Vision-Based Demonstratives
Hemdat Lerman
Wolfson College, Oxford
DPhil Thesis
Trinity Term 2004
DPhil Thesis
Trinity Term 2004
Hemdat Lerman
Wolfson College, Oxford
Vision-Based Demonstratives
Abstract
How should we account for our ability to entertain simple, vision-based demonstrative
thoughts about particular objects (that is, our ability to entertain thoughts about
particular objects simply on the basis of seeing them)? In this thesis I propose an
account of this ability that accords with the common-sense view that seeing an object
puts one in a position to single it out by visually attending to it, and that this provides
one with the ability to entertain demonstrative thoughts about it.
An account of this type requires that we account for what it is to see a particular
object and to visually attend to it without appealing to particular demonstrative
abilities. However, it has been argued that a notion of seeing an object, and similarly a
notion of attending to an object, which is accounted for in this way is unsuitable for
accounting for demonstrative abilities.
I argue that there is no real problem: what we need is a notion of experiential content
which is concept-dependent only in a general manner. That is, the account of the
relevant notion of experiential content requires appeal to the subject's conceptual
abilities, but the account is not given in terms of specific conceptual abilities
(especially, not specific demonstrative abilities). I then characterize a notion of
attention to a seen object which can be accounted for without appeal to particular
demonstrative abilities, and explain how attending to an object in the relevant sense
provides the subject with the ability to think about the object demonstratively.
It is widely agreed that spatial location plays a central role in an account of
demonstratives. I explain this role in terms of the role played by location in visual
attention to the object and the subject's grasp of the fact that he attends to the object.
Table of contents
Acknowledgements
i
Introduction
ii
Part I: Is the content of experience concept dependent and if so in what way?
Introductory note
1
1. Reasons for rejecting the strong-non-conceptual view
6
2. Reasons for rejecting the strong-conceptual view
26
3. Experience and reasons for beliefs
61
4. Subject-level effects without conceptualization
77
5. The middle position
95
Part II: Vision-based demonstratives
6. Attending to an object and knowing which object one is demonstrating
120
7. The role of knowing which object one is demonstrating
156
8. Demonstratives and spatial location: Evans's view
174
9. Demonstratives and spatial location: CampbelPs view
192
References
213
Acknowledgments
I am greatly indebted to John Campbell and Naomi Eilan, who supervised this thesis,
for their invaluable criticism and advice, as well as for their kind encouragement and
support.
I owe a special thanks to John Campbell for his graduate classes which have been a
constant source of inspiration to this thesis.
Early in the project I worked with Bill Brewer and Galen Strawson for a term each.
Both provided very helpful criticism and suggestions for which I am very grateful.
Drafts of various chapters were read by Steve Butterfill, Dorothea Debus, Yuval
Eylon, Guy Kahane, and Richard Price. I am very grateful to all of them for their very
helpful comments and suggestions. I am particularly grateful to Steve and Richard for
numerous, most helpful discussions of work in progress.
Finally, I would like to thank the AVI Fellowships Foundation, the ORS Awards
Scheme, the Anglo-Jewish Association and the lan Karten Trust for their generous
financial support.
Introduction
How should we account for our ability to entertain simple, vision-based
demonstrative thoughts about particular objects (that is, our ability to entertain
thoughts about particular objects simply on the basis of seeing them)? In this thesis I
propose an account of this ability that accords with the common-sense view that
seeing an object puts one in a position to single it out by visually attending to it, and
that this provides one with the ability to entertain demonstrative thoughts about it.
Specifically, I shall spell out what seeing an object and visually attending to it
involves, in a way which will clarify how visually attending to a seen object provides
the subject with the ability to think about the object demonstratively.
If we are to maintain the common-sense view, we should construe seeing a
particular object and visually attending to it as explanatorily more basic than the
demonstrative ability to which they give rise. However, it has been argued that if we
explain seeing an object and attending to it without appeal to the relevant
demonstrative ability, we shall not be able to account for how it is that these
phenomena provide the subject with a demonstrative ability; specifically, we shall not
be able to account for the fact that they provide the subject with knowledge of which
object is in question. In Part I, I argue that the consideration that gives rise to this
worry only requires that we acknowledge a general link between seeing and the
subject's conceptual abilities; that there is no need to appeal to the particular
demonstrative ability which the experience is supposed to explain. And I shall suggest
a view of experiential content according to which such contents are conceptdependent only in this general sense. In Part II, I characterize a notion of visual
attention which accounts for the subject's ability to entertain demonstrative thoughts
about the object he is attending to, and which is explanatorily more basic than the
ability accounted for.
11
In Part I, then, I argue for a view of experiential contents according to which
such contents are concept-dependent only in a general sense, thus providing us with a
notion of experiential content suitable for the account of demonstrative abilities. I
should clarify that the starting point of the discussion is that, at a general level, our
ability to experience things and our ability to think about them are mutually
dependent. At this general level, it is also the case that the ability to experience
particular objects and the general ability to entertain demonstrative thoughts (i.e., the
ability to entertain demonstrative thoughts about any seen object) are interdependent.
What is at issue is the relation between the particular content of a particular
experience and the subject's conceptual abilities; I ask whether an account of the
former requires appeal to the latter and if it does, whether we need to take into
account only general relations between the experience and the subject's conceptual
abilities, or whether an appeal to a specific conceptual ability (or a specific set of
conceptual abilities) is what accounts for the particular content of the experience in
question.
Part I consists of five chapters. In Chapter 11 argue that one cannot account for
a particular experiential content without some appeal to the subject's conceptual
abilities. The following three chapters contribute to showing that an account of such
content does not require appeal to the specific demonstrative ability to which the
experience in question gives rise (where demonstrative abilities are the only plausible
candidates for being the specific conceptual abilities which explain the content of
particular experiences). The main opponents in these chapters are John McDowell and
Bill Brewer who argue that if experience is to play a role in accounting for our
conceptual abilities, then an experience must be viewed as a special type of attitude
towards a proposition which, like other occurrent propositional attitudes, involves the
iii
actualization of relevant conceptual abilities. Further, they suggest that the relevant
conceptual abilities are demonstrative abilities.
In Chapter 3 I argue that McDowell and Brewer do not provide a conclusive
argument for the claim that the content of an experience must involve the
actualization of conceptual abilities. Chapters 2 and 4 show that we cannot, generally,
construe experiential contents as involving the actualization of demonstrative abilities.
First, in Chapter 2,1 discuss the type of account of demonstrative abilities one is
committed to if one is to construe the experience of a fine-grained property as a matter
of the actualization of a predicate which the subject possesses in virtue of
demonstrating the given instance of the property. I show that the actualization of such
an ability must involve the subject's intentionally attending to the fine-grained
property. Thus, one must either accept that experiential content cannot generally be
construed as a matter of the actualization of demonstrative abilities, or opt for the
unintuitive view that we experience only the fine-grained properties we are
intentionally attending to. I then argue that the aspects of the experiential content
which cannot be accounted for in terms of the actualization of demonstrative abilities
are also not to be accounted for in terms of the relevant non-actualized abilities (i.e.,
the abilities which would have been actualized had the subject attended to the relevant
environmental aspects).
In Chapter 4 I examine what may seem to be empirical support for holding that
we do not experience unattended environmental aspects (i.e., aspects the subject does
not intentionally attend to). Empirical data suggest that our intuitions regarding what
we experience and the effect which our experience has on our activities are often
mistaken. This may encourage one to opt for the unintuitive option that we experience
only the fine-grained properties we are intentionally attending to, instead of accepting
that there are aspects of our experience that cannot be accounted for in terms of the
IV
actualization of demonstrative abilities. In response, I point out (i) that the data are
consistent with the claim that we experience unattended aspects and that such
experiences play a role in the account of the subject's activities, and (ii) that an
interaction with the environment which does not involve experience of unattended
aspects and its effect on the subject's reactions is significantly different from the way
in which we, in fact, normally interact with our environment.
If the arguments presented in Chapters 1 to 4 are correct, then we have good
reasons for accepting that states whose content is the result of the actualization of
conceptual capacities are not the only states which involve the subject's grasp of
normative relations between his state and other prepositional attitudes of his; thus we
have reasons for accepting that experiential states involve such a grasp, even though
their content is to be explained in terms of the actualization of experiential capacities
which are not a type of conceptual capacities. Chapter 5 includes a summary of the
considerations leading to this view and some clarification as to how, on the given
view, particular experiential contents are to be specified.
Given the view of experience suggested by the discussion in Part I, I turn in Part
II to discuss how an experience of an object enables the subject to single out the
object by attending to it. The challenge, again, is to characterize a notion of visual
attention to an object which makes it suitable for explaining the subject's ability to
entertain demonstrative thoughts about objects. Specifically, the subject's attending to
an object in the relevant sense should be explanatorily more basic than the
demonstrative ability it gives rise to and account for the subject's knowledge of which
object he is thinking about when he entertains such thoughts on the basis of the
relevant act of attention to the object.
The experience of objects as the particular objects they are is based on the
organization of the information about objects' seen features as information regarding
the seen features of given objects. Conscious visual attention involves the subject's
sensitivity to this organization. That the information is made available to the subject
organized in this way is due to the ways the visual system binds together visual
information. In chapter 6,1 suggest that what provides the subject who is attending to
an object with knowledge of which object he is attending to, and thus with the ability
to think about the object demonstratively, is the combination of: (i) the fact that
information from a given object is made available to the subject as information from
one and the same object, and (ii) the subject's grasp of this relation between the object
and the relevant information.
The view presented in Chapter 6 resembles, in various respects, John
Campbell's account of demonstratives in Reference and Consciousness. However,
Campbell does not seem to view as pressing the question which is the focus of
Chapter 6 - that is, how conscious attention, construed as more primitive than the
subject's ability to think about the object demonstratively, can be what provides the
subject with knowledge of which object he is thinking about. At least one possible
explanation for this is that on his view the characterization of the functional role of a
demonstrative need not involve an appeal to the way in which, from the subject's
point of view, the experience bears on how to evaluate demonstrative thoughts and
which implications can be drawn from them. In Chapter 7 I argue that this view is
unjustified.
It is widely agreed that spatial location plays a central role in an account of
demonstrative thought, though views differ as to what this role is. In the last two
chapters I discuss the views of Gareth Evans and John Campbell on this matter, and
clarify what role is played by location on the account suggested in Chapter 6.
According to Evans the ability to locate the object is necessary for the subject to
distinguish the object of his thought from any other object. In Chapter 8 I argue that
VI
the only way in which this view can be made tenable already requires that the subject
be able to distinguish the object, and thus that it cannot be that the ability to locate the
object is what explains the ability to distinguish it. According to the view suggested in
Chapter 6, what distinguishes the object for the subject is that he grasps the fact that
he is attending to it. On this view, then, part of the explanation of why location is
central is that the availability of information about the object's location is central to
the subject's grasp of the fact that he is currently attending to the relevant object.
In Chapter 9 I turn to Campbell's view. On his view what matters to the
subject's ability to think demonstratively about a seen object is its apparent location.
When evaluating demonstrative thoughts and acting upon them the visual system
selects the information relevant for the evaluation of the thought or for the guidance
of the action on the basis of location, and Campbell holds that it is the fact that the
subject identifies the object as the object at the apparent location which determines for
the visual system which location is relevant to selecting information for the task in
question. I point out a difficulty with this picture and suggest an alternative way in
which the subject's consciously attending to an object can enable the visual system to
select information from the correct location. An object's apparent location still plays a
role, on this alternative picture, in enabling the subject to focus his attention on it. But
this role is explained by appeal to facts about what, from the subject's point of view,
makes an appearance an appearance as of a single object, distinct from others. I argue
that this is the way to explain the role of apparent location even if the visual system
selects information in the way Campbell suggests it does.
I should briefly note that the discussion in the thesis presupposes a realist view
of the objects and properties we experience. However, the account I suggest, if
accepted, supports such a view as it contributes to spelling out the idea that our ability
vii
to think about mind-independent objects is explicable in terms of our primitive grasp
of the actual relations which obtain between our experiences and the way things are in
our environment.
I should also explain that I focus on vision in order to make the discussion
manageable. Ignoring the other senses is justified by the fact that, in the case of
sighted people, vision is the dominant sense. Furthermore, there seem to be clear
cases in which visual-experience is the only experience relevant to the subject's
ability to identify the object. (I am assuming that, as the discussion concerns the
relation between the experience and the subject's thought, the contribution of nonvisual information at the sub-personal-level need not be taken into account). Note
however that the subjects under discussion are ordinary subjects with, at least, vision,
hearing and touch, and that the subject's primitive conception of perception and
objects, to which I often appeal in the thesis, concerns all three senses. Since I do not
make any particular claims about the structure of this conception in general, the
restriction to vision does not create a problem regarding the relation with the subject's
general primitive conception.
A possible worry about the restriction to vision is whether it limits the
implication of the following discussion to those particular cases in which the subject,
when singling out an object, relies on vision alone. I am relying on a non-trivial
assumption that the discussion is relevant to other cases as well; that is, that the
account of the contribution of vision can be later developed into a more
comprehensive picture which includes the contribution of other senses. In effect, it
might be that without this assumption the discussion is irrelevant to the account of an
ordinary subject's ability to think about particular objects, since it might be that, even
when a subject relies on vision alone, his conception of the seen object depends on his
vni
disposition to immediately take information which could be provided by other senses
to be from the same object when the object is experienced the relevant way.
Some terminological notes:
Since the discussion is limited to visual experience I use 'experience' as
meaning visual experience. Further, I use 'seeing' and 'experiencing' as
interchangeable.
Seeing and experiencing are both taken to be conscious. When I wish to speak
generally about gathering information from the environment by means of the senses that is, when the result could, but need not, be a conscious state -1 shall use
'perception' or 'vision'.
When I speak about the seen (experienced) object (or any other environmental
aspect) I refer to the actual object in the environment.
'The way an object is experienced by (or presented to) the subject', and 'the
way it appears to the subject' are all used interchangeably to refer to the aspect of the
experience which explains variations in the information available to the subject from a
particular environmental aspect.
Talk about appearance is understood disjunctively: it is either a case in which an
environmental aspect is seen or a hallucination.
I use 'information' in a rather loose way, close to the everyday notion.
Experience is said to provide the subject with information about the environment in
virtue of its being the product of a mechanism which is a reliable source of
knowledge. Understood in this way, information can be veridical or non-veridical.
(When I wish to refer only to veridical information I shall say this explicitly). I shall
also speak about the information encoded in sub-personal perceptual states. In this
ix
case informational contents are ascribed in virtue of the representational role the state
plays in processing information and controlling action and thought (at the subpersonal-level). It will be clear from the context whether I am discussing experiential
information, information at the sub-personal-level or, generally, information which
can be available both at the sub-personal-level and to the subject.
Following Evans (1982, pp. 124-5) I shall say that information is from an object
(or some other particular environmental aspect) when, if the mechanism which
produces the relevant informational state is functioning properly, the content of the
state is determined by the object's state.
By 'objects' I mean to refer, roughly, to space occupiers which we can
experience and which are causally connected in the sense that each state of the object
at a time is causally dependent on its earlier state and also in the sense that the
possible causal interactions which each of the simultaneous parts of the object can
undergo are constrained by the part's relation with the other parts of the object. I shall
discuss clear cases such as trees, cats, tables, and ignore problematic cases.
As mentioned above, I shall characterize a specific notion of visual attention to
an object which I take to play a central role in explaining demonstrative abilities. The
relevant notion involves the subject's (intentional) selection of an object on the basis
of his experience, where this, in turn, involves the selection of experiential
information by the subject. There are several other senses in which the subject's
interaction with the environment involves attention. I shall attempt to clarify the sense
in which the expression is used whenever the use changes.
x
Part I: Is the content of experience concept dependent and if so in what way?
Introductory note
I mentioned in the introduction that I am taking for granted that, at a general
level, our experiences depend on our conceptual abilities: generally, we cannot
understand what it is for a subject to have an experience without appeal to his ability
to think about the experienced environment. This still leaves open the question of
whether an account of what it is for a particular experience to have the particular
content it does (rather than others) requires appeal to the subject's conceptual abilities.
In addition, there is room for asking whether what is required is merely that relevant
connections between the experience and the subject's conceptual abilities should
figure in the account (when this is the case I shall say that there is only a general
dependence on the subject's conceptual abilities) or whether we can fully account for
what is unique to the particular content in question in terms of a specific conceptual
ability (or a specific set of conceptual abilities). In this Part I discuss these two
questions. It will be argued that one cannot account for a particular content without
appeal to the subject's conceptual abilities, but that the dependence is only general in
the above sense. 1
The position I am arguing for occupies the middle ground between, on the one
hand, Evans's view according to which no appeal to the subject's conceptual abilities
is required when accounting for the content of a particular experience, and on the
other hand, McDowell and Brewer's view according to which the content is to be
(fully) accounted for in terms of specific demonstrative abilities (abilities to think
1 Hereafter, when I speak about an account of a particular experiential content or simply the account of
an experiential content I mean to refer to the account of what it is for a specific experience to have the
particular content it does (rather than others).
demonstratively about each of the currently experienced aspects). I shall argue that
both views are indefensible and clarify what the suggested middle position is.
When discussing different views as to whether or not experiential contents are
concept dependent in both the general and particular senses mentioned above, I shall
refer to views, such as Evans's, according to which there is not even a general
dependence of the content on conceptual abilities as strong-non-conceptual views, and
to views, such as McDowell and Brewer's, according to which there is a particular
(and therefore also a general) dependence as strong-conceptual views. The middle
position I am arguing for involves the rejection of the two strong views, and is thus
weakly-conceptual and weakly-non-conceptual. I shall say that according to the first
view experiential contents are strongly-non-conceptual, according to the second
strongly-conceptual, and so on. Note that this is not meant as suggesting that there are
different types of experiential content. Rather I am using these terms to refer to what
is supposed to be the same type of content where the difference lies in the view held
regarding how such content is to be construed.2 1 should mention that often, when a
distinction between two types of concept-dependence is made, what I call a strongconceptual view is regarded as the conceptual view, the opposing view is regarded as
non-conceptual, and then a further distinction between two non-conceptual views is
made. 3 The difference is merely terminological. I prefer the above terminology
because it indicates that the fact that an experiential content depends on the subject's
conceptual abilities is not less important to our understanding of what having the
2 This is not to deny the possibility that there are differences between the ways in which different
aspects of experiential content should be accounted for. The claim is only that, to the extent that we are
interested in the experience's making information available to a (concept-possessing) subject, the
relation between the content and the subject's conceptual abilities is generally of the same type, thus in
this respect there is uniformity. This is not a trivial claim and I am not suggesting that it can simply be
taken for granted as a general assumption. However, the views I am arguing against are presented as
uniform in this sense.
3 See for example Peacocke 1992 pp.90-92 and Bermudez 1995.
content involves than the fact that the account does not require appeal to particular
conceptual abilities.
I should emphasize that I am characterizing the type of dependency which
defines what makes a content conceptual or non-conceptual (and to what degree) in
terms of what is required for an account of what it is for an experience to have the
particular content it does. Many writers who intend to discuss whether particular
contents depend on the subject's possessing particular conceptual abilities draw the
distinction between conceptual and non-conceptual content in terms of whether or not
the subject must possess the concepts required for understanding the specification of
the content;4 similarly when the general dependence is discussed, the question of
whether or not there is such dependency is normally presented as a question as to
whether or not having an experience (with the relevant content) requires that the
subject possess any conceptual abilities at all. Drawing the distinction in this way will
not capture the distinction I am interested in. It seems clear that if accounting for
having an experience with a specific content requires appeal to the subject's
conceptual abilities, then one cannot have such an experience without possessing the
relevant conceptual abilities; but, at least in the case of the dependence of the
particular content on particular conceptual abilities, the converse implication need not
hold. For example, one might maintain that a subject cannot have a particular
experience with a particular content without possessing certain demonstrative abilities
(abilities to think demonstratively about the currently experienced environmental
aspects) simply because, given that the subject possesses certain general abilities,
experiencing an environmental aspect is sufficient for providing him with the ability
4 A few examples are Bermudez (1995), Crane (1992 pp. 142-3) and Brewer (1999 p. 149, though
Brewer adds another clause to his definition). Such a definition is also implicit in what Evans says on
p. 159 (1982). The above formulation is meant only as a general indication of the type of
characterization in question. Different writers use different formulations which may differ, sometimes
quite significantly, from the above formulation.
to think about it demonstratively (as would be the case if experiencing the aspect and
possessing the relevant general abilities is what constitutes having the particular
demonstrative ability in question). Now, the fact that X is sufficient for Y does not
entail that Y must play a role in the account of X, and if it is not required for the
account, then there is an important sense in which X is independent of Y even though
we cannot have X without Y. It is exactly this sense of independence which is
relevant in the context of this discussion, as the motivation for discussing the relation
between experiential contents and the subject's conceptual abilities is the need for a
notion of experiential content which is prior in the order of explanation to the
conceptual abilities the relevant experience is supposed to explain.
Some writers characterize what they mean by conceptual content by saying that
it is of the kind that can be the content of judgements and beliefs. 5 Not all views I
regard as strongly-conceptual are conceptual on this definition. It might be held that a
particular content is wholly accounted for in terms of particular conceptual abilities,
though the content itself is not a matter of the actualization of these abilities.
Categorizing views of these two types together is convenient in this context, since I
wish to rule out any view according to which experiential contents are explained in
terms of demonstrative abilities.6
To recap, I regard as conceptual any view according to which some appeal to
the subject's conceptual abilities is required in order to account for what it is for a
particular experience to have the particular content it does. Such a view is stronglyconceptual if it is suggested that what is unique to the content (in contrast to other
5 See for example Peacocke (2001 p.243), McDowell and Brewer.
6 In principle, there might also be room for a view according to which the content is not wholly
explained in terms of specific demonstrative abilities but certain specific demonstrative abilities should
figure in the account. As far as I can see the arguments against the strong-conceptual views are
sufficient for ruling out views of this type. This comment makes clear that my aim here is merely to
present convenient tags for the following discussion.
experiential contents) is to be explained by appeal to specific conceptual abilities, and
otherwise - that is, if only a general dependence on the subject's conceptual abilities is
suggested - it is weakly-conceptual. A view which is not strongly-conceptual - that is,
a view which does not suggest that one can account for what is unique to the content
in terms of the subject's conceptual abilities alone - is regarded as non-conceptual.
Such a view would be strongly-non-conceptual if it is suggested that no appeal to
concepts is required (thus, if it is not conceptual), and weakly-non-conceptual
otherwise. (These distinctions are also summarized in the diagram below).
Part I is structured as follows. In Chapter 1 I argue that we should reject the
strong-non-conceptual view. In Chapters 2 and 4 I argue that the strong-conceptual
view cannot be maintained and in Chapter 3 I reject the argument by which strongconceptualists attempt to show that their view is incumbent on us. Chapter 5
summarizes the arguments and develops further some issues regarding the suggested
middle position.
I should emphasize that I do not intend to develop and defend a detailed account
of all aspects of experiential content. The aim is only to outline a general picture
which will serve as a basis for the discussion in Chapter 6 of how experience enables
demonstrative thoughts about particular objects.
Is it possible to account
for the particular content
in terms of conceptual
abilities alone?
1 Reasons for rejecting the strong-non-conceptual view
I
In this chapter I shall argue that one cannot account for what it is for a
particular experience (i.e. a particular conscious perceptual state) of a (conceptpossessing) subject to have the particular content it does without appealing to the
subject's conceptual abilities. I shall discuss Evans's view since he agrees that the
experiences of concept-possessors are essentially linked with their conceptual
abilities and yet suggests that the particular content of a particular experience could
be accounted for independently of this link. 7 My claim will be that this essential link
between experiences and the subject's conceptual abilities must also be apparent in
any consideration regarding particular experiential contents. I shall consider two
possible readings of how Evans suggests to account for the content of a particular
experience, and argue that neither of them provides an acceptable strong-nonconceptual view. The discussion of the problems encountered by the two readings
will clarify why, generally, strong-non-conceptual views are unfeasible.
I should emphasize that what is at issue is not the interpretation of Evans, but
rather the possibility of a strong-non-conceptual view. Apart from a few occasional
o
comments I shall not discuss the faithfulness of any of the readings to the text. I
should also explain that when discussing Evans's view I normally use his
terminology. When it is unclear how exactly he construes certain terms (e.g., 'internal
states of the organism', 'perceptual input', etc.), I shall use them loosely and tighten
up the use if a need to do so arises.
7 Some of the writers who explicitly maintain that experiential contents can be strongly-nonconceptual do not mean the claim to apply to the experience of concept-possessors (for example, this
seems to be the position of Bermudez, Hurley and Peacocke (in his 2001)).
8 In fact, there is room for reading Evans as suggesting a weak-non-conceptual view of experiential
contents (i.e., of the content of conscious perceptual states of concept-possessors}.
II
Evans claims that for an internal state of a subject to be regarded as having a
certain content - that is, as being a state in which the world is represented a certain
way - 'it must have appropriate connections with behaviour - it must have a certain
motive force upon the actions of the subject'.9 He goes on to say that perceptual
informational states - that is, states produced in a subject by a perceptual mechanism
in response to sensory input 10 - 'have a content by virtue of their phylogenetically
more ancient [than their connections with the concept-exercising and reasoning
system] connections with the motor system... '. n What distinguishes cases in which
the subject's perceptual informational states involve conscious experience from those
in which they do not is that in the former 'the internal states which have a content by
virtue of their phylogenetically more ancient connections with the motor system also
serve as input to the concept-exercising and reasoning system. Judgements are then
based upon (reliably caused by) these internal states'; 12 or as Evans puts it on p. 158
'we arrive at conscious perceptual experience when sensory input is not only
connected to behavioural dispositions... but also serves as input to a thinking,
concept-applying, and reasoning system; so that the subject's thoughts, plans, and
deliberations are also systematically dependent on the informational properties of the
input'. 13
One might read Evans as suggesting here what I shall label 'a two-stage
account of experience'. First, we identify a state which has a certain content in virtue
of its connections with the subject's behavioural dispositions, where the connections
in question are independent of any link with his concept-applying system (I shall
9 p.226. All references to Evans are to his 1982.
10 See p. 124.
"pp.226-7.
12 p.227.
13 For brevity's sake I shall often refer to the relevant system as the concept-applying system, or
generally speak about the subject's conceptual abilities.
7
refer to such connections as 'primitive connections'); and then, if this state is also
linked with the subject's concept-applying system, the content which the state has in
virtue of the primitive connections with his behavioural dispositions is also the
content of an experience (i.e., of a conscious perceptual state). Thus, on this picture,
one has to appeal to the subject's conceptual abilities only in order to explain what
makes a given content - which has already been accounted for at the first stage,
independently of whether the relevant state is also linked with the concept-applying
system - the content of an experience (rather than merely a content of an unconscious
perceptual informational state). 14
Alternatively, Evans may be read as suggesting a milder strong-non-conceptual
view which I shall label 'a background-presupposing account'. On this view, when
accounting for the particular content of a particular experience, one must presuppose,
as a general background assumption, that the state whose content we are accounting
for is linked with the subject's concept-applying system. But given this assumption,
specifying the relevant primitive connections between perceptual input and
behavioural dispositions (without any further appeal to the subject's conceptual
abilities) will suffice for explaining what it is for the content to be the particular
content it is rather than others. Thus, according to the background-presupposing
account, specifying the primitive connections will not account for something which is
a. potential content of a conscious state if the link with the concept-applying system is
not presupposed, while according to the two-stage account what is accounted for at
the first stage is a content which can be the content of a conscious state independently
of the assumption that a further link with concepts obtains. Correspondingly, on the
14 For such a reading of Evans see McDowell 1996 pp.49&51. McDowell's formulation suggests that
the contentful state accounted for in the first stage, if linked with the concept-applying system, is also
an experiential state. The following objection applies to the two-stage view regardless of whether one
accepts this or has a different view of the relation between the initial state and the experiential state.
8
two-stage account, the content accounted for at the first stage might equally be the
content of a non-conscious state, while on the background-presupposing account the
account applies exclusively to experiential contents. (It may seem that strictly
speaking the background-presupposing account should be regarded as weakly-nonconceptual; for, ultimately, the link with the subject's conceptual abilities is part of
the account. The strong-non-conceptual element here is the suggestion that there can
be a specific part of the account that explains what it is for a particular content to be
the content it is in terms which do not presuppose the subject's conceptual abilities.
Note also that the view is consistent with allowing that the specification of exactly the
same type of primitive connections, with a different background assumption, can
account for other contentful states (specifically, states of non-concept-possessors).
This is why such a reading can still accord with what seems to be Evans's motivation
for a strong-non-conceptual view; namely, the thought that all perceptual contents,
whether or not the perceiver is a concept-possessor, are explained in the same way). 15
At least as far as concept-possessors are concerned, I accept Evans's view that
only perceptual states which are linked with the concept-applying system are
conscious. For I take it that saying that a perceptual state is conscious amounts to
saying that the perceiver's state is such that, from his point of view, environmental
aspects are presented as being a certain way; and that in the case of conceptpossessors this means that the perceiver is in a position to take the content into
consideration when evaluating thoughts, reasoning and planning without a need for
any kind of further mediating step. (As for non-concept-possessors, I stay neutral
about whether they can have conscious states). However, in contrast to Evans, I shall
argue that it is impossible to account for a content which is linked with concepts in
15 1 do not remember reading a text in which this second version is explicitly ascribed to Evans, though
various people agree in discussion that this seems a plausible reading of him.
this way (that is, to account for what makes it the particular content it is) without
presupposing the link. This claim, if correct, shows that a two-stage account is
unfeasible regardless of how one proposes to account for the content at the first stage.
I shall then clarify that the background-presupposing account is unworkable as well.
Ill
I start, then, with the two-stage account ascribed to Evans. How should we
construe, on this reading, the claim that the content of primitive perceptual states is
due to their primitive connections with the subject's behavioural dispositions?
Evans's discussion of such states16 suggests that he is thinking about the states of
primitive mechanisms (i.e., mechanisms that operate independently of links with the
concept-applying system) which process perceptual information, making it available
for the control and guidance of behaviour; where the states in question play a specific
representational role in the processing of the information or directly in the control and
guidance of motor processes. 17 To say that a state of a certain mechanism has such a
representational role is to say, roughly, that its occurrence affects the organism's
reactions to the environment in a way which is an appropriate way to react (given the
organism's current needs and goals) when the situation in the environment is of a
certain type. Or more accurately, the state is said to be of a type which has a certain
systematic effect on states of perceptual- and motor-mechanisms: an effect which, if
the relevant mechanisms are functioning properly, makes the ensuing behaviour
appropriate to a situation in which the conditions in the environment are of a certain
type (given the organism's current needs and goals).
16 pp. 154-8.
17 1 shall assume that perceptual informational states are partly individuated by the type of perceptual
input which normally causes them and partly by certain information-processing operations. Thus the
subject's being endowed with certain input may count as such a state.
10
Such states have only brute causal effects (by which I mean effects that do not
depend on awareness of the implications which the veridicality of the states' content
may have for the appropriateness of the effect). Thus, it seems unquestionable that
the place such a state occupies in the network of connections between input, output
and other states of this type exhausts the idea that the state has a particular content; it
thus also seems that the state's place in such a network of connections fully accounts
for its having the particular content it does. 18 Roughly, such a state will be said to
have a certain content X if the effect it has in standard conditions is such that its
contribution to shaping the organism's behaviour results in an adjustment of the
behaviour to the situation in which X is the case. 19 Of course, there are properties of
the state which enable it to have this role: normally a state will not play such a role if
it is not - to some sufficient extent - correlated with the aspect of the environment
which it represents, or was so correlated when the connections with the efferent
systems were determined. But such a correlation, by itself, does not make it the case
that the state has a representational role. Furthermore, it does not determine which
representational role the state has when it has one. (When the ascription of content to
a state is construed in the above way, I shall refer to the state as a primitive state and
use 'primitive content' to refer to its content).
Now, the suggestion is that when a primitive state of this type is linked with the
concept-applying system, the subject has an experience whose content is constituted
by the same primitive connections which constitute the content of the primitive state.
But how could this be? The content of an experience is what is presented to the
subject in his experience, while the idea that primitive connections between
18 Note that this does not commit one to a strong holistic view on which any change in the network
entails a change in the content of each of the states. In fact, what I am thinking of here is types of
places in a network which are characterized by the types of effects the state may have, given relevant
general types of needs, goals, capacities and other representational states currently occurring.
19 1 leave open the question of how the content of such states is to be specified.
11
perceptual input and behavioural dispositions constitute the content of a perceptual
state has its place only in the context of the theoretician's description of the relevant
information-processing and behaviour-producing systems.20 However, the objection
requires some spelling out. The proponent of the two-stage account fully agrees that
the mere fact that visual input is connected with the subject's behavioural dispositions
does not make it the case that things are presented to the subject a certain way. His
claim is that it is only when the relevant primitive state is also linked with the
concept-applying system that the primitive connections constitute the content of an
experience. Thus we have to clarify that the fact that a primitive state is linked with
the concept-applying system cannot make it the case that what constitutes the content
of the primitive state also constitutes the content of the experience. I shall do this by
considering the following questions.
In cases like blindsight, there is a link between primitive perceptual states and
the concept-applying system without a corresponding experience.21 The fact that such
cases are possible will suffice for showing the incorrectness of the two-stage account,
unless its proponent formulates his view in a way which makes clear that when
describing the second stage he is referring to a narrower type of link with the
concept-applying system - a link which does not obtain when there is no
corresponding experience. We may then ask whether it is possible to provide a
characterization of the required link which holds only in cases in which a (conceptpossessing) subject has a relevant experience. If it is possible, we should go on to ask
whether the link in question can be of use to a proponent of the two-stage account.
20 See, for example, McDowell 1996 pp.51-55, and also his 1994.
21 By saying that a certain experience corresponds to a certain primitive state I mean that the relevant
experience makes available to the subject the same (or closely related) information which the primitive
state can be said to make available at the level of operation of perceptual- and motor-mechanisms.
12
By criticising possible attempts to argue that the link that obtains in blindsight
is generally of the same type as the link which obtains when there is a corresponding
experience, I shall reach a characterization of the link between primitive states and
the subject's concept-involving activities which obtains in all and only in cases in
which there is a corresponding experience. (As far as I can see, attempts to argue that
the link is of the same type would be based on claiming that there is no essential
functional difference between the cases. Thus the characterization offered in response
will be a functional characterization). We shall see that the suggested characterization
presupposes that the subject is in a conscious perceptual state; thus it will be of no use
to the proponent of the two-stage account. Furthermore, we shall see that aspects of
such a link which are not part of what we presuppose when presupposing that the
subject has a certain conscious experience (as opposed to merely a primitive
perceptual state) - particularly, the facts regarding the primitive state and what
constitutes its primitive content - cannot play a role in an account of the content of the
experience.
The following discussion does not involve particular assumptions as to the way
one should account for the content of primitive perceptual states (it may be accounted
for in terms of the primitive links as suggested above, but one might as well suggest
an alternative account), thus the conclusion will not be restricted to any specific
version of the two-stage account. That is, we will be able to conclude that any
account of content which is not exclusively an account of the content of a conscious
state (of a concept-possessor) cannot be turned into an account of such content simply
by adding that the state in question is linked with the concept-applying system. 22
222
Since we are allowing for any proposed account (independent of links with the concept-applying
of the content of subject's perceptual non-conscious states, 'primitive states' refers now to any
system)
S
such state (even if one suggested that the account should not be given in terms of the state's place in a
network of relevant connections as suggested above). I should clarify that I do not think that there are
plausible alternatives (I have mentioned above why it seems to be the only plausible type of account).
13
IV
Blindsight patients are able to choose, in a frequency of above chance, the
correct statements as to how things are in their blind field (out of a restricted number
of options), when required to do so, while they insist that they have no experience in
"") 1
their blind field. Assuming (i) that what we mean by 'experience' implies that
unawareness that one is having an experience, when specifically occupied with
whether one has a relevant experience, is sufficient for concluding that one does not
have an experience, and (ii) that the subjects' reports are sincere, this seems to be a
case in which the processing of visual input has an effect on the activation of the
relevant concepts without a corresponding experience. A natural reaction here is to
point out that the link with concepts which obtains when the information is available
to the subject in experience is of a different type. First, when the information is
available to a subject in experience it affects the way the subject evaluates thoughts,
reasons, makes plans, etc., while the effect on the subject's use of concepts which is
observed in blindsight does not amount to any of these: the statements made by the
blindsighted subject are regarded by him as mere guesses, something that does not
normally play a role in evaluating thoughts, reasoning and planning. Secondly, in the
blindsight case the primitive state is not immediately linked with the activities it may
affect (such as making statements); rather if the state is to have an effect on, say,
which statements the subject makes, the subject has to be asked to choose between
certain statements at a certain time. (These seem the important functional differences.
For the sake of the argument I ignore other differences such as the fact that
blindsighted patients are limited in the range of properties they can identify or that
But the following discussion enables showing the generality of the claim without going into a detailed
discussion of issues concerning the account of perceptual non-conscious states.
23 For a description of blindsight see Weiskrantz 1990.1 focus on blindsight for convenience's sake;
there are other cases in which processing of perceptual information affects the subject's use of
concepts in the absence of a corresponding experience (and some of these cases might be more suitable
for the current discussion, specifically those which concern normal subjects).
14
they are unable to compare objects which are simultaneously present in their blind
field).
It might seem that these differences are inessential. For it seems that, at least in
principle, a subject in a condition similar to that of a blindsight patient could learn to
prompt himself to make statements about how things are in his blind field, and, in
virtue of past success, he may be willing to accept the statements he is inclined to
make as true, or ascribe a certain likelihood to their being true (unless he suspects that
the conditions are non-standard). 24 But even in this case there is still an important
difference between blindsighted and normal subjects. It seems wrong to describe the
situation of a blindsighted subject as one in which any bit of processed visual
information can, generally, directly affect the way he evaluates thoughts, reasons and
plans. For a certain bit of information to be poised for a general effect on the way the
blindsighted subject performs such activities he has to prompt himself regarding the
relevant aspect and to register which statement he is inclined to make (thus
registering the information at the conceptual-level25). In contrast, the information
available in experience can generally affect such activities without the mediation of
further registration. For example, consider a case in which the processing of light
from an object results in the activation of the concept of red. Suppose however, that
24 Compare this to Block's super-blindsight: a person for whom visual input from the blind field can
affect action and thought whenever he prompts himself without any experience being involved (Block
1997 pp. 385-6). Block uses this imaginary case to argue that the characterization of the link between
input and thought is not sufficient for guaranteeing what he calls phenomenal consciousness - that is,
roughly, the state's having some particular feel for the subject. I should emphasize that the issue here
is not phenomenal consciousness as opposed to mere availability (or accessibility) of information to
the subject, but rather the availability of the information in experience as opposed to other ways in
which it may be made available.
25 The considerations are presented from the point of view of one who does not take the strongconceptual view to be a viable option. A strong-conceptualist who takes experiential contents to be a
matter of the actualization of conceptual abilities cannot take the fact that the information is registered
at the conceptual-level to be a distinguishing characteristic of the blindsight case. He may instead point
out that in the blindsight case the information has to be registered by exercising conceptual abilities
possessed by the subject independently of facts regarding the specific visual information (from the
blind field) currently processed by his visual-system. In any case, the emphasis is not on the type of
registration in question, but rather on the fact that there is a need for some further registration. In what
follows I shall refer to the additional step required in blindsight as conceptual registration simply
because this is a convenient way to clarify that this is a further step.
15
the redness of the object is due to a red beam of light being directed towards the
object. A normal subject also immediately sees, say, that a certain area surrounding
the object appears red; thus he would normally refrain from judging that the object is
red, as it would seem to him that the red colour is due to a beam of red light directed
at that area.26 In contrast, if the blindsighted prompts himself regarding the colour of
the relevant object, the information from the object's surroundings would affect his
judgement about the object's colour only if it as well is registered at the conceptuallevel; thus, only if he also prompts himself regarding the colour of various things or
areas in the general direction of the object.27 It is in this sense that the primitive
perceptual states of the (imaginary) blindseer might embody the same information as
is available to a normal subject in experience without this information directly
f\ O
bearing on the way he evaluates thoughts, reasons and makes plans.
The opponent may suggest that we consider a blindseer for whom it is the case
that whenever he prompts himself, the process leading to the result makes it possible
for any currently processed visual information to have a direct effect on the result.
Thus in the above situation we can assume that, when prompting himself regarding
the object's colour, such a subject just finds himself with an inclination to say that the
object is not red (or make some other relevant statement). If this was the general case,
then there would have been a sense in which the relevant bits of information were,
26 The point I wish to illustrate is independent of whether the situation should be described as one in
which the subject simply sees that red light is projected to that area or as one in which he has to make
an inference from the red appearance of the relevant area. In both cases the information can affect the
subject's reasoning independently of what he judges on the basis of the information. Even if an
inference is not required, the fact that the situation appears to be non-standard can cause the subject to
reflect upon it, and it may happen that, once his attention is drawn to the question of the source of the
light, he will judge (in this example, mistakenly) that the seen object is in fact red.
27 It is not clear which observations, among those possible for the blindsighted, may lead him to
suspect that the object is not red (and why). For the sake of the argument I ignore this difficulty.
28 One might argue that while it seems correct that a normal subject need not register the information at
the conceptual level in order for it to affect the way he evaluates thoughts, the effect on reasoning and
planning requires a prior experience-based judgement. For present purposes it is sufficient that the
information can have a direct effect on the question of which lines of reasoning and planning the
subject takes on.
16
generally, directly linked with the subject's thinking: for any relevant act of thought
evaluation which the subject in fact performs, that act may be affected by the
information. But this falls short of the kind of general link between the information
and the subject's thinking which obtains when the information is available to the
subject in experience. In the blindsight case, mechanisms whose operation is not
directly accessible to the subject are what determine which information will affect the
reaction to a given prompt and in what way. In contrast, the information available to
the subject in experience affects his activities due to the implication which the subject
takes the information to have. Thus, he determines which bits of information affect
his activities, and has a grasp of why he takes each of the selected bits to be relevant
to the activity (which allows him to reflect on the appropriateness of the activity
given the information he selected). In addition, any available bit of information can
direct the subject to initiate certain activities and can direct him in deciding on the
order in which he performs them; where the blindsighted is dependent on the
occurrence of a prompt. This kind of general effect on the subject's thinking can take
place in the blindseer only when the information is registered at the conceptual-level.
I shall use 'subject-level effects' to refer to effects of this type, which, presently are
to be contrasted with what I called brute effects.29
Thus, for example, suppose that after prompting himself about, say, the shape
of a certain object and guessing that it is round, the object moves and the input from it
is sufficient for a normal subject to see that, actually, the object is elliptical. Seeing
this, the subject, unless he is completely occupied with something else or loses
29 People often use 'rational effect' to refer to such effects (in later chapters I shall sometimes do so as
well). Using 'subject-level' clarifies that no evaluation of the resulting activity is implied, and that
what is in question is only those cases in which the effect is due to what the subject takes to be
appropriate in the relevant circumstances. I use 'subject-level' rather than 'personal-level' in order to
emphasize that what distinguishes the relevant effects is the fact that they depend on the subject's
grasp. (Also talk about personal-level effects might be construed as relating, say, to effects which are
due to mechanisms one can ascribe only to the person as a whole, without a requirement that the
relevant effects be due to what the subject takes to be appropriate in the relevant circumstances).
17
interest in the shape of the object, would normally immediately change his view
about the object's shape. The blindseer, in contrast, will have a reason to change his
view only if he prompts himself again regarding the shape of the object, and the mere
fact that the relevant information has been processed will not cause a (automatic or
intentional) prompt of this type to occur.30
Note that it would not matter if the prompting becomes an automatic routine.
