Abduction or Inertia? The logic of syntactic change*
George Walkden
University of Cambridge
Two assumptions often considered principles of inquiry in historical
generative syntax are that linguistic change is abductive (Andersen 1973)
and that syntax is inert (Longobardi 2001). In this paper it is demonstrated
that these two notions, if meaningfully interpreted, are not compatible: if we
wish to develop a coherent theory of language acquisition and change, we
must abandon one or the other. The conclusion reached is that that neither
abduction nor inertia is a necessary or useful concept in diachronic syntax. I
suggest that we should abandon both, instead treating syntactic change on its
own terms.
Two assumptions often considered principles of inquiry in historical generative syntax are
that linguistic change is abductive (Andersen 1973) and that syntax is inert (Longobardi
2001). In this paper it is demonstrated that these two notions, if meaningfully interpreted, are
not compatible: if we wish to develop a coherent theory of language acquisition and change,
we must abandon one or the other, with important consequences for the way we conceptualize
syntactic change.
The paper is structured in four sections. In the first I present abduction, as introduced
into the linguistic literature by Andersen (1973), and outline problems with the notion.
Section 2 does the same for the concept of inertia. In Section 3 I outline how, and why, the
two concepts are mutually incompatible. Section 4 concludes.
1. ABDUCTION AND ITS PROBLEMS
The notion of abduction as a form of inference originated with the American semiotician and
philosopher Charles Sanders Peirce. Andersen (1973) was the first linguist to incorporate it
into a theory of language change. The following is his exposition (highly problematic, as I
will demonstrate), which many linguists have followed (e.g. Lightfoot 1979; McMahon 1994;
Roberts 2007: 124–5).
Andersen (1973: 774–776) distinguishes three modes of inference: deductive,
inductive, and abductive. He proposes that they can be distinguished using Aristotelian
syllogismsέ Deductive inference, a familiar concept, ‗applies a law to a case and predicts a
result‘ (1λιγμ ιι5), as in the syllogism in (1).
(1)
Case
Socrates is a man
Law
All men are mortal
___________________________
Result
Socrates is mortal
≈
P
P ⊃Q
_______
∴Q
Inductive inference, in τndersen‘s terms, ‗proceeds from observed cases and results to
establish a law‘ (1λιγμ ιι5), as in (β)έ
*
Many thanks to the audience at CamLing 2010 where this material was presented. For discussion of various
aspects of the ideas expressed in this paper I am grateful to Debbie Anderson, Tim Bazalgette, Theresa
Biberauer, Chris Lucas, Ian Roberts and in particular David Willis. All errors are mine.
Abduction or inertia? The logic of syntactic change 231
(2)
Case 1
Socrates is a man
Result 1
Socrates is mortal
Case 2
Abraham Lincoln is a man
Result 2
Abraham Lincoln is mortal
Case 3
Michael Jackson is a man
Result 3
Michael Jackson is mortal
__________________________________
Law
All men are mortal
≈
P1
Q1
P2
Q2
P3
Q3
_______
P⊃Q
Crucially, τndersen claims (1λιγμ ιι5) that ‗these two modes of inference share two
important characteristics: first, the conclusion contains nothing which is not given in the two
premises; second – and this is a natural corollary – if the premises are true, the conclusion is
certain to be trueέ‘
Abductive inference, the mode that is key to τndersen‘s proposal, ‗proceeds from an
observed result, invokes a law, and infers that something may be the case‘ (1λιγμ ιι5)έ This is
illustrated in (3), which can be seen to be equivalent to the logical fallacy of affirming the
consequent.
(3)
Result
Trout swim
Law
All fish swim
____________________________
Case
Trout are fish
≈
Q
P⊃Q
_______
∴P
Andersen claims that a) unlike induction and deduction, abduction is fallible, and b) abduction
can form hypotheses and ‗originate new ideas‘, while deduction and induction are merely
processes of hypothesis testing (1973: 775). It is easy to demonstrate that abduction is indeed
fallibleέ If the result ‗Trout swim‘ is replaced by ‗ηtters swim‘ in the abductive syllogism (3)
above, the conclusion becomes ‗ηtters are fish‘έ Despite the correctness of the premises, the
conclusion is false, showing that the mode of reasoning involved is flawed. Andersen takes
abduction to underlie language acquisition, and such flawed abductions to underlie language
change.
