THE UNIVERSAL EVOLUTION AND THE ORIGIN OF LIFE
Gennady Shkliarevsky
DOI: 10.13140/RG.2.2.18564.86404
Abstract: The origin of life occupies a very important place in the study of the evolution. Its
liminal location between life and non-life poses special challenges to researchers who study this
subject. Current approaches in studying the origin and evolution of early life are reductive: they
either reduce the domain of non-life to the domain of life or vice versa. This contribution seeks
to provide a perspective that would avoid reductionism of any kind. Its goal is to outline a frame
that would include both domains and their respective evolutions as its particular cases. The study
examines the main theoretical perspectives on the origin and evolution of early life and provides a
constructive critique of these perspectives. An objective view requires viewing an object or a
phenomenon from all available points of view. The goal of this contribution is not to prove the
current perspectives wrong and to deny their achievements. It seeks to provide an angle that
would be sufficiently wide and would allow synthesizing current perspectives for a
comprehensive and objective interpretation of the origin and evolution of early life. In other
words, it seeks to outline a frame for an objective view that will help understand life’s place
within the universe.
Key words: origin of life, prokaryotes, eukaryotes, multicellular life, process of creation,
evolution, conservation, and levels of organization.
Introduction
Life is perhaps the most intimately familiar experience that all humans have. It begins
even before we are born. Yet when asked what life is, most of us will be at a loss for an
explanation and will be able to offer little more than vague intuitions. For centuries
scientists have reflected on life, but a consensus on what life is or how it originated has
emerged.1 Despite its proximity and familiarity, life has been and remains a mystery that
defies our imagination and challenges our capacity for rational explanation.
Decades of research have produced an impressive array of ingenious theories and
sophisticated experiments; numerous facts about living organisms have become known.
Scientists can describe in minute detail all aspects of a living organism, but are unclear
about the most important distinction between life and non-life. Yet they have so far
failed to provide a definitive solution of the problem of life and its origin. As Nick Lane
summarized in the preface to his book The Vital Question: Energy, Evolution, and the
Origins of Complex Life:
There is a black hole at the heart of biology. Bluntly put, we do not know
why life is the way it is.2
A group of researchers led by Eloi Camprubí expresses a similar sentiment: “[I]t is
clear,” they write, “that we are still far from an answer on how life emerged on Earth, let
alone on life’s place within the Universe.”3
1
The discrepancy between the accumulated knowledge and a lack of the definitive
understanding of life is frustrating. Some researchers are even skeptical about the very
possibility of having “any scientifically relevant language” that can capture the complex
and multifarious phenomenon of life.4 They claim that we may never know answers to
the most fundamental questions related to life. Moreover, they argue that such answers
lie beyond our very capacity to know, thus setting limits to human knowledge.
Many, however, find this verdict hard to accept. They believe that the answer to
fundamental questions about life require new approaches and new ideas. In his review of
David Deamer’s book Assembling Life: How Can Life Begin on Earth and Other
Habitable Planets William Bain opines:
. . . the Origin of Life field as a whole is unconvincing, generating results
in Toy Domains that cannot be scaled to any real world scenario. I
suggest that, by analogy with the history of artificial intelligence and solar
astronomy, we need much more scale, and fundamentally new ideas, to
take the field forward.5
The quest for a new approach motivates this essay. It will examine the theoretical
perspectives on the origin and evolution of early life and will try to formulate a new and
inclusive theoretical perspective that will open new possibilities for addressing the old
questions: How did life originate and come to dominate Earth?
General Theories of the Origin of Life
Definitions of Life
An explanation of the origin of life depends to a significant degree on the way that
researchers define life. Current definitions vary widely both in complexity and
sophistication. As has already been mentioned, there is no consensus on what life is and
what distinguishes it from non-life.
Some definitions are simple, while others are more complicated. Carl Sagan, for
example, defined life as “a system capable of evolution by natural selection.”6 NASA’s
working definition is very similar. Life, it says, “is a self-sustained chemical system
capable of undergoing Darwinian evolution.”7 Theoretical biologist Claus Emmeche
provides a lengthier (and fancier) definition. He views life in semiotic, or rather
biosemiotic terms: “Life is the functional interpretation of signs in self-organizing
material ‘code-systems’ that construct their own ‘um-welts.’”8 Robert Shapiro and
Gerald Feinberg think of life in terms of systems theory. They understand life as “a
highly ordered system of matter and energy characterized by complex cycles that
maintain or gradually increase the order of the system through an exchange of energy
with its environment.”9
2
Other examples include Francisco Varela and Humberto Maturana, famous Chilean
biologists, who see life through the prism of autopoiesis—the term that they invented and
that focuses on the capacity of systems to reproduce, maintain, and renew themselves. A
living organism is, in accordance with their perspective, “the minimal living
organization” that is defined as “a network of processes of production (synthesis and
destruction) of components such that these components: (i) continuously regenerate and
realize the network that produces them, and (ii) constitute the system as a distinguishable
unit in the domain in which they exist.”10 A group of researchers led by Ruiz-Murazo,
characterizes a living being as “any autonomous system with open-ended evolutionary
capacities.”11 In yet another definition, life is “a self-sustained, dynamic, nonequilibrium, extended replicative chemical network, which was initiated by the chance
emergence of a simple, but persistent, replicative chemical system.”12
There seems to be as many definitions of life as there are researchers that work in this
field. Despite their diversity, these definitions share some points. They all consider
autonomy to be a principal feature of life. Another characteristic feature that many
researchers emphasize is life’s capacity for “open-ended evolution.” Most of them view
the evolution through the prism of Darwinian theory that explains the evolution in terms
of variations and natural selection.
It is worth pointing out that Darwin developed his theory primarily with biology in mind
and this theory has been primarily applicable to the biological realm. Yet the origin of
life involves both the inanimate as well as the animate world. For this reason, the
Darwinian approach toward the evolution is perhaps the most problematic aspect of many
current definitions of life
Current OOL Perspectives
1.
The “privileged function” perspective
One popular perspective on the origin of life (OOL) is the so-called “privileged function”
perspective. Kathryn Lanier and Loren Williams define “privileged function” as “an
extant biological function that is excised from its biological context, elevated in
importance over other functions, and transported back in time to a primitive chemical or
geological environment.”13 In other words, this perspective tries to locate what belongs
to the more powerful level of organization—i.e., life—in the inorganic realm that
represents a less powerful level of organization. As Lanier and Williams further explain,
privileged functions “are considered by OOL model builders to be so essential and
fundamental to life that they must also be a requisite for the origin of life.”14
The majority of the “privileged function” models fall into one of the two major groups:
the “gene first” approach and the metabolism first approach. The proponents of the
“gene-first” approach focus on autocatalytic self-sustaining chemical reactions that they
see as fundamental to all living organisms. They argue that life has its roots in the
capacity of molecules to create functionally closed and self-sustaining system
3
characterized by internal autocatalytic operations and functions. Such systems, in their
view, eventually gave rise to the intricate RNA-DNA-protein molecular machinery that
made life possible. From this proposition they draw a conclusion that if autocatalysis
sustains life, then life itself is little more than an autocatalytic set and its spontaneous
emergence from pure chemistry is less improbable than one might think.15
The “gene first” hypothesis maintains that life began with the emergence of RNA
molecules. It sees the capacity of RNA for template-based self-replication and the ability
to catalyze other reactions as playing the decisive role in the emergence of life; hence the
name for this hypothesis is RNA Worlds.16 Clay Worlds is a subgroup of RNA Worlds
that focuses on a variety of mineral surfaces as sites for synthesizing bio-molecules
capable of replication.
2. The “metabolism first” perspective
“Metabolism first” is also a popular approach in the “privileged function” category. This
model emphasizes metabolism as the principal function of living organisms. The
“metabolism first” approach offers a variety of models. One popular model is the socalled “managed metabolism” hypothesis. This hypothesis argues that in order to make
the transition from non-life to life, self-producing systems of chemical molecules must
overcome the so-called “cooperation barrier” that prevents the cooperation in their
unmanaged, self-organizing, autocatalytic networks. These autocatalytic networks of
molecules have a variety of the co-called “free riding” processes that work against
cooperation and they need to be managed. The proponents of this hypothesis identify the
emergence of the system that manages the un-regulated processes and turns them into a
system of orderly metabolism with the onset of life.17 The mechanism that provides this
regulation and overcomes the “cooperation barrier” is the DNA/RNA apparatus since
effective regulation requires information and memory that stores this information.18 An
interesting feature of this model is that it sees the primary role of DNA/RNA in
regulation, rather than in replication.
The Thermal Vent Worlds hypothesis is a subset of the “metabolism first” category. It
focuses on the process of harvesting energy form chemical gradients that takes place at
submarine hydrothermal vents. These vents became the site of abiotic synthesis of
simple organic molecules and later polymers.19
3. The Membrane Worlds
The Membrane Worlds is yet another popular hypothesis in the “privileged function”
category. The “privileged function” in this model is compartmentalization. Its
proponents focus on the role of membranes in the emergence of life. In their view, the
formation of compartments was highly consequential as it produced cascading structures
from simple to complex systems.20 In several “privileged function” models,
compartmentalization is a secondary privileged function, used as an adjunct to a primary
privileged function.21
4
4. The continuity perspectives
There are some hypotheses that emphasize continuity, rather than discontinuity, in the
emergence of life. Such hypotheses base their explanations on general universal laws
that operate in the physical world. In other words, they try to explain biology from
physics.22 As d’Arcy Thompson—one of the early representatives of this trend—has
argued, biologists tend to overemphasize the role of the biological evolution over that of
physical laws in the origin and growth of life.23 Nigel Goldenfeld and Carl Woese, two
relatively recent contributors to this line of thinking, argue:
Evolution is the fundamental physical process that gives rise to biological
phenomena . . . We discuss how condensed matter physics concepts might
provide a useful perspective in evolutionary biology, the conceptual
failings of the modern evolutionary synthesis, the open-ended growth of
complexity, and the quintessentially self-referential nature of evolutionary
dynamics . . . Indeed, the very existence of biological phenomena is an
expression of physical laws that represent a new asymptotic realm in nonequilibrium statistical physics . . . Life is physics and evolution is a
collective phenomenon far from equilibrium.24
Self-organization is another common theme among explanations that emphasize
continuity.25 Its proponents see the emergence of life to be primarily a result of intrinsic
general properties of matter, such as self-organization, rather than a product of natural
selection. Concepts related to self-organization initially found their application in
chemistry and physics, not biology. Their application to various morphogenetic problems
in biology is a later development. The use of this approach to explain the origin of living
cells did not begin until the last century.26
According to the proponents of this perspective, the capacity for self-organization played
a decisive role in the origin and evolution of early life forms.27 Many of them share the
view of Roland Wedlich-Söldner and Timo Betz who argue that self-organization “lies at
the heart of the robustness and adaptability found in cellular and organismal organization,
and hence constitutes a fundamental basis for natural selection and evolution.”28
Another trend in the continuity category emphasizes the connection between entropy and
the origin of life. Entropy production is central to this trend.29 The fact that every human
generates 6,000 times more heat per kilogram of mass than the Sun leads, for example,
Roy Murphy to conclude that “the conversion of pure energy into more disordered energy
such as thermal, kinetic and chemical is the whole reason for our being.”30
Jeremy England, a physicist from MIT and one of the recent contributors to this line of
thinking, According to England,
The formula, based on established physics, indicates that when a group of
atoms is driven by an external source of energy (like the sun or chemical
fuel) and surrounded by a heat bath (like the ocean or atmosphere), it will
5
often gradually restructure itself in order to dissipate increasingly more
energy.31
England argues that the origin and subsequent evolution of life follow from the
fundamental laws of nature and “should be as unsurprising as rocks rolling downhill.”
Critique of the Current OOL Perspectives
1. The flawed strategy
Many current OOL perspectives use the same common strategy. They focus on one
particular property (function or feature) in living organisms that they posit as
fundamental to life. They view the rise of this property in the inanimate world as the
beginning of life and try to reconstruct the process of its emergence.
The logic of this strategy is essentially circular and tautological. Rather than proceed
from causes to effects, this strategy takes the results and tries to find their causes. No
wonder that attempts to locate a property that belongs to a more powerful level of
organization in the level that is less powerful end up in failure.32 A weaker level of
organization simply cannot sustain a feature that requires a more powerful level of
organization. As Addy Pross, among others, has concluded: “The origin of life (OOL)
question might be considered physical organic chemistry’s ultimate challenge, yet despite
continuing efforts over close to a century, the problem remains unresolved.”33
2. The problem of subjectivism and arbitrariness
There is another problem with the strategy of proceeding from results to causes, rather
than vice versa. This strategy involves constructing theories on the basis of some
assumption that is regarded as self-evidently true—for example, the assumption that
metabolism or replication is the fundamental function of the organism—and then using
this assumption as the organizing principle for the theory.
Assumption is essentially an educated hunch; and as all hunches go, assumption,
educated or not, is also to a significant degree subjective and arbitrary. The way
scientific methodology addresses this problem of subjectivity and arbitrariness is by
subjecting the foundational organizing principle of a theory to the test of rational
justification and empirical verification. This test is not an ironclad proof, but it does
show that the principle on which a theory is built is not entirely arbitrary. The
application of rules of logic, reason, and empirical proof shared by other researchers
shows that the author at least to some extent controls the theory, rather than the theory
controls the author. 34
None of the perspectives on the origin of life offer rational justification or empirical
verification to support the assumptions used as their foundational organizing principle.
For example, metabolism and replication are very important biological functions, but
6
there is absolutely no reason to assign a “privileged” status to either of them. Despite
their theoretical sophistication and an impressive cache of empirical data, models that do
not provide rational justification or empirical verification for their foundational principles
cannot be considered objective and they cannot effectively respond to criticism for being
arbitrary and subjective.
3. The randomness problem
Most current OOL perspectives invoke chance or coincidence in their explanations of the
origin of life. Sean Carroll, a well-known evolutionary biologist, refers to the emergence
of life as “the mother of all accidents” and “the accident of all mothers.”35 The problem
with invoking chance or coincidence is that one cannot really demonstrate their existence
(in other words, provide a rational justification for its existence). Genuine randomness
may or may not exist in nature, but there is really no way to prove either its existence or,
for that matter its non-existence. For example, a set of numbers may show randomness,
but there is no guarantee and no proof that if we extend this set indefinitely, it will not
reveal some underlying order or pattern.36
There are a growing number of biologists who dispute the critical assumption of
randomness. Kevin Laland et al., for example, find that “much variation is not random
because developmental processes generate certain forms more readily than others”37
Christian de Duve the author of A Guided Tour of a Living Cell,38 also offers an objection
to using chance in an explanation. In one of his widely publicized quotes, he writes:
If you equate the probability of the birth of a bacteria cell to chance
assembly of its atoms, eternity will not suffice to produce one . . . Faced
with the enormous sum of lucky draws behind the success of the
evolutionary game, one may legitimately wonder to what extent this
success is actually written into the fabric of the universe.39
Many OOL perspectives rely on Darwinian theory. This theory does offer a proof that
mutations exist. However, it does not and cannot demonstrate that these mutations are
random. The lack of proof means in this case that there is at least a fifty per cent chance
that initial variations may be a result of some underlying order, which would be an
anathema to the Darwinian model. Again, this is not to say that initial variations are not
random. This is to say, however, that there is no way of proving their randomness and,
therefore, it must be put in doubt.
The lack of rational justification and empirical verification for the existence of chance
indicates that a theory based on the assumption of the existence of chance is not under
control of reason and, therefore, is subjective and arbitrary. A possibility of such theory
controlling us, rather than we controlling it, is dangerously strong. Chance and
coincidence are not really conducive to rational explanation as they set a limit to our
knowledge. In addition, the distance that separates researchers from the time when life
emerged offers no opportunity for empirical verification either. For example, we have no
7
empirical proof for the existence of hypothetical common ancestors, yet many scientists
use these entities to bolster their theories.
