.
AI
i
e e a
.
.
v
CO O RN
of ersailles in International elations
in
T e main le on
o t e
eor
i
on eren e i t at it i e ential t at t e main Po er
o ld e lear rom t e tart e a tly
ere reali m end and ideali m egin
(Harold Nicolson, 19 2)
A stra t
The legacy of Versailles is a rather well-defined and thoroughly researched area in the
discipline of History. But what did the Treaty of Versailles and the events surrounding
the peace conference give to the discipline of International Relations In order to answer
this uestion, the article first examines the place of Versailles in the foundational myths
of the discipline. After that, in the second part, it briefly reviews the most persistent and
influential ideas in IR which have emerged during the construction of the new world order
of the time, putting a special emphasis on the concept of national self-determination as
the “new master principle” of the international society after Versailles.
e
or s Versailles, IR, theory, foundational myth, liberal internationalism, national
self-determination
Intro u tion
As the 100th anniversary of the Versailles Peace Treaty is passing by, circles of historians
fondly commemorate the well-known and much recited events of the peace conference,
their background and their far-reaching conse uences. The debates and controversies
within the historiography of Versailles have been present since the very days of the
negotiations the books and studies written on the various historical perspectives,
contradictions and standpoints have filled several libraries during the past one-hundred
years (for the historiography of Versailles, see the article by Baranyi Tamás in this issue
of COJOURN). The legacy of Versailles is a rather well-defined and thoroughly
Kinga Szálkai is an assistant professor at the Department of International Relations and European Studies
at E tv s oránd University.
1
.
AI
i
.
.
v
CO O RN
researched area in the discipline of History. But what did the Treaty of Versailles and the
events surrounding the peace conference give to the discipline of International Relations
If we take a closer look at IR and its perspectives on Versailles2, we encounter
statements that may be surprising upon first glance. For example, Anievas claims that
“the theoretical significance of Versailles for IR can hardly be overstated” (Anievas,
201 : 19), but then, in the same article, he goes on to insert a footnote referring to
Randall Schweller’s (2001) observation that “there are surprisingly few substantive
studies within IR specifically examining the making of peace settlements and particularly
Versailles” (Anievas, 201 :
).
In fact, both statements are true. On the one hand, according to its most
widespread foundational myth, even the birth of IR as a discipline is inseparable from
Versailles and the surrounding controversies culminating in the signature of the peace
treaty in 1919. Although the development of the discipline was undoubtedly a longer
process, several new principles and approaches were articulated during the negotiations
concerning the new world order after WWI, which have defined IR since then. On the
other hand, the notion of Versailles and the direct references to the related events as
formative sources of IR theory are mentioned in detail only on a few occasions, especially
in the form of inserting IR-related elements in studies about the history of the peace
conference and its aftermath (e.g. Boemeke et al, 199
Smith, 201 ), and not i e er a.
In spite of its assumed significance, neither IR textbooks (e.g. Steans et al. 2010 Smith
et al., 201
Baylis et al., 201
IR theory (e.g. Carr, 19
Jackson et al., 201 ), nor canonized classical readings of
19 9
Morgenthau, 19
) refer to the treaty, the peace
conference and the conse uences in detail they only reference these sub ects in sweeping
generalisations, and treat them as self-explanatory.
The aim of this article is to shed more light on the relationship between Versailles
and the foundations of IR theory, reviewing the place and importance of the negotiations
to the discipline. In order to do so, the article first examines the place of Versailles in the
foundational myths of the discipline. After that, in the second part, it briefly reviews the
most persistent and influential ideas in IR which have emerged during the construction of
the new world order of the time, putting a special emphasis on the concept of national
In this article, the notion Versailles’ does not only refer to the Treaty of Versailles concluded with the
German Reich, or the Paris Peace Conference. Versailles’ here comprises all negotiations and
controversies which surrounded the creation of the new world order which emerged in the last years and in
the aftermath of WWI.
2
.
AI
i
.
.
