The Science of Mind (精神科学) 54 (2016), pp. 51-70.
Putnam and Davidson on
Coherence, Truth, and Justification
Lajos L. Brons
Nihon University
In the early 1980s both Donald Davidson and Hilary Putnam defended theories
that superficially appear to be coherence theories of truth, but that upon closer
inspection turn out to be better understood as coherence theories of justification
(or perhaps, not as coherence theories at all). In Reason, Truth and History
(1981a), Putnam argued that “truth is an idealization of rational acceptability”
(55), and that rational acceptability of statements is their “coherence and fit”
(id.). And in the same year Davidson gave a talk that would be published two
years later as “A Coherence Theory of Truth and Knowledge” (1983) in which
he defended “what may as well be called a coherence theory of truth and
knowledge” (137). There are more interesting similarities between Putnam’s and
Davidson’s theories than their closeness in dates of birth, however, and in later
work Putnam’s theory further converged with Davidson’s. Furthermore, the most
conspicuous difference – the role and nature of “conceptual schemes” – turns out
to be smaller and more subtle than it may seem at a first glance.
This paper introduces Putnam’s and Davidson’s coherence theories, and
discusses the most important differences and similarities. The following two
sections summarize “middle” Putnam’s and Davidson’s coherence theories
respectively. The two sections after that look into the apparent disagreement on
the possibility of different conceptual schemes, and discuss further developments
in Putnam’s view and the consequent convergence of Putnam’s and Davidson’s
coherentisms. The final section briefly compares the resulting – largely shared –
51
theory with more recent conceptions of coherentism and concludes that by
current standards, Putnam’s and Davidson’s theories are not coherence theories
but hybrids between coherentism and foundationalism.
As will become apparent in the following, both Putnam’s and Davidson’s
writings resist easy interpretation, albeit for very different reasons. Interpreting
Putnam is complicated by his changes of mind; interpreting Davidson by his
obscurity. Putnam belonged to the rare breed of thinkers that aren’t afraid to
reject their own ideas upon realization of their incoherence. For some time in the
1960s and early 1970s, he was at the forefront of analytic philosophy, but when
he became increasingly aware of problems and contradictions in the mainstream
view he had helped to build, he left it behind. And when he found problems in
the views he defended next (in his “middle” period), he left those behind as well.
In this process he became more and more critical of mainstream analytic
philosophy.1 More importantly, because of this continuing development, one
cannot look for clarification of Putnam’s ideas in his own (much) earlier or later
writings. In contrast, in case of Davidson, one has to look for clarification in
earlier and later writings.
Contrary to Putnam, changes in Davidson’s philosophical views are few and
subtle. Davidson was a systematic thinker, and as he suggested in (1990), much
of his system was already in place in the early 1960s. That system was built on
Quine’s (with some modifications), and consequently, like Quine, Davidson
rejected many of the core beliefs of mainstream analytic philosophy. 2 By
implication, his philosophical ideas and terminology (like Quine’s) cannot be
taken at face value (let alone lifted out of their context), and can only be properly
understood within the broader program they are part of (e.g. Malpas 2011a;
Brons 2014). But there are further complications in interpreting Davidson’s
1
For example, in “After Empiricism” (1985), Putnam writes that analytic philosophy is “total
shambles”, that its achievements are entirely negative and that it has only “succeeded in
destroying the very problem with which it started”, that it has “failed”, and that it is “at a dead
end” (51).
2
But unlike Quine (and Putnam) it appears that Davidson was not always fully aware of this. In
fact, he was even surprised when he was characterized as “post-analytic” (1993a).
52
Putnam and Davidson on Coherence, Truth, and Justification
writings. “His style was too cryptic and elliptical, so that it was often unclear
what his claims or arguments were,” said Timothy Williamson about Davidson
in an interview (Williamson & Bo 2009: 60).3 Williamson is not a Davidsonian,
of course, but similar remarks, differing more in tone than in content, can be
found in the writings of philosophers closer to Davidson.4
Davidson himself once described his style as “breathless”,5 and this seems a
fitting adjective. Most of his essays were talks originally, and even those that
were not read like lecture transcripts: style and tone are informal, and usually the
same applies to the reasoning. Because of this, upon a first and cursory reading
many of Davidson’s essays seem to make sense (perhaps to be convincing even),
but second, third, and further readings to figure out what exactly his argument is
often result in puzzlement and more questions than answers. Sometimes the
answers to such questions can be found elsewhere in Davidson’s writings, but
this only points at a related problem already hinted at above: understanding a
single text by Davidson usually requires (at least some) familiarity with all of his
writings.
Putnam on rational acceptability
Hilary Putnam developed a kind of coherentism as part of the “internal realism”
that he defended from 1976 until he gave it up in favor of “natural realism” in
the early 1990s (see especially 1999). It is not clear, however, whether this
3
Williamson continues: “in response to questions or objections, he was defensive and guarded,
doing little to articulate his ideas more explicitly,” but this is not entirely accurate in my opinion.
