resultate des idealistischen Kritikismus
8
And religion itself, in its reasonable forms, can take over the ether theory as an article of
faith, bringing into contradistinction the mobile cosmic ether as creating divinity, and the
inert heavy mass as material of creation.[11] From this successfully scaled height of
monistic knowledge there open up before our joyously quickened spirit of research and
discovery new and surprising prospects, which promise to bring us still nearer to the
solution of the one great riddle of the world. What is the relation of this light mobile cosmic
ether to the heavy inert ‘mass,’ to the ponderable matter which we chemically investigate,
and which we can only think of as constituted of atoms? Our modern analytical chemistry
remains for the present at a standstill, in presence of some seventy irreducible elements, or
so-called primary substances. But the reciprocal relation of these elements, the affinity of
their combinations, their spectroscopic behaviour, and so forth, make it in the highest
degree probable that they are all merely historical products of an evolutionary process,
having their origin in various dispositions and combinations of a varying number of
original atoms.
To these original or mass-atoms—the ultimate discrete particles of inert ‘ponderable
matter’—we can with more or less probability ascribe a number of eternal and inalienable
fundamental attributes; they are probably everywhere in space, of like magnitude and
constitution. Although possessing a definite finite magnitude, they are, by virtue of their
very nature, indivisible. Their shape we may take to be spherical; they are inert (in the
physical sense), unchangeable, inelastic, and impenetrable by the ether. Apart from the
attribute of inertia, the most important characteristic of these ultimate atoms is their
chemical affinity—their tendency to apply themselves to one another and combine into
small groups in an orderly fashion. These fixed groups (fixed, that is to say, under the
present physical conditions of existence of the earth) of primitive atoms are the atoms of
the elements—the well-known ‘indivisible’ atoms of chemistry. The qualitative, and, so far
as our present empirical knowledge goes, unchangeable distinctions of our chemical
elements are therefore solely conditioned by the varying number and disposition of the
similar primitive atoms of which they are composed. Thus, for example, the atom of carbon
(the real ‘maker’ of the organic world) is in all probability a tetrahedron made up of four
primitive atoms.
After Mendelejeff and Lothar Meyer had discovered (1869) the ‘periodic law’ of the
chemical elements, and founded on it a ‘natural system’ of these elements, this important
advance in theoretical chemistry was subsequently put to profitable use by Gustav Wendt
from an evolutionary point of view. He endeavoured to show that the various elements are
products of evolution or of historically originating combinations of seven primary elements,
and that these last again are historical products of one single primitive element This
hypothetical original matter had been already designated by Crookes, in his Genesis of the
Elements, as primary material or protyl.10 The empirical proof of the existence of this
durch den realistischen Kosmos, vol. 2, 1886.) Once thus on the downgrade of dualistic teleology, Kant
afterwards arrived at his untenable metaphysical views of ‘God, Freedom, and Immortality.’ It is probable
that Kant would have escaped these errors if he had had a thorough anatomical and physiological training.
The natural sciences were, indeed, at that time truly in their infancy. I am firmly convinced that Kant's system
of critical philosophy would have turned out quite otherwise from what it was, and purely monistic, if he had
had at his disposal the then unsuspected treasures of empirical natural knowledge which we now possess.
10
The evidences, numerous and important, for the composite nature of our empirical elements, have lately
been compendiously discussed by Gustav Wendt in his treatise, Die Entwicklung der Elemente: Entwurf zu
einer biologischen Grundlage fur Chemie und Physik [I] (Berlin, 1891); compare also Wilhelm Freyer's Die
organischen Elemente und ihre Stellung im System [II] (Wiesbaden, 1891), Victor Meyer's Chemische
9
original matter lying at the foundation of all ponderable material is perhaps only a question
of time. Its discovery would probably realise the alchemists' hope of being able to produce
gold and silver artificially out of other elements. But then arises the other great question:
‘How is this primary mass related to the cosmic ether? Do these two original substances
stand in fundamental and eternal antithesis to one another? Or was it the mobile ether itself,
perhaps, that originally engendered the heavy mass?’11
In answer to this great and fundamental question, various physical hypotheses have been
put forward. But, like the various atomic theories of chemistry, they have not as yet been
clearly established, and the same appears to me to be the case also with the ingenious
hypothesis which the lecturer has unfolded to us with reference to the Influence of Space.
As he himself rightly says, in all these endeavours after a philosophy of nature we are still,
for the present, dealing with ‘scientific articles of faith,’ concerning the validity of which
different persons, according to their subjective judgment and stage of culture, may have
widely divergent views. I believe that the solution of these fundamental questions still lies
as yet beyond the limits of our knowledge of nature, and that we shall be obliged, for a
longtime yet to come, to content ourselves with an ‘Ignoramus’—if not even with an
‘Ignorabimus.’
The case is very different, however, if we turn from these atomistic element hypotheses
and direct our attention to the historical conditions of the evolution of the world, as these
have been revealed to us by the magnificent advances in our knowledge of nature which
have been made within the last thirty years. An immense new territory has here been
opened up to us in the realms of knowledge—a territory in which a series of most important
Probleme der Gegenwart [III] (Heidelberg, 1890), and W. Crookes's Genesis of the Elements. For the
different views as to the nature of the atom, see Philip Spiller on ‘The Doctrines of Atoms’ in Die Urkraft des
Weltalls nach ihrem Wesen und Wirken auf allen Naturgebieten [IV] (Berlin, 1886), (1. The philosophy of
nature; 2. The doctrine of the ether; 3. The ethical side of the science of nature). For the constitution of the
elements out of atoms, see A. Turner, Die Kraft und Masse im Raume [V] (Leipsic, 3rd ed., 1886), (1. On the
nature of matter and its relationships; 2. Atomic combinations; 3. The nature of the molecules and their
combinations. Theory of crystallisation).
[I] ‘The Development of the Elements: an Essay towards a Biological Basis for Chemistry and Physics.’
[II] ‘The Organic Elements and their Place in the System.’
[III] ‘Chemical Problems of the Day.’
[IV]‘The Primary Force of the Universe, its Nature and Action.’
[V] ‘Force and Matter in Space.’
11
The relation of the two fundamental constituents of the cosmos, ether and mass, may perhaps be made
apparent, in accordance with one out of many hypotheses, by the following, partly provisional, scheme.