CO O RN
v
self-determination as the “new master principle” of the international society after
Versailles (Osiander, 199 : 2
e
t
Anniversar of t e
).
irt of a
is i line
e la e of
ersailles in t e
oun ation of I
T e T in To er o
er aille and
ery t yt
In 2019, scholars of IR commemorate not only the centenary of the Treaty of Versailles.
The 100th anniversary of the foundation of the first university institution in International
Relations (the Woodrow Wilson Chair of International Politics at the University College
of Wales), in Aberystwyth in 1919, is another memorable event, which draws attention
to the often-emphasized fact that the closing of WWI, the Paris peace negotiations, and
the surrounding controversies were decisive elements in the establishment of IR as a
discipline, and directly led to the necessity of its institutionalisation in the academic
sphere. However, it is not possible to commemorate this symbolic turning point without
considering the extensive works of revisionist historians and IR theorists, who have
recently clarified the arbitrariness of presenting this period as the birth year (or, as its
criti ues write, the overnight’ birth de Carvalho et al., 2011:
) of the discipline.
According to its most widespread foundational myth, the need for the discipline
of IR was created by the desire to eliminate and prevent wars, and directly stemmed from
the devastating events and conse uences of WWI. In this period of time – so the myth
goes –, scholars had first turned their gaze to the international as an autonomous domain
of theoretisation on its own right (de Carvalho et al., 2011:
). In 19 9, even Carr
argued that before 191 , “nowhere, whether in universities or in wider intellectual circles,
was there organised study of current international affairs” (Carr, 19
19 9 : 1). In this
sense, the establishment of the first IR chair in Aberystwyth could not have been imagined
without the peace negotiations in Versailles, and the former was a logical conse uence of
the latter – both reinforcing the foundational myth of IR.
Carr’s statement is, however, not true. With the strengthening interest in the
history of the discipline after the end of the Cold War and the emergence of numerous
criti ues of its mainstream schools, the roots of IR have also become revisited. Research
underlined that during the last decades of the 19th century, debates about classical IRThe original expression “the twin towns of Versailles and Aberystwyth” was coined by de Carvalho et al.
(2011: 9).
.
AI
i
.
.
v
CO O RN
related issues, such as great power politics, imperialism, geopolitics and trade evolved,
while in 1
0, the first Political Science Department in the US was established at
Columbia University, dealing with the systematic study of international politics, among
others (de Carvalho et al., 2011:
). According to Schmidt, the first book that could be
ualified as IR was published two decades before the alleged birth of the discipline, in
1900, by Paul Reinsch, with the title
(Schmidt, 199 :
orld Politi
at t e nd o t e ineteent
ent ry
0). Vitalis mentions that related to the expanding colonial
administrations of the great powers, several new courses were opened at universities
which dealt with international relations. Publications on related topics were also
encouraged (Vitalis, 200 : 1
oreign
), such as the predecessor of the prestigious IR ournal
air , which was established in 1910 under the name of the o rnal o
e elo ment (de Carvalho et al., 2011:
a e
). In 192 , allegedly ust five years after the
official birth year of the discipline, a textbook with the title nternational
(written by Buell) and a collection titled Sylla
elation
on nternational elation (written by
Moon) were published, accumulating knowledge created during the previous decades
concerning war, imperialism, militaries and armaments in the international sphere
(Vitalis, 200 : 1
n t e ear ie o
), proving that IR was not in fact born overnight’ in 1919.
eali t Great e ate Great arrati e
Versailles and the surrounding controversies are also assumed to have created a turning
point that initiated the so-called First Great Debate’ between Idealism and Realism in
the 1920s–19 0s. According to the mainstream historical narrative of IR (see
uirk and
Vigneswaran, 200 : 99–10 ), this was the beginning of a line of debates which have been
forming the main views and assumptions of the emerging schools of the discipline until
today. This narrative on the Great Debates’, as revisionist historians and IR theorists
have also proved, is no less fictional than that of the birth of the discipline in 1919 –
however, it undeniably represents the nature of the development of IR in a concise form.