Rather, I would say that Davidson’s “responses” were not responses at all: he rarely addressed the
issues raised by those he was responding to. Nevertheless, in some “responses”, he did
(somewhat) clarify his ideas, and consequently, these are valuable sources. Examples of this are
many of the responses in Hahn (1999) and (Davidson 2001a).
4
For example, Ernest Lepore and Kirk Ludwig (2005) write about some apparently critical aspect
of Davidson’s theory of triangulation that “the suggestion is not spelled out enough for it to be
clear what is intended” (408n), and Peter Pagin’s (2001) influential analysis of that same theory
is littered with statements like “if I understand him” and other expressions of uncertainty and
puzzlement.
5
“… let me continue in my breathless way through one more chapter” (1988a: 43).
53
change also implies a rejection of his coherence theory, or merely an
amendment. I will interpret it as the latter below (after introducing Davidson’s
theory), and will briefly introduce the original, internal realist version of
Putnam’s coherentism in this section. Before proceeding, it must be mentioned,
however, that Putnam did not use the term “coherence theory” himself. In fact,
he rejected the label “coherence theory of truth” because of its (to him)
unacceptable connotations.
In Reason, Truth and History (1981a) Putnam argues that there are two opposing
philosophical perspectives. One is that of metaphysical realism or externalism,
which assumes that “the world consists of some fixed totality of mindindependent facts” and that “there is exactly one true and complete description of
‘the way the word is’” (49). The externalist theory of truth is correspondentist:
truth is some kind of correspondence relation of words (etc.) with external
things. Externalism requires and assumes the possibility of an external point of
view, which Putnam aptly characterizes as a “God’s Eye point of view” (id.).
The other perspective – the one Putnam preferred – is that of internalism or
internal realism. According to internalism, a question like “What objects does the
world consist of?” can only be sensibly asked (and answered) “within a theory or
description” (id.), and an internalist theory may hold “that there is more than one
‘true’ theory or description of the world” (id.). About the notion of truth in the
internalist perspective, he wrote that:
‘Truth’ … is some sort of (idealized) rational acceptability – some sort of ideal
coherence of our beliefs with each other and with our experiences as those
experiences are themselves represented in our belief system – and not
correspondence with mind-independent or discourse-independent ‘states of
affairs’. There is no God’s Eye point of view that we can know or usefully
imagine; there are only the various points of view of actual persons reflecting
various interests and purposes that their descriptions and theories subserve.
(1981a: 49-50; italics in original)6
6
54
On “truth” in internal realism, see also (Putnam 1983a; 1983b).
Putnam and Davidson on Coherence, Truth, and Justification
While Putnam noted that internalism does not necessarily hold that there are
multiple true descriptions of the world, his internal realism does hold this claim.
The externalist (or Aristotelian/medieval/Kripkean essentialist) idea of selfidentifying objects makes no sense.7 Rather, “‘objects’ do not exist
independently of conceptual schemes. We cut up the world into objects when we
introduce one or another scheme of description” (52). And there are multiple
ways to do that “cutting up”: there are (at least sometimes) “equally coherent but
incompatible conceptual schemes which fit our experience equally well” (73).
That doesn’t mean that “anything goes”, however, or that any conceptual scheme
is as good as any other. Internal coherence is not the only constraint on
knowledge – there are “experiential inputs” to knowledge as well. These inputs
are partially shaped by our concepts (or conceptual schemes), but only partially,
and rational acceptability of some set of beliefs also requires coherence with
these experiential inputs.
What makes a statement, or a whole system of statements – a theory or
conceptual scheme – rationally acceptable is, in large part its coherence and fit;
coherence of “theoretical” of less experiential beliefs with one another and with
more experiential beliefs, and also coherence of experiential beliefs with
theoretical beliefs. (1981a: 54-5)
Despite the above quoted claim that, for the internalist, truth is some sort of
rational acceptability, Putnam rejects the identification of truth with rational
acceptability. “Truth cannot simply be rational acceptability for one fundamental
reason; truth is supposed to be a property of a statement that cannot be lost,
whereas justification can be lost” (55). In other words, it is justification that is
identified with rational acceptability (and thus coherence) rather than truth,
which means that Putnam’s coherentism is a coherence theory of justification.
7
See also (1981b) and (1983a): “The idea … – i.e., that nature itself determines what our words
stand for – is totally unintelligible. At bottom, to think that a sign-relation is built into nature is to
revert to medieval essentialism, to the idea that there are ‘self-identifying objects’ and ‘species’
out there” (xii).
