1
Stoic Influences in Plotinus’ “On Providence”
Mark Lamarre
The doctrine of providence was fundamental in ancient philosophy and was often debated amongst various
Hellenistic schools, with Platonic, Peripatetic and Stoic schools in favour of it and Epicurean and Sceptics
against. Stoic and Platonist schools agreed about the notion of Providence but disagreed on points of detail.
Numerous treatises’ have come down to us in one form or another, attesting to the vitality of the debate. One
can find works and fragments by such philosophers as Chrysippus, Nemesius of Ephesa, Apuleuis, Calcidius,
Albinus, Pseudo-Plutarch, Alexander of Aphrodisias, Seneca, Epictetus, Cicero, Plotinus, Hierocles, Proclus,
Synesius, and Boethius.1 The stoic formulations in particular were important and influenced the schools that
debated against them.
By the second century AD, the more polemic phase of the debate had abated somewhat2 and both the later
Stoic and Neoplatonic schools had evolved a reasonably stable and consistent formulation with more
development in the area of ethical considerations. 3
Extensive Stoic and middle platonist influence in Plotinus’ thought has been amply documented; we are told
by his pupil Porphyry that ‘’his writings are full of concealed Stoic and Peripatetic doctrines’’ (Henry lvi); a
paper by P.A. Meijer has convincingly argued for an important degree of stoic influence in Enn. VI, 9, 1
citing similarities with Seneca, for example.4 This paper aims to examine possible Stoic influences in
Plotinus’ treatise “On Providence” (Enneads 3.2 & 3.3). Notions and arguments that seem strongly Stoic
abound. Bréhier has pointed out the numerous Stoic borrowings, especially in chapters 5 and 6 (22). For
concision’s sake, fourteen will be listed and compared with similar stoic passages from Epictetus, Seneca and
Marcus Aurelius (who like Plotinus lived in Rome)5, with a particular emphasis on Seneca’s De Providentia.6
The Stoic conception of providence, interchangeable with the more frequently used term of fate,7 can be
described as monistic, immanentist, determist, and materialist (Merlan 124-25). Their notion of providence
was developed and refined to a considerable degree by Chrysippus; Schlimi summarizes the general Stoic
notion of fate thus:
The Stoics did not consider this a blind, unreasoning process. On the contrary, since pneuma
establishes the causal nexus which makes possible an orderly and predictable succession of events
in the cosmos, it was seen as a rational force, synonymous with god and fate. When Chrysippus
identifies the substance of fate as ‘a pneumatic force (dounamis pneumatiken) that governs the
universe by order (tazei), this accords with his universal definition of fate as ‘a certain physical
arrangement (sountazin) of the whole from eternity: some things follow upon and succeed others,
whereby this interconnection is inviolable’. (146)
Although this notion of fate is strongly deterministic, Chrysippus makes allowance for individual free will :
Hence every living creature that moves qua living creature is moved in a movement according to
impulse brought about by fate through the creature’. Although the assent that we give or withhold
from an impulse is ‘in our power’, making us free agents insofar as we are responsible for our
actions, assent depend upon our nature and character, which are the givens of fate. (Schlimi 150)
1
For an overview of these works, see Sharples.
According to Dillon: ‘’the conflict between the doctrines of God’s providence and human free will was perhaps the
most burning philosophical and spiritual issue in second-century Platonism (225).
3
According to Dillon: ‘’although the problem can hardly can hardly be said to have been solved in this period, much
progress was made toward defining its parameters. Somehow the concepts of providence, free will, fate, and chance have
to be fitted harmoniously into an overall world view (225).
4
‘’ Looking closer into Plotinus' treatment of the types of unity and his usage of Stoic material, one is struck by the fact
that Plotinus employs Stoic terminology only scantily, although he makes full use of their examples’’ (69).
5
The passages from Epictetus and Marcus Aurelius are from Bréhier and Armstrong.
6
See appendix for further passages that have comparable Stoic correspondences.
7
The Greek term for ‘’fate’ is ‘’heimarmene’’, the term for providence is ‘’pronoia’’.
2
2
He stresses the importance of critical thinking within the framework of fate :
Although he said, it is true that by fate all things are forced and linked by a necessary and
dominant reason, nevertheless the character of our minds is subject to fate in a manner
corresponding to their nature in a sound and useful manner then they pass on all the force of fate
which imposes on us from outside in a relatively unobjectionable and amore acceptable way.