4. The continuity/discontinuity problem
The use of chance and coincidence in explanations of the origin of life also points to a
deeper problem: the failure by the current perspectives to resolve the problem of
continuity and discontinuity. An overwhelming majority of biologists accept the
evolution as a fact. They also accept that life has its roots in inorganic matter. In other
words, they de facto recognize that the origin of life involves continuity. However, they
also recognize that life represents a totally new level of organization that did not exist
prior to its emergence. Therefore, they also recognize that the origin of life involves
discontinuity. However, they do not explain how the two are interrelated. Moreover,
they do not even raise this issue, accepting the existence of both continuity and
discontinuity as a given. The solution of the fundamental problem of the origin of life is
not possible without explaining how continuity and discontinuity are related. By
invoking chance the current perspectives on the origin of life do not even have to explain
this relationship. They simply evade this subject altogether.
5. The selection problem
As has already been mentioned, many current OOL models use “privileged function” as a
category fundamental to their interpretation. In addition, they commonly use “universal
common ancestor” as another category that they deem to be central to their
explanations.40 They define “universal common ancestor,” or “the last universal common
ancestor” (LUCA), as a population of the most recent organisms to which they trace the
origin of all species. The use of both categories creates confusion as to what was the unit
of selection in the origin of life: function or form (common ancestor).
The recognition that life emerged from the inorganic world means that the origin of life
was a result of the evolution. The Darwinian model to which many OOL perspectives
subscribe, works on selection. If selection is involved, there must be also a unit of
selection that the evolution conserves. The identification of the unit of conservation is
critically important in explaining the evolution. The fact that that the current OOL
perspectives use two very different units of selection—function and organism—creates
confusion and makes the reconstruction of the evolution difficult.
Function and organism are very different from each other. Function is broader than
organism. Many organisms that are very different from each other may have similar
functions. The fact that function relates to many different organisms works better with
evolutionary processes that operate on a broad scale that embraces multiple organisms.
Conservation of a particular function will have a much broader scope that will cover
many organisms.
Function is a form of action. It is dynamic in its nature. So is the evolution that is also
characterized by action and dynamism. If dynamism is the nature of the evolution, then
8
the evolution is primarily about conserving its own dynamism. As it evolves, the
evolution becomes increasingly more dynamic. Since dynamism is so central to both the
function and the evolution, conserving function is more compatible with the nature of the
evolution than conserving an organism, or form, that is static in its nature.
The history of sexual reproduction may help to illustrate this point. Sexual reproduction
is not the oldest form of reproduction. It goes back only to the emergence of
eukaryotes.41 Yet today, sexual reproduction is ubiquitous; it is the dominant form of
reproduction in nature.
The dominance of sexual reproduction in nature puzzles researchers.42 They still cannot
explain why the evolution preferred sexual reproduction to asexual one. Some argue that
sexual reproduction has important advantages over asexual one. They point, for example,
to the capacity of sexual reproduction to produce beneficial mutations and improve
genotypes, which advances the evolution. Their critics object by arguing that sexual
reproduction can also produce harmful mutations and disrupt adaptive genotypes during
independent assortment and crossing over of genes.43 Also, sexual reproduction involves
a huge investment in terms of resources. After all, bacteria do not have to search for a
mate. They simply divide in two. No need to invest energy in finding a partner,
fertilizing an egg, and joining two genomes.44
The prominent British evolutionist Richard Dawkins compares sexual reproduction to a
game of roulette “in which the player throws away half of his chips at each spin.” “The
existence of sexual reproduction really is a huge paradox,” Dawkins concludes.45 The
evolutionary biologist Graham Bell is even more direct in his assessment:
Sex … does not merely reduce fitness, but halves it. If a reduction in
fitness of a fraction of one percent can cripple a genotype, what will be the
consequence of a reduction of 50 per cent? There can be only one answer:
sex will be powerfully selected against and rapidly eliminated wherever it
appears. And yet this has not happened.46
One may agree or disagree with either side in this controversy. However, there is clearly
no definitive answer as to why the evolution favored sexual reproduction. Given what
we know, it remains unclear why the evolution would not treat both forms of
reproduction equally. As Lauren Hurst asks, why not have the best of both worlds and
benefit equally from what both have to offer?47
If we think about both forms of reproduction, no clear advantages emerge from either
sexual or asexual reproduction. Both have advantages and disadvantages. However, if
one thinks about the reproductive function itself, rather than its specific form, the
evolution shows preference for sexual reproduction as the more effective way of
conserving the reproductive function itself. Sexual reproduction conserves the function
of reproduction better than the asexual form of reproduction.
9
Function is about action. In order to conserve action, it has to be enacted. The more
often a function is enacted, the better it is conserved. Sexual reproduction offers more
opportunities to stimulate and activate the reproductive function. In a population of
sexually differentiated organisms the number of real and potential sources of stimulation
of the reproductive function increases exponentially as individual organisms interact with
each other. In other words, sexual reproduction increases the stimulation and activation
of the reproductive function and, thus, conserves it better than asexual reproduction does
since asexual reproduction does not offer multiple external sources of reproductive
stimulation.
The above is a simple illustration why function, rather than form, is a more likely object
of conservation in the evolution. However, one should keep in mind that since life
originated in the inorganic world, the object of conservation in this case should not be a
biological function. It can only be a function that extends to both worlds.
6. The failure to produce a synthesis
Objectivity requires viewing an object or a phenomenon from all sides. The current
perspectives on the origin of life do not observe this condition. They all have their
specific focus, use their specific facts, and interpret these facts in their own way. Each
perspective uses its own specific prism. Each has its own specific angle from which it
views the origin of life. As a result, no matter how valid the points that each perspective
brings up, each is, to one degree or another, incomplete and, therefore, subjective. In
order to solve the problem of the origin of life, the field needs a comprehensive approach
and a frame that would be broad enough to include all perspectives as its particular
cases—cases that are valid under specific conditions or assumptions.
Deliberating the Main Stages in the Origin and Evolution of Early Life
The universally accepted view in the scientific community is that the origin and evolution
of early life is a process that includes several stages. The creation of organic molecules
was the first important stage in this process. It opened the path for the subsequent stages:
prokaryotic cells (bacteria and archaea), modern eukaryotic unicellular organisms, and
finally multicellular life. Each of these stages represented a new and increasingly more
powerful level of organization. Each has emerged from the level of organization that
preceded it; and each has given rise to the next new and more powerful level of
organization.
The Origin of Organic Molecules
The origin of organic molecules is still a much-debated issue that so far has no definitive
solution. There are numerous hypotheses as to how organic molecules may have
emerged. A detailed examination and critique of these hypotheses is beyond the scope of
this study and a general discussion will have to suffice.
10
Most hypotheses regarding the origin of organic matter focus on autocatalytic chemical
reactions. The proponents of this approach see a set of autocatalytic and self-sustaining
chemical reactions as fundamental to all living organisms. The conclusion that they infer
from this observation is that life has its roots in the capacity of matter to create
functionally closed and self-sustaining system characterized by internal autocatalytic
operations and functions. In their view, such systems gave rise to the intricate RNADNA-protein molecular machinery that is fundamental to replication and life.48 This
proposition leads them to conclude that if autocatalysis sustains life, then life itself is
little more than an autocatalytic set and its spontaneous emergence from pure chemistry
is less improbable than one might think.49
This general perspective invokes chance. The common argument for most hypotheses in
this category is that the right combination of necessary ingredients and conditions of
early Earth made the emergence of organic molecules possible. The classic OparinHaldane hypothesis, more commonly known as “the primordial soup” hypothesis, has
been dominant over the last century and still retains its popularity.50 The Miller-Urey
experiment on the formation of nucleobases is perhaps the best-known experimental
attempt to prove this hypothesis.51 This perspective contends that any theory of
abiogenesis must take into account the condition of the Earth about 4.5 billion years ago.
They argue that organic molecules were a product of something similar to the MillerUrey process that took place under the conditions of cooled Earth with its abundance of
water. According to this scenario, Earth’s oceans became a huge pool teeming with a
variety of molecules. Given enough time, they combined by pure chance to form first
organic entities that were capable of replication.52 This original hypothesis has
subsequently evolved into what is known today as the RNA hypothesis that is still very
common among biologists and is used in many textbooks.53 The big attraction of this
hypothesis is its similarity with Darwin’s “warm little pond” proposal. 54
Over the years researchers have added more models describing the emergence of the
organic world.55 Some of them point to various mineral surfaces—such as, for example,
clay--as a possible catalyst for the origin of organic molecules and life.56 Others propose
deep-see thermal vents as possible sites of the origin of organic matter.57
These hypotheses on the origin of organic molecules have several major and unresolved
problems. For one thing, their main focus is not so much on causes as on factors that
facilitated the emergence of the organic world. Also, these hypotheses emphasize
discontinuity in this process and play down continuity. There is no justification for
prioritizing discontinuity over continuity. Just like discontinuity, continuity is of
paramount importance. Without continuity, there would be no evolution.
As a result of their emphasis on discontinuity, these hypotheses have to rely on chance
and coincidence as explanatory factors in the emergence of life. The big weakness of
such hypotheses is that their assumption about the role of chance and coincidence cannot
pass the test of rational justification and empirical verification, which makes them
vulnerable to criticism for being subjective and arbitrary.
11
Analyses of the chemical composition of meteorites and comets have recently revealed
traces of organic matter,58 which led to the formulation of a number of hypotheses that
suggest that organic molecules may have originated somewhere else in the universe and
later came to Earth in the shower of meteorites that pelted the planet.59 These hypotheses
of interplanetary origin of organic molecules also do not solve the problem of origin; they
merely move this problem to some extraterrestrial location. By arguing for an
extraterrestrial origin, they open possibilities that the origin of life does not really need
the special conditions that existed on Earth. They suggest that life could have emerged
under conditions that are very different from those on our planet, which opens a
possibility that factors other than terrestrial ones may have been involved. Reuben
Hudson and his colleagues, among others, argue that there is “no need for special
conditions of Earth to produce life” and “life can emerge elsewhere in the cosmos.”60
The Emergence of Prokaryotic Cells
The currently prevailing theories about the emergence of prokaryotic cells—bacteria and
archaea—argue that these first types of cells emerged from a common ancestor—a
protocell, or protobiont. A protobiont is an aggregate of abiotically produced organic
molecules capable of replication surrounded by a membrane or a membrane-like structure
and having a capacity for rudimentary metabolism. Membranes performed a very
important role. They separated the internal space from the external environment and
made possible to keep close by the products of the genetic material. Membranes
evidently offered a huge advantage as the enclosed replicators quickly outcompeted
“naked” replicators.61
Biologists who study the emergence of protobionts are still unclear as to how this
structure came about. They recognize that they know “disappointingly little about how
any of these remarkable biological innovations came about.” As Greg Fournier, a
geobiologist at the Massachusetts Institute of Technology and a leading authority in the
field, acknowledges: “It’s very hard to infer even the relative ordering of evolutionary
events before the last common ancestor.” Eric Gaucher, a biologist at the Georgia
Institute of Technology in Atlanta, agrees that there is “a huge chasm between the origins
of life and the last common ancestor.”62
Some researchers believe that three main features—genetic reproduction, metabolism,
and membranes—emerged independently and later combined to form a permanent
structure. Others contend that one of them—for example, genetic replication—emerged
earlier and helped generate the other two features.63 Be that as it may, most researchers
recognize that there is a non-trivial chicken-and-egg problem associated with the origin
of the common ancestral cell.64 The fact is that in order to do its work, the genetic
machinery needs a membrane. Membranes are loaded with proteins. In fact, proteins
account for roughly half the mass of most cellular membranes.65 Thus, the genetic
machinery cannot produce proteins without a membrane, but the synthesizing of
12
membranes requires proteins that can only be produced by the genetic machinery of the
cell.66
There are also additional problems that plague the dominant scenario on the origin of
prokaryotic cells. Most, if not all of them, invoke chance or coincidence to explain the
origin of major cell components. Not only that, but they also invoke chance or
coincidence to explain why these components came together to form a cell. As has been
explained earlier, invoking chance even once is highly problematic; invoking it twice to
explain the same phenomenon makes an explanation very questionable.
Not all biologists subscribe to the scenario that the three major components of life formed
separately. In fact, more and more scientists, including David Deamer and Jack
Szostack, adhere to the so-called “everything-first” hypothesis. John Sutherland at the
MRC Laboratory of Molecular Biology in Cambridge, UK, and his team have concluded
that all the cellular subsystems “could have arisen simultaneously through common
chemistry.”67
Atsushi Kamimura and her colleague Kunihiko Kaneko, both from the University of
Tokyo, have proposed what they call the cluster model.68 They argue that in the case of
the origin of cells, the evolution acted on clusters of interacting organic molecules that
gradually increased their complexity and improved copy fidelity. In other words,
prokaryotes and all their important features emerged as a product of clusters of
interacting organic molecules. The formation of such clusters played a singularly
important role in the origin of prokaryotes. This approach helps solve several problems
at the same time: the emergence of heredity, metabolism, and compartmentalization.69
The path of the “everything-first” hypothesis is still a work-in-progress. Certainly more
theoretical and empirical work is needed to flesh out this perspective, but it does show
promise. The growing number of fossil records reveals aggregations of organic material.
These multi-layer mats varied in thickness and were held together by a sticky glue-like
substance. Such mats could serve as sites for the emergence of the level of organization
that could simultaneously give rise to structures with combined differentiated
components: genetic replication, membranes, and metabolism.70 The advantage of the
“everything-first” hypothesis is that instead of three largely independent processes, this
hypothesis envisions one process that produces all major cellular components at the same
time and there is no need to invoke chance to explain why they combined together to
form a cell.
From Prokaryotes to Eukaryotes
The next important stage in the evolution of early life after the rise of prokaryotic cells
was the formation of modern eukaryotic cells. Most researchers recognize that this stage
of the evolution dramatically departs from the Darwinian model. According to the
Darwinian model, the driving force of the evolution is competition. By practically
universal recognition the rise of eukaryotic cells was due primarily to cooperation. At
13
some point, an archaeon and a bacterium fused together and the two organisms began to
live as one. In this new organism, bacterium became an internal energy producing
organ—mitochondrion. Exactly how this happened is still under debate. Perhaps the
recently discovered earliest closest relative to eukaryotes—Asgard archaea—will
provide at least some necessary answers.71
There are basically two theoretical perspectives on the fusion of archaea and bacteria.
The famous microbiologist Lynn Margolis laid the foundation for one of them in the
1960s. This theory of endosymbiosis, as Margolis called it, contends that the origin of
the modern eukaryotic cell was a result of cell-cell fusion that involved bacteria and
archaea. A cluster of bacteria enclosed in the ancient archaean host transformed into
mitochondria—an essential energy producing component of the modern eukaryotic cell.72
The adaptation of both components to the new and more powerful structure that they
created produced the modern eukaryotic cell, thus opening the path to further evolution. 73
Critics of endosymbiosis have built on the work of those (like Carl Woese, for example)
who argued that populations, rather than individual organisms, are a proper unit of
conservation in this evolution. Woese suggested that biology should conceive the last
universal common ancestor, or LUCA, as a multilineage consortium, rather than some
ancestral organism.74
A group of biologists led Maureen O’Malley and Michelle Leger has formulated a
theoretical perspective that differs significantly from endosymbiosis. In an essay entitled
“Concepts of the Last Eukaryotic Common Ancestor” that has appeared in Nature
Ecology & Evolution O’Malley and her colleagues argue in support of the view that the
last eukaryotic common ancestor (LECA) was not a single cell but really a population of
genetically diverse cells, none of which had all the characteristics associated with the
modern eukaryotes.75 “When we’re talking about LECA,” O’Malley explained in an
interview, “we’re probably talking about an ancestral state, a genomic state that we don’t
know was one single cell.”76 George Mikhailovsky and Richard Gordon also argue that
interactions and horizontal gene transfers between archaea and bacteria may explain why
the transition from prokaryotes to eukaryotes took over 2.5 billion years.77 In other
words, this line of thinking suggests that aggregations of prokaryotes had preceded and
were an important condition for the emergence of eukaryotes.
