11
Marx and Cinema
Angelos Koutsourakis
Classical Marxism embodied a political vision that could complete the unfinished
Enlightenment project and overcome the contradictions of modernity, the tensions
between town and country, the proliferation of poverty through the accumulation
of wealth, and the simultaneous production of development and underdevelopment.
Aesthetic modernism reacted against tradition as well as the division of labor between
artists and consumers of art that characterized bourgeois society. In prioritizing
the labor of style, modernism necessitates the labor of the reader and audience,
challenging the neat separations between art and social life putting forward the idea
of “art as material intervention.”1 The ultimate dream of modernism is its desire to
come to terms with the real by refusing its unreflective reproduction. The emergence
of cinema as an art form for the masses reliant on collective labor comes at a pertinent
time in history when modernism seeks to reclaim art as part and parcel of social life.
No other art form at the time was more suited to accomplish such a project, given that
cinema was a new art that did not require literacy skills and could thus easily address
a mass audience. As Adolf Behne wrote in 1926: “Film is something essentially new.
It is the literature of our times.”2 An art form that becomes synonymous with the new
and which can address millions of people irrespective of their educational background
would be at the forefront of the Marxist and the modernist projects.
It is not accidental that the first manifestations and theorizations of a radical and
revolutionary cinema made use of Marx’s dialectical materialism. For the Marxist
understanding of the dialectic seeks to show that what appears as unified, concrete,
and natural is the product of historically determined social conflicts and the material
connections between individuals. The Marxist dialectic is thus antithetical to an
abstractly evolutionary understanding of reality, wherein historical development
proceeds through conflicting collisions, whose synthesis generates more contradictions.
Friedrich Engels argued that the dialectic is the “science of interconnections” that
allows us to understand all social conditions as susceptible to change and not as static
and universal abstractions.3 In these terms, dialectical materialism intends to fragment
what seems to be unitary and complete, so as to reveal the historical transitoriness
of social reality and its potential for radical change. Karl Korsch has described this
dynamic, suggesting that for Marx a given socioeconomic status quo assumes the form
of “consensus” whose self-evidence is to be attributed to its capacity to conceal the
Marx and Cinema
135
social determinants that have produced it. However, the existing state of affairs faces
pressure from new social collisions that lead to further conflicts: “From a harmonious
‘consensus’ it is at a certain point transformed into a ‘dissensus.’”4
Indeed, cinema was the quintessential medium that could serve the modernist
and Marxist projects of analyzing the given state of affairs so as to envisage an
alternative modernity, not least of all because it was a mass medium that refuted the
class-laden understanding of art as the expression of cultivated taste. Film and media
historians have discussed the culture wars initiated following the emergence of the
cinema. Siegfried Zielinski explains that the advent of the new media of storage and
transmission in the nineteenth century was received with suspicion.5 The shift from
a literary to a visual mass culture posed threats to Western civilization and culture.
Similarly, Sabine Hake explains that cinema posed a threat to bourgeois culture, firstly
because it was a collective space where the masses could assemble and encounter
themselves, but also because of its reliance on technology that was at the antipodes
with the idea of art as individual creativity. We can therefore see how cinema in its
early days coincided with the modernist desire to overcome tradition, but also with the
Marxist project that aspired to enlighten the masses and do away with the conditions of
alienation in modernity. Cinema was seen as a threat because it was an art form made
for the masses. The fact that early cinema was an exhibitionist medium that did not
rely on the use of verbal language made it more approachable to the urban proletariat.
The new art form was therefore synonymous with the establishment of a working-class
culture. Noël Burch has famously suggested that the primitive mode of representation
(cinema in its early days) can be understood as a narrative and visual form influenced
by folk art such as the circus, the cabaret, and vaudeville. Early cinema privileged the
autonomy of the shot or tableau rather than narrative coherence and made use of antipsychological representational tropes. For Burch, the shift to a narrative cinema (the
institutional mode of representation) influenced by literary dramaturgy was not the
teleological development of an imperfect medium, but an industrial choice that aimed
at popularizing the new medium to the bourgeoisie of the time so as to expand its
market.6 Raymond Williams voiced a similar concern arguing that many scholars and
students “know surprisingly little about the popular theatre on which, in that phase,
it [cinema] drew so heavily. Some people still compare the new medium with such
older forms as the bourgeois novel or academic painting, when they ought really to
be looking at the direct precedents, with the same urban audiences of melodrama and
theatrical spectacle.”7 According to Williams, cinema in its early days was monitored
by the state, precisely because of its working-class appeal.
