Burke’s Historical Morality
Ryan Holston
The Johns Hopkins University
The precise meaning of the terms “historical understanding,” “historical sense,” or “historical consciousness” can vary greatly, but
they are generally understood as referring to an awareness of the
dependence of human existence on the development of events that
have taken place in the past. During the eighteenth and nineteenth
centuries, a number of thinkers from various fields of study, whose
early expositors include Vico, Burke, Herder, Hegel, and Nietzsche,
began to explore this theme. Along with this fundamental insight
came the related understanding of the fact that the political choices
we face, our language, our meanings, and our values, are embedded within and contingent upon unique, present circumstances.
Despite the emergence of an increasingly widespread historical
sensibility among philosophers in the twentieth and twenty-first
centuries, the further implications of these basic insights remain
unclear and disputed. Consequently, many modern thinkers who
share what may be broadly described as a historicist orientation
nonetheless disagree on much else, including the implications of
our historicity for human knowledge, freedom, and morals. Much
of this article is therefore devoted to identifying a particular strain
of historicism and defending it as an approach to thinking about
morality and moral decision-making. The article will proceed by
first introducing some of the historical aspects of Burke’s thinking
and a unique brand of historicism that his thought inspires. It will
then look more closely at the implications of this Burkean-inspired
RYAN HOLSTON has defended his doctoral dissertation in political science at
The Johns Hopkins University and is assuming a position as Assistant Professor
of Political Science at The University of Alabama in Huntsville.
Burke's Historical Morality
HUMANITAS•37
Human
existence
dependent
on past
developments
and unique,
present
circumstances.
historical consciousness for an understanding of morality. Finally,
it will explore how the past continues to “live” in the present insofar as it shapes the thought and action of moral decision-makers.
Interpreting Burke
Since the early 1950s, the scholarly attention focused on the
thinking of Burke has been marked by two dominant strains of
interpretation.1 First is the critical reading of Burke penned by Leo
Strauss in his now famous tract Natural Right and History, in which
he sets forth a defense of what he terms “classic natural right.”2
The troubling development in modern thinking, according to
Strauss, is the tendency toward historical consciousness, which has
led to the relativization of all standards or claims to right or justice
once the latter were viewed as the mere accidents of history or convention. The charge that Burke is substantially responsible for this
development is leveled in the final pages of this text, where Strauss
is at pains to establish Burke’s credentials as a modern thinker. According to Strauss, Burke’s opposition to French rationalism “parts
company with the Aristotelian tradition by disparaging theory and
especially metaphysics.”3 Moreover, by stressing the importance of
1
An additional strain of scholarship has emerged since the early 1990s associated with thinkers who have variously appropriated Burke’s critique of modern
rationalism, as well as his early aesthetic theory, often for the purposes of antifoundationalist theory and critical theory. See Stephen K. White, Edmund Burke: Modernity, Politics, and Aesthetics (Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications, 1994), Uday
S. Mehta, Liberalism and Empire: a Study in Nineteenth Century British Liberal Thought
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1999), and Luke Gibbons, Edmund Burke and
Ireland (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2003).
2
Leo Strauss, Natural Right and History (Chicago: The University of Chicago
Press, 1965 [1953]), 120. It is disputed whether the conception of natural right presented therein in fact approximates the thinking of the ancient philosophers whom
Strauss claims as his inspiration. Claes G. Ryn has noted, for example, that classical
thinkers such as Aristotle and even Plato demonstrate an awareness of the temporality of experience and historical circumstance that Strauss altogether neglects.
That this abstract conception of right represents an imputation of modern ideas,
which actually distorts classical thinking and is closer in spirit to the ethical ideas of
the French Enlightenment, is argued in Ryn, A Common Human Ground: Universality
and Particularity in a Multicultural World (Columbia: University of Missouri Press,
2003), 75.
3
Strauss, Natural Right and History, 311. While Strauss appears, at first glance, to
view Burke approvingly for his having “restored the older view [of natural right] according to which theory cannot be the sole, or the sufficient, guide of practice” (ibid.,
303), his criticism mounts in the course of these pages, culminating in his conclusion
that Burke “prepared an approach to human affairs which is even more foreign to
38• VolumeXX,Nos.1and2,2007
Ryan Holston
tradition, “Burke’s political theory is, or tends to become, identical
with a theory of the British constitution, i.e., an attempt to ‘discover
the latent wisdom which prevails’ in the actual,”4 thus deriving its
normative authority from the mere accident of its historical evolution. That a tradition, as such, can take on this normative authority
is not only mistaken, for Strauss, but leads to the deleterious transformation of political thought from the study of that which ought
to be into the mere understanding of the actual or what is. 5 Once
traditions are assumed to be just, simply by virtue of their survival
or existence, Strauss questions how any can be deemed morally deficient. He claims that, by making “ought” dependent upon “is” in
this manner, Burke sows the seeds of the moral relativism that later
emerges in nineteenth-century German philosophy, whose more
thoroughgoing historicism proceeds to view all normative claims
as contingent upon their particular, historical contexts.
In marked contrast to this view, the reading of Burke put
forth by Peter Stanlis and Francis P. Canavan places his thinking
squarely within the canon of traditional natural law theory. Stanlis,
for example, relies more heavily than Strauss on the distinction
between natural law as conceived by the ancients and Aquinas and
that put forth by the modern natural rights philosophers of the
Enlightenment, claiming that Burke is much closer in his thinking
to the former than the latter. Stanlis maintains that, while the older
doctrine is capable of taking tradition and historical experience
into account, the newer doctrine that culminates in the thinking of
the philosophes is much more abstract. Therefore, when Burke famously rails against the “clumsy . . . political metaphysics”6 of the
French radicals, Stanlis thinks it is not metaphysical reasoning per
se that is the object of Burke’s criticism, but the particularly dangerous, abstract form of metaphysics that he sees ravaging France
and threatening all of Europe. Providing an abundance of textual
classical thought than was the very ‘radicalism’ of the theorists of the French Revolution,” and that “[w]hat would appear as a return to the primeval equation of the
good with the ancestral is, in fact, a preparation for Hegel” (ibid., 319). That Strauss
sees Burke as an eminently “modern” thinker may also be indicated by his placement in the text, whose order of treatment appears intended to mark the decline of
modern thought, beginning with Hobbes, proceeding on to Rousseau, then Locke,
and ending with Burke.
4
Ibid., 319.
5
Ibid., 320.
6
Burke, Reflections on the Revolution in France, ed. with intro. J. G. A. Pocock
(Indianapolis and Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Co., 1987), 51.
Burke's Historical Morality
HUMANITAS•39
According
to Strauss,
Burke's
opposition
to French
rationalism
leads to moral
relativism.