The point is not that the prompting adds an aspect which, phenomenologically, seems
to be absent when normal subjects experience things. Rather what I have been
appealing to is the fact that the need for a prompt (whether or not the subject initiates
it or is at all aware of its occurrence) and for the following registration at the
conceptual-level has the consequence that, at any given time, the blindseer can take
into account in his concept-involving activities only information which is, by then,
registered at the conceptual-level. Consequently, the information which can have a
subject-level effect on his activities is restricted to information which is registered
serially according to an order that is not guided by the information from the
environment which has not yet been registered. (It is true that aspects of the scene
sometimes automatically attract the visual system and we may assume that such
occurrences would enable the blindseer to register information without selfprompting. But apart from the fact that this allows only a limited set of unregistered
input to affect the order in which the information is registered, it will not be a case in
which the information guides the subject in his determination of the order; it only has
a brute effect on the order31 ).
30 One might suggest adding to the story that the processing of information regarding a change
normally induces relevant prompting, and consequently will get registered. But if this was the case, it
would be impossible for the blindseer to register information even in moderately dynamic situations,
and would also make it impossible for him to focus on gathering specific information he is interested
in while staying relatively sensitive to changes which may take place in his blind field.
31 Allowing that information can be registered in this way as well requires a refinement of the last
sentence in the previous paragraph.
18
This last point - that the information which can have a direct subject-level effect
on the way the blindseer performs concept-involving activities is processed serially in
an order which is not guided by unregistered information - may seem to be significant
only due to empirical facts regarding the limitations of our capacities. For we may
imagine a blindseer with mechanisms which would enable him to (serially) prompt
himself and register information very rapidly, and which would have the power to
continuously register and update the amount and the variety of information normally
available to a subject in experience. It may seem, then, that the effect of the
information embodied by the blindseer's primitive states on his concept-involving
activities does not differ from the effect of the information available to a normal
subject in experience.
Suppose for the moment that the effect is in fact similar. The comparison
between perceivers with limited capacities is still useful to our attempt to characterize
what distinguishes the effect of experiential content on the subject's activities from
the effect of the content of a primitive state. It manifests the difference made, in our
case, by the lack of the possibility of direct, general, subject-level effects on the
subject's concept-involving activities. Furthermore, it is clear that the possibility of
describing a blindseer who appears to be functionally the same as normal subjects
depends on the possibility of describing a blindseer for whom the information
registered at the conceptual-level at any particular period of time (long enough to be
relevant to his considerations as to what to do and how things are) is virtually the
same as the information a normal subject is provided with in experience. Thus, in
effect, we are still assuming that, in the Hindsight case, visual information can have a
direct (here in the sense that it does not require further registration, see footnote 25),
general, subject-level effect on the subject's activities only in virtue of its being
registered at the conceptual-level. In other words, we agree that only contents of
19
conscious states can have this type of effect on the subject's activities, and attempt to
make sure that for each relevant primitive state there will be a corresponding
conscious state with a corresponding content (the state he is in due to the registration
of the information). It is clear, then, that we are regarding the link between the
primitive state and the subject's concept-involving activities as composed of the link
between the primitive state and the registration of the information and a link between
such a registration and the subject's activities; there is no change in status of the
contents of the primitive states (as the contents of such states); that is, they are not,
any more than before, the contents of conscious states.
Note, however, that the blindseer imagined here is not functionally the same as
normal subjects. His ability to register information from things in his blind field
depends on and is restricted by a given repertoire of concepts (that determines which
statements he can be prompted to make and which information would consequently
be registered), where the relevant concepts are such that their contents are fixed
independently of which information (from the blind field) is processed by the visualsystem at the time , 32 This reminds us that an important aspect of the link between
experiential content and our conceptual abilities is that experience enables
demonstrative thoughts and is thus generally basic to our ability to think about a
mind-independent world.
The suggestion, then, is that the information available in experience, in contrast
to information which is processed but not available in experience, can, generally,
have a direct (that is, not mediated by conceptual registration), subject-level effect on
the way the subject evaluates thoughts, reasons and plans. (Where such an effect is
not restricted by the range of conceptual abilities the subject can apply independently
32 Note that not all concepts in the relevant repertoire have to be expressible in words, and it might be
possible for the blindseer to apply quite fine-grained concepts (perhaps with the aid of mental images).
20
of the currently processed information. For the moment I am leaving this point aside).
How does this show the unfeasibility of a two-stage account? The above
characterization is simply a result of spelling out the effect which a content of a
conscious perceptual state can have on the subject's concept-involving activities in
virtue of its being a conscious state. Trivially, a perceptual state which is not linked
with concepts in this way is not a conscious state. Given a state of the latter type,
adding that it is linked with concepts in the above way is just to say that this state is
somehow related to a conscious perceptual state (probably being part of the
processing underlying the relevant experience). Regardless of what we have to say
about this relation, it is clear that the content of the experience cannot be constituted
by whatever it is that constitutes the content of the non-conscious state. For whatever
constitutes the content of the non-conscious state does not, by itself, put the subject in
a position to take into account, in his concept-involving activities, the information
that state might be said to embody.
We can look at it this way. Generally an account of the content of a state of the
subject should account for the state's potential to play the representational role it
does. Thus when we account for the fact that a perceptual state makes specific visual
information available to the subject, so that he is in a position to take the relevant
information into account in his considerations as to how things are and what to do, we
have to make sure that the state is of a type which can make information available to
the subject. But this is just to say that we have to presuppose that the state is a
conscious state (and thus linked with concepts in the relevant way). In contrast, an
account of the content of a state which plays (or can play) some other representational
role would relate to aspects of the systems in relation to which it can play the relevant
type of role. It is, then, the difference between the latter systems and the system that
constitutes a subject's ability to think about the world - a system which essentially
21
involves links between the subject's experiential and conceptual abilities - which
makes accounts of contentful states which are not conscious states of a conceptpossessor unsuitable to be an account of a content of an experience.
Note that if creatures without concepts could be ascribed experiential contents,
this would apply to such contents as well. For the account of such contents would be
an account of what it is for a non-concept-possessor to experience things as being a
certain way; and this would require appeal to the capacities of such a creature in
virtue of which it can be said to have a point of view in relation to which its
perceptual states can be ascribed the relevant representational role. Even if a conceptpossessor possessed the same set of capacities, a primitive link between visual input
and these capacities would not amount to an account of a content of a conscious state
of his, for these capacities do not constitute a concept-possessor's point of view as to
how things are in his environment.
The opponent may complain that I have ignored the possibility that the link I
have described in terms of subject-level effects on the subject's activities is also
describable in terms which do not presuppose the notion of a conscious state. For if
this is possible, the alternative description does not immediately entail that the
content must be the content of conscious state. But this misses the point made above.
Suppose there is such a description. It has been made clear that the obtaining of such
a link (regardless of how it is described) does not affect the fact that the type of
representational role played by a primitive state cannot by itself explain the fact that
things are presented a certain way to the subject. The opponent might then suggest
that we consider the role the state can be said to play in virtue of both the primitive
connections and the further links with the conceptual system (described in the
alternative way). But, without explicitly appealing to the possibility of subject-level
effects of the information on the subject's activities, we will not capture the
22
representational role the experience plays in virtue of its content in the subject's
considerations.
V
I have argued that one cannot account for the particular content of a particular
experience without presupposing that it is the content of a conscious state, and thus
presupposing that the relevant content is a content of a state which is linked with the
concept-applying system in the way described above. This may seem to leave room
for what I have called a background-presupposing account: an account of the content
of a particular experience without a specific appeal to the subject's conceptual
abilities, which is made possible in virtue of a general background assumption that
the state in question is linked with such abilities in the relevant way. A closer
consideration, however, will show that there is no room for such an account.
The problem is that we must be able to account for the significance which the
content of the experience has for the subject. For example, we need to clarify how it
is that, from the subject's point of view, an object is presented to him as, say, being
on his left rather than his right, and also, more generally, how it is that the state in
question is such that the object is presented as having a certain location in a 3D space
rather than a 2D one, or rather than the experience having no spatial significance for
the subject at all. Now, the specification of certain primitive connections between the
current visual input and the subject's behavioural dispositions would not account for
such facts if we merely assume in addition that the state in question is a conscious
state (and thus linked with the concept-applying system in the relevant way). As cases
like blindsight make clear, the primitive connections can obtain without having any
effect on what the subject is aware of; thus they cannot have a direct bearing on what
the subject takes to be the significance of his current experience. Further, it is
23
doubtful whether the current primitive connections bear on the significance the
experience has for the subject in some indirect way; and even if they did, it is rather
implausible that they should fully explain the aspect which distinguishes, from the
subject's point of view, the given experience from other experiences. It is, of course,
reasonable to assume that primitive connections between visual input and behavioural
dispositions play a role in the development of the subject's experiential and
conceptual capacities. But we are not asking how it came about that certain visual
input can give rise to a certain type of experience rather than other; the question is
what it is about the subject's current state in the current situation that makes it a case
of his experiencing things as being one way rather than others.33 The only other
alternative I can think of is that the primitive connections might be part of what
constitutes abilities which are, in turn, part of what constitutes the subject's grasp of
the relations between the current experience and other experiences and actions. But
even without going into detail, it seems clear that the specific primitive connections
would not suffice for explaining what makes it the case that the subject grasps the
particular experience as having the place it does in the network of subject-level
connections.
It does not seem that other suggestions as to which concept-independent factors
may account for particular contents could fare better. In general, since the relevant
factors are supposed to be independent of the subject's conceptual abilities, the mere
fact that they obtain does not explain the fact that things are experienced by the
subject one way rather than another. Presupposing that we are considering a
33 To remove doubts as to whether the effect on the development may somehow imply that the current
primitive connections have some such effect, it is helpful to remember the following facts. The effect
of the primitive connections on the development is due to their actual manifestations in the subject's
interaction with his environment. However, the primitive connections between visual input and
manifestable behavioural disposition may change without an immediate change in the way things are
experienced by the subject. (Paralysis is one type of example; behavioural adaptation to distorting
prisms, in contrast to perceptual adaptation, is another).
24
conscious state is thus unhelpful unless what is presupposed includes specific details
as to how these factors affect the content of the experience. But filling in the details
as to how they affect the content would be helpful only if we explicitly relate the
relevant factor with specific aspects of experiential contents, thus taking for granted
what we are supposed to explain.
VI
I have argued that both types of strong-non-conceptual accounts (the two-stage
and the background-presupposing accounts) are unfeasible. Now, since we must
presuppose that the content is the content of a conscious state, and since the account
must make clear in virtue of what the content is grasped by the subject as having a
specific significance (thus clarifying what makes it the case that the subject takes it to
be linked with other conscious states of his in a certain way rather than others), it may
seem that we should take the content to be of the same type as the contents of
judgements (contents which are a result of the activation of relevant conceptual
abilities). In the next chapter I shall argue that this suggestion is unfeasible as well.
25
2 Reasons for rejecting the strong-conceptual view
I
At first glance a strong-conceptual view - according to which it is possible to
account for a particular experiential content in terms of the subject's conceptual
abilities alone - may seem implausible. For, as Evans points out,34 the content of an
experience is more fine-grained than the concepts the subject possesses; thus the fact
that an experience has a particular content (rather than others) cannot be explained in
terms of such concepts alone. McDowell and Brewer respond that one who argues this
way is ignoring the fact that for any aspect of the environment which one can
distinguish in experience, one has the ability to think about that aspect
demonstratively. They suggest that, though the content of a subject's experience is not
determined by the concepts he possesses independently of his having the relevant
experience, it is determined by demonstrative abilities which he possesses at that
time. 35 Furthermore, McDowell and Brewer not only claim that the content of an
experience is determined by the relevant demonstrative abilities, but also that an
experience involves the actualization of these abilities: experiences, they claim, have
the type of content which can be the content of a judgement, content which is a result
of the actualization of two demonstrative abilities - the ability to think about a
particular object demonstratively and the ability to predicate a particular property
(identified demonstratively) on objects. 36
It seems clear, then, that the question of whether a strong-conceptual view can
be maintained is the question of whether an account of the particular content of a
particular experience can be given in terms of the specific demonstrative abilities
34 p.229.
35 McDowell 1996 pp.56-8 and 1998; Brewer 1999 pp. 170-4.
36 See, for example, McDowell 1996 pp.26&46-7, Brewer 1999 p. 149. (Brewer takes the above claim to
hold only for the experience of aspects which the subject is currently attending to; 1 discuss this
qualification later).
26
which the subject has at the time of the particular experience in question. 37 The
following discussion will be focused on rejecting the stronger suggestion (that the
actualization of such abilities is what constitutes the content of the experience), since
this is the view which is in fact advocated by strong-conceptualists. However, when
the argument against the stronger suggestion leaves room for a weaker version, I shall
give reasons for rejecting the latter as well.
As mentioned in the introduction, a general problem with appealing to a
particular demonstrative ability (the particular ability to think about a specific
environmental aspect which the subject has when experiencing this aspect) in the
account of a particular experience is that it is in virtue of his experience of an object or
property that a subject can single out the relevant object or property and entertain
demonstrative thoughts about them.38 But one leaves no room for experience to play
this explanatory role if one construes, as McDowell and Brewer do, experiencing a
particular environmental aspect as a matter of the actualization of the relevant
demonstrative ability,39 or, generally, if one holds a view which implies that
accounting for the subject's experiencing a particular environmental aspect requires
appealing to his possession of the particular ability to think about it demonstratively.40
Given the intuitive force of the thought that experience plays such a role in the
37 Further, more important, reasons why demonstrative concepts are the only relevant candidates are
related to the particularity of experiential contents and to wider considerations as to how to account for
the content of our non-demonstrative empirical concepts.
38 Since McDowell and Brewer hold that the experience of a property is explained in terms of a
predicative element, it is inaccurate to say that the relevant ability is the ability to refer to the property
or entertain thoughts about it. When the discussion is focused on the predicative element, I try to avoid
such formulations, but when speaking about demonstrative abilities in general, I use the inaccurate
formulation for simplicity's sake.
39 As mentioned in footnote 36, Brewer holds that the actualization of a demonstrative ability is
involved only when the subject attends to the experienced aspect. However, what enables singling out
the experienced aspect is the subject's attention to it, thus this formulation of the objection applies only
to the parts of the content which, on Brewer's view, involve the actualization of demonstrative abilities.
40 For this type of claim see Campbell 2002 pp.97&121-4 and Eilan 2001. Peacocke presents a different
version of the objection, focusing on the role played by the way in which an object or property are
experienced in the individuation of demonstrative abilities (see, for example, 1992 pp.84-5 and 2001
pp.246-50).
27
explanation of demonstrative abilities, it seems that as long as the strong-conceptualist
does not provide an argument for his view, we should, generally, prefer views which
are not strongly-conceptual to those which are. In Chapter 3 I shall argue that
McDowell and Brewer do not provide a conclusive argument for their view, and
consequently we have at least a prima facie reason to reject it. In this chapter I shall
discuss a different objection to the view.
The claim in this chapter will be that the strong-conceptual view is not generally
correct; that at least some aspects of our experience cannot be accounted for in terms
of the demonstrative abilities they give rise to. According to McDowell and Brewer,
experiencing, say, a round object as such involves the actualization of a demonstrative
referring to the object and a demonstrative predicative element which we may
expressed by 'x is thus'. I shall focus on what they take to be the predicative elements
of the content; the elements involved in the experience of properties of objects (where
properties are to be understood as including the relations in which the object stands to
other things). I shall suggest a reconstruction of Brewer's account of the predicative
element which I take to be most favourable to the strong-conceptualist. On the
resulting view (as Brewer himself admits) an experience of a given property involves
the actualization of a demonstrative ability only when the subject is attending to that
property. I shall then argue that the strong-conceptualist cannot maintain the generality
of his view by claiming that the experience of a property which is not currently
attended to must be explained in terms of the specific (non-actualized) demonstrative
ability. First, however, I shall briefly explain my reasons for rejecting McDowell's
construal of the predicative element of the content.
28
II
On McDowell's view, given a certain instance of a certain property (say, a
certain shape or a certain shade of colour), for something to be thus (in relation to the
particular instance) is for it to be, in standard conditions, indiscriminable in the
relevant respect (i.e. in shape, shade, etc.) from the instance in question. The ability to
think about something as thus (in relation to the given instance) is, then, partly
constituted by the subject's capacity to recognize instances which are thus; a capacity
which he has in virtue of his present (or past) experience of the specific instance. 41
This means that on McDowell's view we can have such abilities only when the
experience of the property instance is veridical; for if the experience is non-veridical,
the subject will not have the required recognitional capacity (that is, it will, then, not
be the case that, generally, what he takes to be instances of the same property will be
so). (Note that McDowell must require a capacity to recognize instances which are, in
fact, the same as the given instance in the relevant respect, rather than simply a
capacity to recognize appearances as the same. If the latter rather than the former was
required, then suggesting that our experience involves the actualization of the resulting
demonstrative abilities would amount to suggesting that experience provides us with
the effect of an encounter with the property, not with the property itself).
Consequently, McDowell should either deny that there is an element of the content of
the experience which corresponds to an illusory experience of a certain property, or
hold that there is such an element but that it differs in type from elements of the
content which correspond to a veridical experience of a property (presumably it would
41 See 1996 pp. 170-2. Three comments: (a) In his 1996, McDowell uses expressions such as 'this shade'
to speak about the abilities in question; in his 1998 he acknowledges that he should have used
expressions of the form 'q>-ed thus' instead, (b) The reference to standard condition is my addition; as
far as I understand, McDowell takes this for granted, (c) I use 'is thus' rather than 'is cp-ed thus' since it
makes it clearer that the relevant conceptual ability is not analyzable as two separable conceptual
abilities (an ability to single out a relevant dimension and an ability to single out a currently instantiated
property, of any dimension). (I assume that this is McDowell's view).
29
be an element which could be explained without reference to the actual experienced
property, that is, the actual property of the experienced instance). As I shall explain
later, I take this to be implausible. (Note that the claim concerns only illusions, not
hallucinations; that is, it concerns cases in which there is a perceptual link between the
subject and a certain instance of a property but at least some of the experiential
information he has from it is misleading).
Another difficulty with the above view is that since perceptual indiscriminability
is non-transitive, all the instances which are said to be thus (in relation to a given
sample) do not share the same shade (or shape, etc.) property.42 What they have in
common is only that they are indiscriminable in shade (shape, etc.), in standard
conditions, from the given sample. But, then, if the ability to think about a thing as
thus is an ability to predicate a property which is essentially defined in terms of
discriminability from a particular sample, it is unclear how the claim that abilities of
this type are actualized in our experience can contribute to explaining how experience
makes the way things are in a mind-independent world immediately available to the
subject.
Finally, McDowell requires that the recognitional capacity the subject has in
virtue of her encounter with a certain instance of a property should be one which 'can
in principle persist beyond the duration of the experience itself (1996 p. 57). However,
it simply seems a fact about our ability to make discriminations in experience and our
ability to recognize seen properties as the same as previously seen properties that the
42 McDowell simply stipulates that being thus (in relation to a given sample) is what it is to share a
shade (1996 p. 171). Such use is remote from what we normally mean by a shade property (and even
more clearly in the case of shape, orientation, etc.). In what follows I shall take two things to share a
fine-grained property iff anything which is indiscriminable from one of them, in relevant conditions, is
indiscriminable from the other in the same conditions and vice versa. However, when saying here that
they do not share a shade property I am willing to count as shade properties any property the
individuation of which is not essentially tied to one particular token sample.
30
former is much finer than the latter.43 McDowell claims that if we allow that the
recognitional capacity be restricted to the time of the encounter, then we will not be
able to ascribe to the subject a grasp of the distinction between, say, something's being
shaped thus and its appearing to the subject that something is shaped thus. But, as far
as objects other than the one serving as the sample are concerned, it seems that
subjects do grasp the difference; for they grasp the possibility that something which is
discriminable from the sample in standard conditions appears indiscriminable from it
in non-standard conditions. Thus the problem, it seems, is not that the type of ability
expressed by '* is thus' on this account cannot be regarded as a genuine conceptual
ability but rather that we cannot take judgements of the form 'this is thus', where 'this'
refers to the object which serves as the sample, to involve a genuine predication. The
discussion of Brewer's suggestion will clarify that the problem can be dealt with
without appealing to recognitional capacities which we do not seem to have. 44
Ill
I turn, then, to Brewer's view. There are some aspects of the view which I am
not clear about. What follows is a reconstruction which seems to me faithful to
Brewer's general line of thought, and which answers difficulties regarding the account
of illusions and the possibility of demonstrative predication of fine-grained properties.
The discussion of the reconstructed account will clarify the dependence of the relevant
demonstrative abilities on the subject's attention to the predicated property, thus
making a strong-conceptual account of the experience of unattended aspects
43
Peacocke (2001 p.251) and Kelly (2001) express a similar complaint.
I should mention that on p. 175, prior to the detailed presentation of his account of demonstrative
abilities, Brewer explicitly endorses McDowell's characterization of the ability to think about an object
as being thus as well as the requirement that it be possible for the relevant recognitional capacity to
endure in the absence of the sample. However, in the account he offers in the following chapter the
sample seems to play a different role than in McDowell's account and there is no obvious need for a
recognitional capacity which endures in the absence of the sample. Furthermore, in response to Kelly's
objection (manuscript), Brewer clarifies that he does not think that such a capacity is necessary.
44
31
impossible. For the sake of the argument, I shall assume that there is no difficulty with
holding that the experience of attended aspects involves the actualization of
demonstrative abilities. I shall later reject this assumption.
Brewer explains what he takes to be the predicative aspect of the content of
experience as requiring two interdependent abilities: (i) the ability, given a certain
experience of a property, to think about things as having the property which is the
ground of the current appearance (the appearance of the experienced object having a
certain fine-grained property), (ii) the ability to think about things as appearing the
way the relevant property currently appears (the way it appears from his current
perspective and in the current circumstances).45 (i) is the ability we are in fact
interested in - the ability whose actualization is part of what constitutes the content of
the experience - but we cannot consider it independently of (ii). Its dependence on (ii)
is due to the fact that it requires the subject's grasp of his experience as an experience
of the property which is the ground of the appearance, and such a grasp involves his
grasp of the dependence of the current appearance on, on the one hand, the actual
property to which he is currently attending, and on the other hand, his position in
relation to it and further relevant circumstances.
It is crucial to the view that, in addition, (ii) depends on (i). The ability to think
about an appearance is described by Brewer as involving the subject's bracketing from
his grasp of his experience as an experience of the actual property thoughts about how
his position in relation to the experienced instance and further relevant circumstances
contribute to his experience, where the prior grasp of the experience as an experience
of a certain property from a certain perspective and in certain circumstances is what
makes it the case that the subject grasps the current appearance as an appearance of a
mind-independent object and property. Furthermore, the appearance is not conceived
45 This is how I construe the description in 1999 pp. 198-200.
32
as something independent of the currently experienced object and property something which can be common to hallucinations and experiences, or to experiences
of different particular things. The picture, as I understand it, is that by attending to the
actual instance of the property, the subject singles it out, and his grasp of the relation
between the appearance and its ground is (from his point of view) a grasp of the
relation between the property which he is singling out and its appearing the way it
does (where the fact that it is this particular instance which is experienced is part of
what individuates the appearance as grasped by the subject).46
Now, the subject's grasp of the joint dependence of an appearance on the actual
attended instance of a property and further conditions must be such that the subject has
the ability to keep track of the property while its appearance may change (due to
changes of perspective and further circumstances), grasping it as one and the same
property whose appearance is changing. This ability to keep track of the attended
instance of the property (together with the subject's grasp of the possibility of
experiencing the same property again) is essential to the subject's ability to single out
a mind-independent property which he grasps as such.47 Consequently, this ability is
essential to the subject's knowledge of what it is for any object (including the object
whose current instantiation of the property serves as the relevant sample) to have the
attended mind-independent property. For this reason one's view as to what exactly
constitutes this ability to keep track of the property bears on how one individuates the
ability to predicate the property which the subject can be said to have, and which is
supposed to be actualized, when he experiences the property. I shall thus spend some
46 This is how I interpret Brewer's emphasis that the subject's relation to the experienced aspect is an
attentional relation (see for example 1999 p.202 and manuscript).
47 See pp.210-13. Brewer's interest there is to clarify that what the subject singles out is a mindindependent property rather than only a subjective appearance. But, as he clarifies later (manuscript),
the ability to keep track of the particular instance is what makes it the case that the subject takes the
particular instantiated property to be the particular mind-independent property in question.
33
time criticising what might appear to be Brewer's view on this matter and suggest an
alternative.
IV
When Brewer discusses the ability to keep track of the instance of the property,
he emphasizes the subject's immediate expectations as to how the appearance should
change with changes of perspective and circumstances - that is, the expectation the
subject has, when taking the experience at face value, as to how the experience will
change if he moves in certain ways, if the lighting conditions change in certain ways,
etc. (immediate expectations are to be contrasted with expectations the subject might
have when he has doubts regarding the veridicality of the experience and with
expectations which are at least partly based on further, non-experiential, relevant
information). This may suggest that, on Brewer's view, the ability to keep track of the
specific property is constituted by such immediate expectations. In the next few
paragraphs I shall point out that such a view imposes on the strong-conceptualist an
unappealing construal of illusions, and argue that there is an alternative construal of
the ability which is generally better motivated and which allows the strongconceptualist a more plausible view of illusions.
Suppose that, in the lack of depth cues, a motionless subject sees an elliptical
object, facing him, as a slanted round disc (that is, the elliptical object appears to him
to be a slanted round disc). Assuming that he takes the experience at face value, his
expectations, in this situation, as to how the appearance will change once he moves
differ from the immediate expectations he would have had, had the object appeared to
him to be an ellipse facing him. If one holds that such expectations are what constitute
the subject's ability to keep track of the relevant property (while taking the latter to be
part of what accounts for his grasp of which property is in question), then one cannot
34
ascribe to the subject, in the situation described above, a grasp of what it is for things
to be thus (referring to the actual shape of the object). For, once the conditions change
in a relevant way (e.g. the subject moves, the light becomes dimmer), his expectations
will be violated; since these expectation determine what he will or will not take to be
the same shape, he does not have the ability to keep track of the object's current shape
through changes.
To take this route amounts to saying that when the subject's experience is not
veridical it does not provide him with a grasp of which property he is experiencing,
and thus that no information (or misinformation) about the property is immediately
available to him in experience as such. But this seems wrong; various illusions are
simply cases of the appearance differing from the way things are due to the subject's
current perspective and the specific circumstances.48 Thus, just like the veridical case,
we have an instance of a property which is experienced by the subject a certain way, a
way which systematically depends on the property and relevant conditions.
Furthermore, subjects do (and arguably have to) take into account the possibility that
the current appearance is a misleading appearance of an instance of a relevant type of
property (or that it is not specific enough for determining what the subject can, in fact,
expect) (where this should not be taken to imply more than that they are willing to
accept, in some cases, that a certain appearance might be, is, was or might have been
misleading due to certain conditions - something that should be manifested in how
they take certain information to indicate the possibility or the actual occurrence of a
mistake, how they behave when a mistaken reaction can be crucial, etc.). It is,
48 1 shall interpret the relevant circumstances rather widely; include things like the current interests of
the subject, current memories that might influence the experience, the focus of his attention, etc. When
interpreted this way, I cannot currently think of an illusion which is not such a case. However the point
made in the text does not require that the claim have no exceptions.
35
therefore, unjustified to assume that the subject's immediate expectations exhaust
what he takes to be the possible changes in appearance when the conditions change.
Now, simply taking such possibilities into account does not yet guarantee that a
subject has the ability to keep track, through changes, of a property which currently
appears in a misleading way. But it seems that normally changes in appearance which
result from gathering more accurate information differ in their appearance from
changes in appearance which result from changes of the property. For example, in the
above case, when the subject starts moving towards the object while continuing to
attend to its shape (other things being equal), it will not appear to him that a sudden
change in orientation and shape of a slanted round object is taking place, but rather the
change in appearance will be of a type which occurs when the subject suddenly sees,
due to change in his position in relation to the object, that what has been mistakenly
experienced as a round disc is an ellipse facing him. Whenever this is normally the
case, the subject - who takes into account the possibility that certain appearances may
be misleading - has a (fallible) ability to keep track of the currently experienced
property (that is, the actual property which is the ground of the appearance) as such.49
It is in virtue of this ability that the subject can grasp which property is experienced
even if the experience is currently not veridical.
There are further considerations which support the construal of illusory
experience as providing the subject with a grasp of which property is experienced and
as doing so in the same way a veridical experience does. It is exactly by keeping track
of the instance of the property that the subject can gather more information about it,
The changes in the subject's perspective and circumstances which are relevant here are of the types
which normally occur in a natural environment; thus the fact that one can, for example, create illusions
of change in shape, size, orientation, etc., by a sudden elimination or insertion of aspects which affect
the appearance should not be regarded as a problem. Of course even in natural conditions the
appearance may be misleading as to which change takes place, the important point is that often it is not.
(Note also that the main point is that the change will not appear as a change of the property. In some
cases the fact that one is gathering information which corrects previous mistakes might not be noticed).
49
36
including information which enables him to correct previous mistakes. And it is in
virtue of the current appearance of the property (whether veridical or not) that he has
information as to whether further information is more accurate information from the
same property, or whether the property has changed. The importance of this can be
overlooked; it may seem that the subject's keeping track of the relevant object something he can do independently of whether the relevant property of the object is
continuously seen50 - suffices for explaining the way he gathers experiential
information and uses it. But this is incorrect. If a subject has experiential information
about, say, the object's shape at a time to and he keeps track of the object, but not of its
shape, between to and a later time ti, then gathering information about its shape at ti,
can only yield direct information about the shape it has at ti. In contrast, if the subject
has been continuously attending to the shape since to, the further information at ti is
also immediately related to the information gathered at to: he is thus provided with
experiential information as to whether or not the shape has changed, and if it did, also
as to how it changed. (The immediacy here should be contrasted with cases in which
reasoning or reliance on general assumptions regarding the relevant object, property
and the circumstances are required for the subject to evaluate whether or not the object
has changed its shape since t0 and if so in what way, or rather how likely it is that it
has changed in this or that way).
Note also that often the current non-veridical information can guide the subject's
attempts to gather more information about the property on which the current
appearance depends: it can suggest which specific movements may be more helpful in
exploring the property, to which aspects to attend, what kind of background
information may be relevant, etc. It seems that subjects are able, in such cases, to
50 Remember that an object can be seen while some of its properties are not; e.g., the light might be too
dim for seeing colour, or significant parts of the boundaries of a seen object may be occluded.
37
intentionally conduct their attempt to gather more information about the property
according to the relevant aspects of the experience. But how could one agree to this
while denying that an illusory experience can provide the subject with a grasp of
which property (in the environment) is experienced? It may seem that the subject's
intention can be construed as involving thought about the experienced property as 'the
shape (or colour, etc.) of this object', where this is understood as a mode of thought
that is independent of whether the subject is attending to the property and of whether
he actually has information about it, that is, a mode of thought that is partly
descriptive. But to say that a subject is thinking about a shape in this way - rather than
thinking about it in a way which essentially involves his visually attending to the
object's shape - is to say that it is not the case that he is specifically selecting shape
information from the object and immediately (that is without some additional
inference) taking this information to be from the property he is thinking about. This
simply seems to be the negation of the characterization of the way we actually think
about the property in such cases.
The suggestion, then, is that the current appearance of a property and the
immediate expectations it gives rise to do not play a role in the individuation of the
predicative demonstrative element which, according to the strong-conceptualist, is
actualized when we experience an object as having the relevant property. For the
factors relevant to the individuation of the ability are the attended instance of the
property and aspects of the subject's state which are essential for his having the ability
to keep track of the instance of the property as such. And it is suggested that this
ability to keep track of the instance is not simply constituted by what the subject
immediately expects due to how the property currently appears to him, but rather by a
more general conception of what is involved in keeping track of one and the same
property of the relevant type: a conception which presupposes the subject's (fallible)
38
ability to visually distinguish between cases in which the actual property changes and
those in which the appearance changes due to more accurate information. 51 On this
picture, changes in appearance, even if they have an immediate effect on the subject's
current view regarding the character of the attended property, need not affect the
identity of the demonstrative ability which is actualized in the experience. This is not
to say that changes in appearance do not entail some change in the relevant
demonstrative ability, only that the change need not be one of identity. The current
appearances are part of what presently forms the ability, and thus we might say that
changes in appearance are changes in the character of the ability. (Note that presenting
things this way does not require viewing appearances as more basic than
demonstrative abilities. As mentioned above, the strong-conceptualist may claim that
what is in question are genuine appearances - rather than, say, mere sub-personal
information-processing or mere sensations - only in the context of the actualization of
demonstrative abilities).
V
Whether or not this is Brewer's view, I see no obvious reason for him to reject it.
It might seem that if we treat illusory cases exactly as we treat the cases in which the
experience is veridical, we will not be able to say, as Brewer wishes to say, that simply
experiencing an object provides the subject with a reason to judge that things are the
way they are experienced. But, first, as long as the subject attends to a particular object
51 What about cases in which the appearance changes from being veridical to non-veridical in a
misleading way? It seems that, in non-artificial conditions, ordinary subjects hardly encounter cases in
which, while continuously attending to the property, such changes appear as changes of the property.
First, the fact that the property has been seen and attended to for a while from different perspectives or
in different circumstances means that the conditions are different from those obtaining when the subject
views the property from a perspective and in circumstances which are exactly as the current ones except
that the property had just become visible or that the subject has only presently shifted his attention to it.
Since information is present in dynamic patterns of light, it is possible that only in the latter conditions
the appearance would be misleading. Furthermore, when there is a change which results in a nonveridical appearance, the change might be experienced as such due to the subject's experiencing the
change in the conditions which is responsible for the change in appearance.
39
and to a specific property of it, his judging that this is thus is bound to be true, for the
property he is predicating is the actual property of the demonstrated object. (The ways
in which things can go wrong are (i) the subject fails to realize that what he takes to be
an unchanging property is in fact changing, (ii) he fails to realize that he is
hallucinating. In both cases there will be no corresponding demonstrative element in
the content of the experience). 52 Since the subject's grasp of the relation between
appearances and the experienced property is such that he takes into account the
possibility of inaccurate information, and when the information is inaccurate he still
has the ability to keep track of the property and gather more accurate information
about it, there is a clear sense in which he knows which property is in question even
when he is mistaken about its character: he knows that it is the property he is actually
attending to and that even if his current applications of the predicate to other objects
are mistaken, he is normally able to correct them by performing relevant exploratory
actions while continuing to attend to the property. This also means that, as Brewer
suggests, the mere fact that the subject grasps that this [a seen object a] is thus [a
particular seen property of a] can provide the subject with a reason to judge that this is
thus (even when he suspects that the appearance might be misleading or believes that
it is).
The misleading appearance may, of course, give rise to mistakes when the
subject applies the concept ;c is thus to other objects, makes judgements about the
relations between being thus and being thus* (where the latter relates to a different
instance of a property in the same dimension), or attempts to evaluate thoughts
involving more general concepts (for example, in the discussed case, judging that the
object is round rather than elliptical). But - given the ability to correct such mistakes
52 There is, in fact, a third possibility. An apparent property of an object might be due to information
from a different object. It seems that there is no one clear answer as to what we should say in cases of
this type.
40
by performing various exploratory actions (such as moving towards the instance of the
property while continuing to attend to it) and the fact that the subject takes into
account the possibility of such mistakes and the ways in which he may be able to
correct them - holding that the appearances which explain these mistakes are currently
part of what forms the subject's demonstrative ability but not part of what individuates
it seems more reasonable than saying that there is no aspect of the content which
corresponds to the non-veridical experience or that the relevant aspect of the content is
of a different type (that is, different from the type found when the experience is
veridical).
VI
There is a further question the strong-conceptualist has to answer. The property
predicated by the subject is supposed to be the property he attends to and is able to
keep track of despite changing appearances; but we have not yet clarified in virtue of
what a subject can be said to attend to a specific fine-grained property, rather than to
any other property of the same dimension which is sliced more finely or more
coarsely. Suppose that we have a situation in which it seems correct to say that the
subject is selecting shape information (as opposed to information about colour,
texture, etc.) from a seen object; for example, a situation in which he is comparing, on
the basis of his visual experience, the shape of the object with the shape of some other
object. This description of the situation is not sufficient for saying that the subject is
attending to a particular fine-grained shape, rather than to one which is sliced more
coarsely, more finely, or even that he is, generally, attending to the object's shape
whichever shape it is and whichever way it changes. If there are no current changes in
the object's shape, all these candidates are a source of the information he is currently
selecting. Thus we need to say something about what would make it the case that the
41
subject is attending to one particular shape sliced a certain way; that is, we should
explain what would make it the case that, when certain changes of the object's shape
take place, the subject cannot be regarded as continuing to attend to the same finegrained shape while other changes will not have this effect.
Since we are considering the fine-grained properties which experience makes
available to the subject, it is clear that in some way or another we should appeal to the
subject's (visual) discriminatory abilities. 53 We cannot appeal merely to facts
regarding what would appear to the subject as an actual change of the property rather
than changes in the appearance which are due to change in conditions or an
appearance of lack of change. For a change of the object's shape which appears as
such in certain conditions may not appear so in others. Rather it seems that we should
appeal to the subject's (fallible) ability to discriminate properties in certain favourable
conditions. However, we are constrained by the need to make sure that we can account
for the subject's knowledge of which mind-independent, fine-grained property is in
question. This requires that there be a sense in which the subject grasps which
conditions are the ones in which he should be able to distinguish the property from any
other seen property, a grasp he may have regardless of whether these conditions
actually obtain (and, at least according to the view under discussion, the relevant grasp
should be associated with the subject's grasp of the joint dependence of his experience
on the actual property and relevant conditions, allowing him to grasp that he is
experiencing the same property while the appearance changes).
53 It should be emphasized that an appeal to the subject discriminatory abilities in order to determine the
fine-grainedness of the property does not make the property mind-dependent. Any way of slicing
properties that reflects certain differences in the causal effects which objects might have, has an
objective basis. The fact that we appeal to differences in causal effects on the subject's visual system
does not make the difference mind-dependent. Objects would have had the same causal power whether
or not there were minds to be affected by them. It is true that what I appeal to is partly determined by
limitations of the visual system (and it is possible that these are simply due to physiological limitations),
but the important point is that there actually are objective differences in causal power to be detected.
What the limitations of the visual system add is that they determine, among the different objective ways
in which the relevant dimension can be sliced, which way of slicing is the one that distinguishes
properties the subject can visually keep track of.
42
Before going on to discuss what seems to be the line one should take here, I
should clarify that there is no room for suggesting that the current appearance and the
immediate expectations as to how the appearance may change with change in the
conditions somehow determine the relevant property, and therefore suggesting that the
current appearance is essential to the individuation of the ability to think about things
as thus. The ability to discriminate the property given its current appearance cannot be
that according to which the property is sliced, for we are assuming that the subject can
continue to attend to the property while the appearance changes. But it might seem
that the strong-conceptualist could appeal to the subject's immediate expectations
regarding the appearance of the property in optimal conditions (or something of this
sort) and say that the fineness of the attended property is determined by what the
subject expects to be indiscriminable in those conditions. However, the suggestion is
implausible. First, it is implausible to suggest that at any given time we can pick out
certain expectations as those which relate to conditions we would regard as standard,
and even less plausible to suggest that we can do so consistently in various current
conditions. But even if this difficulty is ignored, it is clearly not the case that the
expectations we have, given the current appearance, as to how things would appear in
certain conditions (different from the current ones) have a form which could enable us
to determine, at present, what we would regard in those conditions as the same or
different fine-grained property. Specifically, they do not normally consist in a current
ability to imagine the exact appearance in the relevant conditions, and even when they
do, it seems that the images are never specific enough for basing on them judgements
about the indiscriminability of fine-grained properties.
What, then, could determine the fineness of the predicated property? First, note
that the relevant candidates (i.e., the properties the subject can attend to) are those
fine-grained properties which vision enables the subject to discriminate as distinct
43
properties. That is, it is not sufficient that in specific given conditions the appearance
of an instance of the property is discriminable from the appearance of instances of any
other relevant property seen in the same conditions. Furthermore, it is not sufficient
that for any other relevant property there could be some conditions (which are in the
range of standard vision-enabling conditions) in which an instance of that property is
discriminable from the instance in question. The latter condition is necessary, but it is
required, in addition, that there be a sense in which, whatever the current conditions
are, the subject has some grasp of the type of conditions in which he could
discriminate the property, and that this be a grasp that could guide him in attempting to
discriminate the property and evaluate the possibility of such discriminations in the
current conditions. (For, otherwise, the subject cannot be ascribed a grasp of the
possibility of his experiencing the same property in varying conditions; a grasp which
can in fact be maintained in varying conditions).
It seems that at least properties which are sliced according to the threshold of the
subject's current visual discriminatory abilities satisfy these conditions. For not only is
it the case that for any property differing from such a property there are conditions (in
the range of standard vision-enabling conditions) in which the subject can discriminate
it from the property in question, but also subjects have some grasp of the kind of
changes in conditions which may enable them to discriminate different fine-grained
properties if they are indiscriminable in the current conditions. Suppose then, that we
agree that subjects are able to discriminate, as distinct properties, instances of finegrained properties which are individuated as follows. Two instances a and b have the
same fine-grained property iff any instance jc that is indiscriminable from a (in the
relevant respect) is indiscriminable from b and vice versa. Where x is indiscriminable
fromjy (in the relevant respect) iff there are no conditions in the range of the standard
vision-enabling conditions in which the subject can discriminate x from>>. (Remember
44
that what is in question is not an ability to decide for any two instances whether they
are instances of the same property but rather to grasp what it is for two instances to be
of the same property). 54
The mere fact that certain properties are discriminable by the subject as distinct
properties does not solve the initial problem which was what would distinguish, for
example, a case in which the subject attends to the fine-grained shape of a given
object, sliced according to the subject's discriminatory threshold, from a case in which
he attends to the object's shape whichever particular shape it is. 55 What we need in
addition is that the subject's interests be such that he restricts his attention to the
relevant fine-grained property; that is, although he might not be able to tell whether he
is successful, his intention should be to select information relating to the relevant
dimension only as long as no change in this dimension which he could discriminate in
the relevant favourable conditions occurs. Without such an intention, all we can appeal
to is the subject's brute dispositions to react in certain ways when a change in shape is
detected. However, since we are assuming that the conditions may be such that the
shape may change while it appears to the subject that there is no change, this will not
suffice for making it the case that the subject attends to the actual fine-grained shape.
And if it is proposed that the relevant dispositions are the dispositions to react in the
relevant favourable conditions, it is unclear what relation there is between these brute
54 1 should mention that I have been speaking about x is thus as predicating a mind-independent property
following Brewer's explicit stress on this in chapter 6. However on p. 175, when Brewer discusses the
conceptualist's response to the difficulty raised by the non-transitivity of perceptual indiscriminability,
he suggests that x is thus should be true of any object which is indiscriminable in the relevant respect
from the demonstrated instance. Unless Brewer wishes to adopt a non-standard view, allowing that the
objects on which a certain property can be truly predicated need not have this property, this should be
taken to be a slip. For surely Brewer would not say that the properties which are presented to subjects in
experience as the properties of seen objects are of the form 'x is indiscriminable in, say, shape from this
[referring to a sample]', and as mentioned in the discussion of McDowell's view, this does not seem to
provide us with an account of what makes mind-independent properties available to the subject in
experience.
55 Or further possible shapes, sliced more coarsely, and similarly from his attending to a certain pattern
of change of shape. It seems that there can be more than one possible property the subject may attend to,
but I shall ignore these possibilities and focus on the question presented in the text.
45
dispositions and the subject's knowledge of which property he is currently attending
to. Specifically, such dispositions can have no bearing on what he grasps to be a case
in which he is keeping track of the same property while the appearance may change.
