From Sean F. Johnston History of Science: A Beginner’s Guide, Chapter 7 (2009)
7
science, history and culture:
evolving perspectives
This chapter could be entitled ‘the present and future of history
of science’. As the previous chapter suggests, history of science
has increasingly been re-examined ‘from the inside’. But not
only have historians revisited the subject: so too have
philosophers, sociologists and the wider public. Together, these
visions of the subject have reworked its goals, its methods and
its audiences. The aim in this chapter, then, is to explore behind
the scenes to illustrate how scholars have drawn meaning from
the history of science.
philosophers and failure: disputing how
science works
From the early nineteenth century, the history of science
became closely associated with philosophy, although, as
historian Simon Schaffer (b. 1955) and others have argued, the
writing of scientific history also developed from biographies of
exemplary practitioners. Both connections were only to be
expected. Mediaeval categories had defined scientific
knowledge as part of natural philosophy, an understanding
traceable to Aristotle; and big names like Aristotle provided
authoritative answers. The narrower term physics – dropping
the philosophical association – was substituted increasingly
during the late nineteenth century, but there were some hold-
182
From Sean F. Johnston History of Science: A Beginner’s Guide, Chapter 7 (2009)
outs. Scottish universities largely retained the term natural
philosophy, with Glasgow University’s department being
reorganized to become the Department of Physics and
Astronomy as recently as 1986.
Elaborated by William Whewell, the history of science served
as raw material to construct philosophical understandings of the
universal nature of knowledge. He categorized branches of
scientific knowledge, traced their histories, and coined new
words (such as physicist, anode and uniformitarianism) to
describe them. Whewell’s History of the Inductive Sciences
(1837) was followed quickly by The Philosophy of the Inductive
Sciences, Founded Upon Their History (1840). The twinned
books argued that the successful advance of scientific
knowledge relied on induction, the generalization of concepts
and laws from particular examples.
Whewell’s French contemporary (and rival) Auguste Comte,
introduced in chapter four, also categorized the sciences via a
historical survey. Unlike Whewell, Comte suggested that the
advance of knowledge could be accelerated by a rigorous
methodology that relied only on observable facts. ‘Positive’
knowledge extended only to what could be experienced directly
(empirical evidence). And, as singer Bing Crosby put it, in
addition to accentuating the positive, it was equally important to
eliminate the negative: theorization about hidden or abstract
entities, Comte claimed, was pointless.
Ironically, while the history and philosophy of science became
closely allied, practicing scientists drew away from both fields
around the turn of the twentieth century. Now increasingly
professionalized and goal-oriented, scientists delved into the
philosophical justifications of their work less often. Perhaps the
last influential scientist-philosophers were Ernst Mach (18381916) and Pierre Duhem (1861-1916). A confirmed positivist,
Mach argued that scientific laws are merely short-hand for
collections of experimental findings. His book The Economical
Nature of Physical Inquiry (1882) suggested that ‘the law
183
From Sean F. Johnston History of Science: A Beginner’s Guide, Chapter 7 (2009)
always contains less than the fact itself’, and promoted the
trimming of scientific claims to only what was strongly
supported by evidence. This rather fundamentalist approach led
him to reject the atomic hypothesis at the turn of the century on
the grounds that direct observations were impossible, and the
indirect evidence was ‘uneconomical’.
French physicist and philosopher Pierre Duhem, on the other
hand, investigated the problem of constructing scientific
theories. His position, known as the Quine-Duhem thesis or the
problem of under-determination, is that for any set of data a
large number of theories can be convincingly applied. In any
experiment then, the results will not provide sufficient evidence
to force revision of a theory (this came up in Chapter 5 in the
discussion of the Michelson-Morley experiment). Duhem’s
unsettling conclusion raises questions that were reviewed by
historians and sociologists of science half a century later: how
can empirical evidence be related to theories at all, and (more
fundamentally) what confidence can we have in scientific
realism – the notion that it is possible to discover the true nature
of things?
