Actual Existence and Factual Objectivation
or: anti-anti-realism with intuitionist negation or: why veracious objectivism with ontological adjustment can do better
than epistemologically infected would-be ontologies
or: what theories are and what they are not
or: why in the course of the matter truth will come to light
by Dan KURTH
Institut für Geschichte der Naturwissenschaften
Johann Wolfgang Goethe Universität
60054 Frankfurt am Main
Germany
e-mail:
[email protected]
First version, finished Frankfurt am Main, May 15th 2002
presented to anpa-list
(http://groups.yahoo.com/group/anpa-list)
PRELIMINARY PRELIMINARIES
3
1 AS A FURTHER PRELIMINARY: INTRODUCING ACTUALISM
3
2 STARTING THE ARGUMENT: ACTUALIST EXISTENTIALISM
5
3 THE INTERFACE OF THEORIES AND ACTUAL EXISTENCE: EVIDENCE
6
4 THEORIES IN THEMSELVES: ONTOLOGICAL RELATIVITY
10
5 INTERTHEORETICAL RELATIONS: ONTOLOGICAL ADJUSTMENT
11
2
Then we entered the Straits in great fear of mind, for
on the one hand was Scylla, and on the other dread
Charybdis kept sucking up the salt water.∗
Preliminary Preliminaries
There is a certain unfair asymmetry in the world: anti-realists make some good points by attacking
epistemological realism1, because there they have a good point. Realists make far less good points by
defending realism, because there they have no good point.
To make this very clear from the beginning this paper is not at all and in no instance whatsoever in the
business of epistemology, some people might feel that it is sometimes somehow about epistemology
which then might be due to their perceptions. But anyway being about something doesn’t mean being
in the business of that something.2 Realism and (some sorts of) anti-realism are rightly seen as representing predominantly epistemological convictions apparently being opposed to each other. But then
this opposition is essentially based on a very common ground or rather the very common fault of them
both as will be shown in this paper. In the course of this paper we will introduce anti-anti-realism
(with intuitionist negation) and whatever this might turn out to be it will definitely not turn out to be
an epistemological position. The notion of ‘anti-anti- realism with intuitionist negation’ anyway is
already by itself a paraphrase of (implicitly) proposing that realism and anti-realism show some
equivalence under a certain aspect and that anti-anti-realism with intuitionist negation does not so.3
We are hopeful that in the course of the paper that aspect will come to light.
Thus a way to correct that certain unfair asymmetry might go as follows: anti-anti-realists should
eventually start to attack anti-realism - from maybe unexpected directions and surely with a very
unconventional strategy - because there they might have some good points to gain. And anti-realists
then should start defending anti-realism (maybe after first having sorted out which one they lately
prefer). Afterwards let’s count the points or rather - the fallen.
1
As a further Preliminary: Introducing Actualism
1.1 We understand the term ‘actualism’ as a shortcut for the following proposition:
The actually existing world is made of actually existing entities and the actually existing interactions
between them.4
1.1.1 For a better understanding of 1.1 one should note that ‘interaction’ here is not meant to be a
theoretical or scientific term in any possible sense or to presuppose or to imply any objective
(theoretical or scientific) knowledge. ‘Interaction’ instead has to be understood as something alike the
∗
Homer, The Odyssey, book XII, (transl. by Samuel Butler), http://classics.mit.edu./Homer/Odyssey. 12.xii.html
Epistemological realism as usually opposed to anti-realism is in principle quite a different thing than ontological
realism as opposed to idealism, notwithstanding the fact that these both kinds of realism frequently go together. If
from now on we speak of ‘realism’ we will always speak of epistemological realism if not explicitly the contrary
is announced.
2 For example there are probably hundreds of tutorial textbooks about epistemology the authors of which do not
stand for any specific epistemolgical position, at least not in these textbooks. Of course such textbooks are only a
very few of a legion of examples which corroborate that proposed distinction of ‘being about something’ and
‘being in the business of something’ as another graphic example may serve that there are quite a lot of today’s
books and papers which are about the historical controversy between the Ptolemaic and the Copernican system,
yet the authors of those books or papers really only rarely turn out to take a side or to be proponents of one of the
both positions, i.e. they write about that historical controversy but they are not in the business of that controversy.
3 That of course will be apparent to people somewhat familiar with intuitionist logic.
4 To elucidate my understanding of ‘actually existing world’ I will give the following as an illustration:
a) Actual physical existence is effected and warranted by actual physical interaction. In other words: only if an
entity actually physically interacts then this entity also exists physically.
b) Therefore the actually existing world should be thought of as the totality of all actually existing entities, i.e. the
totality of all actually (directly and indirectly) interacting entities together with the respective actually operating
interactions.
But because these both statements a) and b) imply a reference to possible objective knowledge they must not be
seen as a part of our preliminary introduction of actualism but only as an illustration - hors concours.
1
3
‘contact between an actually existing person and other actually existing persons or other actually
existing things’. Therefore there is some overlapping of the meaning of ‘actually existing world’ with
the meanings of ‘Lebenswelt’ (as introduced by Husserl) or ‘In-der-Welt-Sein’ (as introduced by
Heidegger). Yet the scope of ‘actually existing world’ is not confined to the (social) world(s) of
human beings or intelligent living beings in general.
1.1.2 As being actually existent also persons (or any observers) - directly or indirectly - do interact
with all other actually existing entities (including such they may never have heard of, they don’t know
anything about and even possibly including such neither they nor anyone else ever had a theory for).
1.2 The actually existing world, i.e. the actual existence of actually existing entities and the actually
existing interactions between them, is a crude given. 5
1.2.1 For a better understanding of 1.2 one should note that the actually existing world has strictly to
be seen as not related to, not dependent on and not derivable from any objective factual knowledge
(about the world), any theories, any science or any epistemological conceptual frames.
1.2.2 Just on the contrary the actually existing world has to be understood as an utmost radically pretheoretical given as well as an extra-theoretical precondition for any possible existence of any
objective knowledge (about the world), any theories, any science or even any epistemological
conceptual frames.
1.2.3 Thus actual existence is utterly not in the scope and not an object of theoretically based factual
knowledge.
1.2.3.1 Therefore it is nothing but missing the point to ask someone: “But how do you know about the
actual existence of the actually existing world?”, because there is no question of knowing but a
question of living (or subjectively existing).
1.3 Actualism as introduced here in the foregoing has no epistemological significance whatsoever.
1.3.1 Therefore actualism as such doesn’t provide any means to refuse either realism or anti-realism at
large. Agreeing to it could make any reasonable ordinary anti-realists at the most feel a bit uncomfortable, but it wouldn’t mean any imminent threat to their position.
1.3.2 Not agreeing to actualism would obviously be the choice for some - perhaps less reasonable but
as a compensation for that maybe more suspicious - anti-realists, in particular the solipsist breed. And
by doing so they would not have to fear any inconsistency of their position so far.
1.4 To make this as clear as possible once more: no anti-realist of whatever kind has to agree to or
admit any of the previous propositions, i.e. till now we didn’t start with an argument but simply tried as a preliminary - to somewhat clarify our terminology and put some of our basic convictions on the
table. Sooner or later we would have to do so anyway and there is no reason why not to do so at the
beginning.
5
For reasons of readability I would have preferred to say ‘a crude fact’ instead of ‘a crude given’ but that would
have been inconsistent with what I thoroughly want to make clear here, namely that the assumption of actual
existence and the actually existing world in particular is neither dependent on nor in any other way due to
reasoning, (learned) knowledge or even theoretical presumptions but that instead it stems from certitude. Thus it
is not in any sense made (for example by means of our intellectual capacity) but instead it is given (for example
as a precondition for our being as such as well as for any possible intellectual capacity of ours). Therefore it
shouldn’t be referred to as ‘fact’.
4
2
Starting the Argument: Actualist Existentialism
6
2.1 Your actual subjective existence is not an attribute, a property or an adjunct to yourself, yet your
actual existence is just your actual existence. As such it is a radical presupposition or rather a radical
given for having any attributes, properties or any adjuncts whatsoever.
2.1.1 You can not have or hold your actual subjective existence as you can have inner states like pain
or hold beliefs, convictions or propositions.
2.2 You don’t need a theory for your actual subjective existence, i.e. therefore that you (can or) do
actually exist.
2.3 Your fundamental existential apprehension of your actual subjective existence is neither derivable
from nor - in principle - dependent on theories, but it is founded in your certitude of actually being
existent. 7
2.4 Thus you must at first exist to possibly hold (or have8) a theory.
2.4.1 Actual subjective existence - as related to theories - is a radically pre-theoretical given as well as
an extra-theoretical precondition for any possible existence of theories.
2.5 To make an explicit distinction between on the one hand actualism, which says that there is an
actually existing world made of actually existing entities with actually existing interactions between
these entities, and on the other hand the set of propositions which are based on the specific assertion
that there is plain actual subjective existence we will call the later from now on ‘actualist existentialism’.
2.6 Actualist existentialism as outlined above now in a way will allow us to finally neglect solipsism.
2.6.1 Actualist existentialism allows us to do so not primarily by arguing with the proponents of solipsism about their epistemological conceptions yet instead by regarding the holding of those
conceptions to be an existential absurdity.