To see that there are circumstances in which we may ascribe to an ordinary
subject the intention to restrict his attention to a fine-grained property sliced according
to his discriminatory threshold, consider a subject who is selecting shape information
from a given object with the purpose of determining exactly which fine-grained shape
the object has. Such a task, it seems, is understood by an ordinary subject as involving
both the recognition of general features of the shape (e.g., which category of shape it
resembles if at all, whether it is angular, symmetric, complex, and so on) and a
question regarding the extent to which it visibly resembles or differs from other shapes
with the same general features. The subject will thus be disposed to evaluate the
visible resemblance and difference between the currently seen shape and other shapes
(which might include the shape of the given object at a later time), while taking into
account the possibility of mistakes and how it is affected by changes in conditions
(where he has at least some general grasp of which changes can affect his ability to
discriminate fine-grained shapes, and is able to recognize changes in conditions which
improve or detract from this ability; however, he need not know exactly to what extent
the current conditions are close to optimal and similarly need not be able to foresee
exactly which changes will affect the ability in which way). Due to his interest in the
fine-grained shape, the subject will be attentive to any small change in the apparent
shape, and any such change which he takes to be an actual change of the object's
actual shape will be viewed by him as a change in which property he is attending to
(as opposed to, for example, a case in which a subject is selecting shape information
from a triangle with the purpose of only making a general categorical shape
judgement; if the triangle is seen to undergo a change in the width of two of its angles
46
this would not be regarded by the subject as a change in which particular shape he is
attending to). Furthermore, the subject will regard in a similar manner cases of change
in the object's shape which he does not notice but which he could have noticed if the
conditions were different (but still in the range of standard vision-enabling conditions).
Thus, in this type of case, as long as the subject, in fact, continues to select
information from the same fine-grained shape (sliced according to his discriminatory
threshold) with the relevant purpose, he should be regarded as attending to this finegrained shape. Attending to the shape together with his ability to keep track of it
(which is a matter of his having these discriminatory abilities as well as a conception
of their dependence on various conditions) makes it the case that he knows which finegrained shape he is attending to and thus has a grasp of what it is for an arbitrary
object to have this shape. This is so even though he is never in a position to determine
with certainty that another instance of a shape is of exactly the same fine-grained
shape as the attended one (since he will always allow for the possibility that there are
other conditions in which he can discriminate the shapes of the two instances), and
though he is always fallible as to whether or not he is actually continuously attending
to one and the same fine-grained shape. 56
One may complain that normally people do not have such interests: most often
we are interested in more general categories of seen things, or in local comparisons
between, say, the shapes of two specific seen objects, where normally this does not
involve worrying about the exact slicing of properties. Brewer concedes that we
experience properties which we are not attending to and claims that in these cases the
account of the content only requires appeal to demonstrative abilities which are not
currently actualized. I shall shortly argue that this aspect of the view is problematic,
56 The subject's certainty about the latter question depends on the extent to which he takes it to be likely
that the attended property and object are such that the fine-grained property is likely to undergo slight
changes without a visible external cause.
47
but at present it is sufficient to note that Brewer does not suggest that, for each
currently experienced aspect, the experience must currently involve the actualization
of a relevant specific demonstrative ability; he only requires that it be possible for such
an ability to be actualized.
A further problem is whether we can assume that the sense in which an ordinary
subject regards certain conditions as standard vision-enabling conditions is such that
he has a grasp of a coherent set of conditions which are specific enough for it to be the
case that discriminability in these conditions would suffice for individuating a certain
fine-grained property. I leave this question open. If the points made above are correct,
then the strong-conceptualist must provide some account along the suggested lines,
and if there is no such plausible account this should be seen as a further reason to
conclude that one cannot construe the experience of fine-grained properties as a matter
of the actualization of demonstrative abilities.
Suppose, however, that an account of this type is possible. One point to note is
that an account of what determines how fine-grained the attended property is does not
seem to support the view that the current appearance plays a role in the individuation
of the relevant demonstrative abilities. Thus, given the considerations presented in
section IV for holding that the current appearance of the property being the appearance
of this or that specific fine-grained property does not play a role in the individuation of
the ability, I shall assume that the above construal is the best construal of the strongconceptual suggestion, and in the following discussion ascribe it to the strongconceptualist.
Secondly, and more importantly, the discussion makes clear that, for a particular
demonstrative ability predicating a fine-grained mind-independent property (expressed
by 'jc is thus') to be actualized, the subject must attend to a particular instance of a
property in a rather demanding sense. It is not sufficient that information from the
48
relevant instance is currently among the information selected by him as relevant to a
certain task (specifically, for the control of his thoughts and actions) or even that as a
matter of fact only information from the aspect is selected. The subject must view only
information from the particular instance of the specific property as relevant to a certain
task, where saying that he views the information this way is saying that he will attempt
to select information, and to evaluate his selection, according to what he takes to be
information from the instance and what he takes to be considerations relevant to the
evaluation of whether it actually is from the same instance of the property. This is
necessary for the subject to grasp which property is predicated, and thus, necessary for
him to grasp what it is for an object (any object) to be thus (to have the given
property).
The point is not restricted only to fine-grained properties. The same difficulty
arises regarding all cases in which the subject is supposed to attend to a specific
property (as opposed to generally attending to the relevant dimension), and as far as I
can see the constraints on what is required if the subject is to attend to the property in a
way which provides him with knowledge of which property is in question is, again,
that he attends with the intention to restrict the selection of information to information
from the relevant property alone. Furthermore, it seems that the point can be
generalized to all environmental aspects, though for present purposes we can focus on
properties (however, for convenience's sake I shall often speak about environmental
aspects in general rather than specifically about properties of objects).
This creates a serious problem for the strong-conceptualist. For, clearly subjects
do not attend, in this demanding sense, to all the aspects of the environment which
they are experiencing. It was just mentioned that subjects do not normally attend in
this sense to fine-grained properties (sliced according to the subject's discriminatory
threshold). And normally there are various other seen aspects which are not attended
49
to in this sense; for example, a subject who attends to a seen table and to its colour
would normally experience several other properties of the table (e.g. its location,
shape, orientation) regardless of whether or not he is currently attending to any of
them. Furthermore, while attending to the table, he may experience several unattended
things surrounding it (e.g. the wall behind it, the objects on it, etc.), thus experiencing
at least some properties of these objects (e.g., the fact that the wall is behind the table,
its colour, or at least the fact that its colour is lighter than the table's, etc.). In the
remaining part of this chapter I shall argue that the strong-conceptualist must either
give up the generality of his view or hold the unintuitive view that we do not
experience properties which we are not attending to in the demanding sense.
(Hereafter I shall use 'attention to x\ where x is a certain environmental aspect, to
refer to attention to the aspect in the demanding sense. When a subject is not attending
to a certain aspect in this demanding sense, I shall refer to it as an 'unattended
aspect').
VII
Brewer mentions the difficulty regarding unattended aspects, and remarks, in
response, that he agrees that there are parts of the content of our conscious experience
which are not conceptualized, but that nevertheless 'the central notion in
understanding perceptual experience is... the attentional selection of information
which is thereby conceptualized in perceptual demonstrative content'. 57 The claim is
presented as following from his description of the non-conceptualized aspects as
information which is available to the subject (rather than only to sub-personal systems)
'in the sense that it is a possible focus for his selective attention, without further ado,
either actively directed in the service of some ongoing project, or passively drawn by
57 p. 240.
50
acquiring some other kind of salience'. 58 If this response is meant as a defence of the
generality of the strong-conceptual view, then it seems that it should be read as
follows. Though the relevant aspects of the experiential content do not involve the
actualization of demonstrative abilities, what makes it the case that they are aspects of
the content of the experience is the fact that the subject can select them for the control
of his thoughts and actions (where, according to Brewer, such selection just is the
actualization of a demonstrative ability).
But what can be the basis for such a claim? At least at first glance it seems to be
based on the thought that it is only when the relevant information is selected by the
subject (and a demonstrative ability is actualized), that the information in question can
have a subject-level effect on his thoughts and actions; where it is only when the
information can have such an effect, that we can speak about it as available to the
subject in the sense which allows us to view it as part of the content of the experience.
If so, the status of the relevant parts of the experiential content as content for the
subject is derived from their potential for affecting his thoughts and actions once they
are conceptualized.
However, this line of reasoning is problematic. First, it seems that the experience
of unattended aspects can have a direct subject-level effect on the subject's thoughts
and actions (where by saying that the effect is direct I mean that it can take place
without the conceptualization of the information). More important, it is difficult to see
how one can deny that information from unattended aspects can have such an effect
without also denying that such aspects are experienced by the subject (prior to a shift
in attention). For, in general, if perceptual information from a certain aspect can have
58 p.240. Brewer's summary of this point (p.241) suggests that by 'further ado' he means further uptake
of information. If I understand correctly, the idea is that the information is available to the subject in
such a way that simply by selecting it for deliberation and control of action the subject's attention is
shifted to the object and property the information is from: no further gathering of information or further
information-processing is required for the shift to take place (though the shift in attention will probably
result in further information-processing and thus further information will be available to the subject).
51
no present direct rational effect on the subject's activities, it is not clear how the
information which can be, but is not yet, selected by him could be regarded as part of
what he is currently aware of; thus it is not clear how it could be regarded as
experiential information. If the subject cannot be immediately aware of implications of
the information to his activities, it is not clear in what sense he is currently aware of
the information. But if he can be aware of the relevance of the information to his
activities, then - assuming that, generally, he has the ability to adjust his activities
intentionally in relevant ways - it should be possible for him to adjust them according
to what he takes to be relevant implication of the information.
In other words, it seems that the claim I ascribed to the strong-conceptualist namely, that certain information can be said to be presented to the subject in
experience only if it can have a subject-level effect on her activities - should be
understood as requiring the possibility of a direct subject-level effect rather than only
the potential for affecting the activities (a potential which could be actualized only
when the subject attends to the relevant environmental aspect). Or, at least, this should
be the case if the motivation for this claim is (as I take it to be) that to say that the
information is presented to the subject in experience just is to say that it is integrated
into her current view of how things are, and thus, like any other aspect of her view, is
immediately grasped by her as having various possible implication for her thoughts
and actions. 59
This should also clarify that there is no room for objecting to the above
consideration by suggesting that attention to the aspect is required for the subject to
realize that the information, which she is already aware of, has implications for her
activities. The connection between the subject's awareness of the information and the
possibility of its direct subject-level effect on her activities is a result of the fact that
59 Which is the point emphasized in Chapter 1.
52
for a certain piece of information to be part of her view of how things are just is for it
to immediately be grasped by her as having various connections with other actual and
possible states of affairs, and thus as having a normative bearing on her thoughts and
actions. That is, the awareness of possible implication is not an additional step which
might or might not take place after the subject becomes aware of the information. I do
not mean to claim that the subject cannot be more or less sensitive to information she
is aware of, and that it cannot happen that in certain conditions she fails to act on it.
The claim is that we cannot generally deny the possibility of her acting on it directly
(where, of course, there are further conditions which enable her reaction; but such
conditions are not specific to the experience of unattended aspects), where it is this
possibility that the strong-conceptualist cannot accept.
We can direct the complaint specifically against Brewer's explanation of the
sense in which he takes information from unattended aspects to be available to the
subject. The suggestion was that it can be said to be available to the subject in the
sense that it is a possible focus of the subject's attention '.. .either actively directed in
the service of some ongoing project, or passively drawn by acquiring some other kind
of salience' (p.240). Now suppose that Brewer denies that the content of the
experience of the unattended aspect can have a direct subject-level effect on the way
the subject directs his attention (thus holding that the way subjects actively direct their
attention can be affected only by things like expectation based on memory, general
knowledge and the information from the attended aspects, instructions, a general plan
for a systematic search of the visual field, etc.). According to the above consideration,
it is, then, unclear why the fact that information from the aspect is a possible focus of a
subject's attention is regarded as relevant to explaining the sense in which he can be
said to (consciously) experience the unattended aspects; for on such a view, the
question of whether he is aware of the information has no bearing on the way he
53
directs or could direct his attention. It might be pointed out that Brewer also says that
the shift in attention does not require any further uptake of information. But it seems
that this addition is, at best, simply a statement that the relevant information is already
available to the subject. If so, we have no explanation of the sense in which the
information is said to be available to him, and in addition there is a need to explain
why this information cannot have any direct rational effect on the subject's activities.
VIII
Intuitively it is implausible to deny that we experience unattended properties
(where what is in question is any property from which the subject is not intentionally
selecting information he takes to be from the property). Furthermore, holding that
experiencing a specific property requires attending to it seems to lead to absurdity. A
subject may attend to the relevant general property; that is, he may intentionally select,
say, shape information from the given object, regardless of whether the shape is
changing and in what way. If the subject does not restrict his attention to a specific
current shape (that is, a shaped sliced in some specific way), he is not attending to it in
the sense required for knowing what it is for an object to have it. If we take this to
entail that the subject is not experiencing the object's fine-grained shape, then we will
have to accept, for example, that it is possible for the subject to experience the shape
changing without experiencing the shapes which it has in any relevant stage.60 Despite
all this, a strong-conceptualist might be encouraged to accept that we do not
experience unattended aspects by various empirical data showing the unreliability of
our intuitions as to what we are in fact experiencing and the actual effect the
60 It would not help to argue that strictly speaking it is not specific shapes which are experienced, but
rather only the change (or some similar claim); for the strong-conceptualist will have to explain what an
experience of the particular changes involves and will then encounter the same difficulties. Similarly,
cases in which the subject attends to an object without attending to its properties will be claimed to
involve experiencing the object without experiencing its properties.
54
experience has on our thoughts and action. I shall consider this possibility in Chapter 4
and argue that the relevant data do not support a complete denial of these intuitive
claims. At present, we should go on to consider which further options are open to
strong-conceptualists who do not wish to deny that we can experience unattended
aspects.
The above considerations, if correct, show that a strong-conceptualist who does
not deny that we experience unattended aspects cannot deny that such experiences
could have some subject-level effect on the subject's activities. In principle there is
room for holding that the content of an experience has to involve the actualization of
demonstrative abilities only when it provides reasons for outright empirical
judgements, and that only the experience of attended aspects provides such reasons.
However, at least McDowell and Brewer's argument for maintaining that only
conceptual content can provide the subject with reasons (which will be discussed in
Chapter 3) seems to rule out any view according to which a subject could be said to
take a non-conceptualized element of the content to have a normative bearing on his
activities. (Note also, that, even if it is agreed that non-conceptualized elements of the
experience do not provide reasons for outright empirical judgements, it seems
impossible to deny that they play a role in the account of demonstrative abilities. For
example, a subject can attend to a seen object and entertain demonstrative thoughts
about it without attending to any specific property of it; in fact, normally he cannot
attend to all of its visible properties at once. But the object's appearance, which
consists of the appearance of its properties, is what guides the subject's attention to it
and plays a central role in the subject's ability to keep track of it; thus the appearance
of these unattended properties can be indispensable to the subject's ability to think
demonstratively about it. Thus the strong-conceptualist should also give up the claim
that an experiential content can play a role in explaining our conceptual abilities only
55
if it involves the actualization of a conceptual ability (though so far it has not been
shown that he cannot maintain that the content of the experience of an attended aspect
is both necessary for such an account and involves the actualization of a demonstrative
ability)).
Even if we conclude here that McDowell and Brewer would not attempt to
defend a view which allows for a subject-level effect of non-conceptualized elements
of experiential content, we should still ask whether one who accepts that there are nonconceptualized elements of the content and that they could have some subject-level
effects, can provide a different motivation for claiming that the non-conceptual
elements of the content are explanatorily dependent on specific, currently nonactualized, demonstratives abilities. Since we agreed that we cannot construe the
content of an experience of an unattended aspect as merely a potential for the exercise
of a certain demonstrative ability, it is difficult to see how such a view could be
defended. In fact, it seems that strictly speaking the subject does not have the
particular demonstrative ability when not attending to the property. For his attention to
the property is required for him to know which property is in question, and such
knowledge is required not only for the actualization of a particular conceptual ability,
but also for possessing it. But it should be clear that the strong-conceptualist cannot
even suggest that the account of the specific experience of a specific unattended aspect
requires appeal to the specific potential for thinking demonstratively about the
experienced unattended aspect in question; i.e., that it requires appeal to the fact that,
due to his experiencing the relevant aspect, he has information from it which enables
him to shift his attention towards it if he wishes to do so, and thus has the ability to
apply, to this particular aspect, his general ability to think demonstratively about
experienced aspects of the relevant type and the general ability to attend to such
aspects, and generally knows that he can do so.
56
One might try to suggest that there is such an explanatory dependence by
pointing out that an experience of a particular aspect depends on the subject's ability
to apply his general grasp of perception to the particular case in question, and it is
central to this that the subject can have the specific demonstrative ability in question.
But it is clear that this relation between the current experience of the unattended aspect
and the potential to think demonstratively about the aspect is such that what is relevant
to explaining the current experience are general abilities: the subject's general ability
to attend to various aspects of the environment and his general ability to reason in
certain ways about the relation between the way things appear and the way they
actually are. The fact that, in addition to the general abilities, the subject currently has
this particular potential rather than others is simply a consequence of the fact that he is
currently experiencing the relevant aspect.
IX
The claim, then, is that one cannot hold that all aspects of the experience are
either conceptualized or accountable in terms of the specific demonstrative ability
which would have been actualized had the subject attended to the relevant experienced
environmental aspect. Furthermore, it was claimed that if the strong-conceptualist
wishes to maintain that we consciously experience unattended aspects, then he must
admit that the non-conceptualized parts of the content can have a direct rational effect
on the subject's activity, that is, an effect which is not mediated by a conceptualization
of the information. However, conceding this possibility seems incompatible with the
motivation for holding that only the conceptualized parts of the content can provide
the subject with reasons for an outright acceptance of empirical propositions. I have
mentioned the possibility that the strong-conceptualist would deny that we experience
unattended aspects. If the reasoning in this chapter is correct, then this is the position
57
one is forced to adopt if there is a conclusive argument showing that only conceptual
contents can have a rational effect on the subject's activities. In the next chapter I shall
argue that the argument McDowell and Brewer provide is not conclusive. One might,
however, find the unintuitive (and arguably absurd) position of denying that we
experience unattended aspects appealing for other reasons. I shall discuss this
possibility in Chapter 4 and clarify why I think it should be rejected. This almost
completes the claim that the strong-conceptual view is both unmotivated and
unworkable. However, the claim in the next chapter is only that the strongconceptualists do not provide a general argument which shows that it is impossible for
non-conceptualized aspects of the content to provide the subject with reasons for
belief. It might still be possible to argue for the need of a strong-conceptual view by
pointing out that no suitable alternative has been provided so far. It is thus time to
clarify what the suggested alternative is.
I fully agree with the strong-conceptualist that for a subject to have a certain
experience - for it to be the case that things are experientially presented to the subject
as being a certain way - the experience must be integrated into the way in which the
subject reasons about how he is related to his environment, and specifically this should
yield a grasp of his experience as jointly dependent on how things actually are and on
various relevant conditions (these are the results of the considerations presented in
Chapter 1 and considerations as to what a subject's grasp of his interaction with a
mind-independent world involves). Furthermore, I agree that the content of a particular
experience is determined by the actual experienced environmental aspects and the
relevant conditions, where this is possible in virtue of the way in which these factors
are integrated into the subject's primitive conception of perception and objects. The
dispute is about whether such a view entails that the experience of attended aspects is a
matter of an actualization of demonstrative abilities and whether the experience of
58
unattended aspects should be explained in terms of the demonstrative abilities which
would have been actualized had the subject attended to the experienced aspect. The
strong-conceptualist thinks that it does since he holds that conceptual abilities are the
only abilities which are such that their actualization immediately entails the grasp of
normative relations between states in which they are actualized and other contentful
mental states. My response is simply to deny this, claiming that we should accept that
experiential content involves the actualization of capacities whose actualization
immediately entails the same type of grasp, but which differ from conceptual abilities
in important respects (and thus should not be regarded as conceptual abilities).
The thought behind this response is that mental abilities, and the states one is
said to be in when they are actualized, are individuated according to the function they
have in the subject's mental life. Thus if the abilities actualized when the subject has a
particular experience with a particular content can be shown to differ in function in a
significant way from conceptual abilities (specifically, demonstrative ones), then this
would justify holding that there are states which are similar to conceptual states in that
being in them suffices for the subject to grasp the normative bearing which they have
on his thinking, while their having the content they do is not due to the actualization of
relevant conceptual abilities. So far we have seen that if we experience specific
properties when they are unattended, then the relevant part of the experience (that
which is due to the fact that the subject is experiencing the relevant unattended
property) does not involve the actualization of a demonstrative ability - where two
essential characteristics of such abilities are that they are actualized only together with
other relevant conceptual abilities, yielding a state with a prepositional content, and
that their actualization is not restricted to a specific context (by which I mean a
specific type of a prepositional attitude). Since saying that the relevant aspects are
experienced entails that they are directly grasped by the subject as having certain
59
implications to his activities, the experience of unattended aspects must be viewed as
involving the actualization of capacities which are similar to conceptual abilities in
this respect, but differ from them at least in the other two respects mentioned in the
previous sentence.
60
3 Experience and reasons for beliefs
I
I have been arguing that the strong-conceptual view is unfeasible, at least as
long as it is meant to be a general view relating to all aspects of our experience.
However, strong-conceptualists like McDowell and Brewer do more than just
suggest their versions of a strong-conceptual view: they argue that experiential
content must be construed in the suggested way if we are to have the ability, which
we take ourselves to have, to think about the way things are in our environment. In
this chapter I shall argue that the argument they provide is inconclusive.
Both McDowell and Brewer argue that (i) if our empirical beliefs are to have the
content we take them to have, experience must provide a subject with reasons for (at
least) some of his empirical beliefs;61 (ii) states with content which is not of the type
that can be the content of a judgement cannot provide such reasons; therefore (assuming
that we have the empirical beliefs we take ourselves to have) (iii) the content of
experience (or rather the parts of the content which provides such reasons) must be of a
type which could be the content of a judgement (where such a content - a proposition is a content which a state has in virtue of the actualization of two or more relevant
conceptual abilities). It is the argument for the second premise which I find
inconclusive. McDowell and Brewer defend this premise by emphasizing that what is in
question is the subject's reasons - that is, the reasons which the subject recognizes as
reasons for endorsing relevant contents (or performing relevant actions) and which
consequently motivate his doing so - and claiming that only the relevant conceptual
contents (propositions) could be recognized by the subject as having such normative
61 McDowell speaks about the experience being the subject's reason, while Brewer normally says that
experience provides the subject with a reason. My interpretation is that Brewer agrees that when the
subject takes the experience at face value and forms relevant beliefs the experience can be said to be his
reason for forming these beliefs, but that he is careful to leave room for cases in which a subject
mistakenly assumes that his experience is not veridical or that there are reasons to doubt its veridicality.
61
bearing on what he believes and does. I shall argue that they do not provide a general
argument for accepting this last claim. Since Brewer presents a more detailed version of
the argument, I focus on his version.
II
Brewer begins by arguing that giving reasons involves identifying certain
propositions as the premises and conclusion of a relevant argument. Since I object to
Brewer's reliance on this claim at the next stage, I shall quote the argument in full.
To give a reason [for making a particular judgement, holding a certain belief or
performing a certain action at a given time] is to identify some feature of the subject's
situation which makes the relevant judgement or belief (or perhaps action) appropriate
or intelligible, from the point of view of rationality. It is... to mention considerations
which reveal the judgement or belief (or action) as at least approximating to what
rationally ought to happen in those circumstances. Now, making something intelligible
from the point of view of rationality in this way necessarily involves identifying a
valid deductive argument, or an inference of some other kind, which articulates the
source of the rational obligation (or permission) in question. For rational intelligibility,
or appropriateness of the kind revealed by giving reasons, just is the mode of
approbation which is made explicit by the reconstruction of valid reasoning62 of some
such kind to a conclusion that is suitably related to the judgement or belief (or action)
for which the reasons are being given. Hence, in making essential reference to the
relevant valid inference, giving a reason involves making essential reference to its
premises and conclusion, and so trivially to the kinds of things which can serve as the
premises and conclusion of some kind of inference [namely, propositions]. 63
If'giving a reason' is understood as the meta-activity of articulating in speech or
thought what makes it appropriate to accept a certain proposition as true,64 then one
cannot but agree that such activity will involve forming an argument which is taken to
be correct.65 One might also be willing to accept that the claim applies to cases in which
62 Brewer comments in a footnote that 'validity' is to be understood here in a wide sense, including the
correctness of inductive and abductive arguments.
63 pp. 150-1.
64 In order to simplify the discussion I shall ignore the case of action (in effect, Brewer does so as well: he
does not consider any aspect which relates to practical, rather than mental, actions alone). Also, for
convenience's sake I shall sometimes mention only one of the possibilities (judging or forming a belief)
or speak in general about taking or holding a certain content to be true.
65 I shall use 'correct' as the general term (i.e., applying to any type of argument) for the property in
virtue of which accepting the premises justifies accepting the conclusion, since 'valid' seems to be linked
too closely with deductive arguments.
62
a subject reveals a reason for a belief in conversation without actually articulating it; for
example, doing this by pointing at a certain location and saying 'just look at that'. For it
might be argued that if the speaker is to be regarded as really giving a reason and if the
hearer is to understand the speaker, they both have to articulate the premises of the
relevant argument in thought. However, agreeing on these two points is not sufficient
for justifying Brewer's application of this consideration at the second stage of his
argument, where the question is what is required for a subject to grasp a reason for
making a judgement as his own reason. At best, one can argue that this involves an
implicit identification of such an argument.66 1 shall expand on this claim after
presenting the second stage.
At the second stage Brewer argues that when what is in question is the subject's
reason - i.e., that which, from the subject's point of view, makes a certain judgement
rationally appropriate and therefore motivates her to make this judgement - then, having
the reason consists in the subject's being in a mental state the content of which is a
proposition that the subject takes to be a premise in an argument that, in her view,
justifies making the relevant judgement. (Thus, it is a mental state with a prepositional
content).
It is first argued that
... the subject's having such a reason consists in his being in some mental state or other,
although this may well be essentially factive. For any actually motivating reason/or the
subject must at the very least register at the personal level in this way. 67
The second sentence may seem to support only the claim that the subject's having
a reason must involve his having an appropriate mental state (allowing that
environmental conditions, which are not themselves constituents of the state, may be
66 Why should this case differ from the case in which a speaker conveys a reason without spelling it out?
The thought is that some explicit articulation is required for the speaker to grasp the usefulness of his
means of communication and for the hearer to grasp what the speaker is doing. However, rejecting this
(and holding that the situation which involves communication does not require an explicit articulation of
the relevant argument) is consistent with the view I wish to defend.
67 pp. 151-2.
63
regarded as further constituents of the subject's reason). For it may seem that the
argument is simply that if the reason is to be causally relevant (as a reason) to the fact
that the subject makes the relevant judgement, then he must recognize its status as a
reason, and this, of course, implies having an appropriate mental state.68 However, what
justifies the stronger claim (that the subject's having the relevant reason consists in his
being in the relevant mental state) is the thought that any environmental condition
which is not in some way part of what constitutes the content of the relevant mental
state cannot affect the subject's activity (in this case mental activity) in the right way;
that is, its causal effect, if it has one, cannot be part of an effect which is due to what the
subject recognizes as justifying his activity. Thus it is not part of the subject's reason.
This seems to me perfectly acceptable.
The final step is to argue that the premise proposition which, according to the
previous consideration, one must refer to when giving a reason
... must actually be the content of [the subject's] mental state in a sense that requires that
he has all of its constituent concepts. Otherwise, even though being in some such state
may make it advisable, relative to a certain end or need, for the subject to make the
judgement, or hold the belief... in question, it cannot constitute his own reason for doing
so. (p. 152)
The argument seems to be that if a subject is to have a reason for judging that;?
which he recognizes as such, then according to the consideration of the first stage he
must grasp a certain argument whose conclusion is p and which articulates what makes
it correct, from his point of view, to judge that;? in the given situation. Thus, his having
the reason must involve a grasp of the premise(s) of the argument (which is(are), by
definition, a proposition(s)), and it is precisely the grasp of the premise(s) as the
premise(s) of a correct argument that has the type of motivating force which the
subject's having a reason is supposed to have. Note that since the subject's grasp of the
premise(s) as the premise(s) of a correct argument is supposed to have this motivating
68 On p. 155 Brewer's spells out the consideration in this way.
64
force, the mental state in question is understood to be an occurrent state which involves
the actual entertainment of the premise(s).
As mentioned above, I see no obvious reading of the consideration presented at
the first stage which immediately implies that the subject's recognition of an experience
as providing him with a reason requires that he actually entertain the premises of an
argument which articulates the normative relation between the experience and judging
that/?. At best, if it is agreed that such normative relations must be articulable, there is a
sense in which when a subject recognizes a reason as such he implicitly refers to a
relevant argument. But in order to claim that the subject has to actually entertain the
propositions the argument consists of, one has to show that a subject cannot be said to
recognize the normative bearing of the experience on his judgement if he does not
articulate this normative relation in thought. Before pressing this point further we
should examine Brewer's positive suggestion as to how the subject recognizes the
reasons provided to her by her experience. I shall do so by discussing his response to a
certain line of objection to his suggestion.
Ill
Brewer takes the relevant argument - the one which the subject is supposed to
grasp in order to recognize that a given experience provides her with a reason for
making a certain judgement - to be the argument consisting of (i) the proposition which
is the content of the relevant experience as a premise and (ii) the content of the relevant
judgement as its conclusion. An opponent may suggest instead that the relevant
argument should be one in which the premise is a proposition of the form 'it appears to
me that this is thus'.69 This alternative, the opponent claims, makes room for the
69 Note that despite the fact that the embedded content involves demonstratives it is not impossible to read
the formulation disjunctively. For we need to assume that there is some story to tell about some kind of
quasi-demonstrative abilities which the subject exercises when he does not believe that he is experiencing
65
possibility that the conceptual abilities involved in thinking that this is thus are involved
only in the subject's grasp of the premise proposition and not in her actually having the
experience. Furthermore, at first glance the alternative seems more appropriate than
Brewer's suggestion, since taking a certain argument to be correct is not, by itself, a
reason for accepting its conclusion as true. One must also accept the premise(s) as true.
But having an experience with a particular content is not yet to accept its content as
true.70 In contrast, there seem to be no situations in which a subject, while her
experience presents her with things as being a certain way, does not accept that things
appear to her this way (construed disjunctively). 71 ' 72
Brewer's reply to the latter difficulty is that demonstrative propositions of the
form 'this is thus' are such that, whenever the object referred to demonstratively and the
property predicated are determined by the subject's attention to an object and to a
certain property of it,73 the subject cannot entertain the content without taking himself to
be justified to hold that this is thus is true. This is so due to the background conception
involved in the subject's grasp of what it is for rthis is thus1 to be true (that is, his grasp
of the dependence of his experience on how things are and on various relevant
conditions), and to the fact that he is aware of relevant aspects of his current relation
with the environment, especially, the fact that he is attending to the relevant object and
an actual object and property - abilities which do not involve the subject's current commitment to there
being a particular object and property which he is actually attending to.
70 Heck (2000 p.507) presents this as a reason for preferring the alternative. The above difficulty with
Brewer's suggestion is also mentioned by Martin in his 2001.
71 Heck (2000, 512ff.) and Peacocke (2001 pp.255-9) both appeal to such an alternative in order to show
that requiring that the normative relation be articulable is consistent with holding that experience has a
non-conceptual content. (Both are responding to McDowell who claims that the subject's recognition of a
reason as such requires articulability, rather than actual articulation, of the relation).
72 1 do not deny that a subject might doubt that what seems to be the way things appeared to him in
experience was actually a visual appearance (rather than, say, imagination or an interpretation of the
visual appearance). It seems, however, impossible for a subject to entertain such doubts about a particular
current appearance which he takes to be the current (visual) appearance.
73 See Martin 2001 and Brewer's reply (2001) for the need for this condition. In effect, the above
condition is not strong enough, for there are cases in which different parts of the same object are visible to
the subject but do not appear to be parts of the same object. However, the exact details are not important
at present and in what follows I shall either omit the condition altogether, or just mention generally the
need for relevant conditions to obtain.
66
property.
Thus even though experience only involves entertaining the content (not yet
endorsing it), the mere fact that it is entertained suffices for displaying to the subject his
right to endorse it. If I understand correctly, Brewer regards the subject's rational move
from grasping the proposition to endorsing it as embodying a grasp of a correct
argument from the proposition to itself.
In addition, Brewer argues that the opponent's suggestion (namely, that the
premise should be the content of a belief about the experience rather than the content of
the experience) does not exempt us from the need to take the content of the experience
to be a proposition. 75 Take for example the following version of the opponent's
suggestion. A subject who has a certain experience endorses the proposition rit appears
to me that/?1 . Due to his general grasp of the relation between his experiences and the
way things are, he knows that when the conditions are standard such an appearance is a
result of its being the case that/?. So if he does not doubt that the conditions are
standard, he takes it to be correct to judge that p. The opponent thus accepts that the
subject's actual recognition that he has a reason to judge that/? requires him to be in a
conceptual mental state with the content rit appears to me that /?n , which is a state
which requires him to posses the concepts which are the components of rp^ . But he
claims that the actualization of these concepts is not required for having the relevant
experience.
The question, however, is what basis the subject has for his belief that things
appear to him to be/? (rather than q, for any q£p). Now, it seems plausible that the way
subjects form such beliefs should involve something along the line of Evans's
suggestion on this issue; that is, it should involve the subject's finding out how things
74 1 use the square quotation marks to signify a proposition.
75 Brewer outlines this objection as a reply to Peacocke and Heck (manuscript). The relevant
considerations are spelled out in ch.4 of his 1999.1 take the argument presented below to be a
reconstruction of one of Brewer's main considerations.
67
appear to him by finding out what he is inclined to judge (about the way things are) in
virtue of his sensitivity to the current experience alone. 76 But if this is part of how the
subject forms the belief, then there is a problem as to how the experience and the
relevant inclination are related. If one construes the inclination as the subject's reaction
to the experience's making it rational to judge that p from his point of view, then we are
presupposing what we are attempting to explain (i.e. that, from the subject's point of
view, a particular experience has a certain normative bearing on which thoughts he
should accept as true). But if, on the other hand, the inclination is not due to any rational
effect of the content of the experience, then, it is difficult to see how one can hold that
the alleged content of the experience is a content for the subject (that is, that from his
point of view, things are presented as being a certain way). Or to put the problem
differently, if the inclination is not due to such rational effect, there is no immediate
reason, from the subject's point of view, for taking his judgement about the way things
appear to him in experience to have a normative bearing on what he believes about the
world; for the mere fact that things appear to him a certain way is not taken by him to
have such a bearing on these believes. An attempt to appeal here to assumptions or
knowledge the subject has about the relation between the appearance and the way things
are - assumptions or knowledge which are not operative when he merely has the
experience - will be futile since such assumptions could not be taken by the subject to
be justified without appeal to experience.
76 See Evans pp.227-8. In general, it seems that one who denies the relevance of these inclinations to the
way we form beliefs about how things appear to us must be thinking that such beliefs are somehow based
on the quality which the experience has for the subject. But this immediately leads to insurmountable
problems as to how the subject could view beliefs about the appearance as justifying judgements about
the way things are in the world. I should mention that Heck explicitly adopts Evans's suggestion.
Peacocke (2001 p.258) offers a more elaborate view which involves special demonstrative concepts that
allow thoughts about the fine-grained ways in which things appear. Such concepts are available only
when things are experienced in the relevant way and, if I understand Peacocke's allusion to his notion of
conceptual redeployment correctly, the normative bearing which the subject takes the experience to have
when he is not reflecting on it plays a central role in what constitutes the subject's grasp of the relevant
demonstrative. Thus at least in this respect it depends on the subject's inclinations to make
(demonstrative) judgements about the world on the basis of his experience.
68
The opponent may respond that he does not hold that the subject actually has to
form the argument in order to recognize that her experience provides her with a reason
to make the relevant judgement. He only agrees that the subject has to have the ability
to articulate the normative relation in thought (thus, the ability to form the relevant
argument); for he agrees that if the subject is to have a genuine grasp of a normative
relation, she should be able to reflect on what she takes to be her reason and to grasp the
possibility that she was wrong in taking it to justify the judgement (where, at least for
the sake of the argument, he accepts that this reflective ability involves the ability to
articulate the normative relation between the experience and the content of the
judgement).77 Since the opponent holds that the subject's recognition of the normative
relation depends only on her ability to reflect on the relation and re-evaluate it and not
on its actualization, it is unproblematic that the beliefs about the experience, which the
subject has to be able to form when reflecting on the relation, presuppose her
recognition of the normative relation between the experience and the relevant empirical
judgement. What is relevant to the subject's determining the embedded content of the
self-ascription is the prima facie normative bearing which she takes the experience to
have on her thought evaluation. And the fact that the experience has such a prima facie
normative bearing is independent of her actually forming the relevant argument.
This brings us back to whether Brewer has an argument for the view that,
generally, recognizing a reason as such must involve forming a relevant argument; that
is, whether it must involve an actual articulation of the relevant normative relation in
thought. Brewer seems to regard the consideration of the first stage as providing such an
argument; thus he seems to regard it not merely as a claim about what the articulation of
77 McDowell emphasizes that a genuine grasp of the normative bearing of experience on judgements
requires an ability to articulate a relevant argument (for example, 1996 p.52); Heck and Peacocke are
reacting to this claim.
69
a normative relation involves, but rather as a claim as to what is required for something
to be displayed as a reason, including the case in which what is in question is the
subject's recognition of his own reasons as such. I have claimed that there is no obvious
reason why one should accept this: that the only obvious essential relation between
reason-giving and arguments is the trivial claim that forming an argument which is
supposed to be correct is simply the way of articulating this relation in speech and
thought. What is more, it is rather natural to view the subject's recognition of the
normative bearing of what he experiences on his thought evaluation as a
counterexample to the claim that a subject's recognition of the normative bearing of the
content of a mental state of his on his thought evaluation must involve actual
articulation of this normative relation in thought.
Now, if the normative relation between the experience and the relevant judgement
was one which was entirely due to structural relations between the content of the
experience and the judgement, then this might have been a basis for arguing that the
subject cannot recognize the relation without entertaining the premise proposition. For it
might be possible to argue that there are no normative structural relations between a
"jo
proposition and a non-propositional content. At some points Brewer seems to ascribe a
special significance to the fact that the relevant argument is one which is correct (and
actually valid) in virtue of the structural relation between the premise and the
conclusion; i.e., that it is an argument of the form '/?; therefore/?'. But it is clear that it is
not the formal relation between the premise and the conclusion that articulates the
relevant normative relation. As mentioned above, Brewer's picture of how the subject
grasps the normative relation between the experience and the judgement deviates from
the standard way in which a grasp of an argument articulates, for the subject, the right
she has for making a certain judgement. What matters on his picture is not the fact that
78 1 am not claiming that this is the case. I am unclear about what an opposing view might be.
70
'/?; therefore p' is a valid form of argument, but rather the fact that merely grasping the
content rthis is thus"1 (in the relevant conditions) involves grasping that, in fact, this is
thus. Clearly, this does not hold for all p. (And it is clear that Brewer is not suggesting
that the subject first endorses the premise as true in virtue of grasping its content and
then relies on the validity of arguments of the form '/?; there fore p" to conclude that she
is justified to judge that this is thus). Furthermore, given what the grasp of the concepts
this and is thus involves, there seem to be transformations from one proposition, say,
rthis belongs to John"1 , to another, say, ""there is something in my visual field now"1 ,
which can be justified in the same way and are not instances of a formally correct
argument.79 (I should emphasize that the main point here does not depend on this last
claim. The point is simply that the justificatory work, in Brewer's account, is done by
the fact that we are dealing with a content which is endorsed merely on the basis of
grasping it and not by the fact that arguments of the form 'p; therefore/?' are valid).
Does Brewer have any other general reason for holding that whatever constitutes a
reason for accepting a certain proposition (or for any other attitude towards it) must
involve entertaining a proposition the grasp of which involves grasp of an inferential
link between the two propositions (either a link which is due to formal relations between
the propositions or one which is due to relations between the particular concepts from
which the 'premise proposition' is composed)? In other words, the question is whether
Brewer has a general argument showing that there is no way in which being in one
mental state puts the subject in a position to recognize its implication for how he should
evaluate his thoughts other than the state's involving grasp of a proposition which he
recognizes as having relevant implications. Now, the discussion on pp. 166-8 is
79
Note that in this example each of the propositions is such that merely grasping it does not give the
subject a reason to endorse it. Thus, one cannot suggest that there is an implicit additional inference from
the premise to itself, or that actually the right to endorse the conclusion is due to the subject's grasp of its
content. It also seems wrong to suggest that entertaining the thought rthis belongs to John1 already
requires the subject to entertain the proposition rthis is in my visual field now1 which he then endorses
and infers from it the existential proposition.
71
presented as addressing this question, but in this discussion Brewer simply assumes that
in the case of states with non-propositional content
... mere possession of the mental state involved in having such a "reason" [in our case,
the experience] is explicitly insufficient for the subject's understanding of the proposition
whose association with this state grounds its putative status as his reason for doing what
he does. Hence any account of his essential recognition of his reason as such which
attempts to exploit the connection between understanding and knowledge of what follows
from what along the lines suggested above [i.e. the knowledge of what a proposition
entails which one has simply in virtue of understanding the proposition] is inapplicable,
(pp. 167-8)
I am not sure how to construe the assumption that there is a proposition whose
association with the subject's non-propositional mental state grounds its putative status
as his reason for doing what he does. However, if the thought is that recognizing a
reason as such must involve forming a relevant argument and therefore the subject must
relate the non-propositional mental state with a premise proposition if he is to recognize
it (the mental state) as his reason, then Brewer is simply presupposing here the claim for
which we are seeking an argument. Alternatively, if this is merely an expression of the
thought that the ability to articulate the a relevant argument whose premise is related to
the non-propositional state is necessary for the subject's recognition of this state as
providing him with a reason, then it was already argued that such a dependence is
consistent with the subject's recognizing that he is provided with the relevant reason
despite the state's content not being propositional. In this case, then, one does not have
to appeal to the connection between understanding a proposition and knowledge of what
it entails; for one assumes that the relevant non-propositional state is such that merely
being in it provides the subject with a grasp of its normative bearing on his thoughts.
Thus, once again, Brewer is simply assuming, rather than arguing, that:
... although conceptual contents are essentially grasped by their subject in precisely the
way which has evident relevance for their inferential powers which are in turn crucial to
sustain their status as reasons, non-conceptual contents are not. ... to categorize a state
as non-conceptual just is to deny that it is given to the subject in such a way as to provide
for the possibility of [the recognition of reasons as reasons] directly. 80
80 p. 168, my italics.
72
IV
The suggestion that experiential contents are only weakly-conceptual is a
suggestion that simply having a certain experience puts the subject in a state in which he
grasps the implications which the state has for his activities; specifically, for thought
evaluation, reasoning and planning. That is, he is presented with the world being a
certain way and, due to his primitive conception of the relation between his experiences
and the way things are, grasps that unless he has reasons for relevant doubts as to
whether the conditions are standard, things are likely to be as they are presented (where
it should be remembered that this conception is part of what is involved in his ability to
experience things; it is not some addition to his experiences which he may or may not
develop on the basis of them). If the claims made so far are correct, then Brewer has not
shown that this type of suggestion is unacceptable.
Is there some other basis for objecting to this weakly-conceptual suggestion? The
suggested view includes the assumption that the content is available to the subject in the
sense that he immediately grasps it as having a normative bearing on his mental and
practical activities. As mentioned at the end of Chapter 2, the justification for assuming
that contents that do not consist of a complex actualization of conceptual abilities can be
of this nature is that we have to view experiential contents in this way in order to have
an accurate and illuminating description of subjects' mental lives. Thus if one is to
question this suggestion (while accepting the general framework of thinking about
mental capacities), one should attempt to reject the arguments intended to show the need
to distinguish experiential capacities from conceptual ones.