10
problems, formerly held to be insoluble, has been answered in the most surprising
manner.12
Among the triumphs of the human mind the modern doctrine of evolution takes a
foremost place. Guessed at by Goethe a hundred years ago, but not expressed in definite
form until formulated by Lamarck in the beginning of the present century, it was at last,
thirty years ago, decisively established by Charles Darwin, his theory of selection filling up
the gap which Lamarck in his doctrine of the reciprocal influence of heredity and
adaptation had left open. We now definitely know that the organic world on our earth has
been as continuously developed, ‘in accordance with eternal iron laws,’ as Lyell had in
1830 shown to be the case for the inorganic frame of the earth itself; we know that the
innumerable varieties of animals and plants which during the course of millions of years
have peopled our planet are all simply branches of one single genealogical tree; we know
that the human race itself forms only one of the newest, highest, and most perfect offshoots
from the race of the Vertebrates.
An unbroken series of natural events, following an orderly course of evolution according
to fixed laws, now leads the reflecting human spirit through long aeons from a primeval
chaos to the present ‘order of the cosmos.’ At the outset there is nothing in infinite space
but mobile elastic ether, and innumerable similar separate particles—the primitive atoms—
scattered throughout it in the form of dust; perhaps these are themselves originally ‘points
of condensation’ of the vibrating ‘substance,’ the remainder of which constitutes the ether.
The atoms of our elements arise from the grouping together in definite numbers of the
primitive atoms or atoms of mass. As the Kant-Laplace nebular hypothesis has it, the
rotating heavenly bodies separate themselves out from that vibrating primeval cloud. A
single unit among many thousands of celestial bodies is our sun, with its planets, which
originated by being centrifugally thrown off from it. Our insignificant earth is a single
planet of our solar system; its entire individual life is a product of the sunlight. After the
glowing sphere of the earth has cooled down to a certain degree, drops of fluid water
precipitate themselves on the hardened crust of its surface—the first preliminary condition
of organic life. Carbon atoms begin their organism-engendering activity, and unite with the
other elements into plasma-combinations capable of growing. One small plasma-group
oversteps the limits of cohesion and individual growth; it falls asunder into two similar
halves. With this first moneron begins organic life and its most distinctive function,
heredity. In the homogeneous plasma of the monera, a firmer central nucleus is separated
from a softer outer mass; through this differentiation of nucleus and protoplasm arises the
first organic cell. For a long time our planet was inhabited solely by such Protista or single12
The fundamental importance of the modern doctrine of evolution, and of the monistic philosophy based
upon it, is clearly evidenced by the steady increase of its copious literature. I have cited the most important
treatises on this subject in the new (eighth) edition of my Natural History of Creation (1889). Compare,
specially, Carus Sterne (Ernst Krause), Werden und Vergehen: Eine Entwicklungsgeschichte des Naturganzen
in gemeinverstaendlicher Fassung [VI] (3rd ed., Berlin, 1886); Hugo Spitzer, Beitraege zur
Descendenztheorie und zur Methodologie der Naturwissenschaft (Graz, 1886); [VII] Albrecht Ran, Ludwig
Feuerbach's Philosophie der Naturforschung und die philosophische Kritik der Gegenwart (Leipsic, 1882);
[VIII] Hermann Wolff, Kosmos: Die Weltentwicklung nach monitisch-psychologischen Principien auf
Grundlage der exacten Naturforschung (Leipsic, 1890).[IX]
[VI] ‘Growth and Decay: a Popular History of the Development of the Cosmos.’
[VII] ‘Contributions towards a Theory of Descent, and towards a Methodology of the Sciences of Nature.’
[VIII] ‘Ludwig Feuerbach's Philosophy of Science, and the Philosophical Criticism of the Present Time.’
[IX] ‘Cosmos: The Development of the Cosmos according to Monistic Principles on the Basis of Exact
Science.’
11
celled primitive creatures. From coenobia or social unions of these afterwards arose the
lowest histones, multicellular plants and animals.
By the sure help of the three great empirical ‘records of creation,’ palaeontology,
comparative anatomy, and ontogeny, the history of descent now leads us on step by step
from the oldest Metazoa, the simplest pluricellular animals, up to man.13 At the lowest root
of the common genealogy of the Metazoa stand the Gastraeadae and Spongidae; their
whole body consists, in the simplest case, solely of a round digestive sac, the thin wall of
which is formed by two layers of cells—the two primitive germinal layers. A corresponding
germinal condition, the two-layered gastrula, occurs transitorily in the embryological
history of all the other Metazoa, from the lowest Cnidaria and Vermes up to man. From the
common stock of the Helminthes, or simple worms, there develop as independent main
branches the four separate stems of the Molluscs, Star-fishes, Arthropods, and Vertebrates.
It is only these last whose bodily structure and development in all essential respects
coincide with those of man. A long series of lower aquatic Vertebrates (lancelets, lampreys,
fishes) precedes the lungbreathing Amphibians, which appear for the first time in the
Carboniferous period. The Amphibians are followed in the Permian period by the first
Amniota, the oldest reptiles; from these develop later, in the Triassic period, the Birds on
the one hand, and the Mammals on the other. That man in his whole bodily frame is a true
mammal, becomes obvious as soon as the natural unity of this highest class of animals is
recognised. The simplest comparison must have convinced the unprejudiced observer of the
close constitutional relationship between man and the ape, which of all the Mammals
comes nearest him. Comparative anatomy, with its deeper vision, showed that all
differences in bodily structure between man and the Anthropoidea (gorilla, chimpanzee,
orang) are less important than the corresponding differences in bodily structure between
these anthropoid apes and the lower apes. The phylogenetic significance of this fact, first
emphasised by Huxley, is quite clear. The great question of the origin of the human race, or
of ‘man's place in Nature,’ the ‘question of all questions,’ was then scientifically answered:
‘Man is descended from a series of ape-like Mammals.’ The descent of man (anthropogeny)
discloses the long series of vertebrate ancestors, which preceded the late origin of this, its
most highly developed offshoot.6
The incalculable importance of the light cast over the whole field of human knowledge
of nature by these results is patent to everyone. They are destined every year increasingly to
manifest their transforming influence in all departments of knowledge, the more the
conviction of their irrefragable truth forces its way. And it is only the ignorant or narrowminded who can now doubt their truth. If, indeed, here and there, one of the older
naturalists still disputes, the foundation on which they rest, or demands proofs which are
wanting (as happened a few weeks ago on the part of a famous German pathologist at the
Anthropological Congress in Moscow), he only shows by this that he has remained a
stranger to the stupendous advances of recent biology, and above all of anthropogeny. The
whole literature of modern biology, the whole of our present zoology and botany,
13
The idea and the task of phylogeny, or the history of descent, I first defined in 1866, in the sixth book of my
General Morphology (vol 2 pp. 301-422), and the substance of this, as well as an account of its relation to
ontogeny or history of development, is set forth in a popular form in Part II. of my Natural History of
Creation (8th ed., Berlin, 1889). A special application of both these divisions of the history of evolution to
man, is attempted in my Anthropogenie (4th ed.), revised and enlarged, 1891: Part I. History of development.
Part II. History of descent.
