Five Problems for the Moral Consensus about Sins (Penultimate Draft)
Mike Ashfield, University of Southern California
This is a preprint of an article published in International Journal for Philosophy of Religion.
The final authenticated version is available online at: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11153-021-09795-x.
Abstract
A number of Christian theologians and philosophers have been critical of overly moralizing
approaches to the doctrine of sin, but nearly all Christian thinkers maintain that moral fault is
necessary or sufficient for sin to obtain. Call this the “Moral Consensus.” I begin by clarifying the
relevance of impurities to the biblical cataloguing of sins. I then present four extensional problems
for the Moral Consensus on sin, based on the biblical catalogue of sins: (1) moral overdemandingness, (2) agential unfairness, (3) moral repugnance, and (4) moral atrocity. Next, I
survey several partial solutions to these problems, suggested by the recent philosophical literature.
Then I evaluate two largely unexplored solutions: (a) genuine sin dilemmas and (b) defeasible
sinfulness. I argue that (a) creates more problems than it solves and that, while (b) is wellmotivated and solves or eases each of the above problems, (b) leaves many biblical ordinances
about sin morally misleading, creating (5) a pedagogical problem of evil. I conclude by arguing
that (5) places hefty explanatory burdens on those who would appeal to (b) to resolve the four
extensional problems discussed in this paper. So Christian thinkers may need to consider a more
radical separation of sin and moral fault.
Keywords Sins • Moral Faults • Dilemmas • Defeasibility • Pedagogical Evil
Ingolf Dalferth (1984) distinguishes the ontological question ‘what is sin?’ from the criteriological question ‘what is sinful?’. Much theological discourse on the doctrine of sin concerns the
ontological question of sin’s nature or essence, but recent philosophical discussions of sin have
often grappled with the criteriological issue of which acts, attitudes, or states of affairs should
count as sinful or fall under sin’s extension, whatever sin turns out to be. In this paper, I identify
problems that emerge from answers to the criteriological question of how sins are extensionally
related to moral faults. My primary aim is to engage critically with recent relevant Englishspeaking philosophical scholarship, so I will not attempt an in-depth historical study of how
theologians or philosophers have answered this question throughout the ages, and I will not address
cognate theological topics, like soteriology. However, in setting up the problems I discuss,1 I will
refer primarily to the Hebrew Bible and the New Testament, because these are the primary
authoritative canons of texts informing the religious traditions, in which recent English-speaking
philosophical discussion of sin has taken place, and because the Christian traditions and their roots
in Jewish traditions are the ones I know best.
1. The Moral Consensus about Sin’s Extension
There are five options for understanding the extensional relationship between one’s target concepts
of moral faults and sins:
1
I rely on the New Revised Standard Version translation of the bible and employ Society of Biblical Literature
abbreviations for biblical texts, though some quoted material contains other abbreviations.
Five Problems for the Moral Consensus on Sin
2
Sub-Moralism: sins are a proper subset of moral faults; all sins are moral faults,
but not all moral faults are sins; moral fault is necessary for sin to obtain, but
not sufficient;
Equi-Moralism: sins and moral faults are co-extensive; sins are moral faults and
vice versa; moral fault is necessary and sufficient for sin to obtain;
Super-Moralism: moral faults are a proper subset of sins; all moral faults are sins,
but not all sins are moral faults; moral fault is sufficient for sin to obtain, but
not necessary;
Non-Moralism: sins and moral faults overlap; some sins are moral faults—some
not; some moral faults are sins—some not; neither is necessary or sufficient for
the other to obtain; and,
Anti-Moralism: sins and moral faults are disjoint; they are wholly distinct
normative states of affairs; each is sufficient for the other’s absence (see
Dalferth 1984, 175).
Equi-Moralism seems to be the majority position among Christians. The Catholic Encyclopedia
(O’Neil 1912) affirms Equi-Moralism from within the natural law tradition, declaring that sin is
moral evil and sins are nothing other than morally bad acts. Likewise, on prominent voluntarist
theories, sin and moral fault are co-extensive, as both are just whatever is contrary to God’s will
or commands.2 Thus, in the Blackwell Companion to Philosophy of Religion (2010) entry on “Sin
and Original Sin,” Philip Quinn affirms that “The concept of sin is the concept of a human fault
that offends a morally perfect God and brings with it guilt” (614), before explaining how
voluntarists and natural law theorists differ in their understandings of sin’s co-extension with moral
fault. Equi-Moralism entails two weaker extensional claims:
Moral Necessity: moral fault is necessary for sin to obtain; and,
Moral Sufficiency: moral fault is sufficient for sin to obtain.
(For convenience, I will sometimes refer to the proponents of these claims as “Moral
Necessitarians” and “Moral Sufficientarians,” respectively.) Unsurprisingly, this combination of
commitments is often assumed in the background of related debates. 3 However, in the 1980s and
early 90s, a flurry of philosophical work on the relation between moral fault and Judeo-Christian
conceptions of sin4 reconsidered each of these Equi-Moralist commitments, picking up earlier lines
of theological criticism.
Sub-Moralists retain Moral Necessity but reject Moral Sufficiency, arguing that while all
sins are moral faults, some moral faults are not sins. This combination of commitments appears to
be rare.5 But David Attfield (1984), following in an enlightenment-era liberal tradition associated
with Pierre Bayle,6 has defended a Sub-Moralist account of the “mature” Christian concept of
sinful acts. On Attfield’s account, sin presupposes the moral, as sins are “acts contrary to morality”
2
For example, Quinn 1978, 136.
For example, M. M. Adams 1988 and 1991 observe that it pervades assumptions about theodicy and the free will
defense.
4 See Mitchell 1984, Dalferth 1984, Attfield 1984, R. M. Adams 1985, M. M. Adams 1991, and a book -length
treatment in Kellenberger 1995. See also Kilcullen 1983 and Lewis 1983.
5 Dalferth, Attfield’s co-symposiast on sin in Religious Studies 20 (2), observes that Sub-Moralism is not even
contemplated by their lead symposiast, Basil Mitchell, “and for obvious reasons: it is difficult to see how it could be
held” (177). Attfield cites Tennant 1912 as the basis for his analysis.
6 See Kilcullen 1983 and Bayle 1686–1687.
3
Five Problems for the Moral Consensus on Sin
3
(237), but “sinful acts” is the narrower category, because it includes only conscious, voluntary,
blameworthy offences that are objectively against God.
Super-Moralists, in contrast, retain Moral Sufficiency while rejecting Moral Necessity,
arguing that while all moral faults are sins, some sins are not moral faults. This combination of
commitments seems to have been espoused by several prominent theologians. For example, Emil
Brunner writes: “It is perfectly possible to combine being a sinner with being “good” in the ethical
sense; indeed, in the last resort the fact of being or not being a sinner has nothing to do with the
difference between the morally “good” and the morally “evil”” (1957; 1939, 154). 7 Other probable
Super-Moralists include Richard Niebuhr (1935), Reinhold Niebuhr (1943), Gerardus van der
Leeuw (1938), and Rudolf Otto (1958).8
Accordingly, a number of philosophers have defended Super-Moralist views. Under the
influence of Brunner and Reinhold Niebuhr, the young John Rawls (1942) defended a SuperMoralist position in his senior undergraduate thesis for the Princeton philosophy department.9
Basil Mitchell argued that while sin is manifested in moral wrongdoing, it is also manifested in
“more impalpable failures of insight” (1984, 172–173). Dalferth similarly declared that “the fact
of sin manifests itself unambiguously in moral wrongdoing and ambiguously in moral rightdoing”
(1984, 188), but he rejected Mitchell’s implicit assumption that ‘sin’ is univocal, adopting a SuperMoral account of sinful acts, and an aporetic stance toward the morality of original sinfulness.
Robert Adams’s (1985) position is less explicit, but he seems to have assumed Moral Sufficiency,
while doubting Moral Necessity. And Marilyn Adams (1991) defended a hybrid of SuperMoralism and Anti-Moralism: at a secondary stipulative level, she argued that moral faults, states
of ritual impurity, and certain kinds of thoughts, emotions, and habits—conscious or unconscious,
voluntary or nonvoluntary—constitute statutory sins; but at a fundamental level, she argued that
‘sin’ signifies an “impropriety in the relation between created persons and God. The difficulty
cannot be moral at bottom” (1991, 2, original emphasis).10 So a number of theologians and
philosophers rejected Moral Necessity in the twentieth century, but these same were careful not to
deny Moral Sufficiency.
In this century, Jesse Couenhoven (2009) has defended an account of sin based on Susan
Wolf’s notion of deep responsibility, which claims to be agnostic about sin’s relationship to
morality. However, Couenhoven’s discussion tacitly assumes Moral Sufficiency, questioning only
Moral Necessity.11 Leigh Vicens (2018) similarly sets aside issues of moral responsibility to argue
that implicit bias constitutes sin, but should implicit bias constitute sin without morally responsible
failure, this would represent a challenge to Moral Necessity alone. Erin Roberts (2014) treats
Moral Necessity about the English meaning of ‘sin’ as one of her principal foils, 12 in advocating
Brunner thinks one can be morally faultless and yet sin in being self -righteous about one’s moral faultlessness (154–
155); K. P. R. Niebuhr (1943, I.212) and Rawls (2002; 1942, 201 –202) make nearly identical arguments.
8 See H. R. Niebuhr 1935, 275; van der Leeuw 1938, 517 and 527; K. P. R. Niebuhr 1943, I.212, and Otto 1958, IV.1
and VIII. For helpful discussion of H. R. Niebuhr, see Couenhoven 2009, 566, 568 –569 (Couenhoven also cites K. P.
R. Niebuhr). For helpful discussion of Otto, see Lewis 1983, 144 –145 (Lewis also cites van der Leeuw) and especially
M. M. Adams 1991, 3–7.
9 Rawls 2002; 1942, 201–202.
10 van der Leeuw 1938 and Otto 1958 each defend hybrid Anti-/Super-Moral accounts, cited approvingly by Lewis
1983.
11 Couenhoven professes agnosticism, but questions only Moral Necessity in discussing sin’s limits (573–574).
12 Roberts argues that “Paul’s use of hamartia and its cognates in 1 Cor aligns neither with the modern [Sub-Moralist]
understanding that sin is a willful offense against God that often comes with soteriological consequences nor with the
[Anti-Moralist] idea that sin is a congenital angst that bears itself out as the kind of guilt that only Christ can fix” (361;
cf. 346).
7
Five Problems for the Moral Consensus on Sin
4
greater flexibility in biblical translation of the Greek term. 13 And, for his argumentative purposes,
Mark Schroeder (2020) assumes the disjunction of Moral Necessity or Moral Sufficiency.14
To the best of my knowledge, no one has defended a purely Anti-Moral view. Søren
Kierkegaard (1849) and Dietrich Bonhoeffer (1949) may be Non-Moralists, but this remains
unclear.15 Thus, despite substantive disputes among Equi-Moralists and their critics about what sin
and morality are, a larger extensional consensus around the disjunction of Moral Necessity or
Moral Sufficiency persists, and I will refer to this as the “Moral Consensus.” Every member of
this Moral Consensus defends or assumes some very close extensional relationship between sin
and moral fault: all sins are moral faults, all moral faults are sins, or all the above.
Figure 1: Proposed Extensional Relationships between Moral Faults and Sins
In what follows, I begin by clarifying the relevance of impurities to the biblical catalogue of sins.
I then present four problems for maintaining Moral Necessity or Moral Sufficiency about this
biblical catalogue of sins: the problems of (1) moral over-demandingness, (2) agential unfairness,
(3) moral repugnance, and (4) moral atrocity. Next, I survey some partial solutions, suggested in
the philosophical literature surveyed above. I then consider two largely unexplored general
solutions that are available to all members of the Moral Consensus: (a) the existence of genuine
hamartiological (i.e., sin) dilemmas; and (b) the defeasibility of pro tanto sinfulness. I show that,
while much can be said for both solutions, (a) creates more problems than it solves; (b) seems
well-motivated and solves or eases each of the above problems, so it is clearly an attractive
solution. But (b) also leaves many biblical ordinances about sin deeply misleading with respect to
morality and God’s will, creating (5) a pedagogical problem of evil. So anyone appealing to (b)
owes us an explanation for why God has allowed such enduring and consequential moral
misguidance in scripture. Parties to the Moral Consensus must further explain how this is
compatible with their commitment(s) to Moral Necessity or Moral Sufficiency. Thus, hefty
ἁμαρτία (hamartia); see Strong’s Greek entry 266; cf. dictionary entries for its classical Greek predecessors here.
Schroeder affirms neutrality between Equi-Moralism, Super-Moralism, and Sub-Moralism (3).
15 See Coady 2012 and Kirkpatrick 2013. Dalferth articulates the Non -Moralist option most clearly, but he dismisses
it as a (gnostic) heresy (1984, 182).
13
14
Five Problems for the Moral Consensus on Sin
5
explanatory burdens await those who appeal to sin’s defeasibility to resolve the four extensional
problems identified in this paper. So Christian thinkers may need to consider a more radical
separation of sin and moral fault.