Philosophers, too, were stimulated (and disturbed) by the
elaboration of new scientific theories such as relativity and
quantum mechanics. One outcome was the influential logical
positivist movement which sprang up in 1920s Vienna and came
to dominate American philosophy of science into the 1960s.
Inspired by Comte’s positivism, its members questioned the
proliferation of concepts that could be only indirectly inferred.
How, for example, do we know that ‘electrons’ and ‘energy
levels’ truly exist? They argued for a more logically-based
scientific method, and could turn to historical episodes to
illustrate how successful science had operated in the past.
While scientists themselves were turning away from
philosophy, then, history of science developed in close
association with it. Early twentieth century historians of science
emphasized the evolution of concepts and the accumulation of
184
From Sean F. Johnston History of Science: A Beginner’s Guide, Chapter 7 (2009)
factual knowledge – intellectual history and its philosophical
significance. The label ‘History and Philosophy of Science’
(HPS) identified a successful proto-discipline at prominent
institutions such as Cambridge. Part of the reason of the
success there can be attributed to its location within the Faculty
of Natural Science. Academic affiliations were also tight
elsewhere: the History of Science Division at the University of
Leeds, for example, was founded in the mid 1950s within its
Department of Philosophy.
More frequently, though, Philosophy departments pursued the
philosophy of science without explicit links to the history of
science. Notable contributors – each with well established
explanations and followers – included Karl Popper (1902-1994)
at the London School of Economics and Thomas Kuhn at the
University of California, Berkeley. Both rejected the positivist
philosophy that was becoming the orthodox explanation for how
science works, but for distinct reasons. Popper emphasized
insights about the scientific method. Importantly, he
demonstrated that scientific theories can never be wholly
proven: at best, they are conditionally confirmed by mounting
evidence. In essence, this is a critique of induction. He
proposed instead the notion of falsificationism to explain the
advance of knowledge. Facts, he argued, could never be
confirmed to be true in general, but they could be proven false.
For example, the claim ‘all swans are white’ cannot be proven
true unless we examine every swan that exists or has existed,
but it can be proven false merely by finding a single example of
a black swan. Swans aside, the same imbalance affects many
modern claims: we could prove that UFOs or ghosts exist by
capturing just one, but we can never disprove their existence;
we may be failing to find them because we are looking in the
wrong places or at the wrong times! Science advances, said
Popper, by testing falsifiable hypotheses. The remaining set of
hypotheses not yet proven false represents our working body of
knowledge. Some historians argue that there are few examples
of this method in practice.
185
From Sean F. Johnston History of Science: A Beginner’s Guide, Chapter 7 (2009)
On the other hand, Kuhn, as we have seen, claimed a different
use for historical evidence, demonstrating that it did not support
the notion that science accumulated knowledge inexorably;
periodically, he showed, there were ruptures of knowledge, and
new frameworks of understanding (or worldviews) were
constructed. The revolutions discussed in chapter three are
evidence of such periodic convulsions. Both Popper and Kuhn
emphasized the importance of theory-making, and so reduced
the stress on fact-collecting and empirical observation.
Imre Lakatos (1922-1974) and Paul Feyerabend (1924-1994),
both junior associates of Popper, provided their own distinct
approaches to the philosophy of science. Lakatos sought to
reconcile the views of Popper and Kuhn. Feyerabend’s Against
Method (1975) argued that science is not a unified body of
knowledge with any identifiable universal method; instead, it is
an incoherent patchwork of particular techniques and
procedures that isolate pockets of knowledge.
As this outline suggests, the history of the philosophy of science
has interesting parallels with history of science itself. A series
of contributors (including Whewell, Comte, Popper, Kuhn,
Feyerabend and their successors) have reformulated the bases of
the subject. As a result, the worldviews of philosophers of
science have been shaken periodically.
science in the post-modern world
As sketched in chapter six, the close alliance between the
history and philosophy of science has been broadened to other
disciplines during the late twentieth century. There has been a
flourishing of approaches to writing the history of science, and
to understanding science itself. These new viewpoints have
resulted from studies of science ‘from the outside’: from other
disciplines and even from other belief systems. This gradual
process, developing after the Second World War, can be
described as waves of reorientation for the history of science.