The verdict is still out as to which of the two hypotheses offers a better understanding of
the process that led to the rise of eukaryotes. However, while the outcome of this
contestation is important, in one sense the outcome makes no difference: in both
scenarios the emergence of eukaryotes was due to cooperation and symbiosis between
bacteria and archaea, not competition. Both perspectives see the emergence of a new and
more powerful level of organization that made the archaeon-bacterium combination
possible. Both hypotheses—whether the rise of eukaryotes involved symbiosis of
individual cells or whether the origin occurred in aggregations of cells—talk about the
emergence of a new level of organization. Their only disagreement is about how this
process occurred. As Ursula Goodenough and Joseph Heitman summarize:
14
The transition from prokaryote to protoeukaryote to the last eukaryotic
common ancestor (LECA) entailed conservation, modification, and
reconfiguration of preexisting genetic circuits via mutation, horizontal
gene transfer (HGT), endosymbiosis, and selection.78
Multicellular Life
For over three billion years since life emerged on our planet, unicellular organisms
dominated the terrestrial environment. Then about 600 to 800 million years ago life
made another major evolutionary leap when cells formed mutlicellular organisms. The
magnitude and complexity of this transition are hard to overestimate. In order to create
this new level of organization, cells had to learn to cooperate. They had to create
common structures in which they divided labor and differentiated their functions. They
produced new and more complex ways of communicating with each other and sharing
resources. They learned to protect the common structure of which they were integral
parts and procure means necessary for its survival. This epic transformation made life on
Earth dramatically different and set a new course for the evolution that created the world
in which we live today.79
The beginning of multicellularity was rather modest. Then about 540 million years ago,
multicellular life erupted into what is known as the Cambrian explosion when a massive
number of animal prototypes emerged. Practically every animal that has ever lived since
that time until today is a variation on one of the body plans that emerged during the
Cambrian explosion.
New details about the transition are still coming out and many are still unknown.
However, some fundamental conclusions have already emerged. Regardless of the
specifics for different lineages and clades, the path of emergence of all multicellular
organisms involved a similar series of steps from the unicellular mode of existence to the
colonial or siphonous mode and finally to the parenchymatous one. As Karl Niklas, a
prominent contributor to the field, concludes:
How exactly steps such as cell-to-cell adhesion or communication were
achieved in plants, animals, fungi, and algae differs among the major
eukaryotic clades, yet an important aspect is that these multicellular
organisms all went through a similar series of steps on their way to
becoming multicellular, functional organisms.80
In all instances cell-to-cell adherence and communication were the conditio sine qua non
that formed the foundation of multicellularity across all clades.81
Many what and why questions about the emergence of multicellular life are still a subject
of heated debates.82 Some researchers argue that the emergence of aggregations
(colonies) of unicellular organisms led to their specialization and differentiation of
functions.83 Others see it as a product of the division of individual cells.84
15
In contrast to the theories of the emergence of life, theories of the emergence of multicellular organisms do not invoke chance or coincidence.85 With much evidential support
they all argue that it was inevitable. Karl Niklas and many other biologists show that the
transition to multicellularity occurred on at least 20 different occasions in different
lineages from algae to plants to fungi.86
Researchers still debate why unicellular organisms formed colonies. Why single cells
began to live together when this common living clearly put them at a fitness
disadvantage? Many biologists find the emergence of colonies puzzling from the point of
view of Darwinian evolution since such collective living increased competition among
cells for resources. As Pierre Durand, a biologist at Wits University, has pointed out, the
solution of this puzzle remains elusive.87
A number of researchers point to serious difficulties on the path to multicellularity.
László Nagy, an evolutionary biologist at the Biological Research Centre of the
Hungarian Academy of Sciences, observes that for all the benefits of multicellularity its
evolution faced major genetic hurdles.88 Yet multicellular life did emerge. Moreover,
the evolutionary histories of some groups of organisms record repeated transitions from
single-celled to multicellular forms, suggesting that the hurdles could not have been so
high.89 Nicole King notes the permeability of the boundary that separates unicellular and
multicellular organisms since some unicellular organisms can easily live either as single
cells or as multi-cellular colonies.90 The fact that multicellular life emerged, endured,
and prospered indicates that conservation had a lot to do with its origin.
Concluding observations
The discussion of the perspectives on the emergence and evolution of early life
warrants some preliminary observations:
1. The accumulated theoretical and empirical knowledge about the origin and
evolution of early life does not fit well with the Darwinian model of the evolution.
In explaining the evolution, Darwinists emphasize variability and natural
selection. Yet variability does not appear to be a prominent factor in the origin of
life or in the course of life’s early evolution. This fact has led some biologist, and
not only biologists, to doubt the role of natural selection during the early stages of
life. John Tyler Bonner, a highly respected figure in the study of early life, is one
of the detractors. Bonner finds intriguing that “extinctions, as in dinosaurs, are
common among mega-organisms, and living fossils, such as the horseshoe crab,
are rare,” which is “in sharp contrast to microorganisms, among which we find
living fossils to be common.” Bonner’s research led to the conclusion that has
raised many brows. He writes in one of his works:
In unicellular microorganisms, which at one time in early
16
Earth history were probably the only living eukaryotic
forms, natural selection plays a relatively minor role, but
with size increase, first made possible by the invention of
multicellularity, selection plays an increasingly central role
in evolutionary change.91
A growing number of researchers find that cooperation and symbiosis were much
more characteristic for early life than competition. Margaret McFall-Ngai and her
collaborators point out that “features once considered exceptional, such as
symbiosis, are now recognized as likely the rule, and novel models for research
are emerging across biology.”92 Leo Mathieu comes to a similar conclusion with
regard to the evolution of prokaryotes. In a chapter characteristically entitled
“Original, Non-Darwinian Evolution of Prokaryotes” he writes:
Associations and mixed communities of prokaryotic strains
are the rule. So, on the basis of what is known about
genetic exchange, metabolite and enzyme sharing,
indications exist that for the overwhelming majority of
prokaryotes the selective pressures have favored
collaboration, not reciprocal or unilateral destruction.
Prokaryotic evolution has been and still is non-Darwinian.93
2. The Darwinian theory has originated and found its primary application in
biology. There are considerable difficulties with applying Darwinian
theory to other fields where evolutionary processes can be observed.94 Its
application to the non-organic domain from which life emerged is
particularly problematic. Yet paradoxically, most current approaches
continue to reflect Darwinian thinking. For example, many of them
maintain that the origin of life involves conservation of a particular
function. Yet they derive this function from the biological realm. As a
result, they face a formidable task of using a biological function to explain
the evolution that begins in the non-organic domain to which this
biological function is not really relevant. Indeed, the origin of life may
involve the conservation of a particular function, but this function should
not be specific to biology; it should be relevant to the evolution of both
life and non-life. In other words, it should have a much broader
application.
3. As has been repeatedly pointed out, the liberal use of chance and
coincidence as an explanatory mode is also a source of concern in theories
about the origin and evolution of early life. The invoking of chance or
coincidence cannot pass the test of rational justification or empirical
verification. Using them every time that discontinuity has to be explained
sends a warning about theoretical limitations that make such explanations
vulnerable to criticism for being subjective and arbitrary. There is ample
evidence showing that continuity and discontinuity play equally important
17
and complementary roles in the evolution. For this reason, the study of
the evolution needs a perspective that would reconcile continuity and
discontinuity and would not see them as opposed to each other. Just as the
concept of evolution compels us to view life and non-life as two distinct
but closely related stages in the origin of life, it also compels us to view
continuity and discontinuity as two equally important and complementary
aspects of the same process.
4. There is also another important concern that relates to all perspectives on
the origin and evolution of early life. They all make valid points that
reflect different aspect of this complex process. An objective view of this
process should include all these perspectives as its particular cases. In
other words, a synthesis of all perspectives will really be beneficial for
understanding the origin and evolution of early life. Yet so far the
prospects for such synthesis look dim. As a result, there is a growing
awareness of the need for a new angle—one that would bring all
perspectives together and open a possibility for a new and comprehensive
vision. One can wholeheartedly agree with William Bains who forcefully
writes in his critique of Deamer’s book Assembling Life:
I argue that the Origin of Life field as a whole is
unconvincing, generating results in Toy Domains that
cannot be scaled to any real world scenario. I suggest that,
by analogy with the history of artificial intelligence and
solar astronomy, we need much more scale, and
fundamentally new ideas, to take the field forward.95
The New Perspective on the Origin and Evolution of Early Life
The study of the origin and evolution of early life is still an ongoing project. Researchers
have formulated many theoretical perspectives and amassed a great deal of information.
Yet a definitive theory remains elusive. Many lacunae are yet to be filled and more facts
are necessary
It is beyond the scope of the present work to complete this task. Its goal is much more
modest. It seeks to provide an angle that could serve as a foundation for a frame that
would be broad enough to include all current perspectives as particular cases—that is,
cases that are true under specific conditions or assumptions.
Although much about the origin and evolution of early life remains unknown, it is not a
closed book either. There is actually quite a lot that we already know and agree. For one
thing, all current perspectives recognize that life represents a new level of organization
that did not exist prior to its emergence. The conclusion that follows from this broad
agreement is that the process that resulted in the emergence and evolution of early life
involved creation.
18
The second point that that all researchers agree on is that life has emerged from inorganic
matter. The idea of the inorganic origin of life is widespread among biologists,
paleontologists, and researchers from other disciplines.96 Darwin’s thinking also reflects
this intuition. He was convinced that “the intimate relation of Life with laws of chemical
combination, and the universality of latter render spontaneous generation not
improbable.”97 If the process that led to the origin and evolution of early life has its roots
in the inorganic domain, then this process is the bridge that connects the two domains.
The processes that create radical novelty either in the domain of life or in the domain of
non-life must have important common features, which suggests a possibility for a
common perspective on the process of creation that operates in both domains.
The Process of Creation and the Universal Evolution
As has already been pointed out, life represents a radical novelty—that is, it represents a
level of organization that did not exist prior to its emergence. We associate radical
novelty with creation. Therefore, we have every reason to view the emergence of life as
a result of the process of creation.
The creative act that led to the emergence of life is not unique to biology, or in fact any
other field. There are many objects and phenomena in our universe that represent radical
novelty—that is, they did not exist prior to their emergence. The process of creation is as
common in the non-living world as it is in life world. The results of this process are all
around: from particles and atoms, to molecules and clouds of molecules, to stars, planets,
galaxies, groups of galaxies and much more. The domain of life also offers numerous
examples of radical novelty: from different types of cellular organisms to various species
of animals and plants, to humans, society, cultures, and civilizations. Each of these
creations represents a new level of organization that is more powerful than the one that
has preceded it and from which it has emerged. Therefore, all these creations are
products of the general process of creation that operates in the universe.
Many scientists have aversion to using the word “creation” because of its religious
connotations. Few researchers use this term as an operational concept. For this reason,
some explanation and demystification of creation is in order to help overcome this
aversion.
One can define the process of creation through an operation that produces something
new—something that has not existed prior to its emergence. The distinct feature of
creation in this sense is its irreducibility.98 We cannot reduce and establish linear causal
connection between the level of organization that has emerged and the level of
organization from which it has emerged. We cannot reduce consciousness to biological
processes that, according to the theory of the evolution, gave rise to it. We cannot explain
how the biological level of organization that sustains insects gives rise to what appears to
be intelligent behavior of insect swarms or colonies.99
19
The process of creation has its roots in the very nature of our universe. Our universe is
unique. It is all there is. Nothing can come into it from outside and nothing can
disappear from it because there is nowhere to disappear. Therefore, everything must be
conserved. Conservation is the fundamental condition of the existence of the universe.
Without conservation the universe simply cannot exist.
Conservation manifests itself at all levels of organization of reality—from physical to
chemical, to biological, and to human social and cultural levels. Examples of
conservation abound. Exploding a stick of dynamite converts chemical energy into
kinetic one. The transformation of the energy of falling water into electricity is another
good example of conservation in action. Conservation is ubiquitous. Due to the ubiquity
of conservation and its connection to the universe we can view conservation as a truly
universal property.
Conservation requires resources. In the universe of finite objects resources are always
limited. Therefore, access to new resources is the only path to conservation. Gaining
access to new resources requires new possibilities that can only come with new and more
powerful levels of organization. When particles combine into atoms or when atoms form
molecules, they acquire a broader range of possibilities, or degrees of freedom. These
new possibilities offer access to new resources that are essential for conservation. Simple
molecules can combine into complex molecules (for example, organic molecules), which
expands their possibilities. Organic molecules allow even more diverse combinations
that create new and even more powerful levels of organization. The emergence of new
and increasingly more powerful levels of organization is the very essence of evolution.
Thus, conservation leads to creation and creation leads to evolution. This process
sustains our universe and everything in it.
All systems that exist in the universe consist of parts, or subsystems. Interactions among
subsystems sustain systems and make their existence possible. These interactions cannot
be chaotic; they and the system as a whole require stability. Therefore, all systems
require regulation that ensures stability and a global regulatory mechanism that provides
regulation. The global regulatory mechanism performs a very important function—one
that sustains the entire system and all its components. However, in order to perform this
function, the regulatory mechanism must also be stabilized and conserved.
Function is a form of action. The only way to conserve action is by acting it out. The
more often a function is enacted, the more stable it is and the better it is conserved. In
order to bring a function into an active state, it must be triggered. This triggering action
comes in the form of a signal that can come from the environment in which the function
operates; it comes from its connections with other functions or systems. Therefore,
establishing connections with entities in its environment is very important for conserving
the regulatory function and the mechanism that performs it.
There are two ways of conserving the global regulatory function: endogenous and
exogenous. The global regulatory mechanism represents a more powerful level of
organization that offers many more possibilities than the level of organization of each
20
subsystem or their sum total. Conservation of a system requires the integration, or
equilibration, of the two levels of organization—local and global. In order to come into
equilibrium, the global level and the local level of organization need to communicate
with each other; in other words, they should have access to each other. Since the global
level is more powerful than the local level, it has access to the latter. The local level,
however, does not have access to the global level, which presents an obstacle to their
equilibration. The overcoming of this obstacle requires the establishment of a frame in
which both the global level and the local level of organization are but two particular
cases. The integration of the two levels of organization enriches local operations and
increases their power. Donald Campbell points to this phenomenon in his discussion of
the so-called “downward causality” that involves the influence of the more powerful
global level of regulation on operations at the local level.100 The equilibration of the two
levels also leads to the differentiation of the global level. Since the frame that makes this
equilibration possible includes both the global and the local level of organization, it
represents a new level of organization that is more powerful than both of them. The
creation of such frame transcends the capabilities of the system and increases its overall
power. With its emergence, the system enters a new cycle in its evolution. Thus
conservation requires combination of differences that leads to the creation of a new level
of organization and thus the evolution of the system as a whole.
The exogenous way of conserving the regulatory mechanism involves its external
connections with other systems and their regulatory mechanism. As has been pointed
out, the global function of regulation represents a level of organization that is more
powerful than that of each individual subsystem or their sum total. In other words, this
function transcends the boundaries of the system and can establish connections with other
systems that exist in its external environment. Such connections with external systems
also trigger the regulatory function into action, thus helping to conserve it. Eventually,
the connections among systems become permanent. The combinations they create result
in the emergence of new levels of organization in which systems begin to function as
subsystems. These new levels of organization are more powerful than that of each
system involved or their sum total. Thus, both the endogenous and the exogenous way of
conservation leads to the creation of new and increasingly more powerful levels of
organization and, thus, to evolution.101
Conservation of function is essential for evolution. Many biologists recognize this fact
and use the functional approach in their OOL models. Karl Niklas, for example,
maintains that functional traits are objects of conservation.102 As has been pointed out
earlier, the problem with the functional approach used by biologists is that they focus on
functions (“privileged functions”) that come from the biological realm. Using a
biological function to explain the emergence of life from inorganic matter presents an
obvious problem. The level of organization that biological functions represent is much
more powerful than the levels of organization in the inorganic (physical or chemical)
domains. Biological functions simply cannot exist at levels of organization of non-living
matter. Using biology to explain processes in the non-organic domain is a form of
organicism, or the reduction of the inorganic world to biology. It simply cannot work
since the level of organization of physical or non-organic chemical processes is less
21
powerful than the level represented by biological processes. The function that gives rise
to life from non-life cannot be limited to biology. It must be related equally to both
domains. It must represent a level of organization in which life and non-life are but two
particular cases.