2. Cataloguing Sins in the Bible: Do Impurities Count?
From the perspectives of most Christian communities and believers, the biblical catalogue of sins
does not by itself settle the question of what is sinful. Still, Couenhoven (2009) rightly observes
that, other things being equal, the more a view of sin can accommodate and make sense of
scriptural data together with other Christian speech and practices concerning sin, the more
attractive it will be, and even sophisticated Christian epistemologies of sin must contend with the
biblical data,16 so I will focus there. Before I proceed, however, I must say a little bit about how
the normative categories of impurity and sin are extensionally related. As this is itself a vexed
question, my aim here is to survey the extant scholarly positions, because, as I will explain in the
next section, none of these scholarly views presents an obstacle or solution to the problems I
enumerate there in section 3.
Marilyn Adams (1991) argues that sin fundamentally is uncleanness, and some scholars
have claimed that impurity is equated with sin in the Hebrew Bible,17 Second Temple Judaism,18
New Testament.19 But most specialists in this area seem to think that the only ancient precedent
for equating the two derives from the Jewish Sectarians at Qumran, known through the Dead Sea
Scrolls.20 Adams is especially indebted to Otto and the early work of anthropologist Mary
Douglas,21 but she is also influenced by Mitchell, all of whom favor the inclusion of some unclean,
impure, or defiled states in the catalogue of sins. Still, the extent of their inclusion is disputed. 22
Scholars often distinguish between different kinds of impurity. The characterization of this
distinction remains contested, but most seem to agree that the Hebrew Bible addresses at least two
kinds of defilement. “Ritual impurity” concerns biological and often unavoidable sources of
pollution, while “moral impurity” is caused by certain sins. The Hebrew Bible juxtaposes these
two conceptions, without ever explaining their interrelationship, so the question of their
relationship has been answered differently by different groups of Jews (Klawans 2000).23
16
See especially Dalferth 1984, 183–184 and Morriston 2012, 128–134.
For examples, Moore 1919, 42 and Buchanan 1970, 159–160.
18 For example, Gavin 1928, 9.
19 For examples, Neyrey 1986, 98 and 101; Borg 1987, 86–87 and 1994, 109; Rhoads 1992, 149; and Malina 1993,
154–157; cf. Klawans 2000, 12, 144, 167 nn. 54–56, and 211 n. 65.
20 Neusner 1973, 54; Newton 1985, 10–51; García Martínez 1995, 139–57; Klawans 2000, 75–91, Kazen 2010, 207–
208; Werrett 2012, 515; cf. Harrington 1993, Himmelfarb 1999, and Holtz 2012. Haber 2008, I.3, summarizes the
foregoing debate.
21 In light of criticism, Douglas later retracted many of her early conclusions about “the Abominations of Leviticus;”
see Douglas 2002, xiii–xvi; Haber 2008, 13 n. 21.
22 My thanks to an anonymous referee at Religious Studies for pressing this objection to a previous version of this
paper.
23 Concerns for ritual purity are broadly understood to reflect a Priestly textual tradition incorporated within the Torah
(including Lev 1–7 and 11–15; see Nihan 2012, 313); moral purity is associated with a later textual tradition in the
Torah, known as the Holiness Code. In place of “ritual,” some prefer “bodily,” “physical,” “levitical,” “cultic,”
“priestly,” or “ceremonial” impurity. In place of “m oral,” some prefer “spiritual” impurity. The latter is caused by
certain “sins,” “offenses,” and “unethical” or “wrongful” acts. In addition to those listed above in footnote 20, scholars
who favor such a distinction include Hoffman 1905, 303 –304; Büchler 1928, ix; Frymer-Kensky 1983, 399; Maccoby
1999, 202–203; Regev 2004, 385; Hayes 2007, 746–749; Konkel 2012, 452; Nihan 2012, 338; and Raushe 2012, 467–
468. In the teachings of Jesus, Kazen 2010 argues it becomes a matter of “outer” vs. “inner” purity; see 222. Klawans
17
Five Problems for the Moral Consensus on Sin
6
Thomas Kazen (2010) identifies two candidate “systems” of ritual purity and a third system
associated with moral purity:
1) The classification of animals into clean and unclean, i.e. edible and non-edible
(Lev 11). This legislation gives no sanctions in case of transgression, nor does
it envisage any means of purification, but assumes that the rules are always
followed.
2) The system of bodily transferable impurity (Lev 12–15; Num 19) ... This
legislation provides both sanctions and purification rites, and descriptions about
how impurity is transferred as well as instructions on how to avoid
contamination, since it assumes that people at times become impure, either by
necessity or accident.
3) Laws concerning grave sins which were regarded as polluting: certain sexual
sins and idolatry, particularly child sacrifice (Lev 18–20), as well as murder
(Num 35). Sexual sins and child sacrifice render the persons involved impure
(Lev 18:24). All three grave sins are seen as making mainly the land (Lev
18:25), and in the case of child sacrifice even the temple (Lev 20:3) impure,
with the result that the land will vomit the people out, i.e. exile them. No
purification is envisaged, but in the case of murder the land can be atoned for
only by vengeance (Num 35:33) (203–204).
However, Kazen argues these “systems” actually overlap to such a degree that the material does
not conform neatly to the above categories (2010), and scholars like Jacob Milgrom (1976) and
David Wright (1991) have instead systematized a spectrum of defilements from the minor and
ceremonial (or “tolerated”) to the serious and sinful (or “prohibited”).24 I will enumerate some of
the most morally problematic elements of these systems in section 3, but before I do, let us consider
an argument for maintaining a clean distinction between impurities and sins.
2.1 Separating (Ritual) Impurities From Sins
Jacob Neusner (1973) and Hyam Maccoby (1999) accept categories approximate to those above,
affirming the authenticity of ritual impurity, but following the second century rabbinic tradition of
the Mishnah, each is critical of a genuine defilement caused by sins. Neusner accepts that the acts
defined in Leviticus 18–20 are sins and moral failures, but he argues they are only metaphorically
defiling (1973). Maccoby draws an even harder distinction between ritual purity and ethics,25
which he says is “characteristic of Judaism at all periods” (205)—Qumran apparently
notwithstanding. He insists that ritual impurity is not sinful, and he denies that sin is ever genuinely
says Hoffman’s seminal work in this area was informed “by talmudic and medieval rabbinic literature. But more
important, Hoffmann and the medieval Jewish exegetes were preceded by Philo and the early rabbinic sages (the
tannaim), who very clearly distinguished between ritual, bodily impurities on the one hand, and the defilement that
results from sin on the other” (2000, 6).
24 See also Newton 1985, 2–4; Frevel 2012, 376–377; Nihan 2012, 339–350; and Rausche 2012, 468–473.
25 Maccoby distinguishes between rules binding only on Jews (lex judaica) and rules binding on all of humanity (lex
gentium), which he insists is basic in biblical and rabbinic Judaism: “[ritual] elements are intended to be subordinate
and limited; they are not a coded philosophy, but just what they purport to be, rules for the conduct of a priestly society
[applying only to Jews, converts, and residents of the Holy Land], in which a sense of constant attendance on God
demands a protocol which in no way supersedes the demands of ordinary [moral] duties to neighbours, family and
strangers” (1999, 195).
Five Problems for the Moral Consensus on Sin
7
defiling.26 But he too accepts that the elements of sexual morality and other ethical concerns
enshrined in Leviticus 18–20 are “the same for all human beings, Canaanites as well as Israelites”
(203), and he never denies the sinfulness of the offenses defined by this “moral” system. So while
there is some precedent for keeping dietary uncleanness and bodily impurities out of the catalogue
of biblical sins, no one seems to deny that “moral impurities” are sinful in the Hebrew Bible.
2.2 Impurity in the New Testament
What did important figures in the New Testament have to say about impurity? The evidence
concerning Jesus’ attitude toward purity is complex, 27 disputed, and difficult to summarize,28 but
the central pieces of textual evidence from Mark 7 and Matthew 15 attribute to Jesus “the idea that
attention to moral purity is more important than attention to ritual purity. That is, Jesus here is
addressing himself to the relationship between ritual purity and moral purity, and clearly he
prioritizes moral purity over ritual purity. [...but...] For Jesus, a discussion of ritual impurity led —
inevitably perhaps?—into a discussion of sin” (Klawans 2000, 149). So while Jesus seems to have
prioritized matters of sin and moral purity, he also did not clearly separate those concerns from
matters of ritual purity.29
The author of the Epistle to the Hebrews thinks the need to maintain ritual purity ended
with Jesus’ death, though enduring lessons are drawn from an analogy between ritual and moral
impurity (Heb 9:9–14). Klawans suggests that Paul’s position bears some resemblance to this:
“Like John [the Baptist], Paul views baptism as a ritual of atonement that effects purification from
moral defilement. Like Jesus, Paul’s interest in defilement is focused on moral impurity. … [but]
he does not articulate any interest in issues relating to ritual impurity. So with Paul we see a break
with the past, in his rejection of the need to maintain ritual purity” (2000, 156). 30 However,
Christine Hayes (2002) has argued that Paul’s ideas concerning purity are innovative and difficult
to describe in terms of moral and ritual impurity, suggesting a third category of “carnal” impurity,
which Moshe Blidstein (2017) summarizes as being “caused by intentional sin and not some
26
27
See Maccoby 1999, 200–201, 208; see also Konkel 2012 on Ezek 40–48.
As Klawans says, in introducing the question of Jesus’ relationship to the Law:
Matthew’s Jesus declares unambiguously, toward the beginning of the Sermon on the Mount, that
“not one letter, not one stroke of a letter, will pass from the law until all is accomplished” (Matt.
5:18). On the other hand, Mark would have us understand that Jesus declared all foods pure (Mark
7:19b), thus abrogating the food laws of Leviticus 11 and Deuteronomy 14. As we will see, Mark
7:19b is widely recognized to be a secondary gloss. And the Sermon on the Mount contains all sorts
of adaptations, interpretations, and other modifications of the law that Matthew’s Jesus claims to
have fully upheld (2000, 143; see 146–150).
28
29
See Kazen 2010 for a book-length treatment of this question.
Klawans arrives at similar conclusions about John the Baptist’s views on purity:
John insisted that in order to atone for sin, one had to undergo a baptism—a rite whose practice
ancient Jews were more likely to associate with ritual purification … [So] he clearly did not
compartmentalize ritual impurity and sin. But because he did not apparently view sin as a source of
ritual defilement, he did not merge the conceptions of ritual impurity and sin. As far as we can tell,
John did not consider sinners to be ritually defiling and thus probably did not conceive of his baptism
as purificatory in the ritual sense. … [So it seems] that John’s baptism worked as a ritual of moral
purification, effecting atonement by purifying individuals from moral defilement (2000, 143).
John appears to have been primarily concerned with sin and moral impurity, but what evidence we have suggests he
did not completely divorce those concerns from matters of ritual purity.
30 See also Newton 1985, 97.
Five Problems for the Moral Consensus on Sin
8
unintended contagion, but nevertheless functions through the physical, individual body, is
transmitted from flesh to flesh, and is purified through a once-in-a-lifetime bodily ritual, baptism”
(154).31
The evidence of the New Testament, therefore, is mixed. Yet, even if Christians think that,
on balance, this evidence weighs in favor of ritual impurities being (or having been at one time)
sinful, it seems that they also have good reason to think they are properly regarded as being (or
having been) less sinful. Moral impurity, on the other hand, remains a grave matter throughout the
New Testament, wherein the catalogues of defiling sins ascribed to Jesus suggest considerable
overlap with earlier lists, despite some significant changes and expansions (Klawans 2000;
Blidstein 2017; Mark 7:20–23; and Matt 15:18–20), while Paul generally reserves the language of
impurity for sexual sins (Newton 1985; Klawans 2000; Blidstein 2017; Rom 6:19; 1 Cor 5:11–13,
6:15–19; 2 Cor 12:21; Gal 5:19; Eph 4:19, 5:3–5; Col 3:5; and 1 Thess 4:3–6.).
All of these extensional models, therefore, count at least some impurities (or so-called
“impurities”) as sins, and this ensures that none of the above presents an obstacle or solution to
any of the problems I enumerate in the next section.
Figure 2: Proposed Extensional Relationships between Impurities and Sins
3. Four Extensional Problems for the Moral Consensus about Sins
Consider Marilyn Adams’s summary of biblical sins:
the Biblical catalog of sins includes, not only (i) conscious voluntary actions, but
also (ii) emotions (e.g., anger) and cognitive states (e.g., belief) not within our
(direct) voluntary control, (iii) dispositions, habits, inclinations that resist the
normative ordering of the self, and (iv) states or conditions of uncleanness (e.g., the
abominations of Leviticus) (1991, 2).
Four extensional problems arise from elements across all four of these categories of sin, with some
problems arising for elements from more than one category. Several of these problematic elements
will be familiar to those well-versed in the problems of evil, but my aim here is to show that they
also pose extensional problems for the Moral Consensus about sins. These problems obtain for all
parties to the Moral Consensus, regardless of how they understand the nature of sin or moral fault.