55
Nevertheless, Putnam does associate truth with “some sort of” rational
acceptability: “truth is an idealization of rational acceptability. We speak as if
there were such things as epistemically ideal conditions, and we call a statement
‘true’ if it would be justified under such conditions” (55; underlining added). 8
“Truth” is not defined as idealized rational acceptability (or “idealized
justification”; p. 122) either, however. The logical nature of underlined “is” and
“if” in the last quote is that of coincidence and material equivalence respectively,
not that of conceptual identity and logical equivalence. The relation between
truth and idealized justification must be one of material equivalence because it
makes no sense to suppose that a statement could be justified under ideal
epistemic conditions and false nevertheless,9 but there is no reason to suppose it
is stronger than material equivalence. This raises the question how – according to
Putnam – “truth” should be defined, but unfortunately, in Putnam’s writings of
the last two or three decades it tends to be (much) clearer what he rejects than
what (exactly) he accepts, and this is the case for “truth” as well.
Davidson’s “coherence theory”
Donald Davidson defended his brand of coherentism most explicitly in “A
Coherence Theory of Truth and Knowledge” (1983), but it is connected to many
other of his writings and ideas. Despite the title of the ’83 paper, Davidsonian
coherentism is not a coherence theory of truth and/or knowledge. As Davidson
8
In (1983b) he writes: “A statement is true, in my view, if it would be justified under epistemically
ideal conditions” (84).
9
Putnam first made the claim that “the supposition that even an ‘ideal’ theory (…) might really be
false appears to collapse into unintelligibility” in (1976). That it is, is easy to see if one considers
the implications of this supposition (but it should be noted that the following is not Putnam’s
argument). If there would be something that is undetectable even under ideal epistemic
conditions, then that (kind of) thing would be absolutely isolated from anything in the ideally
detectable universe, meaning that it would have no effect or influence of any other kind on
anything (in the same ideally detectable universe). That would require it to be non-physical and
without physical causes or effects. Hence, it would not just be unknowable, but also utterly
mysterious, and given its absolute lack of causal powers also completely irrelevant. The idea of
supposing such a (kind of) thing indeed makes no sense.
56
Putnam and Davidson on Coherence, Truth, and Justification
later admitted (1987b), the title is misleading and chosen badly. The sloganesque
phrase “coherence yields correspondence” (1983: 137) in the first paragraph is
equally misleading, but at the same time oddly accurate as a summary of
Davidson’s argument. What makes it misleading – like the paper’s title – is
Davidson’s idiosyncratic use of terms like “coherence” or “coherence theory”
and “correspondence”.
Firstly, Davidsonian coherentism is not a coherence theory of truth because there
can be no theory of truth, or at least no theory that is not “empty or wrong”
(1987b: 155). Truth is a primitive, it is “as clear and basic a concept as we have”
(id.). A theory of truth as a definition of truth and/or a specification of what
makes a belief true adds nothing to our understanding of what truth is. “Truth is
correspondence with the way things are” (1983: 139), but correspondence does
not make a belief true: correspondence is what “truth” means, not what truth
requires. According to (the most common version of) the correspondence theory,
correspondence to facts makes beliefs or sentences true. Davidson rejects the
truth-making element thereof, but also the specific idea of facts as truth-makers.
According to Davidson, there are no distinct facts; there is at most one fact
(1969), and consequently, “there is nothing for sentences to correspond to”
(1987b: 183). Hence, the intentionally vague phrasing as “correspondence with
the way things are”.
Secondly, Davidson rejects the empiricist notion of justification of beliefs by
sense data (or something similar). This argument is related to his rejection of
conceptual schemes and the “third dogma of empiricism” in (1974), and further
elaborated in “The Myth of the Subjective” (1988a). The core idea is that the
relation between sensations and beliefs is causal: sensations cause beliefs, but a
cause is not a justification. Furthermore, beliefs are propositional and the only
thing that can justify a proposition is another (set of) proposition(s). Sensation,
however, is not propositional and there is no special class of intermediate beliefs
such as “observation sentences”. If there is a distinction between observation
sentences and other kinds of beliefs, it is a distinction of their causes, not of their
57
justifications (1983: 145-6). Regardless of the kind or nature of a belief, “nothing
can count as a reason for holding a belief except another belief” (141).
Davidson suggests a few times in the first pages of his “A Coherence Theory”
that coherence is a test of truth, but these suggestions should not be confused
with the idea that coherence makes a belief true, however – that would be getting
things the wrong way around. Coherence can be a test of truth because according
to Davidson, each of our beliefs may be false, but not all of them can be wrong
(140), and consequently, coherence with our necessarily mostly true beliefs,
justifies the belief that a belief is true. More precisely: coherence does not make
a first-order belief true, but justifies a second-order belief x that a first-order
belief y is true. Hence, Davidson’s theory is a coherence theory of justification.