Conservation is the only function that is fundamental for both life and non-life. As has
been argued earlier, conservation is impossible without creation. This universal process
of creation is the common denominator that covers the two such different domains as life
and non-life. Therefore, the universal process of creation makes for a good foundation
for a comprehensive theoretical perspective on the origin and evolution of early life.
Using the universal process of creation in this capacity is not a subjective or arbitrary
decision. This decision passes the test of rational justification and empirical verification.
Without creating mental structures in their brain, humans would not be able to experience
and interpret reality. Reality for them would be nothing, rather than something. In other
words, an act creating these mental structures is a necessary act without which reality
would not exist for humans. On the empirical level, we see results of numerous acts of
creation all around us. We also have the capacity to create and we have created many
new and increasingly more powerful levels of organization that have given rise to many
radically new forms in science, art, or society. Therefore, one would be fully justified to
use the process of creation as the foundation and the organizing principle of the new
perspective on the origin and evolution of early life.
The Universal Process of Creation and the Evolution of Early Life
The purpose of this study is not to provide an exhaustive description of the origin and
evolution of early life. The completion of this task requires more theoretical and
empirical work. The intention of this study is merely to offer a general model for this
important transition.
There is no reason to suppose that the origin and evolution of early life is an isolated
phenomenon that has nothing to do with the evolution that preceded or followed it. The
very notion of evolution presupposes a continuous process where each preceding stage
gives rise to the one that follows it. The evolution is a process that has roots in the very
nature of the universe. Its fundamental pattern of conservation ! creation ! evolution
is observable at many levels of organization of reality both before and after the origin of
life. The connection between conservation, creation, and evolution has been the subject
of several prior studies that have dealt with the cosmic evolution, the biological
evolution, and the evolution of culture and civilization.103 There is no justifiable reason
to believe that the universal evolution made an exception in the case of the origin and
evolution of early life and abandoned its fundamental pattern only to return to it in the
evolution that followed the early life period.
Conservation was the main reason for the process that gave rise to life and then drove the
evolution from life’s early forms to animals and plants, humans, culture, and civilization.
22
It is one unified process that connects biological evolution with the evolution of the
universe as a whole. Ursula Goudenough points to this singular role of conservation in
the origin and evolution of life.
The transition from prokaryote to protoeukaryote to the last eukaryotic
common ancestor (LECA) entailed conservation, modification, and
reconfiguration of preexisting genetic circuits via mutation, horizontal
gene transfer (HGT), endosymbiosis, and selection, as detailed in previous
articles of this collection.104
The pattern of conservation ! creation ! evolution is in evidence in the evolution of
early life, particularly in the evolution from prokaryotes to eukaryotes and from
eukaryotes to multicellular life. As has been pointed out, the evolution of modern
eukaryotic cells was a product of the cell-cell fusion. The symbiosis of archaea and
bacteria created a new level of organization that integrated them both as component parts
of a single organism.105 The adaptation of archaea and bacteria to the new and more
powerful system that they created produced the modern eukaryotic cell. The prokaryotic
bacterium that was engulfed by the archaeon evolved into mitochondria that became an
important component of the modern cell involved in energy production.106
Conservation played an important role in the evolution of multicellularity. It
drove unicellular organisms to aggregate into colonies that preceded the
emergence of multicellular organisms. Conservation of functional activities
through mutual stimulation was the principal reason for cells to come together.
Interactions with each other stimulated individual unicellular organisms, activated
their vital functions, and thus contributed to their conservation. These
interactions created a new level of organization. Cell-to-cell adherence was the
conditio sine qua non of multicellularity across all clades; cell-to-cell
communication was the basis of multicellular development.107 Adaptation of
individual cells to the new structure led to their functional differentiation,
specialization, and cooperation that created multicellular organisms.108
Although the emergence of organic molecules capable of replication and the rise
of prokaryotic cells needs more theoretical insights and empirical facts, what is
known about this process also points to the important role of conservation. The
verdict is still out as to whether the emergence of prokaryotic cells was a result of
assembly of individual components or, as Kamimura and Kaneko theorize, it was
a product of interactions among molecules in clusters that gradually increased
their complexity and improved copy fidelity.109 The scenario proposed by
Kamimura and Kaneko appears to be more promising as it solves several
problems at the same time: the origin of heredity, metabolism, and
compartmentalization.110 However, no matter what the final verdict is going to
be, both paths point to the importance of conservation, as well as adaptation and
assimilation as two vital aspects of combining and equilibrating required for
creating prokaryotes.
23
The accumulated knowledge shows that the origin and evolution of early life has many
features in common with the general process of creation that operates in the universe.
This fact should not come as a surprise since life is a result of the evolution that preceded
its emergence. There can be no question that life inherited the properties of the evolution
that preceded it and made its emergence possible. All essential features of the general
process of creation that propels the evolution of the universe are also observable in all
stages and transitions involved in the origin and evolution of early life. Since life has
emerged in the course of the evolution of the universe, the fact that it inherited
fundamental features of the universal evolution should not be a surprise. Evolution that
is worthy of its name can only be continuous and continuity involves heritability.
Therefore, there is every reason to view the origin and evolution of early life as an
integral part of the universal process of creation.
Just as in the process of the evolution of the universe, assimilation, adaptation,
and regulation also play a very important role in the evolution of life. The rise of
multicellularity is a good case in point. Many researchers note, for example, that
regulation of interactions among cells played a critical part in the emergence of
multicellularity. According to Ruiz-Trillo and his team, increased fine-tuning of
gene regulation is a key to the successful transition to multicellularity.111
Adaptation is another feature that played a major role in the early evolution of life. For
example, adaptation of cells to multicellular structures and differentiation of their
functions was a very important aspect in this transition. Evolutionary biologists Guy
Cooper and Stuart West at the University of Oxford in the United Kingdom, point out in
their piece that appeared in Nature Biology & Evolution that the process of differentiation
of functions as a form of adaptation to new multicellular conditions “was not a
consequence but a driver” in the evolution of multicellular organisms.112
All current perspectives recognize that the origin and evolution of early life was a
continuous process that involved the emergence of radical novelty; that is to say, they
recognize that both continuity and discontinuity are involved in the evolution. Yet, they
do not show how the two are interrelated and, as a result, cannot resolve the problem of
the relationship between continuity and discontinuity in the origin of life.
Instead of resolving this contradiction, they use a palliative approach that assigns priority
to either to continuity or discontinuity. In order to explain the emergence of radical
novelty, many current OOL perspectives invoke chance or coincidence. The use of
chance in explaining radical novelty undermines the very notion that recognizes
evolution as an autonomous process that does not require external causes.
By contrast, the new perspective maintains that continuity and discontinuity as two equal
and complementary aspects of the evolution. Each new stage in this process has emerged
from the one that preceded it as a result of interactions among systems that it sustains.
These interactions and the combination of differences that they effect create a new and
more powerful level of organization that did not exist prior to its emergence and thus
represents discontinuity. Thus the new perspective shows that each new stage emerges
24
from the one that preceded it and, at the same time, it represents a radical novelty that did
not exist prior to its emergence. Each new stage conserves and enhances the power of the
stage that preceded it. In other words, it shows that continuity and discontinuity are two
equal aspects of the same process that complement each other and play an equally
important role in the evolution.
Due to their failure to reconcile continuity and discontinuity, the current OOL
perspectives cannot create an approach that would be equally applicable to both domains.
As a result, they have to assign priority to either life or to non-life. Those who assign
priority to life, use either functions (“privileged functions”) or forms (common ancestors)
that belong to the domain of life. They use the characteristic features of living organisms
to explain the abiogenesis in the domain of non-life. In other words, they use results to
explain causes. This strategy inverts the cause-effect relationship and uses effects to
explain causes, which is not a methodology acceptable in modern science. Those who
assign priority to non-life—either self-organization or entropy production models—
essentially go to the other extreme. They reduce life to non-life. Prioritizing one realm
over another does not and cannot solve the problem. The solution requires a perspective
that views life and non-life as two particular cases of a more general common frame.
As a result of the failure to recognize the role of local integrative interactions in creating
new and more powerful levels of organization, most current OOL perspectives
overemphasize the role of differentiation; they see the evolution primarily as the process
in which new organisms branched off from some common ancestor. In other words, they
prioritize differentiation over integration. The most vivid example of this prioritization is
elaborate phylogenetic trees that show connections of various organisms to their common
ancestors.
The available evidence about the process of evolution does not support interpretations
that privilege differentiation or, for that matter, integration. The evolution provides no
support for prioritizing either one or the other. A good illustration comes, for example,
from linguistics. The Indo-European theory of the origin of languages that emphasizes
differentiation has not been successful in modeling the actual processes that led to the
emergence of new languages. For example, when archeologist and ethnologists tried to
identify an ethnic group that spoke the hypothetical proto-Slavic language, their efforts
completely failed. Archeological excavations at the location where the theory predicted
that the group had resided found no evidence that humans had ever lived in this marshy
and inhospitable territory. The available evidence has shown, however, that contrary to
the Indo-European theory focused on differentiation, the emergence of major Slavic
languages and the ethnic groups that speak them was a result of processes that involved
integration and differentiation at the same time: the integration of local tribes led to the
differentiation of the major Slavic ethnicities.113
Searching for common ancestors and constructing elaborate phylogenetic trees, as many
current perspectives do, is a formidable task that produces mixed results. Empirical
evidence for the existence of such progenitors is often lacking and may never be
available. There is little guarantee that these postulated ancestors have ever existed or
25
that this existence can be proven. As Maureen O’Malley has pointed out, the idea of a
common ancestor is probably more about “an ancestral state, a genomic state that we
don’t know was one single cell.”114 The search for hypothetical progenitors and the
construction of elaborate phylogenetic trees may very well be, as some researchers point
out, a futile and utterly unhelpful enterprise.115 The evolution is not about changes from
some relatively simple ur-forms, or common ancestors, to more complex forms. The
evolution is about transitions from complexity of one kind to complexity of another kind;
it is about differentiation and integration working in harmony with each other. The new
perspective on the origin and evolution of early life does not prioritize either
differentiation or integration. It views differentiation and integration as two equal and
complementary aspects of the same process.
The evolution is a universal process. As a universal process, it must have some universal
criterion that marks its progress. This criterion must be common to all domains. As has
been argued, evolutionary processes in all domains are about creating new and
increasingly more powerful levels of organization. The result of the evolution is
cascading levels of organization that are nested matryoshka-style in each other. Each
new level of organization conserves and enhances the possibilities of the level that
precedes it and from which it has emerged. Thus the level of organization is the only
criterion that is relevant to all evolutionary processes regardless of a particular domain in
which they are taking place.
Levels of organization have received relatively little attention in the studies of the
evolution. Although many scientists use this term and can and do identify specific levels
of organization, such as subatomic and atomic, molecular, cellular, tissue, organ,
organismal, group, population, community, ecosystem, landscape, biosphere, etc., there is
no widely accepted definition of what a level of organization is. In the absence of a
general and universally accepted definition, this study suggests the following working
definition: A level of organization is a network of structurally connected components
that has its own distinct level of combinatorial power—that is, it offers distinct degrees of
freedom. The characteristic feature of each level of organization is the array of
possibilities that it offers. For example, the nervous system in an organism represents a
level of organization that has sufficient combinatorial power to regulate biological
functions of the organism. Human brain represents another level of organization that is
capable of regulating neural functions and through them physiological functions. Brain
and mind represent the most powerful level of organization that exists in nature. It
derives its power from the capacity to create an infinite number of new and increasingly
more powerful levels of organization that are capable of sustaining an equally infinite
array of forms and behaviors.
Biologists recognize the existence of levels of organization and even use the term.
References to levels of organization are prominent in life sciences; they appear in
introductory textbooks, as well as in cutting-edge research. However, the dominant
evolutionary theories do not see the level of organization as the principal object of
conservation that can be used in explaining the biological evolution. They continue to
focus on the more familiar objects of conservation, such as genes, organisms, or some
26
other specific forms. Moreover, there is also a strong tendency to extend this exclusive
approach to other domains—for example, to the cultural or cognitive evolution by using
objects of conservation borrowed from biological evolution, such as genes.
There are scientists who point to the universal utility of the level of organization. Donald
Campbell, for example, emphasizes that levels of organization are much more useful in
discussing biological evolution than arbitrary schemes of classification.116 Etienne Roux
and his co-editors see biogenesis as “the progressive constitution of spatial and temporal
systems beyond individual proto-metabolic organizations.”117 Alvaro Moreno
approaches prebiotic evolution as the emergence of autocatalytic reaction loops between
molecules leading to compartmentalized self-maintained and self-reproducing
networks.”118 Jan Baedke is yet another representative of this trend. He argues that the
perspective that focuses on levels of organization and their origin helps understand better
the process of the emergence of such innovations as, for example, multicellularity. 119
Viewed from the perspective that focuses on specific forms—one that is used in the
Darwinian model—evolution appears to be an erratic, unsteady, and ambiguous process
punctuated by sudden leaps and reversals that are hard to explain. By contrast, when
viewed from the perspective that focuses on levels of organization, the evolution emerges
as a steady and consistent progress. It shows no exceptions to conservation. No level of
organization has ever become extinct; all levels are conserved. There are no reversals and
no instances of non-conservation. When one views the evolution from the perspective of
forms, one can observe that about 95 per cent of all species that have ever lived have
become extinct. Viewed from the perspective of levels of organization, one can see that
levels of organization that once dominated life world may no longer be dominant; yet
they continue to exist. They have not disappeared but have simply yielded their
dominant position to other more powerful levels of organization. Species that represent
these extant levels survive to this day.
The current OOL perspectives lead into another trap that one can describe as chickenand-egg problem. For example, in explaining the origin of self-replication, researchers
point out that replication requires nucleic acids RNA and DNA for storing information
essential in making proteins for replication. Yet proteins are also necessary for making
nucleic acids. In other words, nucleic acids require proteins, but only nucleic acids can
make these proteins. Both proteins and acids are long molecules that consist of smaller
components that are synthesized also by proteins and acids. Thus, as one researcher aptly
characterized the conundrum, contemporary OOL theories end up with what seems to be
an irresolvable problem of “two chickens and two eggs.”120
The proposed new model avoids this trap. It emphasizes that the proper result of the
evolution is not this or that particular form (protein, acid, or organism). The evolution is
not about forms; it is primarily about the emergence of new and increasingly more
powerful levels of organization that give rise to new forms. In other words, the level of
organization (one can call it the level of “chickeneggness” for the lack of a better term)
that gives rise simultaneously to both the chicken and the egg, or rather many different
kinds of chicken and many different kinds of eggs.
27
As has been pointed out, more powerful levels of organization—that is, levels that
regulate interactions among subsystems—conserve all levels that they regulate. They
include the essential features of the levels on which they supervene and, thus, conserve
them. Humans now dominate Earth. Many species that had at one time been dominant
now exist in some extant forms. However, the level of organization that sustains the
human race retains all the essential features of all the levels of organization that have
preceded it. Nature is frugal and does not like conspicuous consumption. It conserves
only what needs to be conserved. What has already been conserved does not need any
additional conservation.
This is not to argue against the role of adaptation and selection in the evolution. Indeed,
they play an important role but in the processes that take place within levels of
organization, not in the transition from one level of organization to another. The capacity
of adaptation is primarily a result of the level of organization that offers the possibilities
used for adapting.