31
See also Hayes 2002, 96 and 254 nn. 16, 17.
Five Problems for the Moral Consensus on Sin
9
3.1 The Problem of Moral Over-Demandingness
With respect to (i) conscious voluntary sins, Jesus is reported to have taught that God requires the
performance of intuitively supererogatory self-sacrificial acts, like turning the other cheek to an
aggressor who strikes you, or loving your enemies (Matt 5:38–48). If conscious, voluntary nonobservance of these requirements is sinful, then Moral Necessity will have significant revisionary
implications for most prominent normative ethical theories. Specifically, it enlarges the extension
of what is morally impermissible to include inactions (i.e., refraining from supererogation)
ordinarily thought permissible. If harshly sanctioning such omissions 32 is sinless, then (by
contraposition) Moral Sufficiency entails that such harsh sanctions are morally permissible. Either
of these changes would make one’s normative ethics implausibly demanding, so call this the
problem of moral over-demandingness.
3.2 The Problems of Agential Unfairness and Moral Repugnance
In relation to (ii), some cognitive states, especially the element of unbelief in an agent’s lack of
religious faith, are said to constitute sin. Most explicitly, the author of Hebrews writes: “Take care,
brothers and sisters, that none of you may have an evil, unbelieving heart that turns away from the
living God” (Heb 3:12; see 3:19; 4:3), warning especially against unbelief born of hard heartedness (Heb 3:8–16; 4:7). The moralist might assume that the relevant cognitive state, or
doxastic process whereby it obtains, is voluntaristic and sinful only when willfully irrational. 33 But
repeated warnings against deception suggest that the state itself is sinful, even if rationally held,
formed in response to misleading evidence, or not directly within one’s voluntary control. 34 After
all, God “has mercy on whomever he chooses, and he hardens the heart of whomever he chooses”
(Rom 9:18), and most Christian believe that without repentance this sin of unbelief receives eternal
punishment in hell. Yet, on most prominent normative ethical views, it is not clear that cognitive
states, especially those beyond our control, constitute moral faults, 35 so the revisionary
implications of Moral Necessity extend even further.
Concerning (iii), Jesus also teaches that conative attitudes, like desires or intentions to
commit adultery, are no less sinful than their objects, like the act of adultery itself. Jesus is reported
to have taught that “everyone who looks at a woman with lust has already committed adultery with
her in his heart” (Matt 5:28). In the preceding pericope, 36 Jesus says there is no difference, in terms
of one’s liability to judgment, between the act of murder and the kind of anger exemplified in
insulting someone, and as he later explains, such evil intentions, which proceed from the heart, are
among the sins that defile a person (Matt 15:18–20; Mark 7:20–23). Similarly, 1 John 3:15
explicitly equates hatred with murder: “All who hate a brother or sister are murderers.” It is widely
accepted that attitudes can express immoral dispositions, or reflect badly on one’s moral character,
but Jesus seems to take the stronger position of equating the sinfulness of conative attitudes with
the sinfulness of the desired or intended act. On most prominent normative ethical views, it is not
32
See e.g., Matt 7:15–23; 13:24–30, 36–43; 25:41–46.
Cf. Job 21:14.
34 See Mark 13:5–6; Matt 24:4–5; Luke 21:8; Eph 5:6; Col 2:8; 2 Thess 2:3; 1 Tim 6:20 –21.
35 However, for arguments that cognitive attitudes can be morally impermissible and can morally wrong others, see
e.g., Basu 2018 and Basu and Schroeder 2019. For arguments that they can wrong God, see Schroeder 2020. For a
defense of moral responsibility for, and the sinfulness of, certain nonvoluntary cognitive attitudes see R. M. Adams
1985.
36 See Matt 5:21–22; see Jas 1:19–20.
33
Five Problems for the Moral Consensus on Sin
10
clear that conative attitudes—particularly those outside our direct or indirect voluntary control—
constitute moral faults at all, much less wrongings on a par with the desired or intended act.37
Finally, listed among the (iv) states of uncleanness are ritual impurities, which intuitively
seem morally permissible. These include things like (unwittingly) touching the carcass of a pig,38
or perhaps wearing clothing of mixed fibers (Lev 19:19). Some conditions outside one’s (direct)
control are also considered ritually impure, like being acutely postpartum, being “leprous,” or
menstruating (Lev 12–14), and Aaronic priests with any physical “blemish,” like blindness,
dwarfism, physical disability, or disfigurement, are excluded from presenting food offerings in the
Tabernacle (Lev 21). Though Neusner, Maccoby, and some others argue that ritual impurities were
not sinful in themselves,39 failures, including unintentional or unknowing failures, to observe cultic
requirements surrounding these ritual impurities, clearly constituted sin (Lipinski and Jacobs 2007;
Hayes 2007; Lev 4–5) and were subject to punishment (Lev 5:17). So even on the most restrictive
accounts, which exclude these impurities (or “impurities) from counting as sins, these ordinances
still create problems.
Maintaining Moral Necessity about the sinfulness of voluntary (ii) cognitive, (iii) conative,
and (iv) bodily states, further enlarges the extension of what is morally impermissible to include
states ordinarily considered beyond moral evaluation, representing a prima facie challenge to the
moral-‘ought’ implies ‘can’ principle (hereafter, “the M-OIC principle”).40 As the M-OIC
principle reflects the idea that morality should make fair demands on our exercises of agency, call
this the problem of agential unfairness. Independently, the implied immorality of some of the
above nonvoluntary bodily states of impurity have misogynistic, xenophobic, and ableist
implications for one’s normative ethics, creating a distinct problem I will call the problem of moral
repugnance. As we saw in the previous section, if sanctioning any or all of these defined offenses
is sinless, then (by contraposition) Moral Sufficiency entails such sanctions are morally
permissible, so versions of these two problems may arise for Moral Sufficientarians as well.
3.3 The Problem of Moral Atrocity
Admittedly, Moral Sufficiency’s problems may appear less serious, especially since no specific
sanctions are defined for some of the above offenses. But a more serious problem arises for
maintaining Moral Necessity or Moral Sufficiency about the system of moral impurities, because
they define intuitively non-moral offenses as grave sins and prescribe morally atrocious sanctions
for the same. Here, I remind the reader that even under the Mishnaic division of ritual impurities
from sins, the following offenses are still considered gravely sinful.
These statutes are depicted as having been designed by God to set Israel apart from its
neighbors (Lev 18:3, 24; 20:22–24), keep citizens and aliens alike (Lev 18:26; 19:10; 20:2) from
practices or states deemed defiling (Lev 18:20–30; 19:31; 20:3, 25),41 profane (Lev 18:21; 19:8,
11, 29; 20:3),42 or abominable (Lev 18:22–30; 19:7; 20:13, 25),43 preserve the land and its
inhabitants from defilement (Lev 18:26–27; 19:10, 33–34; 20:2), and make Israel holy (Lev 19:1).
37
For a defense of moral responsibility for, and the sinfulness of, certain conative attitudes see R. M. Adams 1985.
Lev 5:2; 11:1–8; Deut 14:1–8.
39 Couenhoven concurs that leprosy, for example, was considered ritually impure but not sinful; see 2009, 565 and
576.
40 For discussion see Kellenberger 1995, 305–309; see R. M. Adams 1985 for a partial response to this challenge.
41 See Strong’s Hebrew entry 2930.
42 See Strong’s Hebrew entry 2490.
43 עבַה
ֵ (ּתֹוtoebah); see Strong’s Hebrew entry 8441.
38
Five Problems for the Moral Consensus on Sin
11
Leviticus 20 sets forth capital punishment by stoning 44 for several offences defined in Leviticus
18–19, including cursing or dishonoring a parent, consensual adultery, bestiality, consensual
homosexual sex, and specific narrowly-defined categories of incest, even singling out one of the
latter offences for burning (Lev 20:14), though others are ignored. Leviticus 21:9 adds that a
daughter of a priest who practices prostitution is also to be burned, because she thereby profanes
her father (Lev 21:9). However, burning seems to have been used to aggravate the punishment of
stoning during biblical times, with the corpse being burned after execution (Cohn, Rabinowitz,
and Elon 2008, 445–446; see Josh 7:25).45 God also orders the stoning of a man in Numbers 15:32–
36 for gathering firewood on the Sabbath, an offence defined in Leviticus and elsewhere as a
failure to keep the Sabbath holy (Exod 35:2–3; cf. Lev 19:3; 23:3; Exod 16:23; 20:8–10; 23:12;
31:14–17; Deut 5:12). Most disturbingly, God commands the Israelites to commit genocide during
their conquest of Canaan:
“But as for the towns of these peoples that the Lord your God is giving you as an
inheritance, you must not let anything that breathes remain alive. You shall
annihilate them—the Hittites and the Amorites, the Canaanites and the Perizzites,
the Hivites and the Jebusites—just as the Lord your God has commanded, so that
they may not teach you to do all the abhorrent things that they do for their gods,
and you thus sin against the Lord your God” (Deut 20:16–18; cf. Deut 7:1–11; 1
Sam 15:2–3).
The Hebrew word here for ‘abhorrent things’46 indicates motivations related to impurity, and as
God says earlier: “Make no covenant with them and show them no mercy. … break down their
altars, smash their pillars, hew down their sacred poles, and burn their idols with fire. For you are
a people holy to the Lord your God; the Lord your God has chosen you out of all the peoples on
earth to be his people, his treasured possession” (Deut 7:2, 5–6).
These offenses are harshly sanctioned, because they are understood to be grave sins, and
Moral Necessity entails that these acts are morally faulty. But any such normative ethical view is
implausibly demanding and repugnant. Unfortunately, the problems do not end there, because the
closing chapter of Leviticus strongly implies that failing to observe any of the ordinances contained
in the book, including capital sanctions prescribed in Leviticus 20, is itself sinful (Lev 26: 14–39;
cf. Deut 28:15–68). Moral Necessity about these additional sins of disobedience entails that failing
to put people to death, for things like dishonoring their parents, is morally faulty or wrong, so
putting them to death is morally obligatory.47 At the same time, if obeying these capital sanctions
is sinless, and that seems like a safe assumption, then (by contraposition) Moral Sufficiency entails
that these incredibly harsh sanctions can be enacted without moral fault. Moral Necessity thereby
enlarges the extension of what is morally obligatory, and Moral Sufficiency the extension of what
is morally permissible, to include heinous acts, making moral successes of misogynistic,
homophobic, and xenophobic atrocities, among others, and turning normative ethics upside down.
Call this the problem of moral atrocity. Such morally abhorrent implications can only be sustained
44
Stoning is thought to have been the standard method of judicial execution in Biblical times, but Talmudic jurists
later developed a more humane substitute to stoning, by wh ich the danger of mutilation was considerably reduced and
death accelerated. See Cohn, Rabinowitz, and Elon 2008, 446; cf. Lev 24:23; Num 15:36; 1 Kgs 21:13; 2 Chr 24:21.
45 In contrast, burning someone alive is reported as a non-Jewish Babylonian punishment in Dan 3:6.
46 עבַה
ֵ (ּתֹוtoebah); see footnote 43 above.
47 Given K (◇ ≡ ¬□¬), if it is not permissible to not φ (¬◇¬ φ), because it is morally faulty or wrong to not φ, then
(¬¬ □ ¬¬ φ). Double-negation elimination yields (¬¬ □ ¬¬ φ —> □ ¬¬ φ), and ( □ ¬¬ φ —> □ φ), so it is obligatory
to φ (□ φ).
Five Problems for the Moral Consensus on Sin
12
by sacrificing entirely the substance of God’s alleged moral goodness, not to mention the
plausibility of one’s normative ethics.
4. Partial Solutions in the Recent Philosophical Literature
Prima facie, the Moral Consensus faces serious extensional problems, with Moral Necessity and
Moral Sufficiency each creating their own versions of the problems of moral over-demandingness,
agential unfairness, moral repugnance, and moral atrocity, respectively. There are a number of
ways to limit the scope of these problems,48 but in this section I will focus on solutions.
Michael Bergmann, Michael Murray, and Michael Rea identify three strategies for dealing
with the Bible’s morally problematic contents:
1. Reject God’s Authorship: Deny that the text is divinely inspired;
2. Reinterpret God’s Intent: Allow that the text is divinely inspired, but (i) deny
that the apparently problematic commands and permissions therein were in fact
the commands and permissions intended by God, and (ii) identify a morally
unproblematic message as the overall divine message of the text; or
3. Recover God’s Larger Moral Purpose: Allow that the text is divinely inspired
and that the apparently problematic commands and permissions were in fact
divinely intended, and argue that they are unproblematic because they serve a
greater good, or impose just punishments for sin, or are in some other way
consistent with God’s duties toward human beings and with God’s character as
perfectly loving and morally perfect (2011, 7).