12
morphology and physiology, anthropology and psychology, are pervaded and fertilised by
the theory of descent.14
Just as the natural doctrine of development on a monistic basis has cleared up and
elucidated the whole field of natural phenomena in their physical aspect, it has also
modified that of the phenomena of mind, which is inseparably connected with the other.
Our human body has been built up slowly and by degrees from a long series of vertebrate
ancestors, and this is also true of our soul; as a function of our brain it has gradually been
developed in reciprocal action and re-action with this its bodily organ. What we briefly
designate as the ‘human soul,’ is only the sum of our feeling, willing, and thinking—the
sum of those physiological functions whose elementary organs are constituted by the
microscopic ganglion-cells of our brain. Comparative anatomy and ontogeny show us how
the wonderful structure of this last, the organ of our human soul, has in the course of
millions of years been gradually built up from the brains of higher and lower vertebrates.
Comparative psychology teaches us how, hand in hand therewith, the soul itself, as function
of the brain, has been developed. The last-named science teaches us also that a primitive
form of soul-activity is already present even in the lowest animals, the single-celled
primitive animals, Infusoria and Rhizopoda. Every scientific man who has long observed
the life-activity of these single-celled Protista, is positively convinced that they also possess
a soul; that this ‘cell-soul’ also consists of a sum of sensations, perceptions, and volitions;
the feeling, thinking, and willing of our human soul differ from these only in degree. In like
manner there is present in the egg-cell (as potential energy) a hereditary cell-soul, out of
which man, like every other animal, is developed.15
The first task of a truly scientific psychology will therefore be, not, as hitherto, idle
speculation about an independent immaterial soul-existence and its puzzling temporary
connection with the animal body, but rather the comparative investigation of the organs of
the soul and the experimental examination of their psychical functions. For scientific
psychology is a part of physiology, the doctrine of the functions and the life-activities of
organisms. The psychology and psychiatry of the future, like the physiology and pathology
of to-day, must take the form of a cellular study, and in the first instance investigate the
soul-functions of the cells. Max Verworn, in his fine Psycho-physiological Protistastudies,
has lately shown us what important disclosures such a cellular psychology can make, even
14
Since the death of Louis Agassiz (1873), Rudolf Virchow is regarded as the sole noteworthy opponent of
Darwinism and the theory of descent; he never misses an opportunity (as recently in Moscow) of opposing it
as ‘unproved hypothesis.’ See as to this my pamphlet, Freedom in Science and in Teaching, a reply to
Virchow's address at Munich on ‘Freedom of Science in the Modern State’ (Stuttgart, 1878; Eng. tr., 1892).
15
See on this my paper on ‘Cell-souls and Soul-cells,’ in the Deutsche Rundschau (July 1878), reprinted in
Part 1, of Collected Popular Lectures; also ‘The Cell-soul and Cellular Psychology’ in my discourse on
Freedom in Science and Teaching (Stuttgart, 1878; Eng. tr., 1892, p. 46); Natural History of Creation (8th
ed., pp. 444, 777); and Descent of Man (4th ed., pp. 128, 147). See also, Max Verworn, Psychophysiologische Protisten-Studien (Jena, 1889), and Paul Carus, The Soul of Man: An Investigation of the
Facts of Physiological and Experimental Psychology (Chicago, 1891). Among recent attempts to reform
psychology on the basis of evolutionary doctrine in a monistic sense, special mention must be made of Georg
Heinrich Schneider's Der thierische Wille: Systematische Darstellung und Erklaerung der thierischen Triebe
und deren Entstehung, Entwickelung und Verbreitung im Thierreiche als Grundlage zu einer vergleichenden
Willenslehre [X] (Leipsic, 1880). Compare also his supplementary work, entitled Der menschliche Wille vom
Standpunkte der neuen Entwickelungstheorie [XI] (1882); also the Psychology of Herbert Spencer and the
new edition of Wilhelm Wundt's Menschen- und Thierseele [XII] (Leipsic, 1892). [X] ‘Will in the Lower
Animals: a Systematic Exposition and Explanation of Animal Instincts, and their Origin, Development, and
Difference in the Animal Kingdom, as Basis of a Comparative Doctrine of Volition.’ [XI] ‘The Human Will
from the Standpoint of the Modern Theory of Evolution.’ [XII] ‘Soul in Man and Brute.’
13
in dealing with the lowest grades of organic life, in the single-celled Protista (especially
Rhizopoda and Infusoria).
These same main divisions of soul-activity, which are to be met with in the single-celled
organism,—the phenomena of irritability, sensation, and motion,—can be shown to exist in
all multicellular organisms as functions of the cells of which their bodies are composed. In
the lowest Metazoa, the invertebrate sponges and polyps, there are, just as in plants, no
special soul-organs developed, and all the cells of the body participate more or less in the
‘soul-life.’ It is only in the higher animals that the soul-life is found to be localised and
connected with special organs. As a consequence of division of labour, there have here
been developed various sense-organs as organs of specific sensibility, muscles as organs of
motion and volition, nerve-centres or ganglia as central co-ordinating and regulating
organs. In the most highly developed families of the animal kingdom, these last come more
and more into the foreground as independent soul-organs. In correspondence with the
extraordinarily complicated structure of their central nervous system (the brain with its
wonderful complex of ganglion-cells and nerve-fibres), the many-sided activity of such
animals attains a wonderful degree of development.
It is only in these most highly-developed groups of the animal kingdom that we can with
certainty establish the existence of those most perfect operations of the central nervous
system, which we designate as consciousness. As we know, it is precisely this highest
brain-function that still continues to be looked upon as a completely enigmatic
phenomenon, and as the best proof for the immaterial existence of an immortal soul. It is
usual at the same time to appeal to Du Bois-Reymond's well-known ‘Ignorabimus address
on the Boundaries of Natural Knowledge’ (1872). It was by a peculiar irony of fate that the
famous lecturer of the Berlin Academy of Science, in this much-discussed address of
twenty years ago, should be representing consciousness as an incomprehensible marvel,
and as presenting an insuperable barrier to further advances of knowledge, at the very
moment that David Friedrich Strauss, the greatest theologian of our century, was showing it
to be the opposite. The clear-sighted author of The Old Faith and the New had already
clearly perceived that the soul-activities of man, and therefore also his consciousness, as
functions of the central nervous system, all spring from a common source, and, from a
monistic point of view, come under the same category. The ‘exact’ Berlin physiologist shut
this knowledge out from his mind, and, with a short-sightedness almost inconceivable,
placed this special neurological question alongside of the one great ‘world-riddle,’ the
fundamental question of substance, the general question of the connection between matter
and energy.16+
16
The antiquated view of Du Bois-Reymond (1872)—that human consciousness is an unsoluble ‘worldriddle,’ a transcendent phenomenon in essential antithesis to all other natural phenomena—continues to be
upheld in numerous writings. It is chiefly on this that the dualistic view of the world founds its assertion, that
man is an altogether peculiar being, and that his personal soul is immortal; and this is the reason why the
‘Leipsic ignorabimus-speech’ of Du Bois-Reymond has for twenty years been prized as a defence by all
representatives of the mythological view of the world, and extolled as a refutation of ‘monistic dogma.’ The
closing word of the discourse, ‘ignorabimus,’ was translated as a present, and this ‘ignoramus’ taken to mean
that ‘we know nothing at all’; or, even worse, that ‘we can never come to clearness about anything, and any
further talk about the matter is idle.’ The famous ‘ignorabimus’ address remains certainly an important
rhetorical work of art; it is a ‘beautiful sermon,’ characterised by its highly-finished form and its surprising
variety of philosophico-scientific pictures. It is well known, however, that the majority (and especially
women) judge a ‘beautiful sermon’ not according to the value of the thoughts embodied in it, but according to
its excellence as an aesthetical entertainment. While Du Bois treats his audience at great length to
disquisitions on the wondrous performances of the genius of Laplace, he afterwards glides over, the most
14
As I long ago pointed out, these two great questions are not two separate ‘world-riddles.’