(Aulus Gellius 7.2.7-8, Inwood & Gerson Hellenistic Philosophy 185)
Moreover, he makes a distinction between two types of causality, a principle cause and auxiliary cause:
For, he said some causes are perfect and principal, while others are auxiliary and proximate.
Therefore, when we say all things occur by fate by antecedent cause, we do not want the following
to be understood by perfect and principal causes; but we mean that they occur by auxiliary and
proximate causes.’’ (Cicero On Fate 41 Inwood & Gerson Hellenistic Philosophy 187)
He accounts for a certain degree of freedom in human action : The doctrine of 'co-fated' events was
advanced as an argument against fatalism and for human responsibility: even though everything is fated,
some things still depend on our (fated) actions. (Sharples 247)
Furthermore, he accounts for the role of conscious, deliberate action within the context of fate:
For many things cannot occur without our being willing and indeed contributing a most strenuous
eagerness and zeal for these things, since, he says, it was fated for these things to occur in
conjunction with this personal effort… But it will be in our power, he says with what is in our
power being included in fate. (Diogneanus in Eusebius Prep. Ev. 6.8. 266d Inwood & Gerson
Hellenistic Philosophy 190)
It can sometimes be difficult to determine if the argument is specifically Middle Platonist or Stoic, as both
stoics and platonists were influence by notions of providence in Plato and Aristotle, in particular in Plato’s
Timaeus, and book X of the Laws as well as notions of causality from Aristotle’s Physics. According to
Merlan ‘’with Posidonius (partly even with Panaetius) the Stoa opened itself to Platonic influence’’(126). To
get a sense of the mutual influence of Stoicism and Middle Platonism and how it influenced Plotinus, it might
be useful to briefly sketch out the ideas found in the Pseudo-Plutarch treatise ‘On Fate’, a Middle Platonist
treatise with Stoic influences.
The author introduces a notion of active fate, which represents the laws of nature. Substantial fate is the Soul
of the universe which transmits the actions of active fate. The quality of fate refers to the cyclical nature of the
universe. The universality of fate is that it makes general conditions that subsequently apply to individual
cases.
He details various aspects of fate, commenting on the Stoic notion that ‘everything conforms to Fate’. There
is the possible, (things that are possible because they have the power to occur) and the substance. The
contingent, as opposed to the necessary, refers to things that occur randomly, like rain, whereas the setting of
the sun is necessary because it occurs on a regular basis. What is in our power are deliberate rational
decisions. Chance is a cause not evident to human calculation, unforeseen or accidental. The spontaneous
refers to things that occur outside of the usual expectations, like cold weather in summer.
There are three types of providence: Primary providence is related to the primary Gods. Secondary
Providence belongs to the secondary gods who move in the heaven and cause everything in generation.
Tertiary Providence concerns the daimons that oversee the affairs of man. Providence is considered to be
higher than Fate. 8
Plotinus’ treatise “On Providence” takes up the questions on providence that by that time had become
commonplace and situates them in more dynamic metaphysical framework that makes a deeper appeal to
Platonic dialogues such as the Timaeus, Phaedrus, Theaetetus, Phaedo, and Republic.
1.
Troublesome situations play a role in the coordination of the whole.
“And even these troubles are not altogether without usefulness for the co-ordination and completion of the
whole” (I, 5, 15).
8
Plotinus also points out the difference between higher providence and lower fate, (3, 2, 5, 15).
3
“For the present, I will say so much of the eventualities that you style harsh, unfortunate and detestable; in the
first place, they benefit the individuals to whose lot they fall, and, in the second place , they benefit the whole
body of mankind, for which the gods are more concerned than they are of individuals” (Seneca 3, 1, 15)9
2.
Nothing that happens is bad for the good man; nothing that happens is good for the bad man.
“As for people getting what they do not deserve, when the good get what is bad and the bad the opposite, it is
correct to say that nothing is bad for the good man and nothing, correspondingly, good for the bad one; (3, 2,
6, 5).”
“’Why do many misfortunes fall to the lot of good men?’ It is not possible that any evil can befall a good
man” (Seneca 2, 1, 12). “Yet why does god allow evil to happen to good men? But in fact he does not”
(Seneca 6, 1, 26).
3.
Troubles serve to awaken us and help us understand the nature of virtue and vice.
“For it makes men awake and wakes up the intelligence and understanding of those who are opposed to the
ways of wickedness” (3, 2, 5, 20).
“Do not, I beseech you, dread the things which the immortal gods apply to our souls like goads; disaster is
virtue’s opportunity”. (Seneca 4, 6, 20).