To this list, one might add:
4. Bite the Bullet: Accept that the texts are divinely inspired and that the
apparently problematic commands and permissions were in fact divinely
intended as is.
I think Christian thinkers can sensibly consider this fourth strategy in response to the problem of
moral over-demandingness—especially with respect to the demands of self-sacrificial love—but I
will assume without argument that simply Biting the Bullet in not an appropriate response to the
problems of moral repugnance or atrocity. In general, different strategies may be appropriate for
different problems, and we cannot canvass every version or combination of these four strategies,
For example, Jesus says he is not abolishing even the least demand of the Law, “until all is accomplished” (Matt
5:17–18), suggesting that the sinfulness of (iv) ritual impurities could be abolished when Christ’s High Priestly
ministry is completed with his crucifixion (see Heb 1–10), fulfilling all requirements of holiness in the Law and freeing
God’s people from its constraints (see John 19:30; Acts 10; Rom 3; 7:6; Gal 3; Phil 3). Alternatively, or in addition,
one might try to argue that the most draconian prohibitions related to moral impurity narrowly address the idolatrous
excesses of Israel’s neighbors, which sometimes involved child sacrifice. On this proposal, these prohibitions were
more specifically targeted at acts like consensual homosexual acts of idol worship, and had no wider intended moral
or social import (see e.g., Lein 2015). Meanwhile, the Jewish Sanhedrin decided its competence to inflict capital
punishment ceased with the destruction of the Second Temple in 70 CE, because “at a time wh en there is no priest,
there is no judgment of capital cases” (Sanh. 52b, Ketub. 30a; cf. Sanh. 41a). And though Jewish courts continued to
execute death sentences where they had the power, it is not clear that capital punishments for offenses of moral
impurity continued to be enforced (see Cohn, Rabinowitz, and Elon 2008, 447). At best, however, each of these
proposals only restricts the problems of moral repugnance or atrocity to smaller historical segments of the normative
states of affairs—they do not solve the problems.
48
Five Problems for the Moral Consensus on Sin
13
but in this section I will survey some representative partial solutions suggested by the recent
philosophical literature.
4.1 Robert Adams’s Defense of Moral Responsibility for Some Involuntary Sins
Robert Adams (1985) defends an expanded scope for moral responsibility 49 over nonvoluntary (ii)
cognitive and (iii) conative states: “the thesis that we are ethically accountable only for our
voluntary actions and omissions must be rejected. There are involuntary sins [i.e., involuntary acts,
omissions, and states that are inherently blameworthy].” We need not examine his arguments in
detail, but this is a narrow-scope version of the fourth strategy addressed at two of the more
difficult aspects of the agential unfairness problem, and it looks to be one of the most promising
partial solutions in the philosophical literature. Adams implies that sin has distinctly non-moral
theological meanings, suggesting that he rejects Moral Necessity and avoids its problems.
However, in assuming that ethical blameworthiness suffices for sin, he presupposes Moral
Sufficiency, so one might naturally wonder whether his defense of involuntary sins has any
implications for the Moral Sufficientarian’s problems of agential unfairness and moral repugnance
arising from the sinfulness of nonvoluntary (iv) bodily states of ritual impurity. But it appears that
he would not defend moral responsibility for these nonvoluntary (iv) bodily states,50 so no further
help can be gleaned from his position.
4.2 Placing Morally Relative Limits on Sin with Attfield’s Sub-Moralism
Attfield’s Sub-Moralism avoids extensional problems generated by Moral Sufficiency and lends
itself to Rejecting God’s Authorship of the texts causing problems for Moral Necessity, because
his account is silent on all of the problematic categories of sin. Attfield locates the extension of the
“mature” Christian concept of sinful acts within conscious, 51 voluntary, blameworthy moral
wrongs. He thinks the standards determining moral blameworthiness are socially constructed
within liberal society. In private matters, where liberalism permits “a variable superstructure of
individual ideals, espoused according to choice, resting on top of a common social morality” (229),
the relevant standards of wrongness are subjective, but their eligibility for individual selection is
socially determined. But since “we have no independent knowledge in a disputable area for what
49
See discussion of this tactic in Mitchell 1984, 167–173; Dalferth 1984, 179–181; Kellenberger 1995, 302–307; and
Couenhoven 2009, 567.
50 Adams contends that we are directly responsible for states of mind with intentional objects, “responding,
consciously or unconsciously, to data that are rich enough to permit a fairly adequate ethical appreciation of the state’s
intentional object and of the object’s place in the fabric of personal relationship;” we are not accountable for “simple
feelings of hunger and thirst, insofar as they are primitive responses to physical stimuli” (1985, 26); nonvoluntary
bodily states clearly resemble the latter more closely than the former. Elsewhere, however, Adams suggests that a
divine command theorist might “theorize that the objectively disgusting is what disgusts God ” (1987, 262), leaving
room for impure states to have normative, if not ethical, significance. For recent arguments that cognitive attitudes
can morally wrong others, see e.g., Basu 2018 and Basu and Schroeder 2019; for arguments that they can wrong God,
see Schroeder 2020.
51 Since the eighteenth century liberals have often placed a high value upon sincerity and a comparatively lower value
on being right. Attfield’s Sub-Moralism falls within this liberal tradition, but he acknowledges that in matters of
fundamental social morality, like the wrongness of Nazism or genocide, we dare not recognize sincere “invincible
ignorance” of moral standards or egregious moral error as excuses from moral blame, in otherwise responsible agents.
In this respect, Attfield departs from an earlier liberal tradition, associated with Pierre Bayle and some Jesuits,
according to which there is no sin, properly speaking, unless we know that we are sinning, which implies that if the
Nazi acts in accordance with their warped conscience they do not sin. See Attfield 1984, 234–235; Kilcullen 1983.
Five Problems for the Moral Consensus on Sin
14
is right and wrong and so are hesitant to speak of objective moral law … with ethically debatable
questions [e.g., abortion] we may just have to leave the issue undecided” (233). Attfield says that
“objectively speaking,” sins are offences against God, whether or not they are so understood by
the offender, so the moral rules are not formulated under the assumption that God exists or is a
moral patient. Indeed, many contemporary liberal societies deliberately eschew such assumptions.
But his discussion suggests that the only sense in which this is settled “objectively” is that it is
(mostly) settled by liberal social morality, and never by individual moral commitments alone. No
recourse to objective moral facts is ever implied. Attfield thereby defends a liberal cultural
relativism about the epistemology of moral blameworthiness, and perhaps the ontology of moral
fault itself. Christian Miller (2018) summarizes the problems such a view faces in combination
with theistic commitments:
Moral relativist positions ... are already fraught with numerous problems just on
philosophical grounds. But from a theistic perspective they seem completely
untenable. For it is hard to think that God would leave it up to individuals or cultures
to decide whatever they like about moral matters. This is especially apparent when
we turn to actual theistic religions. Time and again we see in the Bible and the
Koran how God morally condemns human behavior on the basis of invoking a
higher morality that clearly seems to have more authority than whatever the people
in question are thinking (88).
Given Jesus’s reported claim that “with the judgment you make you will be judged, and the
measure you give will be the measure you get” (Matt 7:2), it would be unsurprising for the
Christian God to apply human standards of moral judgment to determine (at least, in part) whether
they are guilty of moral wrongdoing or sin. But Attfield’s account leaves no room for any higher
human-minds-independent divine standard, so while a realist or theistic constructivist SubMoralism could avoid this problem, Attfield’s does not.
Moreover, beyond simply assuming a liberal culture-relative Sub-Moralism from the
outset,52 Attfield’s only argument appeals to a version of the M-OIC principle,53 so as to maintain
Moral Necessity by limiting sin’s scope to acts over which we may unproblematically be said to
have control and bear moral responsibility. 54 This provides a principled defense against the
problem of agential unfairness, but Moral Necessity’s problems with the sinfulness of voluntary
acts or omissions remain.
Attfield deliberately avoids “the more pastoral aspects of the idea of sin that concern confessors. [He neglects] the
original biblical concept to a large extent and the usage of the underlying Hebrew and Greek terms” (22 7). He also
explicitly excludes discussion of dispositional or original sinfulness, though he says that the latter is “a notion
important for any doctrine of man as a moral being” (227). So while he asserts that sin is parasitic on morality, and
characterizes this as his “main thesis,” it is more accurately characterized as the Procrustean bed on which sin is laid
for his analysis. Moreover, Attfield says that “sin is an offence against God and all infractions of God’s law are equally
contrary to the divine will and offensive in his eyes. There are no mitigating circumstances with sin. … the gravity of
sin does not concern men, who can leave adjudication upon this to the judgment -seat of God” (236–237; cf. Jas 2:10–
11). If this is so, demands of the divine law cannot simply be cut away, because they seem over-demanding, make
impossible demands upon our being rather than our agency, are repugnant, or are atrocious by our (liberal) moral
lights. So he says much to undermine his own position.
53 Attfield says that anything “not under the direct control of the will … cannot be a wrong and so a sin” (228 –229);
“for sin to be possible, there must be a choice before the agent between two lines of conduct” (235). So if one morally
ought not-φ, it must be the case that one can choose (by directly controlled act of will) between φ and some other line
of conduct ψ.
54 See discussion of this tactic in Mitchell 1984, 167; Dalferth 1984, 176; and Kellenberger 1995, 302–307.
52
Five Problems for the Moral Consensus on Sin
15
4.3 Marilyn Adams’s Super-Moralist Embrace of Value Conflicts
Marilyn Adams adopts something closest to the third strategy, but she rejects the assumption that
God’s larger purposes are to be recovered in purely moral terms. She unreservedly rejects Moral
Necessity, so her accounts side-step its problems, but it is unclear whether she recognizes the
remaining problems posed by Moral Sufficiency, especially concerning (iv) uncleanness. 55
Like Attfield, Adams accepts a version of moral relativism, 56 on which morality is “a
human institution, roughly the best framework humans generally can master and/or apply on a
large scale to promote friendly and curtail anti-social behavior and attitudes” (1991, 2; see 1988,
232). But as she rejects Moral Necessity, this proves less problematic, because she can appeal to
higher human-minds-independent, categorical, authoritative, normative, knowable facts about sin.
For although she thinks sin is fundamentally an Anti-Moral matter of ontological incommensurability between the divine and human natures,57 she also thinks God stipulates a set of secondary
criteria for sinfulness, including moral faults and breaches of distinctly non-moral norms, like
norms of honor or purity:
Immutable as the ontological incommensuration itself is, the resultant formal
obstacles to relationship can be easily overcome by Divine fiat: just as governments
confer value on relatively worthless paper through legislation stipulating a valueequivalence to silver and gold; so God, the creator and governor of the universe,
can simply count finite creatures as valuable by loving them, declare ex officio
certain conditions and deeds of creatures to be honorific of Him. The result is to
create at the second level a “stipulative” or “statutory” contrast among created
beings and doings between what is sinful and what is worthy and acceptable and
righteous in God’s sight (21, original emphases).
So although human-constructed systems of evaluation and accountability, like the purity and
defilement calculus, the honor code, and morality, lack the requisite normative force to command
God’s recognition or compliance, the norms governing sin are stipulated by God to supervene over
these conventional evaluative systems, conferring upon them the requisite status to determine
55 McCord Adams says that Moral Necessitarians or “Plain Moralists with the courage of their convictions dismiss
(iv) uncleanness as a primitive category deservedly supplanted by the ethical” (1991, 2). But a similar retreat from
(iv) uncleanness is neither attractive nor available to her. Retreating depends on first drawing a distinction between
genuine moral norms and norms of purity or uncleanness, and her efforts to maintain such a distinction do not square
well with her other meta ethical commitments. According to her naturalist-conventionalist picture, morality is a kind
of social technology innovated to facilitate cooperation. But it is difficult to see why the draconian ordinances in
Leviticus are not part of the best framework of constraints ancient Israel was able to master and apply large-scale to
curtail what they understood (wrongly, in several cases) to be antisocial behaviors and attitudes. Indeed, she would
later argue that they proved useful to maintaining social order an d stability (see 1999, 192). So even if Marilyn Adams
could be tempted to reject the sinfulness of statutory uncleanness, her metaethical commitments cannot sustain a
principled distinction between genuine normative distinction in kind between moral failin gs and offenses of
uncleanness.
56 Rogers 2002 notes that there is reason to be cautious in ascribing this view to Marilyn Adams; see 75 –76, 81–83.
However, Rogers may not appreciate Adams’s theistic constructivism about sin or how it can explain the latter’s
acceptance of human-minds-independent, categorical, authoritative, normative, knowable facts about the indignity of
things like slavery; cf. M. M. Adams 1999, 196. Mitchell’s Super-Moralism prefigures Adams’s account in several
important ways, and Dalferth similarly criticizes Mitchell’s moral relativism; see Mitchell 1984, 172; Dalferth 1984,
180.
57 She says “the logically appropriate feeling response for creatures is not [moral] guilt (which befits a rebellious use
of free agency) but a sense of taint and shame” (1991, 21).