2.6.1.1 The basic assertion of a (radical) solipsist is that his or her consciousness (or mind or mental
state) is the only what exists. The problem what he or she will get is with the ‘his or her’ in that assertion. The reason for this is that we can challenge the solipsist by stating that when he or she is con6
Our argumentation in this section of this paper (as well as the terminological introduction of actualism in the
previous one) must not be seen as an end in itself. But it is in its uncompromising setting also meant to do as a
preparation to prevent a seemingly obvious (mis)understanding of what we will say in the 4th and in particular
the 5th section, namely the misunderstanding that we then would propose an idealist view. Emphasizing certain
aspects of theories easily tempts to commit a metabasis namely to feel somehow entitled then to forget about the
primogeniture of actual existence. We shall not be tempted to commit such a metabasis.
7 But it is a sad fact which can be concluded from an awful lot of philosophical writings - including such written
by as prominent authors as Descartes, Berkeley and Fichte - that very many philosophers at least when
considering their topics under the influence of epistemological obsessions simply lacked the sanity of having such
certitude. This didn’t take a turn for the better when it later under the flags of hermeneutics, theory loadeness,
social construction et. al. became increasingly popular to propose that everything had to be seen as being covered
by a set of impenetrable pre-understandings (Vorverständnis) sometimes called ‘interpretation’. This might or
might not have its place in the humanities which are no topic of this paper. But one would have to expect that the
proponents of that stuff would also so intensely lack reason as well as self-respect (I’m not sure in which
sequential order) that they wouldn’t shy away from uttering such sounds as ‘Everything which can be proposed including the proposition that someone’s fundamental existential apprehension or awareness of his actual
subjective existence is founded in certitude - has if it is proposed a mental representation so it is a part of
someone’s mental state or (as a proposition) his cognition and so it is a sort of knowledge and as such inseparably
entangled with various pre-understandings.’ Such inference would in my view even be in itself, namely its last
step, be incorrect (because of an incorrect or at least severely ambiguous notion of knowledge) but that anyway
doesn’t matter much here. Because fortunately such display of self-stultification can already be defeated simply
by examples, one of which may be the following: Imagine a child three to four years old living in a community
which doesn’t hold any proper (i.e. scientific) theories may it be because of social misery or because of belonging
to a pre-theoretical culture. Now imagine someone coming to this community carrying with her some food and
sweets or other little gifts and then start to give it to the children of that community as presents but deliberately
leaving out the one we introduced above and even saying directed to that child or to the other children: ‘No, don’t
hand any presents to that over there, because it doesn’t exist.’ (Dear readers, please calm down and skip your
indignation, I anyway side with you and we will bring that case to UNICEF’s attention together!) If she performs
that cruel behaviour in a not too discouraging way thereby giving our child a chance to defend the actuality of its
existence this one will start to do so may it be with whatever unskilled appeals or by being charming or daring
and will be hopefully successful. Thus it will not only have proven that it has a fundamental existential
apprehension of its own existence (founded in certitude) without possibly holding any theory from which this
insight could have been derived but also that it has more sanity than all these philosophers together which tried
and still try to do it the other way round. (They wouldn’t get a single candy from me!)
8 ‘Having’ a theory of course is something different as having pain. Even if it sometimes may cause pain to
oneself or others (the later being preferable, at least for me).
5
fronted with his or her own actual existence he or she by that then is confronted with a crude given
which is not just a matter of his or her imagination or mind. The solipsist now can either agree and by
that begin to cease to be a solipsist or disagree and claim instead that his or her so-called own actual
existence would just be an imagination or a mental state of him- or herself.
2.6.1.2 But that exactly is something he cannot do. Because such a claim is equivalent to a statement
that he as well as his mental states would not exist. 9 Despite the fact that this could very well be desirable for other people than that solipsist he still simply wouldn’t be entitled to assert such an existential
absurdity apparently based on an implicit logical contradiction.
2.6.2 Yet this indeed was not all the task to be done. This rather comes up with the question if a less
radical solipsist would after having admitted actualist existentialism also have to admit the far more
general propositions of proper actualism itself. And this doesn’t seem to be the case. That less radical
solipsist must not admit actualism. But this is not the (dead) end of the argument and not an easy
escape for more or less radical solipsists. Because the question is not what she must admit or must not
admit but what she cannot propose.
2.6.2.1 For example she cannot deny actualism by saying that she admits her actual subjective existence but at the same time claiming that her actual subjective existence would be the only actual subjective existence which exists and thereby somehow mutate from a solipsist to - so to speak - a holipsist10. A position very similar to that which is frequently thought to be the proper solipsism yet isn’t.
A less radical solipsist cannot propose this or any other alternative to actualism because he in any of
such cases then would not only cease to be a solipsist but even also cease to be a sceptic because he
would have stated to have objective factual knowledge of (the making up of) the world (external to his
consciousness).
2.6.3 Therefore the only thing a solipsist confronted by his own actual subjective existence can do is
either to admit his actual subjective existence and by that to stay in the discourse or to deny it and then
to become a case of existential absurdity. Yet if he admits his own actual subjective existence he cannot propose to have or to be able to have any objective factual knowledge about the external world.
Just to the contrary he would have to propose that he has not and cannot have any objective factual
knowledge about the external world. And that’s exactly what we want him to confess.
2.6.4 A reasonable former solipsist would then eventually have transformed to become a sceptic.
2.7 As far as scepticism is concerned proponents of this position again have three choices: they can
either agree to actualist existentialism as outlined above and then happily live on to be sceptics - at
least for a while - or they can refuse actualist existentialism and thereby turn out to have become
genuine solipsists and then should not wonder if being treated as such. The most appropriate attitude
of a sceptic relating to the question of agreeing to or refusing actualist existentialism of course would
be making no decision at all and to remain sceptical instead. But this would be no escape because
actually being sceptical about one’s own actual existence is not less an existential absurdity as the
respective solipsist position and just being as completely meaningless as that.
2.8 So we might conclude this in a more traditional manner: Nisi sum non cogito. Or to put this in a
more classical Latin and in a one with more notional rigour as the one a particular continental philosopher preferred to apply: Nisi sum existens prius tum ne cogitans ero quidem. (If I do not exist at first I
then will not be thinking too.)
3
The interface of theories and actual existence: evidence
3.1 Theories do not refer to the actually existing world or to any actual existence.
3.1.1 The actually existing world is not in the scope of theories.
3.1.2 The actually existing world doesn’t directly or immediately interact with theories.
3.1.2.1 This is of course is just trivial not at last due to the fact that theories do not act at all.
3.1.2.2 For a better understanding of 3.1.2 please note: The actually existing world has no direct or
immediate significance for theories, except for the fact that theories usually are hold by actually subjectively existent entities, which indeed is an important ‘fact’ (yet not of theories but of life).
9
The reason for this is of course that a mental state cannot exist by itself. Yet there would probably be found
proponents for that as well. Even if these proponents could no more be regarded as proper solipsists (because they
already would have lost that ‘ipse’ and would perhaps better be called ‘mentesolists’) there also is an argument of
the same sort as the previous one available against such people: At least that mental state must somehow exist.
And that existence (or at least some existence which would come up in a possible seeming infinite regress) must
be something different than just an attribute of the mental state of which it is supposed to be its existence.
10 To add insult to injury I have to confess that such a mutation then would seem to me to be a kind of GraecoRoman style transformation.
6
3.2 The holders of theories - apparently inspired by that holding - often show a particular attitude towards a presumed relation of theories to the actually existing world, which is: they test them.
3.2.1 Yet testing a theory does not at all imply or yield the possibility of gaining any so called
empirical (insight or) knowledge about the actually existing world.
3.3 Testing a theory is essentially nothing but a sometimes quite complicated way of making a very
special betting on the outcomes of predictions possible. The result of such bets itself then is
sometimes called ‘evidence’.
3.3.1 The betting - of what we are speaking here - can be as well a bet between different proponents
having opposing expectations concerning the possible outcomes of that testing of a theory as a bet
with oneself about the validity of opposing hypotheses one weighs against each other.
3.3.2 Evidence is gained by the results of the betting on the outcomes of predictions. There are mainly
three kinds of predictions a) predictions of the outcomes of actions possibly combined with events.
Such actions combined with events are normally called experiments, b) another kind of prediction is
rather a then still not observed postulate of the theory like for example - at their time - the existence of
the neutrino or the aberration of the mercury orbit have been. The observation of the postulated
occurrence (i.e. the corroboration of the respective postulate) then has the same significance as the
outcome of a proper experiment and - in a sense - is an experiment (with less action and more event).
c) The third kind are the implicit or rather tacit predictions which underlie as well as diffuse into all
the applications of theories, i.e. all applied science and thereon based technology. These latest are the
ones with the least philosophical relevance because there the basic validity and significance of the
respective theories themselves is hardly ever at stake or disputed, but then these also are the bets by
winning which one can really make the money.
3.3.3 The particular predictions as related to actual tests or experiments are not a proper part of the
respective theories, that is because theories do not specify individual cases and events but predictions
must do.
3.3.4 Yet this is not so obvious in the case b) of 3.3.2 i.e. the one of the mentioned postulates.
3.3.4.1 Even though for example in the case of the aberration of the mercury orbit there had been
indeed still alternative explanations around (even after that prediction of GR had been confirmed), and
the mercury orbit after all is quite an individual case.