There are serious problems with this model, however. Indeed, Deutscher (2002)
demonstrates that Andersen (1973) was critically confused about abduction, and concludes
(βίίβμ δκδ) that ‗the term ―abductive innovation‖ is neither adequate nor necessary for a
typology of linguistic innovations‘έ To begin with, Deutscher shows that τndersen‘s claim
that deductive and inductive inference are both infallible is clearly false. To see that
enumerative induction is also fallible, we might try replacing the word ‗mortal‘ with ‗dead‘ in
the inductive syllogism (2) aboveέ The conclusion then is ‗τll men are dead‘ν once again
false, despite the correctness of the premises. Both enumerative induction and abduction are
forms of fallible ampliative inference in modern philosophical terminology (Deutscher 2002:
δι1)έ This error is τndersen‘s, not θeirce‘s, since θeirce explicitly differentiated deductive
inference from the fallible inductive and abductive modes (Deutscher 2002: 477). Indeed, the
‗problem of induction‘ has been widely recognized in philosophy since Hume (1λ1ί [1ιδκ])έ
Furthermore, Peirce himself was not terminologically consistent throughout his life:
υurks (1λδ6μ γί1) observes that ‗the variation to be found in his views on abduction is ...
typical of θeirce's writings‘έ Specifically, in his early work, θeirce ‗felt bound to express his
very general notions within the straitjacket of τristotelian logic‘ (Deutscher βίίβμ δι1)ν cfέ
the syllogisms (1)–(3) above. In his later work, however, θeirce‘s notion of abduction was
much more general: he viewed it as the process by which any creative hypothesis was formed
(Deutscher 2002: 474). This later view is given in (4).
232 George Walkden
(4)
Peirce‘s later notion of abductionμ ‗The surprising fact, C, is observedν υut if τ were
true, C would be a matter of courseν Hence there is reason to suspect that τ is trueέ‘
This notion is in no way coextensive with the syllogism in (3)μ what is ‗a matter of course‘
has nothing to do with laws, cases or results. Andersen (1973), however, mixes up the two
notions – hence his claim that induction and deduction are processes used only for testing
hypotheses formed by abduction.
This terminological mess has led to mass confusion among historical linguists.
Consider the following example of abductive reasoning given in Trask's Dictionary of
historical and comparative linguistics (2000):
‗I have heard people saying things like ―books‖ and ―trees‖ν therefore there must be a
rule of English that nouns are pluralized by adding -Sέ‘
This is not an example of abductive inference but of enumerative induction in its narrowest,
Aristotelian sense, as in the schema in (2): jumping from cases and results to infer a law
(Deutscher βίίβμ δκ1)έ τlthough it may be consistent with θeirce‘s later notion of abduction
as given in (4), it is in no way consistent with the schema in (3). Another problematic
definition is that given in the glossary to Roberts (2007):
‗Change caused by the fact that learners only have access to the output of a generative
grammar ... and to Universal Grammar ... with no direct access to the grammar itself.
The combination of primary linguistic data ... and Universal Grammar may lead the
learner to abduce a system which is distinct from that underlying the primary linguistic
data by reanalysis ...‘ (2007: 445)
The notion of abduction used here is essentially as broad as the notion of change itself, since
it is entirely possible for deductive and/or enumerative-inductive inference to lead the learner
to postulate a different system from that giving rise to the primary linguistic data (PLD). The
insight that children have no access to the grammar underlying the language they are trying to
acquire is, of course, an important one, and crucially associated with Andersen (1973) as well
as δightfoot (1λιλ), but this was not what θeirce (or τndersen) ever meant by ‗abduction‘έ
Deutscher concludes that the term is misused and indeed useless in linguistics, and
that the way linguists use it is out of step with its more general use in philosophy and science,
where the term has largely been replaced by the more general notion of ‗inference to the best
explanation‘ (cfέ eέgέ δipton βίίί)έ He does, however, make one important qualification:
‗The questions that Peirce raised about the nature of inference still stand at the core of
any theory that attempts to explain language learning and change. How are hypotheses
for new linguistic rules formed in the mind? How does a language learner decide
between alternative rules that can explain the same surface form? What, from the point
of view of the language learner, represents the ‗best explanation‘ for hisήher inputς‘
(2002: 484).