Stanlis places
Burke squarely
in the classical
and Scholastic
tradition.
support for his thesis, Stanlis counters the notion that Burke was
an anti-metaphysical thinker. He argues that, far from disparaging
metaphysics, Burke was unwavering in his adherence to the classical and Scholastic tradition of natural law thinking, so thoroughly
that Stanlis even denies any “development” of this tendency in
Burke’s thought. He marvels: “What was most remarkable in
Burke was the sustained consistency of the Natural Law in his
thought and career.”7
That such dissimilar readings of the same thinker are plausible
points to the severity of the apparent tensions residing within the
corpus of Burke’s work. On the one hand, Burke is comfortable
speaking in the language of natural law and, in this respect, he
does appear to echo the classical, metaphysical conception of a
universal hierarchy of ends whose normative authority supports
what is right and just in the world. On the other hand, Burke’s
concern for a pragmatic awareness of circumstance, together with
his historical sense, appears to signal a new development in the
theory of knowledge and in morals that ought not to be dismissed
as merely realigning the natural law tradition with its experiential
strain. Will Herberg dubs this tension “the Burkean paradox” and
succinctly poses the problematic as follows: “How can a man be an
advocate of expediency and an apostle of principle at one and the
same time? How can he, for example, excoriate the French Declaration of the Rights of Man as ‘abstract’ and ‘metaphysical’ in almost
the same breath that he denounces the French revolutionaries for
their crimes against ‘the eternal immutable law’?”8
Rejecting interpretations that tend to emphasize either of these
aspects of Burke’s thinking at the expense of the other, this article
argues that it is possible to conceive of Burke as laying the foundation for a historically informed understanding of morals, which
sees them as existing concretely in human conduct. Noting that
Burke fits neatly into neither category, natural lawyer nor historical
relativist, Claes Ryn has argued that Burke’s thought points toward
the possibility of synthesis between historical existence and a universal moral order. Burke’s thinking thus serves as the inspiration
for a moral theory developed by Ryn, which he terms “value-cen7
Peter Stanlis, Edmund Burke and the Natural Law (Ann Arbor: University of
Michigan, 1958; New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers, 2003). Citations are to the
Transaction edition.
8
Will Herberg, “Natural Law and History in Burke’s Thought,” Modern Age 3
(1959): 325.
40• VolumeXX,Nos.1and2,2007
Ryan Holston
tered historicism.” According to this theory, Burke’s fundamental
insight is “[seeing] the transcendent moral order as potentially
inhering in history.”9 In other words, Burke expresses an awareness
of the importance of historical context and particularity in human
existence. However, rather than inferring the relativity of morals,
Ryn suggests a novel understanding of morality that sees it as
manifested diversely in concrete human experiences. He explains
this insight:
It is possible to reconcile the acceptance of universality with a historicist appreciation for the particularity, diversity, and changeability of human existence. What is here called value-centered historicism refers precisely to the needed reconstitution and synthesis of
philosophical elements. In this form of historicism real universality
is not separated from the particulars of history; universality is seen
as present to human consciousness in concrete form. Ethical universality is at the same time transcendent of historical experience and
immanent in it.10
This appropriation of Burke and the unique form of historicism
that it inspires has significant implications for the way in which we
conceive of morality and moral decision-making. Consequently,
the remainder of this article will focus on demonstrating in greater
detail what it means to bring history to bear on morality in this
way. The new understanding will be compared and contrasted
with both traditional, intellectualist notions of morality and more
thoroughgoing varieties of historicism.
The Contextual Character of Morality
The fundamental idea behind the concept of value-centered historicism is that the good can be located, “not in abstract theoretical
‘principles’ or other ahistorical judgment or vision, but in concrete
experience; that normative authority, in so far as it exists for man,
resides in historical particularity.”11 While Hegel is perhaps better
known for pioneering the idea that the normative is capable of
such concretization or instantiation within phenomenal experience, it is Burke who, earlier, introduces this idea to the Englishspeaking world through his writings on politics. Moreover, he does
so without the unfortunate rationalist tendencies that characterize
9
Ryn, “History and the Moral Order,” in The Ethical Dimension of Political Life,
ed. Francis J. Canavan (Durham: Duke University Press, 1983), 103.
10
Ryn, A Common Human Ground, 81.
11
Ryn, “Universality and History,” Humanitas 6: 1 (1992), 11.
Burke's Historical Morality
HUMANITAS•41
Ryn's
value-centered
historicism
inspired by
Burke.
Hegel’s thinking. Hegel’s progressivist philosophy of history,
which ultimately sees normative reason as ubiquitous, culminates
in a pantheistic form of rationalism that makes distinctions between good and evil problematic. However, in avoiding—indeed,
in combating—such rationalist tendencies, Burke is able to discern
the variegation and complexity within the concrete normativity
that he observes. He asserts that “steady, independent minds . . .
will judge of human institutions as they do of human characters.
They will sort out the good from the evil, which is mixed in mortal
institutions, as it is in mortal men.”12 Burke senses not only that
such distinctions are possible, but that good and evil exist nowhere
for man outside of the phenomenal reality of everyday life. For
Burke, there is no abstract model against which such phenomena
must be measured in order to determine their moral status. Rather,
man comes to recognize and know the normative character of phenomena through the immanent experience of their historical manifestations. Thus, it is only by virtue of moral phenomena comingto-be in the world of human experience that man can develop his
normative awareness and the capacity to make these distinctions
between good and evil.
The manifestation or instantiation of good and evil in concrete
Good and evil experience is intimately connected with the complexity of morality
transform
mentioned above. For, if good and evil are historical, if they are
themselves in
concretized within phenomenal reality, then good and evil are subdifferent social
ject to the fleeting nature of phenomena. As such, their concretizacontexts.
tion must always take place anew and must always be historically
unique. Moreover, it must take place within new circumstances,
which change the moral character of what is concretized. For
Burke, all of this contingency implies not a radical undermining or
incoherence of good and evil (to be discussed below), but that the
same moral quality or “spirit” essentially transforms itself in different social contexts. Each context provides a historical backdrop in
which morality is then instantiated as concrete, social interaction.
Burke thus argues that, while the “disorderly appetites” such as
pride, ambition, lust, and avarice are the real causes of the world’s
miseries, “[r]eligion, morals, laws, prerogatives, privileges, liberties, [and] rights of men” are often the “pretexts” in which they
are manifested. Consequently, Burke argues, “Wise men will apply
their remedies to vices, not to names; to the causes of evil which are
Experience
of good and
evil in history
makes it
possible to
distinguish
between them.
12
Burke, Reflections, 111.
42• VolumeXX,Nos.1and2,2007
Ryan Holston
permanent, not to the occasional organs by which they act, and the
transitory modes” in which evil becomes concrete.13 According to
Burke, “[w]ickedness is a little more inventive” than to have “the
same modes of mischief” in more than one age.14 Instead, he explains, “[t]he . . . same vice assumes a new body. The spirit transmigrates, and, far from losing its principle of life by the change of its
appearance, it is renovated in its new organs with a fresh vigor of a
juvenile activity.”15 Burke thus hints at the heightened need for moral discernment and vigilance that such variation makes necessary.
Because he sees the social interaction in which morality manifests
itself as “transitory,” and historically unique, he thinks it difficult
to predict the form in which good or evil will appear or to assert in
advance what they will look like. What emerges upon examining
Burke’s suggestion that particular forms of social interaction serve
as the pretexts or vehicles for manifesting good and evil is the contextual or situated character of morality.