Five Problems for the Moral Consensus on Sin
16
categorical, authoritative, normative, knowable facts about sin. 58 Thus, Adams is a theistic
constructivist about the norms governing sin, and this means that her relativism about human
morality does not present the same problems as Attfield’s.
However, because she thinks that God has elevated conflicting conventional human
evaluative systems into genuine systems of divine hamartiological norms, moral norms about sin
come into conflict with non-moral norms about sin. She anticipates the objection that this
undermines morality and asserts that, though the evaluative systems of morality, the honor code,
and the purity and defilement calculus are incongruent, all are illuminating and provide
complementary pictures of human affairs. Thus, she protests:
I have not denied morality a place at the table or contested its usefulness in
regulating contemporary societies. Nor have I doubted that we have moral
obligations to refrain from genocide, from domestic violence, from starving or
maiming other human beings. Nothing I have said calls into question our duty not
to support demagogues or our moral obligation to promote more equitable
distributions of this world’s goods. Hence, I plead innocent to undermining
morality in any of these ways (1999, 192).
But pleading innocence is no substitute for providing a defense. Adams fails to address how these
incongruencies between moral and non-moral norms are to be understood, and Katherin Rogers
(2002) details several problematic implications in her Augustinian reply.
Two things may be said on Adams’s behalf. Firstly, she argues that God does not hold us
morally responsible through the practice of blame, and this is in line with Maccoby’s separation
of ritual purity from ethics.59 Even though there may be reasons, say, to avoid, confess, or repent
of one’s ritual impurity for touching unclean animals or wearing mixed fibers, feelings like guilt
are not apt. Indeed, the observance of merely formal requirements can imbue otherwise mund ane
activities, like getting dressed or preparing meals, with worshipful significance and create a sense
of intimacy with God.60 Secondly, even as the demands of moral and non-moral norms may
provide reasons to avoid, confess, and repent of various sins, these reasons may not all be of equal
weight, and whereas statutory sins are not intrinsically sinful, but merely mala prohibita, it is for
God to determine their comparative weights.
Yet, insofar as there is any hamartiological reason to be purified of menstruation, or confess
as sinful a consensual homosexual act of love, the responses that these may be less weighty, nonmoral sins (though the ordinance of capital punishment for the latter suggests otherwise), or that
they should not elicit feelings like moral guilt, are still unsatisfactory.61 So much then for the partial
solutions suggested by the recent philosophical literature. In the next two sections, I consider two
For Marilyn Adams, this ratification seems to be constrained by “what is good or bad for individuals at the symbolic
level” (1999, 196); cf. Rogers 2002, 75.
59 She distinguishes between “what other people have a right to blame us for” and “what we should be ready to confess
as a sin to God” (1991, 24, n. 11), and later argues that “our personal capacit ies are too limited in relation to Divine
powers of thought and will for it to make sense for God to hold us responsible to God for what we do, any more than
it makes sense for a mother to hold her infant responsible to her for dirty diapers” (1999, 191, o riginal emphasis; cf.
1988, 232–233). Human beings lack the requisite level of agency to merit moral accountability before God, and they
lack the requisite value to command God’s love. Instead, their value is conferred by divine love and their agency
enabled by God’s motherly care; see M. M. Adams 1991, 21; 1999, 103 –104; cf. Kellenberger 1995, 326 and Rogers
2002, 74.
60 For a discussion of norms of etiquette as mere formalities, see Wodak 2019.
61 I am grateful to Ralph Wedgwood for suggesting these responses on Marilyn Adams’s behalf and discussing their
merits.
58
Five Problems for the Moral Consensus on Sin
17
largely unexplored general solutions, available to Moral Necessitarians and Moral Sufficientarians
alike.
5. Hamartiological Dilemmas
One way to develop Marilyn Adams’s embrace of hamartiological value conflicts is to argue that
there are genuine dilemmas between conflicting hamartiological requirements that make it
practically impossible to avoid sin. After all, in her view, sin is fundamentally an immutable fact
of our natures, and prominent accounts of original sin have similar implications, so perhaps the
system of hamartiological norms reflects this metaphysical inevitability. To sketch the proposal,
suppose that hamartiological dilemmas present themselves whenever a member of one’s moral
community commits one of the many offenses defined within the Levitical holiness statutes,
making them ubiquitous in human social life.
Some hamartiological norms have been thought to be absolute, in the sense that they are
unchangeable, exceptionless, and indefeasible. Relatedly, some sins are thought to be mortal,
eternal, or unforgivable, as some have so understood blasphemy against the Holy Spirit (Mark
3:28–30; Matt 12:30–32; Luke 12:8–10), or sins that cry to Heaven for vengeance (Gen 4:10,
18:20–21; Exod 22:21–23; Deut 24:14–15). The Catechism of the Catholic Church defines mortal
sins as concerning grave matter “specified by the Ten Commandments, corresponding to the
answer of Jesus to the rich young man: “Do not kill, Do not commit adultery, Do not steal, Do not
bear false witness, Do not defraud, Honor your father and your mother” (3.1.1.8.1858), which
suggests these norms are absolute. Mortal sins must also be committed with full knowledge of the
sinful character of the act or its opposition to God’s law, and committed with consent sufficiently
deliberate to make the act a personal choice (3.1.1.8.1859).
So suppose that someone dishonors their parents, with sufficient knowledge and deliberate
consent to make it a personal choice, thereby committing a mortal sin. Furthermore, suppose (for
now) that we know that omitting to sanction someone, as prescribed, for dishonoring their parents,
constitutes complicity after-the-fact with grave sin, risking mortal sin. We can morally blame the
offender and punish them proportionately to the (typically minor to moderate) moral wrong this
offense represents. Alternatively, we can purify the community by putting the offender to death.
But we cannot do both, and we commit a mortal sin if we choose to do neither. On this proposal,
no matter which alternative we choose, we will fail to do something we all-things-considered ought
to have done, and God will count the failure sinful.
Super-Moralists are best positioned to argue that the normative demands of distinct
hamartiological kinds, with distinct aims and priorities, conflict. Indeed, Adams (1999) says the
norms of morality, purity, and honor are incongruent. But recall that even she understands the
norms of sin to have been minted by God, from lowly human conventional evaluative systems, to
create a single system of normative symbols, as a currency for facilitating divine-human relations.
So it might still seem surprising for God to create a system that places such grossly incompatible
demands on agents. On Adams’s behalf, one might respond that this is designed intentionally to
reflect, not only sin’s inevitability, but the fundamental incommensurability of the divine and
human natures. The apparent value conflicts involved in moral dilemmas have led several
philosophers to relate moral dilemmas to the incommensurability of values (Hsieh 2016), so
perhaps dishonorable, impure, and (for Moral Necessitarians, other) immoral states of affairs are
deemed sinful by God, in order to stipulate deliberately a set of normatively authoritative 62 reasons
62
For a recent overview and defense of normative authority, see Wodak 2019.
Five Problems for the Moral Consensus on Sin
18
or values that are incommensurable, creating hamartiological dilemmas that are apt symbols of the
ontological incommensurability between the divine and human natures. 63 This explanation
assumes theistic constructivism, but if realists are attracted to dilemmas, perhaps they can find
their own story to tell.
Narrowly construed, Moral Sufficiency’s extensional problems can all be solved by
accepting hamartiological dilemmas, but this solution is a double-edged sword. Maintaining Moral
Sufficiency about enacting sanctions, including capital punishments or genocide mandated as
matters of (iv) moral impurity, entails that these acts are morally permissible, only if enacting them
is sinless. Accepting hamartiological dilemmas allows the Moral Sufficientarian to say these acts
are sinful, as a matter of morality, even if sinless, as a matter of holiness. It also preserves the
Moral Sufficientarian claim that all moral faults lie within the extension of sinful acts, though some
morally obligatory acts, like refraining from killing or degrading moral innocents over matt ers of
impurity, are also brought within sin’s extension.
For Moral Necessitarians, all sins are moral faults, so accepting hamartiological dilemmas
means also accepting moral dilemmas.64 This means that intuitively morally permissible acts or
states, like (i) refraining from acts of self-sacrifice, (ii) cognitive states of unbelief in God, (iii)
conative states of hatred or lust, and (iv) ritual impurities, like leprosy, and moral impurities, like
consensual homosexual sex, really are morally permissible—good. But it means that these same
acts or states are also morally impermissible—bad. Intuitively impermissible acts, like killing or
degrading persons over matters of ritual or moral impurity, really are morally impermissible—
good. But these same acts are also morally obligatory—very bad. So while securing these good
implications for Moral Necessity may help, given the bad implications, dilemmas hardly look like
a solution.
Even for the Super-Moralist, who rejects Moral Necessity, accepting hamartiological
dilemmas means Biting the Bullet and admitting that respecting one’s moral reasons to disobey
morally problematic ordinances is a sin, and this suggests something about sin that is not obviously
less repugnant or atrocious than the original version of the problems, making (perhaps grave or
mortal) hamartiological failures out of having the minimal moral decency to not kill or demean
someone.
For theistic constructivists, hamartiological dilemmas plausibly also undermine God’s
standing to blame us for sin,65 or (as Marilyn Adams would have it) God’s standing to receive
confession for sin.66 For by making it practically impossible to avoid sin, God becomes involved
63
See M. M. Adams 1991, 21, for her discussion of how statutory sin serves this symbolic purpose.
In order to avoid the problem of deontic logical inconsistency, which arises for moral dilemmas (see McConnell
2018, §§4–5), Lemmon 1962 and Trigg 1971 argue that the existence of moral dilemmas provide count erexamples to
the M-OIC principle. As we saw in §3.2, maintaining Moral Necessity, about the sinfulness of nonvoluntary (ii)
cognitive, (iii) conative, or (iv) bodily states, represents a prima facie challenge to the M-OIC principle. One way to
meet this challenge is to say that these sins provide (additional) counterexamples to this principle. So Moral
Necessitarians about the sinfulness of nonvoluntary states have independent reason to reject a wholly general M-OIC
principle. If they are prepared to do so, they can also readily accept the existence of moral dilemmas, while avoiding
deontic logical inconsistency in the way that Lemmon and Trigg recommend.
65 For a helpful introductory discussion and defense of God’s moral standing to blame, see Todd 2018.
66 As we learned in §4.3, Marilyn Adams thinks God elevates human evaluative systems into criteria of statutory sin,
thereby involving humans in the determination of what counts as sinful, and she also argues that God does not hold
us morally responsible through the practice of blame; see footnote 59 above. So worries about God’s standing to hold
us accountable for sin need more work to get off the ground. But it is difficult to see why one should be ready to
confess as sin one’s violations of conflicting requirements of morality and uncleanness (among others, perhaps), if
neither one’s culture nor oneself, recognizes all of the relevant evaluative systems as legitimate. For if neither oneself
or one’s culture recognize all of the relevant evaluative systems as legitimate, it cannot be said that the measure you
64
Five Problems for the Moral Consensus on Sin
19
in our (statutory) sinfulness in a way that may make God complicit. After all, when a blamer is
objectionably involved in the very act for which they are condemning a blameworthy agent, the
blameworthy agent may felicitously retort: “you forced me to do it,” or “you left me with no
alternative” (Cohen 2006, 126). Similarly, God’s involvement in rigging the normative game,
would force us into a position where, through no individual fault of our own, we have no alternative
but to sin. Alternatively, the problem might be that enacting conflicting norms would betray a lack
of genuine commitment to the values underlying each norm, even though it is by these values that
God would presume to condemn sin (Todd 2018, 41). Whichever explanation we prefer for the
undermining of standing, on Adams’s picture, dilemmas would suggest a deeper normative or
legislative incompetence on God’s part, which would subvert any symbolic value God might
confer on these lowly human norms to make them genuinely authoritative hamartiological norms.
All told, these look like significant costs of accepting hamartiological dilemmas, so I think this
“solution” creates more problems than it solves. 67
6. Defeasible Sinfulness and the Pedagogical Problem of Evil
Setting aside the possibility of dilemmas, perhaps problematic hamartiological requirements
should instead be understood as having pro tanto stringency, such that they can be overridden in
some cases by countervailing considerations. 68 For example, short of meeting the conditions for
mortal sin, a sin is considered venial or pardonable in the Catechism of the Catholic Church, either
because the agent fails to be responsible in the required sense or because it violates a defeasible
or even your moral community gives is the measure you are getting from God, pace Matt 7:2. So even if God’s moral
standing to blame is not at issue in Adams’s understanding, God’s stand ing to receive confession for sin still looks to
be undermined for the same kinds of reasons as those outlined above.