The notion of abduction may not even be useful in this sense, though. Lass (1997: 335–336)
expresses doubt that abduction or indeed any form of inference can be used to model language
change, given that in his view language change is not carried out by an agent who can ‗act‘ or
‗abduce‘έ Even assuming that language change can be reduced to language acquisition (which
Lass himself (1997: 337) vigorously denies), it is far from obvious that children choose to
acquire language. There is substantial experimental evidence (e.g. Kisilevsky et al. 2003) that
the process of language acquisition seems to begin before birth, suggesting that it makes more
Abduction or inertia? The logic of syntactic change 233
sense to view it as an automatic biological-mechanical algorithm in the tradition of cognitive
science rather than as the result of any conscious action on the part of the acquirer.
Although a much-mentioned buzzword, then, it is not clear that ‗abduction‘ in fact
means anything at all, or that it is of any use in the study of language change.
2. INERTIA AND ITS PROBLEMS
The origins of the notion of inertia as applied to language change lie in work by Keenan
(1994, 2002, 2009), who expresses the idea as in (5).
(5)
‗Things stay as they are unless acted upon by an outside force or DECAY‘
(Keenan 2002: 327; emphasis his)
Longobardi (2001) goes a step further, proposing what he terms the ‗Inertial Theory‘ of
syntactic change. He claims this has empirically testable consequences, and might turn out to
be ‗empirically false or only partly correct‘ (βίί1μ βικ)έ The cornerstones of the theory are set
out in (6)–(8).
(6)
(7)
(8)
‗syntactic change should not arise, unless it can be shown to be caused – that is, to be
a well-motivated consequence of other types of change (phonological and semantic
changes, including the disappearance of whole lexical items) or, recursively, of other
syntactic changes‘
‗linguistic change proper έέέ may only originate as an interface phenomenon‘
‗syntax, by itself, is diachronically completely inert‘
(Longobardi 2001: 277–278; emphases his)
The idea of inertia has received widespread attention in the literature on diachronic syntax; it
is discussed by, among others, Lightfoot (2002: 130), Hróarsdóttir (2002, 2003), Ferraresi &
Goldbach (2003), Ingham (2006: 257), Roberts (2007: 232), Jäger (2008), Waltereit & Detges
(2008), Biberauer & Roberts (2009: 74), Reintges (2009), Axel & Weiß (2010), Sundquist
(2010), Breitbarth et al. (2010) and Meisel (in press).
It seems desirable, following the view of Lightfoot (1979, 2002) that there are no
principles of history and that ‗there is no theory of change to be had independent of theories
of grammar and acquisition‘ (βίίβμ 1βι), to reduce the Inertial Theory to properties of the
faculty of language and to acquisition. However, it turns out that such a reduction is
impossible. This is so because when working on syntactic change we have to assume (9) and
(10).
(9)
(10)
τcquirers do not have access to the grammar of the ‗target‘ languageέ
Experience plays a direct role in the acquisition of syntax.
These assumptions are uncontroversial: acquirers are not telepathic, and the acquisition
process makes use of evidence. As noted in Section 1, the observation in (9) was an important
part of Andersen (1973). Now in order for the Inertial Theory to work, (11) would also have
to hold:
(11)
The acquisition of syntax is a deterministic process.
The intended meaning of (11) is that, for any temporally ordered set of sentences (PLD), any
and all learners exposed to it will converge on the same grammar (a one-to-one or many-toone mappingν cfέ δightfoot βίί6μ κλ)μ there is no ‗―imperfect‖ learning or ―spontaneous‖
innovation‘ (Longobardi 2001: 278). Clearly (11) is necessary for any version of the Inertial
Theory, since imperfect learning and spontaneous innovation cannot be said to be caused by
234 George Walkden
other types of change or by interface phenomena: the falsity of (11) entails the falsity of (6)–
(8). It must be noted, however, that many algorithms for syntactic acquisition (e.g. Gibson &
Wexler 1994, Yang 2002) do not assume that the acquisition of syntax is deterministic in this
way. While the unambiguous triggers model of Fodor (1998) and cue-based models such as
that of Lightfoot (1999, 2006) are compatible with determinism, the Trigger Learning
Algorithm of Gibson & Wexler (1994), upon which the diachronic model of Niyogi &
Berwick (1995) is based, relies on the existence of local maxima to explain change: the
learning algorithm contains a ‗roll of the dice‘ which may lead learners irretrievably astray in
a certain proportion of cases. Similarly, the probabilistic component of the model developed
by Yang (2002) may lead to the acquirer assigning different weights to certain hypotheses
than the individuals from whose competence the PLD is generated. It is also not the case that
(11) is coextensive with the Inertial Theory, since (11) makes no predictions about any
relation between grammars diachronically, unlike the statements in (6)–(8).