186
From Sean F. Johnston History of Science: A Beginner’s Guide, Chapter 7 (2009)
Two such changes of direction have been described as the
‘linguistic turn’ and the ‘social turn’.
The linguistic turn
The phrase ‘linguistic turn’ refers to a shift in the history of
science towards studies of language and discourse – i.e. research
into the ways that scientific findings have been described,
communicated and perceived. This refocusing of attention
towards language began in Humanities subjects (history,
literature, cultural and media studies) during the 1960s. These
ideas amalgamated developments by philosophers such as
Ludwig Wittgenstein (1889-1951) and literary theorists such as
Jacques Derrida (1930-2004). Wittgenstein had argued that
philosophical concepts are intimately tied up with language. A
separate development was the method of structuralism,
conceived first for the study of linguistics but spreading to other
fields during the 1950s. Structuralism seeks to find abstract
patterns or structures within social events, and to determine
their rules of combination. Anthropologists such as Claude
Lévi-Strauss (1908-2009), for example, sought to discover the
‘deep grammar’ of societies by studying their rituals, kinship
associations and mythology.
By contrast, the next generation of philosophers and critical
theorists, particularly in France, developed a critique of
structuralism that, logically enough, has been dubbed poststructuralism. Derrida, Michel Foucault (1926-1984) and others
argued that various radical philosophies that were critical of
Western philosophies illustrated the degree to which Western
culture itself had defined ways of thought. Post-structuralists
argued that the underlying ‘structures’ of society identified by
structuralists are not universally observable characteristics but
are, in fact, conditioned or created by culture. As a result, the
attempt to apply a scientific approach to social processes is
inherently biased. They seek, instead, to understand the world
by investigating multiple viewpoints or perspectives. Such a
187
From Sean F. Johnston History of Science: A Beginner’s Guide, Chapter 7 (2009)
position clearly challenged the interpretations of the history of
science that had been developed up to the 1960s. It also
challenged the traditionally privileged position held for
scientific knowledge itself.
While its origins are diffuse and definitions are spurned, at the
heart of the linguistic turn is the conviction that our
understanding of the world is strongly filtered and shaped by
language. Rhetoric, it is argued, can create a vision of the world
by defining terms and corresponding concepts. This highlyconstrained perspective can limit or distort our perceptions
about the natural world. Taking up this approach, historians of
science began to study scientific texts in relation to other kinds
of discourse, such as religious and political. They sought to
discover how scientists’ discourse affected the presentation of
their findings and how texts had been used to persuade
audiences of their explanations. This approach probed the
motivations for scientific accomplishments and related them
more clearly to the context of their times and to other varieties
of historical study. Science, previously explained mainly by the
logic of reasoning, was now more fully explained in terms of
ideologies and interests. One might ask, for example, how we
can characterize Isaac Newton, Robert Boyle or Louis Pasteur
by the books they read and wrote. The attention to scientific
rhetoric led naturally to wider interest in historical context that
created these texts. It also opened the door to the study of
different national settings for science. Studies of articles on
science in popular journals, for example, embedded the field
more firmly in the scholarship of Victorian culture, and revealed
differing perceptions of science in the countries of Europe and
America.
The social turn
As suggested by the linguistic turn, growing numbers of
historians of science began to focus on the rhetorical and human
factors underlying scientific knowledge. A closely-related shift
188
From Sean F. Johnston History of Science: A Beginner’s Guide, Chapter 7 (2009)
in attention from the 1970s was the so-called ‘social turn’.
Here, too, the roots of change can be found in the ideas of other
disciplines.