These opening remarks provide a historical hindsight to consider why the key
and still influential theorizations of a Marxist cinema did not start from countries
in the capitalist West, but in the Soviet Union, whose historical experience of
underdevelopment during the Czarist years prevented it from equating art with classladen cultivated taste. As the 1917 revolution contradicted Marx’s prediction that the
revolution would start in the industrial West, similarly it was in the same country that
the theoretical foundations of a revolutionary modernist cinema would be laid. Sergei
Eisenstein and Dziga Vertov are the two central film practitioners who formulated
136
Understanding Marx, Understanding Modernism
the key theories of political cinema that are still influential in the present. Eisenstein,
whose background was in theater, argued for a dramatic revolutionary cinema and his
influence is evident on the majority of Marxist-modernist auteurs—including those
who opposed the aesthetic of montage—such as Jean-Luc Godard, Alexander Kluge,
Straub/Huillet, Miklós Jancsó, Ousmane Sembène, Glauber Rocha, Theo Angelopoulos,
and many more. Vertov, on his part, argued for a radical experimental cinema that
does away with the theatrical tradition and his influence can be seen in the works
of late Godard, Chris Marker, Thomas Heise, Alexander Kluge, and others. Godard,
Kluge, Heise, and Harun Farocki have been equally influenced by both traditions.
Eisenstein came from the theater to the cinema and his schooling next to Vsevolod
Meyerhold was influential in his formulation of a collective dramaturgy that, not unlike
early cinema, relied on the autonomy of the tableau or shot. Meyerhold’s aesthetic of
biomechanics, his departure from the theater of the individual dramatic hero, and his
manipulation of popular art forms such as the circus, commedia dell’arte, and cabaret
had a significant impact on Eisenstein’s theory and practice. Meyerhold’s theater
reacted against the dominant naturalist tradition and proposed an episodic aesthetic
of attractions that did away with the linear drama, aiming instead to produce meaning
out of the power of associations generated by the collision of independent episodes.
Commenting on Eisenstein’s cinema he explains,
What prompted Eisenstein to divide his subject-matter into a series of attractions,
each with a carefully contrived climax? He developed the technique whilst
working at the Proletkult Theatre, but it originated when he was working with
me in my theatrical laboratory on the Novinsky Boulevard in Moscow. We were
looking for a new type of stage, free from anything which might get in the actor’s
way. Like myself, Eisenstein needs an arena, a platform, a theatre like Shakespeare’s
Globe. When interviewers question me about this stage without a stage which I am
building, I simply answer that I want an arena in which we can put on everything
from variety turns like Uberbrettl to vast spectacles of Shakespearian dimensions
like Pushkin’s Boris Godunov or Oedipus, the King. It will be possible to alternate
these productions with gymnastic displays, ballet and folkdancing, because there
will be nothing to separate the spectator from the one thing which matters—the
performer himself.8
Eisenstein inherited Meyerhold’s suspicion of naturalism and formulated a dialectical
theory of representation, which aimed at demonstrating the potential for the
construction of a counter-reality. Here the influence of Marx and Engels is obvious,
given that both argued that social reality might appear as natural and self-evident
because it cannot be understood as the unity of positive and negative forces. One
recalls the famous segment in The German Ideology (1845) where Marx and Engels
explain how the reproduction of life has a dual character since it appears as a natural
process and as a part of a broader web of social relationships. To study the social
quality of life suggests that one can understand its changeability. The crucial step for
this is to place one’s life within the context of human cooperation and consider how
Marx and Cinema
137
the productive forces affect the lives of the individuals: “Further, that the multitude of
productive forces accessible to men determines the nature of society, hence, that the
‘history of humanity’ must always be studied and treated in relation to the history of
industry and exchange.”9 Eisenstein proceeded to achieve this by means of a collective
dramaturgy that did away with the dramatic hero and psychological portraiture. In
placing the collective as the key protagonist of cinema, he aspired to instill a materialist
understanding of history and society to the audience.