The question, of course, is why coherence would justify the second-order belief
that a first-order belief is true. “Mere coherence, no matter how strongly
coherence is plausibly defined, cannot guarantee that what is believed is so”
(1983: 138). However, it can and does if it is the case that “most of the beliefs in
a coherent set of beliefs are true” (id.). According to Davidson this is the case
because “belief is in its nature veridical” (146). In “a Coherence Theory” (and
elsewhere) he offered two closely related arguments for this claim. What relates
the two arguments is that both depend on the triangle of speaker, interpreter, and
a shared world. In Davidson’s early writings this triangle plays a central role in
his theory of radical interpretation; in his later writings the triangular figure is
used to explain intersubjectivity, among others. The “omniscient interpreter”
argument for the veridicality of belief (which first appeared in 1977) is based on
the former, and most commentators focus on this argument. However, Davidson
himself later rejected it as a “sortie into science fiction” (1999b: 192).
The second – and more important – argument is closely related to the
aforementioned causal theory of mental content and belief. Davidson
summarizes this argument in a key passage near the end of “A Coherence
Theory” as follows:
58
Putnam and Davidson on Coherence, Truth, and Justification
What stands in the way of global skepticism of the senses is, in my view, the fact
that we must, in the plainest and methodologically most basic cases, take the
objects of a belief to be the causes of that belief. And what we, as interpreters,
must take them to be is what they in fact are. Communication begins where
causes converge: your utterance means what mine does if belief in its truth is
systematically caused by the same events and objects. (1983: 151)
Communication and language learning require the same triangle of speaker (or
teacher), interpreter (or learner), and a shared world as that required by (radical)
interpretation. The interpreter/learner can not make sense of a word if she does
not share an experience of the object or event referred to by the speaker/teacher
in using that word. At the most basic level, our words are (and must be)
grounded through a social process in a shared, real, external world.
Although this is the same triangle as that of radical interpretation, Davidson’s
theory of “triangulation” or “ostensive learning” turns that triangle on its head.
The theory has weaker and stronger versions or applications. Weaker versions
are intended to explain the source and possibility of intersubjective truth (e.g.
1982a). Stronger versions elaborate Davidson’s claim that “successful
communication proves the existence of a shared, and largely true, view of the
world” (1977: 201). In its strongest form, the theory of triangulation can be
interpreted as a transcendental argument: from the fact that we do communicate
it follows that there is such a shared world, that there are other minds, and that
our beliefs about the shared world are mostly true (e.g. Davidson 1987a; 1991;
see also Sosa 2003).10 It’s a variant of the stronger form that provides the second
argument for the veridicality of belief: the facts that we do have language and are
able to communicate prove that most of our most basic beliefs must be true.
10 Davidson tended to retreat from stronger versions of triangulation to weaker ones in response to
criticism. See, for example, various replies in Hahn (1999) and (Davidson 2001a).
59
conceptual schemes
There is much that Putnam and Davidson would have been able to agree upon
(provided that differences in background, style, and terminology wouldn’t
obstruct mutual understanding). Most fundamentally, both argue that – as
Putnam (1981a) phrases it – “the notion of comparing our systems of beliefs
with unconceptualized reality to see if they match makes no sense” (130), and
that we can only justify our beliefs (etc.) by appealing to other beliefs and
coherence therewith. But there are also important differences, and there are
problems especially in Putnam’s theory, which lead him to give up “internal
realism” in the 1990s (see next section).
The most conspicuous difference between Putnam’s internal realism and
Davidson’s philosophy concerns conceptual schemes. Putnam claims that
description is relative to conceptual schemes and that there are “incompatible
conceptual schemes”, while Davidson famously rejects the “very idea” of
conceptual schemes in (1974). The extent of difference on this issue should not
be exaggerated, however. The gap is made to look wider than it is by
terminological and stylistic differences, and by established preconceptions about
Putnam and Davidson; it can be narrowed by looking below the surface.
Davidson did not reject all notions of conceptual schemes (and thus not “the very
idea”, despite the title of 1974), but only a particular notion of conceptual
schemes that he ascribed to Whorf, Kuhn, and Quine, among others. 11 That
particular notion is one of untranslatable schemes. Additionally, he rejected an
idea that he assumed to be inherently related to the notion of conceptual schemes
and that he called “the third dogma of empiricism”: the idea of epistemic
intermediaries between the world and our minds. The latter rejection was further
developed in “The Myth of the Subjective” (1988a). (We’ll turn to this topic in
the next section.)
11 In (Brons 2011) I show that Davidson misinterpreted Whorf and Kuhn and claimed that he only
rejected a Quinean notion of conceptual schemes. I have come to believe that the latter claim is
wrong, and that Davidson misunderstood Quine as well.
60
Putnam and Davidson on Coherence, Truth, and Justification
That Davidson did not completely reject the notion of conceptual schemes is
evidenced by his own occasional use of the term. For example, in “Seeing
Through Language” (1997) he recognized that there are (or can be) “differences
or provincialisms in our conceptual schemes. But these are variants or features
we can explain to one another, or could, given enough time, adequate attention,
and sufficient intelligence on both sides” (128; see also 1999c).