So far I have suggested that the experience of aspects the subject is not currently
attending to (in the demanding sense) cannot involve the operation of a the relevant
demonstrative ability since without actually attending to the aspect the subject cannot be
ascribed knowledge of which particular aspect is in question. One may respond to this
73
in one of the following ways. Reject the requirement that an actualization of a
conceptual ability involves the subject's knowledge of which aspect is in question;
argue that the sense in which the subject is required to know which object is in question
is weaker than I have assumed; or deny that we actually experience unattended aspects.
The first two responses amount to construing talk about concepts in a different manner.
Whether there are advantages to a relevant alternative construal, and whether there is
room for arguing that it should be preferred to the construal I have been presupposing, is
beyond the scope of the current discussion. Note, however, that the strongconceptualists - McDowell and Brewer - would not choose any of these routes. I have
mentioned the implausibility and even the absurdity of the third objection, but shall
reconsider it in the next chapter.
The claim that the experience of unattended aspects is to be explained in terms of
experiential capacities which are distinct from conceptual abilities also bear on our
account of the experience of attended aspects. It seems that the experiential capacities
involved in the latter case are just the same as those involved in the former.
O 1
The
difference lies merely in the amount of visual input processed and the amount of
processing, due to the way the subject directs his attention. (There is, of course, a
further question of whether the subject's intentionally attending to an environmental
aspect can be distinguished from the actualization of a demonstrative ability, but this
does not bear on the question of which capacities are involved in making it the case that
the aspect is experienced the way it is). A clear manifestation of this is the fact
mentioned earlier that one may, for example, attend to an object without attending to
any particular property of it, while an object being experienced a certain way consists of
the experience of its properties (being organized in a certain way). In addition, the
discussion in Chapter 6 will help clarifying that we cannot account for the generality of
81 In Chapter 5 I shall mention a possible objection to this point and explain why it should not worry us.
74
a specific demonstrative ability if we identity the act of attending to the object
(whatever our view about the capacities in virtue of which the subject experiences the
object is) with the actualization of the demonstrative ability in question. (This is, in
effect, a way of spelling out the fact that the experience plays a role in explaining the
relevant demonstrative ability).
There are further differences between experiences and relevant attitudes to
propositions which might not, on their own, justify the distinction under discussion, but
the fact that they exist supports it. One such difference - related to the restriction of the
actualization of experiential capacities to one specific context (that of experience) - is
the fact that experiential contents as opposed to conceptual ones are not themselves
directly affected by other mental states (that is, not affected in virtue of the content of
those states). In addition, demonstrative abilities are the only conceptual abilities which
might have enabled accounting for things like the continuous nature of experiential
content, the special way in which such content can be unspecific and its particularity. (I
shall say more about these features in Chapter 5).
V
I have argued that Brewer did not show that the content of the experience must be
a proposition. It might, however, seem that Brewer and McDowell's line of argument
supports a weaker strong-conceptual claim: namely, that though the content of an
experience is not a matter of the actualization of demonstrative abilities, the relevant
demonstrative abilities - those which the experience gives rise to - must be appealed to
in the account of the experiential contents in question. Such a claim may seem a
consequent of accepting that the subject's recognition of the normative relation between
the experience and the relevant judgement requires that he be able to reflect on the
relation and thus that he be able to entertain thoughts with an embedded conceptual
75
content that captures the content of the experience (or relevant aspects of it). However,
such a claim is simply a more specific version of the claim considered at the end of
Chapter 2 (namely, that particular experiences depend on the particular potential to
think demonstratively about the experienced aspect, since the experience presupposes
the subject's ability to apply his general grasp of perception in the particular case in
question). Thus here as well the response is that the ability to reflect on the normative
relation, even though it involves an ability to entertain demonstrative thoughts about the
relevant aspects, is accountable in terms of the subject's general abilities to think
demonstratively about aspects he encounters. It would also help here to remember that
thinking about the ability to reflect on the relation as involving an articulation of an
argument (whose premise is a belief about the experience) and an evaluation of its
correctness is somewhat misleading. In effect, reflecting on the normative relation
involves applying any of the variety of ways in which one reasons about one's current
interaction with one's environment, and it is not always the case that the content of the
particular experience in question figures in this reasoning (furthermore, if the reflection
takes place a few seconds after the aspect disappeared from view it cannot figure in the
subject's reasoning).
76
4 Subject-level effects without conceptualization
I
In Chapter 2 I argued that the elements of experiential content which are due to
the subject's experience of a specific property he is not attending to (i.e., a property
from which he is not selecting information with the intention to restrict the selection
to this specific property alone) cannot be explained in terms of the demonstrative
ability this experience may give rise to. It was mentioned that the strong-conceptualist
may respond by denying that we experience unattended properties (or, assuming that
the claim applies to any unattended environmental aspect, generally denying that we
experience unattended environmental aspects). Intuitively, such a denial is
implausible. Not only do we take ourselves to experience aspects which are not
attended to in the demanding sense, but also we take the experience of such aspects to
play a role in the way we interact with our environment. First, it seems undeniable
that experiences of unattended aspects have a subject-level effect on the way we
direct our attention. For example, it seems undeniable that a subject glancing at a
group of people in front of him without attending to any one of them in particular, and
similarly not to any of their specific features, is in a position to form an intention to
attend to the person on the left and act accordingly because he experiences, say, the
person as being woman-like and all the rest as man-like. Further, it generally seems
that we direct various aspects of our actions according to the way things appear even
when it is implausible to suggest that we attend to all the relevant aspects. For
example, it seems that normally a subject who is walking towards a seen target will
direct his action according to the target's seen direction, though subjects do not
normally attend to the specific direction (or to a specific pattern of change of
direction) in such situations. It also seems that the experience of unattended aspects
can have a subject-level effect on the way we evaluate thoughts. Thus in the first
77
example, it seems that, prior to his shift of attention, the subject takes it to be likely
that there is a woman there (referring to a rough egocentric location), quite likely that
there is only one woman in the seen group, etc.
However, empirical data suggest that our intuitions as to what we experience as
well as to the effect of the experience on our reactions to the environment are quite
misguided. This might encourage a strong-conceptualist to accept the unintuitive view
that we do not experience unattended aspects. In fact, such data may encourage one to
hold that only prepositional content can figure in a subject-level explanation,
independently of a wish to establish that the content of experience must be
o^ _
conceptual. Furthermore, one should note that the strong-conceptualist may favour
such a view even if he agrees that there is no general conclusive argument for the
view that only conceptualized contents may have subject-level effects, for he may
prefer it to the alternative - namely, allowing that prepositional contents are not the
only contents which a subject can grasp as having a normative bearing on his
activities - for the sake of parsimony (or for some other reason I have been missing).
In response I shall suggest: (i) that the relevant empirical data are consistent
with holding that we experience unattended aspects and that such experiences have a
subject-level effect on our activities, and (ii) that an interaction with the environment,
where only experiences of aspects which are attended to in the demanding sense have
a subject-level effect on the subject's activities would be very different from the way
in which normal subjects, in fact, interact with the environment. I shall first briefly
present the line of thought in virtue of which the relevant data may seem to support
82 Campbell's view in his 2002 may be an example. On Campbell's view the actualization of the relevant
demonstrative abilities is not part of what constitutes the content of the experience; rather the experience
contributes to the subject-level effect by providing the subject with knowledge of which thing is
experienced and thus with the ability to entertain demonstrative thoughts about it. Whether or not Campbell
would say that experience does not have any direct subject-level effects is not clear. I shall say more about
this in Chapter 7.
78
the view that the experience of unattended aspects has no subject-level effect on
subjects' visually-guided spatial actions. (I focus on visually-guided action, since in
this case the relevant line of thought is clearest and seems most persuasive). I shall
then, without denying any of the hypotheses suggested by the relevant data, provide
an example of a case in which I argue that experiences of unattended aspects do have
such an effect. The example will demonstrate, in general, the type of role the
experience of unattended aspects can play; where it is undeniable the we often do, in
our interaction with the environment, rely on such experiences in the suggested way.
One may wonder why I do not discuss directly the question of whether the data
which show that we experience less than we take ourselves to can support the view
that we do not experience unattended aspects. There are a number of reasons for this.
The current data are not sufficient for providing a general picture of the relation
between what we take to be our current experience and the current visual information
which is in fact available to us. Furthermore, as far as I know, at present,
psychologists do not distinguish attention in the demanding sense from various
weaker senses in which a seen aspect may be attended to, and they would not take the
data to suggest a picture on which we experience only aspects which are attended in
the demanding sense. Thus an attempt to present a line of thought which the strongconceptualist may follow will require a detailed discussion of various highly
speculative (and complex) possibilities. (In Chapter 5 I shall mention one suggestion
as to why and how it might be generally the case that what we take to be the
experience of unattended aspects is not genuine experience, and shall clarify what is
wrong with this suggestion). In addition, by directly showing that our experience of
unattended aspects plays a role in explaining the way we in fact interact with our
environment, we have further direct support for the need to allow for nonconceptualized contents to have such effects. This would help quieting those who
79
have doubts regarding the way I have argued for the relation between a subject's
experiencing things a certain way and the possibility of the experience's having a
subject-level effect on his activities.
II
Intuitively, then, it seems that when we do things like reaching out with our
hand to pick up a seen object our action is guided by our experience: by the apparent
direction, distance, shape and orientation of the object, by whether or not we see that
the route is clear, and so on. However, empirical evidence suggests that some of the
visual information which guides and controls action is processed separately from the
visual information available to the subject in experience. Thus, for example, when a
visual form agnosia patient, who cannot see in which way a slot in front of her is
oriented, is asked to insert her hand into the slot, she does this exactly like normal
subjects: she orients her hand correctly right from the start of her reaching movement.
Or in the case of normal subjects, it has been shown that certain visual illusions do not
affect the way a subject acts; for example, subjects who are asked to pick up discs
which are similar in size but appear different or appear similar in size while they are
different, scale their grip aperture during the reaching movement according to the
actual size of the disc rather than the apparent size.
OT
This is not sufficient for suggesting that there are no aspects of visually-guided
actions which depend on the way things are experienced. For the discrepancies
between information for experience and information for action of the type mentioned
above are limited to particular types of connections between vision and action; for
83 Milner and Goodale 1995.1 am simplifying here. There are minor differences in the size of the grip
aperture which may be interpreted as an influence of the illusion. There are, however, alternative
explanations (see Haffenden and Goodale 2000), and, in any case, for present purposes it is sufficient that
there is a systematic tendency of the grip aperture's size to correspond with the disc's actual size.
80
example, they occur only in particular types of actions such as simple cases of
reaching out with one's hand and grasping simple-shaped objects,84 and only when
the delay between seeing the target and initiating the action is shorter than two
seconds. 85
However, the lack of discrepancies does not yet mean that the effect of the
relevant information on object-directed actions depends on the information being
available to the subject in experience. It may simply be a result of the contingent fact
that the information which is used for the sub-personal control and guidance of the
relevant aspects of action is processed by the same mechanisms which determine how
things are experientially presented to the subject; so that, in principle, it could have
happened that something has gone wrong and the information, though processed, has
not been made available to the subject in experience, without this having an effect on
how the subject performs (or is disposed to perform) the relevant visually-guided
actions. In fact, it seems quite plausible that this is often the way things are. There is
evidence showing that subjects respond to relevant changes in the environment by
adjusting their behaviour much quicker than they report awareness of the change, 86
and that generally information is available for affecting processes at the sub-personal-
84 Examples of more complex types of visually-guided action which require information processed by the
ventral stream are cases in which the action is partly shaped by the subject's taking the object to have
relatively sophisticated affordances, such as the affordances certain tools have for us (e.g., Carey et al.
1996). Another type of example is a case in which the subject is required to orient her hand in relation to a
T-shape target, a target more complex than a simple slot (see Milner and Goodale 1995 pp.138-9). Milner
and Goodale (pp. 139-40) also mention that information processed by the ventral stream is also needed
when actions are guided by cues which require organization according to certain gestalt organization
principles (similarity and good continuity).
85 See, for example, Rossetti 1998 pp.527-9,541-7, and Milner and Goodale 1995 pp. 136-7.
86 See Jeannerod 1997 pp.84-6. It may be objected that the experiments reported by Jeannerod concern
cases in which the information guiding the action is assumed to be processed in the dorsal stream, and thus
do not support the claim in the text. However, Jeannerod stresses that the two visual streams affect action
directly (1997 pp.66-7), and mentions the general consideration I mention in the next sentence in the text in
a discussion of reactions to categorized information (Gallagher and Jeannerod 2002). Also, there does not
seem to be a significant difference in our ability to adjust our actions between reaching out towards a
simple shape and reaching out towards a T-shape, or between picking up a knife and picking up a simple
straight stick (where, as mentioned in footnote 84, the second in each pair is a case in which information
processed in the ventral stream is involved in guiding the action); of course, it is an empirical question
whether there is a relevant difference.
81
level prior to the subject's awareness. 87 If, generally, the direct control of action is
quicker than control mediated by the subject's awareness of the information, then it is
reasonable to assume that, in the various cases in which actions require a rapid update
of information, visual information is available for the control of the action
independently of its availability to the subject in experience.
In fact, it is tempting to go a step further and assume that, since the relevant
sub-personal processing of the information as well as the sub-personal processing
underlying the reaction must be present anyway, a direct effect of the information is
normally possible. It is then tempting to think that the explanation of the fact that
actions of the subject are controlled by visual information is wholly sub-personal,
unless it is clear that his view as to what is appropriate to do, given the way things are
presented to him in experience, is part of what explains certain changes in his course
of action, or part of what explains the fact that he does not change his course of
action. Given this view, a strong-conceptualist may go on to argue that all cases in
which the experience of unattended aspects seems to play a role in explaining the
subject's action are illusory: the effect of the information is, in fact, wholly subpersonal.
Note that a similar suggestion can be made in relation to mental activities such
as the evaluation of a thought. There seems to be evidence that sub-personal structures
which underlie the subject's conceptual capacities can be activated by visual
information in the absence of a corresponding experience. Such effects, it may seem,
are what is manifested when Hindsight patients manage to make accurate guesses in a
frequency of above chance, or in the effects of masked visual cues on normal
subjects' performance in tasks like word recognition and word completion where the
87 See, for example, Libet 1993.
82
cues are related to the words by meaning (rather than shape or other physical
properties of the relevant words). It is reasonable that such effects take place regularly
(whether or not the relevant information is available to the subject in experiences),
and thus the strong-conceptualist may suggest that such effects are responsible for the
effects of visual information on the subject's mental activity when the experienced
aspect is not attended to. Of course, much more has to be said in order to defend the
plausibility of the suggestion in this case; this brief comment is only meant to clarify
that a strong-conceptualist can at least attempt to use the same strategy in all types of
cases in which it seems that the experience of unattended aspects has a rational effect
on the subject's practical and mental activity.
Ill
The step I have mentioned in the penultimate paragraph - concluding that, apart
from cases in which the subject's view as to what is appropriate to do (practically or
mentally), given the way things are presented to him in experience, is causally
relevant to the way he acts, effects of visual information on the subject's course of
action are direct (i.e., independent of whether the information is available to the
subject in experience) - seems to me reasonable and, at least for the sake of the
argument, I shall accept it. The question, then, is whether a strong-conceptualist can
argue that all cases in which the experience of unattended aspects seems to play a role
in explaining the subject's action are illusory (that is, that the effect of the information
is wholly sub-personal).
In order to make clear that the empirical data do not force us to accept that such
cases are illusory, I shall describe (in a somewhat rough manner) an example of a case
in which the subject's action are directly guided by relevant visual information and in
addition the subject's view as to the appropriateness of the relevant aspects of the
83
action, due to his experience of certain unattended aspects, is causally relevant to the
fact that he acts as he does. Furthermore, I shall argue that it is implausible to suggest
that the alleged causal relevance of the experience (due to its effect on the subject's
view) must be illusory, and similarly implausible to suggest that in the discussed case
the subject is actually attending to a relevant environmental aspect. As the example
seems to represent an important aspect of the way in which we in fact interact with
our environment, I shall take this to show the implausibility of suggesting that as a
matter of fact only aspects which are attended to in the demanding sense have a
subject-level effect on our actions.
Consider the following example. Suppose a subject S sees a certain person X
walking away from him, and while attending (in the demanding sense) to X but not to
any other aspect of the environment he thinks 'I shall catch this person' and acts
accordingly. His seeing X bears on his action in virtue of the fact that he attends to X
and this enables him to think demonstratively about the object he intends to catch.
Now, suppose that the effect the information regarding X's (changing) direction and
distance has at the sub-personal-level could suffice for guiding the direction and speed
of his movements, in a way which would enable him to catch X in a certain range of
circumstances. Furthermore, suppose that S's current movement is such that had he
seen X but lacked the relevant experiential information regarding the direction and
distance of X, then, at least in principle, he could have moved as he is actually
moving during an attempt to catch X. It may seem that once we add this last
supposition we should admit that the direction and distance of S's movement are
explained by the operation of the relevant sub-personal visuomotor mechanisms
alone: the fact that in addition information about these aspects is available to S in
experience has no role to play in the explanation. I wish to argue, in contrast, that one
can accept that the operation of the sub-personal mechanisms could have (in
84
principle) sufficed for explaining the actual course of S's action and still hold that S's
experience of X's direction and distance is causally relevant to the fact that, in the
particular situation in question, S directs his action in this particular way. (I should
emphasize that my descriptions of the aspects which are relevant to guiding the action
and of the way they affect it are only meant as rough pointers which must be refined
and perhaps replaced).
The suggestion is that S's visual experience of the relevant aspects (i.e., X's
changing location relative to himself and the speed at which the distance between
them changes) could be causally relevant to the fact that S follows the course of
action he does (i.e., that he moves through the particular path he does in the particular
(changing) speed he does) in virtue of its playing a role in S's monitoring and
controlling the way he acts. S can see whether or not he is moving in a direction
which will enable him to catch X, whether or not he is moving closer to X, etc. If he
sees that he is moving in the wrong direction, or not getting any closer to X, he will be
made aware of the fact that his action is not performed in the appropriate way (given
his intention). If there are no (external or internal) barriers, he will simply change his
course of action: change direction, speed up or give up his attempt. If so, then it is
also the case that, when S is monitoring his action, seeing that he is moving in the
right direction and getting closer to X, is causally relevant to his continuing to act the
way he does. For he will continue acting in this way, other things being equal, only as
long as he takes his movement to be in a direction appropriate for catching X and only
as long as the seen distance between X and himself seems to him to decrease or to be
such that he can make it decrease.
So, in general, the suggestion is that the experience of an unattended aspect can
play a role in a subject-level explanation of the way in which the action is performed,
in virtue of its revealing to the subject whether his action is performed in a manner
85
which is appropriate for carrying out his intention. Since the subject's continuing to
act the way he does or changing his course of action is then dependent on the way
things are experienced by him, that things are experienced in the way which, from his
point of view, makes the action appropriate is causally relevant to his acting in this
way (even if in principle he could have, in the particular case in question, followed
exactly the same course of action without the subject-level monitoring of the action).
Of course, this can apply only to actions which the subject is able to control
during their performance. The first condition is that it should be a non-ballistic action.
Secondly, since there is also sub-personal monitoring and control of visually-guided
actions, it should be possible for the subject-level monitoring and control to make
some difference to the action. I shall take it for granted that this is the case for any
non-ballistic action, since it is always possible that the adjustment required according
to current visual information in order to continue carrying out the relevant action does
not accord with some more general intention of the subject.
In addition, we should remember that often actions which the subject could
control are performed without his monitoring. A subject who reaches out towards the
glass in front of him in order to pick it up might just reach out without continuing to
look in its direction after the initiation of the reaching movement. And even if he
continues to look in the direction of the glass, and his reaching movement is in fact
guided by visual information from the glass, this can take place without the subject's
paying any further attention (in a broad sense) to the glass or to the movement of his
hand. However, there seem to be circumstances in which subjects do monitor their
actions, and are constantly ready to change their course of action if their experience
makes them aware of a need to do so. This seems to be the case, for example, when a
subject takes himself to be unskilled in performing the task, takes it that the object is
changing or likely to change location in unforeseeable ways, takes the task to be
86
dangerous, and so on. More generally, it seems that subjects can and do monitor their
visually-guided actions when their grasp of the situation and of their own abilities is
such that we can say (assuming that part of our grasp of our own capacities involves
indirect reference to relevant sub-personal mechanisms88) that they take it that the
sub-personal mechanisms might not suffice for controlling the action, or when the
control at the sub-personal-level might not yield the most efficient or safest way of
acting. 89
Suppose, then, that S has such an attitude towards his following X (suppose that
he has to weave his way through a crowd of active children; thus he is in a situation in
which it is not difficult for him to visually keep track of X, and the only problem is to
keep moving in an appropriate direction and speed), and that consequently he is in
fact continuously monitoring the relevant aspects of his action, ready to change his
course of action if he sees that he is moving in a direction or speed which are
inappropriate for catching X. In such a case the fact, say, that X appears to S to be
moving in the direction in which he himself is moving and the distance between them
appears to gradually decrease is causally relevant to the fact that S acts the way he
does: had his experience been different in relevant ways, he would have changed his
course of action accordingly. (Note also that it is most likely that a normal subject
would change his course of action if somehow the change in his experience was such
that, though still seeing X, he was no longer able to see X's location in relation to
himself).
I am focusing on the situation in which the experience does not reveal any
deficiencies in the current course of action, since it seems implausible to suggest that
88 That subjects implicitly take the sub-personal activity into account is manifested in things like how they
explain mistakes or reason about possible mistakes, etc. (the idea that subjects implicitly take the subpersonal activity into account is expressed in Eilan 1998 pp. 188-9 and manuscript).
89 Jeannerod (2003) mentions that subjects shift to conscious strategies when the discrepancies between
action and feedback become quite large, and points out that the efficiency of such shifts is manifested by a
comparison between normal subjects and patients who cannot shift to conscious strategies.
87
in such cases subjects normally attend to the specific fine-grained properties or
relations relevant to explaining their course of action. Thus, for example it seems
implausible to suggest that S, while chasing X and monitoring his action, attends to
the specific directions of X relative to himself or the specific patterns of change of the
relative direction. We can agree that he, generally, attends to X's direction in relation
to himself whichever direction it is and whichever way it changes; for he is selectively
sensitive to information regarding the relative direction. But as was made clear in
Chapter 2, this is not sufficient for him to have the ability to predicate any of the
specific directions or patterns of direction which are relevant to his monitoring. Thus
such cases are clear examples of the experience of unattended aspects playing a role
in explaining the way the subject acts, despite the unavailability of a demonstrative
content which according to the strong-conceptualist must be present for the
experience to play such a role. (In contrast, it is at least open to one to argue that,
when the subject changes his course of action due to the experience of a specific
aspect, he also attends to that aspect in the required way. That is, I do not think that
this must be the case, but prefer to focus on what seems an indisputable case).
Now, the opponent might suggest that what I am describing as S's monitoring is
not really a case of S's being sensitive to the experienced aspects in virtue of his
experiencing them, but rather a result of a change in the range of stimuli to which the
sub-personal mechanisms that control automatic shifts of attention are sensitive. A
crude example of what is suggested is that if, when the subject acts without any
intention to monitor a given action, his attention will be automatically captured only
by sudden (large enough) changes, then when the subject performs the action with
relevant intentions, the relevant sub-personal mechanisms are tuned to respond to
additional types of changes. (Note that on this picture there is a subject-level element
in determining how the action is monitored: the suggested type of change is due to the
subject's notion of what the task is. What is denied is only that the fact that the subject
shifts his attention at a certain time towards a certain stimuli is itself a subject-level
reaction to his experience of the relevant stimuli).
It is, of course, an empirical question whether it is possible to account in this
way for all cases in which subjects manifest sensitivity to characteristics of their
environment which would not draw their attention without the intention to monitor
their action. But it seems rather unlikely that, in all cases in which we take ourselves
to be monitoring our actions (without attending to a specific property or relation),
there is a specific set of parameters (associated with a certain general attitude of the
subject towards the current situation) which can account for the fact that the subject is
selectively sensitive to those aspects of the situations to which he is, in fact,
selectively sensitive. Situations of the kind described above seem to make this clear.
For it seems that in this case there just is no specific type (or set of types) of stimuli
which can be determined in advance as the only relevant stimuli (e.g., there seems to
be no fixed set of patterns of stimuli that corresponds to exactly the type of visual
information which S is likely to view as requiring a change in his course of action
(and which he would normally be sensitive to in the type of situation in question). To
give some crude examples: a sudden shift in X's direction of movement may
sometimes, but not always, be regarded by the subject as requiring a change in his
course of action; similarly, moving in a different direction than that in which X is
moving may be the appropriate thing to do but might as well not). If so, it cannot be
that the explanation is due to the tuning of sub-personal mechanisms to be sensitive
only to stimuli of the relevant type.
Note also that a related role is also played by experience in forming an initial
intention to perform a certain action. For example, a subject who cannot see where an
object is located, or to whom the object appears (veridically or not) to be quite distant
89
and rapidly moving farther away from him will not form the initial intention to catch
it by following it on foot.90 It does not seem that one can explain such effects in terms
of relevant sub-personal mechanisms being tuned differently; whereas suggesting that
in all such cases the subject attends to all the relevant specific aspects of the situations
seems implausible.
IV
It may seem inconsistent to claim that S is monitoring whether he is moving in
an appropriate direction given the direction of X in relation to himself and also that he
need not know which specific direction (or pattern of change in direction) is in
question. But remember that it is only denied that he has to single out a specific
direction (or pattern of change in direction) by visually attending to it, and thus it is
only denied that he should know what it is, generally, for something to be located in
that specific direction (or to be changing direction in that specific way) rather than
any other. The knowledge of which direction is in question in this sense is not what
explains the normative bearing which, prima facie, a subject takes a given experience
to have on the way he acts (and on his prepositional attitudes in general). Specific
variations in the normative bearing the subject takes the experience to have are due to
the way the relevant experienced aspects currently appear to him. It was argued in
Chapter 2 that a plausible view of demonstrative abilities must allow for the
possibility that the subject knows which property is in question while the property is
currently presented in his experience in a misleading way. Thus even if S was
attending to a specific direction - and in this sense said to know which direction is in
90 One should not compare here normal subjects with subjects who due to a brain lesion cannot see an
aspect which is relevant to deciding on the appropriate course of action. As far as I understand such brain
damaged patients are at first unwilling to initiate relevant visually-guided actions and would act only on the
psychologist's request or unintentionally. They may consequently learn that they have the ability to
perform the action even when they cannot see (at least not directly) whether they are in a position to do so,
and might then, in certain circumstances, perform the relevant actions intentionally.
90
question - he could have been misled about the appropriate way to act when X is in
the attended direction. Since, generally, he takes such possibilities into account and in
certain circumstances may doubt the veridicality of the experience, it is possible for
him to know which direction is in question in the discussed sense but still not be sure
as to what he takes to be the appropriate way to move in order to catch X.
It might be suggested that, although the relevant knowledge is not sufficient for
explaining the immediate normative bearing, from the subject's point of view, of a
particular experience on his thoughts and actions, it is necessary for explaining this.
However, it should be remembered that such knowledge requires that S attend to a
specific direction or pattern of change in direction rather than others, while it seems
that all that can be required is his attention to the actual changing direction of X in
relation to himself whatever it is and -whichever ways it changes. Specifically, there is
no reason why S should have an interest in singling out a specific direction or pattern
of change, and it is quite unlikely that normally in such a situation subjects actually do
this. Furthermore, in the discussed example it is clear that S's monitoring the
appropriateness of his action only requires him to be sensitive to things like whether
he is, more or less, moving in the same direction as X, the general direction in which
he should turn if he is not, etc.
At this point the opponent might agree that S, when monitoring his action, need
not attend to any of the relevant spatial relations with the intention to single out a
specific fine-grained spatial relation, but suggest that S has an intention to single out a
certain rough spatial relation (e.g., more or less the direction in which X is moving).
But this seems wrong. To begin with, S's general interest is to monitor the
appropriateness of his movement in relation to X, and this does not imply an attempt
to keep moving in a way which preserves one coarsely defined pattern of changing
directions between himself and X, or a disjunction of a number of such patterns. That
91
is, it seems that,/row S's point of view in the given situation, the range of patterns
which he would regard as appropriate is not distinguished in a general manner from
all patterns which he would regard as inappropriate. Suppose, however, for the sake of
the argument, that there is such a roughly specified pattern. There is no reason, in the
standard case, to ascribe to S an interest in singling out a specific spatial relation (e.g.,
the relevant rough pattern of changing direction) which he knows what it is for it to
hold between any two suitable objects. His aim is simply to determine whether his
current way of acting is appropriate or not (for him in the current situation); he is not,
presently, concerned with evaluating the appropriateness of the same pattern of
movement to other situations (e.g. those in which the chased object is not X, the
chaser is not himself, etc.).
To clarify, it is not claimed that S does not take his current action to be,
generally, appropriate (or inappropriate) to fulfilling the type of intention he currently
has in situations which are exactly like the present one except for the identity of the
chaser and the chased thing. Neither is it denied that his general grasp of his relation
to the environment enables him, when the question arises, to reflect on the extent to
which the (in)appropriateness of his action, in the given situation, depends on
conditions which relate to his current physical state, to how interested he is in
catching X, X's physical state, the layout of the environment, and so on. Rather the
claim is that S's monitoring the action in the above example does not involve a
current interest in the relevant generalizable aspects of the situation as such. That is, it
does not involve an interest in the aspects which make his current way of acting
(in)appropriate to a specific range of situations and not others, where he can currently
be ascribed a knowledge of which range is in question.
We can clarify the point by considering the possibility of saying that from the
subject's point of view what defines the relevant range of spatial relations is that they
92
all have the same affordance for the subject. Now the relevant affordance might be
individuated in relation to the subject's current state whatever exactly this state is.
Alternatively it can be individuated in relation to certain parameters regarding the
subject's state (so that once they change, a different affordance would be required for
recommending the action for him). It seems that if we wish to express the way things
are viewed from the subject's point of view, then, to a certain extent, we must ignore
changes in the subject's state; while if the subject is to single out a specific
generalizable relation these specific details regarding the subject's state should play a
role in the individuation of the affordance.
V
I have tried to show that not only do the empirical data not support the claim
that the experience of unattended aspects play no role in explaining the subject's
actions, but also that the interaction with the environment of a person who is never
sensitive in his action to such experiences is rather different than ours. That is, if we
do not allow for subject-level effects of the experience of unattended aspects, we rule
out the possibility of the subject's monitoring what goes on with aspects of the
situation which are not specifically selected by him, continuously noting which
possibilities are open to him and to what extent the changes in the environment
require a change in his course of action. It seems equally clear that monitoring and
general alertness to various aspects of unattended parts of the visual field play an
important role in the way we evaluate thoughts.
It should however be remembered that the argument rests on certain
assumptions regarding empirical matters. Specifically, it was assumed that, given the
type of situations which we can in fact monitor and the type of things we can
consequently be sensitive to, it is implausible to assume that all such cases can be
93
explained in terms of the operations of sub-personal mechanisms alone. The
vulnerability of this assumption is due not only to the possibility of being mistaken as
to what a complex sub-personal mechanism may in fact explain, but also due to the
fact that one's intuitions as to what one can in fact be sensitive to in the relevant
situations may be misleading. However, noting this possibility, I shall continue to
assume that it is unlikely that we can explain in sub-personal terms what seem to be
the actual subject-level effects that the experiences of unattended aspects have on our
activities. Thus I conclude that, pending further data, there is no empirical support for
denying the need to allow for non-propositional contents which are immediately
grasped by the subject as having certain implications to his thoughts and actions.
94
5 The middle position
I
I have been concerned with the question of how the notion of experiential
content should be construed if it is to play a role in explaining our ability to think
demonstratively about objects. Specifically, I focused on whether the relevant notion
is such that one must appeal to the subject's conceptual abilities in order to account
for a specific experiential content (i.e., for what it is for a specific experience to have
the specific content it does rather than others), and if so, whether an account of the
content of a specific experience requires an appeal to the specific demonstrative
ability this experience is supposed to explain. It was argued that one cannot dispense
with an appeal to the subject's conceptual abilities (thus rejecting strong-nonconceptual views), but that there is no need to appeal to the particular demonstrative
abilities the particular experience gives rise to (thus rejecting the only acceptable
strong-conceptual position regarding the account of particular experiences). I shall
first summarize the main points made against the two strong views (section II) and
what the suggested alternative is (section III). In sections IV and V I shall clarify
some points regarding the specification of the content of a particular experience.
II
An experience of an object enables the subject to single out the object and
entertain demonstrative thoughts about it in virtue of its (the experience) presenting
the object to the subject, providing him with information from the object. Thus the
notion of experiential content relevant to the account of demonstratives is that of what
is presented to the subject in experience, where this includes the particular
environmental aspects presented and the way they are presented as being. That an
environmental aspect is presented to the subject in experience as being a certain way
95
means that the aspects' being experienced this way is part of what constitutes the
subject's current view of the way things are. It follows from this that there is a certain
type of link between an experience of a concept-possessor and his conceptual abilities
which marks the difference between his conscious and non-conscious perceptual
states: when certain environmental aspects are presented to him in experience as being
a certain way, this fact could, generally, have a direct (i.e., not mediated by some
further registration), subject-level effect on the way he is disposed to evaluate
thoughts, reason and make plans.
It was argued that, in the case of concept-possessors, one cannot account for the
content of a conscious perceptual state - that is, a content that can be linked with the
subject's concept-applying activities in the above way - if one does not presuppose
that the content is of the type which is linked with the subject's conceptual abilities in
the relevant way. Specifically, it was pointed out that it is insufficient to provide an
account of a corresponding content which can be ascribed to some aspect of the
experiential state in virtue of the representational role it (the relevant aspect) plays at
the sub-personal-level (or any other suggested level that is not the subject-level).
What has to be presupposed, then, are the links between experiences and conceptual
abilities in virtue of which a concept-possessor is ascribed a point of view, and in
virtue of which his experiences are part of this point of view.
It was also argued that we should reject a weaker version of the strong-nonconceptual view according to which one can account for specific experiential contents
without a specific appeal to the subject's conceptual abilities, if one assumes, as a
general background assumption, that experiences are linked with conceptual abilities
in the relevant way. The claim was that what we have to explain is the particular
significance the experience has for the subject, a significance which is manifested in
what the subject takes to be the implications that things being as they are presented in
96
experience (as opposed to others) has for his thoughts and actions. But here again,
aspects of the subject's current experience which are independent of links with his
conceptual abilities cannot explain the fact that from his point of view the experience
is viewed as presenting him with things being a certain way.
I then argued that one cannot, generally, construe the content of a particular
experience in terms of the actualization of particular demonstrative abilities. It was
argued that if the subject is to know which particular fine-grained property he is
currently experiencing - knowledge without which the subject is not in a position to
predicate the property, in thought, in virtue of demonstrating the seen property - he
has to attend to a specific fine-grained property in the following sense. He has to
select information from the property with the intention to select information from the
relevant seen fine-grained property (thus, an intention to select information for the
relevant task only as long as the property does not change). Clearly, we do not often
attend in this demanding sense to seen fine-grained properties; we do not often intend
to restrict the selection of information to the specific fine-grained property, ruling out
any information which would be available after the occurrence of a change which is
detectable in standard conditions. Thus one should either accept that fine-grained
properties can be experienced even though the subject is not in a position to predicate
the property in virtue of demonstrating it, or deny that we experience fine-grained
properties while not attending to them (in the demanding sense). The latter option is
extremely unintuitive and seems to lead to absurdities. Thus it seems that at least the
experience of fine-grained properties, when they are unattended, is not accountable in
terms of the actualization of demonstrative abilities. The same consideration applies
to properties in general (where I use properties to refer also to the relations in which a
thing stands to other things), and it seems that a similar consideration also applies to
other environmental aspects such as objects. (Although I have not argued for the latter
97
claim, for convenience's sake, I treat the claim as applying to environmental aspects
in general).
A strong-conceptualist may be drawn to deny that we experience unattended
aspects (and attempt some solution to what appears to be absurd results) if he is
persuaded by a general, a priori argument that experiential contents must be,
generally, accountable in terms of the actualization of demonstrative abilities. In
addition, he might be encouraged to do so by empirical data showing that our
intuitions regarding the experience of unattended environmental aspects are
misleading. The general argument offered by strong-conceptualists purports to show
that only contentful states which are a result of the actualization of conceptual abilities
can be viewed by the subject as having a normative bearing on his thinking. I argued
that the argument is unconvincing. I then went on to argue that one cannot take the
relevant empirical data to show that, as a matter of fact, there are no aspects of our
experience which cannot be construed in terms of the actualization of demonstrative
abilities. It was argued that the experience of unattended aspects plays a role in the
way we, as a matter of fact, monitor our actions, and generally monitor what goes on
in our visual field, and that these claims are consistent with the empirical data. It
should however be remembered that the argument relies on empirical assumptions
which I took to be plausible but which might be found to be mistaken.
In addition, it was clarified that there is no basis for a strong-conceptualist to
argue that the content of the experience of unattended aspects should be explained in
terms the (non-actualized) particular demonstrative abilities which could be actualized
if the subject attended to the aspect in question.
98
Ill
As an alternative to the two strong views, I suggested that we view experiences
as involving the actualization of capacities which are interlinked with conceptual
capacities but differ from them in significant respects. The content of a particular
experience (i.e., particular environmental aspects being experienced a certain way), on
this suggestion, involves the actualization of various experiential capacities - the
subject's capacity to visually distinguish shades of colour, shapes, etc., his capacity to
visually detect certain relations between them, to visually distinguish objects, to
visually recognize colours, shapes, patterns, and so on - when the subject is in fact
encountering the particular environmental aspects in question. The experiential
capacities are said to be interlinked with the subject's conceptual abilities in that it is
taken for granted that, when they are actualized with relation to a particular
environmental aspect, the result is that the particular aspect is experienced a certain
way (say, as being circular rather than any other shape, larger than the object on its
left, etc.) - where this is immediately grasped by the subject as standing in certain
normative relations to his thoughts and actions. That is, the mechanisms in virtue of
which the subject is said to have these capacities are not just sub-personal
information-processing mechanisms which produce certain sub-personal states, but
rather mechanisms which produce conscious states; states whose content is grasped by
the subject as standing in certain normative relations to his thoughts and actions.
In this respect experiential capacities resemble conceptual capacities. They
differ from them, however, at least in the following two (related) respects. First,
conceptual abilities must be general in the sense that their actualization is not
restricted to a fixed set of propositions and to a fixed set of contexts (by which I mean
different propositional attitudes). Experiential capacities, in contrast, are actualized
only in the context of an experience. (It might be that a better way to say this is to say
99
that there is a sense in which having an experience with a certain content is not an
attitude towards that content (though it will always be accompanied by some
attitude)). Secondly, in contrast to conceptual capacities, the actualization of
experiential capacities does not result in states with prepositional content: the content
of the resulting state or any particular aspect of it is not a result of the joint
actualization of two experiential capacities one singling out a subject and the other
predicating a certain property of it.91 I shall not attempt to identify general principles
which characterize the relation between the actualization of the various capacities and
a given experiential content. I shall only mention that I presented experiential
capacities as general capacities which, when actualized in relation to particular
environmental aspects, yield an experience of these particular aspects as being a
certain way. Given that the subject has the relevant capacities (where this implies that
he has a general grasp of the relation between cases in which they are actualized and
the way things are in the given situation), the fact that they are actualized does not
depend on any further specific grasp the subject has of the particular experienced
aspects. This allows for the difference from propositional contents emphasized in the
discussion in Chapter 2: the fact that a subject need not know which object and
property are in question in order to experience them, while such knowledge is
required if he is to be ascribed the relevant demonstrative abilities. This also clarifies
that the sense in which experiential capacities might be viewed as not restricted to a
fixed set of contents is completely different from the sense in which conceptual
abilities are not restricted to a fixed set of propositions. The restrictions on the way
91 If experiential contents had had propositional content, the relevant propositions would have been
subject-predicate ones.
100
such capacities can be combined is simply a matter of the way the relevant
information-processing mechanisms operate.92
Now, according to this suggestion, the fact that the actualization of such
capacities can yield conscious states should simply be taken as primitive; specifically
we should regard as primitive the fact that what the operation of the relevant
mechanisms contribute to the subject's perceptual state, in appropriate conditions, is
that from the subject's point of view the relevant environmental aspects are presented
as being a certain way. Of course, there is room for asking what type of place such a
state occupies in the subject's primitive conception; thus examining which other
abilities the subject should possess and what type of implications he should take the
relevant state to have for it to be the case that the experience presents a particular
aspect to him as being a certain way rather than others. Also, there is room for
discussing relations between different experiential capacities: the extent to which
some capacities may depend on others, etc. (both from the subject's point of view and,
independently of his point of view, in virtue of the relations between relevant
information-processing procedures). And generally, there are various questions
relating to the way in which the relevant information-processing mechanisms operate.
What has to be taken for granted is that we are speaking about conscious states whose
content explains the subject's grasp of the experience as having certain implications
for his thoughts and actions (rather than other implications).
I should clarify that I am not applying a double standard when accepting that
there is no explanation in simpler terms of what makes an experience the particular
experience it is, while complaining that the strong-conceptualists do not make room
92 1 should emphasize that I am rejecting the way Peacocke argues for the need to distinguish between
the capacities which are actualized in experience and conceptual abilities in his 1989. The difficulty he
discusses does not arise on the suggested view, since a particular experience of a property is partly
individuated in terms of the particular experienced instance.
101
for an explanation of particular demonstrative abilities in simpler terms. The
complaint against the strong-conceptualists is not based on a general requirement for
explanations in simpler terms. It arises in the context of clarifying the relations
between various subject-level phenomena (where it is generally agreed that such
phenomena depend on sub-personal phenomena but that the latter cannot account for
what makes the subject-level phenomena the subject-level phenomena they are93).
Within this framework, claims as to whether or not we should expect an explanation
of certain aspects in terms of more primitive mental phenomena are based, initially,
on our common-sense grasp of these phenomena, and then, where appropriate, on
theoretical considerations. Now, intuitively, we take it that experiences of particular
environmental aspects provide us with the ability to think about them
demonstratively. In contrast, there is no intuitive force to the claim that there are more
primitive subject-level phenomena which account for the fact that - given the way the
visual and cognitive systems of the subject operate, the way things actually are and
the relevant environmental conditions - things are experienced the way they are
(experienced). From our point of view, experiencing things a certain way is simply the
state we find ourselves in when the relevant systems are operating the way they do
and the world is the way it is. (This is not to deny that it often seems intuitive to
regard the fact that the subject has certain general concepts as relevant to his ability to
have certain experiences. Such intuitions, however, suggest only a general
dependence of experiential contents on the subject's conceptual abilities).
As for theoretical considerations, as mentioned above, I rejected the general
consideration, offered by the strong-conceptualists, for thinking that experience must
be construed in terms of the actualization of conceptual abilities, and argued that they
93 Though, this is not to say that sub-personal phenomena cannot be relevant to clarifying various
aspects of subject-level phenomena.
102
cannot maintain that, generally, experiential contents consist in the actualization of
demonstrative abilities. Furthermore, I argued that there is no basis for holding that it
is generally the case that we must, in some way, appeal to the specific demonstrative
abilities the experience gives rise to in order to account for its content.