In good dialectical fashion, Eisenstein’s cinema brings together pathos and reason,
so as to show in a Marxist way the connection between intellectual thinking and the
practical overthrow of the conditions of alienation. The filmmaker solicits the audience’s
emotional and rational responses by means of a synecdochic representational style that
relies on the collision of episodes rather than on their smooth succession. The fragment
is central to Eisenstein’s understanding of a dialectical representational approach that
seeks to connect the particular with the general. Peter Wollen explains that one of the
essays that had a tremendous impact on the Soviet director’s thinking was Lenin’s “On
the Question of Dialectics.” One sentence is said to have struck Eisenstein forcefully:
“In any proposition we can (and must) disclose as in a ‘nucleus’ (‘cell’) the germs of all
the elements of dialectics.” Eisenstein was able to link this to his concept of the shot
as the cell, or later, as his views grew more complex, “the molecule of montage.”10 This
is clarified in Eisenstein’s seminal essay, “A Dialectic Approach to Film Form,” where
he distinguishes his own modus operandi from that of other Soviet filmmakers, such
as Vsevolod Pudovkin, for whom montage serves mainly as a descriptive principle.
Eisenstein instead proposes a constructive understanding of montage produced by the
juxtaposition “of independent shots—shots even opposite to one another.”11 It is by
means of such a collision that a narrative advances through the conflict of contradictory
fragments that operate as clashing theses and antitheses.
One needs to recall here the famous passage from the Старое и новое (The General
Line, 1929), when the farmers test for the first time the cream separator that helps them
make butter. The sequence defies verisimilitude by being intentionally prolonged. The
camera registers a series of close-ups of the farmers looking at the machine in disbelief.
The faces are captured from a variety of angles while visuals of the separator are also
interjected. This rapid succession of visuals produces an emotional impact as well as
a sense of suspense. Interpolated intertitles ask questions whether this is progress or
deception. Eventually the camera cuts to the separator capturing its tubes, followed by
low-angle shots of the tubes and a high-angle one of the separator’s wheel juxtaposed
to the ecstatic faces of Marfa and the Party representative. A series of visuals of the
milk exploding in the air like a water fountain—interrupted again by reaction shots
of the farmers—succeed one another and the sequence culminates with the intertitles
announcing that after this successful demonstration the numbers of the cooperative
were increased.
The sequence here operates as the “cum-shot” of socialist cinema since it combines
an orgiastic aesthetic of visual excess with a rational conclusion regarding the benefits
of collective organization and labor. The sexual connotations of the scene are visibly
manifested when the separator starts spilling milk on Marfa’s hands and her face
138
Understanding Marx, Understanding Modernism
followed by visuals of the milk exploding skyward. This, however, should not be
confused as pornographic hideousness especially in light of the fact that it is Marfa
who has convinced the other farmers to invest in new technologies that can maximize
production and render their labor more effective. The sexual connotations of this
passage may well be seen as the celebration of a new life as showcased by the culmination
of the sequence that privileges the rational conclusion, namely, the success of the
cooperative experiment and its endorsement as an index of progress and development
against religious prejudice and individualist farming production. This combination of
affective engagement and rational deductions is a manifestation of Eisenstein’s desire
to make the Marxist theory of knowledge palpable and graspable by the masses and
not just an abstract theoretical exercise in style that obfuscates the practical effects of
the dialectical worldview. What this passage of the film clearly articulates is the shift
from a semi-feudalistic mode of agricultural production and labor to a socialist mode
of industrial production founded upon the principles of collaboration and collective
organization. The dialectic here is in service of demonstrating how cooperative
labor is the crucial step for the shift from a semi-feudalistic and patriarchal reality
of underdevelopment and prejudice, to a new world of development and socialist
rationality.
Unlike his previous classics, The General Line includes a key narrative agent, Marfa,
who is the one to start the cooperative. Yet, in line with his previous works such as
Стачка (Strike, 1924), Броненόсец «Потёмкин» (Battleship Potemkin, 1925), and
Октябрь (Десять дней, которые потрясли мир) (October, 1928), Eisenstein makes
use of typage, a strategy that he also got to learn while working with Meyerhold whose
typage aesthetic was influenced by commedia dell’arte. According to Eisenstein, typage
is not to be understood solely as the director’s approach to the characters, that is, the
avoidance of psychological portrayal, and the schematic depiction of them based on
their social positions, but “a specific approach to the events embraced by the content of
the film.”12 Typage thus extends beyond the depiction of characters to the ways actions
are represented as the collision between antithetical social forces and not as isolated
conflicts among autonomous individuals whose acts seem to be devoid of social
influence, as it was the case with naturalist theater against which Meyerhold reacted.