The history of IR was rather under-emphasized even as late as in the 19 0s–19 0s,
and discussions about the development of the discipline only went back to the time of
WWII (Donnelly, 199 : 1 1). The narrative on the Great Debates’ referring to 1919 as
the starting point of the Idealist–Realist’ divide was established as an outcome of the
dominant position of Realism in IR during the Cold War years, especially after WWII
and in the 19 0s–19 0s. IR scholars often treat history as a multitude of events on which
theories can be applied, and in their attempts to do so, they fre uently ignore where those
.
AI
i
.
events are rooted historically (Ashworth, 2002:
.
v
CO O RN
). It was not otherwise in the case of
Versailles and the surrounding controversies. In the analysis of these, Realists of the Cold
War narrowed their focus to an extreme extent to be able to discredit
iberalism and
vindicate their own theories, so as to strengthen their own dominant position within the
discipline. In the meantime, they tended to oversimplify and understate the significance
of many details of the events of the period, as it fit their narrative. The Realist narrative
of the First Great Debate’ thus emphasizes the victory of Carr, Morgenthau and Niebuhr
over the allegedly rather na ve but benevolent, legalistic-moralistic’ idealists of Wilson,
Angell and Zimmern, who supported ideas that served as the main foundations of liberal
internationalism in the 20th century. This narrative argues not only that Realism won the
First Great Debate’ by offering a more accurate and practically more applicable
worldview than
iberalism, but also emphasizes that the failure of Idealism’ in both
theory and practice was the reason which led the world to the bloodshed of WWII. The
resulting myth discredited liberal internationalism for a long time.
The historical narratives of IR, however, are sub ects to constant change. iberals
were thus, eventually, able to rehabilitate their “predecessors” in the 1920s and 19 0s.
Other lessons were drawn regarding the fictionality of the narrative of the Great
Debates’. As iberalism had established and strengthened itself as a mainstream school
of IR in the 19 0s–19 0s, the understanding and the label of the Idealist’ side in the
First Great Debate’ also began to shift. “Idealist liberalism”, “liberal idealism”, “classical
liberalism” are all expressions that are in use to refer to the loosely defined group of ideas
emerging in the context of Versailles and the surrounding controversies. Several of these
ideas were later used as the foundations on which the iberal school of IR could develop.
The changing labels signify the attempts of followers of iberalism to (similarly to the
earlier efforts of Realists) extrapolate iberalism’s presence to the time of the alleged
birth of the discipline, thus giving it more legitimacy and weight by “virtue” of stemming
from the era of Versailles.
Beyond o ndational Myt
Overall, as revisionist historians and IR theorists have proven, the myth of the birth of IR
in 1919 is a product of “an ahistorical extrapolation backwards of current developments
and concerns in international relations” (de Carvalho et al., 2011:
) there were no
defining Great Debates’ taking place in the strict sense of the tern. Rather, there
developed multiple parallel discourses on several diverging issues. If there is a period to
.
AI
i
.
.
v
CO O RN
be named as the time of the birth of the discipline, the years following WWII would be
much more suitable for this aim (Schmidt, 199
Guilhot, 200 ). However, the legacy of
Versailles and the surrounding controversies still appear as the cornerstone and the
starting point of the discipline. The symbolic meaning of 1919 has been built into the
mainstream historical narratives, and – with the necessary source criticism – continues to
serve as a useful tool to illustrate the nature, the main agenda and the diverging
assumptions of IR for beginners as well as the broader interested public. Students of IR
encounter the notion of the First Great Debate’ almost without exception. They are also
ac uainted, typically, with Wilsonian Idealism, the eague of Nations and national selfdetermination in the first months of their studies – which are then repeatedly referenced,
again and again, in the course of their becoming scholars of IR, regardless of which school
of IR their respective university institute leans toward. The legacy of Versailles and its
aftermath is, thus, inherently built into the history and historiography of the discipline of
IR and remains part of the standard introductory process of anyone who intends to enter
this field of study.
e e a
e
of ersailles
i loma y or a e
elate Controversies
rin i les an Criti ues
orld rder
Although the discipline of IR did not begin with a Big Bang’ (de Carvalho et al., 2011:
) in 1919, Versailles and the surrounding controversies had created an environment
which encouraged and facilitated its development. Wilson and his followers embarked
upon the road to redesign the architecture of the international system in the spirit of an
early liberal internationalism, which led to the emergence of several new principles and
approaches in the field of IR, and strengthened the significance and position of some
earlier considerations. In the followings, the article reviews the most persistent and
influential ideas in IR which have emerged as a conse uence of Versailles.
