Academia.eduAcademia.edu

Climate Change and the Moral Agent Review

AI-generated Abstract

The paper examines the moral responsibilities individuals hold in the context of climate change, proposing that the priority should be on promoting collective action rather than solely addressing individual duties. It critiques existing analytic moral philosophy for being too narrow and emphasizes the interconnectedness of human agency within collectives, asserting that individual duties are essentially collective. The work argues for a reconceptualization of moral agency as inherently relational, highlighting that true engagement with climate challenges requires reshaping our collective lives.

Published Online 23 Sept 2014 In Journal of Contemporary European Studies 22:3, 347-249 http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/14782804.2014.942130 [I have made some minor corrections to this version] Climate Change and the Moral Agent: Individual Duties in an Interdependent World Elizabeth CRIPPS Oxford University Press, 2013, ISBN 978-0-19966-5655 £55.00 (hbk), 258 pp. Together with many of us, Elizabeth Cripps is deeply concerned about the moral implications of our failure to adequately respond to catastrophic climate change. She is concerned about its implications for our duties, responsibilities and well-being qua moral agents, in a situation where it can seem as if there really is no ‘we’ that is responding at all. The book sets out to defend two claims: 1) There are ‘weakly collective duties’ to respond with mitigation, adaptation and compensation; 2) My primary duty as an individual agent when ‘we’ fail to act is to promote such collective action. Cripps begins by clearing some ground upon which to draw the map of climate duties by making five key factual, normative and ‘metaphysical’ assumptions. The book is then divided into four parts. Part 1 offers three arguments for a ‘weakly collective duty’ to respond to climate change. Parts 2 and 3 explore some of the implications of this duty. Part 2 ‘pushes the boundaries’ of our notion of moral collectivity to include non-human animals, species and ecosystems. Part 3 asks what kinds of action I should prioritise in a situation where we are failing to act to fulfil our collective duties. The claim is that I should prioritise the promotion of collective action above both ‘mimicking duties’ (fulfilling only the duties that I would have in a situation where there was adequate collective action e.g. reducing my own emissions) and ‘direct duties’ (i.e. trying to respond directly as an individual to the harms that are being caused). Part 4 proposes a further argument for the ‘weakly collective duty’, based on the idea that if we don’t act collectively we present individuals with ‘marring choices’, whereby whatever they choose they will feel deep moral regret. The first three parts proceed from the starting assumptions to make careful arguments in favour of the central claims of the book. These claims are important and disturbing in a certain way. The idea that we must consider the responsibilities and duties of ‘potential collectivities’ as well as actual ones, together with the deployment of a ‘non-intentionalist’ model of collectivity, leads Cripps to a view of the moral situation as one in which we are faced with irreconcilable and extremely complex sets of duties and responsibilities that extend far beyond the so-called ‘human sphere’. This will be uncomfortable for those who hold out the hope that the map of climate duties will be marked with an X of moral perfection. The claim that, in a case where it seems that we are failing to act or even constitute ourselves as a collectivity, our priority should be to promote such collectivity, will be uncomfortable for those would prefer to imagine that keeping an eye on the size of their own carbon footprint is all that can now be required of them. Yet Cripps’s vision remains too narrow and too conventional, largely as a result of adopting the prevailing methods and assumptions of analytic moral philosophy. The two key assumptions are: a) moral philosophy can begin by taking certain general normative principles as read because they arise from an ‘impersonal’ perspective; b) human beings qua ‘moral agents’ are primarily and above all freely acting individuals. These two starting assumptions feed into and are fed by the liberal hegemony in moral and ‘political’ thinking, as Raymond Geuss has so convincingly and devastatingly shown. Raymond Geuss, Philosophy and Real Politics (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2008) Climate change is so overwhelming and so disturbing that it forces us to rethink all such assumptions. Rather than consider abstract ‘potential collectivities’ (Cripps absurdly picks out ‘The Young’, ‘The Able’ and ‘The Polluters’ without any regard for the concrete socio-historical situation of the members of these sets) that have ‘weakly collective duties’, we should understand actual and concretely potential collectivity as the basic and fundamental condition of all our agency and receptivity, capacity and incapacity. There is no need to ‘extend’ the moral sphere beyond the human, because we are already continually constituting and re-constituting ourselves as collectivities that distribute ‘agency’ to other living beings and even ‘inanimate’ things. For a compelling account of such fundamental collectivity see Jane Bennett, Vibrant Matter: A Political Ecology of Things (Durham & London: Duke University Press, 2010) These collectivities are irreducibly political because they must continually set out to justify any principles they may adopt in the face of others that they encounter. This brings me to the fourth and final part of the book. This is in many ways the most penetrating rethinking of moral agency that Cripps engages in and it sets out the view of what it is to be a human being that ultimately underpins the whole view. Following Thomas Nagel, Cripps claims that a human being is motivated by three perspectives: the personal; interpersonal; and ‘impersonal moral’. She then goes on to build on the pioneering work of Stephen Gardiner to argue that our failure to act collectively presents individuals with ‘marring choices’ in which they are forced to choose between the fundamental claims of these three perspectives. Being forced to make ‘marring choices’ certainly threatens our desire for moral security and some of them certainly do us great harm. It may be that they are far more prevalent a feature of our moral lives than we care to admit and that one way in which we can be morally ‘marred’ is to fall prey to the delusion that they might be avoided altogether. In the controversy between Bernard Williams and Martha Nussbaum about the appropriate response to moral tragedy, one has the sense that Cripps would take the side of Nussbaum. See Bernard Williams, ‘The Women of Trachis: Fictions, Pessimism, Ethics’ in The Sense of the Past (Princeton: Princeton University, 2006) pp. 49-59 and Martha C. Nussbaum, ‘Bernard Williams: Tragedies, hope, justice’ in Reading Bernard Williams, ed. Daniel Callcut (London & New York, Routledge, 2009) pp. 213-241 The problem is that marring choices cannot be explained as a failure to reconcile the three perspectives, because there are no such perspectives. Being human means taking on a vast and shifting multiplicity of perspectives, each one of which is irreducibly interpersonal. Every personal project and interest already implicates others, whilst any attempt to take an ‘impersonal’ view is in reality an attempt to constitute a new, and in some salient respects potentially more encompassing, interpersonal collectivity. We don’t need to promote this, we need to continue to do it and do it better. In reality our problem is not one of working out what our individual duties are in an interdependent world, in order that we can ‘live with ourselves’ in the midst of devastation. Once we realise that in an interdependent world there is strictly speaking no such thing as an individual duty, because there is no such thing as an individual in that sense, our problem becomes one of finding ways to reshape our already collective lives so that we can continue to live with one another. Tom Greaves University of East Anglia, UK [email protected] 1