The neurological problem of consciousness is only a special case of the all comprehending
cosmological problem, the question of substance. ‘If we understood the nature of matter
and energy, we should also understand how the substance underlying them can under
certain conditions feel, desire, and think.’* Consciousness, like feeling and willing, among
the higher animals is a mechanical work of the ganglion-cells, and as such must be carried
back to chemical and physical events in the plasma of these. And by the employment of the
genetic and comparative method we reach the conviction that consciousness, and
consequently reason also, is not a brain-function exclusively peculiar to man; it occurs also
in many of the higher animals, not in Vertebrates only, but even in Articulates. Only in
degree, through a higher stage of cultivation, does the consciousness of man differ from
that of the more perfect lower animals, and the same is true of all other activities of the
human soul.
By these and other results of comparative physiology our whole psychology is placed on
a new and firm monistic basis. The older mystical conception of the soul, as we find it
amongst primitive peoples, but also in the systems of the dualistic philosophers of to-day, is
refuted by them. According to these systems, the soul of man (and of the higher animals) is
a separate entity, which inhabits and rules the body only during its individual life, but
leaves it at death. The widespread ‘piano-theory’ (Claviertheorie) compares the ‘immortal
soul’ to a pianist who executes an interesting piece—the individual life—on the instrument
of the mortal body, but at death withdraws into the other world. This ‘immortal soul’ is
usually represented as an immaterial being; but in fact it is really thought of as quite
material, only as a finer invisible being, aerial or gaseous, or as resembling the mobile,
light, and thin substance of the ether, as conceived by modern physics. The same is true
also for most of the conceptions which rude primitive peoples and the uneducated classes
among the civilised races have, for thousands of years, cherished as to spectral ‘ghosts’ and
‘gods.’ Serious reflection on the matter shows that here—as in modern spiritualism—it is
not with really immaterial beings, but with gaseous, invisible bodies, that we are dealing.
And further, we are utterly incapable of imagining a truly immaterial being. As Goethe
clearly said, ‘matter can never exist or act apart from spirit, neither can spirit apart from
matter.’
As regards immortality, it is well known that this important idea is interpreted and
applied in a great variety of ways. It is often made a reproach against our Monism that it
altogether denies immortality; this, however, is erroneous. Rather do we hold it, in a strictly
scientific sense, as an indispensable fundamental conception of our monistic philosophy of
nature. Immortality in a scientific sense is conservation of substance, therefore the same as
conservation of energy as defined by physics, or conservation of matter as defined by
chemistry. The cosmos as a whole is immortal. It is just as inconceivable that any of the
important part of his subject in eleven short lines, and makes not the slightest further attempt to solve the
main question he has to deal with—as to whether the world is really ‘doubly incomprehensible.’ For my own
part, on the contrary, I have already repeatedly sought to show that the two limits to our knowledge of nature
are one and the same; the fact of consciousness and the relation of consciousness to the brain are to us not
less, but neither are they more, puzzling, than the fact of seeing and hearing, than the fact of gravitation, than
the connection between matter and energy. Compare my discourse on Freedom in Science and Teaching
(1878), pp. 78, 82, etc.
+
Haeckel misunderstands Du Bois-Reymond (personal rivalry?)
*
GS: one could rewrite this as ‘If we understood the nature of matter/energy, we should also understand how
it can [± under certain conditions] feel, desire, and think.’
15
atoms of our brain or of the energies of our spirit should vanish out of the world, as that any
other particle of matter or energy could do so. At our death there disappears only the
individual form in which the nerve-substance was fashioned, and the personal ‘soul’ which
represented the work performed by this. The complicated chemical combinations of that
nervous mass pass over into other combinations by decomposition, and the kinetic energy
produced by them is transformed into other forms of motion.
‘Imperial Caesar, dead and turned to clay,
Might stop a hole to keep the wind away.
O that that earth which kept the world in awe
Should patch a wall to expel the winter's flaw.’
On the other hand, the conception of a personal immortality cannot be maintained. If this
idea is still widely held, the fact is to be explained by the physical law of inertia; for the
property of persistence in a state of rest exercises its influence in the region of the ganglioncells of the brain, as well as in all other natural bodies. Traditional ideas handed down
through many generations are maintained with the greatest tenacity by the human brain,
especially if, in early youth, they have been instilled into the childish understanding as
indisputable dogmas. Such hereditary articles of faith take root all the more firmly, the
further they are removed from a rational knowledge of nature, and enveloped in the
mysterious mantle of mythological poesy. In the case of the dogma of personal immortality,
there comes into play also the interest which man fancies himself to have in his individual
future existence after death, and the vain hope that in a blessed world to come there is
treasured up for him a compensation for the disappointed hopes and the many sorrows of
his earthly life. [xxx]
It is often asserted by the numerous advocates of personal immortality that this dogma is
an innate one, common to all rational men, and that it is taught in all the more perfect forms
of religion. But this is not correct. Neither Buddhism nor the religion of Moses originally
contained the dogma of personal immortality, and just as little did the majority of educated
people of classical antiquity believe it, at any rate during the highest period of Greek
culture. The monistic philosophy of that time, which, five hundred years before our era, had
reached speculative heights so remarkable, knew nothing of any such dogma. It was
through Plato and Christ that it received its further elaboration, until, in the Middle Ages, it
was so universally accepted, that only now and then did some bold thinker dare openly to
gainsay it. The idea that a conviction of personal immortality has a specially ennobling
influence on the moral nature of man, is not confirmed by the gruesome history of
mediaeval morals, and as little by the psychology of primitive peoples.17
17
Perhaps in no ecclesiastical article of faith is the gross materialistic conception of Christian dogma so
evident as in the cherished doctrine of personal immortality, and that of ‘the resurrection of the body,’
associated with it. As to this, Savage, in his excellent work on Religion in the Light of the Darwinian
Doctrine, has well remarked: ‘One of the standing accusations of the Church against science is that it is
materialistic. On this I would like to point out, in passing, that the whole Church-conception concerning a
future life has always been, and still is, the purest materialism. It is represented that the material body is to
rise again, and inhabit a material heaven.’ Compare also Ludwig Buchner, Das zunkuenftige Leben und die
moderne Wissenschaft (Leipsic, 1889); Lester Ward, ‘Causes of Belief in Immortality’ (The Forum, vol.