One of the most tangible theoretical principles that have appeared during the
negotiations was open diplomacy. As Carr writes in 19 9, “down to 191 , the conduct
of international relations was the concern of persons professionally engaged in it” (Carr,
19
19 9 : 1). Foreign offices worked independently of party politics or public
opinions, while international relations, including warfare, was almost exclusively the
The principle of open diplomacy, however, was never applied consciously in practice during the Paris
peace negotiations (see Keylor, 199 : 1–
).
.
AI
i
.
.
v
CO O RN
business of high-ranking soldiers and diplomats. The events of WWI contributed to the
rise of a discourse on a new diplomacy’, the primary ob ective of which was to make
international relations more transparent, emphasizing the problems with secret treaties
and the lack of public involvement in decision-making about international relations
(Keylor, 199
Weisbrode 201 ).
The new approach towards diplomacy and international relations, however, went
beyond the mere transparency of international relations, and culminated in the creation of
a whole dictionary of new principles for a new world order. The spirit of the time is
illustrated well by the ideas of the British Union of Democratic Control (UDC) about the
rules of a new way of conducting international affairs as early as 191 , in the following
four points: 1) the population’s consent is necessary for a transfer of territory 2) the
parliament has to be involved in decisions about international treaties
) Britain has to
refrain from alliances that function on the mechanism of the balance of power and use the
means of an international court for the settlement of its disputes
) arms reduction. In
191 , a fifth point was added: the promotion of free trade and the termination of trade
wars (Knock, 199 :
). The proposed guidelines of postwar settlement by Wilson
developed these ideas further. The building blocks of the new world order became
canonized in the form of his Fourteen Points (191 ), and later appeared in the Treaty of
Versailles (1919) and in the Covenant of the eague of Nations (1919). These documents
articulated the main principles for the reconstruction of the world order, highlighting the
concepts of open diplomacy, democracy, freedom of the seas, freedom of trade, arms
reduction, national self-determination, e uality of nations, territorial integrity, the
peaceful settlement of disputes, international cooperation, and collective security. In this
form, Versailles and the surrounding controversies did not only lay and strengthen the
foundations of a new world order, but also those of liberal internationalism and
iberalism as a school in IR theory.
For the keen eye, the spirit of Versailles and the surrounding controversies may
also have some features that resemble an early version of an international society,
although the notion was coined by Bull only in 19
, defined as
It was, obviously, not Woodrow Wilson who invented the central principles of liberal internationalism.
The mentioned principles have a rather long history in the development of liberal thought, and they had
their proponents in Wilson’s era as well. However, in the great narratives of history and IR, and in the
imagination of the peoples of the world, early liberal internationalism ( Idealism’) became intertwined with
Wilson’s charismatic (for a while, even messianistic) person in the time of Versailles and the surrounding
controversies (Manela 200 b: 12 ).
.
AI
i
.
.
CO O RN
v
“a group of states, conscious of certain common interests and common values,
form a society in the sense that they conceive themselves to be bound by a
common set of rules in their relations with one another, and share in the
working of common institutions. (
) recognising certain common interests
and perhaps some common values, they regard themselves as bound by
certain rules in their dealings with one another (
). At the same time they
cooperate in the working of institutions such as the forms of procedures of
international law, the machinery of diplomacy and general international
organisation, and the customs and conventions of war” (Bull, 199
19
:
1 ).
In the case of the new world order established in Versailles, common interests and
common values were articulated in the form of the above-mentioned principles, and the
basis of international cooperation was created to settle uestions of international law,
diplomacy, international institutions and war. Democracy was a very significant building
block for this early model of international society, and the principle of public right’ was
often emphasized in Wilson’s formative speeches (Holsti 199
1991 : 1
), establishing
common value-based grounds for mutual understanding at the international level.