The neglect of this contextual character of morality represents
one of the most egregious oversights of the abstract rationalism
Burke famously criticized. Burke’s response to the French radicals’
unqualified demand for “liberty” in the abstract reflects well his
thoughts on the problematic nature of acontextual thinking:
I cannot stand forward and give praise or blame to anything which
relates to human actions, and human concerns, on a simple view
of the object, as it stands stripped of every relation, in all the nakedness and solitude of metaphysical abstraction. Circumstances
(which with some gentlemen pass for nothing) give in reality to
every political principle its distinguishing color and discriminating
effect. The circumstances are what render every civil and political
scheme beneficial or noxious to mankind.16
Morality’s “contextual” nature thus refers not only to the uniqueness of these concrete instantiations, but to the influence of circumstance in creating distinct moral imperatives. Yet this role of
circumstance in shaping the demands of morality need not imply
moral relativism, as intellectualists and thoroughgoing historicists
alike may well infer from such an assertion. On the contrary, the
implication is that close attention to the circumstantial dimension
of moral problems is essential to their most just moral resolution
13
14
15
16
Ibid., 124.
Ibid.
Ibid, 125. Emphasis added.
Ibid., 7.
Burke's Historical Morality
HUMANITAS•43
Form in which
good and evil
will appear in
future difficult
to predict.
and that to neglect circumstance, even in the name of principle, can
actually be unjust or immoral.17
Burke employs an example to illustrate the centrality of circumLiberty's
stance in determining the moral character of phenomena: “Is it bemoral
cause liberty in the abstract may be classed amongst the blessings
significance
of mankind, that I am seriously to felicitate a madman, who has esdependent
caped from the protecting restraint and wholesome darkness of his
on its place
cell, on his restoration to the enjoyment of light and liberty? Am I
within a
broader social to congratulate a highwayman and murderer who has broke prison
context.
upon the recovery of his natural rights?”18 The appropriateness of
such congratulation or moral approbation with respect to liberty,
Burke indicates, can only be determined by considering liberty’s
place within a broader context of social arrangements, i.e., how liberty combines in any particular instance with other features of social life, such as order, religion, manners, self-restraint, etc. In other
words, it can never be determined per se that liberty is “among
the blessings of mankind.” Rather, liberty’s meaning and value
can only be fully grasped in the light of its relation to other social
structures and arrangements. It is only with respect to this broader
social context that liberty takes on its full, moral significance for
human life. The point being made here ought to be distinguished
from its distant cousin, often made in an Aristotelian vein, that
metaphysical principle needs to be supplemented by an awareness
of empirical reality in order to achieve its prudential application by
a wise legislator or moral actor. In contrast, the point being made
here is that there is no metaphysical principle awaiting prudential
application. Rather, context alone is constitutive of a particular historical or existential matrix in which real moral imperatives may be
said to arise or originate.
It is worth noting that Burke sometimes speaks of these moral
imperatives in the language of necessity, such that some interpret17
For further development of the idea that “principled” neglect of circumstance
is in fact morally harmful, see Ryn, “The Politics of Transcendence: The Pretentious
Passivity of Platonic Idealism,” Humanitas 12: 2 (1999), 4-26. The charge is leveled
at the moral and political theory in Plato’s Republic: “Innumerable readers of Plato
have found his moral idealism and his refusal to compromise indicative of complete
dedication to the Good. But is it? A case can be made that, by associating political
morality with an unattainable, ahistorical standard and urging those who aspire
to virtue to contemplate the ideal rather than the possible, Plato falls prey to a romantic abstractionism that undermines political morality.” Ibid., 7. Emphasis in the
original.
18
Burke, Reflections, 7.
44• VolumeXX,Nos.1and2,2007
Ryan Holston
ers have been led to read him as advocating a crude pragmatism or
utilitarianism.19 However, careful attention to certain passages in
which Burke invokes a concern for what is necessary suggests that
he may in fact have been attempting to articulate a kind of necessity that is intimately related to morality or a concept of morality
that recognizes the moral significance of practical, circumstantial
considerations. The English “Revolution of 1688,” which Burke
defends and contrasts with the French Revolution, affords him the
opportunity to discuss how such considerations relating to what is
practicable or suitable to a situation can determine what is moral.
Burke’s aim here is to emphasize England’s rejection of the right
“to choose our own governors, to cashier them for misconduct, and
to form a government for ourselves,”20 in contrast to the democratic
claims of the French revolutionaries. Burke argues that the “Declaration of Right,” which emerged out of the Revolution of 1688
itself, was explicitly meant to establish the proper hereditary succession of the crown.21 Interestingly, Burke admits that, in replacing
King James with William of Orange, the Revolution of 1688 did
19
The secondary literature devoted to utilitarian and pragmatic interpretations
of Burke alone is extensive. Interpretations of Burke as a utilitarian dominated
during the nineteenth century, including Henry T. Buckle’s History of Civilization
In England (London: J. W. Parker and Son, 1857-1861) and John Morley’s Edmund
Burke: A Historical Study (London: MacMillan and Co., 1867). Numerous studies
have since followed along lines similar to these early interpretations. Joseph Baldacchino has effectively countered several of these readings of Burke as a utilitarian in
“The Value-Centered Historicism of Edmund Burke,” Modern Age 27, no. 2 (1983).
Some of the studies mentioned in footnote 1 above have given renewed life to the
interpretation of Burke as a pragmatist insofar as they read his respect for cultural
difference—particularly in the case of India—as emerging from a recognition of the
“strangeness and viability of [other ways] of life.” Uday S. Mehta, Liberalism and
Empire, 22.
20
Burke, Reflections, 15. Emphasis in the original. J. G. A. Pocock, in his informative introduction, goes so far as to claim that the Reflections on the Revolution in
France is in fact part of a long-standing debate about the true nature of the Revolution of 1688. In opposition to the radical current of thought represented by John
Locke, Pocock explains, Burke makes the more orthodox (and thus not reactionary)
argument that “in terminating the kingship of James II and transferring the crown
to William and Mary, the nation had acted by the authority and according to the
forms of the ancient constitution: of King, Lords and Commons, the common law
and its judges, extending back through Magna Carta to the Norman Conquest and
beyond. All had been done by precedent and authority, nothing by the tabula rasa
of the uncommitted intellect. The people had been less free to choose a king or a
government than obliged to maintain and preserve a constitution already existing.”
Pocock, introduction to Reflections on the Revolution in France, xii.
21
Ibid., 15.
Burke's Historical Morality
HUMANITAS•45
represent “a small and temporary deviation from the strict order
of a regular hereditary succession.”22 But what is important, Burke
notes, is that no general principle was or should have been inferred
from “a law made in a special case and regarding an individual
person” to serve a “temporary” need.23 In other words, here Burke
defends a decision that he claims established no precedent, nor
was derived from any principle—it was in every sense exceptional
and particular to its situation. Therefore, if no principle supported
the decision to remove King James and replace him with King William and this was intended to serve only a temporary need, one
might inquire: Was this decision based on mere expediency? More
to the point, in defending the Revolution of 1688, is Burke in effect
advocating a decision that is pragmatic over one based on moral
considerations?
Despite the fact that this action reflected no principle, but was
An action
serving a situational need, it may nonetheless have represented a
that reflects moral decision and not been pragmatic, or at least not pragmatic in
no principle
the barest sense of the term. Burke argues that “to all those who did
can still be
not wish, in effect, to recall King James or to deluge their country in
moral and
not merely blood and again to bring their religion, laws, and liberties into the
pragmatic. peril they had just escaped, it was an act of necessity, in the strictest
moral sense in which necessity can be taken.”24 In other words, if what
was necessary or pragmatic was the impetus for action here, Burke
thinks it was a type of necessity that was nonetheless moral. Such
a “moral necessity” is conceivable if the underlying need is understood to be a situational moral imperative, i.e., a moral requirement
that arises out of its unique, historical circumstances and cannot be
anticipated by an a priori rule or principle.