VIII., September 1889); and Paul Carus, The Soul of Man: an Investigation of the Facts of Physiological and
Experimental Psychology (Chicago, 1891). Carus aptly points out the analogy between the ancient and the
modern ideas with respect to light, and with respect to the soul. Just as formerly the luminous flame was
16
If any antiquated school of purely speculative psychology still continues to uphold this
irrational dogma, the fact can only be regarded as a deplorable anachronism. Sixty years
ago such a doctrine was excusable, for then nothing was accurately known either of the
finer structure of the brain, or of the physiological functions of its separate parts; its
elementary organs, the microscopic ganglion-cells, were almost unknown, as was also the
cell-soul of the Protista; very imperfect ideas were held as to ontogenetic development, and
as to phylogenetic there were none at all.
This has all been completely changed in the course of the last half-century. Modern
physiology has already to a great extent demonstrated the localisation of the various
activities of mind, and their connection with definite parts of the brain; psychiatry has
shown that those psychical processes are disturbed or destroyed if these parts of the brain
become diseased or degenerate. Histology has revealed to us the extremely complicated
structure and arrangement of the ganglion-cells. But, for the settlement of this momentous
question, the discoveries of the last ten years with regard to the more minute occurrences in
the process of fertilisation are of decisive importance. We now know that this process
essentially consists simply in the copulation or fusion of two microscopical cells, the
female egg-cell and the male sperm-cell. The fusion of the nuclei of these two sexual cells
indicates with the utmost precision the exact moment at which the new human individual
arises. The newly-formed parent-cell, or fertilised egg-cell, contains potentially, in their
rudiments, all the bodily and mental characteristics which the child inherits from both
parents. It is clearly against reason to assume an eternal and unending life for an individual
phenomenon whose beginning in time we can determine to a hair's breadth, by direct
observation. Judging of human spiritual life from a rational point of view, we can as little
think of our individual soul as separated from our brain, as we can conceive the voluntary
motion of our arm apart from the contraction of its muscles, or the circulation of our blood
apart from the action of the heart.
Against this strictly physiological conception, as against our whole monistic view of the
relations of energy and matter, of soul and substance, the reproach of ‘materialism’
continues to be raised. I have repeatedly before now pointed out that this is an ambiguous
party word which conveys absolutely nothing; its apparent opposite, ‘spiritualism,’ could
quite easily be substituted for it. Every critical thinker, who is familiar with the history of
philosophy, knows that, as systems change, such words assume the most varied meanings,
In addition to this, the word ‘materialism’ has the disadvantage of being liable to continual
confusion between its theoretical and practical meanings, which two are totally distinct.
Our conception of Monism, or the unity-philosophy, on the contrary, is clear and
unambiguous; for it an immaterial living spirit is just as unthinkable as a dead, spiritless
material; the two are inseparably combined in every atom. The opposed conception of
dualism (or even pluralism in other anti-monistic systems) regards spirit and material,
energy and matter, as two essentially different substances; but not a single empirical proof
can be adduced to show that either of these can exist or become perceptible to us by itself
alone.
explained by means of a special fiery matter (phlogiston), so the thinking soul was explained by the
hypothesis of a peculiar gaseous soul-substance. We now know that the light of the flame is a sum of electric
vibrations of the ether, and the soul a sum of plasma-movements in the ganglion-cells. As compared with this
scientific conception, the doctrine of immortality of scholastic psychology has about the same value as the
materialistic conceptions of the Red Indian about a future life in Schiller's ‘Nadowessian Death-Song.’
17
In thus shortly indicating the far-reaching psychological consequences of the monistic
doctrine of evolution, I trench at the same time upon a most important field, to which our
lecturer in his address has more than once alluded—that of religion and the belief in God
connected therewith. I am at one with him in the conviction that the formation of clear
philosophical conceptions upon these fundamental matters of belief is of the highest
importance, and I would therefore crave the permission of this assembly briefly to lay
before it on this occasion a frank confession of faith. This monistic confession has the
greater claim to an unprejudiced consideration, in that it is shared, I am firmly convinced,
by at least nine-tenths of the men of science now living; indeed, I believe, by all men of
science in whom the following four conditions are realised: (1) Sufficient acquaintance
with the various departments of natural science, and in particular with the modern doctrine
of evolution; (2) Sufficient acuteness and clearness of judgment to draw, by induction and
deduction, the necessary logical consequences that flow from such empirical knowledge;
(3) Sufficient moral courage to maintain the monistic knowledge, so gained, against the
attacks of hostile dualistic and pluralistic systems; and (4) Sufficient strength of mind to
free himself, by sound, independent reasoning, from dominant religious prejudices, and
especially from those irrational dogmas which have been firmly lodged in our minds from
earliest youth as indisputable revelations.
If from this unprejudiced point of view of the thinker, we compare the numerous
religions of the various races of mankind, we shall be compelled, in the first instance, to put
aside as untenable all those conceptions which stand in irreconcilable contradiction to those
principles of our empirical knowledge of nature which are now clearly discerned and
established by critical reasoning. We can thus at once set aside all mythological stories, all
‘miracles,’ and so-called ‘revelations,’ for which it is claimed that they have come to us in
some supernatural way. All such mystical teachings are irrational, inasmuch as they are
confirmed by no actual experience, but, on the contrary, are irreconcilable with the known
facts which have been confirmed to us by a rational investigation of nature.
This is true alike of Christian and Mosaic, of Mohammedan and Indian legends. If now
we thus lay aside the whole mass of mystical dogmas and transcendental revelations, there
is left behind, as the precious and priceless kernel of true religion, the purified ethic that
rests on rational anthropology.18
Among the numerous and varied forms of religion which, in the course of the past ten
thousand years and more, have been evolved from the crudest prehistoric beginnings, the
foremost rank undoubtedly belongs to those two forms which still continue to be the most
widely accepted among civilised races—the older Buddhism and the younger Christianity.