The existence of this early international society is thoroughly intertwined with the
principle of collective security. Wilson and his followers argued that the main cause of
WWI was the instability enhanced by the traditional balance-of-power politics of the great
powers. Therefore, in the new world order, they put emphasis on the principle of
collective security to replace the balance-of-power mechanism (Knock 199 : 11 ),
conceptualized in the Covenant of the eague of Nations in the following way:
“(Article 10) The Members of the eague undertake to respect and preserve
as against external aggression the territorial integrity and existing political
independence of all Members of the eague. In case of any such aggression
or in case of any threat or danger of such aggression the Council shall advise
upon the means by which this obligation shall be fulfilled.
(Article 11) Any war or threat of war, whether immediately affecting any of
the Members of the eague or not, is hereby declared a matter of concern to
the whole eague, and the eague shall take any action that may be deemed
wise and effectual to safeguard the peace of nations.”
.
AI
i
.
.
CO O RN
v
The key international institution to hold this new international society together and
implement its common values and interests was the
eague of Nations. Although its
establishment was surrounded by rather abstract, at times even pathetic, declarations
about the role of the organization (Wilson compared the eague to a “searching light of
conscience” ), it had very tangible and significant benefits both for the iberal school of
IR in general, and concerning the theory of international organisations in particular. On
the one hand, its Covenant contributed to the canonization of the principles of liberal
internationalism and the broader approach of
iberalism towards the conduct of
international affairs, institutionalizing international cooperation in several fields, such as
economy, society, science, technology, and culture (Fleury, 199 : 09). On the other
hand, even if the eague was indeed very far from being perfectly constructed, it has
served the theory of international organisations as a case study for analysis and a model
to improve, while several existing international organizations proudly trace their roots
back to the structure and the values upon which the eague was established (Goodrich,
19
Davies, 2012).
Overall, even though some critical accounts accuse the
eague of discrediting
international organisations due to its very obvious flaws and failures in practice (Fleury,
199 : 1 ), the founding principles of the organization survived its existence, and keep
influencing the development of the United Nations and other international organisations
in general. As for the new world order constructed by Wilsonian Idealists’, as the above
discussion has shown, it provided much more for IR than Realists may have assumed: a
set of ephemeral principles, a failed attempt at their practical implementation, and an
organization responsible for much of this failure. In the direct aftermath of Versailles, the
great powers “accepted Wilsonianism as the foundational discourse for a redesigned
international system” (Smith, 201 : 2
), and its reflections in IR theory (both on the
grand and middle levels) has continued to influence the development of the discipline,
providing a firm basis for the debates around the following new international orders
emerging from WWII and the Cold War.
“My conception of the eague of Nations is ust this, that it shall operate as the organized moral force of
men throughout the world and that whenever or wherever wrong and aggression are planned or
contemplated, this searching light of conscience will be turned upon them and men everywhere will ask,
“What are the purposes that you hold in your heart against the fortunes of the world ” (Wilson, 192 : 0).
.
AI
i
.
.
CO O RN
v
il onian ationali m T e ontro er ial Prin i le o
ational Sel
etermination in
ro e
The new international order was built on nation-states, which brought about one of the
most heated controversies of the Versailles and interwar era: the issue of national selfdetermination. In 191 , Wilson, the most ardent proponent of the concept at the time,
stated that
“This war had its roots in the disregard of the rights of small nations and of
nationalities which lacked the union and the force to make good their claim
to determine their own allegiances and their own forms of political life. (
)
National aspirations must be respected peoples may now be dominated and
governed only by their own consent. ’Self-Determination’ is not a mere
phrase. It is an imperative principle of action, which statesmen will
henceforth ignore at their peril” (Wilson, 192 : 1 0).
As for the Fourteen Points, the Treaty of Versailles and the Covenant of the eague of
Nations, national self-determination was not directly mentioned therein, however, its
spirit was visible in the territorial decisions redrawing the borders of Europe, and thus,
with Osiander’s words, it had become the “new master principle” of the international
society after Versailles (Osiander, 199 : 2
).