Eisenstein admitted that typage is “rooted in theater,” but cinema had the potential to
push this further thanks to its technological advancement.13
Evident in Eisenstein’s representational strategy is an awareness of the Marxist
concept of realism summarized in his and Engels’ view of the individual as “the
ensemble of the social relations” that contradicts the liberal understanding of
the individual as a free and autonomous subject who is free to make their choices
and achieve their goals irrespective of the social conditions.14 The radical aspect of
Eisenstein’s typage and montage aesthetic is precisely this capacity to dramatize social
circumstances and conditions, showing clearly the constraints placed upon individuals
by repressive regimes, but also the collective’s capacity to change these circumstances
on the condition that they understand them. The celebrated sequence in Strike where
the workers’ massacre is juxtaposed through parallel editing to the slaughtering of a
cow, as well as the renowned “For God and Country” sequence in October, and the
Marx and Cinema
139
Odessa steps passage in Potemkin are emblematic in this respect. The first and the
third put forward the brutality of the Czarist regime by means of montage effects
that combine logos and pathos; the second shows the connection between religion
and authoritarian rule by juxtaposing figurines from the Asian, Hindu, and Pacific
traditions that culminate in the reconstruction of the statue of the Czar. The collision
of thesis and antithesis here reveals how religious and patriotic rhetoric seek to divert
the proletarian’s attention from the social conditions of their oppression. Consequently,
Eisenstein’s major intervention was the theorization of a dialectical cinema, which
radically challenged the individualistic dramaturgy motivated by the nineteenthcentury theatrical traditions; he introduced a dramaturgy that viewed characters as
the products of processes taking place on a mass scale, and pointed to their capacity to
act collectively to change them. It is fair to suggest that he is the Godfather of Marxist
narrative cinema because he managed to dialectize representation by means of an
expressive mise-en-scène that enabled the coexistence of entertainment and political
critique.
Nevertheless, Eisenstein’s background was in theater and his cinema was committed
to storytelling. His stories followed the Russian formalist imperative of de-automatizing
perception so as to enable the audience in a Shklovskian way not to recognize things
but to see them differently and identify the social processes behind the narrated events.
This is the reason why it would be interesting to envisage his unrealized film on Marx’s
Capital (1867). The film, which did not materialize, can be imagined as a series of
dialectical constellations, where the key protagonists would be neither the proletariat
nor its exploiters. He envisaged it as an antiheroic film whose dramatis personae would
be the workers’ production of surplus value and all the processes that perpetuate the
capitalist mode of production. Again, the dialectical method occupies a privileged
position in his plan for the film:
In those “great days” I noted on a scrap of paper that in the new cinema, the
established place of eternal themes (academic themes of LOVE AND DUTY,
FATHERS AND SONS, TRIUMPH OF VIRTUES, etc.) will be taken by a series of
pictures on the subjects of “basic methods.” The content of CAPITAL (its aim) is
now formulated: to teach the worker to think dialectically. To show the method of
dialectics. This would mean (roughly) five nonfigurative chapters. (Or six, seven,
etc.) Dialectical analysis of historical events. Dialectics in scientific problems.
Dialectics of class struggle (the last chapter). “An analysis of a centimeter of silk
stocking.” (About the silk stocking as such, Grisha I copied out from somewhere—
the silk manufacturers’ fight for the short skirt. I added the competitors—the
textile masters’ for long skirts. Morality. Clergy, etc.) Still very complicated to
think “somehow” in “extra-thematic” imagery. But no problem . . . a viendra!15
Eisenstein repeatedly states that the film should rely on the power of associations
and start from the exploration of banal situations to move to more concrete ones,
bringing as a model example James Joyce’s Ulysses (1922). Eisenstein intended to
leave behind his theatrical influences without abandoning his commitment to the
140
Understanding Marx, Understanding Modernism
Marxist dialectic. “There are,” he states in his notes, “endlessly possible themes for
filming in CAPITAL (‘price,’ ‘income,’ ‘rent’)—for us, the theme is Marx’s method.”16
Far from being outmoded or obsolete, Eisenstein’s desire to dramatize Marx’s Capital
is pertinent in the present, at a time in history that finance capitalism obfuscates
more and more its own modus operandi, while the shift to an immaterial labor in
the capitalist West has obscured the fact that this transition is the product of the
West’s reliance on material labor outsourced to the global south and industrial semiperipheries. In these terms, Eisenstein’s vision is as relevant today as when it was
formulated in the years after 1917.