18
All Ethic, the theoretical as well as the practical doctrine of morals, as a ‘science of law’
(Normwissenschaft), stands in immediate connection with the view that is taken of the world
(Weltanschauung), and consequently with religion. This position I regard as exceedingly important, and have
recently upheld in a paper on ‘Ethik und Weltanschauung,’ in opposition to the ‘Society for Ethical Culture’
lately founded in Berlin, which would teach and promote ethics without reference to any view of the world or
to religion. (Compare the new weekly journal, Die Zukunft, edited by Maximilian Harden, Berlin, 1892, Nos.
V.-VII.). Just as I take the monistic to be the only rational basis for all science, I claim the same also for
ethics. On this subject compare especially the ethical writings of Herbert Spencer and those of B. von
Carneri—Sittlichkeit und Darwinismus (1871); Entwickelung und Glueckseligkeit (1886); and more
particularly, the latest of all, Der moderne Mensch (Bonn, 1891); further, Wilhelm Streeker, Welt und
Menschheit (Leipsic, 1892); Harald Hoeffding, Die Grundlage der humanen Ethik (Bonn, 1880); and the
recent large work of Wilhelm Wundt, Ethik, eine Untersuchung der Thatsachen und Gesetze des sittlichen
Lebens (Stuttgart, 2nd ed., 1892).
18
The two have very many features in common, alike in their mythology and in their ethics;
indeed, a considerable part of Christianity has come directly from Indian Buddhism, just as
another part is drawn from the Mosaic and Platonic systems. But, looked at from the point
of view of our present stage of culture, the ethic of Christianity appears to us much more
perfect and pure than that of any other religion. We must, it is true, hasten to add that it is
exactly the weightiest and noblest principles of Christian ethic—brotherly love, fidelity to
duty, love of truth, obedience to law—that are by no means peculiar to the Christian faith as
such, but are of much older origin. Comparative psychology proves that these ethical
principles were more or less recognised and practised by much older civilised races
thousands of years before Christ.
Love remains the supreme moral law of rational religion, the love, that is to say, that
holds the balance between egoism and altruism, between self-love and love of others. ‘Do
to others as you would they should do to you.’ This natural and highest command had been
taught and followed thousands of years before Christ said: ‘Thou shalt love thy neighbour
as thyself.’ In the human family this maxim has always been accepted as self-evident; as
ethical instinct it was an inheritance derived from our animal ancestors. It had already
found a place among the herds of Apes and other social Mammals; in a similar manner, but
with a wider scope, it was already present in the most primitive communities and among
the hordes of the least advanced savages. Brotherly love—mutual support, succour,
protection, and the like—-had already made its appearance among gregarious animals as a
social duty; for without it the continued existence of such societies is impossible. Although
at a later period, in the case of man, these moral foundations of society came to be much
more highly developed, their oldest prehistoric source, as Darwin has shown, is to be
sought in the social instincts of animals. Among the higher Vertebrates (dogs, horses,
elephants, etc.), as among the higher Articulates (ants, bees, termites, etc.) also, the
development of social relations and duties is the indispensable condition of their living
together in orderly societies. Such societies have for man also been the most important
instrument of intellectual and moral progress.
Beyond all doubt the present degree of human culture owes in great part its perfection to
the propagation of the Christian system of morals and its ennobling influence, although the
great value of this has been impaired, often in the most deplorable manner, by its
association with untenable myths and so-called ‘revelations.’ How little these last
contribute to the perfection of the first, can be seen from the acknowledged historical fact
that it is just orthodoxy and the hierarchical system based on it (especially that of the
Papacy) that has least of all striven to fulfil the precepts of Christian morality; the more
loudly they preach it in theory, the less do they themselves fulfil its commands in practice.
It is, moreover, to be borne in mind that another and very considerable portion of our
modern culture and morality has been developed quite independently of Christianity,
mainly through continual study of the highly-elaborated mental treasures of classical
antiquity. The thorough study of Greek and Roman classics has at least contributed much
more to it than that of the Christian Church fathers. To this we must now add, in our own
century (rightly called the ‘century of the natural sciences’), the immense advance in the
higher culture which we owe to a purified knowledge of nature and to the monistic
philosophy founded upon this. That these must also exercise an advancing and ennobling
influence cannot be doubted, and has already been shown by many eminent authors
(Spencer, Carneri, and others) in the course of the last thirty years.18
Against this monistic ethic founded on a rational knowledge of nature, it has been
objected that it is fitted to undermine existing civilisation, and especially that it encourages
19
the subversive aims of social democracy. This reproach is wholly unjustified. The
application of philosophical principles to the practical conditions of life, and in particular to
social and political questions, can be made in the most various ways. Political ‘freethinking,’ so called, has nothing whatever to do with the ‘freedom of thought’ of our
monistic natural religion. Moreover, I am convinced that the rational morality of monistic
religion is in no way contrary to the good and truly valuable elements of the Christian ethic,
but is destined in conjunction with these to promote the true progress of humanity in the
future.
With Christian mythology and the special form of theistic belief associated with it the
case is different. In so far as that belief involves the notion of a ‘personal God,’ it has been
rendered quite untenable by the recent advances of monistic science. But, more than this, it
was shown more than two thousand years ago, by eminent exponents of the monistic
philosophy, that the conception of a personal God, creator and ruler of the world, does not
give the slightest help toward a truly rational view of the world. For even if the question of
‘creation,’ in the ordinary and trivial sense of the term, be answered by referring it to the
miraculous agency of a creator working according to plan apart from the world, there
immediately arises upon that the new inquiry: ‘Whence comes this personal God? What
was He doing before creation? And whence did He derive the material for it?’ and such like
questions. The antiquated conception of an anthropomorphic personal God is destined,
before the present century is ended, to drop out of currency throughout the entire domain of
truly scientific philosophy; the corresponding conception of a personal devil—even as late
as last century connected with the former and very generally accepted—has already been
given up once for all by all persons of education.
Let it be noted, however, in passing, that the amphitheism which believes in God and
devil alike is much more compatible with a rational explanation of the world than pure
monotheism. The purest form of this is perhaps the amphitheism of the Zend religion of
Persia, which Zoroaster (or Zarathustra, the ‘Golden Star’) founded two thousand years
before Christ. Here Ormuzd, the god of light and goodness, stands everywhere in conflict
with Ahriman, the god of darkness and evil. The continual conflict between a good and an
evil principle was personified in a similar manner in the mythology of many other
amphitheistic religions: in the old Egyptian, the good Osiris was at war with the evil
Typhon; in the old Indian, Vishnu the sustainer with Siva the destroyer, and so forth.
