[Introduction]
Mario Bunge’s Project
François Maurice
This first issue of Mεtascience pays tribute to Mario Bunge on
the occasion of his 100th birthday. This is not the first time, and
certainly not the last, that thinkers pay tribute to Mario Bunge or
that his work is the subject of a study, and rightly so, because the
man is a humanist and the work is worthy heir to the Enlightenment. Mario Bunge has made significant contributions to a wide
range of disciplines: physics, philosophy, sociology, psychology, cognitive sciences. This issue is also a way to make Bunge’s thinking
known to a French readership.
The Project of a Lifetime10
On New Year’s Eve of 1937, at the age of 18, Mario Bunge resolved to study only serious intellectual subjects. He moves up a
gear. He chooses to study physics at university and philosophy on
his own. He is thus a physicist by training and a philosopher by
vocation.
He had just spent a few relatively difficult years in high school.
However, the last two years of primary school went well. The teachers of the progressive primary school Escuela Argentina Modelo
were competent and motivating: “I flourished at that school, where
I was put in charge of the classroom library, was elected senator of
our miniature parliament, made some friends, and earned some
medals. I looked forward to doing even better in high school. How
utterly mistaken I turned out to be!”
The Colegio Nacional High School in Buenos Aires did not make
a good impression on the young man. He had just left a progressive
elementary school and enjoyed some freedom at home. The Colegio
10 We freely draw inspiration from Mario Bunge’s autobiography, Between Two
Worlds, 2016, to introduce you to this scholar of contemporary Enlightenment. All
quotes in this section come from this autobiography.
20
Mεtascience n° 1-2020
offered only discipline, and merit was assessed only by exam scores.
For Bunge, the school was more like a correctional facility than a
place of learning. He rebelled. He published a short-lived Magazine
against the Professors, one of whose professors, caricatured as a
chimpanzee, made the headlines. He got away with a fourteen days’
suspension: “Even I was surprised at my irreverence, because I had
behaved well in my elementary schools.”
The Colegio “frees” the student at the end of 1936 because he
does not do well in most subjects: “I was a mediocre student because
I was neither motivated nor fond of most of my teachers.” In the
same year, Bunge completed all subjects as a “free student” at the
Colegio Nacional Sarmiento, with the exception of trigonometry, a
subject in which he failed twice. He studied Plane Trigonometry by
Isaac Todhunter, published in 1859, and then easily passed the trigonometry exam. He fell in love with mathematics, so he began to
study Calculus Made Easy by Silvanus P. Thompson, published in
1910, a work which appealed to the notion of infinitesimal rather
than the formal notion of limits. He received his high school diploma
in 1937 and then enrolled in the Faculty of Physicomathematical
Sciences at the National University of La Plata, an ideal place for a
theoretical mind: “The young La Plata University was perhaps the
most advanced in Latin America, because it assigned priority to the
basic sciences […] instead of being a factory for producing lawyers,
physicians and bookish engineers […]”.
The year of resolution was a defining year: “That year of 1937, so
critical for me, I read more than at any other time in my life.” While
reading Bertrand Russell’s Problems of Philosophy, published in
1912, immediately convinced him that psychoanalysis was “pure
fantasy”, it took him ten years to realize that the “Hegelian verbiage” of dialectical materialism concealed two doctrines interesting
in the embryonic state: epistemological realism and ontological materialism. He was impressed by the pre-Socratic, Spinoza and
French Enlightenment philosophers. He also realizes that most philosophers have never practiced science. In order to do better than
them, he studied physics for fourteen years and received his doctorate in 1952 from the University of La Plata. From 1943 to 1951, he
worked under the direction of Guido Beck (1903-1988) on problems
of nuclear and atomic physics. Bunge only considered himself a professional philosopher after two decades of philosophizing and only
after he had published a few books and a dozen articles. The
21
François Maurice Introduction: Mario Bunge’s Project
demands Bunge had placed on himself made him go a long way in
order to reach his goal: “to join philosophy with science.”
After returning from a postdoctoral stay with David Bohm in Sao
Paulo in 1953, Bunge embarked on two long-term research projects:
the study of the philosophy of physics and its foundations, and the
study of categories of determination, including causality and
chance. These projects occupied him from 1954 to 1970 and led to
the publication of Causality and Metascientific Queries, both in
1959, then to that of Foundations of Physics and Scientific Research11, both in 1967. The Treatise on Basic Philosophy was born a
few years later, in 1974, the culmination of this search for a link
between philosophy and science.