Unlike Eisenstein’s desire to dialectize representation by pushing further
experiments initiated in theater, Dziga Vertov epitomizes a filmmaking tradition
which aspired to make use of the lessons of the dialectic through a type of cinema that
was non-reliant on narrative and theatrical conventions. For Vertov, the collision of
independent sequences did not aspire to produce predetermined effects and responses.
Although his cinema was very much anchored in the principles of the dialectic, Vertov
aimed to do away with cinema’s roots in theater and argued for an experimental film
style whose dialectical effects would not be foreordained. It is a cinema committed to
the Marxist theory of knowledge as manifest through the dialectic but whose ultimate
aim is the use of the dialectic as a means of research. It is, as Annette Michelson aptly
calls it, a cinema “of epistemological inquiry.”17
Vertov’s work is also committed to a paratactic style, yet the difference is that
parataxis becomes anti-narrative and does not serve storytelling. So his modus
operandi is grounded in cinema’s capacity to capture a material reality, but in a way
that discontinuity instead of continuity is foregrounded. For Vertov, this process of
recording fragments of reality without describing it is the model for the cinema of the
future, a cinema that valorized the superiority of machinic (Kino-eye) over human
agency (the human-eye) so as to reveal processes not captured by the human. Consider,
for instance, his argument that
The history of Kino-Eye has been a relentless struggle to modify the course of
world cinema, to place in cinema production a new emphasis of the “unplayed”
film over the play-film, to substitute the document for mise-en-scene, to break out
of the proscenium of the theatre and to enter the arena of life itself.18
Literary dramaturgy erects an impediment to radical cinema’s desire to identify the
connection between visual materials and social phenomena. As he says in an essay
written in 1929, “the cinema’s chief function is the recording of documents, of facts, the
recording of life, the historical processes.”19 The refusal to accommodate preordained
narrative effects by means of dramaturgy is linked with his belief that dramaturgy
perpetuates the bourgeois understanding of art as individual creativity. Documenting
processes without commenting on them invites the audience to discover things and
phenomena not visible in everyday life. Vertov’s faith is in the power of the camera
to engage with material reality and not in the director’s individuality and creativity.
The abandonment of authorship can liberate the medium from the remnants of the
Marx and Cinema
141
bourgeois aesthetics “the poser-actor, fairy-tale script, those costly toys-sets, and the
director high-priest.”20
Underpinning Vertov’s aesthetic is the idea that the camera should not reproduce
actions but observe things objectively so as to enable the audience to discover the
social processes behind the events. This is the reason why he stressed the role of the
cameramen rather than the director. In doing so, he aimed at placing art within the
sphere of material production. The cameramen and the filmmaker are to be understood
as people who do not create but construct materials from their encounter with the
world. This is the reason why he vehemently argued in favor of “filming life unawares”
so that the people recorded by the camera would not be aware of its presence and
would be captured performing their everyday undertakings unaffectedly.21 This is
certainly the case in Человек с кино-аппаратом (Man With a Movie Camera, 1929),
where he experimented with the medium to simultaneously produce cinematic and
class consciousness through the camera’s encounter with the material reality of the new
world of the time. Attending to the details of everyday life such as births, marriages,
divorces, the working routine, and homelessness, the film is paradigmatic of Vertov’s
understanding of constructive montage, where the dialectic between observing and
recording is not necessarily synthetic. In this film, the audience is not encouraged
to reconfirm a preexisting conclusion, but to form their own. As Michelson argues,
the film “through the systematic subversion of the certitudes of illusion” proposes an
understanding of the filmmaker as an “epistemologist.”22
Vertov’s legacy in experimental political cinema and documentary has been
tremendous especially when considering the work of late Godard, Alexander
Kluge, Chris Marker, and Thomas Heise. He was a passionate advocate of artistic
experimentation against the platitudes of Socialist Realism and a firm believer that one
should not flatter but challenge the audience. As he suggested in an article published
in 1923,
One of the chief accusations leveled at us is that we are not intelligible to the masses.