67 Naturally, Christians must also ask whether Christ could live a sinless life under such conflicting normative
requirements (2 Cor 5:21; John 8:46; Heb 4:15, 7:26; 1 Pet 2:22; 1 John 3:5). John 8:1 –11 suggests he could. Wanting
to trap Jesus between the Levitical requirement of capital punishment for the grave sin of adultery and Roman law,
which generally retained for itself the right of life and death, particularly against lynch mobs (Corley 1992, 850 –851),
some of his religious opponents presented him with a woman caught in adultery. They challenged him: “the law Moses
commanded us to stone such women. Now what do you say?” In response, “Jesus bent down and wrote with his finger
on the ground. When they kept on questioning him, he straightened up and said to them, “Let anyone among you who
is without sin be the first to throw a stone at her.” And once again he bent down and wrote on the ground [the sins of
each of them].” The trap defeated, his opponents departed, and Jesus asked her: “Woman, where are the y? Has no one
condemned you?” She said, “No one, sir.” And Jesus said, “Neither do I condemn you. Go your way, and from now
on do not sin again.”
Though the text of John 8:1–11 is of dubious provenance and likely a later addition to John’s gospel, Christian
tradition has long credited the story as though it were non-apocryphal. It is also consistent with concerns for hypocrisy
ascribed to Jesus in the other canonical gospels (see Mark 7:6; Matt 6:2 –16, 7:1–5, 15:7, 22:18, 23:13–29, 24:51; Luke
6:37–42, 12:56, 13:15; cf. Ps 26:4; Sir 1:29, 32:15, 33:2), as well as John’s earlier statement that “God did not send
his Son into the world to condemn the world, but to save the world through him” (John 3:17; see also Matt 9:6).
On the Christian understanding of Jesus’ divinity, he appears to invoke his divine authority and mission to
forgive sins, rather than condemn them, offering only correction and a challenge to repent. On some theories of divine
forgiveness, God’s forbearance to mete out (deserved) penalty just is God’s forgiveness (e.g., Londey 1986, Brien
1989, or Geuras 1992; see also Warmke 2017, 6–7 of 9). But should the proper normative conditions for forgiveness,
like an apology, repentance, or a change of heart, not obtain, Jesus might alternatively exercise his divine authority to
condemn the sin at a later date, promising a future reckoning (e.g., Matt 11:20, 12:41–42; Luke 10:13–15). Thus, by
exercising his authority to forgive sins or delay God’s judgment, Jesus could dissolve any hamartiological dile mma
he might encounter, while remaining sinlessly obedient to norm(s) of sin he chose to leave intact.
68 Shea 2018 briefly considers this possibility but sets it aside, because it conflicts with his reconstruction of Aquinas’s
attempt to Recover God’s Larger Moral Purpose in commanding the Israelites to “plunder” the Egypt ians during the
Exodus, as Aquinas views the prohibition against theft as a moral absolute; see Shea 2018, 282 –283.
Five Problems for the Moral Consensus on Sin
20
hamartiological norm. So perhaps an agent’s hamartiological reasons to refrain from venial sins
can be outweighed or defeated by other considerations, including reasons to refrain from more
serious venial or mortal sins.
For illustration, suppose once again that someone dishonors their parents, with full
knowledge of the sinful character of the act, and with consent sufficiently deliberate to make it a
personal choice, thereby committing a mortal sin. We can blame the offender in proportion to the
(often minor to moderate) moral wrong the dishonor represents. Or we can purify the sin by putting
the offender to death. But it seems perverse to deem the offence minor enough to merit correction,
only to later execute the offender for the very same offense, so we ought not do both. Can our
hamartiological reasons to impose one of these sanctions defeat the pro tanto sinfulness of omitting
the other?
Intuitively, the moral reasons against killing someone over a minor or moderate moral
wrong (at least) defeat any reasons of purity to put the offender to death. Many biblical sources
also insist that the weight of hamartiological reasons to refrain from sins varies considerably with
the kind of sin (whether or not they all are, or all involve, moral reasons, as Moral Necessitarians
must insist). For example, Jesus says that some matters of the Law, including matters of justice,
mercy, and faith, are weightier and are to be given priority over minor matters of holiness, like the
tithing of spices (Matt 23:23; Luke 11:42; cf. Lev. 27:30–32; 1 Sam 15:22; Prov 21:3; Isa 1:11–
17; Hos 6:6; Mark 12:33; Matt 9:13; 12:7). Elsewhere, Jesus seems to acknowledge that demands
across these domains can genuinely conflict, requiring weightier matters to (at least) outweigh the
lesser in practical reasoning (Mark 2:23–27; Matt 12:1–8; Luke 6:1–5; cf. 1 Sam 21:1–7; Exod
29:32–33; Lev 24:5–9). So perhaps responding to hamartiological reasons in the right way does
not require a radical departure from our intuitive judgments about what we all-things-considered
have most reason to do. In that case, our reasons to hold the offender morally responsible outweigh
and defeat our reasons to purify the community by their execution.
Accepting sin’s defeasibility solves the problems of atrocity and repugnance for Moral
Necessitarians. For maintaining Moral Necessity about the sinfulness of deliberately omitting
genocide, capital punishments, and milder sanctions for offenses of (iv) ritual or moral impurity,
only entails that such disobedience is morally wrong if it is sinful. But if it is only sinful pro tanto,
the hamartiological reason to obey (or not disobey) can be defeated by our moral reasons against
committing genocide, murder, or degrading treatment of persons, the atrocious and repugnant
implications of Moral Necessity are avoided. Similarly, if other kinds of considerations, like our
mental limitations, can be weighed against the pro tanto sinfulness of defined cognitive and
conative failures, or prudential considerations and obligations to dependents weighed against the
pro tanto sinfulness of failing to make costly sacrifices, then Moral Necessity’s unfair and overdemanding implications can also be eased. Finally, if the pro tanto sinfulness of all of the above
can be outweighed or partly balanced off by other hamartiological considerations, the sinlessness
of sanctioning them will be too.69 In that case, Moral Sufficiency’s problems are also addressed.
Moral Sufficiency’s problems arise from entailing the moral permissibility of (sinlessly) sanctioning morally
faultless sins. Suppose A has some pro ta nto reason to not-φ, but A is all-things-considered justified in φ-ing, and φing involves seriously wronging someone. Some argue we are still required to (sinlessly) sanction A for φ -ing (see
e.g., de Wijze 2013 and Corvino 2015; cf. Roadevin 2019). In su ch cases, the plausibility of sanctioning A depends
on the seriousness of the wronging involved in φ-ing. For where φ-ing involves a less serious wronging, the plausibility
of sanctioning A is in doubt, and the specific problems posed above for Moral Sufficiency do not arise. On the other
hand, where φ-ing involves a serious moral wronging, φ-ing is not a morally faultless sin, but a morally serious
wronging whose sinfulness ex hypothesi is outweighed or defeated, and again the specific problems discussed a bove
do not arise. Yet, if the sinfulness of a morally serious, sanctionable wronging can be outweighed or defeated, it
presents a prima facie counterexample to Moral Sufficiency. So Moral Sufficientarians must either explain how
69
Five Problems for the Moral Consensus on Sin
21
However, if failing to sanction sins of impurity is merely sinful pro tanto, it is difficult to
imagine any case where their sinfulness would not be defeated by the moral reasons against
wrongful killing and disrespectful treatment of persons. Indeed, the weight of our moral reasons
arguably trump any amount of considerations for impurity (Griffin 1986; cf. Hsieh 2016). So
defeasibility obviates the need to identify these offences of impurity as “sins” in the first place, let
alone mandate sanctions like indiscriminate genocide or capital punishment. At first, this may look
like the right result, but it imposes a significant explanatory burden on any account of sin and a
further explanatory burden on parties to the Moral Consensus.
6.1 Reinterpreting God’s Intent with Defeasible Sinfulness
One might be tempted to adapt sin’s defeasibility in service to the second strategy of Reinterpreting
God’s Intent. For instance, Augustine argues for a purely theoretical interpretation of these kinds
of ordinances: “Those things, again, whether only sayings or whether actual deeds, which appear
to the inexperienced to be sinful, and which are ascribed to God, or to men whose holiness is put
before us as an example, are wholly figurative, and the hidden kernel of meaning they contain is
to be picked out as food for the nourishment of charity” (2020, III.12).70 Thus, in order to deny
that the problematic passages contain genuine divine commands and permissions, one could argue
that, interpreted defeasibly, these morally problematic passages are emptied of their seemingly
objectionable normative content, and then provide some justification for their faux-identification
as sanctionable “sins.” But this last step presents a significant challenge.
The relevant ordinances take the form of general hamartiological principles ordained by
God (and therefore, general moral principles, per Moral Necessity), so if they are purely figurative,
they are also dangerously misleading. After all, the Hebrew scriptures depict the Israelites as
having complied with the ordinances for capital punishment and genocide on several occasions.
For example: “Then Israel made a vow to the Lord and said, “If you will indeed give this people
into our hands, then we will utterly destroy their towns.” The Lord listened to the voice of Israel,
and handed over the Canaanites; and they utterly destroyed them and their towns ...” (Num 21:2–
3; cf. Josh 6:21; 10:20; 11:11). As Wes Morriston (2012) reports, “The consensus of mainstream
biblical scholarship is that the genocides did not take place as described in the biblical texts … but
this does nothing to remove the moral problem … divinely mandated genocide is included in a
founding story that the ancient Israelites told themselves— a story that has helped to shape the
theological traditions of both Jews and Christians” (119). 71 These theological traditions, in turn,
shape the moral understandings of their adherents, and they present these general
hamartiological/moral principles as having been obeyed by exemplars of their faith.
serious, sanctionable wrongings can be morally faultless in such cases (so as not to be sufficient for sin) or deny the
possibility of such cases (e.g., by insisting that hamartiological norms against the relevant kinds of serious wrongs are
absolute, not defeasible). My thanks to Jonathan Quong for pressing me on this point.
70 A purely theoretical interpretation of the ordinance of capital punishment for a stubborn and rebellious son (Deut
21:18 –21) is similarly contemplated in the Talmud, where it is stated that “It never happened and it never will happen”
and that the law was given merely “that you may study it and receive reward” (i.e., for pure study; Tosef., Sanh. 11:6;
Sanh. 71a). The Mishnah (Mak. 1:10; Mak. 7a) also says that a Sanhedrin court that orders the death penalty once in
seven years (or once in seventy years, according to Rabbi Eleazer b. Azariah) is considered murderous or bloody,
while Rabban Simeon b. Gamaliel opines that one passing no death sentences at all would only multiply murderers in
Israel. See Cohn, Rabinowitz, and Elon 2008, 447.
71 Morriston includes several representative statements from biblical scholars in a footnote; see Morriston 2012, 119,
n. 7.
Five Problems for the Moral Consensus on Sin
22
As a result, the Talmud records continued court-ordered executions for offenses of
impurity, including the stoning of a man for Sabbath-breaking (Sanh. 46a), the burning alive of a
priest’s daughter for adultery (Sanh. 7:2), and extra-judicial killings are also recorded, including
the hanging of eighty women in Ashkelon for witchcraft (Cohn, Rabinowitz, and Elon 2008; Sanh.
6:4, cf. Lev 19:31; 20:27; Sanh. 46a). We also know, from work on the philosophy of religious
trauma, that these ordinances continue to be used to rationalize comparatively lesser atrocities like
child abuse and the indoctrination of traumatic religious beliefs. Consider, for example, this
factually inspired case discussed by Michelle Panchuk (2018):
A young child is repeatedly and brutally beaten by her Christian parents. She is told
that since God commanded the Israelites to stone their rebellious children, anything
they do to her short of that is divinely approved and morally deserved. And she
believes them. One night, they lock her out of the house as punishment for some
misdeed. Sitting alone, bruised and bleeding, gazing at the stars, the girl has an
overwhelming sense of the presence of God—a presence utterly terrifying because
she perceives it to be of a being who delights in her suffering (514). 72
When you are among the victims of the misinterpretation and misapplication of these ordinances,
the Augustinian claim, that God did not intend for them to be understood that way, rings hollow.
These victims understandably ask “why does God care so little for me that God said this, knowing
I would be the collateral damage of those who dared to think God actually meant what God said?”73
Thus, even if the learned opinion among Jewish and Christian scholars is that these
ordinances were rarely or never to be applied in practice, by taking the form of general
hamartiological and perhaps moral principles, they enjoin misunderstanding and misapplication.
Mitchell opines that it is natural for the deeply religious "to confuse a sense of their inadequacy as
finite creatures before the infinite glory of God with the guilt that properly accompanies only moral
failure. The sense of finitude in morally sensitive people who are also religious inclines them to
assume moral guilt where none can reasonably be imputed” (1984, 166). But if this kind of
confusion is natural, God’s authorship of these ordinances is all the more problematic.