3.3.4.2 In such other cases - as the neutrino case is one - this can no longer be reasonably proposed,
even though absolutely any observation presupposes an extra-theoretical interpretation requiring
specifications and even acts of pointing to something for ascribing that something the property of
being an instance of a model of a respective theory. But this is just a further explanation of the fact
that theories do not refer. It does not provide the means to play down or lower the significance of such
kind of postulates which stem from the very entrails of a theory (in the case of Pauli’s prediction of
the existence of the neutrino from the role of symmetries in QM) and then become confirmed by
observation. Thus we have clearly to admit the fact that in such cases a particular evidence appears to
come into very close contact with the adjunctive ontology of the respective theory.
3.3.4.3 But even then presumably actually existing neutrinos are not in any sense more a part or an
element of QM (or any other theory) than actually existing electrons, the presumed existence of which
had not been postulated by QM but rather been - loosely spoken - a dowry by preceding theoretical
models (as e.g. Rutherford’s model of the atom), i.e. neither neutrinos nor electrons nor any presumably actually existing entities are proper parts or elements of any theory. Simply because of that stubborn fact that theories are made of propositions or models and not of entities.
3.4 Evidence doesn’t consist of or lead to (empirical) knowledge of the actually existing world. Evidence rather contributes positively or (in the case of lost bets or lack of evidence) negatively to the
degree of conviction which potential (rational and not too old) holders can muster up for their support
of a particular theory.
3.5 Evidence selects.
3.5.1 To try to provide a better understanding of that selective function of evidence I will - for a moment - transgress to a seemingly unrelated topic being well aware that by this transgression I will
hardly make more friends.
3.5.1.1 Saying that theories do not refer implies - in my view - a very strong analogy to saying that
biological species do not adapt. I tend to hold both these propositions for similar reasons. Explaining
the reasons for holding the proposition related to evolutionary biology may help (or not) to understand
the proposition related to the philosophy of science.
3.5.1.2 Adaptation is an utterly Lamarckian concept (despite the fact that Darwin used it at the core of
his work). Adaptation implies and demands a possible minute change and variation of the built-in
construction of an organism caused by comparably minute interactions with a so called environment
which the organism must be somehow enabled to actively grasp or even screen as such. And then to
be effective that minute change and variation had to be adjusted to a rather invariant structure of the so
called environment and not just to the ever varying appearances of it. But for the organism such an
7
invariant structure of the so called environment simply doesn’t actually exist. If anything at all would
exist in that sense then it would have to be the mentioned ever varying appearances and there strictly
would be no adaptation or active assimilation possible to that, because an organism impossibly ever
could minutely change or vary its built-in construction in any therefore required way as we know from
genetic biology.
3.5.1.3 The environment is rather a black box for the organism. And the changes and transformations
which the subsequent organisms are subject to in the course of biological evolution are - so to speak caused by the unpredictable boons or strikes effected by the unaccountable forces in that black box.
‘Adaptation’ should - in my view - be regarded as to be nothing than a synonym for ‘fine tuned selection’, but then selection anyway is always fine tuned (i.e. as fined tuned as necessary to be effective).
3.5.1.4 What adaptation implies and demands, namely minute change and variation of a built-in perceptive construction of an organism, can only be accomplished and performed by a learning system.
After all adaptation is an utterly Lamarckian concept.
3.5.2 Now let’s see if we could have learned (since at least we should be supposed to be somehow
learning systems) anything for the sake of the philosophy of science by that transgression to evolutionary biology?11
3.5.2.1 If that proposed analogy holds than the actually existing world should be the same for theories
what the environment has been said to be for the organisms, namely a black box. But because that
doesn’t sound as philosophical speech is supposed to sound, we rather would translate this: For theories the actually existing world is - a sort of - thing in itself. 12 13
3.5.3 And evidence (or the lack of it) should be seen as analogous to the unpredictable boons or
strikes which - in the case of evidence - now are effected by the unaccountable making of the actually
existing world. That these boons or strikes are unpredictable is in no contradiction to the proposition
that evidence is gained by the results of the betting on the outcomes of predictions. Because if we
would be able to predict these boons or strikes this would mean that we would be able to make a (kind
of meta)prediction about the possible success or failure of our original predictions, i.e. we would
always win, i.e. we would actually have (total) factual objective knowledge about the entire making of
the actually existing world. Which would correspond to an assertion refused in this paper and which to put it mildly - also doesn’t seem to be the case.
3.6 Ceterum censeo: For a theory the actually existing world is a black box or a sort of thing in itself.
3.7 Evidence doesn’t provide either falsification or verification of theories.
3.7.1 Evidence instead rather increases or diminishes the strength of the adherence to (or the convictions concerning) particular theories, namely the respective strength (of convictions or adherence)
which the holder of these theories can muster. Thereby the insufficiency or lack of evidence might
sometimes even induce these holders to give up respective theories.
11
But then there also a note of caution has to be expressed, especially addressed to those which might admit the
significance of the analogy mentioned in 3.5.1.1. Despite this analogy of adaptation (of organisms) and reference
(of theories) in respect to the fact that both do not exist, I don’t view the development of theories in the history of
science bearing any relevant similarity to biological evolution. Just to the contrary: there are overwhelmingly
differences between these both kinds of development.
12 The sort of this ‘thing in itself’ at least is one which is neither derived nor presupposed by any epistemological
consideration, i.e. it is not of the Kantian sort.
To address another aspect of our topic in this section, namely the ‘interface’ of theories and actual existence,
might perhaps help a bit to sort out: In the view of so much windowlessness as we ascribed to theories some
people might somehow feel reminded of the monads of Leibniz and perhaps such feeling is not completely
misleading.
13 To carry that proposed analogy between the selection of theories in the course of the history of science and the
selection of species in the course of biological evolution to the extreme of a statement analogous to that telling
semi-tautology at the core of the theory of natural selection, i.e. the one concerning the ‘survival of the fittest’ one
could state that in the history of science theories become selected by evidence to the result of the ‘confirmation of
the best-fitting’. Yet as fitness in biological evolution shouldn’t imply adaptation but just the ability to survive (at
a particular stage of evolution) so ‘fitting best’ in the philosophy of science shouldn’t imply representation but
just the ability of a theory to relatively better conceive, elucidate and explicate a theoretical problem or question
(at a particular stage of the history of science) than its competitors at that time could do. This could include as
well a fitness for successful predictions (or wining bets) as - in particular in somewhat earlier stages of the history
of science - a fitness for withstanding being examined in the light of even completely arbitrary authoritative
extra-theoretical dogmas. Of course neither the evidence mustered for the predictions nor the ability to
successfully pass (or survive) the examinations based on those extra-theoretical dogmas ever had anything to do
with the proper internal truth of the respective theories. (Cf. the sentences 5.6 to 5.17 in this paper.)
Thus the fitness in both cases (the biological and the one related to the historical development of theories) is a
fitness for (a qualification, a capability or a state of being enabled) and not a fitting in, a fitting into, a fitting to or
a fitting with which all are characterized by connotations implicating adaptation or some kind of a possible
mapping or representation.
8
3.7.2 Theories cannot be falsified but instead become either meaningless (as - very generally spoken for example the phlogiston theory), defunct (as for example the Ptolemaic system) or a restricted if not
transmogrified model (often called: a special case) of another theory (as for example the Keplerian
theory in relation to the Newtonian or the Newtonian in relation to GR). After having become meaningless or defunct theories then sometimes even have been given up. But even if theories are given up
this is not because of falsification yet because of selection which becomes effected by the relative
amount of supporting or debilitating evidence which can be gathered or must be admitted by their
agents, i.e. their proponents.
3.8 Theories do not actually exist.14
3.8.1 To spend a little soothing to them which may need it, I am prepared to give a maybe little less
shocking interpretation of 3.8: Theories strictly are no elements of the Lebenswelt.
3.8.2 It is - to say the very least - reasonable to assume that manuscripts, textbooks, CD-ROMs, writings, sentences, formulas, graphics, illustrations as well as lessons, acoustic occurrences in
universities, demonstrations and experiments do exist. Yet theories do not actually exist.
3.8.3 Theories cannot interact, therefore theories cannot actually exist. This seems to lead us to the
rather unpleasant conclusion that there are ‘somethings’ which do not actually exist, an assumption
which frequently can be found having close ties with weird ideas. To somewhat avoid such unwelcome alliances we say that theories exists not actually yet merely intelligibly15, but we agree that such
terminological subtlety alone doesn’t effectively fend off weird ideas.
3.8.4 Theories do not act or perform anyhow in the history of science, but theories become selected by
potential holders or dismissers16 according to the respective evidence (or the lack of it).
3.8.4.1 Theories as such do not act upon the actually existing world, i.e. theories as such do not influence, change or alter any actually existing entity or any of the interactions amongst these actually
existing entities. Especially also a change of theories (i.e. rather a change of preferences by one or
more scientists towards holding another theory instead of the one she or they did hold earlier) doesn’t
influence, change or alter any actually existing entity or any of the interactions amongst these actually
existing entities.
3.8.4.2 Yet the holding of theories might perhaps motivate the respective holders to either act in a
specific way or to perceive or observe things in a specific way and thereby that holding would perhaps
somehow influence their so-called perceptions of the actually existing world. Holding a theory may
motivate scientists even to do extreme things. But theories as such never do anything, never act upon
anything, never interact with anything. This of course is a mere triviality but shifting the focus to that
triviality might help against the tendency of anthropofying theories or else suddenly think of them as
actually existing entities.