Social history, a branch of historical studies that had been
growing since the 1950s, called attention to ‘history from
below’. Its proponents argued that social norms and beliefs
could arise from, and be sustained by, the masses rather than
from figures of authority. Applied to the history of science,
social history focused on audiences and different portions of the
public – by class, education, occupation or national origin –
rather than on men and women of science. Histories of science
could now be devoted to the reception of scientific ideas instead
of merely to their creation. Indeed, social history has more
recently extended to cultural history of science. This approach
focuses on the relationship between science and culture, a
subject that makes sense only if the historian appreciates that
knowledge may have different cultural expressions or be subject
to cultural shaping. For instance, the national preference for the
concepts of Descartes in France was diminished after the French
translation and commentary of Newton’s Principia by woman
of science Émilie du Châtelet. The fruit of this approach is the
broader understanding of science as a social process: a
collective human activity fraught with human emotion,
motivations and mistakes as well as successes.
A second outcome of the social turn was a new attention to craft
skills and artisanal knowledge as drivers of science. As
suggested by philosopher Jerome Ravetz (1929-) during the
early 1970s, this approach counteracted the traditional interest
in intellectual history for the field. Rather than focusing on
concepts and their mutation, historians of science increasingly
investigated the importance of process skills. Historian Myles
Jackson (b. 1964), for example, has argued that the development
of spectroscopy by Joseph von Fraunhofer in early nineteenth
century Germany owed much to his artisanal expertise in
precision optics.
189
From Sean F. Johnston History of Science: A Beginner’s Guide, Chapter 7 (2009)
But just as post-structuralism had influenced ‘the linguistic
turn’, it provided a more radical slant for the ‘social turn’ than
did social history. The relationship between social activities
and scientific findings can be explored one step further: can
society not merely constrain or filter our scientific practices, but
also shape our scientific beliefs? An example of this possibility
is the investigation of N-rays discussed in chapter five. The Nray studies and claims of René Blondlot had been conditioned
by his working environment. The contemporary discoveries of
x-rays and radioactivity, along with state-of-the art practices of
measuring the brightness of light and detecting radio waves, had
made him and his scientific collaborators receptive to
interpretations that might have seemed improbable in other
social contexts. The data reported in papers by several
laboratories were later judged to be illusory and misguided. On
a much larger scale, it can be argued that the Aristotelian
understanding of the heavens – the Western orthodoxy for
nearly 2000 years – was supported by prevailing theological
ideas and trust of ancient authority.
An extension of such anecdotal cases suggests that, at least
sometimes and for certain periods, scientific facts can be social
constructs.
Social constructivism: the view that knowledge is a human
product that is socially and culturally shaped, rather than being
based primarily on discoverable physical reality.
This new approach had at least two clear consequences. First, it
brought scholarship in the history of science closer to other
fields such as literature, anthropology and sociology. This new
cluster of scholarly interests has been described by labels such
as science studies, science and technology studies (STS) or
science-technology-society (also abbreviated STS).
The second consequence of these turns has been that they
diminished the perceived separation between scientific
knowledge and other forms of human belief. Another
190
From Sean F. Johnston History of Science: A Beginner’s Guide, Chapter 7 (2009)
intellectual current for historians of science during the late
twentieth century came once again from philosophy and
sociology. So-called sociology of scientific knowledge (often
referred to by its abbreviation, SSK) was the product of
interdisciplinary studies from the 1970s. One of its principal
founders, David Bloor (b. 1942), argues that sociological factors
influence all aspects of science, from the selection of problems
to funding, from categorization of results to dissemination, and
from observation to theory construction. Members of the socalled Edinburgh School (the Science Studies Unit at the
University of Edinburgh from the late 1960s) distinguished two
versions of this viewpoint. The ‘Weak Program’, they argued,
applies discussion of social factors merely to erroneous beliefs.
Thus Blondlot’s N-rays would be attributed to the social
considerations that flavored his scientific work, while the
successes of his critics would be attributed solely to intellectual
factors and rational, objective judgment. As suggested by the
pejorative label ‘weak’, the members of the Edinburgh School
favored a different approach, which they dubbed the ‘Strong
Program’.