Even if one allows that some of our work is difficult to understand, does that mean
we should not undertake serious exploratory work at all? If the masses need light
propaganda pamphlets, does that mean they don’t need the serious articles of
Engels, Lenin? . . . The LENIN of Russian cinema may appear in your midst today,
but you will not allow him to work because the results of his production will seem
new and incomprehensible.23
Consistent with the Marxist project of radicalized enlightenment, Vertov’s work aspired
to elevate the masses and teach them a new method of thinking. At the same time,
one needs to acknowledge that with a few exceptions—Man with a Movie Camera is
an obvious one—many of his films failed to promote the cinematic vision articulated
in his manifestos and writings. Films like Шагай, Совет! (Stride Soviet, 1926) and
Энтузиазм: Симфония Донбасса (Enthusiasm, 1930) produced undialectical results
that did not comply with the filmmaker’s desire to observe reality without describing
it. The first, for example, shows through the use of parallel editing the progress of the
142
Understanding Marx, Understanding Modernism
Soviet Union following the end of the civil war, so as to affirm the superiority of the
present over the past. The dialectic here is devoid of complexity. Equally problematic
is the reproduction of the Stalinist mottos of the five-year plan in Enthusiasm that
deprive the film of any dialectical complexity especially in its depiction of labor at the
time. Even key aspects of his aesthetic, such as filming life unawares, are visibly absent
since the workers in the film seem to be very conscious of the camera’s presence; it is
fair to suggest that the filming approach is not one of construction, but of reproduction,
possibly a product of the pressures artists faced during the Stalinist years.24 One also
needs to point out how many of his aesthetic approaches can be easily assimilated by
the market, especially in the current reality of image saturation. To this, one should add
that excessive abstraction can lead to indifference rather than political enlightenment.
On these grounds, Viktor Shklovsky was one of the first to call Vertov’s project into
question:
Cine-eye and the whole “kinoki” movement do not want to understand the
essence of cinema. Their eyes are placed unnaturally far from their brains.
They don’t understand that cinema is the most abstract of all arts, close in its
essence to certain mathematical devices. Cinema needs action and meaningful
movement the way literature needs words, the way a painting needs semantic
meaning. Without it, the spectator becomes disoriented; his view loses direction.
In painting, shadows are a convention, but they can only be replaced by another
convention. Cinema needs to accumulate conventions, they’ll work the way case
endings work in language. The primary material of cinema is not the object, but
a particular way of filming it.25
Similarly, Eisenstein famously suggested that “I don’t believe in kino-eye, I believe
in kino-fist” although he later praised Vertov for having invented “musical rhythm
in cinema.”26 These criticisms cannot be easily dismissed, especially if the Marxist
utopian dream is to use cinema as a public sphere that can change collective perception
by means of logical and emotional persuasion. At the same time, Vertov’s writings
prefigure Godard’s argument that artistic and theoretical experimentation can have
equal importance as the class struggle itself and Vertov was undoubtedly one of the
film practitioners who broke ground in this respect.
It will be worth recalling that modernist art negates the old so as to affirm the
singularity of the present and the urgency to place art within the context of material
production. This desire to simultaneously negate the old and construct something
new links modernism with a manifesto culture initiated by Marx and Engels. Martin
Puchner has described the Communist Manifesto’s (1848) influence on avant-garde
manifestos of the twentieth century. He argues that political modernism and the
avant-garde absorb the style and the form of the Manifesto and its combination of
aphoristic, political, and poetic modes of expression. This is verified not only by the
furious reproduction of manifestos on the part of modernism and the avant-garde but
also by the eccentric styles of these manifestos and their longing for intervening in
what they consider a moment of crisis. As Puchner says, “the avant-garde manifesto is
Marx and Cinema
143
unthinkable without the genre-producing force of Marx and Engels’ text, its translations
and adaptations. The emergence and breathtaking proliferation of art manifestos
rival the proliferation of the Manifesto itself.”27 The polemical force that characterizes
modernist literary and artistic manifestos is also evident in the manifestos of politically
invested modernist cinema. The influence of the Manifesto on these is an area that
remains relatively unexplored considering the majority of these texts openly use
Marxist terms and rhetoric to envisage the emergence of a new cinema that can shake
the cinematic institution and enlighten its audience; the spectators envisaged by these
manifestos are like the proletariat of the Manifesto: they are a collective subject under
construction whose emergence is envisioned as the dialectical other to the emergence
of a new cinema.