Burke returns to the subject of the Revolution of 1688 later in the
Reflections and, in doing so, reaffirms this link between the necessary and the moral: “The Revolution of 1688 was obtained by a just
war, in the only case in which any war, and much more a civil war,
can be just. Justa bella quibus necessaria. [Wars are just when they are
necessary.]”25 To be sure, it is possible to read Burke’s remark here
in a strictly pragmatic light, according to which he is not referring
to the “moral necessity” presently being attributed to him. This
22
23
24
25
Ibid., 16.
Ibid.
Ibid. Emphasis added.
Ibid., 26-27, 220. Emphasis in the original.
46• VolumeXX,Nos.1and2,2007
Ryan Holston
strict, pragmatist reading of Burke would then interpret him as
saying that justice, and the justice of a war in particular, is merely
a function of what is necessary or expedient as such. However, it is
also possible to read Burke as arguing that the morality of any war
must be based on whether war serves the needs of justice in the
particular situation. This interpretation is supported by its clear
contrast with the position Burke in fact is opposing—that of the
French radicals who see war, particularly revolution, as a matter
of the absolute right of the subject for all times and places. Burke
refutes this position by underscoring the need for situational moral
judgment, as opposed to abstract rules conceived in advance:
The speculative line of demarcation where obedience ought to end
and resistance must begin is faint, obscure, and not easily definable.
It is not a single act, or a single event, which determines it. . . . Times
and occasions and provocations will teach their own lessons. The
wise will determine from the gravity of the case; the irritable, from
the sensibility to oppression; the high-minded, from disdain and
indignation at abusive power in unworthy hands; the brave and
bold, from the love of honorable danger in a generous cause; but,
with or without right, a revolution will be the very last resource of
the thinking and the good.26
Viewed in the broader context of his opposition to the abstract right
of the subject to revolt, Burke appears to have in mind a necessity
that relates to situational moral imperatives and the keen moral
discernment this requires. In stating that “wars are just when they
are necessary,” he is not advancing the strictly pragmatic view that
what merely works or is expedient is what is right, but the view
that whether war is right will depend upon what justice requires
within a particular, political context.
This theme of moral necessity appears to emerge again when
Burke rebukes the French revolutionaries’ treatment of the French
nobility, arguing that the nobility’s punishment was incommensurate with their supposed mistreatment of the French populace.
While Burke admits that there is, on rare occasion, the need to hold
accountable a cruel and unjust nobility, he argues that the instance
in question fell well short of this type of situation. Still, Burke’s
hypothetical is instructive, for he notes that when such occasions
do arise, “The statues of Equity and Mercy might be veiled for
a moment. The tenderest minds, confounded with the dreadful
exigency in which morality submits to the suspension of its own
26
Ibid., 27.
Burke's Historical Morality
HUMANITAS•47
"Revolution
will be the
very last
resource of the
thinking and
the good."
Burke
articulates a
non-legalistic
concept of
morality.
rules in favor of its own principles, might turn aside whilst fraud
and violence were accomplishing the destruction of a pretended
nobility.”27 The quote is revealing for its insight into the nature of
moral necessity, or “exigency,” that arises in exceptional situations.
Yet the precise meaning of Burke’s metaphor is not immediately
obvious: What is the distinction that he aims to establish between
morality’s “rules” and its “principles”? It appears that the contingent nature of moral necessity is ill-suited to the formalistic and
law-like character of “rules.” Burke claims that meeting certain
moral imperatives would require the suspension of such rules.
Groping for a different term, Burke says that morality’s “principles” would have to take precedence—though he clearly does not
intend this term to carry with it its intellectualist connotations, as
the contrast with moral “rules” indicates. Instead, Burke appears
to be struggling to articulate a conception of morality that is nonlegalistic, one according to which justice transforms itself to meet
the particular moral needs of particular situations. To conceive of
justice in this way is to suggest more explicitly what has been latent
in this contextual understanding of morality: that justice is mutable
and capable of serving unique moral imperatives that arise in connection with our changing historical circumstances.
Burke’s assault on abstract metaphysics reveals this sense of
justice’s mutability. The neglect of moral complexity that he attributes to the philosophes results directly from their ignorance of
justice’s need to vary in order to meet the distinct moral requirements of changing, historical circumstances. Burke, on the other
hand, displays a keen awareness that what is right or just will not
always look the same and thus cannot be stated so uniformly and
unequivocally as the philosophes assume. He communicates morality’s complexity in the philosophes’ own terms, i.e., in the language
of “abstract right” itself: “These metaphysic rights entering into
common life, like rays of light which pierce into a dense medium,
are by the laws of nature refracted from their straight line. Indeed, in the gross and complicated mass of human passions and
concerns the primitive rights of men undergo such a variety of
refractions and reflections that it becomes absurd to talk of them
as if they continued in the simplicity of their original direction.” 28
Though expressed in the vocabulary of metaphysics, Burke’s prism
27
28
Ibid., 118-119.
Ibid., 54.
48• VolumeXX,Nos.1and2,2007
Ryan Holston
metaphor is not evidence of the metaphysical underpinnings of his
thinking. Rather, it ought to be viewed as a heuristic device that
uses metaphysical imagery to communicate that justice must undergo variation in order to cope with the messiness of circumstance
in the real world. Burke’s metaphor further underscores the notion
that describing moral imperatives in terms that convey uniformity
is inappropriate, insofar as such imperatives are dependent upon
complex and unpredictable historical circumstances.
To say that justice is mutable and that it adapts to meet moral
needs specific to historical circumstances is not to imply that justice is arbitrary or historically relative, as both intellectualists and
radical historicists may be tempted to infer. Rather, justice’s mutability can be interpreted to mean that “the transcendent reveals
itself in history by becoming selectively immanent in it.”29 In other
words, just as Burke noted that evil undergoes permutations across
various contexts, such is the case with what is good or just: “The
spirit transmigrates, and, far from losing its principle of life by
the change of its appearance, it is renovated in its new organs.” 30
Therefore, while what is good, in one sense, never changes, insofar as its “spirit” is concerned, each manifestation of it must,
in another sense, be sui generis, in that its occurrence is within
the uniqueness of a historical moment. Concrete instantiations of
goodness are unique both in their adaptation to circumstances that
are situational and idiosyncratic, and in that they themselves are
enacted within history. As will be discussed shortly, Burke is comfortable with the idea that what is constant or enduring in human
life is maintained, not in spite of the change and flux of history, but
because of and through such historical change itself.
The historicity of experience is what makes abstract speculation
inadequate to the task of making judgments of a moral or political
nature. Interestingly, the cost of such speculation appears greater
to those who are less radical in their historicism. In other words,
the moral stakes are higher for those who see morality as concretized within history than for those who interpret moral variation
in history as implying the relativity of morals. For those who see
justice or the good as transforming itself to meet the moral needs
of particular situations, moral and political decisions based on
abstraction and absolutes threaten to violate real, historically spe29
30
Ryn, “Defining Historicism,” Humanitas 11: 2 (1998), 88.
Burke, Reflections, 124.