4.
Why are good people sometimes disfavored and bad people sometimes favored?
“But what if one considers the comparative distribution of evils to men of opposite character, that the good
are poor and the wicked are rich, and the bad have more than their share of things which those who are human
beings must have, and are masters, and peoples and cities belong to them?” (3, 2, 7, 30).
‘’Yet why was god so unfair in distributing destinies as to allot good men poverty and wounds and painful
death?’’ (Seneca 5, 9, 25)
5.
The earth is very small and unimportant compared to the vastness of the universe.
“but men are in the middle and below, and above are heaven and the gods in it; but the earth is like a central
point even in comparison with only one of the stars” (3, 2, 8,5).
“The whole earth is a mere point in space: what a minute cranny within this is your own habitation, and how
many and what sort will sing your praises here!” (Marcus Aurelius 4, 3).
6.
It is normal for things to happen according to physical laws, such as the stronger defeating the
weaker.
“Then again, it is ridiculous for people to do everything else in life according to their own ideas, even if they
are not doing it in the way which the gods like, and then be merely saved by the gods without even doing the
things by means of which the gods command them to save themselves?” (3, 2, 8, 40)
“Somewhere or other we are going to have encounters with wild beasts, and with man, too – more dangerous
than all those beasts. Floods will rob us of one thing, fire of another. These are conditions of our existence
which we cannot change’’ (Seneca Epist. 107, 7, 226)
7.
The good life consists in being good; a bad life consists in being bad (I, 9,10).
“But it says that those who have become good shall have a good life, now, and laid up for them hereafter as
well, and the wicked the opposite” (3, 2, 9, 10).
“But to you I have given goods that are sure and abiding, goods which are better and greater the more one
turns them about and scrutinizes them from every side. (Seneca 6, 5, 27)
8.
Adversity has benefits that are either evident are otherwise hidden.
“No, it is necessary that these, too, should exist; and some of the benefits which come from them are obvious,
and those which are not evident, many of them time discovers”(3, 2, 9,35).
“Of all these propositions the most difficult, apparently, is the first in the list, that the objects of our dread and
horror are actually advantageous to the persons to whose lot they fall” (Seneca, 3, 2, 15)
9.
Things occur in a chain of causation.
9
Bréhier points out this notion in Plotinus (3, 2, 17) and compares it to a passage in Chrysippus (48).
4
“Given a first principle, it accomplishes what follows with the inclusion in the chain of causation of all
principles there are; but men, too , are principles; at any rate, they are moved to noble actions by their own
nature, and this is an independent principle” (3, 2, 10, 15).
“I know that all things proceed according to a law that is fixed and eternally valid. Fate directs us, and the first
hour of our birth determines each man’s span. Cause is linked with cause, and a long chain of events governs
all matters public and private” (Seneca 5, 7, 24-5).
10.
Beauty and order in the natural world is a sign of providence
“for example, the workmanship which produces wonders in rich variety in ordinary animals, and the beauty of
appearance which extends to the fruits and even the leaves of plants, and their beauty of flower which comes
so effortlessly, and their delicacy and variety, and that all this has not been made once and come to an end
but is always being made as the powers above move in different ways over this world” (3, 2, 13, 20).
“that this orderliness is not a property of matter moving at random; and that fortuitous conglomerations
cannot arrange their balance so skillfully that the earth, which is heaviest in weight, should abide unmoved
and, as spectator, observe the rapid flight of the surrounding sky, how the seas are distilled into the valleys to
soften the earth, how huge growths burgeon from tiny seeds” (Seneca 1, 2, 10-11)
11.
Play your role in life as actor in a play
“But in the truer poetic creation, which men who have a poetic nature imitate in part, the soul acts, receiving
the part which it acts from the poet creator; “ (3, 2, 17, 35)
“Remember that you are an actor in a drama, of such a kind as the author pleases to make it“ (Epictetus,
Manuel, 17 ).
12.
Death is like an actor exiting a play.
“If, then, death is a changing of body, like changing of clothes on the stage, or, for some of us, a putting off of
body, like in the theatre the final exit, in that performance, of an actor who will on later occasion come in
again to play, what would there be that is terrible in a change of this kind of living beings into other?” (3, 2,
15,20).
“It is like the officer who engaged a comic actor dismissing him from the stage.’ But I have not played my
five acts, only three.’ Completion is determined by that being who caused first your composition and now
your dissolution. You have no part in either causation. Go then in peace: the god who lets you go is at peace
with you.” (Marcus Aurelius XII, 36)
13.