Eisenstein’s 1925 manifesto “The Method of Making Workers’ Films” is a good
case in point. In it, Eisenstein contends the importance of the cinema of attractions
as the route to the making of useful and socially engaged films that can instill class
consciousness. This manifesto is significant because it clearly sets forth the need to
produce films that employ affective stimulation as a means of producing political
enlightenment. It also suggests that political cinema must acknowledge the nonhomogeneity of the audience even when it comprises members of the working class,
for different types of workers react differently to artistic experiments rendering many
of the desired political effects innocuous. One of the examples he brings forward is
the famous slaughter sequence in Strike that failed to affect peasants for whom animal
slaughter is part of their working routine. The modernist desire to encounter the real
in its material complexity is aptly articulated in Cesare Zavattini’s 1953 manifesto of
neorealism, “Some Ideas on the Cinema,” which proceeds to differentiate the postwar
Italian cinema from Hollywood’s illusionism by explaining that whereas the latter
turns a blind eye to the complexities of everyday reality, neorealism is concerned with
capturing the contradictions of reality as manifested in its raw and unembellished
state. Indeed, the characters of neorealism are not the exceptional dramatis personae of
commercial cinema but everyday people; this corresponds with Marx and Engels, for
whom history is not to be produced by gifted individuals and party leaders, but by the
international proletariat.28 Jean-Luc Godard’s 1970 manifesto “What Is to Be Done?” is
wholly in keeping with this standpoint. The title is a direct reference to Lenin and the
text itself is preoccupied with a desire to explore how making films politically differs
from making political films, and yet the text also makes clear that the latter cannot
exist without the former. In other words, Godard’s manifesto demonstrates how a
militant type of cinema counters its bourgeois past, but is at the same time reliant on
it in order to overcome it.29
An analogous approach can be seen in the manifestos of Third Cinema, a
film movement that explicitly sees its cinema as a direct response to conditions of
underdevelopment in the global south. Fernando Solanas and Octavio Gettino’s
1969 manifesto “Towards a Third Cinema: Notes and Experiences for the Development
of a Cinema of Liberation in the Third World” is a good case in point. Reacting
against economic, political, and cultural imperialism, the premise of this argument
is that the imposition of conditions of dependency in colonized countries produces
144
Understanding Marx, Understanding Modernism
an image of cultural inferiority. The structures of economic exploitation on the
part of the colonizers obfuscate the conditions of economic and political exploitation
of the peripheral countries. Paraphrasing Marx and Engel’s famous formulation in the
Communist Manifesto that the bourgeoisie creates an image of the world out of its
own image, Solanas and Gettino imply that the colonizers produce a reality structured
around their own imperialist historical experience. In effect, the task of the Third
Cinema filmmakers is to produce a revolutionary cinema that cannot just deconstruct
but also destroy the images that neocolonialism has produced of itself and of the
colonized people. It is striking here, the rhetoric of construction through destruction
that chimes neatly with the modernist and avant-garde manifestos of the twentieth
century, and also with the Communist Manifesto to which Solanas and Gettino allude.