Burke's Historical Morality
HUMANITAS•49
cific, moral imperatives. The speculation of the human intellect,
divorced from concrete reality, then, informs decisions that are
insensitive to moral needs and thus morally harmful. While the
historical relativist might view intellectualist thinking about morality as narrow-minded, the notion that there may be moral “costs”
associated with abstract decision-making is knowledge of which
the relativist thinks we are deprived. Ahistorical thinking, for the
relativist, can and perhaps ought to be viewed as ignorant, but it
cannot be understood as having normative significance beyond the
confines of its historic situation.
However, for Burke and the position being advanced here, the
Good govern- purpose of opposing abstract speculation and remaining sensitive
ment must
to the needs of particular political contexts is decidedly moral.
accommodate
Thus, Burke repeatedly emphasizes the virtues of making small
changing
adjustments to attend to political problems and criticizes French
needs of
political life. lawmakers for their grand schemes that have no relation to circumstance.31 One such scheme of which Burke is particularly critical is
the attempt to re-configure the political jurisdictions in France according to a highly rationalistic, geometrical design.32 Burke favors
the more prudential approach of the lawmaker who instead works
to improve upon “useful parts of [the] old establishment.”33 Moreover, he prefers to have numerous legislators contributing to political arrangements in a piecemeal fashion over time, thus providing
“the aid of more minds than one age can furnish.”34 With this basis
in particular knowledge, the political system becomes more nuanced, more attuned to specific moral needs. Having the flexibility
to adapt and adjust political designs, “[t]he evils latent in the most
promising contrivances are provided for as they arise. One advantage is as little as possible sacrificed for another. We compensate,
we reconcile, we balance.”35 According to Burke, the best legislators are aware that good government is that which accommodates
the contingencies of political life with its “plastic nature.” 36 Realizing the most just outcomes requires precisely this plasticity and
responsiveness to particular moral needs on the part of moral and
political decision-makers.
31
32
33
34
35
36
Ibid., 148.
Ibid., 152.
Ibid., 148.
Ibid., 149.
Ibid.
Ibid.
50• VolumeXX,Nos.1and2,2007
Ryan Holston
The subject of the mutability of justice is considered in depth in
Ryn’s essay “History and the Moral Order.” A striking part of this
discussion is that Ryn finds some limited support for and development of the idea that justice varies to meet contingent moral needs
in the thinking of Leo Strauss, a self-avowed anti-historicist. 37 Ryn
points to Strauss’s dispute with Thomas Aquinas over the interpretation of Aristotle’s assertion in The Nicomachean Ethics that “all
right—hence also all natural right—is changeable.”38 According to
Strauss, Thomas had read Aristotle too narrowly when Thomas
interpreted Aristotle’s remark to mean that only specific, derivative
rules of justice could be mutable.39 Strauss insists, on the contrary,
that Aristotle unequivocally asserts natural right’s mutability, and
Strauss ultimately places Aristotle’s concept of justice somewhere
between the Averroistic view that natural right is a product of human convention and what Strauss perceives to be the moral absolutist reading rendered by Thomas.40
In what follows, Strauss aims to discover a “safe middle road”41
between these two extreme positions. As Ryn correctly observes,
Strauss’s efforts here suggest that it may be possible to get away
from an understanding of natural right conceived as propositions
or rules.42 Contemplating this possibility, Strauss remarks, “One
is tempted to make the following suggestion: When speaking of
natural right, Aristotle does not primarily think of any general
propositions but rather of concrete decisions. All action is concerned
with particular situations. Hence, justice and natural right reside,
as it were, in concrete decisions rather than in general rules.”43 Ryn
reads Strauss as considering the problems of legalistic conceptions
of morality,44 particularly the fact that general rules, because of their
rigidity, may actually prevent just outcomes.45 Strauss reflects on the
potential implications of the conception of justice as residing in con37
See Ryn, “History and the Moral Order,” 92-96. The remarks that follow draw
heavily on Ryn’s reading of Strauss in this essay. I am also indebted to Professor
Ryn for discussions relating to this section of Natural Right and History.
38
Strauss, Natural Right and History, 158, cited in Ryn, “History and the Moral
Order,” 93.
39
Strauss, Natural Right and History, 157-58.
40
Ibid., 159.
41
Ibid.
42
Ryn, “History and the Moral Order,” 94.
43
Strauss, Natural Right and History, 159.
44
Ryn, “History and the Moral Order,” 94.
45
Ibid.
Burke's Historical Morality
HUMANITAS•51
crete decisions: “In every human conflict there exists the possibility
of a just decision based on full consideration of all the circumstances,
a decision demanded by the situation. Natural right consists of such
decisions. Natural right thus understood is obviously mutable.”46
Although Strauss subsequently rejects this view in favor of the
intellectualist conclusion that general principles are somehow implied within or presupposed by all concrete decisions,47 the thought
experiment he undertakes here is instructive. For he illustrates the
direction in which one’s thinking is forced in considering how it is
possible to meet the unique moral demands associated with contingent circumstances. According to Strauss, legalistic conceptions of
morality appear inadequate where “extreme situations” can arise.
Then perhaps “the normally valid rules of natural right are justly
changed.”48 Indeed, Strauss appears to acknowledge the validity
of Aristotle’s suggestion that “there is not a single rule, however
basic, which is not subject to exception.”49 Moreover, with respect
to how a just society might deal with “an absolutely unscrupulous
and savage enemy” he goes so far as to say that “[t]here are no
limits which can be defined in advance, there are no assignable limits to what might become just reprisals.”50 Illustrating this potential,
Strauss notes that, where the survival of a society is at stake, the
use of espionage—which he says even the most just society cannot
forgo—will require the suspension of the rules of natural right. 51
What is particularly interesting is that Strauss’s remark here
is reminiscent of Burke’s statement that morality’s “rules” might,
on occasion, need to be suspended in favor of its “principles.”
Moreover, Strauss adds that “[n]atural right must be mutable in
order to be able to cope with the inventiveness of wickedness,” 52
appearing to echo Burke’s remark that “[w]ickedness is a little
more inventive”53 than is implied by a morality based on formalistic rules. The purpose of drawing these parallels is to suggest
that Strauss may have become aware that Burke—in part reacting
to the excessive abstractionism of his own age—had explored the
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
Strauss, Natural Right and History, 159.
Ibid.
Ibid., 160. Emphasis added.
Ibid.
Ibid. Emphasis added.
Ibid.
Ibid., 161.
Burke, Reflections, 124.
52• VolumeXX,Nos.1and2,2007
Ryan Holston
problems of moral intellectualism and had begun to consider what
it would mean to reconceive justice in more historical terms. What
Strauss appears to recognize, and we ought to recognize as well,
is that Burke had broken with the moral and political philosophy
that had preceded him precisely by virtue of his emerging historical
consciousness. As the preceding discussion has attempted to make
clear, Strauss hesitantly acknowledges the fact that conceiving of
justice concretely means recognizing that sometimes justice requires
exceptional, unanticipated action. The conclusion that Strauss ultimately abandons, but which Burke does not, is that such exceptional
circumstances bring with them exceptional moral imperatives and a
reconsideration of what actions are properly considered “just.”