With this qualification, one can agree with Bonner that natural selection is not a
particularly useful concept in explaining the evolution.121 Each new level of
organization that emerges in the course of the evolution conserves everything that
has preceded it. Even if some species disappear, the levels of organization that
they represented do not. They are conserved. Dinosaurs disappeared long time
ago, but their level of organization is alive and well. Species that represent this
level are still around and live right next to us.
Finally, when viewed from the perspective based on levels of organization, one can see
that the process of the evolution represents a steady increase in power of new emerging
levels of organization all the way to human brain that represents the most powerful level
of organization in nature. Even though many specific organisms have become extinct,
the levels of organization they represented still survive. The evolution of such key
aspects of organism as neural organization and modes of behavior reveals steady increase
in capabilities and power. Pierre Teilhard de Chardin, a famous French philosopher and
paleontologist, was one of the first who pointed to this steady increase in his famous book
The Phenomenon of Man.122 The constant growth of the power of the neural system in
the course of the evolution is a well-documented fact.123
Conclusion
The evolution is integral to the world in which we live. Our universe constantly evolves.
This evolution makes the existence of the universe and the existence of all it contains
possible. The understanding of the evolution is the most important quest in our pursuit of
knowledge, both about us and about our place in the universe.
The study of the origin and evolution of early life is perhaps the most intriguing part of
this quest. It deals with two domains—the domain of life and the domain of non-life.
28
There are hardly any two other domains that are more different than these two. We are so
sure in our intuitive knowledge of the existence of the fundamental boundary that
separates life from non-life that we accept it as self-evident. For us, this difference
requires no proof; it just is.
The study of the origin of life defies this intuitive knowledge. It requires a rational
explanation of how non-life could give rise to life. It forces us to go against our intuition
about the difference between life and non-life and search for their connection. T hat is
why the study of the origin and evolution of early life acquires such particular
significance. The uncompromising liminal location of the origin of life—between the
animate and inanimate world—infringes on established disciplinary boundaries. It
requires the recognition of the autonomy of each domain and defies any prioritization of
one over the other. It permits no reductionism. Rather than look for similarities between
life and non-life, the new theoretical perspective must focus and combine their
differences without reducing them.
Most current perspectives on the origin and evolution of early life accept the Darwinian
model of the evolution. They rest on the foundation of Darwin’s theory. Yet the origin
and evolution of early life in many ways challenge this connection. The core of the
Darwinian model is variability and natural selection. According to this model, natural
selection acts on variations that are due to imperfections in replication or to chance. The
more adaptable variations survive and bring about evolutionary advances. Natural
selection rewards the capacity of an organism to adapt to new conditions.
This model does not really work well in the domain of non-life. The capacity for
adaptation is a distinct feature of life and biological organisms. We cannot really talk
about adaptability of inanimate matter. Atoms certainly do not change when they
combine into molecules; they remain atoms regardless of whether we find them in the
Sun, in interstellar space, or here on Earth.
If there is no variability, natural selection has nothing to act upon—it simply does not
work; and if there is no natural selection, the Darwinian model is not applicable to the
inanimate world. How then can a radical novelty, such as life, emerge from this world
that has no variation on which natural selection can work? The Darwinian model is
completely silent on this matter and simply resorts to various miraculous devices such as
chance or coincidence. That is perhaps the reason why Bonner is skeptical about the
universality of natural selection. He recognizes its applicability to later stages in the
evolution of animals and plants, but not to the evolution of early life. He writes:
In unicellular microorganisms, which at one time in early Earth history
were probably the only living eukaryotic forms, natural selection plays a
relatively minor role, but with size increase, first made possible by the
invention of multicellularity, selection plays an increasingly central role in
evolutionary change.124
29
In a way, Bonner alerts us to a possibility that the Darwinian model may not have
a universal application and a broader view is necessary to explain the general
evolutionary process that led to the emergence of life.
The origin and evolution of early life requires a broader frame than the Darwinian model
that originated in the study of life and deals mostly with the biological realm. Attempts to
apply it to other domains—social, cultural, intellectual, etc.—have produced mixed
result.125 Its applications to the evolution of the universe and the inorganic world in
general are practically non-existent.
Using the Darwinian model in fields other than biology poses a difficult choice: either
one has to reduce a non-biological evolution to biological processes, as the Darwinian
model often does (for example, reducing evolution of human behavior, society or culture
to genetics), or one has to claim that each individual domain has its own unique
evolutionary process that has little to do with evolutionary processes operating other
domains. One route leads to reductionism; the other leads to the proliferation of
dramatically different evolutionary models. This latter route undermines the unity of the
evolution since evolution makes sense only as a unitary process. If we are to take the
evolution seriously, we must recognize that despite some specific differences, the
evolution can exist only as a continuous and unitary process. The evolution of life does
not start from point zero; it has its roots in the evolution of the inanimate world that
precedes it. If we break this vital connection, we have to reject the very notion of
evolution.
The new perspective presented in this study does not prioritize the domain of life over the
domain of non-life. This perspective rests on the recognition of the universal process of
creation that propels the evolution of the universe and everything in it. The choice of the
process of creation as the main organizing principle of the new perspective is not
subjective or arbitrary. It passes the test of rational justification and empirical
verification. Without the process of creation humans would not be able to make any
sense of reality. Only mental constructs that humans create in their mind make their
perceptions of reality and interpretations of these perceptions possible. The universe is
full of examples of wonderful creations that represent increasingly more powerful levels
of organization. Humans inherited this capacity to create in the course of the evolution
that has led to the emergence of humanity. Our entire civilization is the most vivid
example of the power of the process of creation.
The universal process of creation covers both the domain of life and the domain of nonlife. This process is a natural result of conservation that is ubiquitous in the universe and
is the main condition of its existence. Conservation requires creation and creation results
in evolution. Indeed, the exhaustive description of the transition from non-life to life
requires more theoretical and empirical research that will fill remaining lacunae and
provide more evidence. However, the sequence of conservation ! creation ! evolution
is as true for the inanimate world as it is true for the animate one. It is a bridge between
the domain of life and the domain of non-life.
30
Since the process of creation is broad enough to be relevant to the entire universe and
everything in it, the model based on this process also has a broad applicability.
Evolutions in all domains follow the same pattern of conservation ! creation
!evolution. For this reason, the model of the evolution based on the process of creation
is applicable in domains other than biology. In addition to biology, it can be used in
interpretations of the evolution of cosmos, culture, society, intellectual evolution, and
others.126
Both life and non-life conserve themselves by creating new and increasingly more
powerful levels of organization. This is not to deny the difference between life
and non-life. As many biologists have pointed out, the critical difference between
life and non-life is autonomy. Ruiz-Murazo and his co-authors, for example, see
autonomy as the distinct feature of life.127 New and increasingly more powerful
levels of organization emerge in the inanimate world and, obviously, inanimate
matter is involved in these creations. However, inanimate matter is subject to
external forces, such as gravity, magnetism, etc. The drive for conservation in
living organisms is largely internal. Just like non-life, life continues the process
of creating new and increasingly more powerful levels of organization. However,
living organisms have their own internal capacity for securing their own resources
for performing this creative process and thus conserving themselves. They are the
source of their drive that starts with conservation and leads to creation and
evolution.
The new perspective offers a possibility to resolve the problem of the origin of
life without resorting to chance or coincidence. The suggested general path does
not require any miracles. Aggregations of organic molecules with topological
differentiation into the inner and outer regions, their adaptation to this structure,
differentiation and specialization of their functional activities could be the path to
the origin of the level of organization that gives rise to autonomous entities
capable of storing information, as well as harvesting and transmitting available
ambient energy from the environment to their inner zone.
This scenario does not require any chances or coincidences. It describes the same
processes of aggregation, differentiation, and specialization that we can see in the
inorganic world. The only difference is that there is no need for external forces of
compulsion. They occur as a result of the internal momentum to conserve.
Another advantage of the new perspective is that it eliminates contradictions associated
with binary opposites, such as continuity vs. discontinuity, differentiation vs. integration,
determinism vs. indeterminism. The process of creation reconciles these binary
opposites. It shows that they are not ontological opposites but are equal and
complementary aspects of the same process of creation. The connection between these
aspects plays an essential role in the process of creation and hence in the evolution.
The universal evolution is a unitary process. It conserves one important function that
sustains the universe and everything in it: the capacity to create new and increasingly
31
more powerful levels of organization. All stages of the universal evolution conserve this
important function by exercising it in different variations over and over again. Humans
have inherited this function in the course of the evolution that is the source of their
existence. The capacity to create new and increasingly more powerful levels of
organization represents the fundamental promise of their future existence. By performing
this function, humans fulfill their destiny—the destiny that is eternally etched in the
evolution that made the existence of the human race possible.
32
NOTES
1
Erin Garcia de Jesus, “Two New Books Investigate Why It’s so Hard to Define Life.”
Science News, March 17, 2021, https://www.sciencenews.org/article/biology-two-newbooks-why-hard-define-life-meaning.
2
Nick Lane, The Vital Question: Energy, Evolution, and the Origins of Complex Life (New
York: W. W. Norton & Company, 2015), p. 6,
http://archive.org/details/vitalquestionene0000lane.
3
E. Camprubí, J. W. de Leeuw, C. H. House, F. Raulin, M. J. Russell, A. Spang, M. R.
Tirumalai, and F. Westall, “The Emergence of Life,” Space Science Reviews, vol. 215, no. 8
(December 12, 2019), p. 34, https://doi.org/10.1007/s11214-019-0624-8.
4
Kepa Ruiz-Mirazo, Juli Pereto, and Alvaro Moreno, “A universal definition of life: Autonomy
and open-ended evolution,” Origins of Life and Evolution of Biospheres, vol. 34 (2004) 34, pp.
323–46; p. 323.
5
William Bains, “Getting Beyond the Toy Domain: Meditations On David Deamer’s
“Assembling Life,” Life, vol. 10, no. 18 (2020), p. 1.
6
Carl Sagan, “Life,” The Encyclopedia Britannica (London: William Benton, 1970); RuizMirazo et al., “A universal definition of life,” p. 327.
7
NASA, “About Life Detection,” Astrobiology at NASA/Life in the Universe,
https://astrobiology.nasa.gov/research/life-detection/about.
8
Claus Emmeche, “Defining Life as a Semiotic Phenomenon,” Cybernetics and Human
Knowing, vol. 5 (1998), pp. 3–17; Ruiz-Mirazo et al, “A Universal Definition of Life,” p. 326.
9
R. Shapiro and G. Feinberg, “Possible Forms of Life in Environments Very Different from the
Earth,” in J. Leslie (ed.), Physical Cosmology and Philosophy (New York: MacMillan, 1990),
pp. 248-55.
10
F. Varela, F. J.: 1994, “On Defining Life,” in G. R. Fleischaker, S. Colonna and P. L. Luisi
(eds.), Self-Production of Supramolecular Structures: From Synthetic Structures to Models of
Minimal Living Systems (Dordrecht: Springer, 1994), pp. 23–33; F. Varela and H. Maturana,
Autopoiesis and Cognition: The Realization of the Living (Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing
Company, 1972); F. Varela, H. Maturana, R. Uribe, “Autopoiesis: the organization of living
systems, its characterization and a model,” Currents in Modern Biology, vol. 5 (1976), pp. 18796, PMID 4407425 DOI: 10.1016/0303-2647(74)90031-8.
11
Ruiz-Mirazo, “A universal definition of life,” p. 330.
12
Addy Pross, “Physical Organic Chemistry and the Origin of Life Problem: A Personal
Perspective,” Israel Journal of Chemistry, vol. 56, no. 1 (January 2016), pp. 83–88,
https://doi.org/10.1002/ijch.201500073, p. 87.
33
13
Kathryn A. Lanier and Loren Dean Williams, “The Origin of Life: Models and Data,” Journal
of Molecular Evolution (2017), p. 1.
14
Lanier, “The Origin of Life: Models and Data,” Journal of Molecular Evolution, p. 1.
15
Wim Hordijk, “Autocatalytic Sets: From the Origin of Life to the Economy,” BioScience, vol.
63, no. 11 (November 2013), pp. 877–81; pp. 880-81; pp. 880-81, https://doi.org/10.1525/bio.20.
16
John E. Stewart, “The Meaning of Life in a Developing Universe,” Foundations of Science,
vol. 15, no. 4 (November 2010), pp. 395–409; p. 2. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-010-9184-9.
17
Stewart, “The Meaning of Life in a Developing Universe,” p. 1.
18
Stewart, “The Meaning of Life in a Developing Universe,” p. 15.
19
Lanier and Williams, “The Origin of Life: Models and Data”; William F. Martin, Filipa L.
Sousa, and Nick Lane, “Energy at Life’s Origin: Analysis of the Bioenergetics of Primitive
Organisms Suggests That Life Began at Hydrothermal Vents,” Science, vol. 344, no. 6188
(2014), pp. 1092–93; V. Sojo, B. Herschy, A. Whicher A, E. Camprubí, and N. Lane, “The origin
of life in alkaline hydrothermal vents,” Astrobiology, vol. 16 (2016), pp. 181–97.
20
G. Ourisson and Y. Nakatani, “The terpenoid theory of the origin of cellular life: the evolution
of terpenoids to cholesterol,” Chemical Biology, vol. 1 (1994), pp. 11–23; E. Koonin and W.
Martin, “On the origin of genomes and cells within inorganic compartments,” Trends in Genetics,
vol. 21 (2005), pp. 647–654; J. Szostak, D. Bartel, and P. Luisi, “Synthesizing life,” Nature vol.
409 (2001), pp. 387–390.
21
Lanier and Williams, “The Origin of Life: Models and Data.”
22
Camprubí, et al., “The Emergence of Life,” p. 56; see also Adrian Bejan and Sylvie Lorente,
“Constructal Law of Design and Evolution: Physics, Biology, Technology, and Society,” Journal
of Applied Physics, vol. 113 (n.d.); Roy Murphy, “Inevitability of Life,” Medium (October 26,
2018), https://medium.com/@DrRoyMurphy/inevitability-of-life-b7cc7dde1639.
23
Eric Karsenti, “Self-Organization in Cell Biology: A Brief History,” Nature Reviews
Molecular Cell Biology, vol. 9, no. 3 (March 2008), pp. 255–62,
https://doi.org/10.1038/nrm2357, p. 261.
24
Nigel Goldenfeld and Carl Woese, “Life Is Physics: Evolution as a Collective Phenomenon
Far from Equilibrium,” ArXiv:1011.4125 [Cond-Mat, q-Bio], November 17, 2010,
http://arxiv.org/abs/1011.4125; pp. 1 and 15 (emphasis added).
25
Derek McCusker, “Cellular Self-Organization: Generating Order from the Abyss,” Molecular
Biology of the Cell, vol. 31, no. 3 (January 30, 2020), pp. 143–48,
https://doi.org/10.1091/mbc.E19-04-0207; Goldenfeld and Woese. “Life Is Physics; William
Graham, William, “Nature’s Self Organizing Patterns,” Nature’s Web Of Life (May 2, 2014).
http://www.freshvista.com/2014/natures-self-organizing-patterns/; Yoshiharu Mukouyama and
Yoshihiro Nakato, “Dynamic Self-Organization in an Open Reaction Network as a Fundamental
Mechanism for the Emergence of Life,” ChemRxiv, December 7, 2020,
34
https://chemrxiv.org/articles/preprint/Dynamic_Selforganization_in_an_Open_Reaction_Network_as_a_Fundamental_Mechanism_for_the_Emergen
ce_of_Life/13332458, https://doi.org/10.26434/chemrxiv.13332458.v1; Eric Karsenti, “SelfOrganization in Cell Biology: A Brief History.” Nature Reviews Molecular Cell Biology 9, no. 3
(March 2008): 255–62. https://doi.org/10.1038/nrm2357.
26
Karsenti, Eric. “Self-Organization in Cell Biology: A Brief History,” p. 255.