These parallels have to do with the polemical form of the Third Cinema Manifesto
whose ultimate aim is the production of a cinema that radically questions the cinematic
institution of the world-system, destroys the cinematic images of colonialism and
neocolonialism, and entails a radical critique of the ways capitalism reproduces itself
in noncoercive ways through the power of its cinematic institution. It is, therefore, not
coincidental that the new cinema proposed is directly linked with the class struggle,
anti-colonialism, and dialectical enlightenment as formulated in a direct reference to
Marx: “there is no knowledge of a reality as long as that reality is not acted upon, as
long as its transformation is not begun on all fronts of struggle.”30
As these and other manifestos suggest, Marx’s influence on filmmakers across
the world committed to the modernist project has been indispensable and needs to
be rediscovered, rethought, and reexamined. Now that discussions of politics and
representation have returned with a vengeance—following scholars’ apolitical dalliance
with postmodernist clichés and a kind of identity politics that was more an index of
neoliberal fragmentation rather than political critique—the relationship between
Marx and modernism merits revisiting and can inspire new ways of thinking about
cinema and politics. The skeptics could interject that cinema has now lost its cultural
force and that modernism has been deradicalized, becoming part of the institution it
once criticized. The truth, however, is that audiovisual representation can only become
political on the basis that it addresses a collective audience as opposed to isolated
individuals binging on films and series alone on their couches, as is encouraged by
the current on-demand culture. Similarly, modernist cinema’s desire to render reality
strange was never more pertinent than in the present, when the plethora of audiovisual
objects and choices has not led to the development of audiovisual literacy but its
opposite. The study of Marxist-modernist cinema can provoke the types of questions
that enable us to reconsider the impermanence and changeability not only of the world
in which we live but also of the type of cinema with which we engage.
Notes
1 Terry Eagleton, “Capitalism, Modernism and Post-Modernism,” New Left Review 152
(1985): 61.
Marx and Cinema
145
2 Adolf Behne, “The Public’s Attitude toward Modern German Literature,” in The
Promise of Cinema: German Film Theory, 1907–1933, eds. Anton Kaes, Nicholas
Baer, and Michael Cowan (Berkeley: California University Press, 2016), 393.
3 Engels, Dialectics of Nature, trans. Clemens P. Dutt (London: Lawrence and Wishart,
1946), 26.
4 Karl Korsch, Karl Marx (Boston, Leiden: Brill, 2016), 135.
5 Siegfried Zielinski, Audiovisions: Cinema and Television as Entr’actes in History,
trans. Gloria Custance (Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press, 1999), 16.
6 Noël Burch, “Porter, or Ambivalence,” Screen, 19.4 (1978): 91–106.
7 Williams, Politics of Modernism: Against the New Conformists (London: Verso, 2006),
110.
8 Vsévolod Meyerhold, Meyerhold on Theatre, ed. Edward Braun (New York:
Bloomsbury, 2016), 327.
9 Marx, “The German Ideology,” 157.
10 Peter Wollen, Readings and Writings: Semiotic Counter Strategies (London: Verso,
1982), 47.
11 Sergei Eisenstein, Film Form: Essays in Film Theory, ed. and trans. Jay Leyda
(London and New York: Harvest Book, 1977), 49.
12 Eisenstein, Film Form, 8.
13 Eisenstein, Film Form, 9.
14 Marx, “Theses on Feuerbach,” 145.
15 Eisenstein, “Notes for a Film of ‘Capital,’” October 2 (1976): 10.
16 Eisenstein, “Notes for a Film of ‘Capital,’” 23.
17 Annette Michelson, “From Magician to Epistemologist: Vertov’s The Man with a
Movie Camera,” October 162 (2017): 123.
18 Jay Leyda, Kino: A History of the Russian and Soviet Film (Liverpool, London,
Prescott: George Allen and Urwin, 1960), 176.
19 Dziga Vertov, Kino-Eye: The Writings of Dziga Vertov, ed. Annette Michelson, trans.
Kevin O’Brien (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984), 101.
20 Vertov, Kino-Eye, 71.
21 Vertov, Kino-Eye, 71.
22 Michelson, “From Magician to Epistemologist,” 132.
23 Vertov, Kino-Eye, 37–8.
24 Consider for instance Eisenstein’s troubles during Stalinism when he was
(undialectically) accused of making films deprived of individual characters by
placing too much emphasis on collective actions and processes.
25 Viktor Shklovsky, Viktor Shklovsky a Reader, ed. Alexandra Berlina (New York:
Bloomsbury, 2017), 361.
26 Wollen, Readings and Writings, 41.
27 Puchner, Poetry of the Future, 66.
28 Cesare Zavattini, “Some Ideas on the Cinema,” in Film Manifestos and Global
Cinema Cultures: A Critical Anthology, ed. Scott MacKenzie (Berkeley: University of
California Press, 2014), 126.
29 Jean-Luc Godard, “What Is to Be Done?” in Film Manifestos and Global Cinema
Cultures: A Critical Anthology, 169–70.
30 Godard, “What Is to Be Done?” 241.