3.8.5 The actual subjective existence of the potential holders of a theory - including their motivations
and convictions - has no relevance whatsoever for the truth and meaning of the propositions of the
theory.
3.8.5.1 Any social or cultural context or any psychological or emotional disposition of the potential
holders of theories doesn’t affect the truth and meaning of the propositions of the theory in any possible way. Obviously such contexts or dispositions will affect the actual utterances of holders of
theories in the same way as such contexts or dispositions affect the utterances of anyone who make
any utterance. But the utterances of holders of theories are as such not the same as the propositions of
a theory, not even the propositional content of such utterances is by itself necessarily equivalent to the
propositions of a theory. To find out if there would be any sort of correspondence between these
different kinds of propositions one at first would have to understand the theory and from that
perspective judge the propositional content of the respective utterances. This of course is a mere
triviality but shifting the focus ... (see above).
3.9 Now, what’s really going on in that development of somethings (called ‘theories’) which allegedly
do not actually exist but then somehow seem to have a history of their own?
3.9.1 For a first provisional answer the following must do:
3.9.1.1 It seems as if there would be a beauty contest going on for the relative splendor of being more
right than the others at which the competing claims are supported (or not) by evidence (or the lack of
it). As the jury in that contest act respective subgroups of (or entangled with) the scientific community
having their judgements more or less based on evidence. But even if this comes very close to what
there is actually going on it only shows us half the picture.
14
We understand the term ‘actually exist’ as used in 3.8 in the sense of ‘actual existence’ as introduced in the
foregoing sections of this paper.
15 Saying that theories do not actually exist is of course just a special version of saying that propositions or
meanings (or ideas) do not actually exist; this being a point of view which often led to Platonism. In this paper we
will certainly not follow this lead.
16 Sorry, but sometimes (?) a little Germanism happens.
9
3.10 There namely are rather two different struggles going on delicately interlocked.
3.10.1 The already mentioned contest is between the proponents of the theories and it is done by the
mentioned betting and it is primarily about to be right, i.e. to get the higher score for example in right
predictions or consistency.
3.10.2 The other struggle is much harder to understand. It is somehow in between the theories themselves and it is no more a contest at all and in particular it is no more for the relative splendor of being
more right than others. Here instead everything is about the ultimate splendor of - oh yeah - truth.17
3.11 That later struggle will be the main topic of the last section of this paper where we will try our
best to somewhat elucidate it. But by now the time has come to look for what we have achieved in this
section in relation to our campaign against anti-realism.
3.11.1 And there we have to face a sobering result.
3.11.1.1 If theories do not interact with anything, i.e. do not influence, change or alter any actually
existing entity and above all if theories do not even refer then realism(s) of all sorts they may be metaphysical, naive, scientific, internal, moderate, modest or any meaningful combination of these predicates has (have) to be refused.
3.11.1.2 Thus in our rigid campaign against anti-realism of all sorts we just have - it may be admitted
- not even exactly by accidence killed off realism of all sorts. A strategy which - at the first glimpse would not appear to be the most target-seeking thinkable or to be overly inspired at all therefore calling it ‘very unconventional’ as we did at the beginning of that paper seems to be an euphemism as
well as an understatement of sorts. So the only thing we can do in that unpleasant situation is to hope for a second chance to come which then hopefully will show us a more pleasing picture.
4
Theories in themselves: Ontological Relativity
4.1 There is no ontology beyond the ontology/ies of (the) science(s)18.
4.1.1 An ontology is just an adjunct19 to a theory.
4.1.1.1 An ontology just should be thought of as a (formally structured) set of all potentially comprehended and acknowledged objects stated by a respective (e.g. physical) theory plus all interaction
structures presupposed or implied by the assumption of these objects (the explication of these interactions then being a part of the formal structure of the mentioned set).
4.1.1.2 An ontology - as just defined - therefore is inherently relative to the respective theory which
implicates that ontology.
4.1.1.3 As an explication of that ontological relativity we describe it as the inherent adjunctiveness of
any ontology to a respective theory.
4.2 Actual existence (including of course the actual existence of the actually existing world) is not an
element of any ontology20, and that above all because it is not an object of any theory.
4.2.1 A theory cannot have any actually existing entity as a possible object of itself, because theories
do not refer.
4.2.2 That actual existence is not an element of any ontology should already become obvious to anyone (somewhat informed) merely by the notion of ontology itself. Ontology means and equally meant
to its first practitioners like Parmenides21 and Plato22 a logos (i.e. a teaching or a doctrine) of the
being.
4.2.2.1 But actual existence in distinctive difference to such a ‘the being’ is not a subject of any teaching or doctrines because it is not related to, not dependent on and not derivable from (any theses or
axioms of) any teachings or any doctrines or any immature theories or science.
17
That will be the topic of this paper following sentence 5.6.
Please note that the slash in ‘ontology/ies’ has not the same scope as the brackets in ‘(the) science(s)’, therefore
it follows that there are four different yet equally justified possible combinations signified.
19 By using the term ‘adjunct’ we try to emphasize on the one hand the (projective) generation of an ontology
from the base of a respective theory (where the ontology then could be seen as something like an ontified dual of
the theory) and on the other hand the prevalence of the theory with respect to its ontology.
20 The proposition that actual existence is not an element or part of any ontology relates also in particular to such
chimeras as so-called ‘fundamental’ or ‘existential’ ontologies.
21 Please note: Parmenides of course incontestably not just intensely pursued ontological questions but even was
the primary founder of that subject of ontology as such, despite the fact that he didn’t use the term ‘ontology’
(which eventually had not been introduced before the early 17th century).
22 Cf. the preceding footnote, exchange ‘Plato’ for ‘Parmenides’ and adapt accordingly (i.e. there is usually only
one primary founder but possibly more than one primary scholar of a subject).
18
10
4.2.3 Therefore (not just as a gentle(?) reminder): Actual existence is an utmost radically pretheoretical crude given the inner sense for which is ultimately and entirely founded in one’s own
certitude of being actually existent.
4.2.3.1 The preceding statements 4.2.2.1 and 4.2.3 (following the colon) claim an entirely different
status than the similar sounding sentences 1.2.1 or 1.2.2 because these then had just been terminological preliminaries whereas 4.2.2.1 and 4.2.3 follow (ex negativo) from our foregoing arguments about
the inherent adjunctiveness of ontologies to the respective theories.
4.3 A theory by no means ever can produce, create, designate, impart or bestow (the) actual existence
for, of, to or on the potentially comprehended and acknowledged objects which that theory states to be
its objects. In other words: a theory doesn’t ever yield actual existence. From that follows
4.3.1 that the notion of ‘ontological commitment’ is - as the tacit proposition it was designated to be completely meaningless because as it implies that one who holds a theory should feel (or be)
committed also to hold the adjunctive ontology it proves to be nothing but a mere triviality. Anyone
who seriously holds a theory cannot ever help also holding its adjunctive ontology. As a term then
‘ontological commitment’ turns out to be a sort of pleonasm;
4.3.2 that theories do not refer (on - what is often called - an ‘outside world’, i.e. on an extratheoretical actually existing world). From that follows
4.3.2.1 again that (scientific) realism(s) of all sorts has(have) to be refused. From that usually is
derived
4.3.2.2 a pile of ... - at least in so far as science is concerned - utterly unreasonable, unjustified and
unwarranted - allegedly (implicitly) epistemologically founded - (mis)conceptions known as
relativism, contextualism, deconstructivism et al. which all have in common that they are (at least
implicitly) varieties of anti-realism.
4.4 Now again comes that nasty question up of what we have achieved in this section in our campaign
against anti-realism.
4.4.1 And being deeply patient and humble23 we remorsefully admit that even justified invectives (see
4.3.2.2) are not the best possible substitute for a striking argument. And we also have to admit that the
picture we are now confronted with - if at all - changed for the worse since we looked at it the last
time at the end of the previous section.
4.4.2 So we hear the triumphant joy of all these anti-realists and with our heart full of mercy we won’t
envy them their enjoyment - since we know the old wisdom: the end is - sort of - near.
4.4.3 To give - as it is good custom with such prophecies - a more exact date: the end is a little less
remote than the length of the next - which also happens to be the last - section of this paper. 24
5
Intertheoretical relations: ontological adjustment
5.1 But whatever could then be accomplished by theories, if theories do not refer?
5.2 To start answering with the very least: theories implicate or postulate objects, i.e. theories essentially objectivate.
5.2.1 Operating with theories then as a matter of course strictly necessitates operating with the objects
of the respective theories. And exactly by doing so anyone who appropriately operates a theory inevitably performs a reasonable approach towards its implicated adjunctive ontology, i.e. its objects or
objectivations.
5.2.1.1 Such a reasonable approach could - severely overdetermined - also be called ‘ontological
commitment’ (but better shouldn’t, see 4.3.1).
5.2.1.2 But pretending that those objects of a theory would ever be in any sense related to or even be
identical with actually existing entities25 would be nothing else than ontological superstition.26
23
Or what’s that synonym for artful?
If however it would be exactly as far remote as the length of the next section this indeed would not only be a
very cheap prophecy but also a very devastating - at least for the prospect of our campaign. By the way that next
section is unmannerly long.