Note also that anyone who holds that prepositional attitudes are not
epiphenomenal is in a similar position in relation to states in which conceptual
abilities are actualized. On such a view, the fact that the subject is aware of
implications of an occurrent conceptual state he is in and aware of the grounds he may
have for being in this state is regarded as indispensable for clarifying what it is for
someone to be in this state (rather than in a similar mental state with different
content). But we do not wish to say that the mere fact that the subject is disposed to
reason in the relevant ways (or more accurately, that his dispositions to reason are
affected in a particular way) constitutes the fact that he is exercising the relevant
conceptual abilities; rather we want to say that there is a sense in which his, say,
judging (or supposing, etc) that a is F (rather than, say, that a is G or that b is F) is
what explains the fact that he is now disposed to reason in one way rather than others
(in other words, his being in this state is supposed to be the ground of a certain
second-order disposition). As far as I can see, one has no choice but to regard as
primitive the fact that a given conceptual ability is such that when actualized (together
with other suitable conceptual abilities) the subject grasps a specific content; where
the fact that he grasps the content explains his grasp of how other states of his bear on
which attitude he should have towards the content and the implications he should
draw for his thoughts and actions, given his attitude towards it.
Thus the disagreement with the strong-conceptualist is about whether occurrent
conceptual states (that is, the states one is in when exercising specific conceptual
abilities) are the only states being in which explains the subject's grasp of relevant
103
implication for his concept-involving activities. I have suggested that the answer to
such a question depends on considerations as to whether an accurate and illuminating
description of our mental lives requires a distinction between experiential and
conceptual capacities. Thus I take the discussion of the role played by the experience
of unattended aspects and the claim that this role cannot be due to the actualization of
conceptual abilities to provide a strong motivation for allowing that there are two
types of capacities the actualization of which results in states whose content is
immediately grasped by the subject as having a normative bearing on his thoughts and
actions (which differ at least in the respects mentioned above).
IV
In the rest of the chapter I wish to clarify what I take to be the particular content
of a particular experience, and point at some of the limitations on our ability to
specify such contents accurately. I shall first present what seems the natural way of
distinguishing experiential contents and specifying what each content is. A discussion
of difficulties this suggestion encounters will point to what I take to be a more
accurate view of the specification of particular contents.
The content of an experience was said to be what is presented to the subject in
experience, where this includes both the particular experienced aspects (the particular
objects, collections of objects, instantiations of properties and relations, events, etc.,
from which the subject currently has experiential information) and the way they are
experienced by the subject (or the way they are presented or appear to him). 'The way
an aspect is presented', or more accurately, 'the way it is presented to the subject as
being', is a way the environmental aspect can actually be, and is supposed to capture
what the subject, simply in virtue of the fact that he has the experience, takes to be the
way the aspect is if his experience is veridical. Thus talk about the way an
104
environmental aspect is presented captures the aspect of the experience in virtue of
which we say that certain (veridical or non-veridical) information (rather than other
information) from the particular aspect is immediately available to the subject,
enabling him to direct and modify his thinking and acting accordingly (that is, he can
currently do so without any need for him first to perform an additional operation such
as an inference or a calculation). It is, in this sense, the ground of the experience's
specific potential to affect the way the subject performs tasks to which he takes
information from the aspect to be relevant.
When attempting to specify the particular way a certain environmental aspect is
presented to a subject in a particular experience, it is natural to appeal to the effect the
experience has on the subject's dispositions to evaluate thoughts whose truth depends
on the way things are with the relevant aspect when he has no relevant doubts
regarding the veridicality of his experience and is in fact sensitive to the relevant
experience94 (where the relevant judgements include judgements of similarity and
difference between the aspect and other seen and unseen aspects). This seems the
natural approach since the effect that taking the experience at face value has on the
way the subject evaluates such thoughts manifests what, from his point of view, is the
way the aspect is presented to him in his experience, and assuming that he is in fact
94 This qualification is required for ruling out cases in which the subject experiences things a certain
way but, due to some further non-visual effect, his current dispositions do not manifest the way things
are experienced by him. Such cases may occur, for example, when the subject reacts hastily with
minimal or no sensitivity to his actual experience, or when certain expectations or certain thoughts or
memories the subject is occupied with have a brute effect on the resulting activities. 1 am assuming
here, without further argument, a distinction between (i) cases that can be seen as involving factors
which affect the subject's disposition in addition to the effect of the way things actually appear to the
subject, and (ii) cases in which such factors affect the subject's dispositions in virtue of their effect on
the visual appearance. Such a distinction is based on the thought that visual appearance is the product
of the operation of the visual mechanisms (mechanisms whose function is to process current visualinformation), and that the products (or states) of other cognitive systems may affect the appearance by
affecting the operation of visual mechanisms, or alternatively interfere with the effect of the appearance
at some higher level. Note that it does not matter whether we can correctly detect cases of type (i), and
further, there need not be a clear-cut boundary between the two types of cases (for there need not be a
clear-cut boundary between visual and non-visual mechanisms). In what follows I shall assume that all
the cases discussed do not involve effects of type (i).
105
sensitive to the experience, this should also be the way things are, in fact, presented to
him in experience.95 Furthermore, one's own reflection on what one is disposed to
judge to be the case when taking the experience at face value is what enables one to
articulate how things appear to one to be.
It should be clear that if we appeal to such effects we have to take into account
the potential effect the relevant experience could have on a wide variety of relevant
judgments. For experience, even if we narrow our view to the experience of a specific
limited environmental aspect such as the colour of a particular object, immediately
provides the subject with more than one specific bit of information. Thus, for
example, saying that the colour of an object is experienced as red leaves out details
such as whether it appears to be red in bright light or dim light, shadowed or partly
shadowed, whether or not it appears to be a homogenous red, whether it is
experienced as, say, darker than its background, similar in colour but not in shade to
the colour of the object on the right, and so on. It might be that in some cases, due to
the way the subject attends to the colour, no such additional information is
immediately available to him, but there is no doubt that if there are such cases, they
are the exception. Often, even if the subject's only interest is to determine the object's
colour, his experience immediately provides him with some such additional
information. Furthermore, in the case of aspects such as particular objects it is
essential to the experience of the aspect that more than just one bit of information
from it is immediately available to the subject (this will be clarified in Chapter 6). The
need to take into account such a variety of effects might make it impractical for one to
actually provide a full, accurate specifications of experiential contents, but it does not,
95 The way an aspect is presented to the subject is also manifested in its effect on other activities, but
the effect on the relevant judgements (i) seems to provide the most straightforward manifestation, (ii) is
more likely to be systematizable, and (iii) it is natural to think (though I shall mention a reason for
doubting this) that we can fully capture in this way any of the effects an experience may have.
106
by itself, raise special difficulties regarding what should count as sameness in the way
things are presented to a subject and what he takes to be the way things can be which
is thus presented.
Difficulties arise, however, due to (i) the role played by attention in our
evaluation of thoughts on the basis of visual experience, and (ii) the fact that changes
in attention can affect the way things appear to the subject. A subject's experience
provides him with more information than he can, at the time, use for evaluating
thoughts. Consider, then, a case in which a subject experiences a certain aspect (say,
the shape of a particular object) which is not taken by him to be relevant to any
question he is currently occupied with (I shall focus on an experience of the, roughly
bounded, region of the visual field towards which the subject directs his gaze. This
will enable separating the effects of changes in attention from those of a change in the
amount of information available due to the aspect's location in the subject's visual
field). We wish to clarify what the potential effect of this experience on relevant shape
judgements would have been, had the subject intended to answer relevant questions
and taken the experience at face value. To do so, we have to take into account the
subject's interests when making the judgement. There are, however, two ways in
which his interests can affect which judgement he would make, only the second of
which is relevant here. First, his interests are relevant to determining what he would
count as similarity or dissimilarity in shape in the given context. Secondly, assuming
that the first question is determined, they can also affect the judgement by affecting
the way he makes it. This is so since they can affect the extent to which it matters to
him whether the resulting judgement is accurate, and thus the extent to which he
would focus his attention on the task; similarly they are relevant to determining the
amount of time he devotes to the task, the amount of exploratory behaviour he may
perform, the extent to which he is sensitive to relations between the aspect and other
107
seen aspects, etc. Changes in any of these factors can change the amount and variety
of visual input processed by the visual system, and thus the way the aspect appears to
the subject when the judgement is made. For example, in the case of a motionless
subject who sees an elliptical disc facing him, an immediate judgement would be that
the disc is circular, while a more careful judgement which is made only after, say, the
subject moves a bit, is likely to result in the judgement that the disc is elliptical. This
would be insignificant if in the latter case the movements result in a change in the way
the disc appears to the subject (the type of case described in Chapter 2). The crucial
point is that in certain circumstances an immediate judgement could have differed
from a more careful judgement in the above way, while in both cases there would
have been no change of apparent shape. That is, from the subject's point of view, the
first case would be a case in which he is reacting to the sight of a slanted circular disc
by judging that it is circular, and the second would be a case in which he is reacting to
the sight of an elliptical disc (where the disc appears elliptical all along) judging that it
is elliptical.96
One might suggest, then, that we limit our view to the experience's effect on
judgements which the subject could make without any further change in visual
attention. There are various difficulties with such a suggestion. To begin with, there is
a sense in which it is incoherent to suggest that a judgement can be based exclusively
on an experience of an aspect which is seen while the judgement is made without
some relevant adjustment of visual attention. For it seems that basing the judgement
on experience, that is, being sensitive in evaluating the relevant thought to the relevant
experiential information, just is a specific mode of visual attention. It might, then, be
suggested that we should focus on judgements which can be made with only the
minimal, necessary change in visual attention: judgements which are based
96 See Dennett & Kinsbourne 1992 on this type of effect of further visual input on 'prior' appearance.
108
exclusively on the experiential information which can be said to be possessed by the
subject at a given time (so that had a relevant question been raised at that time, this
information alone - excluding further information which may be gathered while the
subject is making the judgement - would serve as the basis for the judgment). It seems
that in practice we cannot make such judgements when the aspect is in sight (or at
least cannot do so intentionally), but one may suggest that it would be sufficient if
they were in principle possible. Further, it may be suggested that we can think of such
judgements as, in effect, the same as judgements that occur when the relevant
question is asked immediately after the relevant aspect disappears from view.97
One may doubt that judgements made immediately after the aspect disappears
from view can be regarded as experience-based rather than memory-based. But for the
sake of the argument I shall suppose that they are;98 thus, we can rely on intuitions as
to what one would judge in such a case, when attempting to specify (according to this
suggestion) how an aspect appears to the subject. There seems however to be a further
problem with such judgements. Though taken by the subject to be based on his recent
experience alone, it seems that to some degree they are affected by memories of
earlier experiences, by general assumptions regarding the type of scene, etc. (In a
familiar environment we seem to experience more details than in an unfamiliar one,
and similarly we seem to experience more details when the environment is of a
familiar type than when it is not). This seems to raise the following problem.
Suppose that what the subject takes to be the way he experiences what I shall
label 'an unconsidered aspect' - an aspect which is not currently considered by him to
97 This is the type of thought behind Mack and Rock's inattention paradigm (see their 1998). I should
stress that I am discussing a different type of case: one in which the subject is supposed to have
experiential information from the aspect, and is likely to be able to answer correctly multiple-choice
questions regarding relevant general categories. To the best of my knowledge such cases are not
currently examined by psychologists; thus I have to rely on intuitions which are likely to be at least
partly mistaken.
It is assumed that a judgement should still count as experience-based if it is based on what is often
called iconic memory.
109
be directly relevant to a specific question he is currently attempting to answer on the
basis of vision - is often affected by memory and general knowledge in addition to
current visual input. I mentioned in footnote 94 that when a subject attempts an
experience-based task and his performance is affected by further factors, such as his
expectations, there is room for distinguishing cases in which the effect is additional to
the effect of the experience and those in which the expectations (or other relevant
factor) affect the way things are experienced. Such a distinction also seems in place in
the case under discussion. Effects of the first type need not interest us; they only
create a practical difficulty. Suppose then that memory and general knowledge affect
the way unconsidered aspects are experienced, and suppose that the explanation of
this effect is as follows. It is a reasonable hypothesis that mechanisms which are
operative in visual recognition are such that factors like memory and general
knowledge play a role in determining which visual information is selected and
processed as well as the course of the recognition procedure (and in this way
contributing to the speed of the process).99 We may, then, assume that in the lack of
the relevant modes of visual attention there is less control of the processing by visual
input, and thus in such cases memory and general knowledge are often the factors
which dominate the process. If something of this sort is the case, one may argue as
follows. It is true that the relevant mechanisms are those which, when an aspect is
considered, contribute to determining the way the aspect is experienced. But in the
case of unconsidered aspects, the operation of the mechanism is, generally, such that
the aspects' appearance is due to a process in which the effects of current visual input,
memory and general knowledge are mixed (rather than dominated by the visual
input). Thus the appearance is only partly sensitive to the way things actually are and
99 See Palmer 1999ch.9.
110
thus it seems that, strictly speaking, it should not be regarded as providing
experiential information.
However, if we consider the situation more carefully and take into account the
role played by the experience of unconsidered aspects in the subject's interaction with
the environment, we will see that this reaction is exaggerated. First, one should
remember that the way things are presented to the subject in such cases is, to some
extent, constrained by visual input. Thus even when the appearance is misleading, it is
likely that the mistaken appearance bears some relation to the way the aspect actually
is. It should also be remembered that we are discussing a wide range of cases where
the effect of memory and general knowledge varies in degree; in cases in which
memory and knowledge have a lesser effect (though still possibly greater than when
the aspect is considered) - as, for example, when a subject experiences the
unconsidered shape of an object he is currently attending to - it seems implausible to
conclude that the subject is not provided with experiential information from the
aspect. More important, even when memory and general knowledge are dominant, the
appearance of changes as well as the general outline of boundaries and of where
things are located are, normally, systematically dependent on the way things are; thus,
at least regarding these aspects, the subject is provided with experiential information.
Now, it seems that all this is taken into account by ordinary subjects; that is, the
experience of unconsidered aspects is, in the first place, regarded by the subject as
indicating the general features of the surroundings and providing information about
changes, while he takes it that if more specific information is required for a specific
task, it is best pursued by shifting attention to the relevant aspect. Furthermore, when
it is impossible to attend to the aspect, the information the subject takes himself to
have is normally treated as more likely to be misleading than the information he
would have had had he attended to the aspect (where, in addition, subjects are
111
sensitive to the degree to which aspects are currently remote from being
considered
). Thus we may agree that what we take to be the way unconsidered
aspects are presented to us in experience provides us with some genuine experiential
information, and that we are sensitive to the qualifications there are on the reliability
of what we take to be the relevant available information in such cases. 101
There is however a more fundamental problem with the suggestion under
discussion. The suggestion to appeal to the effect of the information available prior to
any change in visual attention was put forward since we saw that the way one attends
to the aspect may affect the appearance. But the problematic cases were those in
which what we take to be the appearance of an aspect at a given time seems to be
affected by further visual input. And the immediate problem created by such cases is
that it is unclear whether we can assume that there is specific relevant information
available to the subject at the time in which the question is raised. Moreover, it seems
to me that the lesson to draw from the existence of such cases is that we cannot
construe a continuous appearance as a sequence of brief appearances, where each
brief appearance can be considered as being the appearance it is independently of its
place in the sequence. If so, it is wrong to suggest that the appearance at a particular
time could be specified in terms of the potential effect which the appearance at that
time, considered in abstraction from its place in the sequence, would have had on the
subject's dispositions to judge.
100 The terminology I am using makes it difficult to express this properly. The fact that information
from an aspect is not currently playing a role in a focused vision-based task leaves us with a very wide
range of possibilities - it may be taken by the subject to be somewhat more remotely relevant to the
task, or may be relevant to more general on-going projects.
101 If the second type of effect (the effect of memory and general knowledge on experience-based
reactions which does not involve an effect on the appearance) occurs frequently, then there will also be
a need to mention it in the above considerations. I do not know enough about the relevant mechanisms
in order to speculate about the occurrence of such effects. However, presently 1 do not see a reason to
think that they are significantly frequent.
112
Of course, given a certain continuous experience, we can ask which information
was available to the subject at a given time in addition to the information which, at
that time, was considered as relevant to a specific focused task (if there was such a
task). Since the specific continuous appearance is influenced by the subject's
attention, this would require taking into account the facts about the particular tasks the
subject was performing at the time, and considering in this context which effects the
relevant elements of the appearance could have, given that he is performing the
relevant task; for example, we may ask which aspects could have drawn his attention
and in what way, if he had relevant general intentions (that is, intentions which do not
involve any direct reference to a visually-guided task) in addition to his intentions to
perform the tasks he is performing. It is natural to think about this in terms of what the
subject would have judged about the unconsidered aspects, had they disappeared from
view immediately after the relevant time. But it is important to note that now we are
treating this question as a tool that may give us an indication of which further
information was available at the time, rather than as directly pointing at one of the
possible effects of the appearance by which it (the appearance) is to be specified. That
is, we are not assuming that there must be a fact as to what the subject would have
been disposed to judge at the particular time in question on the basis of the
information available to him at that time alone, and that our specification of the
content is correct to the extent that it corresponds to this fact.
One's intuitions as to what one would have judged in such a case are far from
reliable, but in the lack of a better indication, the following is a tentative suggestion
based on such intuitions. It seems that the information we have from an unconsidered
aspect is to a certain degree unspecific, indicating a roughly bounded range within
which rests the way the aspect actually is if the experience is veridical. Thus, for
example, it seems that we can be aware of the fact that there is a rectilinear-shaped
113
object behind the object we are attending to, but that in order to gather more specific
information about its shape or about how far behind the attended object it is we have
to attend to the relevant shape or distance (correspondingly). There seem to be
different factors that can be responsible for this. It seems that generally when less
attention (in a wide sense) is paid to a seen aspect, less information is processed for
one or more of the following reasons. It might be that less input is available from the
start (for example, due to the fact that the aspect is not foveated), that attentional
mechanisms inhibit further processing at various stages, or it might be that certain
aspects (like fine details) are not processed further without a specific intention.
There is also a somewhat different sense in which unconsidered information at a
given time is unspecific. If the subject, at the time, is not basing a judgement on
certain experiential information (or basing on it some similar focused task), talk about
this information being available to the subject at the particular time is an abstraction
from the continuous flow of information available to the subject from the aspect (this
is also true about the information on the basis of which the judgement is made, but as
the subject is making the judgement there is a sense in which he selects the
information given at a particular time). Being part of such a flow, the relation with
further information is not irrelevant to the question of which information is then
available: further information may affect the meaning of what is seen (for example,
whether he sees a 2D or 3D object, whether the object is moving or not), and it may
provide more specific information or more accurate information. That is, I am
suggesting that this is also the way things are from the subject's point of view. Thus,
from his point of view, as long as a specific fragment of the flow is not actually
distinguished - due to the subject's making a judgement or a similar type of decision
at a particular time, or simply because the aspect disappears from view or undergoes
114
an instant significant change - the information available to him at the relevant time is
to some extent taken by him to be open for further determination and corrections.
It seems that the best way to capture the sense in which, from the subject's point
of view, the available information is not specific is to say that, when unconsidered
(which implies that it is unattended in one or other everyday sense), an aspect is
presented as, say, a roundish unattended shape in a sense similar to that in which we
would say that a certain colour is presented as red in dim light, a certain shape is
presented as a partly occluded roundish object, and so on. For the way things appear
to the subject is that he is experiencing a certain aspect which has certain determinate
features about which he has some information, which is to a certain degree unspecific,
indicating to him what information he may expect to gather if he shifts his attention
towards it, and also (since attending to different aspects may require different things)
indicating the relevant way in which the subject should shift his attention in order to
gather more specific information. (The degree to which the subject has specific
information from the aspect can, of course, vary; the same particular instance of a
shape may be experienced as an unattended cube, an unattended rectilinear shape, and
so on).
Note that the appearance of unattended aspects bears directly on the
specification of the appearance of attended aspects. As I have been construing
attention to a certain aspect, it involves intentional selection of experiential
information from that aspect; that is, the subject intends to be sensitive in the selection
to whether or not the information is from the relevant aspect. Now, attending, for
example, to an object in this way, does not require attention to any of its properties.
But, of course, the way the subject experiences each of the properties of the object
(which are experienced at the time) is part of the way the object is experienced by
him. The same holds for any other environmental aspect and its visible features.
115
V
The suggested picture then is one on which experience involves the continuous
provision of information from environmental aspects. Attending to a particular aspect
with an intention to answer a certain question can be seen as having the effect of
selecting certain (relatively) well-specified information about the aspect, while other
bits of information are less specific and play a role in providing the subject with a
general outline of the changing current environment, thus informing him about which
further specific information may be gathered by him and in what ways. 102 The
difficulties I have been discussing arise, I suggest, because of the need to appeal to
reflection on what we would judge (in relevant conditions) in order to clarify to
ourselves which further information is made available in experience, and specifically
in order to find a way to articulate which information is in question. But if remembering that a given bit of experiential information is not only relevant to
determining which attitude the subject should take towards this or that proposition,
but also relevant to making clear the presence of the actual aspects and guiding the
subject as to ways he may gather further information from the aspects he might be
interested in - we treat such reflections as merely indicating which further information
is available, the difficulties we encounter are only practical.
Note that the fact that what I have been calling information from unconsidered
aspects plays a role in directing the subject's attention means that there is a sense in
which these aspects are considered by the subject in his current interaction with the
environment (it is only that the information from them is not immediately involved in
102 Such information can also play a role in the subject's control of actions other than exploratory
actions; thus, to be more accurate one should add that the available information can be directly taken to
provide information about possibilities of action. I focus on cognitive tasks and exploratory actions in
order to simplify the picture. Before adding relations with action in general to the picture, there is a
need to discuss issues regarding the way such information is to be specified, and regarding the relation
between what we would intuitively describe as practical and cognitive tasks. (Remember that the
descriptions of the relevant experiential contents in Chapter 4 were only meant to be rough pointers).
116
the subject's performance of a focused task). Note also that there is room for
distinguishing different degrees in which experienced aspects are 'considered' by a
subject. For example, while considering what shape an object has, various relations to
the surrounding objects, as well as their shapes might not be specifically considered
but still the subject may be disposed to be more sensitive to them than to other
surrounding aspects. At the same time other aspects can be said to be considered
simply as part of his current general interest in what is going on around him
('current', since this may change both in relation to the type of things which he is
likely to be interested in and the extent to which he is currently sensitive to such
things).
At this point there is a further question as to where exactly to draw the line
between information which is available to the subject though unconsidered in the
strong sense and cases in which visual information may affect the subject's reactions
(say, draw his attention to a relevant aspects) but the effect is only sub-personal. A
decision as to what to say here requires more knowledge than I have about the
mechanisms involved. However, if we agree that the main role played by information
from unconsidered aspects is in directing the subject's attention, we can accept that
there is a continuum between cases in which the subject is guided by experiential
information and cases in which visual information affects his behaviour at the subpersonal-level and that there might very well be borderline cases regarding which
there is no clear fact as to whether we should regard them as of the one type or the
other.
I have mentioned the analogy between the fact that information from an aspect
is somewhat unspecific and other cases in which the conditions are such that the way
in which an aspect is experienced indicates to the subject that more specific
information is available from the object and also indicates ways in which this
117
information can be gathered. In effect, this seems a general feature of the way things
are presented to the subject in experience; a feature which is due to the fact that the
experience provides the subject with information both about the way things are with
the relevant aspect independently of its relation to the subject and about the obtaining
of conditions which can affect the appearance together with the fact that the subject
has a grasp of the appearance as dependent on both types of factors. There are various
degrees and various ways in which the possibility of further information is indicated
to the subject. The type of case I have been discussing requires only a shift in
attention, and the information which the subject could be said to have prior to shifting
his attention can be quite specific. Cases of occlusion suggest specific ways in which
further information can be gathered and, again, there are various degrees in which the
subject may be provided with information as to which information to expect. In other
cases, such as objects seen at the far distance or in thick fog, the information the
subject may have can be rather minimal and the indication as to what can be done in
order for the subject to gather more specific information may be quite impractical. We
may also view as a phenomenon of the same type the fact that certain apparent
features of objects indicate the availability of information which can be gathered by
observing certain causal effects on the object (e.g., the object's appearance as having
a volume indicating information which would be available when the object is opened
or broken, etc.). And in a sense it is also the case that seeing mind-independent
environmental aspects, generally, indicates the possibility of further facts to be
discovered (where there is always the possibility that the facts are not perceivable).
These points are relevant to clarifying the sense in which the aspect itself is said to be
part of the content of the experience. The above claim - that from the subject's point
of view the experience does not just provide him with information that bears on the
way he should currently evaluate thoughts, but also provides him with information as
118
to which fiirther information is available and in what ways it may be gathered - when
embedded in the subject's more general conception of his relation with the
environment, explains the sense in which he grasps his situation as one in which he
encounters a particular environmental aspect which he is experiencing as the
particular aspect it is. This will be central in the next chapter.
119
Part II: Vision-based demonstratives
6 Attending to an object and knowing which object one is demonstrating
In this chapter I outline a suggestion as to how attention to a seen object
(construed as explanatorily more basic than the particular demonstrative ability it may
give rise to) enables a subject to entertain demonstrative thoughts about that object. It
seems unobjectionable to say that by attending to a seen object the subject singles out
the object and this provides him with the ability to entertain singular thoughts about it
(since it provides him with the knowledge of which object he is thinking about). The
challenge is to clarify what attention to a seen object involves and how it is related to
the relevant demonstrative thoughts in such a way that, despite the fact that it is
construed as more basic than the particular demonstrative ability it may give rise to, it
can explain how the object is singled out by the subject and taken to be the object of
the relevant thoughts - that is, how it is that from the subject's point o/vzewthe truth
values of the thoughts in question depend on the way things are with that particular
object. It should be remembered that the claim concerns only the relation between
particular acts of attention and particular demonstrative abilities; I am not denying
that the general ability to attend to particular objects and the general ability to think
about them demonstratively are interdependent.
I shall first sketch, in a general manner, what I take attention to an object to
involve and how a certain act of attention to a particular seen object is related to a
certain demonstrative thought which is based on it. It will be suggested that what
explains the subject's knowledge of which object he is thinking about is his grasp of
the relations between the object and himself while he is attending to it, especially his
grasp of the way in which his experience provides him with information from the
120
object. In the rest of the chapter I shall further develop the initial sketch and discuss
some possible objections.
Bundles of information, attention and demonstrative thought
I start, then, by outlining what I take the subject's attention to an object and his
exercise of a particular demonstrative ability to involve, and by introducing some
terminology.
Normally, a subject who is attending to a particular seen object is in a state in
which information from that object is continuously available to him as information
from one and the same object. There are three points here, (i) Information (that is,
visual experiential information) from the object is available to him in the sense that at
present the object (visually) appears to him a certain way and thus there is information
from the object which he can presently take into account in evaluating thoughts,
reasoning, etc., and also in the sense that he can gather more information from the
object by continuing to attend to it, possibly, while performing relevant exploratory
activities. (In what follows I shall use 'information available to the subject' to refer to
information which is available in both the above senses, and shall use 'information the
subject currently has' or just 'current information' to refer only to the former; the
latter will be distinguished by contrasting it with current information).
(ii) Information from the object is available to the subject continuously as long
as conditions which enable gathering visual information from the object obtain (e.g.,
as long as he keeps looking at the object and there is sufficient light). What counts as
continuous in this context, and therefore also which gaps in the obtaining of the
enabling conditions matter, is relative to the subject's point of view. Gaps in the
visual input processed which are unnoticed by the subject, like those due to blinking
121
and saccadic suppression, as well as gaps which are noticeable but do not affect the
subject's sense of a continuous encounter with one and the same object, like those due
to brief occlusion, should not be regarded as interrupting the continuity. Thus, in
effect, the fact mentioned in (i) that information which the subject does not possess at
present is available to him, together with (iii) entails that information is continuously
available in this sense. I mention this point only for emphasis and in what follows will
omit the reference to continuity.
(iii) The information is available to the subject as information from one and the
same object in the sense that those aspects of his (actual or possible) experience in
virtue of which he is (or would be) said to have the relevant information are all
aspects of a (actual or possible) continuous experience as of one object; in other
words, the relevant appearances are or would be aspects of a (possibly changing)
appearance of an object, for the lack of a better expression, I shall often speak about
the information appearing to the subject to be information from one and the same
object in order to stress that what is in question is simply a matter of the way in which
things are presented to the subject in experience; that is, we are dealing with cases in
which if the subject does not have relevant doubts regarding the veridicality of his
experience, there is nothing further required for understanding why he takes the
information to be from the same object. 103 This is to be contrasted with cases such as
a subject's simultaneously seeing two parts of the same building through two widely
spaced windows, or his seeming to see an object dissolving and suddenly
reappearing. 104 In these cases the subject might have grounds for believing that what
is experienced through the two windows, or before and after the gap, is the same
103 Remember that I use 'appear' as meaning visually appear, referring to the aspect of a particular
experience in virtue of which, from the subject's point of view, this experience provides him with certain
information about the environment.
104 Scholl and Pylyshyn (1999) show that interruptions of this type (as opposed, for examples, to cases in
which an object is momentarily occluded) impair subjects' ability to keep track of moving objects.
122
object - and thus take the available information to be from the same object - but these
grounds go beyond his taking the current experience at face value when having no
reason for relevant doubts in its veridicality. (A similar contrast exists with cases in
which the subject imposes boundaries between objects where no boundaries are seen,
as may happen when, say, a subject takes what appears as one bar, occluded at some
point, to be two bars lying in succession). I should clarify that I am relying here on
what seems to me an intuitive way of describing the phenomenology in certain clear
cases. I do not assume that in all cases in which a subject takes given visual
information to be from one and the same object it is clear whether this is due only to
the way things appear to him or whether other factors (other sources of information,
inferences, etc.), are involved; neither is it assumed that there must always be a
definite answer to this question.
That information from a particular object is available to a subject as information
from one and the same object is crucial to his ability to selectively attend to particular
objects: this is what immediately (that is, without the mediation of further
considerations) distinguishes, from his point of view, between distinct, or possibly
distinct, 105 objects experienced by him (simultaneously and at different times), and
thus what enables him to select (without the mediation of further considerations)
information available from one object (as distinct from information available from
other objects) and to keep doing so as long as the object is visible to him (a period
during which the object, its relation to the subject, and various environmental
conditions may change). When information which is available to the subject appears,
105 In cases like that of a subject seeing two parts of one building through widely spaced windows, the
subject, due to further knowledge, may believe, or take it to be likely, that the two 'apparent objects' are
different parts of the same object; but experience does not present the two parts as parts of the same object.
Also, when there are pauses between different episodes of the subject's attending to an object, he may take
be unlikely that he is attending to different object, but experience alone leaves open the possibility that
it" to) be
gathered before and after the pause is from different objects.
information
the
123
or would appear, as information from one and the same object, I shall say that it is
bundled together, and I shall use the expression 'a bundle of information' to speak
about available information which is bundled together in this sense. I am introducing
the expression as referring to any collection of pieces of information which are made
available to the subject in experience as information from one and the same object; I
shall shortly make further distinctions between types of bundles according to the
restrictions on which information is to be included in a bundle. It should be clear from
the above attempt to explain what is meant here by 'information appearing as being
from one and the same object' that saying that certain information is bundled together
should not to be understood as implying that, from the subject's point of view, the
appearance is as of separate aspects (e.g. shape, size, colour, etc.) together with some
further distinct aspect of the appearance which connects them. From the subject's
point of view the appearance is as of an object which has such and such colour, shape,
size, etc., or is changing colour, shape, size, etc., in such and such ways; the relevant
information is, in the first place, information that the object (which appears as having
several other features) is such and such. 106
It was pointed out that the bundling of information from particular objects is
crucial to the subject's ability to selectively attend to seen objects; that is, to his
ability to single out a particular object and keep track of it in virtue of seeing it. In
effect, for a certain type of bundle and a certain construal of what it is for the subject
to select the information which is included in a single bundle, the subject's selecting
the information which is in a specific bundle (of the relevant type) is an aspect of his
in which the different aspects can be said to be grasped by a subject as
is able to attend to certain aspects of an object, ignoring others. I should also clarify that the way in whid
refer to the object in the above description of the information should not be regarded as an indication that
*u« information
:^,iVvr^-,of;/-vv> relates
i-olotoc to
t/-> the
tVip> object
nKiprt descriptively.
rlesrrintivelv
the
I ClCl
l\J U1C UUJt^l 111 UlS^ C*L^WVV \JWk7Wllpvivi*
\-»A
mv i
124
visually selecting (or singling out) an object. (When a subject selects the information
which is included in a single bundle I shall say that he selects the relevant bundle).
First, we should remember that the information the subject can be said to be selecting
is the information available to him in virtue of the way the particular object appears or
would appear if he keeps track of the object in various possible conditions, where the
particular object is a constituent of the appearance. Given his primitive conception of
perception and objects the subject takes the information which is currently bundled
together to be information available to him from the particular object in question and
takes it that by continuing to gather information which appears to be from the same
object he can gather more information from it. Thus from the subject's point of view
his ability to distinguish the object and keep track of it involves his continuous
sensitivity to which information appears or would appear to be from this object.
Note that what the subject takes to be the information which would appear to be
from this object, is not simply the information which would appear to be from the
same object (as the one currently seen). The subject's grasp of the relation between
appearances and the way things are makes room for the possibility that what
continuously appears to him to be one and the same object is, in fact, a number of
objects replacing each other. Thus the further information which he takes to be
relevant to his ability to keep track of the object is information which appears to be
from the same object as long as information from this object continues to be gathered.
(In effect, since it is possible that more than one bundle from the same object be
available to the subject at the time, what is required is that information which would
be bundled in the relevant bundle should continue to be gathered. Hereafter, I shall
125
omit this qualification). 107
This may seem more sophisticated than what seems to be involved in visually
singling out an object. But remember that from the subject's point of view the
appearance of a particular object as such provides indications as to which further
information may be available to him and how it may be gathered, and that generally
the object is grasped by the subject as a continuous source of information. The further
complications of the above description are simply what is implied by the fact that
from the subject's point of view the information is from the object he is currently
experiencing (where the subject's point of view is best captured by the initial
formulation referring to 'information from this object'). We can thus say that the
subject attends to an object in the relevant sense when he is (intentionally) selecting a
specific type of bundle: the bundle consisting of the information which, given current
bundled information from a particular object, appears or would appear as from the
same object as long as information from the object in question (i.e., the object the
relevant current information is from) continuous to be gathered. Henceforth, unless
specified otherwise, when I speak about a bundle I shall refer to this type of restricted
bundle.
I shall later discuss these claims in more detail. The point I wish to emphasize at
present is that the fact that singling out an object involves singling out a certain
bundle of information, together with the fact that the subject has a grasp of the
relation between the object and the bundle, provides him with a grasp of what
107 There is also a need to take care of further special cases. For examples, it is possible that an unnoticed
replacement of one object by another takes place gradually, and thus that there are stages in which
information from the first object, which appears as from the same object, is still gathered but is negligible
(in the next section I shall clarify the exact sense in which it is said to be negligible). To prevent the
inclusion in the bundle of the information available if such a situation occurs, one has to add that
information from the object which continues to be gathered also continues to be dominant in the bundling
of information in the relevant bundle (this too will be clarified in the next section). For simplicity's sake, I
shall focus on cases in which there is only one bundle, dominated by information from one object.
126
currently distinguishes the object, for him, from any other object. He views it as the
object from which he currently has the relevant selected information, and from which
further information is available to him if he keeps selecting information that will be
bundled in the same bundle. And if he is simultaneously attending to other objects as
well, he also distinguishes it from the other attended objects by virtue of certain
relations between current information in the different selected bundles (for example,
by its appearing to be the only red object among them, the closest one, the one at the
middle, etc.). 108
If this picture is accepted, then there is a clear sense in which a subject who
attends to a particular object knows which object he is attending to, and is thus able to
entertain singular thoughts about it. Furthermore, the subject's grasp of the relation
between the object and the selected bundle of information explains what makes this
mode of distinguishing an object basic to our ability to evaluate thoughts about
objects and to intentionally direct actions towards objects. As the subject immediately
takes the information in the selected bundle to be from the object, he also, when
entertaining a certain demonstrative thought on the basis of this act of attention,
immediately takes the information in that bundle to bear upon the way in which he
evaluates the thought (that is, whether he takes it to be true, false, probable, etc.) and
on what implications (for other thoughts and for action) he takes the thought to have.
Borrowing Evans's expression, I shall say that the subject immediately takes the
information in the bundle to bear on the evaluation and appreciation of the thought. 109
108 It is assumed that the relations between the bundles enable the subject to distinguish each of the objects.
Some cases in which subjects are described as simultaneously attending to a number of objects might not
enable doing this. For example, when a subject observes a number of qualitatively indistinguishable objects
moving rapidly in random ways and attempts to track 4 of them (see Pylyshyn 2001), he might not, all
along, be in a position to distinguish each of the attended objects (due to the spatial relations between
them). The way I use 'attention to an object', when the subject is not in such a position, he should not be
said to be attending to each of the objects, but only to all of them as a group.
109 Evans pp. 121-2. This schematic structure of what a demonstrative mode of thought involves is based on
Evans. For a similar schematic description see Campbell 1997 p.57.
127
It should be emphasized that 'taking the information to bear' is meant as a
description of how things are from the subject's point of view. He (immediately) takes
the information to be from the object the thought is about and for this reason
immediately takes it to bear on the evaluation and appreciation of the thought. Thus it
is not a matter of brute dispositions to react in certain ways or make certain transitions
in thought. Further, it is not necessary that when the subject evaluates the thought or
draws implications from it, each bit of information in the bundle has a certain effect
on these activities; in fact, some of the information is not yet in his possession, and
might not be gathered by him at all.
Note that the immediacy in question relates only to the subject's basis for taking
the information to be from the object the thought is about. There is another sense in
which information can be said to bear either immediately or mediately on the
evaluation and appreciation of the thought, which is not relevant here: one can
distinguish between (i) cases in which the subject's evaluation of the thought involves
an inference or some other consideration as to whether or not he should take the
predicative element of the thought to apply to the object (for example, a subject may
take the experience of an object as a G to bear on his evaluation of the thought 'this is
F' due to his belief that most things that are G are F), and (ii) cases in which no
additional inference or consideration is involved (for example, a subject immediately
takes the experience of an object as G to bear on his evaluation of the thought 'this is
G'). (A similar distinction can be made regarding the basis for drawing implications).
Note also that a subject immediately takes the information to bear on the
evaluation and appreciation of the thought even when he does not take the
information to be veridical. If he takes the information to be from the object, he takes
it to systematically depend on how things are with the object; thus misinformation can
both be relevant to his gathering more accurate information about the object, and,
128
combined with whatever views he has regarding the illusion (or possibility of one),
relevant to the particular way in which he evaluates and appreciates the thought. It
thus has an immediate bearing on his evaluation an appreciation of the thought in the
sense that no consideration regarding the object's identity is required. Things are
different when the subject believes, or considers the possibility, that certain
information which appears to be from the object is not actually so. However, in such
cases, not taking the information to bear on the evaluation and appreciation of the
thought involves an additional consideration on the subject's part. (Thus the
immediacy is not only a matter of the lack of a need for further consideration but also
of the subject's attitude being prior to further considerations which might overrule it).
The suggestion then is that visually attending to an object provides the subject
with knowledge of which object he is attending to since it involves the subject's
selection of a particular bundle of information and a grasp that the object he is
attending to is the object the selected bundle is from. This knowledge accounts for the
subject's ability to entertain thoughts about the object, as he then takes his thought to
be about the object the selected bundle is from. It further accounts for the particular
way in which we evaluate and appreciate demonstrative thoughts - the fact that we
immediately take the information in the bundle to bear upon the evaluation and
appreciation of the relevant thoughts.
It should be clear that this is not a suggestion that the subject identifies the
object descriptively; namely, that he first selects a certain bundle of information
(where this could be done independently of his ability to select the object) and then
entertains a thought about 'the object, whichever it is, which this bundle is from'.
First, the view is that the relevant information cannot, generally, be specified without
reference to the object and that as long as the subject does not have relevant doubts he
grasps the information as such. Furthermore, the restriction as to which further
129
available information is included in the bundle involves appeal to the object (it is the
information bundled while information from the object continues to be gathered), and
is grasped in this way by the subject. Thus the subject relies on his grasp of which
object is in question when selecting the bundle. (In the third section I shall discuss this
point in more detail and mention another contrast with the descriptive view).
The point is that without the grasp of the relation between the object and the
bundle, whatever else is involved in the subject's singling out the object will not
suffice for making it a case of the subject singles out a particular object; that is, a case
in which he is intentionally visually singling out the object, as opposed to a case in
which the object is discriminated, as a matter of fact, by his actually being selectively
sensitive, or being disposed to be selectively sensitive, to information which is from
it. In effect, this is simply an attempt to spell out how, given the way the visual system
works and the type of environment with which we interact, the relevant aspects of the
subject's primitive conception contribute to his ability to experience a particular
object as such and his ability to intentionally single it out.
In what follows I shall develop this picture further and clarify that attending to
an object in this sense is explanatorily more basic from the demonstrative ability it
may give rise to. However, before turning to these tasks, there is a need to discuss the
relation between bundles of information and objects in virtue of which the bundling
enables subjects to single out particular objects and to keep track of them. So far it has
been taken for granted that there is a certain unproblematic relation (a relation which,
as I did when describing the subject's grasp of his situation, I shall express by saying
that a bundle is from a certain object), but we shall shortly see that it is not
immediately clear what this relation is.
130
What is it for a bundle of information to be from a particular object?
According to the suggested view attention to an object involves the subject's
selecting a specific bundle of information which is from this object. Further, it is
suggested that when a subject selects such a bundle, his grasp of the fact that the
bundle is from the attended object is an essential part of what makes it the case that he
knows which object he is attending to, and thus also of what explains his ability to
entertain demonstrative thoughts about the object. But what exactly is this relation
between a particular bundle of information and a particular object supposed to be?
(Our main interested is, still, bundles which include information available as
information from one and the same object as long as the subject keeps gathering
information from the object in question. However, I am now clarifying what it is for
any type of bundle - that is, any collection of information bundled by the fact that it
appears as information from one and the same object - to be from a particular object).
The most straightforward answer would be that each bit of information in the
bundle should be from the object (that is, it should be due to an aspect of the
appearance which is systematically dependent on the corresponding feature of the
particular object in question, given the relation between the object and the subject and
relevant environmental conditions). However, if we accept this answer, the above
suggestion as to what a demonstrative thought involves (namely, that the subject
selects a bundle of information which is actually from the object and grasps it as such)
will imply that whenever the selected bundle includes information from more than
one object, the subject cannot entertain a demonstrative thought about it (similarly, it
would be implied that in such cases the subject cannot attend to the object in
131
question).
But it is undeniable that there are cases in which it is possible to think
demonstratively about a seen object even though the way the object appears to the
subject is partly dependent on other objects (that is, the information in the selected
bundle includes bits of information which are, at least partly, from different objects).
Simple examples are cases in which an object appears to the subject as having a
certain pattern on it, or a patch of a different colour, while in fact the seen differences
in colour are due to colour information from a different object; as can happen, for
example, when a thread which is lying on a tablecloth appears to a subject as part of
the pattern of the tablecloth, or the black tail of a cat with a white feather stuck to it
appears as a black tail with a white patch. Clearly in such cases we take it to be
possible to attend to one object (in the above examples the tablecloth or the cat) and
entertain simple demonstrative thoughts about them, by being selectively sensitive to
information which includes information from other objects (like the thread or feather).
Similarly a subject can misperceive an object's shape due to shape information from a
number of objects being mixed together, without this preventing him from being able
to entertain simple demonstrative thoughts about the relevant object (take, for
example, a case in which it appears to the subject that he is encountering an object
which is spherical apart for a small triangular protrusion on its right side, where in
fact what he is seeing is a spherical object and the corner of a triangular object partly
occluded by the spherical one).