If we really must retain the conception of a personal God as the key to our view of the
universe, then this amphitheism can explain the sorrows and defects of this world very
simply, as being the work of the evil principle or devil. Pure monotheism, on the contrary,
as represented in the religions of Moses and Mohammed in their original form, has no
rational explanation of these to offer. If their ‘one God’ is really the absolutely good,
perfect being they proclaim, then the world which he has created must also be perfect. An
organic world so imperfect and full of sorrows as exists on this earth he could not possibly
have contrived.
These considerations gain in force when we advance to the deeper knowledge of nature
acquired by modern biology; here it was Darwin, especially, who thirty-three years ago
opened our eyes by his doctrine of the struggle for existence, and his theory of selection
founded upon it. We now know that the whole of organic nature on our planet exists only
by a relentless war of all against all. Thousands of animals and plants must daily perish in
every part of the earth, in order that a few chosen individuals may continue to subsist and to
enjoy life. But even the existence of these favoured few is a continual conflict with
20
threatening dangers of every kind. Thousands of hopeful germs perish uselessly every
minute. The raging war of interests in human society is only a feeble picture of the
unceasing and terrible war of existence which reigns throughout the whole of the living
world. The beautiful dream of God's goodness and wisdom in nature, to which as children
we listened so devoutly fifty years ago, no longer finds credit now—at least among
educated people who think. It has disappeared before our deeper acquaintance with the
mutual relations of organisms, the advancement of oecology and sociology, and our
knowledge of parasite life and pathology.
All these sad but insuperable facts—truly the dark side of nature—are made intelligible
to religious faith by amphitheism; they are the ‘works of the devil,’ who opposes and
disturbs the perfect moral order in the world of the ‘good God.’ For pure monotheism
which knows only one God, one perfect highest being, they remain unintelligible. If, with a
monotheistic creed, any one still continues to talk of the moral order of the world, he in so
doing shuts his eyes to the undeniable facts of history, both natural and civil.
In view of these considerations, it is hard to understand how the large majority of the socalled educated classes can persevere, on the one hand, in declaring belief in a personal
God to be an indispensable principle of religion, and, on the other hand, in at the same time
rejecting the belief in a personal devil as an exploded superstition of the Middle Ages. This
inconsistency on the part of educated Christians is all the more incomprehensible and
censurable, inasmuch as both dogmas in equal degree form an integral part of the Christian
creed. The personal devil, as ‘Satan,’ ‘the Tempter,’ ‘the Destroyer,’ and so forth,
undeniably plays a most important part in the New Testament, though not met with in the
earlier portions of the Old. Our great reformer, Martin Luther himself, who ‘sent to the
devil’ so many antiquated dogmas, was unable to rid himself of the conviction of the real
existence and personal enmity of Beelzebub; we have only to think of the historical inkspot at Wartburg! Moreover, our Christian art, in many thousands of paintings and other
representations, has exhibited Satan in corporeal form just as realistically as it has the three
‘Divine Persons,’ about whose ‘hypostatical union’ human reason has for eighteen hundred
years been tormenting itself in vain. The deep impression made by such concrete
representations, a million times repeated, especially on childish understandings, is usually
under-estimated as to its tremendous influence; to it certainly is in large measure to be
attributed the fact that irrational myths of such a kind, under the mask of ‘doctrines of
faith,’ continue to hold their ground in spite of all protests of reason.
Liberal-minded Christian theologians have, it is true, often sought to eliminate the
personal devil from Christian teaching, representing him as merely the personification of
falsehood, the spirit of evil. But with equal right we must in that case substitute for a
personal God the personified idea of truth, the Spirit of Goodness. To such a representation
no objection can be made; rather do we recognise in it a bridge connecting the dim
wonderland of religious poesy with the luminous realms of clear scientific knowledge.
The monistic idea of God, which alone is compatible with our present knowledge of
nature, recognises the divine spirit in all things. It can never recognise in God a ‘personal
being,’ or, in other words, an individual of limited extension in space, or even of human
form. God is everywhere. As Giordano Bruno has it: ‘There is one spirit in all things, and
nobody is so small that it does not contain a part of the divine substance whereby it is
animated.’ Every atom is thus animated, and so is the ether; we might, therefore, represent
God as the infinite sum of all natural forces, the sum of all atomic forces and all ethervibrations. It comes virtually to the same thing when (as was done here by a speaker on a
former occasion) God is defined as ‘the supreme law of the universe,’ and the latter is
21
represented as the ‘working of universal space.’ In this most important article of belief it
matters not as to the name but as to the unity of the underlying idea; the unity of God and
the world; of spirit and nature. On the other hand, ‘homotheism,’ the anthropomorphic
representation of God, degrades this loftiest cosmic idea to that of a ‘gaseous vertebrate.’19
Of the various systems of pantheism which for long have given expression more or less
clearly to the monistic conception of God, the most perfect is certainly that of Spinoza. To
this system, as is well known, Goethe also paid the tribute of his highest admiration and
approval. Of other eminent men who have given a similar pantheistic form to their natural
religion, we shall here mention only two of the greatest poets and students of man,
Shakespeare and Lessing; two of the greatest German rulers, Frederick II of Hohenstaufen
and Frederick II of Hohenzollern; two of the greatest scientists, Laplace and Darwin. In
adding our own pantheistic confession to that of these great and untrammelled spirits, let it
only be noted further, that it has received an empirical confirmation, never before imagined,
through the wonderful advances of natural knowledge within the last thirty years.
The charge of atheism which still continues to be levelled against our pantheism, and
against the monism which lies at its root, no longer finds a response among the really
educated classes of the present day. It is true that not so very long ago the German Imperial
Chancellor, in the Prussian Chamber of Deputies, found it in him to put forward such an
alternative as this: ‘Either the Christian or the atheistic view of the world’; this in the
defence of a most objectionable law, designed to hand over our school training, tied hand
and foot, to the papal hierarchy. The vast distance which separates the last-named
degenerate outgrowth of the Christian religion from pure primitive Christianity is not
greater than that which separates those mediaeval alternatives from the cultured religious
consciousness of the present day. To one who regards as true exercises of Christian religion
the adoration of old clothes and wax dolls, or the thoughtless repetition of masses or
rosaries, who believes in wonder-working relics, and purchases pardon for his sins by
means of indulgence-money or Peter's pence, we willingly concede the claim to possess the
‘only saving religion’; but with such fetish-worshippers we will willingly submit to be
ranked as ‘atheists.’
In like case with the charge of atheism and irreligion are those so often heard against
monism, that it destroys the poetry of life and fails to satisfy the spiritual wants of human
nature; we are told, in particular, that aesthetics—certainly a most important department
both in theoretical philosophy and in practical life—is prejudiced by a monistic philosophy.