Assuming (9), (10) and (11), the following scenario illustrates how the Inertial Theory
must be false: imagine a child whose parents‘ grammar requires ↑-to-C movement in
wh-questions. Now let us suppose that the parents never needed or wanted to ask direct
questions in the presence of the child (for whatever reason), and therefore that the PLD
includes no relevant examples. The child therefore fails to acquire V-to-C movement in
wh-questions in her grammar. The scenario may be unlikely to occur, but, crucially, cannot be
argued to be impossible for any principled reason.
Syntactic change has clearly occurred in the above scenarioέ Is this change ‗caused‘, in
the terminology of (6)? The answer is unclear: if there is a cause, it is clearly whatever
motivated the fluctuation in the trigger experience. But this is not necessarily a wellmotivated consequence of other types of change. Here it is essentially chance that has
‗caused‘ the changeν even assuming determinism in acquisition as in (11), there is simply no
guarantee that the PLD will contain relevant examples. The claim that syntactic change does
not arise unless caused, as phrased in (6), then, makes predictions that are too strong. The
scenario is even more of a problem for (7), since there can be no question that the change in
this scenario might have originated as an ‗interface phenomenon‘μ no semantic or
morphophonological change preceded it. Finally, if (6) and (7) are false of this scenario, then
(κ) is also falseμ syntax is not ‗diachronically completely inert‘έ →hile the assumption in (11),
that acquisition is deterministic, may be tenable, then, the Inertial Theory as proposed by
Longobardi (2001) is not.
There may be a deeper problem even with the application of the ‗pretheoretical‘ notion
of inertiaέ (5), Keenan‘s claim that things stay as they are unless acted on by an outside force
or decay, applies not only in linguistics, as he stresses; in fact, the formulation is very similar
to that of ζewton‘s (16κι) first law of motionέ The problem is that, if the Chomskyan view
that traditional conceptions of ‗language‘ are incoherent is accepted (as, implicitly, by Keenan
2002 and Longobardi 2001, and those in the generative community making use of the notion),
there is no clear sense in which a language is diachronically a ‗thing‘έ Under this view, Ilanguage is the object of study, and each generation has to acquire a grammar anew, as
Lightfoot (1979, 2002: 117, 2006) has consistently argued. In other words, if the I-language
thesis is accepted and there is no meaningful entity above the level of the individually
instantiated grammar, there is no reason we‘d expect inertia to hold in language change.
Inertia, and the Inertial Theory of Longobardi (2001), therefore suffer from a number
of crippling problems, suggesting that, like abduction, the concept may be of little use in the
study of language change.
3. THE INCOMPATIBILITY OF ABDUCTION AND INERTIA
As we have seen, the notions of abduction and inertia are highly problematic in their own
right. In this section I demonstrate that the two notions are mutually incompatible: no theory
Abduction or inertia? The logic of syntactic change 235
of abduction with empirical content is compatible with any theory of inertia with empirical
content, as the assumptions that underlie them are conflicting.
In particular, the assumption of determinism in (11), and therefore also the Inertial
Theory, cannot easily be reconciled with abduction or inference to the best explanation.
Broadly speaking, abduction, and inference to the best explanation, emphasize the creativity
of acquirers, while determinism denies the possibility of such creativity. Recall that (11) is
intended to mean that, for any temporally ordered set of sentences (PLD), any and all learners
exposed to it will converge on the same grammar. But if learning takes place by abduction or
inference to the best explanation, how can this be guaranteed? As emphasized by Deutscher
(βίίβ), θeirce‘s late notion of abduction as in (δ) and inference to the best explanation are
forms of ampliative inference, and as such are, definitionally, not deductively valid; see, for
example, the definition in the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Craig 1998). So if
learning takes place by abduction or inference to the best explanation, unless all people can be
guaranteed to abduce in precisely the same way (cf. Lass 1997: 335) it cannot be
deterministic, and syntax therefore cannot be inert.