25 Thus here for the first time ‘objects which are no entities’ came across. They might be worth to retain.
26 Unfortunately it was rather something of that sort what we just called ‘ontological superstition’ what Quine
originally meant by ‘ontological commitment’. Even though Quine would also have denied that theories possibly
could ever refer (in a proper sense of that word), his respective denial was based on thoroughly different reasons
above all on his concept of the underdetermination of the theory of nature (by so-called data). This famous
concept despite being a philosophical icon revered by many could - perhaps a bit sketchy - be illustrated as
pointing out some veil of fuzziness somehow wrapping up the so-called data in some opaqueness (which couldn’t
ever be completely overcome) and by that diffusing any definite relation from any particular theory to those
‘data’ thus effectively preventing the positive precision required for any (proper) reference. This then - so to
24
11
5.3 Ceterum censeo: There is no ontology beyond the ontology/ies of science.
5.3.1 But the ontology/ies of science is/are not yet completely discovered nor is/are it/they neither
comprehensively nor with exceeding depth understood, because for that being the case the ontology/ies of science would at first has/have to be founded in the ontology of the ultimate theory.
5.4 An ultimate theory is anticipated and foreshadowed in the course of the history of science.
5.5. Such a kind of parousia of an ultimate theory anticipated in the course of the history of science
comes to light by intertheoretical relations.
5.5.1 The preceding statements 5.4 and 5.5 could easily be perceived as at best a rather fanciful
version of pragmatism or worse than that as a severely chiliastic vision, but they are not meant to be
either.
5.5.1.1 The second of these both dismal interpretations is not only the one which is the even more
dismal but also the one which unfortunately will at this stage of our argumentation probably by many
be seen as the more fitting as well. But soon it anyway will casually become obsolete.
5.5.1.2 There is much more about a certain seeming accordance with an imaginable somewhat teleological version of pragmatism.
5.5.1.3 What could - though in the end rather unjustifiably - be seen as the element of such a seeming
accordance would simply be some partial similarity in the respective concepts of truth (which related
to this paper still lurks behind the scene).27
5.5.2 Such partial similarity in the respective concepts of truth would be based on only one partly
common feature, namely the stand against representation theory of truth28.
5.5.2.1 But as we later will see that stand against representation theory of truth comes in the case of
pragmatism from entirely other reasons29 than in the case of veracious objectivism 30 with ontological
speak - by ‘retroaction’ leads to the conclusion that potentially infinitely many theories - including mutually
incommensurable ones - could be equally consistent with those data. The shortcut for this is called
‘underdetermination of the theory of nature’. But there is more about underdetermination than just this ‘linguistic’
aspect. There is also an epistemological background of this concept from which it even originated.
‘Underdetermination’ as argued for by Quine in ‘Word and Object’ (cf. W.v.O.Quine, Word and Object,
Cambridge (Mass.) 1960, 21ff, 26-35, 40-46, 78) is inseparably connected with a so-called stimulus meaning (cf.
ibid. 31ff) which again is a home-bred concept of Quine based on a rather indefensible behaviorism.
But all these obstacles and impediments to a relation of theories and ‘data’ do (at least for Quine) not preclude
that relation as such. Quite on the contrary the concept of underdetermination itself strictly implies and requires
such a - however diffused - relation somehow to exist. And it is exactly here where ontological commitment
comes along as a call not to give up the loyalty to your theory just because of underdetermination.
In sharp contrast to such - except for (post)empiricism - baseless worries we would neither take any ‘data’ (in the
mentioned sense) for granted (nor admit that such a concept has any significance) yet we would consequently
deny that that claimed relation (as well as any reference of a theory to any actual existing entities, which of
course are something distinctively different from ‘data’) exists at all.
27 But then also made a step forward lately.
28 A representation theory of truth shall be defined in this paper as a theory of truth which states that a claim of
truth (i.e. a claim of being true) of a theory or a claim of truth of a sentence (or a statement) of a theory is justified
(or warranted or confirmed) if that theory (or respectively that sentence or that statement) corresponds to an
extra-theoretical (or extra-linguistic) fact (of the so-called real world). The expression ‘corresponds to’ in the
previous sentence means ‘refers to in the way of an one-to-one mapping (or a bijective mapping or an
isomorphism)’. Thus by substitution: a representation theory of truth states that a claim of truth of a theory (or a
sentence etc.) is justified (or etc., see above) if that theory (or etc., see above) refers to an extra-theoretical (or
extra-linguistic) fact (of the so-called real world) in the way of an one-to-one mapping (or etc., see above). A
historical example of a representation theory of truth is the Thomistic adequation theory of truth (adaeqatio
intellectus et rei). The ‘correspondence theory of truth’ of A.Tarski - which had been very unfortunately named
this way - has been sometimes unjustifiably misinterpreted as a kind of representation theory of truth.
29 And is as well conceived there under the premises of an entirely different conceptual scheme, namely a
watered-down epistemological one.
30 I would have preferred to call that kind of ‘objectivism’ - which will be clearly presented in the following ‘veritative objectivism’ but for not to overdo the introduction of neologisms I then decided to better drop that
intention. Most important in the characteristic of the objectivism we will present is that it essentially has to do
with truth, but that it is not at all in the common sense ‘verificationist’. I.e. it is not about any justification or
verification of sentences or the methodological reflection of how possibly to do so and it is also not about criteria,
standards and measures relevant for such purposes. I.e. it is not about any potential practice of verifying but about
something completely different and perhaps strange, namely about a certain self-contained process of the increase
of truth. ‘Verification’ on the contrary suggests a method or practice of gaining truth or making something true
and this is not implied in veracious objectivism.
Yet verificationism might be a effective if not the only way to accurately point out a reasonable notion of ‘truth’
for the ordinary language, but actually to do that would - in my view - be indeed a much harder task than for
example just defeating anti-realism. One reason for the intricate difficulties of such a task would be the lack of
the relatively invariant anchor of theories in ordinary language and the excess of arbitrary context-dependent
belief systems instead.
12
adjustment as we - admittedly a bit long-windedly - like to name our position. Obviously such difference in the respective reasons should not come as a surprise since pragmatism after all is a species of
anti-realism which is something veracious objectivism with ontological adjustment of course
shouldn’t be.
5.5.3 Thus the distinctive difference between pragmatism and veracious objectivism with ontological
adjustment now comes up exactly in respect to the same matter at which the seeming accordance of
them both could have been found before, i.e. in respect to their concepts of truth. And this again
should really not come as a surprise since - up from the beginning of this paper - we bluntly announced it as anti-anti-realism with intuitionist negation. 31
5.5.4 The concept of truth as proposed in veracious objectivism with ontological adjustment is - in
sharp contrast to that of pragmatism - not at all dependent on any practice or utility and no pragmatic
aspect of operating or propagating theories matters at all for the validity of truth as related to
veracious objectivism with ontological adjustment.
5.5.5 Pragmatism of course is merely a special case of anti-realism in general. Therefore more
generally speaking we say that the concept of truth as proposed in veracious objectivism with
ontological adjustment is - in sharp contrast to that of anti-realism - not at all dependent on any extratheoretical context be it pragmatic, social, cultural, psychological or epistemic in whatever disguise.
5.5.6 The concept of truth as proposed in veracious objectivism with ontological adjustment instead is
found as well as founded in particular intertheoretical relations between certain successive theories.
5.6 We will call that kind of intertheoretical relations the intertheoretical truth-relation. 32
5.6.1 In the following we will show that the intertheoretical truth-relation is designed as to be an
application of the correspondence theory of truth which had been originally proposed by Alfred
Tarski.33
5.6.1.1 The ‘correspondence theory of truth’ had been sometimes misinterpreted by philosophers as a
somehow formalized version of the Thomistic adequation theory of truth (adaeqatio intellectus et rei),
but it never was meant to be that, it never was that and it even never could have been that. 34
5.6.1.2 The correspondence theory of truth was introduced by Tarski for purely (meta)mathematical
reasons namely to explicate the semantic concept of truth 35 which is inherent in model theory of
which Tarski was the primary founder.
5.6.1.3 The criterion of truth in Tarski’s semantic theory of truth goes as follows
"p" is true iff p
(1)
(1) simply says that a statement "p" of an object-language OL is true in a meta-language ML, in which
also the predicate "true" is used, if and only if it is satisfiable in ML. Thus (1) first of all is a statement
of ML. ‘Satisfiable in ML’ means that there must be a possible consistent and meaningful interpretation of "p" in ML. Such consistent and meaningful interpretations here are usually called ‘models’.
Then (1) actually says that "p" is true in ML if and only if there is a model p of "p" in ML. Which
could also - a bit shorter - be expressed by (1*)
"p" is true in ML iff there is a model p of "p" in ML
(1*)
31
For a more detailed explanation of what is meant by anti-anti-realism with intuitionist negation see the footnote
of 5.16.
32 For more details about the intertheoretical truth-relation cf. D.Kurth, Der Weg der Wahrheit, in: P.Eisenhardt,
F.Linhard, K.Petanides (eds.), Der Weg der Wahrheit, Hildesheim 1999
33 Cf. A.Tarski, Der Wahrheitsbegriff in den formalisierten Sprachen, Studia Philosophica 1, Leopoli 1935 (repr.
in: Alfred Tarski Collected Papers vol. 2, Basel Boston Stuttgart 1986, pp 51-198). A further explanation of
Tarski’s concept of truth where he also deals with the philosophical interpretation of his theory can be found in:
A.Tarski, The Semantic Conception of Truth and the Foundations of Semantics, Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research, vol. 4, 1944 (repr. in: Alfred Tarski Collected Papers vol. 2, Basel Boston Stuttgart
1986, pp 661-699).