The question, then, is in virtue of what a subject in the above examples can
select a bundle which can be said to be from just one of the objects, even though only
110 In the following discussion any claim about what enables thought about a particular object also applies
to what enables attention to that object and vice versa. I often prefer speaking about whether or not a
demonstrative thought is possible because talk about attention to an object can be understood in various
ways and therefore less helpful in attempting to examine intuitions as to how to describe various example
(and possibly also generally less clear). However, at some points, for ease of exposition, I speak about what
enables attention to an object.
132
bundles which include information from more than one object are currently available
to him (for the current information in relation to which we ask whether further
information appears to be from the same object is from a plurality of objects). Clearly
there are several cases in which, because the information bundled together is from
more than one object, a subject who selects the bundled information cannot be
regarded as attending to just one object, and if he takes the selected information to
bear on the evaluation and appreciation of an attempted demonstrative thought we
should say that he is mistaken in taking himself to actually be entertaining a
demonstrative thought about a particular object. An example of the latter type will be
a situation in which a subject is attending to what appears to him as one object but is,
in fact, two copulating flies (of more or less the same size), or to what appears to him
as one object but is, in fact, two entangled bushes (each of which has more or less the
same amount of parts visible to the subject). 111 (It should be mentioned that attending
to the combination of the two (or more) objects which appear to be one could enable
the subject to entertain visually-based thoughts about the combination of the objects,
and we might express such thoughts by using 'this' or 'that'. But such thoughts differ
from the type of demonstrative thoughts discussed here in that the subject does not
take them to be about a particular object. This will be manifested in his not taking
such thoughts to conform to the same principles which thoughts about particular
objects do; for example, he will not draw from such thoughts implications which
presuppose cohesion. To emphasize, if the subject takes himself to entertain a thought
about a particular object, this thought will fail).
1 '' The additions in brackets are only a rough indication of one type of condition in which the subject
cannot be regarded as attending to any one of the objects in particular. It might not be sufficient and
certainly need not be necessary.
133
What, then, distinguishes between the two types of cases? It might be suggested
that in the former cases but not in the latter there is one object such that most of the
current information bundled together is from it, and that it is in virtue of this condition
that a subject who selects the bundled information can be regarded as attending to an
object even when some of the information in the bundle is from other objects. 112 The
immediate problem with this suggestion is that it is not clear what measures are
relevant here. It does not seem that it is simply the amount of detail that matters, for it
seems possible to think demonstratively about a particular tree even if, being partly
covered by a vine, there is no obvious sense in which the bundle contains more bits of
detailed information - regarding shape, colour, texture, movements, etc. - from the
tree. It also seems that it is not the number of dimensions affected by information
from additional objects which matters; for example, it is possible to describe a case of
seeing a tree partly covered by a vine in which one can entertain simple demonstrative
thoughts about the tree though most dimensions include information from both
objects (that is, a case in which information about colour, shape, texture, movements,
and also about exact location and size are all partly due to information from the vine).
It may seem that some dimensions are more important than others and thus the
condition should be that a bundle is from the object most of the information relating
to these dimensions is from. For example, it may be suggested that location, shape
and size have such a priority, as they determine the apparent portion of space
occupied by the object and thus seem to be responsible for the appearance being an
appearance of a distinct object. To assess such a suggestion, there is a need to clarify
how the contribution of the location, shape and size of the different objects to the
apparent location, shape and size should be compared (for as mentioned above, it is
possible to entertain simple demonstrative thoughts about an object when the
112 Campbell makes such a suggestion when considering a version of this problem (2002 p.99).
134
information available to the subject about these three aspects depends on the location,
shape and size of more than one object), and it is not immediately clear how to do
this. Suppose it is suggested that the attended object is the one such that significant
global changes in its location, shape and size systematically affect the apparent
location, shape and size (where any changes in the location, shape and size of the
other objects may only have an effect on details or have rather limited global effects).
This is still quite vague, 113 but even without attempting to clarify what should count
as significant global changes, the following example seems to show that it cannot be
correct. If it were correct, then a subject who sees something which looks to him as
some kind of tent but is in fact a plastic pyramid covered by a blanket should be
regarded as attending to the plastic pyramid alone and demonstrating it when
entertaining a simple demonstrative thought. This seems counterintuitive. It seems
that if the subject is to be said to attend to anything at all, it would be the combination
of the pyramid and the blanket rather than any one of them. That is, it seems that
attention to the covering material alone or to the pyramid alone - if the latter is at all
possible - is more sophisticated than simply attending to the combination. The
important point, however, is that as long as it is agreed that it is not uniquely the case
that a subject in such a situation attends to the pyramid alone, this is a counterexample
to the above suggestion.
The comments in the last two paragraphs are not meant as a conclusive
113 Think about a white, flat, round clock with a black hook at its top, hanging on a larger, black, flat,
square board. A subject might see this as a square object - a clock with a black wooden frame - of the size
of the board. On the face of it the global changes in the location, size and shape of the board will have a
global affect the location, shape and size of the whole apparent object. While it is not obvious that the same
can be said about changes in the location, shape and size of the clock (in effect, it seems that apart from
small changes occurring in specific ways, the effect in this case would be that the two objects will appear as
two separate objects). There is thus a need for a more complex story about how to compare the
contributions (for otherwise the above suggestion commits us to the unintuitive result that the subject is
attending to the board).
135
argument showing that there is no possible interpretation - which conforms to our
intuitions about whether or not a subject is attending to one object (and thus can refer
to it demonstratively) in a given situation - of the suggestion that what determines one
object as the object a certain bundle is from is that most of the information in the
bundle should be from it. The aim was only to point out that it is not straightforward
what this interpretation should be. One way in which one could continue looking for
an appropriate interpretation would be, first, to try further to pin down which aspects
of the appearance are dominant in making it the case that a certain appearance of an
object (extending over some period of time) is a continuous appearance of one object
distinguished from the appearances of other objects (where this will probably require
specifying a complex relation between the different aspects 114). Secondly to clarify in
what sense one of the objects the information about these aspects is from could be
regarded as the one on which the information (about these aspects) available to the
subject mostly depends (where a suggestion would be acceptable if it accords with our
intuitions about which object is attended to, if at all, in various cases). But when the
task is presented this way, it seems that an explication of what it is for a bundle to be
from just one object need not require knowledge of the exact way in which various
aspects contribute to the appearance being the appearance of one and the same object.
The latter, it seems, concerns the principles according to which the mechanism
responsible for the information appearing as from one and the same object operates,
and thus required for explaining how it is that a particular object is, in fact, the one the
bundle is from. To clarify what it is for a bundle to be from one object, however, we
only need to clarify the sense in which the fact that the relevant information is
bundled together - that is, that it appears (or would appear) as information from one
114 One relevant aspect which was not mentioned explicitly so far, and which complicates things further, is
the kind something appears to be (when it appears to be of a certain kind).
136
and the same object - depends on how things are with just one object as opposed to
cases in which this depends on how things are with more than one object. I shall try to
sketch a way this can be done while leaving open the question regarding the principles
according to which the information is bundled together.
It seems helpful to appeal here to conditionals and counterfactuals which bring
out the way in which changes in the bundling depend on changes in conditions such
as the spatial relations between the subject and the relevant objects and between the
objects themselves; specifically, conditions which bring out the dependence of the
bundling of information over time on whether or not the information from just one
particular object is continuously gathered. (Note that the question of what counts as
continuous gathering of information, like that of what counts as information being
continuously available to the subject, is relative to the subject's point of view). I
suggest the following as at least a close approximation of what a bundle being from a
certain object involves.
Given a bundle of information b, which includes some information b' gathered
at a certain time t\ from a number of objects o\,... on, o\ (!</<«) is the object b is
from iff (i) if the subject has selected b' at t\ and continues to select information from
o\ till a later time tn, and at some time between t\ and tn there is a change in his
position in relation to O]... on or in the spatial relations between o\... on which affects
the bundling of the information in such a way that the information (gathered after the
change) from each o} (l<j<n) appears as information from a separate object1 5 (and no
other change affecting the availability of information from the objects occurs), then
the information from o\ would appear to him as information from the object he has
115 This should be read as restricted to cases in which the relevant change does not cause a change in the
visible features of the objects which would affect the way information from the object in question is
bundled, or if such changes are unavoidable, to cases in which the minimal amount of such changes takes
place.
137
been attending to (that is, it would appear that all along he has been selecting
information from the same object); and (ii) for any Oj, #i (l<j<n), if between t\ and tn
the subject continues to select information from it and the change in the bundling of
the information specified above takes place, then it would appear to him as if he had
shifted his attention to what is only a part of the object he was attending to, 116 an
object which was attached to it in some way or another, or an object (or part of one)
which was simply located close to it.
To see how this is supposed to work, consider the examples mentioned above.
Continuing to select information from the tablecloth while the thread is removed from
it or from the cat while the feather is removed from it, it will still look to the subject
as if he is attending to one and the same object, but if instead he goes on selecting
information from the thread or feather while they are removed, it will surely look to
him as if he is shifting attention from one object to another (or in certain conditions,
from one object to what was previously a part of it; e.g., the conditions may be such
that removing the feather appears as removing a bit of fur). Similarly, if the subject
moves around the spherical and triangular objects while continuing to select
information from the spherical object, it will appear to him that he is attending to the
same object, while continuing to select information from the triangular object (or
from the corner which was visible to him before he started moving) the appearance
would be one of his shifting his attention to a different object.
In contrast, in the relevant cases of the copulating flies and the entangled bushes
(the cases in which the flies are of more or less the same size, etc.), it seems that if
there is a situation in which the objects are separated and the subject's continuing to
select information from one of them appears to him to be a case in which he is
116 As would happen, for example, if a subject who was attending to a tree will go on attending to a leaf or a
branch falling off the tree.
138
continuing to attend to one and the same object, then there will also be a possible
scenario in which if he continues to select information from the other object, while the
objects are separated, it will appear to him that he is continuing to attend to one and
the same object. (It might be the case that in all situations in which the objects are
separated, the appearance will be such that the subject realizes that what he took to be
one object was in fact two (it seems that this is what would happen in the blanket and
pyramid case)). Note also that the conditions in which there might be room for saying
that the subject is attending to one of the flies or bushes - say, when one of them is
significantly larger or occupies a significantly larger part of what is currently visible
to the subject - are conditions in which it seems plausible that there is an asymmetry
as to which fly or bush will appear to be the same as the object initially attended to
(while the other appears to be a different object or merely a fragment of the initial
object).
There are cases which seem to complicate the above suggestion, specifically
cases in which the change required for bringing about the separate bundling affects
the objects themselves in such a way that the change in the objects is sufficient for
explaining why the current information from any of them does not appear as from the
same object. I shall not try to deal with the various possibilities and what one may say
about them, partly because the way things will appear in such cases is an empirical
matter which, because these are not the kind of cases we encounter often, I can only
hypothesize about. It might be that in, at least, some of these cases it is not clear to the
subject whether or not any of the objects appear as the same after being separated. If
the suggestion is correct, cases of this type should also be ones in which it is unclear
which object is demonstrated.
What determines which conditionals and counterfactuals are true is the way in
which the visual system works: the way in which the information available to the
139
subject is organized by the visual system (where this should include any aspect of the
operation of the visual system relevant to whether or not different bits of information,
either simultaneous or successive, appear or would appear to the subject as
information from the same object. Location and gestalt organization principles are
surely relevant to this, but also the visual recognition of the object as of a certain
familiar shape, kind, etc., can play an important role). As mentioned earlier, the exact
details of how this is done need not be known. What matters is that there are such
mechanisms and thus that there are facts about what would and what would not
appear as one and the same object in certain conditions in a certain range of cases (as
well as facts about the conditions relevant to determining this range). (The range in
question excludes cases in which it is unclear, from the subject's point of view,
whether or not he continues to attend to the same object. It need not have a clear cut
boundary; what is important is that there are clear cases and that one can, generally,
characterize the type of factors which distinguish them from the unclear ones).
Note that this account of what it is for a particular bundle to be from a particular
object can be generalized to an account of what it is for a particular bundle of
information to be from something: a particular object, a definite combination of two
or more objects, some indefinite combination or a plurality of things, etc. For the
above suggestion identifies the thing (in this wide sense) on which its appearing to the
subject that he is seeing one particular object depends.
The subject's grasp of the relation between bundles and objects
I
The question, to repeat, is how, from the subject's point of view, the object he is
attending to - and, if he is entertaining a particular demonstrative thought about it, the
140
object the thought is about - is distinguished from any other particular object. The
suggested explanation is that the subject's selection of the object involves his
selection of a bundle of information (of the relevant type) which is from the object,
and that he grasps his current situation as one in which he is selecting such a bundle.
In the previous section I tried to clarify what it is for a certain bundle of information
to be from a certain object. The clarification involved appeal to facts about what
would appear to the subject to be information from one and the same object in
relevant possible situations. Assuming this is the way to understand what it is for a
bundle to be from a particular object, there is a need to clarify in virtue of what an
ordinary subject can be ascribed a grasp of this relation.
Such a grasp, I suggest, is simply part of the subject's primitive conception of
perception and objects. An ordinary sighted subject, operating in the types of
environments in which we normally operate, would undoubtedly have some grasp of
how various conditions may affect the way information is bundled. He should, for
example, take it that in the absence of movement (his and the objects') two separate
objects might appear to be one object, depending on their locations relative to each
other and to himself, their colours, light conditions, whether any of them is recognized
by him, etc.; that two attached objects moving together may appear to be one, and so
on. And he will take it that otherwise - i.e., if these and other conditions with similar
effects 117 do not affect the bundling - the information will be bundled according to
whether or not it actually is from one and the same object. 118 (As with other aspects of
117 The subject should also have a grasp of conditions which cause information from the same object to be
bundled separately. I shall ignore this aspect of the subject's grasp, as it is not immediately relevant to
clarifying what his taking a bundle to be from one object involves.
118 This asymmetric description (that is, speaking about conditions which may affect the bundling while
assuming that without their effect the bundling and the source of the information correspond) is preferred
here to speaking about general rules which are operative both in correct and incorrect bundling, since it
seems more suitable for capturing the subject's point of view. The latter type of general rules should be
relevant when one explains the way the visual system enables bundling.
141
his primitive conception, the subject need not know all the relevant conditions, and
may be mistaken about some of them; particularly about the exact range of cases in
which they apply and the exact way their effect in a given situation depends on further
conditions).
A subject who has no relevant doubts regarding the veridicality of his current
experience thus takes the information provided to him due to an appearance as of one
object to be from one object, but takes into account the possibility of a mistake. One
type of mistake he takes to be possible is that what appears to be one object is not in
fact so; where he takes it that if this was in fact the case, the appearance in question
would not enable him to attend to a particular object and to entertain demonstrative
thoughts. In addition, he also takes into account a less radical possibility; namely, that
what appears to be one object is one object but that some aspects of the appearance do
not provide him with information from the object but rather with (mis)information
from some other object (or part of object) or with misinformation which is a mixture
of (mis)information from a number of objects.
Consider, then, what it is that the subject takes into account in the second case.
The subject's grasp of such a possibility is his grasp that certain conditions which
affect the bundling may obtain. As he has a grasp of the way various conditions can
cause information from other objects to be bundled together with the object in
question (the one the appearance is of), he also grasps how, if such mistakes occur,
changes in the conditions can lead to the information from each of the different
objects being bundled separately. For example, he may grasp that information from
each of the objects would be bundled separately if they were viewed from a different
angle, or if he got closer, recognized the objects, saw them while at least one of them
was moving, saw them when they were somehow separated from each other, etc.
Now, the subject takes the appearance to be the appearance of a particular object; thus
142
he takes it that when the conditions change so that the information from the two
objects is bundled separately (and there is no further change in the conditions), further
information from the object the appearance was of would appear to be from the same
object (that is, it would be bundled with the information the subject has in virtue of
the initial appearance). For it is assumed that the only effect the changing conditions
have is that the information from the different objects is now bundled separately, thus
it is assumed that there are no conditions which prevent the bundling of further
information from the same object with the information currently available due to the
appearance in question.
Furthermore, this is exactly the condition the subject takes to be missing if what
appears to be one object is not in fact so. In such a case he takes it that changes in the
conditions which will separate the information are likely to result in the dissolution of
the initial appearance as of one object, or alternatively, that different changes in the
conditions, all similarly relevant to affecting the bundling, may allow that the current
information be bundled with information from different objects.
The claim, then, is that the way in which I have described the relation between
the bundle and the object it is from (when there is such an object) is the kind of
relation the subject takes to obtain between a particular object and the bundle of
information he selects when attending to this object, if the current appearance of the
object is affected by other objects as well. 119 This conception of what it is for a bundle
to be from one object is manifested in the way the subject uses the information in the
bundle and deals with the possibility of mistakes. Specifically, as long as he takes the
bundle to be from one object, he takes it to be the case that, although some of the
information might not be from the object, continuing to be sensitive to information
119 The same holds for his grasp of the possibility that at a later stage information from other objects would
be gathered simultaneously with information from the attended object.
143
from this bundle will ensure that he will keep being sensitive to the information
available to him from the object and, as far as possible, will be able to correct
mistakes by gathering more visual information. (Note that the conditions which may
make it impossible for the subject to correct 'bundling mistakes' are not limited to
conditions which affect the availability of the relevant information at the time, such as
the disappearance of the object from view. In some cases the factors relevant to the
individuation of the objects might be unobservable or at least not directly observable.
As mentioned earlier, in those cases in which two objects have to be separated from
each other in order for the information from them to appear as information from
separate objects, the appearance of the separation process can be misleading. Seeing
such a separation, a subject may experience it as the division of one object into two,
or it may be a case in which it is unclear to the subject whether what initially appeared
as one object was actually so. The subject will take such possibilities into account,
and have, at least, some partial grasp of the type of considerations which may be
relevant to inquiring further whether the two were or were not distinct objects. But
often the relevant considerations would relate to things which are not directly
observable: the objects' origin and history, their function, the designer's intention, and
so on). 120
I have been discussing the question of what it is for the subject to take a bundle
of information to be from a particular object, and implicitly also what it is for him to
take an object-appearance to be of a particular object. It was made clear that when the
appearance is not of one object the subject cannot select the required bundle and
120 The subject need not know in detail what the exact considerations are and might be mistaken about
several details, but he should be disposed to take certain types of considerations into account. (In the case
of artificial objects this means that the ability to demonstrate objects which are not physically distinct from
other objects, or which consist of a conjunction of separable objects, depends on the subject's having some
grasp of the relevance of considerations other than the causal considerations which seem to be more basic.
These issues require further discussion).
144
cannot entertain demonstrative thoughts. Note however that the structure of the
subject's grasp of the relation between a bundle and an object can be applied by the
subject when he does not take the experience at face value and therefore considers, in
general, what thing a particular bundle is from (thus allowing that the thing in
question is not necessarily a particular object but rather might be a (definite or
indefinite) combination of a plurality of objects, etc.). In such a case, the subject may,
on the basis of his experience, entertain thoughts about whatever it is that the bundle
is from. As mentioned earlier, we may find it natural to express such thoughts by
means of demonstrative expressions. But the thoughts themselves are of a different
type, as they do not involve the same commitments singular thoughts involve. 121
II
It is now possible to see more clearly how different this suggestion (the
suggestion that the subject's knowledge of which object he is demonstrating should be
explained by the fact that he grasps his situation as one in which the object of his
thought is the object the bundle he is selecting is from) is from a descriptive
suggestion (the suggestion that the subject singles out the object of a demonstrative
thought by selecting a bundle, which is in fact from a certain object, and taking the
object of the thought to be whichever object the bundle is from).
As mentioned earlier, the bundle which is supposed to be selected by the subject
when he attends to an object, and which is then taken by him to be relevant to the
121 One may be willing to accept that in such a case the subject's attempt to entertain a demonstrative
thought fails, but might argue that regardless of the subject's view as to what the appearance is of his
attempt to attend to what he takes to be an object should be regarded as his attending to whatever it is that
bundle is from in this wider sense. I should clarify that I am not denying that there is a sense in which he
can be said to be attending to that thing. However the notion of attention which I take to be required for
explaining the subject's ability to think demonstrative thoughts involves his conception of the type of thing
he is attending to and thus is specific to cases in which the appearance is in fact of one object. The subject's
conception matters exactly because principles regarding the object's causal structure are relevant to his
grasp of the relation between the appearance and the way the object is.
145
evaluation and appreciation of the demonstrative thoughts he entertains on the basis of
this act of attention, is partly individuated in terms of the object it is from: in addition
to information which the subject can currently be said to possess in virtue of a certain
appearance as of an object, the bundle should include the information which would
appear to be from the same object as long as he continues to gather information from
the relevant object. The descriptivist cannot deny this. The selection of further
information which appears to be from the same object is a necessary aspect of the
subject's attending to the object; it is an immediate result of his grasp of the situation
as one in which he is singling out a mind-independent object which has its own causal
progression. And, as clarified earlier, the restriction of the relevant information to
information gathered while information from the object continues to be gathered is a
further aspect of his grasp of what is involved in his visually keeping track of the
relevant object.
However, a descriptivist may agree that attending to an object as well as
thinking about it demonstratively must involve selecting a bundle which is
individuated by appeal to the object, but suggest that such a selection depends on a
prior descriptive identification of the object which requires only the selection of a
narrower bundle: a bundle which includes only the information the subject can be said
to have in virtue of the current appearance of the object; or to simplify the formulation
we may present the suggestion as requiring only the selection of a current objectappearance. A subject who selects a certain object-appearance can identify the
relevant object as the object which satisfies the description 'the object this appearance
is of. 122 This, in turn, will enable him to select the information which is available to
122 If objected that the subject's conception of what it is for an object to be from the bundle (or of what it is
for an object-appearance to be of one object) involves appeal to whether or not he continues to gather
information from this or that object, the descriptivist would reply that the subject can grasp this without
actually identifying any of the objects in question, he only has to grasp that the relevant conditionals relate
to whichever objects are the sources of the information in the (narrow) bundle (or of the appearance).
146
him as information from the same object when information from the object this
appearance is of continues to be gathered. 123
One problem with this suggestion is as follows. According to the descriptivist,
the selected appearance is supposed to play a role in determining the condition by
which the subject identifies the object. Thus it would not be sufficient to construe
such a selection as merely a matter of the subject's being sensitive, as a matter of fact,
only to the relevant object-appearance (say, in the context of a certain task). He must
have a grasp of what he is selecting as an appearance, something which he can view
as the appearance of a particular object. But the subject's grasp of a specific
appearance as an appearance is not independent of his grasp of it as the appearance of
the particular environmental aspect it is in fact an appearance of: from his point of
view what he experiences is the object and its properties (or possibly some other thing
- a combination of objects, etc. - and its properties), and it is only due to his grasp of
what is involved in his experiencing the particular object and properties (which he is
in fact experiencing) that he is able to single out the appearance in abstraction from its
source. That is, he can be said to select a mere appearance only in virtue of, first,
selecting an appearance which he does not grasp to be independent of a particular
object and, then, abstracting from this relation with the object. 124
Contrast this with the view I am suggesting. The current object-appearance is
supposed to play a special role in the individuation of the bundle and in the subject's
ability to select it. It provides a point of reference in relation to which we ask which
information appears to be from the same object: thus determining both what would
count as available information which appears as from the same object, and which
123 Searle's view of demonstratives in his 1983 (that the object is identified as 'the object which is causing
this experience') can be construed as such a suggestion.
124 Things are different if he believes that (or proceeds as if) he is hallucinating. But this cannot be the most
basic case, which is what the present discussion concerns.
147
bundle among those the subject is presently in a position to select is in fact selected.
But this role does not depend on the subject's selecting the appearance prior to and
independently of the identification of the object: for the current information to serve
as the required reference point, it does not matter that the subject's selecting the
relevant appearance is an aspect of his selecting the object.
Another contrast with a descriptive view is that according to it the subject's
grasp of the relations between the way things appear and the way they are is supposed
to determine a condition which the attended object satisfies (namely, the condition
that it be the object the relevant appearance is of) prior to his singling out the object.
But it is clearly implausible to assume that ordinary subjects have a general grasp of
these relations which, considered independently of its application in a particular
situations, is accurate and detailed enough to suffice for determining a condition
which, in all those cases in which it seems implausible to say that a subject cannot
single out the object, would pick out the object the appearance is actually of. The
view I am suggesting, in contrast, is not affected by such a problem. The subject's
grasp is required for making it the case that his actual relation with the object is
generally grasped as a relation of this type. Thus the details may be, to some extent,
mistaken or unknown, and to a large extent can be of a kind which the subject cannot
articulate without relying on his ability to refer to particular aspects of the
environment and to the states he is in.
The view, then, is that the subject's seeing a particular object as such is a matter
of there being a bundle of information which is, in fact, from the object in question
and which is currently available to the subject. (Where the fact that the information is
bundled the way it is is due to way the subject's visual system operates). Seeing the
object, the subject is in a position to visually single out the object: first, as a matter of
fact, continuous sensitivity to information which is in the bundle would enable the
148
subject to keep track of the object and generally to make sure that tasks he wishes to
direct towards the object will be controlled by information from the object. Secondly,
the subject has a general grasp of the relation between the information in the bundle
and the seen object and thus can knowingly single out the object in question. When he
does in fact single out the object, intending to be selectively sensitive to the
information in the relevant bundle, the fact that he grasps which object he is attending
to provides him with the ability to entertain thoughts about the object. When
entertaining a particular thought on the basis of his attention to the object, he
immediately takes the information in the bundle to bear on the evaluation and
appreciation of the thought (provided he has no relevant doubts as to the source of the
information), and further, his grasp of the object as the object the relevant bundle is
from is also manifested in the way he considers possible mistakes and reacts when he
believes that a mistake occurred.
The basicness of the subject's attention to an object
I
The aim of the discussion is to characterize a notion of attention to a seen object
which can play a role in the account of a demonstrative ability. So far I have focused
on the requirement that the subject's attention to the object provide him with
knowledge of which object is in question, but the further requirement was that the
relevant notion of attending to a seen object be explanatorily more basic than the
particular demonstrative ability it is supposed to give rise to. Does the notion of
attention to an object I have been appealing to (attention as involving the subject's
selection of the bundle which is partly individuated by reference to the object) satisfy
149
this latter requirement? I shall consider and reject two lines of reasoning which might
seem to support the claim that it does not.
II
Suppose, first, that one argues as follows. It was claimed that when a subject is
attending to an object in the relevant sense he grasps himself as attending to it,
knowing which object he is attending to. This is sufficient for ascribing to him a grasp
of what it is to apply any concept he takes to be applicable to objects he encounters in
his environment, a grasp which involves his taking the selected bundle to bear on any
such thought. But this seems sufficient for ascribing to him the specific demonstrative
ability which is based on the given act of attention. It thus follows that consciously
attending to an object implies the possession of a particular demonstrative ability. But
if the relevant notion of attention is thus inseparable from the particular ability to
think about it demonstratively, in what sense could the former be regarded as more
basic than the latter?
The reply is simple. The above explanation of why consciously attending to an
object in a particular situation entails having a particular ability to think about it
demonstratively is consistent with holding that the fact that, in the situation in
question, the subject has the relevant particular demonstrative ability plays no role in
explaining the fact that he is attending to the object, in the situation in question, in the
particular way he does. That is, the fact that he has the particular ability to think about
the object demonstratively in that situation, and the fact that it is the particular ability
it is, need not figure in an explanation of the fact that the subject is attending to the
object in that situation and that it is the particular act of attention it is. The opponent
has merely pointed out that attending to an object, given the relevant concepts and a
general grasp of what is involved in applying them to particular objects, is what
constitutes the subject's having the particular ability to think about the object
150
demonstratively in the situation in question. This does not imply an explanatory
dependence of his attention to the object on his having the particular demonstrative
ability. In fact if this is the correct picture, then the explanatory relation is the other
way round: given an unchanging general ability to apply concepts to particular objects
and a general grasp of conditions which apply in the case of seen objects, changes
regarding which object the subject is attending to (if at all), and which bundle of
information is selected by him (in virtue of this act of attention), can explain changes
as to which particular demonstrative abilities he has (if at all), but not vice versa.
I am not denying that the general ability to consciously attend to objects
depends on the general ability to think about them demonstratively (the latter is
necessary for a subject to have a primitive conception of perception and objects). But
the question under discussion is not how, in general, to explain the ability to think
about objects demonstratively in terms of something which does not depend on it at
all, but rather only how to explain, in particular situations, the fact that a subject has a
particular ability to think demonstratively about a particular object (specifically, the
focus was what makes it the case that it is one object rather than others which is the
object of the thought125). The claim is that the subject's particular act of attention to
the object in the given situation plays a central role in such an account, and that to
play this explanatory role all that is required is that the particular act of attention
being the particular act of attention it is will not depend on the possession of the
particular demonstrative ability this act of attention is supposed to explain.
Ill
However, there seems to be a stronger argument for the claim that attention to
125 The other aspect which the particular act of attention plays a role in explaining is the question of what
distinguishes between different demonstratives referring to the same object.
151
an object, as construed here, cannot be regarded as more basic than the demonstrative
ability it is supposed to give rise to. The relevant notion of attention is such that it has
to be the subject who is selecting the object and the relevant bundle (the bundle
consisting of the information which appears or would appear as from the same object
while information from the object the bundle is from continues to be gathered). But
one might argue that it is only when the subject takes a seen object to be the object of
a particular demonstrative thought, taking the information in an appropriate bundle to
bear on the evaluation and appreciation of this thought, that he can be said to be
selecting the object and bundle. It may then seem that attending to an object in the
required sense just is an actualization of the relevant demonstrative ability.
What justification is there for the claim that a subject can be said to be selecting
an object and the relevant bundle only in the context of entertaining a specific
demonstrative thought? One possible line of thought is this. Merely experiencing an
object as such makes it the case that the relevant bundle of information is available to
the subject (that is, first, information from the object which appears as information
from one and the same object is available to him, and secondly, his general grasp of
the relation between objects and the experience of objects, which he takes to apply in
the current situation, makes it the case that he has a grasp of which particular bundle
of information is relevant to his ability to single out any of the objects he is currently
experiencing and to his ability to keep track of it). The question then is what
additional element is required for making it the case that the subject is selecting the
relevant object and bundle rather than merely experiencing the object. Saying that the
subject is currently taking the object to be the object of a particular demonstrative
thought, selecting the information for the evaluation and appreciation of the thought,
would provide a neat explanation of the sense in which the subject is focusing on this
object. And the opponent would suggest that there is no alternative explanation.
152
But why should we agree to this? Suppose, first, that one suggests that what
distinguishes the currently attended object (or objects) from other experienced objects
is the fact that, at the sub-personal-level, resources are allocated in such a way that
there is more processing and continuous binding of information from the relevant
object (or objects); where from the subject's point of view we would describe the
result as a case of the object's being at the focus of one's view. 126 It is agreed that we
can focus in this sense on a very small number of objects at a time (at most four, but
some will argue that only one). Consider, then, a case in which one object is currently
focused.
The fact that the subject views the focused object as an object seems
sufficient for there to be a sense in which he is singling out the bundle consisting of
the relevant current information and information which would appear to be from the
same object as long as he continues to gather information from the object: his
conception is such that he takes this bundle to directly provide him with information
from the object and to enable him to keep track of it.
The opponent may complain that we need a sense in which the subject is
actually singling out this object (where if he cannot be said to do this, we should say
only that he is disposed to select the relevant bundle in the above sense). And the
mere fact that the object is focused is not sufficient for this. For the fact that this or
that particular object is focused at a time need not depend on the subject's intending
to focus on the particular object; for example, the relevant attentional mechanisms
could simply be drawn towards the relevant object; alternatively, focusing on a
particular object might take place while the subject is scanning the scene or be a result
126 Alternatively Campbell (2002) speaks about the object being highlighted, and of course it is also natural
to say that the object is at the centre of one's attention.
127 1 discuss this case in order to simplify. If more than one object is focused, then it would be suggested
that they are all singled out by the subject. And as long as relations between the bundles distinguish them
for the subject, we can also say that each of them is singled out by him; otherwise it would be a case in
which they are singled out as a group of objects (see footnote 108).
153
of the subject's intention to examine what can be found at a certain location. So, at
least when no relevant intention is involved, it cannot be said that the subject is
selecting the relevant object and bundle.
It is not obvious that there is room for such an objection, since it is not
immediately clear that the fact that objects are focused (as such) in these situation can
be independent from the subject's having some interest in particular objects, but in
any case, we may respond by pointing at cases in which the subject does have such
interest and argue that in these cases - whatever explains the fact that a particular
object happened to be focused - as long as the subject has some general interest in
experienced objects, this would make it the case that the subject is to be said to single
out the object (even if, only for a very short while).
The opponent might respond that those cases in which we agree that a general
interest allows saying that the subject is singling out the object, are also cases in
which the subject should be ascribed a particular demonstrative thought about the
object. For example, if the subject's general interest implies an interest in a currently
focused object (say, he is looking for a pen), then the subject currently has a
particular interest in this object: he is occupied, for example, with the question 'what
kind of thing is thisT.
We can agree that focusing on a particular with a general interest does very
often imply that the subject is to be ascribed a demonstrative thought without yielding
to the opponent. There seems to be room for distinguishing between a general interest
in objects which is part of a certain project (like looking for a pen, finding out
whether there are any obstacles on the route, etc.) and a more general sense in which
we can be said to be interested in objects - our general interest in objects due to their
role in the organization of the environment and to the fact that their causal unity is
central to the way we interact with the environment. And it is only due to the former
154
that focusing on an object immediately requires ascribing a demonstrative thought to
the subject. It might very well be that our attitude towards the environment is such
that there always is some more specific project with which focused objects are
connected (thus, that it is never the case that an object can be said to be selected by
the subject without his also entertaining a demonstrative thought about it), but we can
still distinguish between ascribing to the subject the relevant demonstrative thought
this entails and the more general aspect of his relation with the environment: the fact
that he is currently regarding the experience of the focused object as the experience of
a particular object which is thus singled out by him and could then be the object
towards which he directs various specific questions and intentions.
We may also put the reply to the opponent this way: a subject who is
entertaining a specific demonstrative thought is thus selecting the object as the object
of this particular thought and selecting the information as the information which he
takes to bear on the evaluation and appreciation of this particular thought. But we
wish to say that in doing so he is actualizing a general ability, an ability which is not
restricted to this particular thought. That he has such a general ability is explained by
the fact that he is currently singling out the particular object (and the relevant bundle
of information) thus grasping which object he is attending to (and therefore grasping
what it is to apply any of his relevant concepts to the object in question). Thus, his
attending to the object is an element of the demonstrative ability which is actualized
when he is entertaining the thought; it is not itself a specific actualization of the
demonstrative ability.
155
7 The role of knowing which object one is demonstrating
I
The view presented in Chapter 6 resembles, in various respects, Campbell's
account of demonstratives in Reference and Consciousness (2002). However, Campbell
does not seem to view as pressing the question which is the focus of Chapter 6 - that is,
how conscious attention, construed as more basic than the subject's ability to think
about the object demonstratively, can be what provides the subject with knowledge of
which object he is thinking about. At least one possible explanation for this is that on
his view the characterization of the functional role of a demonstrative need not involve
an appeal to the way in which, from the subject's point of view, the experience bears on
how to evaluate demonstrative thoughts and which implications can be drawn from
them. In this chapter I shall argue that this view is unjustified.
II
An account of what the knowledge of the reference of a demonstrative consists in
is constrained by the need for it to enable an account of how the knowledge of the
reference has the functional role it actually has. 128 In Chapter 6 I described this
functional role in a way which was intended to capture what seemed to me an intuitive
way of thinking about it. It was said that a subject who is thinking demonstratively
about an object on the basis of a certain act of attending to it immediately takes the
experiential information in a given bundle to bear upon the evaluation and appreciation
of the thought in question. Talk about the way the subject takes the information to bear
upon the evaluation and appreciation of the thought was meant as relating to the way
128 Campbell's discussion relates both to the subject's knowledge of which object she is thinking about
when entertaining a demonstrative thought and to her knowledge of which object is referred to when she
utters or hears a verbal report expressing such a thought. In both cases he speaks about the knowledge of
the reference of a demonstrative. I continue to focus on thought. For convenience's sake I shall
occasionally use 'knowledge of the reference (of a demonstrative thought)' and 'knowledge of which
object one is thinking about' interchangeably.
156
things are from the subject's point of view, that is, to his viewing certain judgements and
actions as correct, or appropriate, in the light of the information, given other intentions
and beliefs of his. (Where viewing an action or a thought as appropriate - given his
other prepositional attitudes - would, in the absence of physical obstacles, cause him to
act in the relevant way or make the relevant judgement). Given this characterization, the
account of the subject's ability to think about the object demonstratively, knowing
which object he is demonstrating, is constrained by the need to account for how his
knowledge can explain (causally and normatively) the fact that he takes the information
available to him from the object to bear upon the evaluation and appreciation of the
thought. The claim that the subject's attending to the object involves his selection of a
relevant bundle and taking this bundle to be from the object, immediately accounts for
this; it immediately follows that when his attention to the object is his basis for
entertaining a thought about the object, he takes the information in the bundle to bear on
the evaluation and appreciation of this thought (unless he has doubts regarding the
source of certain pieces of information in the bundle).
In contrast, when Campbell discusses the functional role of the knowledge of the
reference, he discusses only the relation between the relevant propositions and subpersonal input and output. If it is assumed that this aspect of the use of demonstrative
propositions is all that has to be accounted for when accounting for the fact that the
knowledge of the reference has the functional role it does, then the main issue is how
conscious attention to the object causes and justifies the selection of sub-personal
information for affecting the evaluation of the thought and the implication for action
drawn from it. The discussion of this issue, however, does not, by itself, require dealing
with how attention to an object (construed as more basic than the subject's ability to
think about the object demonstratively) can be said to single out the object for the
157
subject.
I shall argue that one cannot ignore, in this context, the common-sense
aspects of the use (namely, the relation between experiential information experienced as
being from the object, on the one hand, and judgements and intentional actions directed
towards the object, on the other hand), and thus that accounting for the relation between
knowledge of reference and its functional role requires a discussion of the sense in
which conscious attention singles out the object for the subject.
This may seem a minor point, for it seems that there are other ways to raise the
question of how conscious attention to the object singles out the object for the subject.
However, the constraint from the need to explain the subject-level aspect of the use is
also a constraint on how we should construe talk about the subject's knowledge of
which object he is thinking about. 130 Thus the following discussion helps clarifying that
the robust construal of knowledge of reference which I took for granted to be required,
is in fact required. (I should emphasize that I am not arguing that one can ignore the
aspect discussed by Campbell. I shall say more about this aspect in Chapter 9).
Ill
Why does Campbell, when discussing the procedures used for evaluating
demonstrative propositions and finding their implications for action, consider only input
and output at the sub-personal level? When first introducing the question of how
attention to the object affects the role that the experience of a particular object plays in
the way the subject verifies and acts upon the relevant demonstrative propositions,
Campbell mentions two types of explanation of why a subject makes a certain
129 Campbell is clear that the relevant notion of attention to an object is more primitive than the ability to
think about it demonstratively, e.g., p.45 (Hereafter, unless specified otherwise all pages references to
Campbell are to his 2002). He also emphasizes that what is in question is conscious attention, by which I
understand that it is a case in which the subject, in virtue of experiencing the object, singles it out. For
present purposes it will not matter whether or not this yields exactly the same notion as the one
characterized in Chapter 6.
130 As Evans points out on p.89, it is open to one to construe such talk as requiring no more than a causal
link between the object and the subject.
158
experience-based judgement or performs a certain visually-guided action directed
towards a demonstrated object: (i) by appeal to the way the object is experienced by the
subject - for example, explaining that S judges that this [an attended object] is blue
because it looks to him blue, (ii) by appeal to the relevant sub-personal processing - for
example, explaining that S judges that this [an attended object] is blue because the cellfiring in V4 is registering blueness at location;?. 131 ' 132 (It should be emphasized that
since we are discussing the functional role of the demonstrative element, the focus in (i)
is on the fact that accepting the proposition as true is due to the fact that the
demonstrated object, rather than anything else, is experienced as having the relevant
property and in (ii) the emphasis is on the fact that accepting the proposition as true is
due to the relevant information being registered at location/? rather than any other
location133).
Campbell says that both types of explanation seem legitimate (p.l 1), and later
(p. 16) that they are actually descriptions of different aspects of the same causal
process. 134 However, he then goes on to discuss only the second type of description, that
is, he discussed only the connection between conscious attention and the selection of
sub-personal information to affect judgements and action. The only passage which may
be read as suggesting a reason for ignoring the first type is on p. 15 where he says:
131 p.l 1. The example in (ii) is meant only to clarify which type of explanation is suggested; Campbell
mentions that an actual explanation may require appeal to other relevant brain areas, and that the appeal
to location has to be supplemented by appeal to Gestalt organization principles.
132 Similarly, we may explain implications for action by appeal to the effect of the way the object is
experienced on the way the action is performed, or by an appeal to the effect of sub-personal information
registered at location p on the performance.
133 The reason why this should be so is presented in Chapter 9.
134 On p.l 1 Campbell says: 'both types of explanation are, on the face of it, legitimate.' (my emphasis)
Thus it might be that in the end he does not think that both types identify a cause of the verification or of
the way in which one acts. Regarding implication for action his view is that several cases in which we
tend to think that there is a subject-level explanation of certain aspects of the action are such that we are
mistaken in this respect (see p.55. But this does not entail that this must generally be the case; thus he
might agree that subject-level explanations of the way one acts are legitimate, only that often we are
mistaken about whether a particular case should be explained in this manner). Also, I shall shortly point
out that there is room to suspect that according to Campbell subject-level explanations (as they are
normally construed; namely, as citing a cause the effect of which is due to the subject's taking it to be the
appropriate effect) are actually always mistaken. On the other hand, the formulations on pp. 15-6 seem to
suggest that the subject-level type of explanation can be regarded as legitimate.
159
Once we accept the legitimacy of B-type explanations [type (ii) above] at all, it is hard to see
how conscious attention could play a role in bringing it about that your verbal report is controlled
by a particular aspect of your conscious experience, except by bringing it about that your verbal
response is controlled by an appropriate aspect of the underlying information-processing.
The view seems to be that although the two types of explanation are descriptions
of different aspects of the same causal process, the level-crossing description (that is,
the one mentioning information-processing) is more relevant to accounting for the effect
conscious attention has on the process: the fact that conscious attention to the object
makes it the case that certain experiential information is selected to affect the judgement
is explained by the fact that conscious attention to the object makes it the case that subpersonal information from the object is selected to affect the judgement.
If such a claim is to justify ignoring the purely subject-level descriptions, then it
must be understood as the claim that there are two types of descriptions - (i)
descriptions of the sub-personal process in virtue of which the selected sub-personal
information controls the subject's judgement (in the sense that it plays a role in
determining which property the subject judges the object to have), and (ii) descriptions
in which the selected experiential information is specified as what controls the
judgement - and that for any case in which a description of type (ii) is true, there is a
description of type (i) which is a true description of the same process and which
explains the fact that the type-(ii) description in question is true. That is, it must be that
the effect which the selected experiential information has on the judgement is wholly
explained by the fact that by selecting specific experiential information one is selecting
specific sub-personal information and the latter then affects the judgement due to its
sub-personal processing. However, on this picture, if descriptions of type-(ii) are ever
true, then the relation between the experiential information and the judgement which
such descriptions are supposed to describe should not be read as what is normally
regarded as the type of causal relation typical to subject-level explanations; that is, the
160
effect that the selected experiential information can be said to have on the judgement is
not due to the fact that this particular experience is taken by the subject to justify the
judgement - that is, given his other prepositional attitudes, experiencing the object this
way makes it correct, from his point of view, to make the relevant judgement. (Of
course, those who hold that there is such an effect accept that it is underlain by certain
sub-personal information-processing. What is denied is the stronger claim that the subpersonal processing can suffice for explaining the fact that there is such an effect.) Thus,
not only is it the case that on this picture the subject-level explanation adds nothing to
understanding how conscious attention explains the use of the relevant procedure, also
what seems to be the common-sense understanding of such explanations turns out to be
mistaken.