One might try to save the compatibility of abduction and inertia in the following way:
one could argue that abduction/inference to the best explanation applied regularly in language
acquisition, in that, given a set of conditions R, the criteria for the best explanation would
always apply in the same way and the same explanation would be adduced by each acquirer.
This would equate to adopting the idea, mentioned with some scepticism by Lass (1997: 335–
6), that all people could be guaranteed to abduce in a uniform manner. Notationally this would
look something like the following:
(12)
P⊃Q
R ⊃ (Q ⊃ P)
Q
R
________________
∴P
In other words, there exists a law P ⊃ Q (as in the syllogistic schematization of (3) in Section
1), say ‗If x is a man, then x is mortal‘ or ‗If x is the head of a head-final phrase, then the
phrase that is x‘s complement is head-final‘ (cfέ Holmberg βίίί, Biberauer, Holmberg &
Roberts 2007, 2008 for discussion of this putative linguistic universal, which is in fact
certainly more complex than this if it holds at all). But in a certain set of circumstances,
represented by the boundary conditions R, it is legitimate to flip the rule around and to infer
that ‗If x is mortal, then x is a man‘ or ‗If the phrase that is x‘s complement is head-final, then
x is the head of a head-final phrase‘έ (Biberauer, Holmberg and Roberts (2007, 2008)
demonstrate that the latter is not a universal.) Then if R obtains, and if Q obtains (i.e. if x is
mortal or if the phrase that is x‘s complement is head-final), then we infer P, that x is a man
or that x is the head of a head-final phraseέ →hile of course this system isn‘t guaranteed to
produce ‗truth‘, it is fully compatible with the assumption of determinism in (11)έ τssuming
that R ⊃ (Q ⊃ P) is shared by all acquirers, whenever R and Q are both the case, P will also
be.
→hat‘s the problem with this solutionς →ell, in one important sense there is no
problem at allμ it‘s a deductively valid inferenceέ Crucially, however, if we apply this logic
then we have reduced this instance of ‗inference to the best explanation‘ to deductive
inference. But since inference to the best explanation is definitionally ampliative, what we‘ve
argued is actually that if language acquisition works in this way it is not a case of ampliative
inference, inference to the best explanation or abduction, but rather a deductive process. It
then becomes redundant and meaningless to refer to the acquisition process as ‗abductive‘. By
236 George Walkden
formulating abductive inference in such a way as to be compatible with the determinism of
(11), we have in fact done away with the notion of abduction entirely.
Alternatively, we could abandon the notion of determinism in (11), and with it any
notion of ‗inertia‘, whether that of Keenan (1994, 2002, 2009) as in (5) or that of Longobardi.
(2001) as in (6)–(8). But (11) is an ontological claim, and if we deny it, we are making the
opposite claimμ that there are random ‗rolls of the dice‘ involved in language acquisitionν cfέ
Bresnan & Deo‘s (βίί1) ‗όallacy of Reified Ignorance‘ and the discussion in Hale (βίίι)έ
This amounts to abandoning any hope of coming up with a fully causal explanation for
acquisition phenomena, and to abandoning θopper‘s θrinciple of Causalityμ ‗the simple rule
that we are not to abandon the search for universal laws and for a coherent theoretical system,
nor ever give up our attempts to explain causally any kind of event we can describe‘ (θopper
1968: 67; cf. the discussion in Lass 1980: 101–103). This does not necessarily mean that
insight into the patterns behind the data is impossible in linguistics, as Lass (1980) argues; it
could conceivably be the case that this deductive-nomological mode of explanation is
inappropriate to language acquisition. However, even if (11) turns out to be empirically
untenable (and I know of no evidence falsifying it for syntax), there is still a case to be made
that something like it should be adopted on methodological grounds, as is done in e.g.