According to the Strong Program, historical, sociological and
philosophical investigations of scientific practice should strive
to be neutral with respect to our current beliefs about the truth
or falsity of claims. This approach, known as symmetry or
methodological relativism, gives equal attention to historical
episodes that today are seen as ‘successes’ and ‘failures’. The
history of science is thereby broadened to document and analyze
not just how we came to hold our present scientific beliefs, but
also the numerous blind alleys, failed initiatives and errors of
the past. This is not merely a matter of being ‘fair’ to the
collection of historical actors, but also to better understand the
strategies and philosophies of knowledge pursued by our
forebears. It also extends history of science into the present
and, indeed, the future: the scientific practices and strategies of
the past inform those of the present, and so historians,
anthropologists, philosophers and policy-makers have much to
teach each other.
191
From Sean F. Johnston History of Science: A Beginner’s Guide, Chapter 7 (2009)
A more radical position of the Strong Program, however, is its
commitment to social constructivism. The original expositions
set out to investigate the hypothesis that all scientific knowledge
is socially constructed to some extent, and possibly entirely so
constructed. This claim certainly opposed most scholarship in
history of science up to that time, but members of the Edinburgh
School and others employed historical case studies as the basis
of such research.
An early and highly influential example is the still controversial
historical hypothesis put forward in 1971 by American historian
of science Paul Forman (b. 1937). The ‘Forman thesis’ argues
that the content of early quantum mechanics was shaped by the
culture in which it developed, interwar Weimar Germany. The
unexpected defeat of Germany in the First World War, it is
claimed, caused a loss of confidence among the educated elite in
rationality, deterministic processes and even causality itself. In
this cultural environment, Weimar physicists opted to support
the uncertainty principle proposed by Werner Heisenberg rather
than alternate interpretations of quantum mechanics. As a result
of these cultural pressures actively shaping the subject in the
German context and its rapid international spread, the
Copenhagen interpretation became the new orthodoxy.
Forman’s claims were followed by a generation of historical
studies to further explore the social and cultural mechanisms
that could influence the content of science.
Other variants of the sociology of scientific knowledge, notably
attributed to French scholar Bruno Latour (b. 1947), argued
from the 1970s for more radical understandings of science,
technology, knowledge and technical products. His early work
Laboratory Life: the Social Construction of Scientific Facts
(1979, co-written with sociologist Stephen Woolgar (b. 1950))
unconventionally explored science by applying the methods of
anthropology to a biology laboratory. These perspectives are
beyond the scope of this book, but they, too, continue to
motivate current research by some historians of science.
192
From Sean F. Johnston History of Science: A Beginner’s Guide, Chapter 7 (2009)
Such theorizing about the scientific enterprise may appear arid
and divorced from the concerns of previous generations of
historians of science, who more frequently adopted a narrative
style (that is, constructing carefully-researched stories of
scientific episodes and historical figures). They may also fail to
tempt the casual reader with their intellectual vistas. However,
these radical positions, during the early 1990s, assumed a public
and even political dimension. Dubbed the ‘Science Wars’ by
the American media, the differences in viewpoint between
radical constructivists and practicing scientists were played out
in magazine articles, campus debates and television interviews.
In their crudest form, they illustrated a polar division between
so-called ‘relativists’ and ‘realists’. The relativists argue, with
varying degrees of compromise, that scientific belief is
influenced, shaped or determined by the society in which it is
practiced. The realists, calling upon older and still widely
accepted philosophical foundations, argued that human
knowledge based on rational scientific approaches is ultimately
unlimited in its accuracy and power to describe the natural
world. Both extremes accommodate nuanced approximations,
making the ‘wars’ more a spectrum of discord. While the
‘Science Wars’ cooled down, they are a potent illustration of the
relevance of history of science in contemporary culture.
anti-scientific movements and popular
belief
The section above limited itself to changing scholarly opinion
since the Second World War. But, as discussed in chapter five,
one of the most dramatic features of science over that period
was the rise and fall of public confidence in scientific authority.
So, alongside the scholarly turns, we can track changing
understandings of science in popular culture.
Popular criticisms of science have roots as old as the scientific
revolution and have been supported by a range of scholars.