34 Tarski’s correspondence theory of truth is on no account about a correspondence between a sentence or
proposition on the one hand and an (extra-linguistic) fact on the other. On the utmost contrary it states a
correspondence between two sentences or propositions of which one is a sentence of a (formalized) objectlanguage quoted in quotation-marks in Tarski’s famous truth-matrix (see 5.6.1.3 of this paper) and the other is a
respective version of that truth-matrix (or criterion of truth) itself which of course is a sentence of a respective
(formalized) meta-language. Furthermore Tarski’s correspondence theory of truth doesn’t apply to ordinary
languages anyway because an ordinary language is not a formalized semantically closed language; but - by the
way - theories are.
35 In contrast to syntactic concepts of truth (as provability or derivability) which are characteristic for e.g. proof
theory and most mathematical practice.
13
and of course (1*) has to be a proper sentence of ML, therefore than the expressions ‘in ML’ and
‘there is a model .. of "p" in ML’ turn out to be fully redundant and (1*) turns out to be a redundant
version of (1).
5.7 Applying the semantic concept of truth in the field of intertheoretical relations for the purpose of
establishing an intertheoretical truth-relation is definitely a bit more complicated as applying it in
(meta)mathematical model theory.
5.7.1 The main objection against trying to do so would probably run under the title of incommensurability.
5.7.1.1 But that objection stands and falls with the (rather unreasonable) measure of commensurability
it usually presupposes.
5.7.1.2 At least there are enough historical cases available which by a minute reconstruction could be
shown to be proper examples for the applicability of that proposed intertheoretical truth-relation. Such
amongst others are in particular the Newtonian revolution for which it can be shown that for Newton’s
theory of gravitation models - which indeed had to be slightly altered compared with the respective
proper Newtonian models - could be constructed effectively matching Galilei’s theory of gravity, Kepler’s theory of planetary motion and Huygens’ theory of the motion of the pendulum. And the same
applies to Einstein’s theory of general relativity with respect to Newtonian gravitation, Einstein’s own
special relativity and by that of course also Maxwell’s electrodynamics.36
5.7.2 Of course the crux of that matter has to do with the mentioned ‘slight alteration’. But then this is
altogether a technical question concerning actual reconstructions of such stages of scientific progress,
and there are no a priori arguments against the possibility of an appropriate minute reconstruction of
respective cases. I.e. reconstruction as such by no means implies incommensurability.
5.7.2.1 And for now that must do as a preparation for introducing the intertheoretical truth-relation.
5.8 As an application of the semantic concept of truth the intertheoretical truth-relation goes as
follows
T2: "pT1 " is true iff Μ *pT1
(2)
(2) says that a statement "pT1 " of a preceding theory T1 is true in a succeeding theory T2 if and only if
there is a peculiar model Μ*pT1 of "pT1 " in T2.
5.8.1 What we have done here obviously is to take a succeeding theory T2 as a kind of meta-language
related to a preceding theory T1 as the respective object-language.
5.8.2 The peculiarity of Μ*pT1 (expressed by the asterisk) is altogether due to the crux concerning the
mentioned ‘slight alteration’. Obviously in many cases in which the intertheoretical truth-relation
might be applicable and then especially in the more interesting ones there will be no proper model of a
statement of a preceding theory T 1 found as well to be a proper model of a respectively succeeding
theory T2. Instead in T2 there must at first be a new model constructed only for the purpose to satisfy
for "pT1 ". Such a new model then would probably differ significantly from the proper models of T2. It
would probably be characterized by restrictions compared with the respective proper models of T 2, i.e.
important features of T2 would become meaningless in the particular context of that peculiar model
Μ*pT1 and - somehow as a ‘substitute’ - different theoretical terms would probably ad hoc be introduced which would be seen as meaningless in T2. Altogether Μ*pT1 of course would be quite trans36
But then immediately a note of caution must be made. There are of course also - more or less - directly
succeeding theories to which such an intertheoretical truth-relation is not or only in a drastically altered way
applicable. The later are for examples cases in which the succeeding theory would not be inherently improved,
i.e. for example a case where there would be no amplification of the original scope (or extension of the preceding
theory) be found in the succeeding, i.e. relatively new theory.
A good example for that is the intertheoretical relation of the Ptolemaic and the Copernican system despite the
fact that this so-called revolution is usually rated as one of the outstanding popular examples of scientific
progress. Yet in fact it was mainly a transformation of coordinates. Both theories are purely phoronomic theories,
i.e. they contain and imply no relation whatsoever to any dynamical concept or aspect. By calling these theories
‘phoronomic’ it is also meant that they are not even just kinematic theories, since being a kinematic theory
implies by the historical introduction of kinematics well enough a relation to dynamics, namely a relation of
methodically skipping the nevertheless strictly presupposed and recognized dynamical causes of the considered
motion. But such causes haven’t been at all considered in either the Ptolemaic or the Copernican theory.
And as just a phoronomic theory the Ptolemaic was the better one, i.e. it significantly better matched the
ob servations. The main reason for that has to do with a technical aspect, namely the punctum aequans which
comes surprisingly near to the empty focus of Kepler’s ellipses. Therefore the planetary motion if represented as
seen from that punctum aequans as well would surprisingly resemble that which is known from Kepler’s theory.
And - by the way - the Ptolemaic theory could do with fewer epicycles than the Copernican.
The true revolution initiated by the Copernican theory was of course in regard of its consequences for respective
doctrines of the church and by that for the entire weltbild of that time in history.
14
mogrified compared with the proper models of T2, i.e. it would only be a very partial model of T2 and
even as such it would look rather bizarre.
5.8.3 But such features or theoretical terms becoming or being meaningless would as long be of no
relevance for a possible reconstruction of "pT1 " under the auspices of T2 as long as such a reconstructed model Μ *pT1 would not be inconsistent with T2. 37 And in the eyes of some looking bizarre
might even be fashionable.
5.8.4 Now we hope to somewhat have elucidated the rôle that uncommon ‘veracious’ has been designated for to play in veracious objectivism with ontological adjustment, but what’s about the other
elements of that long-winded expression?
5.9 Objectivism and ontological adjustment will eventually go together.
5.9.1 Objectivism could easily be explained as a position standing for the argument that there are possible statements or sentences the asserted truth of which is valid utterly independent on any direct or
indirect subjective motives, contexts or pre-understandings. The subjectivity in question must not be
confined to an individual but could also be incarnated in social or cultural contexts, influences or
traditions. But there is essentially more about objectivism than such an ordinary definition could bring
out.
5.9.1.1 Objectivity as pointed out in 5.9.1 could obviously be only found in theories. And that is so
not primarily for the incorruptibility by which theories come to their judgements since theories do not
come to any judgements anyway. 38
5.9.2 But it is so for the fact that theories objectivate.
5.9.2 1 Now, ‘objectivation’ is admittedly a neologism but then it is also nothing really new, at least
not in this paper. ‘Objectivation’ is just the term we use to describe the fact that a theory implicates
the totality of its objects (including all relations between them)39, i.e. its ontology (cf. 5.2.1), which
again is the ontology of the stated facts of the theory.
5.9.3 So we should better say: that theories objectivate factually. Factuality now is - so to speak - the
meta-ontological counterpart of actuality, namely the way the intelligible objects of theories intelligibly meta-exist. 40
5.93.1 And to say that a theory implicates the ontology of its stated facts is again rather a further explanation of the statement that any theory has its ontology just as an adjunct (cf. 4.1.1.3 and 4.3.1).
But when we dwelled the question of an ontology merely being adjunctive to a respective theory then
these ontologies had been quite relative. And that was a bit ‘bad’.41 Therefore time has come to put
that overdone relativity of the ontologies in order, i.e. to adjust the ontologies.
5.10 Ontological adjustment means that the ontologies of respectively appropriate theories become
adjusted in the course of the history of science by means of the intertheoretical truth-relation.
5.10.1 Truth as increasingly revealed or discovered by subsequently succeeding theories is then an
entailment of these theories which are linked by the intertheoretical truth-relation in the history of
science.
5.10.1.1 Already the truth of the first theory - which satisfies the required standard of formalization,
namely the ‘theory of planetary motion’42 by Hipparchos of Nicaea43 - as revealed or brought into
37
Could it possibly be the case that some anti-realists should get a creeping feeling as if some of the stuff they
usually like to throw at others comes flying back?
38 This was a bit unfair, but actually theories also do not come to conclusions, but only scientist do so by using
theories. Theories as such contain no conclusions but - at best - just implications. This - by the way - marks an
important difference of the works of scientists and detectives.
39 Of course this includes as well all relations of higher order like functions, functionals etc. and by that in the
end the network of the entire formal structure of which the primitive objects merely mark some crossings of the
ties.