Without the benefit of foreknowledge, at best, God would be culpably negligent to lay
down faux-moral ableist, misogynistic, homophobic, and xenophobic sanctions, including death
penalties and genocide, for God would be knowingly misleading sincere submissive devotees—
naturally inclined to confuse their sense of what is inadequate or their aesthetic sense of impurity
for moral failings—to commit (mass) murder and other moral evils, on the basis of reasons
constructed to appear normatively authoritative and overriding of other considerations. With the
benefit of foreknowledge, God is complicit in every gratuitous death and lesser evil meted out in
obedience to these faux-commands and exercise of these faux-permissions. Even in the knowledge
that (eventually) intelligent people will discover their limited or empty practical import and
discover their deeper theological meanings, given more straightforward pedagogical alternatives,
God would be sacrificing lives and allowing suffering without sufficient justification. For any
As Panchuk explains in a footnote: ”Although this case is fictional, it is inspired by a narrative offered anonymously
at Homeschoolers Anonymous. Being personally acquainted with the author, I can speak for the veracity of the story
and have gotten permission to use an adaptation of it in this context” (see Mary 2013). Panchuk 2019 reports similar
experiences of her own: “Mine were the vain attempts to find jo y in submitting to abuse inflicted in the name of God,
the name of the cross, the name of the atoning Christ. When the cross is what you deserve, anything short of that is
“grace.” So I listen to defenses of penal substitution and vicarious punishment with shaking hands, racing heart, and
tears welling in my eyes (69).
73 My thanks to Kenny Pearce and especially Michelle Panchuk for their very helpful discussion of this point.
72
Five Problems for the Moral Consensus on Sin
23
resulting evils would have to be justified by appeal to the value of the spiritual food to which
Augustine appeals, and the value of this spiritual food, limited by its convoluted method of
delivery, is just not plausibly of comparable value to the lives lost and suffering inflicted by its
convoluted method of delivery. So accepting sin’s defeasibility, in service to the second strategy
of Reinterpreting God’s Intent, looks untenable, because it invites a potent version of the evidential
problem of apparently gratuitous evils, arising from God’s own moral misguidance: a pedagogical
problem of evil.
6.2 Rejecting God’s Authorship with Defeasible Sinfulness
Alternatively, one could adapt Morriston’s argument that moral correction runs in both directions
between the believer and the scriptures:
Sometimes, reflecting on a particular passage may bring us up short and help us to
see something new. At other times, our moral intuitions (themselves partly formed
by reflecting on Scripture) may give us good reason for making a negative ethical
judgment about a particular text. As we struggle with the texts, we may learn from
them; but we may also have to pass judgment on them. … [and if] we engage in
ethical criticism of the genocide texts, we are continuing a process begun by the
biblical authors themselves (2012, 134).74
Following this model, one could argue that the scriptural bases for accepting defeasible sinful-ness
are best interpreted as reasons to Reject God’s Authorship of those problematic commands and
permissions seemingly trumped by commonsense moral considerations. Indeed, Morriston himself
contends that the genocide passages provide us with strong prima facie reasons to reject claims of
their authoritative inspiration by God, and having been unconvinced by arguments against
Rejecting God’s Authorship (2009) and attempts to Recover God’s Larger Moral Purposes in the
genocide passages (2012), Morriston concludes that God did not in fact command genocide. So
one could extend this argument, Rejecting God’s Authorship of more or all of the problematic
ordinances discussed above.
But this still implies that, however natural their mistakes, God’s people have dangerously
misled one another at a deeper level, with respect to the inspiration, authority, and reliability not
only of their core canonical scriptures but of God’s moral guidance of their communities, so that
at least many of them have been complicit in gratuitous killings and lesser moral evils, whether
meted out in zealous obedience to faux-commands, or tolerated in deference to faux-permissions.
So while defeasible sinfulness seems well-motivated, solves the problems of atrocity and
repugnance, and eases the problems of over-demandingness and agential unfairness, for Moral
Necessitarians and Sufficientarians alike, if it is employed to Reject God’s Authorship of
problematic ordinances related to sin, it leaves the rejected ordinances no less misleading. And
while denying their divine authority undercuts their dangerousness going forward, it lays their
gratuitous historical consequences at the feet of complicit religious communities and perhaps God
as well. Therefore, this version of the first strategy cannot succeed on its own without some effort
to explain God’s larger purposes.
74 Morriston assumes here that moral intuition can reliably inform our judgments about what really is or is not sinful,
but for anyone who rejects Moral Necessity, this is not a safe assumptio n. To adapt Morriston’s argument, absent the
assumption of Moral Necessity, one must identify suitable analogues to moral intuition (themselves also partly formed
by reflection on scripture), including, perhaps, aesthetic intuition; see especially chapter 7 of M. M. Adams 1999.
Five Problems for the Moral Consensus on Sin
24
6.3 Recovering God’s Larger Purposes with Defeasible Sinfulness?
Christian thinkers may still decide to embrace the defeasibility of pro tanto sinfulness as part of a
solution to one or more of the four extensional problems discussed in this paper, but they if do,
they owe us an explanation for why God has allowed morally misleading ordinances about sin to
drastically misshape the behavior of believers and warp their understandings of God’s will. Parties
to the Moral Consensus must further explain how this is compatible with their commitment(s) to
Moral Necessity or Moral Sufficiency. But it is not obvious these moralistic commitments are
compatible with the recognition that God has allowed core teachings about sin to morally mislead
believers so badly. If moral fault really is necessary or sufficient for sin to obtain, why does the
prevention of moral fault not impose a more effective constraint on Judeo-Christian teachings
about sin itself? Is there a way to Recover God’s Larger Purposes for allowing such moral
misguidance, while preserving God’s standing to hold us accountable for moral faults in the way
that Moral Necessity or Moral Sufficiency imply? These are difficult questions, which we cannot
answer here. For now, we should recognize that hefty explanatory burdens await those who appeal
to sin’s defeasibility to resolve the four extensional problems discussed in this paper.
7. Conclusions
In this paper, we have seen that nearly all Christian thinkers defend, or at least assume, some kind
of close extensional relationship between sin and moral fault: all sins are moral faults, all moral
faults are sins, or all the above. So there is a “Moral Consensus” around the disjunction of Moral
Necessity or Moral Sufficiency. Despite substantive disputes about what counts as sin in the Bible,
we have also seen that maintaining Moral Necessity or Moral Sufficiency about the biblical
catalogue of sins creates four problems: (1) moral over-demandingness, (2) agential unfairness,
(3) moral repugnance, and (4) moral atrocity. After surveying some partial solutions suggested in
the recent philosophical literature, I considered two largely unexplored general solutions, available
to all parties in the Moral Consensus: (a) genuine hamartiological dilemmas, and (b) the
defeasibility of pro tanto sinfulness. I showed that while much can be said for both solutions,
dilemmas create more problems than they solve.
However, defeasible sinfulness seems especially well-motivated, solves the problems of
moral atrocity and repugnance, and eases the problems of over-demandingness and agential
unfairness, for Moral Necessitarians and Moral Sufficientarians alike. So it is clearly an attractive
solution to the problems we have identified, and one worthy of further consideration. Yet, even if
the defeasibility of pro tanto sinfulness is embraced as part of a solution to these problems,
Christian thinkers owe us an explanation for why God has allowed morally misleading ordinances
about sin to drastically misshape the behavior of believers and warp their understandings of God’s
will. For parties to the Moral Consensus, any such explanation must remain compatible with their
commitment(s) to Moral Necessity or Moral Sufficiency. But it is not obvious these moralistic
commitments are compatible with the recognition that God has allowed core teachings about sin
to morally mislead believers so badly. If moral fault really is necessary or sufficient for sin to
obtain, why has its prevention not imposed a more effective constraint on Judeo-Christian
teachings about the very topic of sin? Is there a way to resolve this pedagogical problem of evil,
while preserving God’s standing to hold us accountable for moral faults, as Moral Necessity or
Moral Sufficiency imply? These are difficult questions, which we cannot answer here. For now,
we should recognize that hefty explanatory burdens await those who appeal to sin’s defeasibility
to resolve the extensional problems discussed in this paper. So while a number of theologians and
Five Problems for the Moral Consensus on Sin
25
philosophers have opposed what they take to be overly moralizing approaches to the doctrine of
sin, insofar as they remain party to the Moral Consensus about sins, they may need to consider a
more radical separation of sin and moral fault.75
References
Adams, Marilyn McCord. 1988. “Theodicy Without Blame.” Philosophical Topics 16 (2): 215–
245. doi: 10.5840/philtopics198816220.
---. 1991. “Sin as Uncleanness.” Philosophical Perspectives 5, Philosophy of Religion: 1–27. doi:
10.2307/2214089.
---. 1999. Horrendous Evils and the Goodness of God. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Adams, Robert Merrihew. 1985. “Involuntary Sins.” The Philosophical Review 94 (1): 3–31. doi:
10.2307/2184713.
---. 1987. “Divine Commands and the Social Nature of Obligation.” Faith and Philosophy 4 (3):
262–275. doi: 10.5840/faithphil19874343.
Augustine. 397–426. “On Christian Doctrine, in Four Books.” In Christian Classics Ethereal
Library. Last accessed July 15, 2020: https://ccel.org/ccel/augustine/doctrine/.
Attfield, David G. 1984. “The Morality of Sins.” Religious Studies 20 (2): 227–237.
Basu, Rima. 2018. “Can Beliefs Wrong?” Philosophical Topics 46 (1): 1–17. doi:
10.5840/philtopics20184611.
Basu, Rima; and Mark Schroeder. 2019. “Doxastic Wronging.” In Pragmatic Encroachment in
Epistemology, edited by Brian Kim and Matthew McGrath. Routledge: 181–205.
Bayle, Pierre. 1965 (1686–1687). “Commentaire philosophique sur ces paroles de Jesus-Christ,
‘Contraine-les d’entrer’.” In Oeuvres Diverses, Volume 2. Olms.
Bergmann, Michael; Michael J. Murray; and Michel C. Rea. 2011. “Introduction.” In Divine
Evil: The Moral Character of the God of Abraham, edited by Michael Bergmann,
Michael J. Murray, and Michael C. Rea. Oxford University Press: 1–21.
Blidstein, Moshe. 2017. Purity, Community, and Ritual in Early Christian Literature. Oxford
University Press. doi: 10.1093/oso/9780198791959.001.0001.
75 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS: I wish to thank Ralph Wedgwood, Jonathan Quong, an anonymous referee for Religious Studies,
and an anonymous referee for the Journal of Analytic Theology for their extensive comments on earlier versions of
this paper. I am also grateful to Mark Schroeder, Michelle Panchuk, Kenny Pearce, Alida Liberman, Erik Encarnacion,
Leigh Vicens, Lorraine Street, Maegan Fairchild, and Renee Jorgensen for helpful conversations and suggestions
along the way. Finally, I want to thank the participants of the 2019 SLU Graduate Student Conference, especially my
commentator, James Dominic Rooney, as well as participants in the 4th Theistic Ethics Workshop, and audiences at
the 2018 meeting of the Canadian Society of Christian Philosophers, and the 2017 meeting of the Atlantic Region
Philosophers’ Association, for their comments and discussions o f earlier related work.
Five Problems for the Moral Consensus on Sin
26
Bonhoeffer, Dietrich. 1995 (1949). Ethics, translated by Neville Horton Smith and edited by
Eberhard Bethge. Simon and Schuster.
Borg, Marcus J. 1987. Jesus, a New Vision: Spirit, Culture, and the Life of Discipleship. Harper
& Row.
---. 1994. Jesus in Contemporary Scholarship. Valley Forge, PA: Trinity Press International.
Brien, Andrew. 1989. “Can God Forgive us our Trespasses?” Sophia 28 (2): 35–42. doi:
10.1007/BF02789857.
Brunner, Emil. 1957 (1939). Man in Revolt: A Christian Anthropology. Olive Wyon (Trans.)
Lutterworth.
Buchanan, George W. 1970. The Consequences of the Covenant. Brill.
Büchler, Adolf. 1928. Studies in Sin and Atonement in the Rabbinic Literature of the First
Century. Oxford University Press.
Catholic Church. 2012. “The Gravity of Sin: Mortal and Venial Sin.” In Catechism of the
Catholic Church (Second Edition) (1854–1864). Libreria Editrice Vaticana. Last
accessed July 15, 2020: http://www.vatican.va/ archive/ENG0015/__P6C.HTM.
Coady, C. A. J. 2012. “Moralism and Anti-Moralism: Aspects of Bonhoeffer’s Christian Ethic.”
Sophia 51 (4): 449–464. doi: 10.1007/s11841-012-0340-2.
Cohen, Gerald A. 2006. “Casting the First Stone: Who Can, and Who Can’t, Condemn the
Terrorists?” Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 58: 113–136. doi:
10.1017/S1358246106058061.
Cohn, Haim Hermann; Louis Isaac Rabinowitz; and Menachem Elon. 2008. “Capital
Punishment.” In Encyclopaedia Judaica, Volume 4 (Second Edition), edited by Michael
Berenbaum and Fred Skolnik. Macmillan Reference USA in association with the Keter
Publishing House: 445–451.
Corley, Bruce. 1992. “Trial of Jesus.” In Dictionary of Jesus and the Gospels, edited by Joel B.
Green, I. Howard Marshall, and Scot McKnight. InterVarsity Press: 841–854.
Corvino, Fausto. 2015. “Punishing Atypical Dirty Hands.” International Journal of Applied
Philosophy 29 (2): 281–297. doi: 10.5840/ijap201612755.