193
From Sean F. Johnston History of Science: A Beginner’s Guide, Chapter 7 (2009)
During the second half of the eighteenth century, the grand
aspirations of the Enlightenment were criticized by scholars
such as Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712-1778). Rousseau
criticized the power and adequacy of rationalism to create the
better world, and argued that humans inevitably were corrupted
by society. He suggested that the advancement of knowledge
had concentrated power in the hands of governments to the
detriment of individual liberty.
Supported by such ideas, Romanticism became an important
cultural and intellectual force influencing literature, art and
music through the mid nineteenth century. The movement
represented, in part, a resistance to Enlightenment claims. It
stressed direct individual experience, imagination, emotion and
intuition over cold rationality. While no consensus can be
identified, Romanticism challenged the scope of reason and
emphasized subjective human qualities. By extension, this
challenged universal laws and scientific methodologies such as
reductionism and quantification as means of describing and
explaining the complexities of the natural world. Incidentally,
such perspectives inform some contemporary scientific
concerns, too: environmentalism and so-called ‘deep ecology’
owe much to the Romantic movement, in opposition to
technologically-oriented solutions that can be linked more
closely to the worldviews of the mechanical philosophers and
many of the other practitioners that have been the focus of this
book. In exchange for the expanding methods of science,
proponents of Romanticism offered holistic, multi-layered
description founded on particular experience.
Reductionism: the breaking down of a problem into more
easily explainable parts, or the simplification and generalization
of an explanation in terms of a more fundamental one (note:
there is a distinct definition that may be encountered: in biology,
where reductionism can refer to a materialist explanation of
life).
194
From Sean F. Johnston History of Science: A Beginner’s Guide, Chapter 7 (2009)
Holism: the consideration of multiple scales and interconnected
contributions making up an effect.
The most influential scientific expression of this was
naturphilosophie. Most widely supported in the Germanspeaking world by exponents such as Johann Wolfgang Goethe
(1749-1832), this philosophy emphasized the
interconnectedness of nature. Its approach promoted
alternatives to the ‘new science’ of the seventeenth and
eighteenth centuries, rejecting the procedure of dividing
problems into more easily manageable portions. Goethe, for
example, championed explanations of light and color that were
distinctly at odds with those of Newton a century earlier. A
drawback of his color theory was that, unlike Newton’s, it was
difficult to make predictions from it.
While the late nineteenth century witnessed a growing popular
acceptance of progress as discussed in chapter four, the pace of
scientific and technological change provoked varied critical
responses. Romanticism had offered an early alternative, but
quite distinct counter-forces emerged in the twentieth century.
Emerging in Switzerland during the First World War, Dadaism
was a cultural movement that expressed a rejection of logic and
reason. Through art, theatre, manifestos and design, Dadaists
expressed irrationality and chaos as a reaction to the conformity
and perverse ‘logic’ that they argued had led to war. Within a
decade the movement had fostered surrealism. Surrealist
artists, writers and performers juxtaposed unrelated and dreamlike images, communicating a rejection of logic and orderly
sequential thought.
In their very distinct ways, the Romantic, Dadaist and Surrealist
movements were important examples of opposition to the
techno-scientific basis of modern culture that was expanding
during the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries. They
challenged the completeness of scientific explanation and
offered multiple perspectives in place of general explanation.
Although Dadaism and surrealism were relatively elite and
195
From Sean F. Johnston History of Science: A Beginner’s Guide, Chapter 7 (2009)
narrow in membership, they affected the wider public at least
peripherally and temporarily.
A more direct expression of popular anti-scientific sentiments
was through the adoption of non-western religious, medical and
metaphysical ideas. The New Age movement, for example, can
be characterized as an individualistic approach to spiritual
exploration and consciousness. Like the artistic movements
described above, it criticizes the constraints and limitations of
the scientific approach, and argues for a holistic understanding
of the natural world. Although the term New Age circulated
from the early 1970s, there are identifiable links with ideas that
developed during the late nineteenth century, such as
spiritualism and alternative medicines. Here, again, universal
definitions cannot be constructed but the body of ideas draws
upon a wide range of religious concepts from many cultures.