40 For pointing out the distinctive difference of the status of theoretical objects on the one hand and actual
existing entities on the other we have to use some telling predicates. But by using ‘intelligible’ in contrast to
‘actual’ (see also 3.8.3 of this paper) or ‘meta-exist’ in contrast to ‘exist’ we do not want to imply, indicate,
insinuate in any way that we tend to a dualist or Platonist position either in ‘ontology’ (as it is traditionally
understood) or in the theory of universals. On the contrary: we oppose dualism and Platonism vigorously in any
of its appearances. But all these subjects are not the topic of that paper so we only can assure you if there would
be more time we could bring forward the required arguments to show why we do so justifiably. Just to give a
hint: such arguments would probably have to do with an appropriate kind of neutral monism and - by the way with the fact that ‘meta-existence’ obviously does not imply ‘pre-existence’.
41 I.e. it is ‘bad’ in our view, not only because it is so fine in the anti-realists view but also for that reason.
42 To be a bit stubborn: ‘Theory of planetary motion’ is of course just a name because there is no, there never was
and there never will be a theory of planetary motion, if one understands by ‘planetary motion’ an actual
happening going on in the actual existing world. This of course doesn’t relate specifically to a theory of planetary
motion but equally to all theories. Yet it might become more evident in a case like Hipparchos’ theory since today
hardly anyone anymore would believe that planets run on epicycles which themselves run on a deferent.
15
appearance or discovered44 by its actual successor theory (which could in fact be as far remote as the
theory of Tycho Brahe45) is an entailment of all succeeding theories eventually up to the ultimate
theory.
5.10.2 But it is of course not the proper ontology of the theory of Hipparchos or the quite equivalent
one of the Ptolemaic system which will eventually become a proper part of the proper ontology of the
ultimate theory. It didn’t even become a proper part of the proper (and of course mutually distinct)
ontologies of Tycho Brahe’s, Kepler’s or Newton’s respective theories.
5.10. 2.1 The proper ontologies of the different theories in the history of science still remain to be
relative.46 But they are linked by the reconstructed, i.e. ‘slightly altered’ models47 as outlined related
to the intertheoretical truth-relation.
5.10.2.2 And it is by the chain of subsequent intertheoretical truth-relations how the true substance 48
of these relative adjunctive ontologies becomes refined. Refinement then means that only these elements, parts or aspects of the adjunctive ontologies of preceding theories maintain significance (i.e.
are regarded as being true in the context of an appropriate reconstruction) in the course of the history
of science which can be linked by the intertheoretical truth-relation with appropriately altered models
of a succeeding theory (at which these models could also be accounted for as potentially meaningful).
5.11 Thus ontological adjustment is exactly this process of refinement, i.e. the subsequent pointing out
of appropriately altered models of theories in subsequent applications of the intertheoretical truthrelation.
5.11.1 Since the adjunctive ontology of a theory is nothing but the entirety of the models of that
theory we are entitled to speak of ontological adjustment despite the fact that the proper ontologies of
the original theories still remain relative.49
5.11.2 Now, what’s still left to do? Oh yeah, there was that ‘severely chiliastic vision’. Now, I
suppose that no one at least a bit reasonable could mistake veracious objectivism with ontological
adjustment or that process of refinement of the ontological substance (sometimes simply called: truth)
by the means of iterated applications of the intertheoretical truth-relation for a severely chiliastic
vision.
5.11.2.1 But then there was also that reference to an ultimate theory, supposed to be anticipated and
foreshadowed in the course of the history of science.
5.12 That science has an inherent tendency towards unification and thereby an increase of the internal
complexity of the succeeding rather more unified theories compared with their respective less unified
predecessors should be evident to anyone who ever looked a bit deeper at the history of science, not at
least at the rather later stages of it.
5.12.1 Therefore the presumption of an ultimate theory to come is nothing more than a simple
extrapolation of that inherent tendency severely enforced by the implications of veracious objectivism
with ontological adjustment, in particular of course by the intertheoretical truth-relation.
5.12.2 An ultimate theory should not be thought of as being something mysterious. An ultimate theory
will not refer more to the extra-theoretical actually existing world than any other theory ever did, i.e. it
will not refer to that at all. And by that an ultimate theory consequently has ever to be regarded to be
just a provisional ultimate theory.
5.12.2.1 No actual theory ever could be rated as the ultimate theory beyond any possible doubt, i.e.
any apparently ultimate theory could turn out only to be - so to speak a little bit seemingly paradoxical
- a provisional ultimate theory. But this of course would not devaluate the significance of the concept
43
We don’t say or want to imply that Hipparchos’ theory was actually the first theory in the history of mankind’s
endeavours of theorizing, but it is - to our knowledge - the first one of which we have enough hard information
for the purpose of reconstructabilty and a respective degree of formalization on the one hand and for which a
clear link to succeeding theories can be shown on the other. Yet any other possibly more ancient theory be it of
Babylonian, Egyptian, Indian, Greek or whatever origin which would meet a comparable standard could of course
turn out to be the ‘true’ first theory. The link to succeeding theories wouldn’t even have to be to the same type of
theories, namely an astronomical or phoronomic one, as it is the case for Hipparchos’ theory.
44 I am not at all interested in the meaningless discussion if theories ‘discover’ or ‘invent’ their assertions. Such a
discussion would only make any sense at all under the assumption that a representation theory of truth applies.
But there is a meaningful interpretation of ‘discovery’ which doesn’t imply such epistemologically contaminated
connotations. It goes in the direction of the meanings of for example ‘making something apparent’, ‘bringing
something into appearance’ or ‘reveal something’.
45 Since the Ptolemaic system was merely a strictly conservative extended application of Hipparchos’ theory and
the Copernican system was mainly a transformation of the coordinates of the Ptolemaic system But there are also
arguments for the usually hold opinion that the Copernican theory would be an appropriate candidate.
46 But from now on that relativity shouldn’t be anymore so much overstated as it has been frequently done.
47 Yet sometimes a rather hefty slightness (sorry) might have to be applied.
48 Which stands for a dynamically increasing core or generative invariant of reconstructible claims of truth in the
history of theories.
49 It sometimes helps to think about intuitionist logic, i.e. intuitionist negation in particular.
16
of an ultimate theory since that turn from the status of an ultimate theory actually recognized as such
to a status of a merely former ultimate theory could only take place by the actual establishment of a
then newly accepted ultimate theory thoroughly encompassing its predecessor (as always in the history of science).
5.12.3 Therefore it must be said, that the concept of an ultimate theory is sort of a very modest one.
I.e. it only implies that the ontology of the ultimate theory provides the utmost true factual
objectivation corroborated by a maximum of evidence and validated by the greatest possible
coherence, i.e. the maximally attainable truth. But that’s already the main point of it.50
5.13 And now the time eventually has come to make good for our prophecy in 4.4.3, since that last
section of that paper meanwhile became a bit lengthy.
5.13.1 In the beginning of this paper we proposed that realism and anti-realism would show some
equivalence under a certain aspect and that anti-anti-realism with intuitionist negation would not do
so. And we were hopeful that in the course of the paper that aspect would come to light. And so it did.
5.14 That certain aspect is the underlying theory or standard of truth, namely a common fixation of
anti-realism as well as realism to a representation theory of truth.51
5.14.1 Thus that’s the gist of the matter both realists as well as anti-realists deeply believe in the representation theory of truth as the natural and only possible standard of truth. One difference however
lies in the fact that poor realists honestly believe in that bogus, but some tricky anti-realists don’t even
believe in their beliefs. 5253 Various realists believe in representation theory of truth in the sense that
they in different degrees of intensity believe that its promises are more or less redeemable. Various
antirealists instead believe 54 in representation theory of truth in the sense that they in different degrees
of intensity do not believe that its promises are redeemable. And based on this then they say that for
that reason there would be no relevant notion of truth in science (or at least that in principle truth
would not be attainable in science).
5.15 All the trick of that argument is concealed in that ‘for that reason’. That’s the place where they
hide the tell tale trace which leads to the evidence that they inconsistently adhere to the representation
theory of truth and refuse it at once.
5.16 Anti-anti-realists with intuitionist negation55 instead hold that the representation theory of truth is
at best an obstinate illusion or worse an utterly meaningless and severely misleading fixed idea.
5.17. Truth instead emerges together with the emergence of proper scientific theories and increases in
the course of the history of science.
--------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------ADDENDUM: Now the end of this paper comes really somewhat nearer and therefore the day of judgement not just for the sceptics but even for all the remaining anti-realists has come.56 That might turn
out to be a bit boring or redundant since all the basic arguments have been already presented but as a
matter of fact we planned our campaign methodically and we will also bring it to an end this way.57
50
Fortunately there can be found various other types of modesty too.
More than 10 years ago Peter Eisenhardt several times energetically used to stress that theories would not be
something like window glasses or spectacles. At that time I wondered what he wanted to say in particular because
I knew that he was not in favour of externalism (in the philosophy of science) or instrumentalism. Now I tend to
think that it then was his way to show his reservation relating to a representation theory of meaning (with respect
of theories).
52 Yet in the case of some anti-realists not to believe in their own beliefs then could be rated as a first indication
of becoming reasonable, so maybe they believe in their beliefs indeed.
53 Just another try to bring the message out: most realists view theories as if they would be something like
(slightly abstracted and remarkably clear-sighted) persons, some anti-realists (for example radical constructivists)
tend to view persons as if they would be something like (slightly animated and severely handicapped) theories;
both views are mistaken.
54 I.e. accept it as a relevant measure which can be matched or not be matched or - in an extreme version - even
never actually be matched, but even for that extreme version then still serve as the tacit measure.