In (1974) and elsewhere Davidson rejected the idea of untranslatable or
incommensurable conceptual schemes, but even though the above quoted term
“incompatible” may seem to suggest otherwise, Putnam (1981a) rejected
incommensurability between schemes as well (see 114ff). Hence, the difference
between Putnam and Davidson with regards to schemes is not one of rejection
versus acceptance, but one of the degree of possible difference between schemes.
According to Quine (1960) different conceptual schemes commit us to the
existence of different things; that is, different schemes posit different things.
Putnam and Davidson appear to disagree about our freedom in positing things.
More specifically, they appear to give different answers to the question whether
our posits (or positings) follow inherent “joints” in nature or external reality.
“Appear to” because Putnam’s answer to this question is clear – it is a negative
answer12 – but Davidson’s is not.
One of Davidson’s arguments against conceptual schemes in (1974) is that those
“organize” what is already organized. This argument makes sense only if it is
interpreted as meaning that nature or reality provides that prior organization. His
arguments in (1992) and (1993b) similarly seem to depend on the presupposition
of an external reality consisting of (or pre-organized into) discrete objects and
events, and in (1999d) Davidson argued for the existence of “divisions in nature”
explicitly:
12 According to Putnam there are no joints or self-identifying objects: “we cut up the world into
objects” (1981a: 52). See also above.
61
Nature is pretty much how we think it is. There really are people and atoms and
stars, given what we mean by the words. The infertility of hybrids defines real
species, though this matters only to those interested in the relevant concepts. This
explains why it is foolish to deny that these divisions exist in nature, whether or
not anyone entertains the thought. Even if no one had ever had a concept, there
would be species, though of course this is our concept and our word, born of our
interests. (38)
Furthermore, Davidson’s notion of causality as a law-like relation between kinds
of events presupposes that events come in discrete natural kinds (and perhaps
even kinds with causal essences). And the fact that he called the irreducibility of
kinds of mental events to kinds of brain events “anomalous monism” strongly
suggests that he not just took natural kinds for granted, but their reducibility to
more basic, physical kinds as well (otherwise there wouldn’t be anything
“anomalous” about the mind), and as John Dupré (1993) has shown, such
reducibility requiries natural kinds to have structural essences.
Although this may seem to settle the question – Davidson’s answer to the
question whether our posits follow inherent joints in nature was positive – that
may be too hasty. None of the “textual evidence” is unambiguous, and Samuel
Wheeler (2014), for example, has argued that Davidson actually held the
opposite position (i.e. that he denied joints in reality). Furthermore, Frank Farell
(1994), Jeff Malpas (2001b), and me (Brons 2012; 2013) have defended
interpretations or extensions of Davidson’s philosophy that give (moderately)
negative (i.e. joint-denying) answers as well. If these interpretations are right (or
these extensions don’t deviate all too radically from their source), then the
difference between Putnam and Davidson on the matter of conceptual schemes
turns out to be very small; but even if they are wrong, Putnam and Davidson are
considerably closer than they seemed at first hand.
62
Putnam and Davidson on Coherence, Truth, and Justification
convergence
In the early 1990s Putnam became increasingly aware of a number of problems
with internal realism, which resulted in his rejection of that theory in favor of
“natural realism” (in or before the Dewey Lectures given in 1994 and published
in 1999). Some of these problems relate directly to his coherence theory, but as
mentioned before, it is not clear whether the switch to natural realism implies a
rejection or amendment of his coherentism. Perhaps, the lack of a clear positive
theory in Putnam’s writings of this period should be taken to mean that he
intended natural realism to be an amendment rather than a substitute. Because in
the present context it is more productive to treat it as an amendment indeed, that
is what I will assume it is.
The most common objection to coherence theories is that they seem to imply that
any coherent system of beliefs is as good as any other coherent system of beliefs.
Putnam (1981a) and Davidson had different answers to that objection. Putnam’s
answer was that the choice between conceptual schemes is constrained by
experiential inputs which are partially conceptual, and that we judge whole
schemes by – among others – their coherence with experiential inputs. But this
suggestion results in a dilemma. If these experiential inputs are (even partially)
conceptual indeed, then they are already (largely) determined by a scheme and
thus cannot function as scheme-independent constraints. If they are not
conceptual (to a significant extent) then this (testing for) coherence with
experiential inputs is nothing but another variety of “comparing our systems of
beliefs with unconceptualized reality to see if they match” (1981a: 130), which
“makes no sense” (id.). Putnam (1999) opted for the first horn of this dilemma,
and thus gave up on the idea of external coherence of a scheme with experience
(or experiential beliefs or inputs).13
13 It is a peculiar twist that what lead to the rejection of internal realism is that it wasn’t
(consistently) internal enough.