Reading Bunge
Mario Bunge’s project has led him to write more than 150 books
and 540 articles or chapters, including translations into several languages. The work covers all branches of philosophy, from ontology
to ethics, including semantics, epistemology, methodology, praxeology and axiology, as well as a wide range of scientific disciplines,
from physics to sociology, including chemistry, biology and psychology. Undoubtedly, Bunge’s magnum opus is the Treatise on Basic
Philosophy. The first volume of the Treatise was released in 1974,
the last in 1989. There is a before and an after the Treatise.
There was also a before and an after Foundations of Physics and
Scientific Research. The year is 1967. For Bunge, the situation is
clear. In his preface to Foundations of Physics, he invites us to roll
up our sleeves since in any case the analytical tools for metascientific research are available:
There is little excuse for failing to attempt it, as all physical theories
teem with logical and semantical difficulties, and the great majority
of them are in their infancy as regards logical organization and
physical interpretation. The prime matter—supplied by the physicist—and the tools—wrought by the mathematician, the logician
and the philosopher of science—are there.
This work of axiomatization of theories of physics was undertaken to combat operationalism and to remove from the field of
physical theories any concept pertaining to psychology. For Bunge,
11
Scientific Research was republished as Philosophy of Science in 1998.
22
Mεtascience n° 1-2020
without this double axiomatization, formal or logical, and factual or
semantic, to discuss the interpretation of a theory is only tantamount to “hand-waving, when not magic-wand-waving.”
With Scientific Research, Bunge offers us a manual of “methodology”, each section of which ends with a set of 10 problems, which
makes a total of 930 problems to be solved. Many of these problems
could be the subject of a master or doctoral thesis, and some of them
would occupy a lifelong researcher. Answers to problems are not
provided! Fortunately, each chapter ends with a detailed and commented bibliography. Let us understand that this is a manual of
methodology in the Bungean sense, and not a manual of method,
that is to say a manual which explains the methods specific to a
discipline, the methodology here being the study of methods, the
normative branch of epistemology. Scientific Research is an opportunity not only to deal with the methodology of science, but also the
methodology of philosophy and metascience. The successes of formal logic and semantics “suggest adopting a clear methodology,
more precisely one that draws on that of science.” A significant part
of the work is also devoted to the semantics of the factual sciences,
a theory necessary for the dual axiomatization of Foundations of
Physics.
There was also a before and an after Causality and Metascientific
Queries. The year is 1959. Several of the main Bungean themes are
present: the dichotomy between formal and factual sciences, the notion of factual semantics, the unity of science, the nature of scientific laws, the different meanings of “law”, the notion of levels of
organization, that of novelty and emergence, the different categories of determination, including causality and randomness, the lawfulness principle], scientific explanation and prediction, as well as
a conception of metascience. Make no mistake, Causality is not just
about causality; the work is sharp and wide, as evidenced by the
subtitle: The Place of the Causal Principle in Modern Science. In the
same way that Scientific Research is the companion of Foundations
of Physics, Metascientific Queries is that of Causality: one is the general framework in which the research of the second takes place. We
will find similar couples a few years later with Philosophy of Psychology and The Mind-Body Problem, then Finding Philosophy in
Social Science and Social Science under Debate.
23
François Maurice Introduction: Mario Bunge’s Project
After the publication of Foundations of Physics and Scientific Research in 1967—and a few other texts in the same year and the following years!—during a trip to Spain, while staying with his family
in a rented house near Marbella, Bunge recalls in his autobiography
that “in the backyard there was a green lawn without trees and surrounded by a high wall, so there was nothing to do but think. There
I had the idea of expanding my work to encompass all the main
branches of philosophy.” It is an understatement! Not only will
Bunge publish a treatise on philosophy which will cover all
branches of philosophy, but he will also give himself the task of
studying the main scientific disciplines in the light of his philosophical theories.
The Treatise is therefore the culmination of some twenty-five
years of research and reflection on the nature of science, but also on
the nature of philosophical or metascientific research. But to fully
appreciate both the Treatise and the entire work, one must keep in
mind the fiction/reality dichotomy and the distinction between reflection and theorization. From the dichotomy between fiction and
reality follows other dichotomies: between the formal and the factual, between a concept and the object to which it refers, between
an attribute and the property it represents, etc. So the world should
not be confused with our representation of it. This implies that
there are no philosophical, metaphysical, logical or linguistic links
between us and the world. But, instead of concluding that the world
is then inaccessible, Bunge reflects on the situation, takes note of
the success of science, adopts the same general postulates to which
science subscribes, to finally develop general theories, a theorization that is not about the facts of the world but their scientific representation. To adopt the same general postulates as science is to
say that Bunge does not problematize scientific facts in the same
way as his fellow philosophers.