Mishaps should be seen as a children’s game
“But if anyone joins in their play and suffers their sort of sufferings, he must know that he has tumbled into a
children’s game and put off the play-costume in which he was dressed” (3, 2, 15,40).
“Thus, when you are unable to convince any one, consider him as a child, and clap your hands with him;
(Epictetus I, 29, 30-32)
14.
The wrongdoer is punished by becoming wicked
‘’But those who do these things are punished, first by being wolves and ill-fated men;’’ (3, 2, 4, 25)
‘’But he is the person hurt who suffers the most miserable and shameful evils; who, instead of a man,
becomes a wolf or viper or a hornet’’ (Epictetus IV, 1, 127)
On the whole a treatise like Seneca’s On Fate is very different from Plotinus’ On Providence.10 Seneca
encourages a martial heroic outlook where god is like a stern and benevolent father to the good person and
brings adversity upon him to strengthen and test him. The stoic philosopher welcomes and actually seeks
challenges to test himself. He lives in an optimistic world designed to benefit man and is under the special
care of god. He essentially presents a philosophy of action with a Ciceronian patriotic use of historical
examples.
With Plotinus man is in an intermediary position between gods and beasts and must become aware of his
moral responsibility in the vast interplay of dynamic changes and movement. The immortality of the soul is a
10
Although, as Bréhier notes, they both share a similar structure of presenting the three commonplace questions on
providence while giving prominence to the third point.
5
fundamental consideration with the ideas of the process of reincarnation and the judgment of the soul create a
strong pervasive determinism where every misguided action committed is subject to a punitive retribution.
At the same time, they share basic notions on providence where man’s essential path to goodness is to
cooperate with a providence that represents a natural order. The discomforts and adversities of existence
should not affect the inherent goodness of a person.11 According to Bréhier, the most prominent aspect of the
treatise, is, the place that the famous theory of the Logos holds (chapters 15-18), highly unusual for
Plotinus.12,13
They believe that there are two principles of the universe, the active and the passive. The passive,
then, is unqualified substance, i.e., matter while the active is the rational principle logos in it, i.e.,
god. For he, being eternal and penetrating all of matter, is the craftsman of all things. (Diogenes
Laertius 7.134 Inwood & Gerson Hellenistic Philosophy 132)
Plotinus’ makes use of a universal governing logos to account for diversity and conflict. Bréhier considers it a
clear attempt by Plotinus to assimilate the stoic notion of the logos into a Platonic framework, evoking
similarities with Philo and Origen (19-23). It is in the area of ethics that one can find many notions that can
denote a Stoic influence or have a close similarity to Stoic ideas. According to Dillon:
Plotinus’ predecessors had produced various rather facile formulations, side-stepping rather than
meeting the Stoic challenge. Plotinus does not shirk the difficulties, but does not really resolve the
problems. If anything, he comes down on the Stoic side, in the process of producing some
observations that appear to us distinctly harsh. (xcix)14
Simplicius, who wrote a neoplatonic commentary on the Manual of Epictetus’ explains the ethical
compatibility between stoicism and neoplatonism, despite the metaphysical differences:
But even if it were supposed that the soul is mortal, and that it is destroyed along with the body,
still, in that case anyone who lived according to these precepts would be genuinely happy and
blessed, since he would achieve his own perfection, and reach the good proper to him. (Simplicius
2,1 8-10)
Iamblichus succinctly ‘’summed up the similarity between Stoa and Neoplatonism by saying: both systems
believe in the identity of the cosmic soul with the soul in us’’(Merlan 131). Stoicism then can be to seen to
represent a considerable influence that neoplatonists integrated and synthesized. Part of the reason Plotinus is
considered so important is his capacity to reflect on and integrate a wide variety of ideas from different
schools of philosophy. He began a school that was ‘’regarded, with considerable justification, as the
philosophia perennis of Greek civilization’’ (Inwood & Gerson, Introduction xix).
Thanks to Brooks Sommerville for his valuable comments and suggestions.
Merlan remarks: ‘’As far as ethics is concerned, Plotinus must, of course, have been in sympathy with Stoic
indifference to everything external; thus, he, differing from both the Academy and the Peripatos, recommends Stoic
apathy and, as we have seen, believes that perfection suffices to makes its possessor happy. But what the Stoic considers
to be man’s ultimate goal, viz. independence and inner freedom, is, for Plotinus, only preliminary to the complete union
with the supreme deity-be it in this life in mystical ecstasy, be it in the future, when the soul will return to its original
home” (Merlan 130).