Some concepts, such as meditation and reincarnation, have links
to Eastern religions. An attention to mystical and mysterious
dimensions of knowledge has roots in a number of world
religions, including Christian and Jewish sects and Shamanism.
The collection of practices may also amalgamate a variety of
medical traditions from other cultures. Some of these are
ancient and widespread, such as acupuncture (China) and
Ayurvedic medicine (India). Others represent new
interpretations of old concepts, such as aromatherapy’s adoption
of ideas traceable to alchemy. Admittedly this sparse survey
cannot do justice to the forms of knowledge that challenge
science; this book highlights the twists and turns of the
scientific perspective and can only sketch a background against
which to contrast it.
There is one further aspect of these alternatives that can be
mentioned, though. Some critical perspectives do not merely
challenge conventional science: they sometimes have sought to
incorporate and extend it. Some alternative medicines have
recognizable scientific links, such as therapies based on magnets
or light. New Age thinking is informed by certain sciences,
notably aspects of psychology and ecology. Its interpretations
196
From Sean F. Johnston History of Science: A Beginner’s Guide, Chapter 7 (2009)
of quantum mechanics, for example, draw connections between
consciousness, causality and spirituality. New Age claims
promote notions of knowledge (epistemologies) that extend
beyond the methods and theories of science, but frequently
make reference to them. Like spiritualism, one of its disparate
roots, some New Age beliefs borrow from the terminology of
science. Where spiritualists detected ‘vibrations’ from the spirit
world, promoters of ‘crystal therapies’ may invoke
‘resonances’, ‘energy levels’ and ‘recharging’; alternative
therapists may refer to ‘toxins’. Such adoption of scientific
jargon with unconventional meanings has been described as
pseudo-scientific. The criticism of practicing scientists usually
focuses on the lack of reliable evidence for such claims, and the
lack of precision of their foundational ideas.
Pseudoscience: a body of knowledge that claims scientific
authority without appropriate scientific methodology.
Not all of the counter-forces to modern science are to be found
in older or non-western traditions. Stalwart opposition to
Darwinism, for example, has in recent decades been buttressed
by (piecemeal) arguments drawn from the history and
philosophy of science. Rather like supporters of phrenology in
the early nineteenth century, certain supporters of creationism
have attempted to construct a ‘creation science’ that adopts
some features of scientific methodology. They may cite certain
scientists as figures of authority for their claims (although most
have credentials outside biology) or may point to inadequately
explained observations as crucial refutations of evolutionary
theory. The work of historians to reveal the complex history of
many scientific claims may be used by creationists to hint that
no scientific orthodoxy is safe and authoritative. Such pickand-mix scholarship nevertheless is inevitably patchy and
underlain by a clearly non-scientific foundation: that one
particular theory – the Biblical account of creation – is beyond
critical investigation and adjustment. By contrast, Darwinian
evolution and Mendelian genetics have adapted to new
empirical evidence.
197
From Sean F. Johnston History of Science: A Beginner’s Guide, Chapter 7 (2009)
The most serious challenge to the consensus of biologists was
probably the set of claims made by Ukrainian agronomist
Trofim Lysenko (1898-1976), who argued during the 1940s and
50s for the inheritance of acquired characteristics (rather similar
to the ideas of Lamarck some 150 years earlier). His methods
of mutating crops by vernalization (acquisition of springhardiness of crops by exposing young plants to winter
conditions) were carefully tested in other countries and found to
be irreproducible. The rise of Lysenkoism, which promised
higher crop yields, was supported in the Soviet Union by active
suppression of Mendelian genetics until 1964. What had, for a
time, been Soviet science was recast as pseudoscience.