This state of mind is reflected in Bunge’s work through the use
of a singular expression: to take for granted. We find the expression
everywhere in Bunge’s work, and without an understanding of it,
the expression will appear incomprehensible or trivial. Aren’t we
saying that nothing should be taken for granted? Isn’t it peculiar to
a philosopher to question everything? Bunge disagreed. He takes
for granted an astonishing quantity of principles and postulates,
the justification of which is found in a reflection on the world, on
our relationship to it, and on the success of science. If science is
24
Mεtascience n° 1-2020
successful, the majority of assumptions taken for granted by scientists must be the right ones. Why problematize them if they are the
source of such success? Why not adopt them and thus build general
theories, ontologies, epistemologies, methodologies and semantics,
on a common basis with science? That’s what he did. It must be understood that these general postulates are for Bunge a springboard
for the development of his philosophical or metascientific theories;
they are not the culmination of metascientific research but its beginning.
At the end of this introduction, we have grouped together a few
books and journal numbers devoted to the thought of Mario Bunge.
For the French readership, we have also grouped books, articles and
chapters of Mario Bunge as well as texts devoted to his thinking
available in French. This is not the first attempt to introduce Mario
Bunge into the French-speaking world, but it seems to remain hermetic to his thinking. Note the effort of Éditions Vigdor to have published in the ’90s three translations by Adam Herman of Mario
Bunge’s text as well as to have produced two videos in which Mario
Bunge explains his vision of quantum physics and democracy. Publishing Bunge in French is a militant gesture.
Contributions
The eight contributions to this issue come from authors of different backgrounds, as it should be for a thought that covers as broad
as that of Mario Bunge. Like Bunge's project, the following contributions are neither part of the analytic movement nor the continental movement in philosophy. Note, however, that the contributors
to this first issue of Mεtascience do not necessarily endorse Sopromet's research program or the journal's editorial policy. We can
reasonably think that they were willing to participate in the issue
in order to pay tribute to a thinker dear to them. Nevertheless, we
distinguish three types of contribution: 1) studies on the Bunge system; 2) applications or extensions of Bungean thought; 3) reflections
and testimonies.
1] Studies on Bunge’s System
François Maurice, in his contribution “Metascience: for a Scientific General Discourse”, defends a non-philosophical
25
François Maurice Introduction: Mario Bunge’s Project
interpretation of Bunge’s work by revisiting the problem of the nature of philosophy, including the way it has to problematize reality
and the knowledge of it, as well as that of the nature of human reflection, which does not present itself as the prerogative of philosophy, but as “the most fairly distributed thing in the world.” In order
to take into account the particular nature of philosophy and the universal nature of reflection, Maurice advances the notion of general
discourse. Philosophy then appears as a general discourse among
others. Since Mario Bunge neither problematizes reality nor
knowledge of it in the same way as philosophers, he cannot be considered as a philosopher, but rather as a metascientific. By separating the faculty of reflection from the philosophical discourse, it is
then possible to envisage the development of a general scientific discourse, a metascience, the objects of study of which are the products
of science, i.e. concepts, propositions and scientific theories, and
whose main task is the development of metascientific theories, as
found in Mario Bunge’s Treatise on Basic Philosophy.
2] Applications or Extensions of Bungean Thought
Luis Marone, in his contribution “On the Kinds of Problems
Tackled by Science, Technology, and Professions: Building
Foundations of Science Policy”, proposes to distinguish the
components of the system of human knowledge, namely the science,
technology and professions, based on an analysis of the types of
problems encountered in each of them. He puts forward a typology
of problems and solutions to these problems where the notions of
direct problems and inverse problems, dear to Bunge, play an essential role. From this typology, it is then possible to classify activities within science, technology or professions. This understanding
of the distinct nature of the activities of the system of human
knowledge is essential for the formulation of a science policy for integral development.
Eduardo Scarano, in his contribution “The Inverse Approach
to Technologies”, offers us a study of the components of technology, especially the non-scientific components, through an approach
complementary to that of Bunge. Scarano’s analyses reveal no less
than a dozen components of the technology. Although aware of the
existence of non-scientific components of technology, Bunge was primarily interested in the link between science and technology. The
study of the components of the technology, what Scarano calls the
26
Mεtascience n° 1-2020
inverse approach (not to be confused with an inverse problem), allows a tidy classification of technologies. In fact, Scarano postulates
the existence of a continuum of technologies that “at one extreme,
come close to being almost confused with science and, at the other
extreme, tenuously fulfill some requirement of science.”