A Living History
Two interrelated aspects or dimensions of Burke’s emerging historical consciousness bear importance for the thought and action of
moral decision-makers. First is Burke’s sense that man’s normative
orientation is shaped not only by the cultural embeddedness of
the present in which he lives but also by the tradition into which
he is born that exists over time. Second is the related awareness
that man’s historical situation is the inheritance of a past whose
continuity with the present and future is an ineradicable fact of
life. Each of these aspects of Burke’s historical consciousness—
his awareness of the normativity and facticity of man’s historical
existence—will be treated in turn. Comprehending both of them
requires an appreciation of the sense in which what endures and
what changes—i.e., life’s universality and its particularity—are in
a dialectical relationship.54
54
It is important to distinguish the use of “dialectical” here from Hegel’s original use of the term. Much has been written and disputed concerning what Hegel
meant by “dialectic.” Most fundamentally, Hegel may be understood as referring
to the inner movement and development of a given subject matter. Many attribute
to this dialectical movement the schema “thesis-antithesis-synthesis.” While Hegel
never uses such terminology, this is the triadic form used by Kant which served
as an inspiration for Hegel’s dialectic and to which the stages of the dialectic correspond. Hegel’s concern is to show how the finite understanding can grasp the
metaphysical absolute, an apparent contradiction. He does this by demonstrating
that reason must first posit something that is unconditioned or absolute (the thesis),
then examine this thing and discover that it is only understandable by distinction
and relation to other things (the antithesis), and finally realize that what is in fact
unconditioned is neither of these parts but the whole that they comprise and upon
which they depend (the synthesis). But to understand this whole, it must be differentiated from similar wholes, which can then be synthesized into a larger whole.
Burke's Historical Morality
HUMANITAS•53
Exceptional
circumstances
give rise to
exceptional
moral imperatives.
Tradition
communicates
normativity
as such—both
good and
evil—and
serves as a
medium for its
future manifestations.
It has been mentioned that Burke sees good and evil as intermingled and residing within phenomenal reality. Because Burke
views concrete, historical experience as normative, history may be
understood as at once expressing and shaping our normative orientation. In other words, history is both the forum where social interactions are realized and the background in which the normative
awareness of individual and collective actors is shaped. History being comprised of both good and evil, it is wrong to think of Burke
as looking to the past with simple nostalgia, as a romantic reactionary who sees only goodness in an inherited tradition and wishes
to restore a preexisting social order. This is frequently thought to
be Burke’s attitude toward the feudal order of old Europe. On the
contrary, Burke explicitly contends that one of the most cherished
aspects of having an inherited tradition is the ability to “draw
moral lessons . . . from [it]”55 regardless of whether one discerns
the need to cleave to or depart from a given tradition. Burke goes
so far on one occasion as to focus exclusively on the evil that may
infect tradition and its didactic quality: “In history a great volume
is unrolled for our instruction, drawing the materials of future
wisdom from the past errors and infirmities of mankind.”56 He
continues: “History consists for the greater part of the miseries
brought upon the world by pride, ambition, avarice, revenge, lust,
sedition, hypocrisy, ungoverned zeal, and all the train of disorderly
appetites which shake the public with the same
‘—troublous storms that toss
‘The private state, and render life unsweet.’”57
Thus, tradition for Burke is not simply the embodiment of what is
right or just, and he hardly advocates the restoration of the old order. Rather, he sees the importance of tradition as its ability to comThis is said to continue until knowledge of the absolute is reached. Frederick Beiser,
Hegel (New York: Routledge, 2005), 159-169. The use of the term “dialectical” in the
present project is not meant to imply this process of rational development or unfolding. However, the term is nonetheless employed because, by “dialectic,” Hegel
also captures the coexistence, interdependence, and harmony of certain antithetical
qualities in human existence. For example, Hegel’s dialectic shows a thing can both
be conditioned and unconditioned at the same time, both F and -F. As Beiser argues,
this does not imply a violation of the law of contradiction, since F and -F are true of
distinct aspects of what is being described. In other words, reality cannot be completely determined with one predicate (F or -F) alone. Ibid., 162.
55
Burke, Reflections, 124.
56
Ibid.
57
Ibid. Here Burke quotes Spenser, Faerie Queene, II. c.7, st. 14.
54• VolumeXX,Nos.1and2,2007
Ryan Holston
municate normativity as such—both good and evil—and to serve as
a medium for its future instantiations.
Yet, in another sense, it is exclusively the instantiations of good
accumulated in historical experience—what Burke calls “the general bank and capital of nations and of ages”58—that he finds valuable in a tradition. The latter has a special role in bringing about
future moral action. In order to frame possibilities for action out of
the flux of phenomenal experience, the individual must draw on
an awareness of the positive worth of particulars communicated to
him through past experience. Such awareness is what makes incipient action appear worthwhile. To assume a normative sense in the
absence of this contact with historical particulars is to assume an
ahistorical actor or subject for whom present choices miraculously
acquire value ex nihilo. In this manner, the historical dimension of
moral decision-making is frequently ignored by Enlightenment
thinkers who then explain moral decisions either in terms of “selfevident” moral knowledge or by reducing such decisions to mere
interests or preferences. In contrast, Burke sees in history examples
that provide us with a normative orientation and, in so doing,
facilitate creative moral action. He rails against the philosophes for
ignoring this indebtedness to the past in moral decision-making:
[Y]ou chose to act as if you . . . had everything to begin anew. . . .
[But,] under a pious predilection for [an earlier race of] ancestors,
your imaginations would have realized in them a standard of virtue
and wisdom beyond the vulgar practice of the hour; and you would
have risen with the example to whose imitation you aspired. . . .
[B]y following wise examples you would have given new examples
of wisdom to the world.59
For Burke, a tradition is essential to making moral decisions, not
because the past is to be copied, but because it provides the normative orientation that is essential for new moral decisions. Rightly
understood, a tradition thus provides a normative sensibility and
inspiration to moral decision-makers rather than patterns of conduct merely to be replicated.
It is in the human capacity to make use of the past in the present
that one first encounters the quality of dialectic in Burke’s historicism. Insofar as Burke shows past concretizations of the good as inspiring their own vital appropriation and novel application under
58
59
Ibid., 76.
Ibid., 31-32.
Burke's Historical Morality
HUMANITAS•55
Historical
examples
provide a
normative
orientation,
facilitating
creative moral
action.
present circumstances, the past can be seen as a “living past.”60 As
The good
such, the normative character of past experience is shared by those
relies upon
actions inspired in decision-makers of the present. There is a dialecparticular
tical quality to such present concretizations in that they are in one
instantiations
sense universal and in another particular. On the one hand, present
for its very
concretizations of the good are universal insofar as they exhibit this
existence.
superior normative quality; on the other hand, such instantiations
are particular with respect to the uniqueness of their historical realization. Each of these qualities—universality and particularity—are
needed to predicate such historical concretizations. Once the idea
of morality has been historicized in this manner, and intellectualist
assumptions about metaphysics have been abandoned, the good
can be seen as actually relying upon particular instantiations for
its very existence. As individual and society find inspiration in
the “bank and capital” of past concretizations, they continually
create and enrich the good as they reconnect with the past. Burke
suggests this dialectical coexistence of what endures and what
changes, what is in one sense transcendent and in another immanent, when he says of British society that “in what we improve
we are never wholly new; in what we retain we are never wholly
obsolete.”61 The British tradition is thus constantly being renovated
through new, historical concretizations while, at the same time, the
connection between past and present is maintained by way of a
normative continuity.