63
A few pages back I mentioned that Davidson’s (1974) rejection of the notion of
conceptual schemes was related to his rejection of “the third dogma of
empiricism”: the idea of epistemic intermediaries between the world and our
minds. In The Threefold Cord (1999) Putnam focuses his attention on perception
to develop a similar view. He characterizes the belief in an interface between the
mind and the (external) world as “Cartesian” and “disastrous” (43). In perception
we have direct and unmediated contact with the world, but it is a conceptual
contact. Davidson similarly rejects the idea of non-conceptual (or even nonpropositional) perception. “What the senses ‘deliver’ (i.e., cause) in perception is
perceptual beliefs”, he argues (1999a: 106). And both authors argue that with
giving up the “disastrous” idea of an intermediary between our mind and the
world, there is no room left for skepticism or massive error. According to
Davidson, “it is impossible for most of our perceptual beliefs to be false”
(1998b: 189). Hence, for both Davidson and Putnam (real)14 perception (or
perceptual belief) is inherently veridical as well as conceptual.15
It is from this idea that Davidson’s answer to the aforementioned most common
objection to coherence theories follows: internal coherence is sufficient. 16
Because most of our (most basic) beliefs are necessarily true (because they are
caused by the world), any completely internally coherent set of beliefs must be
true. And therefore, internal coherence (with other beliefs) is sufficient to justify
(the belief in the truth of) some particular belief. Putnam (1999) gives
14 As opposed to illusions and hallucinations. Putnam (1999) rejects the common suggestion that
these are indistinguishable from perception.
15 There are differences, however. For example, Davidson describes the relation between the world
and our perceptual beliefs as causal, while Putnam appears to reject this suggestion. The
disagreement may be largely terminological, however, although this is difficult to judge as
neither author is sufficiently clear on this issue.
16 Davidson attributes this “most common objection” to Moritz Schlick in (1982b). He quotes
Schlick arguing that “the coherence theory is shown to be logically impossible … for by means
of it I can arrive at any number of consistent systems of statements which are incompatible with
one another”, to which he replies that “it’s not clear what it means to say I could ‘arrive’ at
various systems, since I do not invent my beliefs; most of them are not voluntary” (173).
64
Putnam and Davidson on Coherence, Truth, and Justification
approximately the same answer for approximately the same reasons: the
veridicality of perception implies that internal coherence is sufficient.
Putnam’s philosophical development can be characterized as a step-wise process
in which more constructive phases of theory development and elaboration are
interspersed with shorter, more destructive phases resulting from the realization
that the theory developed and elaborated in the preceding constructive phase can
no longer be maintained (see introduction). Hence, a comparison between
“middle” and “late” Putnam is a comparison between two constructive phases,
which means an analysis of the destructive phase in between. Putnam gave up
his (1981a) “middle” coherence theory because it was incoherent in requiring
what it rejected, namely to compare (systems of) beliefs to reality. In (1999) he
suggests that he “went astray” because he “was still assuming something like the
sense datum picture” (18), the “disastrous idea that has haunted Western
philosophy since the seventeenth century” (43).
The key point of Davidson’s coherence theory – simultaneously accurately and
misleadingly summarized as “coherence yields correspondence” – is that
coherence justifies the belief that a belief is true, and truth means
correspondence. The former is the case because most of our (most basic) beliefs
are necessarily true; the latter is primitive.17 Between (1981a) and (1999) Putnam
gradually moved closer to Davidson. 18 If (1999) is read as an amendment of his
(1981a) coherentism, then the differences between his later coherentism and
Davidson’s are small and subtle.
17 Or more accurately, the concept of truth is a primitive, and that primitive concept means a kind of
correspondence with the way things are.
18 Unfortunately not just in substance, but in style as well, considering that some of Putnam’s later
writings surpass even Davidson in inscrutability.
65
But is it coherentism?
Putnam’s and Davidson’s coherence theories have been largely ignored in the
debate on coherentism about justification of the last decades. 19 Since the end of
the 1990s much of that debate is phrased in probabilistic terms. One of the most
influential arguments against a coherence theory of justification is presented by
Erik Olsson in (2002). It’s most recent version can be found in Olsson (2012).
The following summary is based on that version.
If E1 is the proposition that witness 1 reports that A and E2 is the proposition that
witness 2 reports that A, then coherentism claims that:
[Coherence Justification]
P(A | E1, E2) > P(A) .
However, if the two testimonies are independent from each other, then it is the
case that:
[Conditional Independence]
P(E2 | E1,A) = P(E2 | A) & P(E2 | E1,¬A) = P(E2 | ¬A) .
And if coherentist justification and foundationalist justification are mutually
exclusive, then the following applies:
[Non-foundationalism]
P(A | E1) = P(A) & P(A | E2) = P(A) .
And from [Conditional Independence] and [Non-foundationalism] it follows that:
P(A | E1, E2) = P(A) ,
which contradicts [Coherence Justification]. Therefore, coherentism is wrong.
Of course, neither Putnam nor Davidson ever responded to this objection, but
what their response would be can be easily inferred from the foregoing.
Putnam’s (1999) thesis of the veridicality of perception and Davidson’s thesis of
19 For example, in Olsson (2005) Putnam is mentioned only once in a footnote and Davidson is
quickly discarded after a brief recapitulation of the usual misunderstandings about his view.