microeconomic theory, where the many contingent factors affecting individuals‘ decisions are
abstracted away from and uniformity is assumed. Such a methodological decision is implicitly
taken in general linguistic theory, where it is normally assumed that whatever constitutes the
human capacity for language is biologically invariant across the species, despite the fact that
other organs (e.g. the eye) are known to vary between individuals in subtle ways. In other
words, perhaps it‘s methodologically more responsible to argue, as Einstein (1λι1 [1λ26]) put
it in a letter to εax υorn regarding quantum mechanics, that ‗He does not throw dice‘έ
4. CONCLUSION
In Section 1 I argued, following Deutscher (βίίβ), that the notion of ‗abduction‘ in linguistics
is confused, misused, and out of step with philosophy and other sciences. It may well be the
case that abduction (or inference to the best explanation) is not relevant to language
acquisition at all (Lass 1997). In Section β I argued that the notion of ‗inertia‘, insofar as it
has content as a hypothesis, e.g. the Inertial Theory of Longobardi 2001, cannot hold if we
take even a broadly Chomskyan world-view, since it presupposes a relation between
grammars diachronically that cannot be guaranteed to obtain. Even a weaker claim, the
assumption of determinism in acquisition (11), is far from uncontroversial (cf. also Walkden
2010). In Section 3 I argued that no version of inertia with empirical content is compatible
with any version of abduction (or inference to the best explanation) with empirical content,
since the assumption that language acquisition proceeds deterministically excludes the
possibility that the type of inference involved is ampliative.
My conclusions for syntactic change are: The notions and buzzwords surrounding
‗abduction‘ and ‗inertia‘ are unhelpful, and it is a logical necessity to abandon at least one of
them. In my view, we should stop talking about abduction, we should stop talking about
inertia, and we should start taking seriously the task of coming up with syntactic learning
algorithms that are compatible with what we know about language acquisition and language
change. Borrowing terms and metaphors from philosophy and other sciences may be useful
on occasion, but in the case of ‗abduction‘ and ‗inertia‘ it has led only to confusion and timewastingέ Sometimes it‘s better to talk about language on its own termsέ
Abduction or inertia? The logic of syntactic change 237
REFERENCES
Andersen, Henning (1973) Abductive and deductive change. Language 49:765-793.
Axel, Katrin, and Helmut Weiß (2010) What changed where? A plea for the re-evaluation of
dialectal evidence. In Anne Breitbarth, Christopher Lucas, Sheila Watts and David
Willis (eds.) Continuity and change in grammar. Amsterdam: John Benjamins, pp. 1334.
Biberauer, Theresa, Anders Holmberg and Ian Roberts (2007) Disharmonic word-order
systems and the Final-over-Final Constraint (FOFC). In Antonietta Bisetto and
Francesco Barbieri (eds.) Proceedings of XXXIII Incontro di Grammatica Generativa,
pp. 86-105.
Biberauer, Theresa, Anders Holmberg and Ian Roberts (2008) Linearising disharmonic word
orders: the Final-over-Final Constraint. In K-A. Kim (ed.) Perspectives on Linguistics
in the 21st Century, pp. 301-318.
Biberauer, Theresa, and Ian Roberts (2009) The return of the Subset Principle. In Paola
Crisma and Giuseppe Longobardi (eds.) Historical syntax and linguistic theory.
Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 58-75.
Breitbarth, Anne, Christopher Lucas, Sheila Watts and David Willis (2010) Introduction. In
Anne Breitbarth, Christopher Lucas, Sheila Watts and David Willis (eds.) Continuity
and change in grammar. Amsterdam: John Benjamins, pp. 1-12.
Bresnan, Joan and Ashwini Deo (2001) ύrammatical constraints on variationμ “ψe” in the
survey of English dialects and (stochastic) Optimality Theory. Ms. Stanford
University.
Craig, Edward (ed.) (1998). Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. London: Routledge.
Deutscher, Guy (2002) On the misuse of the notion of ―abduction‖ in linguisticsέ Journal of
Linguistics 38: 469-485.
Einstein, Albert (1971) The Born-Einstein Letters. New York: Walker.
Ferraresi, Gisella and Maria Goldbach (2003) Some reflections on inertia: Infinitive
complements in Latin. In Nicole Baumgarten, Claudia Böttger, Markus Motz and Julia
Probst (eds.) Übersetzen, Interkulturelle Kommunikation, Spracherwerb und
Sprachvermittlung - das Leben mit mehreren Sprachen: Festschrift fur Juliane House
zum 60. Geburtstag, pp.1-12. [Zeitschrift für Interkulturellen
Fremdsprachenunterricht [Online] 8.]
Fodor, Janet Dean (1998) Unambiguous triggers. Linguistic Inquiry 29: 1-36.