In addition to this sort of continuity, Burke displays an awareness of a second sense in which the past can be understood as “living” in the present: our historical situation is the culmination of a
series of past events that determine all of the problems we confront
and even the way society conceives of alternatives for action. Burke
demonstrates an awareness of this continuity in his frequent allusions to the corporate nature of a society that exists over time,
which so many Enlightenment rationalists were prone to neglect
in their ahistorical focus on the individual. Burke’s idea of the individual’s place within this larger whole is made readily apparent
in his allusion to society as “a permanent body composed of transitory parts,” a description which tends to mitigate the importance of
the individual vis-à-vis the larger society. And yet Burke also recognizes that the corporate nature of society is only possible insofar
60
61
Ryn, A Common Human Ground, 94. Emphasis in the original.
Burke, Reflections, 30.
56• VolumeXX,Nos.1and2,2007
Ryan Holston
as it coexists with and is dependent upon variation and renewal,
since change is indeed in the nature of history. Thus, he admits the
need for individuals who, despite their transitory nature, make
society’s continuity conceivable. Once again, Burke demonstrates
a propensity for dialectics in his thinking: change and continuity
both qualify the nature of a society that exists over time. He thus
marvels that “by the disposition of a stupendous wisdom, molding
together the great mysterious incorporation of the human race, the
whole, at one time, is never old or middle-aged or young, but, in
a condition of unchangeable constancy, moves on through the varied tenor of perpetual decay, fall, renovation, and progression.” 62
Despite the uniqueness and variation among transient individuals,
they inherit and pass on to one another a history that binds them
as part of a greater, corporate whole.
This idea of society’s continuity amidst historical change can
also be detected in Burke’s discussion and critique of the Enlightenment’s ahistorical idea of the social contract. Burke rejects the
conception of society modeled on the idea of an economic transaction in which the fleeting demands of utility are met. For Burke,
society evolves slowly and organically over time, based on nothing resembling the rational calculations or agreements of homo
economicus:
Society is indeed a contract. Subordinate contracts for objects of
mere occasional interest may be dissolved at pleasure—but the
state ought not to be considered as nothing better than a partnership agreement in a trade of pepper and coffee, calico, or tobacco, or
some other such low concern, to be taken up for a little temporary
interest and to be dissolved by the fancy of the parties. It is to be
looked upon with other reverence because it is not a partnership in
things subservient only to the gross animal existence of a temporary
and perishable nature. It is a partnership in all science; a partnership
in all art; a partnership in every virtue and in all perfection. As the
ends of such partnership cannot be obtained in many generations,
it becomes a partnership not only between those who are living, but
between those who are living, those who are dead, and those who
are to be born.63
Thus, beyond the narrow economic meaning, Burke cleverly employs “contract” here as a metaphorical reference to the bond established through everything we inherit and bequeath to one another
across generations—not simply our material possessions, but our
62
63
Ibid.
Ibid., 84-85.
Burke's Historical Morality
HUMANITAS•57
The present
is a living
and growing history
which will be
constitutive of
the “presents”
of those who
follow us.
habits, our manners, and our culture. Burke is thus cognizant—
where social contractarians working from a “blank slate” are not—
that this inheritance establishes a strong continuity between past
and present. Individuals do not make choices in a vacuum but are
embedded within a historical society where they confront circumstances that grow out of a unique past. From the alternatives for
action with which we are presented to the language and logic we
use to contemplate those alternatives, Burke is aware that we are
unavoidably part of the movement of history. To make the point
more acutely, it may be more accurate to describe the present as a
living and growing history which in turn will be constitutive of the
“presents” of those who follow us. The historical is ceaseless both in
its growth and in its constitution of the present, which are in fact two
ways of stating the same phenomenon, two sides of the same coin.
Despite this prominence of the historical in Burke’s thinking, it
ought to be made clear that he is not a historical determinist. For,
although Burke considers history to be ubiquitous in human decision-making, he sees history as at once liberating and constraining,
thus exhibiting yet another dialectical antithesis in his thought.
In one sense, history limits our choices by virtue of the particular
context or framework within which it forces us to choose, and
yet, in another sense, history provides concrete opportunities for
choosing, the necessary “friction” that makes creative movement
within a life possible. Illustrative of this dualistic perspective is
the emphasis Burke places on reform and making the most of the
particular circumstances with which one is confronted. Burke seeks
“a middle”64 between the extremes of revolutionary leveling, on
the one hand, and blind acquiescence to the status quo, on the other.
He elaborates: “There is something else than the mere alternative
of absolute destruction or unreformed existence. Spartam nactus es;
hanc exorna. (Sparta is your lot; now adorn it.) This is, in my opinion, a rule of profound sense and ought never to depart from the
mind of an honest reformer.”65 The importance placed on reform
here or “working with what is already there” indicates a wariness
of both the radical freedom assumed by those who treat society as
if it were a “tabla rasa” (blank slate) and a fatalistic resignation to
the historical circumstances one inherits. Burke’s reformist stance
suggests, in contrast to these dispositions, that one is capable of
64
65
Ibid, 138.
Ibid.
58• VolumeXX,Nos.1and2,2007
Ryan Holston
shaping history while nonetheless acknowledging that one’s “lot”
is always shaped by history. These two sides to Burke’s position
are, in fact, not merely compatible but are actually implicated in
one another, insofar as the concrete choices of the reformer are
fully acknowledged to be the inheritance of an unchosen history.
At this point, it is worth considering a potential objection from
those with a more thoroughgoing historicist orientation. It might
be maintained that, contrary to the appropriation of Burke set forth
here, careful attention to the historical nature of human existence
tends to undermine the prospect of continuity amidst historical
change. It may be argued that history implies change, contingency,
and flux of a much more radical kind than has been acknowledged. This view challenges the foregoing analysis in two ways.
First, once history is understood to imply substantial changes in
language, culture, and meaning across time, a problem emerges
with respect to the normative status of past concretizations of the
good. The situatedness that is implied by history effectively makes
each historical period “time-bound.” As such, the perspective
of the individual who draws inspiration from the past is historically contingent to such a radical extent that past concretizations
cannot be understood in the same manner as they were by those
who realized them. If our normative understanding is merely perspectival, how can what is concretized in history be described as
“good” in any objective sense of the word? One cannot even say
with confidence that past concretizations one believes to be “good”
were viewed as “good” by the historical actors who realized them!
Second, for the same reason (i.e., the time-boundedness associated
with radical change and contingency), Burke’s notion of an inherited past that shapes our present must be brought into question.
For, if time-boundedness implies radical limitations on perspective, there is no meaningful sense in which our social context is an
“inheritance” that binds us as an intergenerational, corporate social
entity. On this view, our particular social context simply represents
the facticity of our historical existence, interpreted uniquely by us
in our present circumstances and understood by past and future
generations in ways incomprehensible to us. Their habits, manners,
and culture have no bearing on our own.
However, in conceiving of history as a series of discrete, hermetically sealed moments, such time-bound conceptions tend to
atomize history and altogether neglect its fluidity and the ultimate
Burke's Historical Morality
HUMANITAS•59
Time-bound
conceptions of
human historicity neglect
the ultimate
inseparability
of “past” and
“present.”
inseparability of “past” and “present.” Time-bound understandings of history tend to reify and isolate historical moments and, in
doing so, refuse to recognize the possibility of continuity existing
together with—or, more accurately—through what changes. However, as the foregoing arguments have attempted to make clear
with respect to the dialectical nature of human existence, such
qualifications need not imply the absence or exclusion of their antithesis. In fact, historicists of widely divergent stripes who share a
notion of life’s dialectical nature have come to appreciate the sense
in which man’s historical existence must be predicated by both
continuity and change.