12
‘’Le trait le plus saillant du traité, c’est la place, tout à fait inaccoutumée chez Plotin, qu’y tient la célèbre théorie du
Logos’’ (18).
13
See Plotinus 3, 2, chapters 15-18 and passages 11-13 of this paper.
14
For example: ‘’Or would it not be right for even the lawgiver to allow them to suffer this as a penalty for their laziness
and soft and slack living allowed themselves to become fattened lambs, the prey of wolves?” (I, 8,25).
11
6
Appendix
1. One can see the order of nature by observing that each part of the body is designed for a useful function
(3, 3, 35)
(Epictetus 1, 16, 2)
2. Destruction is a necessary part of nature. There are phases of order and disorder (3, 2, 4, 15)
(Marcus Aurelius 9, 1, 5)
3. Situations like poverty and sickness are not bad things for good people (3, 2, 5, 10).
(Epictetus (3, 17, 1)
4. One should be self-reliant and not blame providence (3, 2, 9, 15).
Epictetus (1, 6, 5)
5. The rational principle governs the all (3, 2, 11).
(Marcus Aurelius 6, 42)
6. Good conduct consist in acting in accordance with providence (3, 3, 5,45)
(Seneca, 5, 41)
7. No one blames providence when animals attack men (3, 3, 9, 35)
(Seneca 2, 31)
8. Providence heals like a doctor healing an wound or sickness (3, 3, 5, 30)
(Marcus Aurelius 5, 8)
7
Works Cited
Dillon, John. "Plotinus, an Introduction". Plotinus. The Enneads. London: Penguin Books, 1991. lxxxiv-ciPrint.
Dillon, John. "Plutarch and second Century Platonism". Classical Mediterranean Spirituality. A.H. Armstrong, ed. New
York: Crossroads, 1986. 220-232. Print.
Epictetus. Moral Discourses. Enchiridion and Fragments. E. Carter, transl. London: J. M. Dent & Sons, 1910. Print.
Inwood, Brad & L.P. Gerson. Hellenistic Philosophy. Inwood, Brad & L.P. Gerson, eds. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2003. Print.
Henry, Paul. "The Place of Plotinus in the History of Thought". Plotinus. The Enneads. London: Penguin Books, 1991.
xllii-lxxxiii. Print.
Inwood, Brad & L.P. Gerson. "Introduction". Neoplatonic Philosophy. Inwood, Brad & L.P. Gerson, eds. Indianapolis:
Hackett Publishing Company, 2004. xiii-xxii. Print.
Laërce, Diogène. Vie, Doctrines et Sentences des Philosophes Illustres I. R. Genaille, transl. Paris: Garnier- Flammarion,
1965.
Laertius, Diogenes, et al. '' II- Stoicism ''. Hellenistic Philosophy. Inwood, Brad & L.P. Gerson, eds., Indianapolis:
Hackett Publishing Company, 1997. 103-260. Print.
Marcus Aurelius. Meditations. M. Hammond, transl. London: Penguin Books, 2006. Print.
Meijer, P. A. "Stoicism in Plotinus' ‘Enneads’ VI 9,1" Quaderni Urbinati di Cultura Classica, New Series, (1978) 30 3
61-76 7 Apr. 2011 < http://www.jstor.org/stable/20546965>.
Merlan, P. "The Stoa". The Cambridge History of Later Greek & Early Medieval Philosophy. A. H. Armstrong, ed.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1967. 124-132. Print.
Plotinus. Enneads III. A. H. Armstrong, transl. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1967. Print.
Plotinus. Ennéades III. E. Bréhier, transl. Paris: Les Belles Lettres, 1925. Print.
Schibli, Hermann S. Hierocles of Alexandria. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002. Print.
Sharples, R. W. "Alexander of Aphrodisias, De Fato: Some Parallels" The Classical Quarterly, New Series, (1978) 28 2
243-266 31 Mar. 2011 <http://www.jstor.org/stable/638677>.
Seneca. Epistulae Morales, Vol. 3 . R. M. Guinnere , transl. Cambridge: Harvard University Press (Loeb), 1925. Print.
Seneca. "De la Providence". Dialogues, Tome IV. M. Waltz, transl. Paris: Societe d’Edition “Les Belles Lettres”, 1965.
6-29. Print.
Simplicius. On Epictetus’ Handbook 1-26. Brittain, C. & T. Brennan, tranls. Ithaca : Cornell University Press, 2002.
Print.