27
Graham, “Nature’s Self Organizing Patterns”; McCusker, “Cellular Self-Organization:
Generating Order from the Abyss”; David Korten, “Life’s Ability to Self-Organize and Learn,”
David Korten (blog). Accessed January 14, 2021. https://davidkorten.org/the-new-economy/lifeas-teacher/; Eric Karsenti, “Self-Organization in Cell Biology.”
28
Roland Wedlich-Söldner and Timo Betz, “Self-Organization: The Fundament of Cell
Biology,” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, vol. 373, no.
1747 (May 26, 2018), p. 20170103, https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2017.0103.
29
Natalie Wolchover, “A New Thermodynamics Theory of the Origin of Life,” Quanta Magazine
(January 22, 2014), https://www.quantamagazine.org/a-new-thermodynamics-theory-of-theorigin-of-life-20140122/; Natalie Wolchover, “A New Physics Theory of Life,” Scientific
American (June 27, 2017), https://www.scientificamerican.com/article/a-new-physics-theory-oflife/.
30
Roy Murphy, “Inevitability of Life.”
31
Natalie Wolchover, “A New Physics Theory of Life.”
32
Lanier and Williams, “The Origin of Life,” p. 7.
33
Pross, “Physical Organic Chemistry and the Origin of Life Problem,” p. 83.
34
John R Searle, The Construction of Social Reality (New York: Free Press, 1995), pp. 150-55.
Shkliarevsky, The Civilization at a Crossroads: Constructing the Paradigm Shift (Raleigh, N. C.:
Glasstree Publishing, 2017), particularly pp. 245-46.
35
“Online Event: Origins of life with Sean B Carroll,” New Scientist, April 22, 2021,
https://www.newscientist.com/science-events/origins-life-sean-bcarroll/?utm_source=nscon&utm_medium=email&utm_campaign=18022021-big-thinkerorigins-of-life&.
36
Jean Bricmont, “Determinism, Chaos, and Quantum Mechanics” (n.d.),
http://www.freeinfosociety.com/pdfs/mathematics/determinism.pdf; Jean Bricmont, Making
Sense of Quantum Mechanics, 1st ed. (New York: Springer, 2016); M. Buchanan, “Quantum
Randomness May Not Be Random,” New Scientist (online edition).
https://www.newscientist.com/article/mg19726485-700-quantum-randomness-may-not-berandom/, p. 1034a; H. Atmanspacher and R. Bishop, eds., Between Chance and Choice:
Interdisciplinary Perspectives on Determinism (Thorverton: Imprint Academic, 2002).
37
K. Laland, G. A. Wray, H. E. Hoekstra, et al., (2014), ”Does evolutionary theory needs a
rethink?” Nature, vol. 514 (2014), pp. 161-64; also W. Arthur, Biased Embryos and Evolution
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004).
35
38
Christian de Duve, A Guided Tour of the Living Cell (New York: W. H. Freeman and Co.,
1985).
39
Christian de Duve, A-Z Quotes (n.d.) https://www.azquotes.com/quote/730686
40
Keith Cooper, “Looking for LUCA, the Last Universal Common Ancestor,” Phys.org
(December 18, 2018), https://phys.org/news/2018-12-luca-universal-common-ancestor.html.
41
Ursula Goodenough and Joseph Heitman, “Origins of Eukaryotic Sexual Reproduction.” Cold
Spring Harbor Perspectives in Biology, vol. 6, no. 3 (March 1, 2014), p. a016154,
https://doi.org/10.1101/cshperspect.a016154.
42
Brad Harrub and Bert Thompson, “The Origin of Gender and Sexual Reproduction,” TJ, vol.
18, no. 1 (2004), pp. 120–28, https://creation.com/images/pdfs/tj/j18_1/j18_1_120-127.pdf.
43
Goodenough and Heitman, “Origins of Eukaryotic Sexual Reproduction,” a016154.
44
Carl Zimmer, “On the Origin of Sexual Reproduction,” Science, vol. 324, no. 5932 (June 5,
2009), pp. 1254–56, https://doi.org/10.1126/science.324_1254, p. 1254.
45
Richard Dawkins, The Blind Watchmaker (New York: W.W. Norton, New York, 1986), p.
130.
46
G. Bell, The Masterpiece of Nature: The Evolution and Genetics of
Sexuality (Berkley: University of California Press, 1982), pp. 77–78.
47
Laurence D. Hurst, “Why Did Sex Evolve? Researchers Edge Closer to Solving Longstanding
Mystery,” The Conversation (February 29, 2016), http://theconversation.com/why-did-sexevolve-researchers-edge-closer-to-solving-longstanding-mystery-55407.
48
Bin Liu, G. Charalampos, Jim Pappas, Gaël Schaeffer, Christoph Jurissek, Priscilla F. Pieters,
Meniz Altay, Ivana Marić, Marc C. A. Stuart, and Sijbren Otto, “Spontaneous Emergence of SelfReplicating Molecules Containing Nucleobases and Amino Acids,” Journal of the American
Chemical Society, vol. 142, no. 9 (March 4, 2020), pp. 4184–92,
https://doi.org/10.1021/jacs.9b10796.
49
Hordijk, “Autocatalytic Sets: From the Origin of Life to the Economy,” pp. 880-881.
50
A. Oparin, Origin of Life (Moscow: Moscovskij Rabochij, 1924); J. Haldane, “The Origin of
Life,” Rationalist Annual (1929).
51
Bains, “Getting Beyond the Toy Domain. Meditations On David Deamer’s “Assembling Life,”
p. 1.
52
James Trefil, “The Origin of Life,” American Scientist (February 6, 2017),
https://www.americanscientist.org/article/the-origin-of-life.
53
Bains, “Getting Beyond the Toy Domain,” p. 1; Gerald Bergtrom, “20.5: Origins of Life
Chemistries in an RNA World,” Biology LibreTexts, January 3, 2021,
36
https://bio.libretexts.org/Bookshelves/Cell_and_Molecular_Biology/Book%3A_Basic_Cell_and_
Molecular_Biology_(Bergtrom)/20%3A_The_Origins_of_Life/20.05%3A_Origins_of_Life_Che
mistries_in_an_RNA_World.
54
E. Camprubí, J. W. de Leeuw, C. H. House, F. Raulin, M. J. Russell, A. Spang, M. R.
Tirumalai, and F. Westall, “The Emergence of Life,” Space Science Reviews, vol. 215, no. 8
(December 12, 2019): 56. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11214-019-0624-8; “Darwin Correspondence
Project,” http://www.darwinproject.ac.uk/.
55
Camprubí, et al., “The Emergence of Life,” p. 56.
56
J. D. Bernal, “The physical basis of life,” Proc. Phys. Society, vol. 62 (1949), pp. 537–555;
A.G. Cairns-Smith, Genetic Takeover and the Mineral Origins of Life (Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge, 1982).
57
William F. Martin, Filipa L. Sousa, and Nick Lane, “Energy at Life’s Origin: Analysis of the
Bioenergetics of Primitive Organisms Suggests That Life Began at Hydrothermal Vents,”
Science, vol. 344, no. 6188 (2014), pp. 1092–93.
58
Royal Holloway, “Organic Materials Essential for Life on Earth Are Found for the First Time
on the Surface of an Asteroid,” Phys.org (March 4, 2021), https://phys.org/news/2021-03materials-essential-life-earth-surface.html; Rueben Hudson, et al., “Process That Might Have Led
to First Organic Molecules: New Research Could Have Relevance to Search for Extraterrestrial
Life, Green Chemistry,” ScienceDaily (September 8, 2020),
https://www.sciencedaily.com/releases/2020/09/200908170535.htm; Lisa Grossman, “CarbonRing Molecules Tied to Life Were Found in Space for the First Time,” Science News (March 22,
2021), https://www.sciencenews.org/article/carbon-ring-molecules-life-found-space-first-time.
59
NASA, “Key Building Block for Organic Molecules Discovered in Meteorites,” Lab Manager
(December 28, 2020), https://www.labmanager.com/news/key-building-block-for-organicmolecules-discovered-in-meteorites-24712; Hudson, et al., “Process That Might Have Led to
First Organic Molecules”; Dimitar Sasselov, John P. Grotzinger, and John D. Sutherland, “The
Origin of Life as a Planetary Phenomenon,” Science Advances, vol. 6, no. 6 (February 1, 2020), p.
eaax3419, https://doi.org/10.1126/sciadv.aax3419; Steven A. Benner, Hyo-Joong Kim, MyungJung Kim, and Alonso Ricardo, “Planetary Organic Chemistry and the Origins of Biomolecules,”
Cold Spring Harbor Perspectives in Biology, vol. 2, no. 7 (July 2010),
https://doi.org/10.1101/cshperspect.a003467.
60
Hudson, et al. “Process That Might Have Led to First Organic Molecules: New Research Could
Have Relevance to Search for Extraterrestrial Life, Green Chemistry,” ScienceDaily (September
8, 2020), https://www.sciencedaily.com/releases/2020/09/200908170535.htm.
61
Textbook. “From Soup to Cells - the Origin of Life.” Evolution (accessed February 21, 2021),
https://evolution.berkeley.edu/evo101/IIE2bDetailsoforigin.shtml; Harvey Lodish, et al.,
Molecular Cell Biology (New York: W. H. Freeman, 2000),
https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/books/NBK21570/.
62
Emily Singer, “How Structure Arose in the Primordial Soup,” Scientific American (May 19,
2015), https://www.scientificamerican.com/article/how-structure-arose-in-the-primordial-soup/.
37
63
Sven B. Gould, “Membranes and Evolution,” Current Biology, vol. 28 (2018), p. R381;
Michael Marshall, “Life’s Big Bang,” New Scientist, vol. 247, no. 3294 (August 8, 2020), pp. 34–
38, https://doi.org/10.1016/s0262-4079(20)31377-4.
64
Robert F. Service, “Researchers May Have Solved Origin-of-Life Conundrum,” Science
(March 16, 2015), https://www.sciencemag.org/news/2015/03/researchers-may-have-solvedorigin-life-conundrum.
65
Nature Briefing. “Cell Membranes | Learn Science at Scitable,” accessed March 27, 2021,
https://www.nature.com/scitable/topicpage/cell-membranes-14052567/.
66
Marshall, Michael. “Life’s Big Bang” New Scientist 247, no. 3294 (August 8, 2020); Service,
“Researchers May Have Solved Origin-of-Life Conundrum.”
67
Marshall, “Life’s Big Bang.”
68
Atsushi Kamimura and Kunihiko Kaneko, “Molecular Diversity and Network Complexity in
Growing Protocells,” ArXiv:1904.08094 [q-Bio], April 17, 2019,
http://arxiv.org/abs/1904.08094.
69
Kate Mcalpine, “Cluster Model Shows How First Cells Could Have Divided,” New Scientist
(January 5, 2011), https://www.newscientist.com/article/mg20927942-400-cluster-model-showshow-first-cells-could-have-divided/; Kate Mcalpine, “In the Beginning Was Naked Genetic
Material,” New Scientist, vol. 209, no. 2794 (January 8, 2011), https://doi.org/10.1016/S02624079(11)60017-1.
70
Marshall, “Life’s Big Bang”; CheggStudy, “Learn About Origin Of Prokaryotic Cells,”
CheggStudy, accessed March 26, 2021, https://www.chegg.com/learn/biology/introduction-tobiology/origin-of-prokaryotic-cells.
71
Marshall, “Life’s Big Bang.”
72
Nick Lane, Origins of Life: An Improbably Journey; Adrian Woolfson, “Origins of Life: An
Improbable Journey,” Nature, vol. 520 (April 29, 2015), pp. 617–18,
https://doi.org/10.1038/520617a; p. 617.
73
Lynn Margulis, Origin of Eukaryotic Cells: Evidence and Research Implications for a Theory
of the Origin and Evolution of Microbial, Plant, and Animal Cells on the Precambrian Earth
(New Haven: Yale University Press, 1970); Lynn Margulis, “Symbiosis and Evolution,”
Scientific American, vol. 225, no. 2 (1971), pp. 48–61; Nick Lane, The Vital Question: Energy,
Evolution, and the Origins of Complex Life (New York: W. W. Norton & Company, 2015),
http://archive.org/details/vitalquestionene0000lane; Nick Lane and William F. Martin,
“Mitochondria, Complexity, and Evolutionary Deficit Spending,” Proceedings of the National
Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, vol. 113, no. 6 (2016), pp. E666–E666;
Woolfson, “Origins of Life: An Improbable Journey”; Biology Libre Texts, “Eukaryotic Origins”
(2020,
https://bio.libretexts.org/Bookshelves/Introductory_and_General_Biology/Book%3A_Concepts_i
n_Biology_(OpenStax)/13%3A_Diversity_of_Microbes_Fungi_and_Protists/13.2%3A_Eukaryot
ic_Origins.
38
74
Carl Woese, “The Universal Ancestor,” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, vol.
95, no. 12 (June 9, 1998), pp. 6854–59, https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.95.12.6854.
75
M. O’Malley, M. M. Leger, Jeremy G. Wideman, and I. Ruiz-Trillo, “Concepts of the Last
Eukaryotic Common Ancestor,” Nature Ecology & Evolution, vol. 3 (2019), pp. 338-44,
https://doi.org/10.1038/s41559-019-0796-3.
76
Christie Wilcox, “Rethinking the Ancestry of the Eukaryotes,” Quanta Magazine (April 9,
2019), https://www.quantamagazine.org/rethinking-the-ancestry-of-the-eukaryotes-20190409/.
77
George E. Mikhailovsky and Richard Gordon, “LUCA to LECA, the Lucacene: A Model for
the Gigayear Delay from the First Prokaryote to Eukaryogenesis,” Biosystems, preprint, (April 1,
2021), 104415, https://doi.org/10.1016/j.biosystems.2021.104415.
78
Goodenough and Heitman. “Origins of Eukaryotic Sexual Reproduction,” p. 1.
79
John Tyler Bonner, First Signals: The Evolution of Multicellular Development, 1st edition
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2001); Karl J. Niklas and Stuart A. Newman, eds.,
Multicellularity: Origins and Evolution, 1st edition (Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 2016);
Elizabeth Pennisi, “The Momentous Transition to Multicellular Life May Not Have Been so Hard
after All,” Science (June 28, 2018), https://www.sciencemag.org/news/2018/06/momentoustransition-multicellular-life-may-not-have-been-so-hard-after-all; Karl Niklas and Stuart
Newman, “The Origins of Multicellular Organisms,” Evolution & Development, vol. 15 (January
21, 2013), pp. 41–52, https://doi.org/10.1111/ede.12013; Kat McGowan, “How Life Made the
Leap From Single Cells to Multicellular Animals,” Wired (August 1, 2014),
https://www.wired.com/2014/08/where-animals-come-from/.
80
Karl Niklas, “From One Cell to Many: How Did Multicellularity Evolve?” ScienceDaily
(January 25, 2014), https://www.sciencedaily.com/releases/2014/01/140125172414.htm.
81
Karl Niklas and Stuart Newman, “The Origins of Multicellular Organisms,” p. 42.
82
Thibaut Brunet and Nicole King, “The Origin of Animal Multicellularity and Cell
Differentiation,” Developmental Cell, vol. 43, no. 2 (October 23, 2017), pp. 124–40,
https://doi.org/10.1016/j.devcel.2017.09.016.
83
Niklas and Newman, eds., Multicellularity: Origins and Evolution; Niklas, “From One Cell to
Many: How Did Multicellularity Evolve?”
84
Brunet and King, “The Origin of Animal Multicellularity and Cell Differentiation,” p. 127.
85
John Bonner, “Evolution, by Chance?” New Scientist, vol. 219, no. 2926 (July 20, 2013), pp.
26–27, https://doi.org/10.1016/S0262-4079(13)61798-4; John Tyler Bonner, Randomness in
Evolution (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2013),
https://press.princeton.edu/books/hardcover/9780691157016/randomness-in-evolution.