But David Friedrich Strauss, one of our subtlest exponents of aesthetics and also one of our
noblest writers, has already refuted such a charge; and shown how, on the contrary, the care
for poetry and the cultivation of the beautiful are in the ‘new faith’ called upon to play a
still greater part than ever. My present hearers, at once investigators and lovers of nature,
do not need to be told that every new insight which we obtain into the secrets of nature at
19
Under the term homotheism (or anthropomorphism) we include all the various forms of religious belief
which ascribe to a personal God purely human characteristics. However variously these anthropomorphic
ideas may have shaped themselves in dualistic and pluralistic religions, all in common retain the unworthy
conception that God (Theos) and man (homo) are organised similarly and according to the same type
(homotype). In the region of poetry such personifications are both pleasing and legitimate. In the region of
science they are quite inadmissible; they are doubly objectionable now that we know that only in late Tertiary
times was man developed from pithecoid mammals. Every religious dogma which represents God as a ‘spirit’
in human form, degrades Him to a ‘gaseous vertebrate’ (General Morphology, 1866; Chap, xxx., God in
Nature). The expression ‘homotheism’ is ambiguous and etymologically objectionable, but more practical
than the cumbersome word ‘Anthropotheism.’
22
the same time also kindles our souls, affords new material for imagination to work on, and
enlarges our perception of the beautiful. To convince ourselves how closely all these
noblest spiritual activities of man hang together, how intimately the knowledge of truth is
bound up with the love of goodness and veneration of the beautiful, it will be enough to
mention a single name, Germany's greatest genius—Wolfgang Goethe.
If the perception of the aesthetic significance of our monistic nature-religion, as well as
of its ethical value, has hitherto so little pervaded the educated classes, this is due chiefly to
the defects of our school training. It is true that in the course of the last few decades an
infinite deal has been spoken and written about school reform and the principles of
education; but of any real progress there is as yet but little trace. Here also reigns the
physical law of inertia; here also—and more especially in German schools—the
scholasticism of the Middle Ages exhibits a power of inertia, against which any rational
reform of education must laboriously contest every inch of ground. In this important
department also, a department on which hangs the weal or woe of future generations,
matters will not improve till the monistic doctrine of nature is accepted as the essential and
sure foundation.
The school of the twentieth century, flourishing anew on this firm ground, shall have to
unfold to the rising youth not only the wonderful truths of the evolution of the cosmos, but
also the inexhaustible treasures of beauty lying everywhere hidden therein. Whether we
marvel at the majesty of the lofty mountains or the magic world of the sea, whether with the
telescope we explore the infinitely great wonders of the starry heaven, or with the
microscope the yet more surprising wonders of a life infinitely small, everywhere does
Divine Nature open up to us an inexhaustible fountain of aesthetic enjoyment. Blind and
insensible have the great majority of mankind hitherto wandered through this glorious
wonderland of a world; a sickly and unnatural theology has made it repulsive as a ‘vale of
tears.’ But now, at last, it is given to the mightily advancing human mind to have its eyes
opened; it is given to it to show that a true knowledge of nature affords full satisfaction and
inexhaustible nourishment not only for its searching understanding, but also for its yearning
spirit.
Monistic investigation of nature as knowledge of the true, monistic ethic as training for
the good, monistic aesthetic as pursuit of the beautiful—these are the three great
departments of our monism: by the harmonious and consistent cultivation of these we effect
at last the truly beatific union of religion and science, so painfully longed after by so many
to-day. The True, the Beautiful, and the Good, these are the three august Divine Ones
before which we bow the knee in adoration; in the unforced combination and mutual
supplementing of these we gain the pure idea of God.20 To this ‘triune’ Divine Ideal shall
the coming twentieth century build its altars.
Ten years ago I was present at the celebration of the third centenary of the university of
Wuerzburg, which forty years ago I had entered as a medical student. The festal address on
20
Amongst the many attempts which have been made in the course of the last twenty years to reform religion
in a monistic direction on the basis of advanced knowledge of nature, by far the most important is the epochmaking work of David Friedrich Strauss, entitled The Old Faith and the New: A Confession (11th ed., Bonn,
1881: Collected Writings, 1878). Compare M. J. Savage, Religion in the Light of the Darwinian Doctrine;
John William Draper, History of the Conflict between Religion and Science; Carl Friedrich Retzer, Die
naturwissenschaftliche Weltanschauung und ihre Ideale, ein Ersatz fuer das religioese Dogma (Leipsic,
1890); E. Koch, Natur und Menschengeist im Lichte der Entwickelungslehre (Berlin, 1891). For the
phylogeny of religion see the interesting work of U. Van Ende, Histoire Naturelle de la Croyance (Paris,
1887).
23
that occasion was delivered in the university church by the then rector, the distinguished
chemist, Johannes Wislicenus. His concluding words were: ‘God, the Spirit of Goodness
and of Truth, grant it.’ I now add, ‘and the Spirit of Beauty.’ It is in this sense that I also, on
this commemorative occasion, dedicate to you my best wishes. May the investigation of
nature's secrets flourish and prosper in this corner of our Thueringian land also, and may
the fruits of knowledge, ripening here in Altenburg, contribute no less to the culture of the
spirit and to the advancement of true religion, than those which three hundred and seventy
years ago the great reformer, Martin Luther, brought to the light of day in another corner of
Thueringen, on the Wartburg at Eisenach.
Between Wartburg and Altenburg, on the northern border of Thueringen, lies Weimar,
the classical City of the Muses, and, close by it, our national university of Jena. I regard it
as a good omen that precisely at this moment a rare celebration should have called together
in Weimar the most illustrious patrons of the university of Jena, the defenders of free
research and free teaching.21 In the hope that the defence and promotion of these may still
be continued, I conclude my monistic Confession of Faith with the words: ‘May God, the
Spirit of the Good, the Beautiful, and the True, be with us.’
21
The jubilee of the ‘Naturforschende Gesellschaft des Osterlandes’ was celebrated in Altenburg on October
9, 1892, contemporaneously with the commencement of the brilliant celebration of the golden wedding of the
Grand Duke and Duchess in Weimar. As exceptional as the celebration are the characteristics which
distinguish this august couple. The Grand Duke Carl Alexander has, during a prosperous reign of forty years,
constantly shown himself an illustrious patron of science and art; as Rector Magnificentissimus of our
Thueringian university of Jena, he has always afforded his protection to its most sacred palladium—the right
of the free investigation and teaching of truth. The Grand Duchess Sophie, the heiress and guardian of the
Goethe archives, has in Weimar prepared a fitting home for that precious legacy of our most brilliant literary
period, and has anew made accessible to the German nation the ideal treasures of thought of her greatest
intellectual hero. The history of culture will never forget the service which the princely couple have thereby
rendered to the human mind in its higher development, and at the same time to true religion.
24