The passage quoted above could be read as only pointing out that the truth of a
type-(i) description is necessary for the truth of a rype-(ii) description. It is thus possible
that Campbell ignores descriptions of type-(ii) simply because he assumes that
explaining the sub-personal effect of conscious attention is a more pressing task than
explaining the subject-level effect. In any case, my aim is to clarify that one should not
ignore the description of type-(ii) whatever the reason for this is.
I shall argue that the -way the object is experienced is causally relevant to the
control of judgements and actions, where the causal effect is due to the subject's taking
the experience to justify the judgement and the relevant ways of acting, and that for this
reason an account of how conscious attention affects the procedures used by the subject
cannot leave out the subject-level description (understood in the common-sense way). I
shall first discuss the effect on judgements and then comment on the effect on actions.
161
IV
The first claim I shall defend, then, is that the subject's selecting experiential
information and regarding it as relevant to his making a certain judgement is causally
relevant to whether or not he actually makes the judgement which the sub-personal
procedure is supposed to lead to; where its causal relevance is due to the subject's
taking the information to justify the judgement (rather than only due to an effect on the
way information is selected at the sub-personal-level). Thinking about the following
possibility may help seeing that this is the case. We may assume that when a subject
judges (on the basis of vision) that a seen object is F, there is a certain sequence of subpersonal processing starting with visual input from the object and resulting in the
activation of the concept of F (i.e., resulting in the neural activity which is specifically
necessary for a subject to apply the concept). Some stages of this sequence are surely
shared by the sequence which would lead to the subject's experiencing the object as F.
Suppose, however, that in the sequence resulting in an experience there are some stages
which are not shared by both sequences, and that a malfunction at one of these
additional stages may affect the experience in such a way that, while relevant processing
leads to the activation of the concept of F, the object is not experienced as F (it may,
then, be experienced as having a different property of the same dimension, or it may be
that regarding the relevant dimension the subject does not experience the object as
having any particular feature; for example, if F is a shade of red the object might appear
to be of a different colour or colourless). It seems that when this is the case there is a
sense in which the subject is inclined to judge that this is F, though as long as he is
sensitive to the way the object appears to him, he would not make such a judgement: he
would not take the propositions rthis is F1 to be true (unless he believes or suspects that
his experience is misleading in a relevant way). For judging that this is F, when one
intends an experience-based judgement, involves taking the way in which the object is
162
experienced to bear on whether the thought is true. Thus if the subject is sensitive to the
object's appearance, and has no specific beliefs or suspicions about the relevant aspect
of his experience not being veridical, he would not make the experience-based
judgement in question.
The main assumption here is that an ascription of a judgement implies that the
subject, in making the judgement, is rationally responsive to what he takes to be
evidence for or against it as well as to other propositional attitudes of his. The situation
in which he makes a judgement is contrasted with a situation in which, while intending
to make a judgement about some aspect of the attended object (say, its shape), at the
sub-personal-level a certain concept (e.g., the concept of round) is activated but the
subject does not take himself to have the kind of evidence which he takes, in that
situation, to justify judging that that concept applies to the object in question (that is, the
object does not appear to him round). In such a situation, the activation of the concept
might not reach consciousness at all (I assume that in such cases, though the subject is
unaware of any inclination to judge, say, that the relevant object is round, had he been
forced to make a statement about its shape, he would have stated that it is round), in
which case it seems indisputable that he should not be ascribed the relevant
judgement. 135 But even if he is aware of the relevant inclination, this will not amount to
a judgement, as long as the subject does not actually endorse the proposition as true.
And the claim is that the subject's endorsing the proposition as true depends on whether
or not he takes himself to have the type of evidence for its truth which, in that situation,
he takes to be relevant to the evaluation of the proposition (and does not have any
particular doubts regarding what he takes to be the relevant evidence).
135 The difference between this state and a state in which the subject acquires a belief without making an
explicit judgement is more complex; generally the latter, but not the former, should have specific
implications as to what the subject is disposed to judge in virtue of the way things appear to him and what
he will be disposed to judge on the basis of his memory of the experience. (The issue can be left aside as
the discussion concerns the procedures used in explicit evaluation of thoughts).
163
Note that the question of whether or not a subject endorses a certain proposition p
is a question as to whether his current state is such that he currently takes it to be the
case that p. The contrast between such a state and a mere inclination to judge would be
manifested in the way each of these states affect the subject's reasoning and actions.
When a proposition is endorsed as true it would affect reasoning and action according to
which implication the subject takes it to have for his thoughts and actions; an effect
which depends on the subject's being aware of his endorsing the proposition and on
what he takes to be its implications given his other occurrent prepositional attitudes. On
the other hand, the effect of a mere inclination is independent of which implication the
subject takes the endorsement of the relevant proposition to have; it is thus independent
both of the subject's awareness of the inclination, and of whether or not he takes it to
make the effect appropriate given his other prepositional attitudes.
It was said that the reason the subject does not make the relevant judgement in the
situations in question is that he does not take himself to have the kind of evidence which
he takes, in that situation, to justify judging that the relevant concept applies to the
attended object. There are two aspects to this relativization of what the subject takes to
be relevant evidence: first it seems that subjects, depending on their particular past
experience and general tendencies, may vary in what exactly they regard as evidence
and how reliable they take the evidence to be. Secondly, when intending to make a
particular judgement the subject has a certain conception of the type of evidence which,
in that particular situation, he takes to be relevant to the evaluation of the proposition
j -jy- _
and of the extent to which he is willing to rely upon them.
Thus the above claim is
consistent with the possibility that, for a certain subject, awareness of his having an
136 Such a conception may, in some cases, be quite fuzzy; the important point is only that in each
particular case there must be some such conception (where the case in which the subject does not accept
anything as evidence for or against the judgement might be regarded as a borderline case).
164
inclination of this type would serve as a basis for a judgement (which might be the case
if a subject who lacks conscious experience of certain features of objects which he can
see and can attend to, learns that his guesses regarding the relevant features are quite
reliable
). The point is only that normal subjects take the way an object is experienced
to bear on the evaluation of their thoughts about that experienced object; that they
regularly attempt to make judgements about the object on the basis of their experience
of it; and that when they do so, whether or not the object is experienced in a particular
way is causally relevant to whether or not they will actually make the judgement in
question. 1 ^8
The point of the above example was to show that due to the fact that the subject
takes his making an experience-based judgement to require his being responsive to the
way the object appears to him, the object's appearance is causally relevant to whether or
not he actually judges what he is inclined to judge in virtue of the sub-personal
processing. Now, whether or not the inclination to judge and the experience can actually
come apart in this way is an empirical matter. But the above point holds even if, given
the way our actual sub-personal mechanisms work, this is impossible. The causal
relation between the knowledge of the reference and the subject-level aspect of the
procedure has to be taken into account if one wishes to explain how the knowledge of
the reference causes not simply an inclination to judge but rather a judgement. For if
what the process leads to is a genuine judgement, and the judgement in question is
137 The case is supposed to be analogues to the imaginary blindsighted mentioned in Chapter 1 (we might
think of visual form agnosia or achromatopsia as a basis for such a story).
138 As mentioned above, Campbell's examples are about verbal reports rather than judgements. But this
should not make a difference. Suppose, for example, that due to the subject's consciously attending to the
relevant object, sub-personal processing of information from the object causes him to utter the sentence
'this is F'. If the object does not appear to him to be F, then according to the above discussion his
utterance does not express the judgement that this is F, thus his making the utterance cannot be regarded
as a case in which he verifies the proposition this is F.
165
experience-based, then whether or not the subject makes the particular judgement in
question is responsive to the way the relevant object appears to him. 139
One might point out that my description of what is required for the subject's state
to count as an experience-based judgement rather than a mere inclination to judge
makes it, at least in principle, possible that there are cases in which the sub-personal
processing by itself (that is, without the specific way the object is experienced affecting
whether or not the subject endorses the proposition) results in a judgement (while the
claim was that the sub-personal processing by itself can only yield an inclination to
judge). This is so because what is required for ascribing to the subject a judgement
rather than a mere inclination to judge is a (rational) disposition to fit the judgement to
the way the object is experienced when he is sensitive to the way the object is
experienced (that is, to whether the object is experienced as having the relevant
property). It is thus, at least in principle, possible that there be occasions on which the
subject is disposed in the relevant way without the specific way the object is
experienced causally affecting the judgement.
Suppose, for example, that a subject is attending to a seen object and considering
what shape it has. Suppose that at the sub-personal-level the correct information is
selected and processed, and that consequently a certain shape concept, say square, is
activated, and that due to this the subject is inclined to judge that this is square-shaped.
It seems possible that this inclination brings it about that the subject judges that this is
square-shaped when he is not sensitive to which shape the object appears to have but
mistakenly takes himself to have been sensitive in the required way to the object's
139 Note that a discrepancy between the experience and what the subject is inclined to judge (in virtue of
the activation of a concept) might occur due to a malfunction at a stage which is specific to the process
leading to the activation of the concept (and it seems quite likely that such cases can and do occur). I did
not appeal to this possibility in arguing that the experience plays a role in the process, since I wanted it to
be clear that experience plays the relevant role when all aspects of the procedure captured by the subpersonal description are in order.
166
appearance. It seems, for example, that this might happen if the subject considers the
question of the object's shape hastily, and immediately after making a hasty judgement
becomes occupied with some other task. 140 As he intends to make an experience-based
judgement and takes himself to be responsive to the way the object appears to him, his
state is not a mere inclination to judge (he endorses the relevant proposition). Still his
making the judgement is not affected by which shape he experiences the object as
having (had the processing of the input resulted, say, in the activation of the concept
round, all other things being equal, the subject would have judged that this is round).
Thus there seems to be a counterexample to the claim that the sub-personal process by
itself cannot result in a judgement.
However, this description of the situation is misleading. The fact that the subject
is disposed to take the experience to bear upon the evaluation of the thought (which is
necessary for it to be the case that the situation is one in which he can be ascribed a
judgement) is simply part of what constitutes the particular procedure he is using: a
procedure which, when he is sensitive to the relevant aspect of the object's appearance,
makes this aspect of the appearance causally relevant to whether or not he makes the
judgement. In the situation described above, the subject uses this procedure, but fails to
do so successfully.
To recap, the question was whether it is possible to account for the way the
knowledge of the reference of a demonstrative causes a subject to use particular
procedures leading to an experience-based judgement about that object without taking
into account the subject-level description of the procedure. I first argued that if we
completely ignore the subject-level description of the procedure, then we are actually
considering procedures which result in a mere inclination to judge rather than in a
140 There might be reasons for denying the plausibility of such cases. Note, however, that the problem
addressed here arises only if situations of this type are (at least in principle) possible.
167
judgement,
while what we wanted to explain was the way knowledge of reference
causes the procedures leading to judgements. The objection then was that there might be
cases in which a subject can make an experience-based judgement about an attended
object without the relevant aspect of the way the object is experienced playing a role in
the causal explanation of the fact that the subject makes this particular judgement. In
response it was pointed out that it is still the case that the procedure used in these cases
is of the type which cannot be described accurately without appeal to a possible subjectlevel effect on the judgement, and that it is only due to the aspect of the procedure
which requires the appeal to the subject-level description that applying the procedure in
the described situation yields a judgement.
V
It might seem that the above argument is flawed since I have ignored the effect
that the subject's knowledge of which property is predicated may have on the selection
of the procedure. An objector may claim that if we take into account both the effect of
the subject's knowledge of which object he is thinking about and his knowledge of
which property is predicated (when evaluating the truth value of a given proposition),
then we would have a satisfactory account of what causes the selection of the relevant
judgement-yielding procedures without a need to appeal to a subject-level description of
the procedure. The thought, it seems, is that, an experience-based judgement as to
whether a seen object has a property which can be decided on the basis of vision,
involves, in addition to the subject's conscious attention to the object, his conscious
attention to the relevant property of the object. For example, it may be suggested that
the subject's conscious attention to the property is what ensures that the sub-personal-
141 Or rather 'we are considering an aspect of our actual procedure that, by itself, only explain how the
subject comes to have the relevant inclination'.
168
level procedure required for the judgement will involve the correct type of visual
information, e.g. shape information rather than, say, colour information. 142 It is
unquestionable that the subject's intentionally attending to a seen property of a seen
object is guided by the relevant aspect of the way he experiences the object, namely, its
being experienced by him as having the relevant property. Thus it may seem that the
subject's experience of the object as having the relevant property is acknowledged as
causally relevant to the subject's judgement and therefore there is no need for a further
appeal to a subject-level description of the procedure which is selected due to the
subject's attention.
Now, the suggestion mentioned in the previous paragraph - that attention to the
property is required for selecting information about the relevant property at the subpersonal-level - does not depend on which particular property (of the relevant
dimension) the object is experienced as having. For this reason, the mere fact that the
attended property is experienced as the property of the relevant object is not sufficient
for affecting the judgement in the way which I have claimed to be necessary for the
procedure to be a judgement-yielding procedure: whether or not the subject makes a
judgement he inclined to make depends on whether it appears to him that the object has
the specific property predicated (or at least, that he takes it that this is how the object
appears to him).
Suppose, however, that we were offered a view on which the effect of the
subject's knowledge of the property on the selection of the procedure did depend on the
subject's experiencing the object as having a specific property F. This would still not
suffice for showing that the subject-level description of the procedure is not needed for
ensuring that the procedure yields judgements rather than merely inclinations to judge.
142 Campbell suggested such a view in a seminar.
169
The point of the above discussion was that if the procedure (selected in virtue of the
subject's attention to the object and property) is to be of a type which results in a
judgement, then there is a need for the procedure itself to include the subject's
sensitivity to whether or not the object is experienced as being F. The fact, if it is one,
that the experience of the object as F plays a role in causing the judgement due to its
playing a role in determining which procedure is to be carried out does not imply that it
also affects his decision as to whether or not to endorse the proposition he is inclined to
judge (due to the relevant sub-personal processing), and thus does not imply that a subpersonal description of the procedure suffices for ensuring that it is a judgementyielding procedure. (This would be manifested when there is a discrepancy between the
experience and the activated concept due to a malfunction at a stage of the processing
which results in the activation of the concept; the relevant experience may affect the
selection of the information for the procedure, but then only the activation of the
concept would be relevant to determining the content of the alleged judgement). Thus it
is still the case that if we ignore the effect of the subject's attention to the object on the
subject-level aspect of the procedure, we will not have a full understanding of how the
procedures which result in judgements are caused.
VI
I turn now to the implication that a demonstrative thought has for visually-guided
intentional actions. The subject-level description, I maintain, plays here a similar role to
the one it plays in the case of judgements. The claim is that an appeal to the relation
between the knowledge of the reference and the subject-level description of the
procedures leading to the actions is required for the relevant procedures to be of a type
which yields intentional visually-guided actions.
170
It may seem that there are clear counterexamples to this claim. In Chapter 4, when
discussing the role played by the experience of unattended aspects in explaining action,
I mentioned that in several cases in which the subject directs a visually-guided action
towards a seen object (for example, common cases of reaching out towards a glass
which is in front of one at a hand-reaching distance away from one) there is no subjectlevel monitoring of the way the subject reaches out towards the glass. Thus, it may seem
that in such cases we should accept Campbell's picture according to which all we can
say about the relation between the demonstrative proposition and its relevant
implication for actions is that the subject's attending to the object makes it the case that
the right sub-personal information - the information from the object which is required
for setting the parameters for the action - is selected.
However, even in cases of this type (that is, when no further subject-level
monitoring is involved), questions like whether the object appears to the subject to be at
a hand-reaching distance, whether it appears to be of a size and shape which are
graspable without any need for special manoeuvres, etc., can matter to whether the
subject intends to act one way or another, and thus to whether his acting in the relevant
way, when acting this way, is intentional (under the relevant description). If, for
example, the object appears to the subject beyond reach or he simply cannot visually
detect its distance, or if it appears to be too large for grasping with his hand, then he will
not have the intention to grasp it by merely reaching out with one hand and grasping it
(as he does in ordinary cases in which he performs such an action).
I am not denying that, at least in principle, there can be cases in which a subject
simply intends to pick up the object and the sub-personal mechanisms are wholly
responsible for determining the course of the action (including whether the subject just
reaches out to the object or first stands up and walks a few paces towards it; whether he
reaches with one hand or two, and so on). But this does not seem to be the general case.
171
There are cases in which we are aware of the type of action that is required in the
current situation in order to pick up a particular object (given its distance, direction,
size, shape and so on): and such awareness could matter to whether or not we intend to
pick it up in the situation in question (for example, I may wish to pick it up only if this
does not require me to stand up, or only if I think I can grasp it with one hand).
Furthermore, as explained in Chapter 4 such awareness can be relevant to whether or
not the subject changes his course of action. (Note that in both cases there is no
implication that the subject has to explicitly consider any particular aspect of the
action).
VII
I shall end with a brief comment on the role of the knowledge of the reference in
justifying the procedures which the subject uses in evaluating and acting upon
demonstrative thoughts. Campbell clarifies that the sense in which he means that
knowledge of reference justifies the use of the relevant procedures is that it determines
what their aim (or point) is, thus setting the standard in relation to which one can ask
whether the procedures used by the subject are correct or not. 143 In this way Campbell
clarifies that he is not committed to saying anything about what justifies the procedures
from the subject's point of view. Now, I have just claimed that the subject's having a
grasp of which procedures he should use and whether he is actually using them is an
essential part of the practice of making judgements, reasoning and acting intentionally
143 Note that there are two ways in which the procedures can be evaluated: we can ask whether the correct
type of procedure has been selected (specifically, whether the sub-personal selection of information for
the control of a thought or action is of the type which normally ensures selection of information from the
attended object); secondly, we can ask whether a given procedure is carried out correctly. It seems that
Campbell is mainly thinking about the former question (see, for example, pp.26 & 87), but occasionally
he points out that determining the aim is what enables an evaluation of particular performances (e.g.,
p.226). In any case, one may say that when the correct procedure is selected (or carried out), the question
of what makes it correct is to be answered by indicating its aim, and in this sense attention to the object
can be said to justify it.
172
(e.g., the claim that making judgements involves some conception of the procedures
which the subject is currently taking to be relevant to the evaluation of the thought, and
a disposition to make the judgement only if he takes himself to be evaluating the
thought in the relevant way). Thus the above discussion immediately implies that we
should also think about the knowledge of the reference as playing a role in determining
the aim of the procedures/or the subject; thus playing a role in his evaluation of the
appropriateness of the procedures.
173
8 Demonstratives and spatial location: Evans's view
I
It is widely agreed that spatial location plays a central role in our ability to
entertain demonstrative thoughts about seen objects, though views differ as to what
this role is. In this and the next chapter I criticize the views of Evans and Campbell on
this matter. The comparison with the two views will clarify the role location plays in
the suggestion outlined in Chapter 6.
II
According to Evans, the fact that a subject can, on the basis of an ordinary
perceptual information-link with an object, spatially locate the object which he is thus
linked to is what explains the fact that experiencing the object (that is, the fact that
there is an ordinary information-link between them) provides the subject with a
genuine ability to think about it (i.e., an ability to entertain singular thoughts which
are about it). 144 In what follows I shall describe Evans's argument for the need to
appeal to the ability to locate the object. I shall then point out that reading Evans as
requiring that the subject have knowledge of the object's location, rather than merely
an ability to locate it, renders the view implausible. Finally I shall argue that (given
what seems to me the most plausible view of what such an ability involves) the ability
to locate the object can play the role it is supposed to play in the account of
demonstratives only if the subject already satisfies the condition which would allow
him to think about the object, and consequently that the ability to locate the object
144 See for example 1982 p. 150. Evans's claim is meant to apply to ordinary perceptual information-links in
general; I discuss only its application in the visual case. It should also be remembered that I construe talk
about the information bearing on the evaluation and appreciation of the thought as referring to the subject's
view of the relation between the information and his thoughts and actions, while at least some of Evans's
formulations suggest that he construes such talk in terms of brute dispositions.
174
cannot play the role it is supposed to play. The argument will clarify how the
alternative suggested in
Chapter 6 stands in relation to Evans's view.
Why does Evans take the ability to locate the object to be necessary? Evans
clarifies that if an alleged demonstrative thought is to be a genuine singular thought, it
must conform to the generality constraint; that is, the subject must be able to entertain
any thought of the form 'this is F' (where the demonstrative element refers to the
same object in the same way) for any property F of which she has a concept (allowing
for category restrictions). That subjects have such an ability, he claims, is explained
by their understanding of what it is for the relevant object to be identified according to
what he calls 'the fundamental ground of difference of that object', which is 'a
specific answer to the question "What differentiates that object from others?", of the
kind [generally] appropriate to objects of that sort' (p.107). 145 In the case of spatiotemporal objects, which are the type of objects under discussion here, this will be an
understanding of what it is for the object to be identified by its sort and its spatial
location at a particular time (where the way in which the subject identifies the object's
location must be such that he knows what it is for this location to be distinct from any
other location). Thus for a subject to be ascribed a singular thought about a spatiotemporal object, he must either know its sort and its spatial location at a certain time
and think about it as an object of this sort, occupying that location at that time, or
have a way of identifying the object which is such that he knows what it is for an
object identified in this way to be identical with some particular object identified by
145 How does this explain the conformity to the generality constraint? According to Evans, our grasp of the
concept of being F consists in knowledge of what it is for an arbitrary object (of a category to which the
concept applies), identified according to its fundamental ground of difference, to be F. Thus, once one
knows what it is for an object to be the object identified according to its fundamental ground of difference,
one also knows, for any relevant concept F he grasps, what it is for that object to be F.
175
its sort and spatial location at a certain time. (In the latter type of case what is required
is that, in addition to a general understanding of what it is for an object to be of a
certain sort and to be located at a particular place at a particular time, the subject
should have some way of distinguishing the object from any other object. Thus, for a
subject to grasp what it is for an object to be identified according to its fundamental
grounds of difference is for him to have a distinguishing knowledge of the object. In
what follows saying that a subject has distinguishing knowledge of a certain object
should be construed as saying that the subject satisfies the above conditions regarding
that object 146).
The need to appeal to the ability to locate the object on the basis of a given
information-link (when explaining ordinary perceptual demonstratives) arises,
according to Evans, since the mere obtaining of an information-link between the
subject and the object does not supply the subject with the required distinguishing
knowledge. To elaborate on Evans's example, a subject who is watching television
and attending to a particular image of a plant seen on the screen147 may have
continuous information from the plant whose image it is, which he can then take to
bear on the evaluation and appreciation of certain thoughts he entertains (thoughts
which he might express by sentences of the form 'this plant is F\ but which are not
simple demonstrative thoughts according to Evans). Evans claims that the fact that
there is such a link by itself- that is, without taking into account the fact that, in some
sense, the subject takes himself to be seeing the plant on television - cannot suffice for
him to have distinguishing knowledge of the particular televised plant. He argued in
146 Also, since a subject who knows the object's sort and location at a time trivially knows what it is for an
object identified this way to be identical to an arbitrary object identified by its sort and location at a time, I
shall often, instead of explicitly specifying the two conditions, just say that the subject is required to grasp
the truth conditions of the above type of identity proposition.
147 1 say that the subject attends to the image rather than to the plant since the claim that in such a situation
he attends to the plant is at least controversial, while to the extent that he is, he does this via attending to the
image (his keeping track of the same plant is directly responsive to changes of the image, and only in virtue
of this also to changes in the plant).
176
an earlier chapter (Chapter 4) that the mere obtaining of a causal link between the
object and the subject does not, by itself, constitute the subject's distinguishing
knowledge;
thus such knowledge could only be provided by the information with which the link
provides the subject. But, any description of the plant which the subject can form on
the basis of the information provided by the information-link (excluding information
about the plant's location relative to himself) may be satisfied by more than one plant.
Similarly any description of the plant's location which the subject can form on the
basis of the information from the plant and its surroundings (again excluding
information about egocentric location) may be satisfied by more than one location.
The information about egocentric location, on the other hand, cannot be relevant to
his knowledge of the plant's location since there is no systematic dependence of the
apparent egocentric location on the plant's actual egocentric location. In those rare
cases in which the plant will be where it appears (egocentrically) to be, this will be a
result of a rare coincidence or a special arrangement of the situation.
In contrast, according to Evans, when simply seeing an object, the subject can
locate it relative to herself on the basis of the information-link, and this guarantees
that she has discriminating knowledge of the object. 148 When the subject's visual
experience provides her with information about the object's location which is
veridical and specific enough to exclude the possibility of a plurality of objects (of a
relevant sort) occupying it at the same time, it is quite straightforward that Evans's
148 One might object to this reasoning, pointing out that had Evans been considering only ordinary
perceptual information-links rather than a wider range of information-links, it would have been false that
the existence of the information-link and the subject's taking the information to bear on the evaluation and
appreciation of the thought do not suffice for having distinguishing knowledge of the object (for such an
objection see Peacocke 1991). As far as I understand, one reason why Evans does not start by considering
such a restricted range of information-links is that it is not clear how to draw the line between ordinary and
non-ordinary links. Secondly, the point of the discussion is to bring out what makes it the case that ordinary
perceptual information-links as opposed to other information-links provide the subject with discriminating
knowledge of the object (and Peacocke seems to accept that the ability to locate is what explains this).
177
conditions for having distinguishing knowledge of the object are satisfied. If the
subject knows the thing's sort and knows where she is located (relative to some
objective frame of reference), then she can identify the object according to its sort and
location at a time; if she does not know the thing's sort or is, at present, lost, she still
knows what it is for it to be the case that the object which is at position p (specified
egocentrically) now is identical with some object of some sort G located at a
particular place (specified objectively) now to be true. This is so because we have
some conception of a unified space (in which places are individuated by their
relations to other objects, regardless of our current relation to them) and a general
ability to find out where we are located relative to this frame of reference, as well as a
general ability to find out the sort of objects we encounter. 149
Thus, at least when the subject's experience supplies him with veridical
information about the object's egocentric location which is specific enough (to
exclude the possibility of its being occupied by a plurality of objects of a relevant
sort), the subject has distinguishing knowledge of the object as Evans requires. It is,
however, implausible to hold that a subject's (simple) ability to think demonstratively
about seen objects is restricted to cases in which he actually has such veridical
information about the object's egocentric location. There are several cases in which it
seems implausible to hold that a subject is not able to entertain simple demonstrative
thoughts about a seen object even though its apparent location differs from its actual
location (as, for example, when an object is seen through a shifting prism), or is not
149 In this brief presentation of Evans's view, I am ignoring difficulties regarding his view as to what the
objective way of identifying locations involves. It is not entirely clear what his view is, and it has been
argued that at least the more obvious readings yield an implausible view. All that matters for the present
discussion is that there should be some way in which subjects grasp the idea of one unified space which is
objective in the sense that places in it can be identified in ways which do not depend on any specific point
of view of the subject. I shall also ignore difficulties regarding the egocentric mode of identification of
locations.
178
specific enough (as is the case, for example, with the apparent distance of distant
objects and of objects seen against an empty background).
At least on the face of it Evans does not hold the implausible view that for
having distinguishing knowledge of a seen object - and thus for having the ability to
think about it demonstratively - a subject must actually know the object's egocentric
location. He seems to require only that the subject be able to locate the object
(egocentrically) on the basis of the information-link (where a subject's having such an
ability is also described as his effectively being able to locate the object, and as
having an effective method for locating it). 150 But this raises the question what exactly
is meant by an ability to locate the object, and how such an ability is supposed to be
relevant to the subject's knowledge of what it is for the relevant identity propositions
to be true; or more specifically, to his knowledge of what it is for the object he is
demonstrating to be the object presently located in a particular location which he
identifies egocentrically. In what follows I shall suggest a construal of this ability
which, given the facts about the information available in visual experience regarding
objects' spatial locations, seems to me the most plausible construal of the type of
ability Evans is appealing to. I shall then point out a difficulty for one who holds that
such an ability to locate the seen object is what explains the subject's ability to
discriminate it (in Evans's sense).
Evans does not expand on what he means by the subject's ability to locate
On p. 172 Evans says: 'in a great many cases a subject may make a demonstrative identification of an
object without actually knowing where it is. The information-link with the object may enable the subject
effectively to locate the object without providing very specific information about its location - for example,
when one is able to home in upon a beetle eating away in a beam.' Furthermore, in his formulations of what
the ability to think demonstratively requires he is careful to speak about the ability to locate rather than just
knowledge of the location. (Peacocke stresses this in his reply to McDowell, 1991, pp. 124-5). Nevertheless
both McDowell (1990) and Campbell (2002 pp. 111-3) read Evans as holding that the subject's ability to
think demonstratively about an object requires his actually knowing the object's egocentric location.
Campbell takes this to be a serious flaw for the reason I have just mentioned in the text, while McDowell
simply ignores the difficulty.
ISO
179
perceived objects. However the examples he gives, his emphasis that what enables the
subject to locate the object is the fact that there is an information-link between the
subject and the object (as opposed to an ability which would rely on the subject's
thought about the link), and the emphasis on the practical nature of the ability
suggests the following construal.
When a subject attends to a seen object he has some experiential information as
to where it is in relation to himself. 151 In addition, when the information he currently
has is not accurate or not specific enough (for some relevant purpose; in the present
discussion, the purpose of distinguishing the object), certain movements of the subject
(or object, as well as certain changes in environmental conditions) may enable him to
gather more specific and more accurate information about the object's location.
Consequently, when the subject's current information about the object's location is
inaccurate or not specific enough, there is something he can do (in favourable
conditions) which may provide him with more specific and more accurate information
about its location (and thus, if the conditions are favourable, he may, ultimately, have
specific enough veridical information about its location). For example, a subject who
sees an object at a distance and consequently is only provided by his experience with
rough information about the distance between the object and himself can, by moving
towards the object while continuously attending to it, bring himself to a position in
which he has specific, accurate information regarding the distance between the object
and himself (assuming the conditions are favourable); similarly, such movement can
enable a subject, who has non-veridical information about the seen direction of an
object due to a the refraction of the light from it, to bring himself to a position in
which he has (specific) accurate information about the object's direction.
151 Visual experience always provides some information about location even if in some cases this is rather
unspecific. (Even patients suffering from visual-disorientation would not mistake the location of a seen
object beyond a certain range).
180
It is not immediately clear that the claim that there is something the subject can
do (in favourable conditions) in order to gather veridical information about the
object's location which is specific enough for individuating it applies to all cases in
which a subject can entertain simple demonstrative thoughts despite not having such
information at present. Or more accurately, since one can fiddle with what the
relevant favourable conditions are, the difficulty is that it is not clear that for any
relevant case there is a sense in which the subject can be said to have an ability to
locate the object in certain favourable conditions where ascribing this ability to him is
also relevant to his knowledge of what it is for the object to be in the particular
location it is. 152 The more crucial question, however, is how, when a subject can be
said to have such an ability in the most straightforward sense, the fact that he has it is
relevant to his knowledge of what it is for the object to be in the particular location it
is. In what follows I focus on the straightforward cases and argue that even then this
question raises a problem for the view.
How then is the ability a subject has in cases like the two simple examples
mentioned above relevant to his knowledge of what it is for the object to be located in
the particular (egocentrically specified) location it is? A minimal requirement seems
to be that the subject have some grasp of the fact that he has such an ability, a grasp
which he takes to be relevant to the question of the object's actual location. And it
seems that, at least in the unproblematic cases, this condition is satisfied: as with any
other seen feature of seen objects, grasp of what may enable gathering more accurate
and specific information and of the conditions which may prevent this is part of the
subject's primitive conception of perception and objects. Thus it seems that there is a
152 For example, it seems that there is nothing patients suffering from visual-disorientation can do in order
to gather accurate and specific enough visual information about the object's location. Thus, if one is to
ascribe to them an ability to locate the object, one should count the normal functioning of the visual system
as part of the relevant favourable conditions. The question, then, is whether an ability to locate the object
construed in this way is relevant to their knowledge of what it is for the object to be in a certain location.
181
sense in which a subject takes himself to have an ability to locate seen objects (that is,
an ability to gather specific, accurate information of the location, if the information he
currently has is not accurate or specific enough) and takes this to be relevant to the
question of where the seen object is located in relation to himself.
However, what matters to the subject's knowledge of what it is for a particular
object he is seeing in a particular situation to be in the particular location it is is his
grasp of his ability, in that particular situation, to locate that particular object.
Further, if his grasp of the particular ability is to be a basis for such knowledge, it
must involve a grasp of the difference between cases in which exercising his ability
results in his successfully locating the relevant seen object and cases in which it does
not. 153 (It should be emphasized that what is required is a grasp of the difference, not
an ability to tell in each particular case whether it is successful or not). But it seems
that to grasp this, the subject must already be able to identify the seen object: he has to
grasp, for example, that in order to gather more specific information about the
location of the seen object he should move towards it while continuously attending to
it. If so, then it seems that the ability to locate the object cannot be necessary for
explaining the subject's possession of his discriminating knowledge of the object. For
as explained earlier, having some way of identifying an object suffices for a subject to
know what it is for this object to be identical to an object identified according to its
sort and location at a time.
Why must the subject be able to identify the object? Suppose there was no such
requirement and that what he grasps was specifiable without reference to the object
(to be exact, reference to the object should not appear in the scope of what is
153 More accurately, if (as seems more accurate) cases of exercise of the ability are to be individuated by
appeal to the object itself, the requirement is that the subject be able to grasp the difference between cases
in which he successfully exercises the ability and cases in which he does not. (I use the less accurate
formulation since the more accurate one makes it difficult to see what the distinction in question is).
182
supposed to be part of the content of what he grasps); thus, suppose it was specifiable
by descriptions of movements the subject can make, ways in which things appear to
him, and environmental conditions all of which can be given without reference to the
object (again, within the scope of what the subject is said to grasp). The difficulty
would then be to explain the subject's grasp of the (actual) difference between
successful and unsuccessful cases; for example, to explain his grasp of the difference
between his moving towards the seen object and his moving first towards one object
then towards another when the shift of his attention from the one to the other is
unnoticed by him. (Where such a grasp is necessary if the subject's ability to locate
the object is to be the basis for his knowledge of what it is for the object to be in the
location it is).
It may seem that there is a simple way in which a subject can distinguish
between successful and unsuccessful cases without identifying the particular object in
question; he only needs to grasp that a successful case is, for example, one in which
he actually continues to move towards, and to attend to, one and the same object
(whichever object that is). But, as pointed out above, he must be able to understand
what would make particular exercises of the ability, in a particular situation,
successful or not, and for this it is not sufficient that he grasps that the information
could be gathered by, say, moving towards one and the same object. It also has to be
the case that the object he moves towards is the object the location of which is in
question. But to grasp this some mode of identification of the object is required.
One might try to ascribe to the subject such a grasp by appeal to what seems a
quite plausible assumption: that for any situation in which an unsuccessful exercise of
the ability appears to the subject as a successful one there are some aspects of the
situation (e.g., the position from which the subject views the object(s)) such that had
these aspects been different in certain ways, it would have appeared to the subject that
183
his exercising the ability is unsuccessful: that he is not gathering more accurate
information about the location of one and the same object (i.e., in the type of
examples discussed here, it would have appeared to the subject that he is not moving
toward one and the same object). But an attempt to appeal to this assumption in order
to explain in virtue of what the subject can be said to grasp the difference between
successful and unsuccessful cases (without presupposing that he can identify the
object) seems misguided.
First, it seems that there is no simple way in which one could distinguish
between successful and unsuccessful cases only by appeal to how things appear to the
subject at present and how they would have appeared to him in relevant possible
situations. It is not simply that only the unsuccessful cases of the subject's exercising
his ability are such that they either appear to the subject as unsuccessful or would
have appeared so if some aspect of the situation had been different. There are
situations in which the subject's exercising his ability to locate the object could have
resulted in his correctly locating it even though it would not appear to him to be such
a case; for example, it can happen that when a subject moves towards one object,
while 'keeping his eyes on it', it (visually) appears to him that he loses track of it and
continues moving towards a different object. Thus it is impossible to distinguish the
unsuccessful cases as those which at least in some relevant counterfactual situation
would appear unsuccessful, and it does not seem that a more complex story would
help here.
Secondly, even if this difficulty could be dealt with, the question is in virtue of
what the subject could be said to take the required sets of possible situations to be
relevant to his grasp of what distinguishes successful from unsuccessful cases of
exercising the ability in the current situation. For example, what makes it the case that
a subject who is looking at an object takes the following situations - (i) the various
184
possible future situations in which he changes his current position in such a way that
it appears to him that he is keeping track of the object while moving towards it, and
(ii) for each such situation the various possible situations that differ from it in ways
which may affect the appearance (e.g., situations in which he moves differently, light
conditions or the background differ, etc.) - to be relevant to the question of how he
could gather more specific and accurate information about location, if the information
he has is not accurate or specific enough. (That is, generally the question concerns
sets of sets of possible situations, each of which includes all the possible situations
obtained by taking one possible situation - which, given the subject's actual position
in relation to the object and the actual environmental condition, is a possible
development of his exercising his ability to locate the object - and varying the
conditions which can affect the way things appear to the subject (where all this is
specified in terms that do not involve reference to the object)).
There is no doubt that the subject need not think explicitly about each of the
relevant possibilities; rather it seems that what would make the above mentioned
possibilities relevant to his grasp is his having some general grasp of how changes in
a situation in which he attends to a seen object may affect the way things appear to
him, and his taking such changes to be relevant to his ability to locate the object and
to detect whether or not what appears to be a successful case of locating it is actually
so. But if one is to maintain that a specific set (of sets) of possibilities is taken by the
subject to be relevant to his grasp of what locating the seen object in the particular
situation involves, then there must be something about his attitude that explains, for
example, which specific changes are relevant to determining sets of possibilities and
which ones are not. If no reference to the object is allowed, then this should be wholly
explained in terms of the subject's general grasp. But surely the subject's general
185
conception could include mistakes, or simply not suffice for determining all the
relevant details in each particular situation.
The natural way to explain how the subject identifies the relevant possibilities
and takes them to bear on the question of where the object is located is that he
identifies the object and takes himself to be considering where it is located. Thus,
given that he takes into account that (i) the object's state and the relation between the
object and himself may vary in various ways, and (ii) such variation may have certain
effects on the way things appear to him, there is a sense in which he can be said to
take the relevant possibilities into account. Of course, once it is accepted that the
subject has the ability to identify the object, his grasp of what it is to locate it - that is,
of what a successful exercise of the ability involves - does not depend on his taking
specific sets of possibilities into account: he simply knows that what makes an
exercise of the ability correct (at least in the example considered above) is that he
keeps exercising it in relation to the same object. (The specific possibilities would,
however, be taken by him to be relevant to questions regarding his ability to tell
whether or not he is successful).
Ill
I have been arguing that the relevance of the ability to locate an object (on the
basis of an information-link) to the subject's knowledge of what it is for the object to
be in the particular (egocentric) location it is depends on his ability to identify the
object. I take this to show that a knowledge of what it is for the object to be in the
particular location it is, which can be ascribed to the subject in virtue of his ability to
locate the object (regardless of whether or not he actually knows the object's
location), cannot play a role in explaining the subject's ability to identify the object.
Now, it is true that the latter claim does not follow from the former; the former claim
186
allows for the possibility that the relation between the subject's ability to identify the
object and his knowledge of what it is for the object to be in the particular location it
is is one of mutual dependency. But, given the role which the ability to identify the
object is supposed to play in explaining the subject's knowledge of what it is for the
object to be in the particular location it is, a mutual dependency claim is rather
unattractive.
It was argued that the subject's ability to identify the object is required for his
grasp of what it is for him to successfully locate the object by exercising the ability in
question: that, given his general grasp of how information about location depends on
factors such as his changing position in relation to the object, identifying the object
enables the particular grasp of what locating this particular object in the given
situation would involve. The mutual dependency claim implies that whether or not the
subject is actually identifying the object depends on whether he actually has a grasp of
his ability to locate the object (in virtue of the information-link) and consequently
knows what it is for the particular object in question to be located in the particular
place it is. But why should this be so? If the subject has the means to identify the
object in a way that suffices for allowing that he has a conception of what locating the
object involves, why should it matter whether or not he actually has, in this particular
case, a grasp of how he could locate the object? Furthermore, why should it matter
whether such a grasp actually yields (in the particular case) knowledge of what it is
for the object in question to be in the particular location it is?
The first point can be illustrated by the following example. Consider a subject
wearing spectacles that shift the apparent visual field 15° to the left. Suppose that he is
not presently aware of the fact that things are not where they appear to him to be, and
suppose further that he had never encountered, or considered the possibility of,
shifting spectacles (or other partly transparent objects with the same effect). At least
187
at first glance it seems plausible to say that he does not have a grasp of his current
ability to locate the objects he sees. Now, this first impression might very well be
mistaken, but the thing to note is that it seems rather odd to suggest that our
entitlement to suppose that this subject has the ability to identify the object should
depend on the decision as to whether he has a grasp of his current ability to locate the
relevant object. As for the second point, consider a subject who is completely
paralyzed and thus unable to locate objects in any of the normal ways (or even by
giving orders to someone else to move him). One may ascribe to him the ability to
locate objects on the basis of the information link had the relevant systems been
functioning properly, and we may suppose that there is a sense in which he takes this
to be the case. But it is difficult to see how this grasp provides him with knowledge of
what it is for the object to be at the location it currently is. Once again, even if I am
wrong about this, it is odd to think that the answer to the question of whether such a
subject can identify the object should depend on our decision as to whether there is a
sense in which he can be said to grasp his ability to locate the object which also
provides him with a knowledge of what it is for the object to be in the location it is.
This is not a conclusive refutation of the mutual dependency claim, and had
there been no alternative suggestion as to how a seen object is discriminated by the
subject, we should have reconsidered the above points. However, the suggestion made
in Chapter 6 is such an alternative. The suggestion was that the subject's grasp of the
fact that an attended object is the object which a specific bundle of information is
from explains in virtue of what he can be said to distinguish the relevant object from
any other object. Accepting this, it is possible to make sense of the view that his grasp
of his ability to locate the object and his knowledge of what it is for the object to be in
its particular location depend on his identifying the object but not vice versa.
188
It may seem that the suggestion that the subject distinguishes the object as the
object a particular bundle of information is from encounters a difficulty similar to the
one allegedly encountered by Evans's view. The subject is ascribed a grasp of his
situation as one in which he is selecting a particular bundle which is from the relevant
object in virtue of the fact that he takes his primitive conception of perception and
objects to apply to the relevant aspects of the current situation. But taking the general
conception to apply to the relevant aspect of the current situation depends on the
subject's ability to identify the relevant object. The reply is that - in contrast to the
relation between identifying an object and a grasp of one's ability to locate it - in this
case there is no room for distinguishing two different elements: the subject's
identification of the object and his grasp of the relation in which he stands to the
object. Due to (i) actual facts regarding the subject, the object and relevant
environmental conditions, (ii) the subject's general conception of perception and
objects, and (iii) his current interests, it is the case that the subject is attending to the
object while taking his general conception to apply to this situation; thus singling out
the object, grasping it as the object the bundle is from. In this case, then, there is no
room for debating whether we should accept a mutual dependency claim.
IV
I should emphasize that I am not denying that the ability to gather more accurate
and specific information about an object's location is central to our ability to think
about objects demonstratively. The claim is only that this ability to locate the object is
not what explains the subject's ability to discriminate it. The ability to gather more
accurate and specific information about location is central because spatial location is
central both to the way in which objects are individuated and to the conditions which
enable and affect visual experience. Since location is central in this way, the subject's
189
grasp of the object's current location in relation to himself and to other seen objects a grasp which involves his grasp of the possibility that the current experiential
information he has about the object's location is not accurate, and of his ability to
gather more accurate and specific information - is central to his particular conception
of the object and of the conditions which enable him to see it and affect the way it
appears to him. It should be clear, then, that on this picture, although it is significant
that a subject has the ability to gather more accurate and more specific information
about location and similarly significant that he has some general grasp of what this
may involve, it is not necessary, in each particular case, that veridical information
about the specific location (specific enough for the individuation of the object) be in
fact available to the subject (given the current information-link), and not necessary
that the subject has a full, accurate grasp of what his current ability to locate a specific
object in the current condition involves.