Having distinct aims and memberships, other forms of
opposition to specific scientific claims have become
increasingly visible from the late twentieth century. The case of
British opposition to the mumps-measles-rubella (MMR)
inoculation during the late 1990s is a typical example. The case
is interesting beyond the British context precisely because it
became controversial only there; it begs the question of what
conditions were remarkable at that time in that particular
country. A small-scale study by a doctor suggested that the
MMR injection could be correlated with subsequent emergence
of autism in a small number of inoculated children. Unswayed
by large-scale trials and statistical analysis – the methodology of
modern medicine – many anxious parents rejected the perceived
dangers of inoculation in the face of unverified anecdotal
claims. This did not necessarily represent a blanket rejection of
science and medicine, but often a construction of seemingly
more acceptable explanations: for instance, that the vaccine
would be safer if divided into three separate inoculations for
mumps, measles and rubella, respectively; that the British
Medical Association, National Health Service and Department
of Health responded directly and unanimously to demands of
their political masters, and so were suspect; or that ‘rogue’
doctors would routinely be attacked when they threatened
industrial, institutional and professional establishments. Even
198
From Sean F. Johnston History of Science: A Beginner’s Guide, Chapter 7 (2009)
for rational audiences, conspiracy theories may prove more
compelling than plodding, and increasingly invisible and
incomprehensible, science. Such claims are generally
challenged by practicing scientists who argue that, even taking
political, social and cultural factors into account, bodies of
expert and independent peers (operating in different countries
under distinct political and religious systems, for example) tend,
in the long run, to agree on questions of scientific fact.
These very recent challenges to scientific knowledge and
practice are not unprecedented: as this book suggests, different
approaches to knowledge have always coexisted. What makes
them remarkable is their increased visibility in the past few
generations after a long decline in the west since the scientific
revolution. Old and new, they are topics of direct relevance to
historians of science. Not only are they linked to ideas as old as
modern science itself, but they can be expected to influence
twenty-first century thinking about science and its integration
into wider culture. The history of science, therefore, is firmly
embedded in analysis of the present-day.
between the universal and the particular
We live in interesting times, to paraphrase an ancient Chinese
blessing. History of science today is more vibrant and relevant
than ever in the past. It is enriched – and made contentious – by
other disciplines and perspectives. The debates of the ‘science
wars’ have diminished considerably, but proponents of both
extremes continue to lob volleys through historical studies. As
a result, the hot spots in the history of science are equally
changeable and multi-dimensioned. The field offers timely
opportunities for research and exploration based on every type
of human scholarship.
This beginner’s guide has suggested that the observation,
innovation in technique, logical reasoning and application of
knowledge so characteristic of science are widely-shared human
199
From Sean F. Johnston History of Science: A Beginner’s Guide, Chapter 7 (2009)
attributes readily discernible across human societies. It has
argued that natural phenomena are an inexhaustible resource to
motivate human curiosity and research. Equally universal are
the drives to explain patterns and to apply knowledge in the
pursuit of power and control. The history of science focuses on
the myriad contexts in which these human attributes have been
expressed and shaped.
Alongside this seemingly ubiquitous drive, though, are
dramatically different cultural expressions. The activities we
call ‘science’ have emerged and mutated at particular times and
places and been shaped and applied in those environments. The
techniques of how best to recognize and weigh up these events
and contexts have motivated – and sometimes divided –
historians and scientists. The challenging and continuing goal
for history of science is to detect and explain the subtle
intellectual and cultural interactions of this diverse human
enterprise.
further reading
Barnett, S. A. 2000. Science, Myth or Magic? A Struggle for
Existence. St. Leonard’s, Allen & Unwin.
Collins, H. M. and T. J. Pinch 1998. The Golem: What You
Should Know About Science. Cambridge, Cambridge University
Press.
Hess, D. J. 1993. Science in the New Age: the Paranormal, its
Defenders and Debunkers, and American Culture. Madison,
University of Wisconsin Press.
Ladyman, J. 2002. Understanding Philosophy of Science.
London, Routledge.
Latour, B. and S. Woolgar 1979. Laboratory Life: the Social
Construction of Scientific Facts. Princeton, Princeton University
Press.
200
From Sean F. Johnston History of Science: A Beginner’s Guide, Chapter 7 (2009)
Ziman, J. M. 1998. An Introduction to Science Studies: the
Philosophical and Social Aspects of Science and Technology.
Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
201