Gibson, Edward and Kenneth Wexler (1994) Triggers. Linguistic Inquiry 25: 407-454.
Hale, Mark (2007) Historical linguistics: theory and method. Oxford: Blackwell.
Holmberg, Anders (2000) Deriving OV order in Finnish. In Peter Svenonius (ed.) The
derivation of VO and OV. Amsterdam: John Benjamins, pp. 123-152.
Hróarsdóttir, Thorbjörg (2002) Explaining language change: a three-step process. Linguistics
in Potsdam 19: 103-141.
Hróarsdóttir, Thorbjörg (2003) Language change and language acquisition. Nordlyd 31: 133155.
Hume, David (1910 [1748]) An enquiry concerning human understanding. New York:
Collier.
Ingham, Richard (2006) On two negative concord dialects in early English. Language
Variation and Change 18: 241-266.
Jäger, Agnes (2008) History of German negation. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Keenan, Edward (1994) Creating anaphors: an historical study of the English reflexive
pronouns. Ms. University of California at Los Angeles.
Keenan, Edward (2002) Explaining the creation of reflexive pronouns in English. In Donka
Minkova and Robert Stockwell (eds.) Studies in the history of the English language: a
millennial perspective. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter, pp. 325-355.
238 George Walkden
Keenan, Edward (2009) Linguistic theory and the historical creation of English reflexives. In
Paola Crisma and Giuseppe Longobardi (eds.) Historical syntax and linguistic theory.
Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 17-40.
Kisilevsky, Barbara, Sylvia Hains, Kang Lee, Xing Xie, Hefeng Huang, Hai Hui Ye, Ke
Zhang and Zengping Wang (2003) Effects of experience on fetal voice recognition.
Psychological Science 14: 220-224.
Lass, Roger (1980) On explaining language change. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Lass, Roger (1997) Historical linguistics and language change. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Lightfoot, David W. (1979) Principles of diachronic syntax. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Lightfoot, David W. (1999) The development of language: acquisition, change and evolution.
Oxford: Blackwell.
Lightfoot, David W. (2002) Myths and the prehistory of grammars. Journal of Linguistics 38:
113-116.
Lightfoot, David W. (2006) How new languages emerge. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Lipton, Peter (2000) Inference to the best explanation. 2nd edn. London: Routledge.
Longobardi, Giuseppe (2001) Formal syntax, diachronic Minimalism, and etymology: the
history of French chez. Linguistic Inquiry 32: 275-302.
McMahon, April M.S. (1994) Understanding language change. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Meisel, Jürgen (in press) Bilingual language acquisition and theories of diachronic change:
bilingualism as cause and effect of grammatical change. Bilingualism: Language and
Cognition.
Newton, Isaac (1687) Philosophiæ Naturalis Principia Mathematica. London: Royal Society.
Niyogi, Partha, and Robert Berwick (1995) The logical problem of language change. MIT
Artificial Intelligence Laboratory Memo No. 1516. Cambridge, MA.
Reintges, Chris (2009) Spontaneous syntactic change. In Paola Crisma and Giuseppe
Longobardi (eds.) Historical syntax and linguistic theory. Oxford: Oxford University
Press, pp. 41-57.
Roberts, Ian (2007) Diachronic syntax. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Roberts, Ian and Anna Roussou (2003) Syntactic change: a Minimalist approach to
grammaticalization. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Sundquist, John (2010) Variation, continuity and contact in Middle Norwegian and Middle
Low German. Anne Breitbarth, Christopher Lucas, Sheila Watts and David Willis
(eds.) Continuity and change in grammar. Amsterdam: John Benjamins, pp. 145-168.
Trask, Robert L. (2000) Dictionary of historical and comparative linguistics. Edinburgh:
Edinburgh University Press.
Waltereit, Richard, and Ulrich Detges (2008) Syntactic change from within and from without
syntax: a usage-based analysis. In Ulrich Detges and Richard Waltereit (eds.) The
paradox of grammatical change: perspectives from Romance. Amsterdam: John
Benjamins, pp. 13-30.
Yang, Charles (2002) Knowledge and learning in natural language. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Abduction or inertia? The logic of syntactic change 239
George Walkden
Department of Linguistics
Sidgwick Avenue
University of Cambridge
Cambridge
CB3 9DA
United Kingdom
[email protected]
http://www.srcf.ucam.org/~gw249/