55 OK, now then the definition: anti-anti-realism with intuitionist negation states similar to anti-realism that the
common prevailing standard of truth as set by realism is unwarranted. Yet anti-anti-realism says so for an entirely
different reason than anti-realism. Anti-anti-realism holds that standard as being meaningless, anti-realism holds
that standard as being irredeemable. Then anti-anti-realism with intuitionist negation as presented in this paper
provides an alternative standard of truth whereas anti-realism laments or rejoices at the seeming fact that there
would no (claim of) truth be redeemable in scientific theories. I.e. anti-anti-realism with intuitionist negation
negates anti-realism obviously without becoming realism again. This also will provide us the means to then
finally dismiss any of such expectable arguments claiming that veracious objectivism with ontological adjustment
enforced by the intertheoretical truth-relation would in the end just be a special sort of anti-realism.
56 The end announced in 4.4.3 already came in 5.15.
57 And to be honest now we want to have some enjoyment to our taste.
Our very unconventional strategy - announced in the beginning of this paper - of course was to at first build up
the most conclusive and - as in particular the many readers which are partial to realism will agree - even quite
51
17
But let’s proceed step by step and start with the steadfast sceptics. For the sceptics namely the day of
judgement is rather - literally - the moment of truth.
Let’s at first recapitulate the sceptics’ argument or rather his two arguments linked by a peculiar and
unwarranted implication. The sceptics (in various versions and with various qualifications) essentially
say
(1) that there is no reliable58 objective knowledge of the outside world59 attainable and
(!) for that reason
(2) that there is no ‘truth’ ascribable to theories.60
Now, we are not in any discussion of (1) since we hold (1) for being a meaningless play of words61,
and - what’s most important - we , i.e. the proponents of veracious objectivism with ontological adjustment enforced by the intertheoretical truth-relation62 are in no way obliged to be in a discussion of
(1) to defeat the claims of the sceptics as stated in (2). The reason for this of course is that we
explicitly presented a concept of truth that in no way relies on epistemolgical presuppositions as stated
in (1) and which will be valid independently of the fact which of the following cases applies to the
assertion (1) of the sceptics namely if it would turn out either to be justified or to be unjustified or what it is in fact - to be utterly meaningless.
But now let’s change sides and have a look how the sceptics or any anti-realist might try to defend
their conviction.
How then could a sceptic or any anti-realist try to defy veracious objectivism as outlined before in that
paper? In the first instance such defiance doesn’t seem to be a task too hard. The sceptic simply could
assert that veracious objectivism as outlined in that paper is unwarranted, i.e. false. Which would be
the same as saying that veracious objectivism doesn’t give the right picture of the history of science,
in particular that the proposal of an intertheoretical truth (or correspondence) relation is unwarranted.
But as being a proper sceptic a sceptic is not entitled to do so, because scepticism is an essentially
epistemological position defined by - rather ridiculous yet nevertheless purely - epistemological
convictions. 63
Therefore by raising such objections (as mentioned before) against veracious objectivism the sceptic
already has ceased to be a sceptic. Because even if he would be right, such objections would be no
epistemological objections at all but purely factual objections decided upon by arguments concerning
the philosophy and history of science. The sceptic anyway would then have transformed into a sort of
relativist or contextualist or social constructivist, and would as such also be obliged to bring some
respectively relevant arguments forward.
A sceptic of course could be more intelligent than doing so (especially considering the appalling consequences). He could either say he wouldn’t care at all about veracious objectivism or that even if
veracious objectivism would provide an appropriate picture of the history of science (with some inherent function of progress) he still would not care because an appropriate picture of the history of sciradical anti-realist position. In the course of that build-up we then sorted out the not so conclusive varieties and
after having admitted the genuine conclusiveness we showed that it eventually cannot stand firm against the
exposure of that not so little (and even not so secret) dirty secret of anti-realism namely sharing the same attitude
towards truth with realism. This secret being nothing than the enshrined idol of epistemology.
58 The difference between the various kinds of sceptics reaching from radical to moderate ones is mainly about
the degree of reliability.
59 I.e. of course the world outside of the consciousness of a respective subject.
60 That ascribability might be qualified as ‘legitimately’, ‘justifiably’ etc., but that makes no difference.
61 And we did thoroughly justify that standpoint by the argumentation in that paper concerning the misconception
of possibly having objective, i.e. theory-based knowledge of the actually existing world. The real problem is of
course with the notion of ‘knowledge’. Realists as well as anti-realists use this term as if it could be taken as an
unspecified comprehension of practical, so-called empirical and theoretical knowledge. But practical skill - even
very generalized and methodically organized versions of this - belonging to the realm of actual existence on the
one hand and theoretical knowledge on the other are entirely different things whereas so-called empirical
knowledge is a misconceived mongrel brought up by erroneous epistemologies. (Don’t worry about that ‘realm’
we still maintain our rigorous anti-Platonist stance.)
62 From now on we refer to ‘veracious objectivism with ontological adjustment enforced by the intertheoretical
truth-relation’ a bit shorter as just ‘veracious objectivism’.
63 But note: that sword doesn’t cut at all at both sides. We, i.e. the veracious objectivists (as alluded to in this
paper), didn’t ever use any epistemological arguments. Just to the contrary veracious objectivism implies that
epistemological arguments are of no avail whatsoever concerning the question how the scope of scientific
theories in the course of the history of science widens or how the set of true propositions (or models) of the
theories increases in the course of the history of science.
18
ence by no means would yield or guarantee an appropriate picture of the real world. Especially that
later argument seems to make a hit. But then it also indicates a fatal inconsistency (which applies as
well to the simple denial to care at all about veracious objectivism) in the sceptics seeming argument.
By denying veracious objectivism any relevance for the question concerning the true picture of the
real world the sceptic sets a standard for what such a picture would have to be. And it is no wonder
that the standard he must set is simply the standard of realism.64 To defend that standard of truth he
then inevitably would have to recur to a sort of representation theory of truth like for example the
Thomistic adequation theory of truth (adaeqatio intellectus et rei) and that of course is what he cannot
do as a sceptic. The only thing what is left to the sceptic then is to say that a representation theory of
truth is utterly irredeemable (by his defining presupposition for being a sceptic) on the one hand but
that it is also his strictly presupposed standard of truth on the other. And thereby the inherent
inconsistency which is as well the principal trick of scepticism became apparent. 65
Thus nothing helps him out against veracious objectivism because this position is in no way whatsoever related to a representation theory of truth, and so we are not obliged either to join his
lamentations or - as realists would be - to try to convince him of the opposite concerning his view of
the redeemability of the representation theory of truth. Yet the sceptic would still be obliged to argue
against the assertions of veracious objectivism in case he would intend to stay in the discussion at all.
And by doing so he would cease to be a sceptic and this time even finally. By refusing to do so he
would be out of the discussion exclusively by his own fault.
But what’s about the other remaining anti-realists - the relativists, contextualists and social
constructivists - for they at least seem not to argue based as exclusively and specifically as sceptics
must do on epistemological convictions. I.e. they seem to skip the argument (1) of the sceptic and just
to hold on to the second argument (2). This is also the position the sceptic’s one would have turned to
by him seriously trying to stay in the discussion with veracious objectivism after having been
defeated, i.e. proven to be inconsistent relating to his first argument (1).
But one has to note that meanwhile something important has changed concerning the possible effectiveness of the usual tactics of such remaining anti-realists. The exit to the usual escape route of these
relativists, contextualists and social constructivists et al. has been finally locked up. I.e. if challenged
on the field of the history or philosophy of science most of them sooner or later often try to retreat to a
rather unspecified scepticism, which at least is a revelation of the fact that that actually is their tacit
presupposition providing the base of their argument. Yet this escape route now is no more available
for them. Therefore it all boils down to an argument about the proper history and philosophy of
science.66 There are of course no a priori arguments concerning that matter. But there is the challenge
of an internalist reconstructional ansatz based on the intertheoretical truth relation (or an implicated
entailment theory of scientific truth) to the externalist (mis)conception of the history of scientific
theories as the narrations of its various (social, cultural, biographic etc.) contexts.
Then there is a comparably sober kind of anti-realism left namely instrumentalism which wouldn’t
deny that there is truth gainable by theories and that this truth could even increase in the history of
science. But instrumentalism would put a certain reservation forward relating to a presumed
distinction between different asserted qualifications and consequently varieties of truth itself. This
asserted difference would be seen by instrumentalists as being between the attainable truth provided
by the fitness or capability of steadily improved theories on the one hand and the unattainable ideal of
an authentic truth thought of as representing the entire real facts. And already claiming such a
distinction between those two kinds of truth is just the same as claiming that a representation theory of
truth could be justified and valid. But we have tried to show for the philosophy and history of science
that such validity or even any possible applicability of a representation theory of truth with respect to
either theories as such or the history of science should better be precluded. There is no meaningful
difference justifiably conceivable between a maximal and a maximal attainable truth, and asserting
such a difference reveals again just a fatal inclination to the representation theory of truth and by that
the inherent inconsistency of anti-realism becomes apparent once more.
64
This might seduce us to the innuendo that a sceptic - or for that any anti-realist - is in fact just an offended
realist.
65 Cf. sentence 5.15 of that paper.
66 And this evidently holds as well for the cases in which the respective anti-realists are not (explicitly or tacitly)
affiliated to a proper epistemological position.
19