86
Niklas. “From One Cell to Many”; Kat McGowan, “How Life Made the Leap From Single
Cells to Multicellular Animals.” Wired (August 1, 2014), https://www.wired.com/2014/08/whereanimals-come-from/. Niklas, Karl, and Stuart Newman. “The Origins of Multicellular
Organisms.”
39
87
Erik R. Hanschen, “How and Why Single Cell Organisms Evolved into Multicellular Life,”
Phys.org (April 25, 2016).
88
Pennisi, “The Momentous Transition to Multicellular Life May Not Have Been so Hard after
All.”
89
Pennisi, “The Momentous Transition to Multicellular Life May Not Have Been so Hard after
All.”
90
Pennisi, “The Momentous Transition to Multicellular Life May Not Have Been so Hard after
All”; McGowan, “How Life Made the Leap From Single Cells to Multicellular Animals.”
91
John Tyler Bonner, “The Evolution of Evolution: Seen through the Eyes of a Slime Mold,”
BioScience, vol. 65, no. 12 (December 1, 2015), pp. 1184–87,
https://doi.org/10.1093/biosci/biv154, p. 1184 (emphasis added).
92
Margaret McFall-Ngai, Michael G. Hadfield, Thomas C. G. Bosch, Hannah V. Carey,
Tomislav Domazet-Lošo, Angela E. Douglas, Nicole Dubilier, et al., “Animals in a Bacterial
World, a New Imperative for the Life Sciences,” Proceedings of the National Academy of
Sciences, vol. 110, no. 9 (February 26, 2013), pp. 3229–36,
https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1218525110. p. 3234.
93
Sorin Sonea and Léo G. Mathieu, “Chapter III. Original, Non-Darwinian Evolution of
Prokaryotes,” on Prokaryotology : A Coherent Point of View (Montréal: Presses de
l’Université de Montréal, 2018), pp. 73–88. http://books.openedition.org/pum/14303.
94
Gennady Shkliarevsky, “The Evolution of Civilization as a Process of Creation,” SSRN
Scholarly Paper (Rochester, NY: Social Science Research Network, January 28, 2020),
https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3526961.
95
Bains, “Getting Beyond the Toy Domain. Meditations On David Deamer’s Assembling Life.”
96
A.G. Cairns-Smith, Genetic Takeover and the Mineral Origins of Life (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1982); E. Camprubi, S.F. Jordan, R. Vasiliadou, N. Lane, “Iron catalysis at the
origin of life,” Life, vol. 69, no. 6 (2017), pp. 373–381; N. Lane, J.F. Allen, W. Martin, “How did
LUCA make a living? Chemiosmosis in the origin of life,” BioEssays, vol. 32 (2010), pp. 271–
280.
97
J. Peretó, J.L. Bada, A. Lazcanol, “Charles Darwin and the origin of life, Orig. Life Evol.
Biosph, vol. 39, no. 5 (2009), pp. 395–406.
98
Gennady Shkliarevsky, “Quantum Discontents, or What Is Wrong with Our Science Practice,”
Philosophies, vol. 3, no. 4 (November 23, 2018), https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies3040040,
pp. 7-8.
99
For more on the process of creation see Gennady Shkliarevsky, “Understanding the Process of
Creation: A New Approach,” Manag. J. Sustain. Bus. Manag. Solut. Emerg. Econ., vol. 22
(2017), pp. 1–13; S. Kauffman, “A God of Creativity,” New Science, vol. 198 (2008), pp. 52–53;
S. Kauffman, Humanity in a Creative Universe (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016); I.
40
Prigogine, and I. Stengers, Order out of Chaos: Man’s New Dialogue with Nature (Toronto:
Bantam Books, 1984).
100
D. Campbell, D. (2013). “Downward Causation in Hierarchically Organized Biological
Systems,” E:CO , vol. 15, no.3, pp. 139–51; Gennady Shkliarevsky, Conservation, Creation, and
Evolution, p. 40.
101
For more on how the process of creation works, see Gennady Shkliarevsky, “Understanding
the Process of Creation: A New Approach,” Management: Journal of Sustainable Business and
Management Solutions in Emerging Economies, vol. 22, no. 3 (October 31, 2017), pp. G1–13,
https://doi.org/10.7595/management.fon.2017.0021; Gennady Shkliarevsky, “Conservation,
Creation, and Evolution: Revising the Darwinian Project,” Journal of Evolutionary Science , vol.
1, no. 2 (September 25, 2019), pp. 27-57, https://doi.org/10.14302/issn.2689-4602.jes-19-2990;
Gennady Shkliarevsky, “The Evolution of Civilization as a Process of Creation,” SSRN Scholarly
Paper (Rochester, NY: Social Science Research Network, January 28, 2020),
https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3526961; Gennady Shkliarevsky, The Civilization at a Crossroads:
Constructing the Paradigm Shift (Raleigh, NC: Glasstree Publishing, 2017),
https://www.researchgate.net/publication/318431832_The_Civilization_at_a_Crossroads_Constru
cting_the_Paradigm_Shift.
102
Niklas. “From One Cell to Many: How Did Multicellularity Evolve?”
103
Shkliarevsky, “Conservation, Creation, and Evolution”; Gennady Shkliarevsky, “Revising the
Cosmic Story.” ArXiv:2012.12749 [Physics], December 23, 2020,
http://arxiv.org/abs/2012.12749; Gennady Shkliarevsky, “The Evolution of Civilization as a
Process of Creation.”
104
Goodenough and Heitman. “Origins of Eukaryotic Sexual Reproduction,” p. 1.
105
Margulis, Origin of Eukaryotic Cells; Lane, The Vital Question.
Margulis, Origin of Eukaryotic Cells; Margulis, “Symbiosis and Evolution”; Lane, The Vital
Question; Nick Lane and William F. Martin, “Mitochondria, Complexity, and Evolutionary
Deficit Spending,” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of
America, vol. 113, no. 6 (2016): E666–E666; Woolfson, “Origins of Life”; Biology Libre Texts.
Eukaryotic Origins.
106
107
Niklas and Newman. “The Origins of Multicellular Organisms,” p. 42.
108
Niklas, “From One Cell to Many: How Did Multicellularity Evolve?”
109
Kamimura and Kaneko, “Molecular Diversity and Network Complexity in Growing
Protocells.”
110
Mcalpine, “Cluster Model Shows How First Cells Could Have Divided”; Kate McAlpine, “In
the Beginning Was Naked Genetic Material,” New Scientist, vol. 209, no. 2794 (January 8, 2011),
https://doi.org/10.1016/S0262-4079(11)60017-1.
111
Pennisi, “The Momentous Transition to Multicellular Life.”
112
Pennisi, “The Momentous Transition to Multicellular Life.”
41
113
Михало Брайчевский, M. (1968). Походження Русі (Kиїв:_Наукова думка. 1968).
114
Christie Wilcox, Christie. “Rethinking the Ancestry of the Eukaryotes.”
115
T. Guidotti, “The Phylogenetic Tree Topples,” American Scientist.(2006)
http://www.americanscientist.org/issues/pub/2006/3/the-phylogenetic-tree-topples.
116
Campbell, “Downward Causation in Hierarchically Organized Biological Systems”;
Shkliarevsky, “Conservation, Creation, and Evolution,” p. 43.
117
Etienne Roux, Marko Marhl, and Matteo Mossio, “Editorial: Multilevel Organization and
Functional Integration in Organisms,” Frontiers in Physiology, vol. 12 (January 28, 2021), pp. 46. https://doi.org/10.3389/fphys.2021.626977.
118
Alvaro Moreno, “The Origin of a Trans-Generational Organization in the Phenomenon of
Biogenesis,” Frontiers in Physiology, vol. 12 (January 28, 2021), pp. 127-136,
https://doi.org/10.3389/fphys.2021.626977.
119
Jan Baedke, “The Origin of New Levels of Organization” (preprint), ResearchGate, 2021.
120
James Trefil, “The Origin of Life,” American Scientist (February 6, 2017),
https://www.americanscientist.org/article/the-origin-of-life.
121
Bonner, “The Evolution of Evolution,” p. 1184.
122
Pierre Teilhard de Chardin, The Phenomenon of Man (New York: Harper & Row Publishers.
1959).
123
J. Niven and I. Chittka, (2016), “Evolving Understanding of Nervous System Evolution,”
Current Biology, vol. 26 (2016).
124
Bonner, “The Evolution of Evolution,” p. 1184 (emphasis added).
125
Shkliarevsky, “The Evolution of Civilization as a Process of Creation.”
126
Shkliarevsky, “Revising the Cosmic Story.”
127
Ruiz-Mirazo, et al., “A universal definition of life.”
42
REFERENCES
“Cell Membranes | Learn Science at Scitable.” Nature Briefing, accessed March 27, 2021,
https://www.nature.com/scitable/topicpage/cell-membranes-14052567/.
“Darwin Correspondence Project,” http://www.darwinproject.ac.uk/.
“From Soup to Cells - the Origin of Life.” Evolution (textbook). Accessed February 21, 2021),
https://evolution.berkeley.edu/evo101/IIE2bDetailsoforigin.shtml.
Arthur, W. Biased Embryos and Evolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004.
Atmanspacher, H. and R. Bishop, R. Eds. Between Chance and Choice: Interdisciplinary
Perspectives on Determinism. Thorverton: Imprint Academic, 2000.
Baedke, Jan. “The Origin of New Levels of Organization” (preprint), ResearchGate, 2021.
Bains, William. “Getting Beyond the Toy Domain: Meditations On David Deamer’s
‘Assembling Life.’” Life, vol. 10, no. 18 (2020).
Bejan, Adrian, and Lorente, Sylvie. “Constructal Law of Design and Evolution: Physics,
Biology, Technology, and Society.” Journal of Applied Physics, vol. 113 (n.d.).
Bell, G. The Masterpiece of Nature: The Evolution and Genetics of Sexuality. Berkley:
University of California Press, 1982.
Benner, Steven A., Kim, Hyo-Joong, Kim, Myung-Jung, and Ricardo, Alonso. “Planetary
Organic Chemistry and the Origins of Biomolecules.” Cold Spring Harbor Perspectives
in Biology, vol. 2, no. 7 (July 2010), https://doi.org/10.1101/cshperspect.a003467.
Bergtrom, Gerald. “20.5: Origins of Life Chemistries in an RNA World.” Biology LibreTexts,
January 3, 2021,
https://bio.libretexts.org/Bookshelves/Cell_and_Molecular_Biology/Book%3A_Basic_C
ell_and_Molecular_Biology_(Bergtrom)/20%3A_The_Origins_of_Life/20.05%3A_Origi
ns_of_Life_Chemistries_in_an_RNA_World.
Bernal, J. D. “The physical basis of life.” Proc. Phys. Society, vol. 62 (1949), pp. 537–555.
Biology Libre Texts, “Eukaryotic Origins” (2020),
https://bio.libretexts.org/Bookshelves/Introductory_and_General_Biology/Book%3A_Co
ncepts_in_Biology_(OpenStax)/13%3A_Diversity_of_Microbes_Fungi_and_Protists/13.
2%3A_Eukaryotic_Origins.
Bonner, John Tyler. “The Evolution of Evolution: Seen through the Eyes of a Slime Mold.”
BioScience, vol. 65, no. 12 (December 1, 2015), pp. 1184–87,
https://doi.org/10.1093/biosci/biv154.
43
Bonner, John Tyler. First Signals: The Evolution of Multicellular Development. 1st edition.
Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2001.
Bonner, John Tyler. Randomness in Evolution. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2013,
https://press.princeton.edu/books/hardcover/9780691157016/randomness-in-evolution.
Bonner, John. “Evolution, by Chance?” New Scientist, vol. 219, no. 2926 (July 20, 2013), pp.
26–27, https://doi.org/10.1016/S0262-4079(13)61798-4.
Bricmont, Jean. “Determinism, Chaos, and Quantum Mechanics” (n.d.)
http://www.freeinfosociety.com/pdfs/mathematics/determinism.pdf.
Bricmont, Jean. Making Sense of Quantum Mechanics, 1st ed. New York: Springer, 2016.
Buchanan, M. (2008). “Quantum Randomness May Not Be Random,” New Scientist (2008),
(online edition), https://www.newscientist.com/article/mg19726485-700-quantumrandomness-may-not-be-random/.
Cairns-Smith, A. G. Genetic Takeover and the Mineral Origins of Life. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1982.
Campbell, D. “Downward Causation in Hierarchically Organized Biological Systems,” E:CO ,
vol. 15, no.3 (2013), pp. 139–51.
Camprubí, E., de Leeuw, J. W, House C. H. , Raulin, F., Russell, M. J., Spang, A., Tirumalai, M.
R., and Westall F. “The Emergence of Life.” Space Science Reviews, vol. 215, no. 8
(December 12, 2019), https://doi.org/10.1007/s11214-019-0624-8.
Camprubi, E., Jordan, S. F., Vasiliadou, R., Lane, N. “Iron catalysis at the origin of life,” Life,
vol. 69, no. 6 (2017), pp. 373–381.
Carroll, Sean B. “Online Event: Origins of life with Sean B Carroll.” New Scientist, April 22,
2021, https://www.newscientist.com/science-events/origins-life-sean-bcarroll/?utm_source=nscon&utm_medium=email&utm_campaign=18022021-bigthinker-origins-of-life&.
CheggStudy. “Learn About Origin Of Prokaryotic Cells.” CheggStudy, accessed March 26,
2021, https://www.chegg.com/learn/biology/introduction-to-biology/origin-ofprokaryotic-cells.
Cooper, Keith. “Looking for LUCA, the Last Universal Common Ancestor.” Phys.org
(December 18, 2018), https://phys.org/news/2018-12-luca-universal-commonancestor.html.
Dawkins, Richard. The Blind Watchmaker. New York: W.W. Norton, New York, 1986.
44
de Duve, Christian. A Guided Tour of the Living Cell. New York: W. H. Freeman and Co.,
1985.
de Duve, Christian. A-Z Quotes (n.d.) https://www.azquotes.com/quote/730686
de Jesus, Erin Garcia. “Two New Books Investigate Why It’s so Hard to Define Life.”
Science News (March 17, 2021), https://www.sciencenews.org/article/biologytwo-new-books-why-hard-define-life-meaning.
Emmeche, Claus. “Defining Life as a Semiotic Phenomenon.” Cybernetics and Human
Knowing, vol. 5 (1998), pp. 3–17.
Goldenfeld, Nigel, and Woese, Carl. “Life Is Physics: Evolution as a Collective Phenomenon
Far from Equilibrium.” ArXiv:1011.4125 [Cond-Mat, q-Bio], November 17, 2010.
http://arxiv.org/abs/1011.4125.
Goodenough, Ursula and Heitman, Joseph. “Origins of Eukaryotic Sexual Reproduction.” Cold
Spring Harbor Perspectives in Biology, vol. 6, no. 3 (March 1, 2014), p. a016154,
https://doi.org/10.1101/cshperspect.a016154.
Gould, Sven B. “Membranes and Evolution.” Current Biology, vol. 28 (2018).
Graham, William. “Nature’s Self Organizing Patterns.” Nature’s Web Of Life (May 2, 2014).
http://www.freshvista.com/2014/natures-self-organizing-patterns/.
Grossman, Lisa. “Carbon-Ring Molecules Tied to Life Were Found in Space for the First
Time.” Science News (March 22, 2021), https://www.sciencenews.org/article/carbonring-molecules-life-found-space-first-time.
Guidotti, T. “The Phylogenetic Tree Topples.” American Scientist.(2006),
http://www.americanscientist.org/issues/pub/2006/3/the-phylogenetic-tree-topples.
Haldane, J. “The Origin of Life,” Rationalist Annual (1929).
Hanschen, Erik R. “How and Why Single Cell Organisms Evolved into Multicellular Life.”
Phys.org (April 25, 2016).
Harrub, Brad and Thompson, Bert. “The Origin of Gender and Sexual Reproduction.” TJ, vol.
18, no. 1 (2004), pp. 120–28, https://creation.com/images/pdfs/tj/j18_1/j18_1_120127.pdf.