66
Putnam and Davidson on Coherence, Truth, and Justification
the veridicality of (perceptual) belief imply a rejection of
[Non-foundationalism]
in
favor of something like:
[Weak Foundationalism]
P(A | E1) > P(A) & P(A | E2) > P(A) ,
provided that the probabilistic framework and conceptualization in terms of
witness reports would make sense to them, of course (which is far from
obvious). And from
[Conditional Independence]
and
[Weak Foundationalism]
the
conclusion [Coherence Justification] does follow.
However, if Putnam’s and Davidson’s theories adhere to something like
Foundationalism],
[Weak
then they are not coherence theories, because coherentism
supposedly adheres to
[Non-foundationalism].
Rather, if the theses of the
veridicality of perception and belief are interpreted as a kind of (weak)
foundationalism, then Putnam’s and Davidson’s theories of justification are
hybrids between coherentism and foundationalism,20 and are, therefore, more
closely related to other hybrids such as those defended by Susan Haack (2009) 21
and Paul Thagard (2000) than to the “pure” coherentism that Olsson and others
argue against. This shouldn’t come as a surprise, however, considering that
Davidson wrote about “a pure coherence theory” that “perhaps no one has ever
held such a theory, for it is mad” (2005a: 43).
A potentially more serious problem for Davidson’s and Putnam’s coherence
theories (I’ll continue to call them that, even if they really are hybrids) than that
posed by Olsson is the ambiguity of the notion of coherence. Neither Putnam,
nor Davidson ever specified what exactly coherence means and/or requires in
this context. What does it mean for a set of beliefs to be coherent?
20 Not just Putnam’s and Davidson’s epistemological theories are hybrids; so is their metaphysics.
Both opt for a hybrid of – or intermediate position between – realism and anti-realism. Davidson
(2005a) rejects both realism and anti-realism and argues that these are not the only options, and
Putnam (1999) aims for what he calls “a middle way between reactionary metaphysics and
irresponsible relativism” (5).
21 Haack spends many pages arguing against Davidson’s coherentism, but in those pages she only
rejects the “omniscient interpreter” argument, which Davidson later rejected himself.
67
Mere non-contradiction (in a logical sense) is usually (if not universally)
considered to be insufficient. If there is a set of beliefs B1 about a set of “things”
T1, and another set of beliefs B2 about T2, such that there is no contradictory
belief in B1 and no contradictory belief in B2, and the intersections of B1 and B2
and of T1 and T2 are empty, then the union of B1 and B2 will contain no
contradictory beliefs. It will, however, consist of two subsets that are completely
isolated from each other. Any belief that is isolated in this sense will be perfectly
non-contradictory with any set of beliefs it is isolated from, but this means that
any completely unconnected belief is coherent – by this definition of
“coherence” – and thus justified.
For Davidson, however, this objection to identifying coherence with noncontradiction is irrelevant for two reasons. Firstly, the objection assumes the
existence of discrete, individual beliefs, but according to Davidson there is no
meaningful way to individuate beliefs (1983). And secondly, even if you could
individuate beliefs, there could be no isolated beliefs (in the above sense):
Davidson’s holism entails that every one of our beliefs is necessarily related to
many others (e.g. 1999d; 1995).
The brief considerations in this last section show that Putnam’s and Davidson’s
coherence theories aren’t just of historical interest, but are viable alternatives to
the positions commonly recognized by mainstream analytic epistemology
(although their dependence on unfashionable views such as – but not limited to –
anti-essentialism in case of Putnam and social externalism (i.e. triangulation) and
holism in case of Davidson make it doubtful that they will be welcomed or even
understood by mainstream analytic philosophers). There may very well be other
problems for their theories, of course, but that is a matter for further research.
68
Putnam and Davidson on Coherence, Truth, and Justification
references
Brons, L.L. 2011. “Applied Relativism and Davidson’s Arguments Against Conceptual
Schemes. The Science of Mind 49: 221-40.
—— 2012. “Dharmakīrti, Davidson, and Knowing Reality”. Comparative Philosophy 3.1: 30-57.
—— 2013. “Meaning and Reality: a Cross-Traditional Encounter”. In Bo Mou & R. Tieszen
Eds. Constructive Engagement of Analytic and Continental Approaches in Philosophy.
Leiden: Brill. pp. 199-220.
—— 2014. Book review of: Samuel Wheeler III (2014), Neo-Davidsonian metaphysics: from
the true to the good. In International Journal of Philosophical Studies 22.2: 286-91.
Davidson, D. 1969. “True to the Facts”. In (1984). pp. 43-54.
—— 1974. “On the Very Idea of a Conceptual Scheme”. In (1984). pp. 183-98.
—— 1977. “The Method of Truth in Metaphysics”. In (1984). pp. 199-214.
—— 1982a. “Rational animals”. In (2001b). pp. 95-105.