Couenhoven, Jesse. 2009. “What is Sin? A Differential Analysis.” Modern Theology 25 (4):
563–587. doi: 10.1111/j.1468-0025.2009.01555.x.
Dalferth, Ingolf. 1984. “How Is the Concept of Sin Related to the Concept of Moral
Wrongdoing?” Religious Studies 20 (2): 175 –189.
de Wijze, Stephen. 2013. “Punishing ‘Dirty Hands’—Three Justifications.” Ethical Theory and
Moral Practice 16 (4): 879–897. doi: 10.1007/s10677-012-9396-x.
Five Problems for the Moral Consensus on Sin
27
Douglas, Mary. 2002 (1970). Purity and Danger: An Analysis of the Concepts of Pollution and
Taboo. Routledge Classics.
Frymer-Kensky, Tivka. 1983. “Pollution, Purification, and Purgation in Biblical Israel.” In The
Word of the Lord Shall Go Forth: Essays in Honor of David Noel Freedman in
Celebration of His Sixtieth Birthday, edited by Carol L. Meyers and M. O’Connor.
Eisenbrauns: 399–410.
García Martínez, Florentino. 1995. “The Problem of Purity: The Qumran Solution.” In The
People of the Dead Sea Scrolls: Their Writings, Beliefs, and Practices, edited by
Florentino García Martínez and Julio Trebolle Barrera. Brill: 139–157.
Gavin, Frank. 1928. The Jewish Antecedents of the Christian Sacraments. Society for Promoting
Christian Knowledge.
Geuras, Dean. 1992. “In Defense of Divine Forgiveness: A Response to David Londey.” Sophia
31 (1–2): 65–77. doi: 10.1007/BF02772354.
Griffin, James. 1986. Well-Being: Its Meaning, Measurement and Importance. Clarendon Press.
Haber, Susan. 2008. “Part I: Bibliographic Studies.” In They Shall Purify Themselves: Essays on
Purity in Early Judaism, edited by Adele Reinhartz. Society of Biblical Literature: 7–71.
Harrington, Hannah K. 1993. The Impurity Systems of Qumran and the Rabbis: Biblical
Foundations. Scholars Press.
Hayes, Christine. 2002. Gentile Impurities and Jewish Identities: Intermarriage and Conversion
from the Bible to the Talmud. Oxford University Press.
---. 2007. “Purity and Impurity, Ritual.” In Encyclopaedia Judaica, Volume 16 (Second Edition),
edited by Michael Berenbaum and Fred Skolnik. Macmillan Reference USA in
association with the Keter Publishing House: 746–756.
Himmelfarb, Martha. 1999. “Sexual Relations and Purity in the Temple Scroll and the Book of
Jubilees.” Dead Sea Discoveries 6 (1): 11–36. doi: 10.1163/156851799X00027.
Hoffmann, David Z. 1905. Das Buch Leviticus, Volume 1. Berlin, DE: M. Poppelauer.
Holtz, Gudrun. 2012. “Purity Conceptions in the Dead Sea Scrolls: ‘Ritual-Physical’ and ‘Moral’
Purity in a Diachronic Perspective.” In Purity and the Forming of Religious Traditions in
the Ancient Mediterranean World and Ancient Judaism, edited by Christophe Nihan and
Christian Frevel. Brill: 519–536.
Hsieh, Nien-he. 2016. “Incommensurable Values.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
(Spring 2016 Edition), edited by Edward N. Zalta. Last accessed July 15, 2020:
https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/value-incommensurable/.
Kazen, Thomas. 2010. Jesus and Purity Halakhah: Was Jesus Indifferent to Impurity?
Pennsylvania State University Press.
Kellenberger, James. 1995. Relationship Morality. The Pennsylvania State University Press.
Five Problems for the Moral Consensus on Sin
28
Kierkegaard, Søren. 1989 (1849). The Sickness Unto Death, translated by Alastair Hannay.
Penguin Classics.
Kilcullen, John. 1983. “Antoine Arnauld Against Philosophic Sin.” Philosophy Research
Archives 9: 595–637.
Kirkpatrick, Matthew D. 2013. “Bonhoeffer, Kierkegaard, and the Teleological Suspension of
the Ethical: The Beginning or End of Ethics?” In Ontology and Ethics: Bonhoeffer and
Contemporary Scholarship, edited by Adam C. Clark and Michael Mawson. Pickwick
Publications: 86–101.
Klawans, J. 2000. Impurity and Sin in Ancient Judaism. Oxford University Press.
Konkel, Michael. 2012. “The System of Holiness in Ezekiel’s Vision of the New Temple (Ezek
40–48).” In Purity and the Forming of Religious Traditions in the Ancient Mediterranean
World and Ancient Judaism, edited by Christophe Nihan and Christian Frevel. Brill: 429–
455.
Lein, John Elliott. 2015. “An Abomination in Leviticus 18:22.” In J. Elliott Lein. Gay Marriage
and the Bible (Self-published book manuscript). Last accessed July 15, 2020:
https://www.gaymarriageandthebible.com/an-abomination-in-leviticus-18.
Lemmon, E. J. 1962. “Moral Dilemmas.” The Philosophical Review 71 (2): 139–158.
Lewis, Charles. 1983. “Divine Goodness and Worship Worthiness.” International Journal for
Philosophy of Religion 14 (3): 143– 158. doi: 10.1007/BF00136891.
Lipinski, Edward; and Louis Jacobs. 2007. “Sin.” In Encyclopaedia Judaica, Volume 18
(Second Edition), edited by Michael Berenbaum and Fred Skolnik. Macmillan Reference
USA in association with the Keter Publishing House: 621–625.
Londey, David. 1986. “Can God Forgive us our Trespasses?” Sophia 25 (1): 4–10. doi:
10.1007/BF02912217.
Maccoby, Hyam. 1999. Ritual and Morality: The Ritual Purity System and Its Place in Judaism.
Cambridge University Press.
Malina, Bruce J. 1993. The New Testament World: Insights from Cultural Anthropology
(Revised Edition). Westminster/John Knox Press.
Mary. 2013. “Home Is Where the Hurt is: Mary’s Story,” Parts Two and Three. Homeschoolers
Anonymous. Last accessed July 15, 2020:
https://homeschoolersanonymous.net/2013/04/03/home-is-where-the-hurt-is-marys-storypart-two/ and https://homeschoolersanonymous.net/2013/04/05/home-is-where-the-hurtis-marys-story-part-three/.
McConnell, Terrance. 2018. “Moral Dilemmas” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
(Spring 2016 Edition), edited by Edward N. Zalta. Last accessed July 15, 2020:
https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/moral-dilemmas/.
Five Problems for the Moral Consensus on Sin
29
Milgrom, Jacob. 1976. “Israel’s Sanctuary: The Priestly Picture of Dorian Gray.” Revue Biblique
83: 390–399.
Miller, Christian. 2018. “What Should Theists Say about Constructivist Positions in
Metaethics?” In Religious Ethics and Constructivism: A Metaethical Inquiry, edited by
Kevin Jung. Routledge: 82–103.
Mitchell, Basil. 1984. “How Is the Concept of Sin Related to the Concept of Moral
Wrongdoing?” Religious Studies 20 (2): 165–173.
Moore, George F. 1919. The History of Religion, Volume 2. Charles Scribner’s Sons.
Morriston, Wes. 2009. “Did God Command Genocide? A Challenge to the Biblical Inerrantist.”
Philosophia Christi 11 (1): 7–26.
---. 2012. “Ethical Criticism of the Bible: The Case of Divinely Mandated Genocide.” Sophia 51:
117–135. doi: 10.1007/s11841-011-0261-5.
Neusner, Jacob. 1973. The Idea of Purity in Ancient Judaism. Brill.
Newton, Michael. 1985. The Concept of Purity at Qumran and in the Letters of Paul. Cambridge
University Press. doi: 10.1017/CBO9780511555022.
Neyrey, Jerome H. 1986. “The Idea of Purity in Mark’s Gospel.” Semeia 35: 91–128.
Niebuhr, H. Richard. 1935. “Man the Sinner.” The Journal of Religion 15 (3): 272–280.
Niebuhr, K. P. Reinhold. 1943. The Nature and Destiny of Man, Volume I: Human Nature.
Nisbet & Co.
Nihan, Christophe. 2012. “Forms and Functions of Purity in Leviticus.” In Purity and the
Forming of Religious Traditions in the Ancient Mediterranean World and Ancient
Judaism, edited by Christophe Nihan and Christian Frevel. Brill: 311–367.
O’Neil, Arthur Charles. 1912. “Sin.” In The Catholic Encyclopedia, Volume 14. New York:
Robert Appleton Company. Last accessed July 15, 2020:
http://www.newadvent.org/cathen/14004b.htm.
Otto, Rudolf. 1958. The Idea of the Holy, translated by John W. Harvey. Oxford University
Press.
Panchuk, Michelle. 2018. “The Shattered Spiritual Self: Philosophical Reflections on Religious
Trauma” Res Philosophica 95: 505–530.
---. 2019. “That We May be Whole: Doing Philosophy of Religion with the Whole Self.” In The
Lost Sheep in Philosophy of Religion: New Perspectives on Disability, Gender, Race, and
Animals, edited by Blake Hereth and Kevin Timpe. Routledge: 55–76.
Quinn, Philip L. 1978. Divine Commands and Moral Requirements. Clarendon Press.
---. 2010. “Sin and Original Sin.” In A Companion to Philosophy of Religion (Second Edition),
edited by Charles Taliaferro, Paul Draper, and Philip L. Quinn. Blackwell: 614–621.
Five Problems for the Moral Consensus on Sin
30
Rausche, Benedikt. 2012. “The Relevance of Purity in Second Temple Judaism according to
Ezra-Nehemiah.” In Purity and the Forming of Religious Traditions in the Ancient
Mediterranean World and Ancient Judaism, edited by Christophe Nihan and Christian
Frevel. Brill: 457–475
Rawls, John. 2009 (1942). “A Brief Inquiry into the Meaning of Sin and Faith.” In John Rawls:
A Brief Inquiry into the Meaning of Sin and Faith; with “On My Religion,” edited by
Thomas Nagel. Harvard University Press: 103–258.
Regev, Eyal. 2004. “Moral impurity and the temple in early Christianity in light of ancient Greek
practice and Qumranic ideology.” Harvard Theological Review 97 (4): 383–411. doi:
10.1017/S0017816004000768.
Rhoads, David M. 1992. “Social Criticism: Social Boundaries.” In Mark and Method: New
Approaches in Biblical Studies, edited by Janice Capel Anderson and Stephen D. Moore.
Fortress Press: 135–161.
Roadevin, Cristina. 2019. “To Punish or to Forgive? Responding to Dirty Hands in Politics.”
Theoria: A Journal of Social and Political Theory 66 (160): 122–142. DOI:
10.3167/th.2019.6616007.
Roberts, Erin. 2014. “Reconsidering Hamartia as “Sin” in 1 Corinthians.” Method and Theory in
the Study of Religion 26: 340 –364. doi: 10.1163/15700682-12341315.
Schroeder, Mark. 2020. “Sins of Thought.” Faith and Philosophy 37 (3): 1–21. doi:
10.37977/faithphil.2020.37.3.1.
Shea, Matthew. 2018. “Aquinas on God-Sanctioned Stealing.” American Catholic Philosophical
Quarterly 92 (2): 277–293 doi: 10.5840/acpq201831146.
Tennant, Frederick R. 1912. The Concept of Sin. Cambridge University Press.
Todd, Patrick. 2018. “Does God Have the Moral Standing to Blame?” Faith and Philosophy 35
(1): 33–55. doi: 10.5840/faithphil201811796.
Trigg, Roger. 1971. “Moral Conflict.” Mind 80 (317): 41–55.
van der Leeuw, Gerardus. 1938. Religion in Essence and Manifestation: A Study in
Phenomenology. J.E. Turner (Trans.). George Allen & Unwin.
Vicens, Leigh. 2018. “Sin and Implicit Bias.” Journal of Analytic Theology 6: 100–111. doi:
10.12978/jat.2018-6.110407210818a.
Warmke, Brandon. 2017. “Divine Forgiveness I: Emotion and Punishment‐Forbearance
Theories.” Philosophy Compass 12 (e12440): 1–9 of 9. doi: 10.1111/phc3.12440.
Werrett, Ian. 2012. “The Evolution of Purity at Qumran.” In Purity and the Forming of Religious
Traditions in the Ancient Mediterranean World and Ancient Judaism, edited by
Christophe Nihan and Christian Frevel. Brill: 493–518.
Five Problems for the Moral Consensus on Sin
31
Wodak, Daniel. 2019. “Mere Formalities: Fictional Normativity and Normative Authority.
Canadian Journal of Philosophy 49 (6): 828–850. doi: 10.1080/00455091.2018.1433795.
Wright, David P. 1991. “The Spectrum of Priestly Impurity.” In Priesthood and Cult in Ancient
Israel, edited by Gary A. Anderson and Saul M. Olyan. JSOT Press: 150–181.