Holloway, Royal. “Organic Materials Essential for Life on Earth Are Found for the First Time
on the Surface of an Asteroid.” Phys.org (March 4, 2021), https://phys.org/news/202103-materials-essential-life-earth-surface.html.
45
Hordijk, Wim. “Autocatalytic Sets: From the Origin of Life to the Economy.” BioScience, vol.
63, no. 11 (November 2013), pp. 877–81; pp. 880-8, https://doi.org/10.1525/bio.20.
Hudson, Rueben, et al. “Process That Might Have Led to First Organic Molecules: New
Research Could Have Relevance to Search for Extraterrestrial Life, Green Chemistry,”
ScienceDaily (September 8, 2020),
https://www.sciencedaily.com/releases/2020/09/200908170535.htm.
Hurst, Laurance D. “Why Did Sex Evolve? Researchers Edge Closer to Solving Longstanding
Mystery.” The Conversation (February 29, 2016), http://theconversation.com/why-didsex-evolve-researchers-edge-closer-to-solving-longstanding-mystery-55407.
Kamimura, Atsushi and Kaneko, Kunihiko. “Molecular Diversity and Network Complexity in
Growing Protocells.” ArXiv:1904.08094 [q-Bio], April 17, 2019.
http://arxiv.org/abs/1904.08094.
Karsenti, Eric. “Self-Organization in Cell Biology: A Brief History.” Nature Reviews
Molecular Cell Biology, vol. 9, no. 3 (March 2008), pp. 255–62,
https://doi.org/10.1038/nrm2357.
Kauffman, S. “A God of Creativity.” New Science, vol. 198 (2008).
Kauffman, S. Humanity in a Creative Universe. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016.
Koonin, E. and Martin, W. “On the origin of genomes and cells within inorganic
compartments.” Trends in Genetics, vol. 21 (2005), pp. 647–654.
Korten, David. “Life’s Ability to Self-Organize and Learn,” David Korten (blog). Accessed
January 14, 2021. https://davidkorten.org/the-new-economy/life-as-teacher/.
Laland, K., Wray, G. A., Hoekstra, H. E., et al. ”Does evolutionary theory needs a rethink?”
Nature, vol. 514 (2014), pp. 161-64.
Lane, N., Allen, J. F., Martin, W. “How did LUCA make a living? Chemiosmosis in the origin
of life.” BioEssays, vol. 32 (2010), pp. 271–280.
Lane, Nick and Martin, William F. “Mitochondria, Complexity, and Evolutionary Deficit
Spending.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of
America, vol. 113, no. 6 (2016).
Lane, Nick. The Vital Question: Energy, Evolution, and the Origins of Complex Life. New
York: W. W. Norton & Company, 2015,
http://archive.org/details/vitalquestionene0000lane.
Lanier, Kathryn A. and Williams, Loren Dean. “The Origin of Life: Models and Data.” Journal
of Molecular Evolution (2017).
46
Liu, Bin, Charalampos, G., Pappas, Jim, Schaeffer, Gaël, Jurissek, Christoph, Pieters, Priscilla
F., Altay, Meniz, Marić, Ivana, Stuart, Marc C. A., and Otto, Sijbren. “Spontaneous
Emergence of Self-Replicating Molecules Containing Nucleobases and Amino Acids.”
Journal of the American Chemical Society, vol. 142, no. 9 (March 4, 2020), pp. 4184–92,
https://doi.org/10.1021/jacs.9b10796.
Lodish, Harvey, et al. Molecular Cell Biology. New York: W. H. Freeman, 2000,
https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/books/NBK21570/.
Margulis, Lynn. “Symbiosis and Evolution.” Scientific American, vol. 225, no. 2 (1971), pp.
48–61.
Margulis, Lynn. Origin of Eukaryotic Cells: Evidence and Research Implications for a Theory
of the Origin and Evolution of Microbial, Plant, and Animal Cells on the Precambrian
Earth. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1970.
Marshall, Michael. “Life’s Big Bang.” New Scientist, vol. 247, no. 3294 (August 8, 2020), pp.
34–38, https://doi.org/10.1016/s0262-4079(20)31377-4.
Martin, William F., Sousa, Filipa L. and Lane, Nick. “Energy at Life’s Origin: Analysis of the
Bioenergetics of Primitive Organisms Suggests That Life Began at Hydrothermal Vents.”
Science, vol. 344, no. 6188 (2014), pp. 1092–93.
Mcalpine, Kate. “Cluster Model Shows How First Cells Could Have Divided.” New Scientist
(January 5, 2011), https://www.newscientist.com/article/mg20927942-400-cluster-modelshows-how-first-cells-could-have-divided/.
McAlpine, Kate. “In the Beginning Was Naked Genetic Material,” New Scientist, vol. 209, no.
2794 (January 8, 2011), https://doi.org/10.1016/S0262-4079(11)60017-1.
McCusker, Derek. “Cellular Self-Organization: Generating Order from the Abyss.” Molecular
Biology of the Cell, vol. 31, no. 3 (January 30, 2020), pp. 143–48,
https://doi.org/10.1091/mbc.E19-04-0207.
McFall-Ngai, Margaret, Hadfield, Michael G., Bosch, Thomas C. G., Carey, Hannah V.,
Domazet-Lošo, Tomislav, Douglas, Angela E., Dubilier, Nicole, et al. “Animals in a
Bacterial World, a New Imperative for the Life Sciences.” Proceedings of the National
Academy of Sciences, vol. 110, no. 9 (February 26, 2013), pp. 3229–36,
https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1218525110. p. 3234.
McGowan, Kat. “How Life Made the Leap From Single Cells to Multicellular Animals.” Wired
(August 1, 2014), https://www.wired.com/2014/08/where-animals-come-from/.
47
Mikhailovsky, George E. and Gordon, Richard. “LUCA to LECA, the Lucacene: A Model for
the Gigayear Delay from the First Prokaryote to Eukaryogenesis.” Biosystems, preprint,
(April 1, 2021), 104415, https://doi.org/10.1016/j.biosystems.2021.104415.
Moreno, Alvaro. “The Origin of a Trans-Generational Organization in the Phenomenon of
Biogenesis.” Frontiers in Physiology, vol. 12 (January 28, 2021), pp. 127-136,
https://doi.org/10.3389/fphys.2021.626977.
Mukouyama, Yoshiharu and Nakato, Yoshihiro. “Dynamic Self-Organization in an Open
Reaction Network as a Fundamental Mechanism for the Emergence of Life.” ChemRxiv,
December 7, 2020, https://chemrxiv.org/articles/preprint/Dynamic_Selforganization_in_an_Open_Reaction_Network_as_a_Fundamental_Mechanism_for_the_
Emergence_of_Life/13332458, https://doi.org/10.26434/chemrxiv.13332458.v1.
Murphy, Roy. “Inevitability of Life.” Medium (October 26, 2018),
https://medium.com/@DrRoyMurphy/inevitability-of-life-b7cc7dde1639.
NASA. “About Life Detection.” Astrobiology at NASA/Life in the Universe,
https://astrobiology.nasa.gov/research/life-detection/about.
NASA. “Key Building Block for Organic Molecules Discovered in Meteorites.” Lab Manager
(December 28, 2020), https://www.labmanager.com/news/key-building-block-fororganic-molecules-discovered-in-meteorites-24712.
Niklas, Karl and Newman, Stuart. “The Origins of Multicellular Organisms.” Evolution &
Development, vol. 15 (January 21, 2013), pp. 41–52, https://doi.org/10.1111/ede.12013.
Niklas, Karl J. and Newman, Stuart A. Eds. Multicellularity: Origins and Evolution. 1st
edition. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 2016.
Niklas, Karl. “From One Cell to Many: How Did Multicellularity Evolve?” ScienceDaily
(January 25, 2014), https://www.sciencedaily.com/releases/2014/01/140125172414.htm.
Niven, J. and Chittka, I. “Evolving Understanding of Nervous System Evolution.” Current
Biology, vol. 26 (2016).
O’Malley, M., Leger, M. M., Wideman, Jeremy G., and Ruiz-Trillo, I. “Concepts of the Last
Eukaryotic Common Ancestor.” Nature Ecology & Evolution, vol. 3 (2019), pp. 338-44,
https://doi.org/10.1038/s41559-019-0796-3.
Oparin, A. Origin of Life. Moscow: Moscovskij Rabochij, 1924.
Ourisson, G. and Nakatani, Y. “The terpenoid theory of the origin of cellular life: the evolution
of terpenoids to cholesterol.” Chemical Biology, vol. 1 (1994), pp. 11–23.
48
Pennisi, Elizabeth. “The Momentous Transition to Multicellular Life May Not Have Been so
Hard after All.” Science (June 28, 2018),
https://www.sciencemag.org/news/2018/06/momentous-transition-multicellular-life-maynot-have-been-so-hard-after-all.
Peretó, J., Bada, J. L., Lazcanol, A. “Charles Darwin and the origin of life.” Orig. Life Evol.
Biosph, vol. 39, no. 5 (2009), pp. 395–406.
Prigogine, I. and Stengers, I. Order out of Chaos: Man’s New Dialogue with Nature. Toronto:
Bantam Books, 1984.
Pross, Addy. “Physical Organic Chemistry and the Origin of Life Problem: A Personal
Perspective.” Israel Journal of Chemistry, vol. 56, no. 1 (January 2016), pp. 83–88,
https://doi.org/10.1002/ijch.201500073.
Roux, Etienne, Marhl, Marko, and Mossio, Matteo. “Editorial: Multilevel Organization and
Functional Integration in Organisms.” Frontiers in Physiology, vol. 12 (January 28,
2021), pp. 4-6. https://doi.org/10.3389/fphys.2021.626977.
Ruiz-Mirazo, Kepa, Pereto, Juli, and Moreno, Alvaro. “A universal definition of life:
Autonomy and open-ended evolution.” Origins of Life and Evolution of Biospheres, vol.
34 (2004), pp. 323–46.
Sagan, Carl. “Life.” The Encyclopaedia Britannica. London: William Benton, 1970.
Sasselov, Dimitar, Grotzinger, John P., and Sutherland, John D. “The Origin of Life as a
Planetary Phenomenon.” Science Advances, vol. 6, no. 6 (February 1, 2020),
https://doi.org/10.1126/sciadv.aax3419.
Searle, John R. The Construction of Social Reality. New York: Free Press, 1995.
Service, Robert F. “Researchers May Have Solved Origin-of-Life Conundrum.” Science
(March 16, 2015), https://www.sciencemag.org/news/2015/03/researchers-may-havesolved-origin-life-conundrum.
Shapiro, R. and Feinberg, G. “Possible Forms of Life in Environments Very Different from the
Earth.” In Leslie, J. Ed. Physical Cosmology and Philosophy. New York: MacMillan,
1990, pp. 248-55.
Shkliarevsky, Gennady. “Conservation, Creation, and Evolution: Revising the Darwinian
Project.” Journal of Evolutionary Science, vol. 1, no. 2 (September 25, 2019), pp. 27-57,
https://doi.org/10.14302/issn.2689-4602.jes-19-2990.
Shkliarevsky, Gennady. “Quantum Discontents, or What Is Wrong with Our Science Practice.”
Philosophies, vol. 3, no. 4 (November 23, 2018),
https://doi.org/10.3390/philosophies3040040,
49
Shkliarevsky, Gennady. “Revising the Cosmic Story.” ArXiv:2012.12749 [Physics], December
23, 2020, http://arxiv.org/abs/2012.12749.
Shkliarevsky, Gennady. “The Evolution of Civilization as a Process of Creation.” SSRN
Scholarly Paper. Rochester, NY: Social Science Research Network, January 28, 2020),
https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3526961.
Shkliarevsky, Gennady. “Understanding the Process of Creation: A New Approach.”
Management: Journal of Sustainable Business and Management Solutions in Emerging
Economies, vol. 22, no. 3 (October 31, 2017), pp. 1–13,
https://doi.org/10.7595/management.fon.2017.0021.
Shkliarevsky, Gennady. The Civilization at a Crossroads: Constructing the Paradigm Shift.
Raleigh, NC: Glasstree Publishing, 2017,
https://www.researchgate.net/publication/318431832_The_Civilization_at_a_Crossroads
_Constructing_the_Paradigm_Shift.
Singer, Emily. “How Structure Arose in the Primordial Soup.” Scientific American (May 19,
2015), https://www.scientificamerican.com/article/how-structure-arose-in-the-primordialsoup/.
Sojo, V., Herschy, B., Whicher, A., Camprubí, E., and Lane, N. “The origin of life in alkaline
hydrothermal vents.” Astrobiology, vol. 16 (2016), pp. 181–97.
Sonea, Sorin and Mathieu, Léo G. “Chapter III. Original, Non-Darwinian Evolution of
Prokaryotes.” Prokaryotology : A Coherent Point of View. Montréal: Presses de
l’Université de Montréal, 2018, pp. 73–88,
http://books.openedition.org/pum/14303.
Stewart, John E. “The Meaning of Life in a Developing Universe.” Foundations of Science, vol.
15, no. 4 (November 2010), pp. 395–409, https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-010-9184-9.
Szostak, J., Bartel, D., and Luisi, P. “Synthesizing life,” Nature, vol. 409 (2001), pp. 387–390.
Teilhard de Chardin, Pierre. The Phenomenon of Man. New York: Harper & Row Publishers.
1959.
Thibaut Brunet, Thibaut and King, Nicole. “The Origin of Animal Multicellularity and Cell
Differentiation.” Developmental Cell, vol. 43, no. 2 (October 23, 2017), pp. 124–40,
https://doi.org/10.1016/j.devcel.2017.09.016.
Trefil, James. “The Origin of Life.” American Scientist (February 6, 2017),
https://www.americanscientist.org/article/the-origin-of-life.
50
Varela, F. J. “On Defining Life.” In G. R. Fleischaker, G. R., S. Colonna, S, and P. L. Luisi, P.
L. Eds. Self-Production of Supramolecular Structures: From Synthetic Structures to
Models of Minimal Living Systems. Dordrecht: Springer, 1994, pp. 23–33.
Varela, F., and Maturana, H. Autopoiesis and Cognition: The Realization of the Living.
Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company, 1972.
Varela, F., Maturana, H., Uribe, R. “Autopoiesis: the organization of living systems, its
characterization and a model.” Currents in Modern Biology, vol. 5 (1976), pp. 187-96,
PMID 4407425 DOI: 10.1016/0303-2647(74)90031-8.
Wedlich-Söldner, Roland and Betz, Timo. “Self-Organization: The Fundament of Cell
Biology.” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, vol.
373, no. 1747 (May 26, 2018), p. 20170103, https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2017.0103.
Wilcox, Christie. “Rethinking the Ancestry of the Eukaryotes.” Quanta Magazine (April 9,
2019), https://www.quantamagazine.org/rethinking-the-ancestry-of-the-eukaryotes20190409/.
Woese, Carl. “The Universal Ancestor.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, vol.
95, no. 12 (June 9, 1998), pp. 6854–59, https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.95.12.6854.
Wolchover, Natalie. “A New Physics Theory of Life.” Scientific American (June 27, 2017),
https://www.scientificamerican.com/article/a-new-physics-theory-of-life/.
Wolchover, Natalie. “A New Thermodynamics Theory of the Origin of Life.” Quanta
Magazine (January 22, 2014), https://www.quantamagazine.org/a-new-thermodynamicstheory-of-the-origin-of-life-20140122/.
Woolfson, Adrian. “Origins of Life: An Improbable Journey.” Nature, vol. 520 (April 29,
2015), pp. 617–18, https://doi.org/10.1038/520617a.
Zimmer, Carl. “On the Origin of Sexual Reproduction,” Science, vol. 324, no. 5932 (June 5,
2009), pp. 1254–56, https://doi.org/10.1126/science.324_1254.
Брайчевский, Михайлo. Походження Русі. Kиїв:_Наукова думка. 1968.
51