Martín Orensanz, in his contribution “A Critique of Meillassoux’s Reflections on Mathematics from the Perspective
of Bunge’s Philosophy”, criticizes the main thesis defended by
Meillassoux in his book After Finitude in light of Bunge’s philosophy
of mathematics: “all those aspects of the object that can be formulated in mathematical terms can be meaningfully conceived as properties of the object in itself”, or as Orensanz reformulates it, “any
property which can be mathematized can be construed as a primary
quality”. Orensanz’s critique has as its starting point an ambiguity
in Meillassoux’s conception of the nature of mathematics and that
of objects in themselves and their primary qualities, which compromises Meillassoux’s very thesis. By appealing to the Bungean dichotomy between the factual and the formal, Orensanz refutes the
Meillassian thesis while betting that Meillassoux’s philosophy can
hold up if it benefited from Bunge’s mathematical philosophy.
Ricardo Gomez’s contribution, “Mario Bunge : Epistemology
is here to Stay”, is a defense of the Enlightenment, of modernity,
of epistemology, and of Mario Bunge, contemporary representative
of modernity, and a destructive criticism of Latour’s notion of nonmodernity. Two brief comments by Gómez on Latour’s conceptions
say it all: “Enough is enough”, and a little further, “Enough, again”.
Latour builds a straw man and then tells us that we have never
been this straw man. It introduces ill-defined and ad hoc concepts,
unrelated to scientific disciplines, such as “hybrids”, “networks”,
“hybridization”, “purification”: for Gómez, it is a “creative paraphernalia of an alternative version of modernity and what it is to be
modern.” Before even tackling this notion of non-modernity, Gómez
gives us a taste of Latour’s argumentative method by criticizing a
text by Latour on special relativity, “A Relativistic Account of Einstein’s Relativity”, whose conclusion is unequivocal: “All these
statements show that Latour has not the slightest idea of what Einstein holds.”
27
François Maurice Introduction: Mario Bunge’s Project
3] Reflections and Testimonies
Mario Bunge, in his contribution “Criticism: Destructive and
Constructive”, invites us to consider constructive criticism as
more important than destructive criticism, although the latter
proves necessary. Bunge calls upon his experience as a critic of sterile philosophical schools to deliver the message “the most effective
criticism is the one accompanied by a suitable substitute”, and for
Bunge a solution often takes the form of a philosophical theory.
These and other contributions, published in various languages,
including English and Spanish, demonstrate the potential of a research program inspired by Mario Bunge’s project. This project is
part of the humanist and scientific tradition of the first Enlightenment in ancient Greece and the second Enlightenment in Europe.
The researcher, unlike followers of the contemporary Counter-Enlightenment sects, does not conclude in the face of a difficult and
complex problem that there is no solution or that all solutions are
equal. No, he lifts up his sleeves, he works hard, he thinks, he analyzes, he synthesizes, he advances solutions, he tests them, he offers
them for examination, in short, he confronts reality, at the risk of
undermining his own beliefs.
Selected Bibliography on Bunge
1990, New Ideas in Psychology, vol. 8, no 2 et 3.
Agassi J. & Cohen R. (éd.), 1982, Scientific Philosophy Today : Essays in Honor of
Mario Bunge, Reidel/Kluwer.
Denegri G. & Martínez G., 2000, Tópicos actuales en filosofía de la ciencia : Homenaje a Mario Bunge en su 80º aniversario, Universidad Nacional de Mar
del Plata-Editorial Martín.
Denegri G., 2014, Elogio de la sabiduría : ensayos en homenaje a Mario Bunge en
su 95° aniversario, Eudeba.
Matthews M., 1996, « Editorial for a special issue on science and education in honor
of Mario Bunge », Science & Education, vol. 5, no 2.
Matthews M., 2003, « Mario Bunge : Physicist and Philosopher », Science & Education, vol. 12, no 5 et 6.
Matthews M., 2012, « Mario Bunge, Systematic Philosophy and Science Education
: An Introduction », Science & Education, volume 21 no 10.
Matthews M., 2019, Mario Bunge : a Centenary Festschrift, Springer.
Moessinger P., 1991, « Editorial », New Ideas in Psychology, vol. 9, no 2.
28
Mεtascience n° 1-2020
Pickel A., 2004, « Systems and Mechanisms : A Symposium on Mario Bunge’s Philosophy of Social Science », Philosophy of the Social Sciences, volume 34,
no 2.
Silberstein M. (éd.), 2013, Matériaux philosophiques et scientifiques pour un matérialisme contemporain, Éd. Matériologiques.
Weingartner P. et Dorn G., 1990, Studies on Mario Bunge’s Treatise, Rodopi.
COPYRIGHT AND DISTRIBUTION POLICY
This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License,
which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution, and reproduction in any medium
or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the
source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate if changes were
made. The images or other third-party material in this article are included in the article’s
Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material.
If material is not included in the article’s Creative Commons licence and your intended
use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need
to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence,
visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/.