Ryn and the philosopher Hans-Georg Gadamer are two such
historicists who appear to share an awareness that continuity is
able to coexist with historical change.66 It has been remarked that
Gadamer has an appreciation for “the fundamental continuity of
history.”67 Every act of interpretation, for Gadamer, is a fusion of
the horizons of past and present, whereby the two become indistinguishable.68 Moreover, Gadamer is explicit that “the horizon of
the present cannot be formed without the past. There is no more an
isolated horizon of the present in itself than there are historical horizons which have to be acquired.”69 This dependence of the present on the past refers to the fact that “[t]he prejudices and interests
that mark out our hermeneutical situation are given to us by the
very movement of tradition.”70 Similarly combating the tendency
to hypostatize past and present, Ryn rebukes modern abstractionists for assuming they can “[choose] between modern and premodern thought.”71 He continues: “Such differentiations must . . . not be
mistaken for sharp divisions within concrete reality itself. Actual
thought is marked by a perpetual give and take between differ66
The influence of Hegel’s philosophy on both Ryn and Gadamer may be responsible for this affinity. Hegel’s impact on Ryn is transmitted through the thinking
of the Italian Hegelian Benedetto Croce. Hegel is also known to have had a direct
bearing on the thinking of Gadamer, particularly through the Phenomenology of the
Spirit. Paul Gottfried, The Search for Historical Meaning (Dekalb: Northern Illinois
University Press, 1986), 157.
67
David E. Linge, introduction to Philosophical Hermeneutics, by Hans-Georg
Gadamer (Berkley: University of California, 1976), xvi.
68
Ibid.
69
Gadamer, Truth and Method, trans. and ed. Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G.
Marshall (New York: Continuum, 2004), 305.
70
David E. Linge, introduction to Philosophical Hermeneutics, xvii.
71
Ryn, A Common Human Ground, 80.
60• VolumeXX,Nos.1and2,2007
Ryan Holston
ent points of view and defies the neat boundaries of abstractly
conceived categories.”72 Boundaries between “past” and “present”
are thus revealed to be mere imputations of the intellect upon a
historical existence that does not contain such strict separations. In
contrast to these abstractionist views that see our situatedness as
an obstacle to interpreting “the past,” both Ryn and Gadamer see
historical particularity as productive, facilitating a mediation of
past and present. There is no “past” or “present” as such, but only
situated orientations that, with every act of understanding, fuse
historically particular horizons.
This notion of the fusion of horizons between past and present
weakens both potential criticisms of the appropriation of Burke
presented here. First, if the past is implicated in every understanding of the present and the present in every understanding of the
past, the atomistic variety of perspectivism that radical historicism
relies on for its critique is brought into question. Insofar as the
hermeneutical situation of our present emerges from within a particular tradition,73 the idea that our habits, manners, and culture do
not connect us with the past but constitute an idiosyncratic present does not hold water. Moreover, insofar as the particularity of
the present mediates our understanding of the past, the past cannot be understood apart from the present. Though there is not an
ahistorical vantage point from which to comprehend and assess the
past, the present nonetheless provides a particular orientation from
which one can interpret the past—indeed, such interpretation contributes to what the past is. But interpreting the past also changes
the present. Every understanding is a hermeneutical mediation
of the one by the other, such that the two horizons are ultimately
indistinguishable. In attempting to articulate a concept of discrete
historical periods, one in which radical historicity severs the continuity between past and present, allegedly more thoroughgoing
historicisms in fact begin to appear ahistorical. At a minimum, the
very historical change they describe is incomprehensible unless the
“present” is in some sense the organic outgrowth of a particular
72
Ibid. For a fuller treatment of some of the epistemological issues associated
with the historical nature of thought and writing, see Ryn, Will, Imagination and
Reason: Babbitt, Croce, and the Problem of Reality, 2nd expanded edition with a major
new introduction by the author (New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers, 1997),
especially Chapter 7.
73
Ryn characterizes this as the past “moving in” the present. Ryn, “Defining
Historicism,” 89.
Burke's Historical Morality
HUMANITAS•61
Interpreting
the past
changes the
present.
“past” that is responsible for present circumstances and the changes that have taken place.
Second, the continuity between past and present achieved by
Human
particularity’s mediation is sufficient for the task of finding inunderstanding spiration in the instantiations of the good in the past. For it is not
and moral
necessary in order for such inspiration to occur to understand the
action are at
concrete good of the past precisely as it was understood by those
once historically situated who realized it. All that is necessary is for such concretizations to
and morally
evoke the quality of inspiration associated with “the general bank
meaningful
and capital of nations and of ages,” as seen through the lens of
beyond the
one’s particular historical situation. Individuals and societies will
historical
always grasp historical episodes from within the particularity of
moment.
their own perspective, which is to say, they will take inspiration
and appropriate history in ways that are unique and meaningful for their own perspective. In fact, the understanding of those
who previously realized the concrete good would be anachronistic
from the perspective of the person acting in the present, since it
is the particularity of his own perspective that alone has meaning
for him. Consequently, the concretized good is not good from an
“objective” point of view, if by objective one means understood
and assessed from an ahistorical vantage point. Insofar as man is
concerned, his understanding and moral action are at once historically situated and morally meaningful beyond the confines of
their historical moment. Obtaining objectivity of perspective in the
manner of a purported ahistorical observer is both impossible and
beside the point.
Summary
The development of historical consciousness among modern
thinkers has not resulted in a consensus on the implications of the
historicity of human existence for morality. The purpose of this
article has been to identify a particular strain of historical thinking
and to defend its interpretation of what it means for morality to be
conceived historically. Burke’s writing inspires a way of thinking
about morality—what Ryn terms “value-centered historicism”—
that is at odds with both the intellectualist tradition in moral philosophy and historically informed theories that infer the relativity
of morals. Rejecting the notion that justice ought to be conceived
as abstract principles of the intellect, Burke’s thinking instead suggests that morality comes to be in concrete, human conduct. Burke
62• VolumeXX,Nos.1and2,2007
Ryan Holston
sees both good and evil as manifested in various forms of social
interaction, each time realized anew within history and under new
circumstances. But this situated character of morality need not imply moral relativism. In fact, Burke’s concern with abstract norms
is that their insensitivity to circumstance precludes the realization
of just outcomes. What is just varies based on the historical context
of human action and must, in that sense, be considered mutable.
While justice is particular, insofar as its form is always changing,
it is, in another sense, universal, insofar as its spirit endures and
transcends these permutations within history.
The idea that what endures coexists with what changes expresses the dialectical character of Burke’s historical consciousness.
There are two senses in which Burke comprehends continuity in
the face of historical change. First is his notion that concretizations
of the good in the past can inspire in the decision-makers of the
present novel action of a superior normative quality. As such, the
good is itself expanded and enriched as “the bank and capital of
nations and of ages” is further built upon with every new historical instantiation. Second, insofar as we inherit a past from generations before us, it affects everything we are, from the problems we
confront to the way in which we conceive of alternatives for action.
Burke’s references to the intergenerational society that exists over
time implies the sense that we inherit and bequeath to one another
more than mere material possessions—a real history and culture that
binds the ages. There is continuity through change with respect to
both the normativity and the facticity of man’s historical existence.
Burke's Historical Morality
HUMANITAS•63