The contrast with Evans might be described by saying that I take the subject's
distinguishing knowledge of the object to be due to his grasp of the particular link
which obtains between the object and himself. 154 The grasp of this link (which is
simply an aspect of the subject's singling out the object) involves a grasp of the
subject's ability to gather further information (about location as well as about any
other visible feature of the object), an ability which often leads to his gathering more
specific and accurate information. To the extent that information about location has a
special role, this is due to more general aspects of the subject's conception of this
relation with the object rather than to the specific question of whether he could
currently distinguish the object by distinguishing its location.
154 Which, as clarified in Chapter 6, is not a case of the subject thinking about the object descriptively and
thus should not be taken to be a version of the descriptive modes of thought about the object, which Evans
rules out (e.g., pp.128 & 173), where the description involves reference to the information-link.
190
V
It is worth noting that on the suggested view of how the subject identifies the
demonstrated object, as on Evans's view, simple demonstrative thoughts differ from
the thoughts about televised objects which subjects may express by sentences of the
form 'this G is F ' (and similarly from thoughts based on other non-ordinary
perceptual information-links that allow the subject to gather continuous information
from the object). The difference lies in the fact that, generally, the subject's grasp of
how visual experience of objects depends on the objects' state and on further relevant
conditions does not apply to the televised objects (even if for simplicity's sake we
consider only cases in which the objects are seen during one shot, taken without the
camera moving). That is, we should remember that the relevant grasp is not a grasp of
a detached theory, but rather partly consists in the subject's ability to interact with his
environment and to reason about possible and actual interactions. It should then be
clear that the inapplicability of the subject's grasp of the relation between the object's
apparent location and its actual location is only one instance of this. For example,
turning a source of light towards the television will not affect the apparent colour of
the televised objects in the same way it would affect the apparent colour of an object
in the immediate environment, while changes in lighting conditions on the set may
affect the colour in the relevant way but will not be recognized by the subject as
changes in light conditions in the way he would have recognized such changes if they
occurred in the immediate environment. Similarly, moving around the television will
not yield more information about the object's shape; while such information could be
gathered in virtue of movements of the camera, in which case the grasp of the relevant
191
change in conditions differs from anything the subject encounters in his immediate
interaction with the environment. 155
155 There is much more to be said on this issue. For example there is a need to explain why watching
television, even if accompanied by an ability to act upon the televised scene, does not result in simply
amending the simple theory, as for example, might be the case with seeing things in mirrors. (The reply to
this particular question seems to be that the 'gap' between the principles governing ordinary vision and
those governing gathering information from seeing an object on television is too big. Thus one is simply
adding another set of quite different principles (which would never apply to ordinary vision), and in this
sense it is not an amendment of the theory of what seeing objects involves.) Furthermore, there is room for
asking whether the conception of how information is gathered which is in fact more basic in our own case
is necessarily more basic; that is, whether it could have been possible for a subject who did not interact with
the immediate environment but only interacted with objects on the basis of information he gathered from
watching television screens to develop a conception of a mind-independent world.
192
9 Demonstratives and spatial location: Campbell's view
I
I turn now to Campbell's view of the role played by location in enabling us to
think demonstratively about particular objects. Campbell maintains that the apparent
location of an object plays a role in explaining the subject's ability to verify and act
upon demonstrative thoughts about it. 156 1 shall argue that we can accept this claim as
well as Campbell's suggestion that this is so because of the role that the object's
apparent location plays in explaining how conscious attention to the object enables the
subject to verify and act upon demonstrative thoughts. However, I shall claim that we
should reject the particular way in which Campbell explains why the object's apparent
location plays the latter role; that is, we should reject the claim that conscious
attention to the object enables the subject to verify and act upon demonstrative
thoughts in virtue of a correspondence between the particular aspects of the
experience which enable the subject to identify the object and the characteristics used
at the sub-personal-level for selecting information for the relevant verification or
action.
II
As just mentioned, Campbell's view is that an object's apparent location plays a
role in explaining the subject's ability to verify and act upon demonstrative thoughts;
specifically, it plays a role in explaining how the evaluation of a demonstrative
thought, in which the predicated property is such that whether it applies to an object
can be evaluated on the basis of vision, can be governed by visual information from
156 'The apparent location of an object' refers to the location in which the object visually appears to the
subject to be. It is taken for granted that the ways locations are experienced are essentially egocentric; that
subjects see objects as located relative to a frame of reference defined by the axes of left/right, up/down and
nearer/farther away. (I leave open questions as to how exactly these axes should be construed).
192
the demonstrated object, and how the subject's visually-guided actions, which he
intends to direct towards the demonstrated object, are guided by information from the
object.
Apparent location plays such a role since it plays a role in explaining how
conscious attention to an object causes the information-processing procedures
involved in evaluating and acting upon the relevant thoughts to be carried out with the
use of the relevant information from the object.
Campbell defends this last claim by first pointing out that, as a matter of fact,
information about different features of the object - information for perception as well
as information for action158 - is processed separately in the brain (for example,
information about colour is processed in one area, information about shape for
perception in another, information about shape for action in yet another, and so on159).
This raises the question how, when attempting to evaluate a demonstrative thought,
the information about, for example, the colour of the demonstrated object is selected
from the information about the colour of other things in the subject's visual field, and
how, when the subject intends to act on the demonstrated object, the information from
that object, which is required for determining the parameters of the action for the
relevant sub-personal mechanisms, is selected. Now, a common suggestion as to how
it is that, in the first place, the subject experiences a unitary object rather than
157 In what follows, when speaking about evaluating demonstrative thoughts and acting upon them I will be
referring to these special cases. (I started by speaking about the verification of demonstrative thoughts, as
this is the way Campbell formulates his view, but will often prefer speaking about the evaluation of the
thought as I had been doing in previous chapters).
158 These are the terms used by Milner and Goodale (1995) to speak about the distinction which was
presented in Chapter 4. I shall use them here as convenient tags (however, remember that the information
'processed for perception' does have an effect on action, and that on their use 'perception' has a narrower
range than on my use of the term).
159 It is probably inaccurate to speak, generally, about a stream processing information about shape for
action: it seems likely, for example, that information about shape which guides grasping-behaviour and
information about shape which has a role in guiding walking-behaviour are processed separately. For
present purposes it is sufficient to note that, generally, information for action is processed separately from
information for perception. In order to simplify formulations, when discussing the selection of information
in general (that is, for action and for the evaluation of thoughts) I shall describe things according to what
seems to be the appropriate description in the case of information for perception; that is, I shall speak about
the selection of information from feature maps; this might not be accurate in the case of information for
action.
193
disconnected features is that information about location is encoded in each
information-processing stream (in which information is processed for perception), and
information from the same location (where Gestalt organization principles play a role
in determining the exact location in question) is bound together as information from
the same object. Given this picture, it seems that exactly the same binding parameter
(current location refined by the relevant Gestalt organization principles) can be used
by the visual-system to refer back to any relevant information-processing stream and
select the correct information for the evaluation of a thought about the object. 160
Furthermore, it is suggested that the correct information for the guidance of actions
directed towards the object can also be selected in a similar way.
If this is correct - that is, if, at the sub-personal-level, the relevant information is
selected according to the relevant binding parameter - then there must be something to
say about the subject's conscious attention to the object which explains how this can
happen (remember that on Campbell's view conscious attention to the object is what
provides the subject with his knowledge of which object he is demonstrating, and
thus, as mentioned in Chapter 7, should play a role in accounting for the functional
role of the demonstrative). Campbell suggests the following account. The subject
identifies the object he is attending to by its experienced location (and the relevant
aspects of Gestalt organization) and this guarantees that when intending to evaluate a
demonstrative thought about the object or to direct an action towards it, at the subpersonal-level, the corresponding information about location (and the corresponding
aspects of Gestalt organization) will be used for selecting the information to control
the evaluation of the thought or the action. Thus he says:
160 1 should clarify that I am ascribing the role of selecting visual information for the evaluation of thoughts
and for action to the visual-system only for convenience's sake: I do not wish to commit myself to any
particular view about how sub-personal systems should be categorized.
194
Suppose now that conscious attention to the object... identifies the object as the object at a
particular seen location. The identification of the target object as the thing at that location will
then be enough for the visual-system to know how to search the feature maps to find the shape,
colour, or orientation of the thing. The binding parameter will then provide an address for the
object, as it were - a way of identifying which object is in question, that can be used by the visualsystem when it has to verify or find how to act on the basis of propositions about that object. 161
The assumption here is that when the subject identifies the demonstrated object
as the object at a particular apparent location, at the sub-personal-level the processing
which underlies the fact that the object is experienced at that location (which I shall
refer to as the sub-personal correlate of the current experience of the relevant location)
is, in some way, singled out for the visual-system as relevant for determining which
information should be selected. 162 Campbell comments that this might not
immediately provide the system with the location from which information is to be
selected, since different frames of reference may be involved in encoding the
locations of features in the various information-processing streams and in the
processing of the information about the location of objects for perception; but
sameness of structure between the different ways of identifying locations should
enable the system to determine, on the basis of the location processed for perception,
from which location information should be selected. 163
The suggestion, then, is that (a) what enables a subject to evaluate and act upon
a demonstrative thought on the basis of information from the demonstrated object is
the fact that he identifies the object by means of its apparent location, and (b) the
161 p.37.
162 Campbell is most explicit about this being the type of picture he has in mind on pp.41-3. However, the
point made there - that the system can determine the location for selecting information in virtue of the fact
that what correspond to the experience of the object at the sub-personal-level is synchronized activity of the
various cells responding to input from the same location - does not seem to require that it should be,
specifically, the sub-personal correlate of the experience of the location which is singled out; in effect, this
suggestion seems closer to the alternative which I discuss below. (I should clarify that the formulation 1 use
in the text is mine).
163 pp.37 & 89. To be accurate, Campbell speaks about the frame of reference involved at the subject-level
rather than at the sub-personal processing of information for perception. However, the assumption seems to
be that since the processing of information about location for perception underlies the experience of the
object as at the relevant location, the same frame of reference is used for identifying locations at the
subject-level and at the sub-personal-level of processing for perception. (Note that even without this
assumption the claim about the similarity of structure still applies to all relevant levels).
195
subject-level identification has to be by means of apparent location because: (i) the
visual-system selects information for evaluating demonstrative thoughts and guiding
object-directed action on the basis of location, (ii) the visual-system determines from
which location information is to be selected on the basis of the (sub-personal)
information about location processed for perception that is singled out as relevant to
the task (at the sub-personal-level), and (iii) the relevant location information is
singled out as relevant to the task at the sub-personal-level in virtue of the fact that the
subject identifies the object as the object at the apparent location.
I do not deny that the object's apparent location has a role to play in
determining which information is to be selected at the sub-personal-level for
evaluating demonstrative thoughts and acting upon them, but will argue that this is not
because (ii) and (iii) describe correctly the procedure determining the location from
which information is to be selected. I shall first point out a reason to doubt the
correctness of (ii), and suggest an alternative story as to how the visual-system
determines from which location information is to be selected. I shall then argue that,
even if (ii) is in fact correct, given the sense in which it is correct to say that subjects,
when entertaining a demonstrative thought, identify the object of the thought as the
object at a certain apparent location (and thus, given the way in which we should read
(iii) if it is to be correct), (i)-(iii) are not what explain why subjects identify the object
in this way.
Three notes of clarification: First, condition (ii) requires that the visual-system
determines the location for selecting information on the basis of the relevant
information about location processed for perception. This is to be read as entailing (a)
that the relation between the locations encoded by the sub-personal correlates of
apparent locations and the locations used for selecting information is either one of
sameness or of a (non-trivial) one-to-one correspondence, and (b) that the visual196
system exploits this relation in determining the location for selecting information.
Secondly, to simplify formulations I have formulated the view as relating to location
alone, leaving out reference to Gestalt organization principles. The same type of
relations between the subject-level identification and the parameter affecting the
selection of information is supposed to hold when the relevant parameter is a certain
organization-principle. 164 Thirdly, I should explain that, as I interpret Campbell,
when he says that the subject identifies the object by its apparent location, or as the
object at a certain apparent location, he means that the object's apparent location
plays a role, at the subject-level, in distinguishing the object as one seen object
distinct from others, and thus is an aspect the subject is sensitive to when the object's
identity is in question.
Ill
I start, then, by asking whether (ii) is correct, that is, whether the visual-system
determines the location from which information is to be selected on the basis of the
information about the object's location processed for perception. It was mentioned
that Campbell assumes that this need not be problematic, for, even if different frames
of references are involved, the ways of identifying locations will have the same
structure. But there is a further issue. Information about location processed for
perception is affected by the relations between seen objects. This is manifested by
cases like the following. If a subject looks at a stationary object surrounded by a
rectangular frame which is slowly moving to the left, it will appear to him as if the
object is moving to the right while the frame stays still. However, while the
information processed for perception is affected in such ways, information about
164 Campbell does not give an example of the how this is supposed to work, but it is clear that he takes it
that the relations are the same (see, for example, p.89).
197
location processed for other purposes need not be so affected. One manifestation of
this is the fact that subjects who, in the above situation, are asked to point to the
object immediately after seeing it and the moving frame, point to the actual location
of the object (rather than the location it appeared to move to). 165 That is, the
information processed for action is not affected, in this case, by the relation between
the object and the moving frame. Given that there are such discrepancies, we should
ask whether the information about location relevant to binding is affected by
relations between seen objects in exactly the same way that the information
processed for perception is.
It is not unreasonable to assume that the information about location used for
binding is processed at early stages, which precede the segregation between the two
pathways and between the various information-processing streams, and thus that it is
not influenced by relations between seen objects as is the information about location
processed for perception. 166 First, information about location is in fact encoded at
these stages and thus there is a common way of mapping both the information which
is later processed for action and that processed for perception. 167 Secondly, it is often
assumed that the mapping at the various information-processing streams is due to the
connections between each processing stream and areas VI and V2 (the areas prior to
165 See Bridgeman et al.1981.1 am simplifying here. The data show that the direction in which subjects
point is closer to the actual location than to the apparent location, thus they show, at least, that the frame's
movement does not have the same effect on the information used for guiding pointing-behaviour as it has
on the information processed for perception. There is a debate as to how exactly to explain such data.
However, the fact that after a 2-second delay subjects point at the apparent location is interpreted as
showing that there is a real discrepancy between the information processed for action and that processed for
perception. For present purposes it is sufficient that there is some discrepancy.
166 There are cases in which relations between seen objects (specifically contiguous objects) may affect
information processed at early stages. Dyde and Milner (2002) mention such an effect on information about
orientation, and such an effect is also an effect on the exact location which the object appears to occupy.
However, what matters for the current discussion is that there are some effects which are restricted to later
stages. For simplicity's sake I shall ignore the possibility of early effects and speak as if, generally,
relations between seen objects do not affect early-processed information about location.
167 Campbell (2002 p.55) refers to Jeannerod (1997 p.80) who suggests that the connection between
selecting an object for action on the basis of certain experienced features (say, colour) and the selection of
the correct parameters for action could be explained by the possibility of the motor representation '"looking
back" toward areas common to the ventral and the dorsal systems where both the visual primitives and
some degree of spatial localization are present on the same map.'
198
the segregation). 168 This, of course, does not conclusively prove that the information
about location encoded in the various information-processing streams is in fact
information processed at an early stage. However, I only wish to clarify that we
cannot take it for granted that the visual-system determines the locations for selecting
information on the basis of information about location processed for perception.
Suppose that the information about location relevant to binding is, in fact,
processed at an early stage, and thus that neither the location assigned to features in
the various information-processing streams nor the location assigned to the
information for action is affected by relations between seen objects. If the system
determines the location for selecting information on the basis of the information
processed for perception, then whenever a discrepancy occurs, the information from
the wrong location should be selected for evaluating thoughts and actions. However,
it is clear that in cases like the above example the correct information is selected for
evaluating demonstrative thoughts about the object: the subject is not inclined to
judge, say, that the object's colour is the colour at the location which actually
corresponds to its current apparent location. Similarly the fact that subjects point
correctly to the object shows that the correct information for action can be selected.
Thus it seems that, if the information about location relevant to binding is processed
at an early stage, it cannot be that the location relevant to selecting information for
the task is determined by the information about the object's location processed for
perception.
168 See, for example, Zeki 1993 pp.330-3, 337-8 and Robertson et al.1997 p.296. There is room for holding
that due to the links between the retinotopic mapping in VI and V2 and a more sophisticated mapping
which plays a role in directing attention, one could say that information about location of the more
sophisticated type is implicitly encoded in the various information-processing streams. However, this may
still allow discrepancies between the information about locations processed for perception and that encoded
in the information-processing streams, since it is assumed that the more sophisticated map is due to
information-processing in the dorsal stream (see, for example, Robertson et al.1997).
199
Campbell might respond that there is no real problem, and that the apparent
problem results from my ignoring the role played by Gestalt organization principles in
binding features. For it may seem that the exact boundaries of the relevant earlyprocessed location need not be identified by directly specifying an exact location;
rather it is sufficient (at both stages) to identify a rough location and relevant
organization principles. However, although this may enable us to explain how the
correct information is selected in the previous example, it will not do so generally.
Suppose that a subject is viewing a stationary, horizontal line of qualitatively
indistinguishable Xs and a frame in the background, and that due to the frame moving
to the left the Xs appear to move to the right; suppose also that the apparent
movement is greater than the distance between any two adjacent Xs. If the subject
attends to one of the Xs around the center of the line, there is no rough location which,
together with the relevant Gestalt organization principles (in virtue of which an X
appears as a separate object), will suffice for explaining the fact that information from
the same X is continuously selected.
As the examples mentioned above involve apparent motion of the demonstrated
object, one may try to resolve the difficulty by suggesting that the visual-system has
to rely on the information about location processed for perception only for an initial
determination of the correct early-processed location, and then it can keep track of the
correct early-processed location by constantly updating the relation between it and the
information about location processed for perception. But there are similar effects on
the location processed for perception which do not involve change of the location over
time. For example, a stationary background frame whose centre is to the left of the
200
subject's direction of gaze will cause stationary objects located inside the frame to
appear to the right of their actual (egocentric) location. 169
In principle, it is possible that the visual-system somehow explicitly registers
any particular effect which the relations between currently seen objects have on
information about location processed for perception, and thus that, at any given time,
it can directly determine the relevant early-processed location on the basis of the
current information about location processed for perception. 170 Whether the visualsystem actually does this is an empirical question I shall not try to speculate about. 171
Instead I shall suggest that consciously attending to an object may enable the visualsystem to use early-processed locations to select information from the object without
the system determining the relevant early-processed location on the basis of
information about location processed for perception. I shall then argue that the
discussion of this alternative shows that even if information about location processed
for perception is in fact the basis upon which the visual-system determines the
locations for selecting information, this fact is not what explains the role played by the
object's apparent location in evaluating and acting upon demonstrative thoughts.
IV
Here is a suggestion as to how the visual-system can determine the location
from which information is to be selected without relying on the information about the
169 See Bridgeman and Huemer 1998.
170 That there has been such an effect is implicitly registered when the 'affected locations' are registered
For the effect to be registered explicitly there should be independently accessible information about any
shift in location (this might be done by a continuous updating of a function connecting locations on two
maps).
171 Though I should mention that, given my current knowledge, this seems to me a rather unlikely
possibility.
201
location processed for perception. 172 The fact that a subject is experiencing an object
as an object which has certain features and stands in certain relations to its
surroundings implies that the sub-personal correlates of the various bits of information
bundled together as information from this object are bound together (at the subpersonal-level) on the basis of location (and relevant Gestalt organization principles).
Thus there is a certain location which the system is currently using as the binding
parameter for this particular experience. (The relevant location may be a changing
location; the process in an ongoing process - information from the relevant location is
processed and bound together as long as attention is allocated to the object173 - and
during this time the relevant location may change). Consequently, if the subject is
currently singling out an object, on the basis of a particular experience, as relevant to
a certain task (specifically, to the evaluation of a certain thought or to a certain objectdirected intentional action), then the sub-personal correlate of the particular
experience on which this act of attention is based involves continuous selection of
information from a particular location (here, selection for the experience), and in this
sense contains the information as to which location is relevant for selecting
information for the task. Now suppose that when the subject singles out an object for
a task on the basis of a particular experience, the sub-personal correlate of this
experience (in general) is singled out as relevant to the task; since it contains the
information as to which location is relevant for selecting information for the task (in
the sense explained above), it should, at least in principle, be possible for the system
172 Hereafter I shall speak about the location from which the information is to be selected rather than refer
to it as an early-processed location. Ultimately, the following suggestion is supposed to be independent of
the assumption that the relevant information is processed at an early stage. Also, when speaking about the
system's determining the location relevant for selecting information on the basis of information about
location processed for perception, I mean to refer also to the possibility that this might be so trivially; that
is, that the above consideration was mistaken and that the information relevant to selecting information just
is the information processed for perception.
173 Attention here is not necessarily conscious attention of the type discussed in Chapter 6, but rather the
operation of sub-personal-level attentional mechanisms.
202
to determine the relevant location without relying on the information about the
object's location which is processed for perception.
One simplified model of how this can happen is as follows. Suppose that we
accept Treisman's hypothesis that information which is bound together is integrated
into an object-file. 174 The suggestion would then be that when a subject singles out an
object on the basis of a particular experience as relevant to a particular task, a
particular object-file is singled out at the sub-personal-level as relevant for the task.
Since the location from which information is selected for the file is continuously used
for updating the file, the singling out of an object-file can enable determining the
location which is relevant for selecting information for the task. 175
To stress, the contrast with Campbell's view is one between (i) the sub-personal
correlate of a certain of aspect (or a limited set of aspects) of the experience (e.g., the
experience of the object's location), in virtue of its carrying information about the
relevant aspect, provides the basis for the visual-system to determine (as a function of
that information) the parameters for selecting information for the task, and (ii) the
sub-personal correlate of the experience of the object in general (or some aspect of it
which is general in the sense that it is not related to one particular aspect, or set of
aspects, of the experience) enables the visual-system to determine the parameters for
selecting information for the task in virtue of the fact that relevant parameters are
actually being used in maintaining this correlate of the experience. One should thus be
careful to distinguish the two different claims made when (in the presentation of the
suggestions) it was said that a certain sub-personal correlate of the experience is
singled out. On Campbell's suggestion the relevant correlate is singled out as
174 See, for example, Treisman 1993 p.24.
175 This model seems to be an extension of Treisman's suggestion that attention can be controlled by the
selection of object-files (1993 p.32). (This need not be the only possible way to flesh out the suggestion,
and of course there is a need to expand on this simplified model).
203
providing the information on the basis of which the parameter for selecting
information is determined as in (i). On the alternative suggestion the correlate is
singled out as that which enables determining the relevant parameter in virtue of its,
as it were, containing the information as to which parameters are relevant to selecting
information as in (ii).
Note that since the different sub-personal correlates of the different bits of
experiential information which are bundled together are linked at the sub-personallevel, the current suggestion is consistent with the possibility that the mechanism by
which the sub-personal correlate of the experience of the object (in general) is singled
out at the sub-personal-level proceeds via the selection of the correlate of the
experience of the object's location. What makes it a case of type (ii) is the fact that the
system does not determine the location for selecting information on the basis of the
information of the location carried by the sub-personal correlate selected at the firststage (it should be clear that the correlate of any other experienced feature could, in
principle, play this role just as well).
Now suppose that the location for selecting information for the task is
determined in the second way (thus without being based on the information about
location processed for perception). It would still be the case that the object's apparent
location has an effect on the way the visual-system determines the location for
selecting information for the task. The suggestion was that when the subject singles
out an object for a task on the basis of a particular experience, the sub-personal
correlate of this experience is singled out as relevant to the task. And, given the way
our visual experience is in fact organized, an object's apparent location has an effect
on the subject's ability to single out this object on the basis of experience. This is so
since what enables the subject to single out a particular object is the fact that
information from it is made available to him in experience as information from one
204
and the same object (that is, it forms a bundle of information). Given an appearance as
of an object, the subject, unless he has relevant doubts, takes the relevant bundle to be
from the object, and can thus single out the object and entertain demonstrative
thoughts about it. Now, a visual appearance as of one object is an appearance as of a
thing that occupies a discrete, connected portion of space, and which changes location
over time in a continuous way. 176 Thus when a subject singles out a particular object
on the basis of visual experience he is sensitive to these spatial aspects of the
appearance.
In addition, contrasts between the spatial relations between a certain
object and the other objects surrounding it, like other contrasts between the apparent
features of the object and of the surrounding objects (e.g. contrasts in colour, shape,
etc.), often help the subject to single it out.
It can thus be said that on this picture the object's apparent location has an
effect on the way information is selected (at the sub-personal-level) for evaluating and
acting upon demonstrative thoughts. But this is so only because of its relevance to
how the subject distinguishes between seen objects on the basis of his experience; an
effect that is due to facts about the way visual experience is organized, and to the
subject's grasp of the relation between the way things appear to him in experience and
the way they are. No appeal is made, in this explanation, to the role played by location
in determining (at the sub-personal-level) which information is to be selected for
176 I am regarding this as a mere fact about how objects are presented to us in visual experience, leaving
open the question of whether this is necessary for objects to be experienced as objects. It should be
emphasized that saying that a thing appears to the subject as occupying a connected portion of space does
not imply that there must be spatial continuity between all the currently visible parts of the object which
appear as parts of the same object. What is required is that they appear as parts of a thing occupying a
connected portion of space, but the appearance could be, for example, one of an object whose middle part is
occluded by a post, etc. (A similar point applies to the relevant apparent changes in location).
177 Martin (1997 p.90) makes a similar point when discussing the role location plays in determining whether
two demonstrative thoughts involve the exercise of the same demonstrative ability.
205
evaluating and acting upon a demonstrative thought. 178
V
We have, then, two stories about how the visual-system determines from which
location information is to be selected for evaluating and acting upon a demonstrative
thought. The first - which I shall label 'the correspondence story' - is that when the
subject singles out an object for a task, the sub-personal correlates of those aspects of
the experience which correspond to the binding parameter are singled out for the task
and the information they encode is the basis for determining which information is to
be selected for the task. The second - which I shall label 'the inclusion story' - is that
the sub-personal correlate of the experience of the object in general (or some general
aspect of this correlate) is singled out as relevant to the task, and this enables the
visual-system to find out from which location information is to be selected since this
sub-personal correlate includes the information as to which location this is. Campbell
holds that the correspondence story is the correct one, and takes this to be central to
explaining the role played by apparent location in our ability to evaluate and act upon
such thoughts. I tried to show that it is not straightforward that the correspondence
story is correct: first, I pointed out a reason to doubt that it can be the correct story,
and secondly, even if one is not persuaded by the considerations I appealed to, if the
inclusion story is plausible, it is at least an open question which of the two stories is in
fact correct.
However, the correctness of the correspondence story is only a necessary
condition for accepting CampbelFs explanation. The fact that, at the sub-personal-
178 Note that it is possible to argue here that talk about the organization of the experience of objects
involves an implicit reference to the parameters for binding information selected for the experience, but this
claim is weaker than Campbell's claim - that these parameters are relevant to explaining the role of the
arent location in virtue of their relevance to the selection of information for thought evaluation and
action (rather than only selecting information for experience).
206
l, the information about location processed for perception plays a certain role in
enabling the subject to evaluate and act upon demonstrative thoughts need not have
implications for the question of what role the fact that the subject experiences the
object as at the relevant location plays in enabling these activities. That is, it does not
immediately follow from the correctness of the correspondence story that, because
things are as stated in this story, the fact that the subject experiences the demonstrated
object as at a particular location (rather than just the fact that the sub-personal
correlate of this aspect of the experience is singled out as relevant to the task) has a
certain effect on how the subject evaluates and acts upon demonstrative thoughts. I
shall try to indicate briefly why I think that, even if the correspondence story is in fact
correct, this does not explain any of the effects an object's apparent location actually
has on how the subject evaluates and acts upon the relevant demonstrative thoughts.
For an aspect of the subject's experience to have an effect on the way he
evaluates thoughts and acts upon them, it must be the case that, from his point of view,
the question of whether things are as experienced bears on the way he should evaluate
thoughts and act upon them. 179 It might therefore seem that since subjects are unaware
of the particular details of the sub-personal processing, it is generally the case that
such details cannot be relevant to explaining possible effects of subjects' experiences,
and thus that we can immediately reject the suggestion that the correctness of the
correspondence story is relevant to explaining the effect of the object's apparent
location on his thoughts and actions. 180 But this is too quick. Experiencing, thinking
and acting are not simply the end result of sub-personal activity, but rather are partly
179 If certain visual information has a certain effect on what the subject is disposed to do, while the
information is available to the subject in experience but it is not the implication which the subject takes this
information to have which explains this effect, then the effect is fully accounted for by the sub-personal
effect of the corresponding information available at the sub-personal-level (see Chapter 4).
180 Such a view is expressed by Martin (1997) in his response to an earlier version of Campbell's view
(presented in Campbell 1997).
207
constituted by such activity. Furthermore, the fact that this is so is implicitly taken
into account in our primitive grasp of what experience, thought and action involve.
181
Thus one cannot, generally, rule out the possibility that there are cases in which
details about particular sub-personal mechanisms are relevant to explaining particular
aspects of the subject's perspective on the relation between his experiences and the
relevant thoughts and actions. However, I want to suggest that the discussion of the
inclusion story shows that the particular question of whether the correspondence story
or the inclusion one is correct is irrelevant to explaining the role of apparent location.
It was claimed that, assuming the inclusion story is correct, an object's apparent
location plays a role in enabling the subject to evaluate and act upon demonstrative
thoughts in virtue of the fact that when singling out an object on the basis of an
experience, subjects are sensitive to whether a particular experience is an experience
as of one object, where spatial aspects are central to this.
1 89
Now, it seems that one
cannot deny the general correctness of the assumptions on which this claim was
based, i.e., the assumptions about the way our visual experiences are organized and
about the way we rely on our experiences when singling out objects. Thus it seems
that one cannot dispute the claim that an object's apparent location, in fact, affects the
way subjects single out objects (and consequently, the way they evaluate and act upon
demonstrative thoughts) in this particular way and for this particular reason.
Furthermore, the assumption that the inclusion story rather than the correspondence
one is correct is not required for explaining these facts (i.e., the facts about the
organizations of our experiences and the way we view the relation between the
experience and how things are). It is true that in order to explain how it is that subjects
181 As mentioned in Chapter 4, the subject's implicitly taking the sub-personal activity into account is
manifested in things like how he explains mistakes or reasons about possible mistakes, etc.
182 1 also mentioned the fact that the spatial relations between objects help the subject to focus his attention
on one experienced object. Since it should be clear how the points made below apply to this additional type
of effect, I discuss only the first one.
208
take it that they can rely on the experience the way they actually do, one has to
assume that there is a mechanism in virtue of which, when a subject singles out an
object on the basis of experience, information from the object is selected for
evaluating and acting upon the relevant thoughts; 183 but those respects in which the
mechanism suggested by the inclusion story differs from the mechanism suggested by
the correspondence story are not specifically relevant to this explanation. 184 This
means that the effect in question is explained by facts which obtain independently of
which of the two stories is correct; thus, even if the correspondence story is correct,
this will not be relevant to the explanation of this particular effect of the object's
apparent location on the way subjects evaluate and act upon demonstrative thoughts.
One may accept this but argue that (i) there is a further way in which an object's
apparent location affects the way subjects single out objects, and (ii) an appeal to the
correspondence story is required for explaining this further effect. Now, if the
subject's sensitivity to the apparent location when singling out an object, is due only
to the effect of the apparent location on what makes an experience an experience as of
one object, then the subject only has to be sensitive to relations between simultaneous
and sequential apparent locations (for the apparent location of an object matters to its
experience being as of an object only to the extent that it appears to be different from
the apparent locations of other currently seen objects and that its relation to the
preceding and succeeding apparent locations does or does not appear as a continuous
change). Specifically, the way a subject evaluates and acts upon demonstrative
thoughts need not be sensitive to whether he identifies the object's apparent location
by means of a particular (egocentric) frame of reference (for example, whether, given
183 In the way it is actually selected, that is, accounting for the same patterns of mistakes.
184 Remember that we are assuming that either story might be correct; thus it is assumed that we are
considering versions of the two stories which, given the facts about the organization of our experiences of
objects, yield exactly the same results as to which information is selected for the control of thought and
action.
209
two objects which are roughly seen to be straight ahead, the subject can identify their
locations as different not only by appeal to facts such as that this object appears to the
left of that one, but also by identifying one location as, say, being exactly straight
ahead and the other slightly to the left of straight ahead). 185 On the other hand,
according to the correspondence story, the location (processed for perception) which
is supposed to determine the location for selecting information should be identified in
relation to a certain (egocentric) frame of reference which is independent of the
information from objects currently processed (i.e., what is registered at the subpersonal-level as current visual objects is not part of what defines the frame of
reference; the current information about objects can only affect which location is
assigned to each object). It might, then, be suggested that, somehow, on the
correspondence story, the subject's ability to identify the object's exact location in
relation to a certain (egocentric) frame of reference should be regarded by him as
relevant to his ability to single out objects. So we may at least accept that if the
correctness of the correspondence story explains the role played by apparent location,
then the identification of such exact egocentric location of an object must be taken by
a subject to be necessary for his singling out that object.
1 RA
185 When speaking about the way the subject identifies the object's apparent location, I am referring to the
way he grasps which location this is in virtue of seeing it; thus it is a way the information about location is
given to him in experience. As explained in footnote 156,1 am leaving open the question of the exact way
in which the egocentric frame of reference used in visual experience is to be construed. It is often assumed
that the visual straight ahead is the direction one's head is facing, I shall assume this in order to have a
convenient example. The points made below apply equally to other suggestion as to what constitutes the
subject's visual straight ahead (and any other location identified egocentrically).
186 Note that the other two considerations I claimed to be relevant to explaining the role played by location
in subjects' ability to single out objects do not require that subjects take the identification of an exact
egocentric location to be necessary for singling out an object. The second point mentioned above (that
various contrasts help the subject to single out the object) only implies that the subject is sensitive to the
differences between spatial relations between different objects. The claim made in Chapter 8 (that
experiential information about egocentric location plays a role in the subject's grasp of the relation between
the experience and the way things are) implies that subjects take their ability to identify the object's
location in relation to themselves to be relevant to their ability to single out objects, though the relevant
location may be only a rough location.
210
It seems, however, that subjects do single out objects without taking their ability
to identify the object's exact apparent location in relation to a particular egocentric
frame of reference to be relevant to this. Consider our ability to single out any of the
Xs in a line of qualitatively indistinguishable Xs with small, equal distances between
them. The opponent is committed to the view that when singling out one of the Xs, a
subject is sensitive to whether he identifies, in relation to a relevant frame of
reference, a location which is exact enough to enable (given the relevant Gestalt
organization principles) an identification of that X. 187 But this implies that the subject
attends or is disposed to attend to very fine differences in where the object appears in
relation to himself, while it seems that it is only in very special circumstances (if at
all) that we attend or are disposed to attend to such differences. Singling out an X
from a line of Xs does not seem, specifically, to form such a circumstance: normally,
when we do so, we are not concerned about whether, for example, the apparent
direction of one particular X, rather than that of an adjacent one is the exact straight
ahead. 188
I cannot develop this claim properly here, but suppose we accept that there are
counterexamples to the suggestion that subjects, when singling out objects, are
sensitive to whether they can identify the object's apparent location in relation to a
certain (egocentric) frame of reference, where the location thus identified can enable
(given the relevant Gestalt organization principles) an identification of the object. The
argument I have tried to sketch was this. Apparent location affects the way a subject
187 In fact, it is not crucial that the subject be able to identify a location which only the relevant X occupies.
The important question is whether at all the subject's way of identifying locations in relation to the relevant
frame of reference fixes their boundary in a fine enough way. (If he could, for example, identify a location
in which three specific Xs appear, then the pattern they form could have enabled the identification of just
one of them).
188 1 am relying here on self-observation: when I try to attend to such fine differences it is immediately clear
that this is not something I normally do or am disposed to do when singling out an X from such a line of
Xs.
211
singles out objects in virtue of (a) the fact that, when singling out objects, he is
sensitive to the organization of the experience as experience of objects, and (b) the
fact that the relations between simultaneous and sequential apparent locations of seen
things are central to what is experienced as one object, distinct from others. The
question of whether the correspondence story or the inclusion story is correct is
irrelevant to explaining these facts. Therefore, whether the correspondence story or
the inclusion story is correct is irrelevant to explaining the effect of the object's
apparent location which is due to these facts. The question then was whether there is a
further way in which the object's apparent location affects the way subjects single out
objects and which may be explained by the correspondence story. As far as I can see,
the only candidate is an effect which is due to subjects' taking their ability to identify
the apparent location in relation to a certain (egocentric) frame of reference (in an
exact enough way) to be relevant to their ability to single out objects. Thus if we
accept that subjects do not, generally, take the ability to identify locations in this way
to be relevant to their ability to single out objects, we can conclude that, even if the
correspondence story is correct - that is, even if what happens when a subject singles
out a particular object as the object of the thought he intends to evaluate or act upon is
that at the sub-personal-level information about location processed for perception is
singled out as relevant to the task and serves as the basis for determining from which
location information for the task is to be selected - the effect of the object's apparent
location on the subject's ability to evaluate and act upon demonstrative thoughts is
due to the above mentioned facts about the organization of the experience, and thus
independent of the correctness of the correspondence story.
212
References
Bermudez, J.L. (1995) 'Nonconceptual Content: From Perceptual Experience to
Subpersonal Computational States', Mind and Language, 10(4), 333-369.
Block, N. (1997) 'On a Confusion about a Function of Consciousness' in Block N.,
Flanagan O., and Giizeldere G. (eds.), The Nature of Consciousness, Cambridge,
Mass.: MIT Press, 375-415.
Bridgeman, B., Kirch, M. and Sperling, A. (1981) 'Segregation of Cognitive and Motor
Aspects of Visual Function Using Induced Motion', Perception and
Psychophysics, 29, 336-342.
Bridgeman, B. and Huemer, V. (1998) 'A Spatially Oriented Decision does not Induce
Consciousness in a Motor Task', Consciousness and Cognition, 7, 454-464.
Brewer, B. (1999) Perception and Reason, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Brewer, B. (2001) Precis of Perception and Reason, and response to commentators,
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 61, 449-464.
Brewer, B. (manuscript) 'Do Sense Experiential States Have Conceptual Content?'
Campbell, J. (1997) 'Sense, Reference and Selective Attention', Proceedings of the
Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume, 71, 55-74.
Campbell, J. (2002) Reference and Consciousness, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Carey, D.P., Harvey, M., Milner, A.D. (1996) 'Visuomotor Sensitivity for Shape and
Orientation in a Patient with Visual Form Agnosia', Neuropsychologia, 34(5),
329-337.
Crane, T. (1992) The Nonconceptual Content of Experience', in Crane T. (ed.), The
Contents of Experience: Essays on Perception, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Dennett, D., Kinsbourne, M. (1992) 'Time and the Observer: The Where and When of
Consciousness in the Brain', Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 15, 183-247.
Dyde, R.T. and Milner, A.D. (2002) 'Two illusions of perceived orientation: one fools all
of the people some of the time, but the other fools all of the people all of the
time', Experimental Brain Research, 144(4), 518-527.
Eilan, N. (1998) 'Perceptual Intentionality: Attention and Consciousness', in O'Hear A.
(ed.) Current Issues in Philosophy of Mind, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Eilan, N. (2001) 'Consciousness, Acquaintance and Demonstrative Thought', Philosophy
and Phenomenological Research, 6 1.
213
Eilan, N. (manuscript) 'Science, Causation and Phenomenology'.
Evans, G. (1982) The Varieties of Reference, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gallagher, S. and Jeannerod, M. (2002) 'From Action to Interaction: An Interview
with Marc Jeannerod', Journal of Consciousness Studies 9(1).
Haffenden, A.M. & Goodale, M.A. (2000) 'Independent Effects of Pictorial Displays on
Perception and Action', Vision Research, 40(10-12), 1597-1607.
Heck, R. (2000) 'Nonconceptual Content and the "Space of Reasons'", Philosophical
Review, 109(4), 483-523.
Jeannerod, M. (1997) The Cognitive Neuroscience of Action, Oxford: Blackwell.
Jeannerod, M. (2003) 'Consciousness of Action and Self-Consciousness. A Cognitive
Neuroscience Approach', in Roessler J. and Eilan N. (eds.), Agency and Self
Awareness: Issues in Philosophy and Psychology, Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Kelly, S. D. (2001) 'Demonstrative Concepts and Experience', Philosophical Review,
110,397-420.
Libet, B. (1993) 'The Neural Time Factor in Conscious and Unconscious Events', in
Bock G. and Marsh J. (eds.) Experimental and Theoretical Studies of
Consciousness, Ciba Foundation Symposium 174, Wiley: Chichester, 123-137
Mack, A. and Rock, I. (1998) Inattentional Blindness, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Martin, M.G.F. (1997) 'Sense, Reference and Selective Attention', Proceedings of the
Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume, 71, 75-98.
Martin, M.G.F. (2001) 'Epistemic Openness and Perceptual Defeasiblity', Philosophy
andPhenomenological Research, 61, 441-448.
McDowell, J. (1990) 'Peacocke and Evans on Demonstrative Content', Mind 99(394),
255-266.
McDowell, J. (1994) 'The Content of Perceptual Experience', Philosophical Quarterly,
44(175), 190-205.
McDowell, J. (1996) Mind and World, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard UP.
McDowell, J. (1998), 'Replies to Commentators', Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research, 58,403-431
Milner, A.D. and Goodale, M.A. (1995) The Visual Brain in Action, Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
214
Palmer, S.E. (1999) Vision Science: Photons to Phenomenology, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT
Press.
Peacocke, C. (1989) 'Perceptual Contents', in Almog, Kaplan, Perry, Wettstein (eds.),
Themes from Kaplan, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 297-329.
Peacocke, C. (1991) 'Demonstrative Content: a Reply to John McDowell', Mind, 123133.
Peacocke, C. (1992) Ch. 3, A Study of Concepts, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Peacocke, C. (2001) 'Does Perception Have a Nonconceptual Content?', The Journal of
Philosophy. 98(5), 239-264.
Pylyshyn Z.W. (2001) 'Visual Indexes, Preconceptual Objects, and Situated Vision',
Cognition, 80(1-2), 127-158.
Robertson, L., Treisman, A., Friedman-Hill, S., and Grabowecky, M. (1997) 'The
Interaction of Spatial and Object Pathways: Evidence from Balint's Syndrome',
Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 9, 254-76.
Rossetti, Y. (1998) 'Implicit Short-Lived Motor Representations of Space in Brain
Damaged and Healthy Subjects', Consciousness and Cognition, 7(3), 520-558.
Searle, J. (1983) Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Scholl, B.J., and Pylyshyn, Z.W. (1999) 'Tracking Multiple Items Through Occlusion:
Clues to Visual Objecthood', Cognitive Psychology, 38, 259-290.
Treisman, A. (1993) 'The Perception of Features and Objects', in Baddeley A.D. and
Weiskrantz L. (eds.), Attention: Selection, Awareness and Control. Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 5-35.
Weiskrantz, L. (1990) Blindsight: a case study and implications, Oxford: Clarendon
Press.
Zeki, S. (1993) A Vision of the Brain, Oxford: Blackwell.
215