—— 1982b. “Empirical Content”. In (2001b). pp. 159-76.
—— 1983. “A Coherence Theory of Truth and Knowledge”. In (2001b). pp. 137-53.
—— 1984. Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation. Oxford: Clarendon.
—— 1987a. “Knowing One’s Own Mind”. In (2001b). pp. 15-38.
—— 1987b. “Afterthoughts”. In (2001b). pp. 154-8.
—— 1988a. “The Myth of the Subjective”. In (2001b). pp. 39-52.
—— 1988b. “Epistemology and Truth”. In (2001b). pp. 177-92.
—— 1990. ‘Epistemology externalized’. In: (2001b). pp. 193-204.
—— 1991. “Three Varieties of Knowledge”. In (2001b). pp. 205-20.
—— 1992. “The Second Person”. In (2001b). pp. 107-22.
—— 1993a. “The Third Man”. In (2005b). pp. 159-66.
—— 1993b. “Locating Literary Language”. In (2005b). pp. 167-81.
—— 1995. “The Problem of Objectivity”. In (2004). pp. 3-18.
—— 1997. “Seeing through Language”. In (2005b). pp. 127-42.
—— 1999a. “Reply to John McDowell”. In Hahn (1999). pp. 105-8.
—— 1999b. “Reply to A.C. Genova”. In Hahn (1999). pp. 192-4.
—— 1999c. “Reply to Stephen Neale”. In Hahn (1999). pp. 667-9.
—— 1999d. “Interpretation: Hard in Theory, Easy in Practice”. In M. De Caro Ed.
Interpretations and Causes. Dordrecht: Kluwer. pp. 31-44.
—— 2001a. “Comments on Karlovy Vary Papers”. In Kotatko et al. (2001). pp. 285-307.
—— 2001b. Subjective, Intersubjective, Objective. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
—— 2004. Problems of Rationality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
—— 2005a. Truth and Predication. Cambridge MA: Belknap.
—— 2005b. Truth, language, and history. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Dupré, J. 1993, The Disorder of Things: Metaphysical Foundations of the Disunity of
Science. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.
69
Farell, F.B. 1994. Subjectivity, Realism and Postmodernism: the Recovery of the World in
Recent Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Haack, S. 2009. Evidence and Inquiry: a Pragmatist Reconstruction of Epistemology. New
York: Prometheus.
Hahn, L.E. Ed. 1999. The philosophy of Donald Davidson. Chicago: Open Court.
Kotatko, P., P. Pagin, & G. Segal Eds. 2001. Interpreting Davidson. Stanford: CSLI.
Lepore, E. & K. Ludwig 2005. Donald Davidson: Meaning, Truth, Language, and Reality.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Malpas, J. 2011a. “Introduction” in Malpas, J. ed.. Dialogues with Davidson. Cambridge
MA: MIT Press. pp. xvii-xxv.
—— 2011b. “Triangulation and philosophy: a Davidsonian landscape”. In Amoretti, M.C. &
G. Preyer eds.. Triangulation from an Epistemological Point of View. Frankfurt: Ontos.
257-279.
Olsson, E.J. 2002. “What is the Problem of Coherence and Truth?”, The Journal of
Philosophy 99: 246-72.
—— 2005. Against Coherence: Truth, Probability, and Justification. Oxford: Clarendon.
—— 2012. “Coherentist Theories of Epistemic Justification”. In E.N. Zalta Ed.
The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Spring 2014 Edition.
<http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/justep-coherence/> .
Pagin, P. 2001. “Semantic Triangulation”. In: Kotako, Pagin, & Segal (2001). pp. 199-212.
Putnam, H. 1976. “Realism and Reason”. In 1978. Meaning and the Moral Sciences.
London: Routledge. pp. 123-40.
—— 1981a. Reason, Truth and History. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
—— 1981b. “Why There Isn’t a Ready-Made World”. In (1983c). pp. 205-28.
—— 1983a. “Introduction”. In (1983c). pp. vii-xviii.
—— 1983b. “Reference and Truth”. In (1983c). pp. 69-86.
—— 1983c. Realism and Reason: Philosophical Papers Volume 3. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
—— 1985. “After Empiricism”. In 1990. Realism with a Human Face. Cambridge MA:
Harvard UP. pp. 43-53.
—— 1999. The Threefold Cord: Mind, Body, and World. New York: Columbia University Press.
Quine, W.V.O. 1960. Word & Object. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.
Sosa, E. 2003. “Knowledge of self, others, and world”. In K. Ludwig Ed. Donald Davidson
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 163-82.
Thagard, P. 2000. Coherence in Thought and Action. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.
Wheeler, S.C. 2014. Neo-Davidsonian Metaphysics: from the True to the Good. New York:
Routledge.
Williamson, T. & Chen Bo. 2009. “Thinking Deeply, Contributing Originally: an Interview
with Timothy Williamson”. Annals of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science
18: 57-87.
70