The content of the principle, however, was rather vague. The origins of its
articulation in the peace negotiatons can be traced back to three substantive and
interrelated principles appearing in Wilson’s speeches: the principle of public right,
government by consent of the governed, and democracy. On the basis of these, he could
declare “that nobody has the right to impose sovereignty upon anybody else that, in
disposing of the affairs of a nation, that nation or people must be its own master and make
its own choice” (Wilson, 1919a). The most widely accepted core of the practical
application of the principle of national self-determinism, the so-called Wilsonian
nationalism’, was “to make state frontiers coincide with the frontiers of nationality and
language” (Hobsbawm, 1992 1990 : 1 2–1
), which has also often been interpreted as
being grounded in concepts of political or territorial independence and ethnicity.
In practice, however, it proved largely impossible to make borders and
nationalities coincide in Europe after WWI (see Hobsbawm, 1992 1990 : 1 1–1 2).
Except for two rather indefinite indications of the concept in Points V and VI, referring to colonies’ and
Russia’s right to determine their own development.
.
AI
i
.
.
v
CO O RN
Moreover, the discussion of the practical application of the idea of national selfdetermination in Europe was often based on a lack of knowledge or insufficient
information (see ynch, 2002). In this sense, the principle of self-determination did not
only trigger overly great expectations in Central Europe and foster the spread of
nationalism, but also planted the seeds of in ustice in several parts of the continent
( ynch, 2002). Although Wilson was committed to the implementation of the principle
“without introducing new or perpetuating old elements of discord and antagonism that
would be likely in time to break the peace of Europe and conse uently of the world”
(Wilson, 191 ), the “new master principle” of the new world order significantly
contributed to the demise of the Versailles system, generating processes that were in sharp
contradiction with the other principles of liberal internationalism.
Considered as an essential principle of international law (i
ogen ) today, the
concept first appeared in Article 1 of the Charter of the United Nations (19
), and was
codified in Article 1 of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (19
),
stating that “all peoples have the right of self-determination. By virtue of that right they
freely determine their political status and freely pursue their economic, social and cultural
development.” The principle of national self-determination, supported and spread by
Wilson and his followers in Versailles, was built on the approaches of liberal
internationalism and the
iberal school of IR. However, the general vagueness of the
concept continues to make its practical application in addressing political aspirations of
independence controversial, up to this day.
il onian ationali m
ational Sel
etermination on To r aro nd t e olonie
In 1919, the principle of national self-determination resonated not only in Europe, but
attracted the attention of colonized peoples and their leaders supporting anti-colonial
nationalism all over the world. The fifth of the Fourteen Points called for
“a free, open-minded, and absolutely impartial ad ustment of all colonial
claims, based upon a strict observance of the principle that in determining all
such uestions of sovereignty the interests of the populations concerned must
have e ual weight with the e uitable claims of the government whose title is
to be determined.”
In Versailles, however, “non-Western regions and peoples figure most often as inert
masses of territory and humanity” (Manela, 200 a: x) during the negotiations, discussed
.
AI
i
.
.
v
CO O RN
only in those rare cases when this served great power interests, and the participation of
local actors was minimal even in these cases. The Covenant of the eague of Nations had
created the mandate system to ensure the development of the colonies of defeated powers
in its Article 22, stating that “the well-being and development of such peoples form a
sacred trust of civilisation and that securities for the performance of this trust should be
embodied in this Covenant”. Nevertheless, in the interwar era, this principle was
implemented for the benefit of the colonial powers and against the self-determination of
colonial people.
The great powers did not calculate with the incendiary effects of the principle of
self-determination in the colonial world. However, WWI had not yet ended when they
already had to face the phenomenon that colonial peoples began lobbying for their own
nation-states, arguing that on the basis of ethnic consciousness they have a right to
establish a sovereign state. Argumentations based on Wilsonian nationalism’ emerged in
Turkey, Egypt, Vietnam, India, China, Korea, Indonesia, Nigeria and in several other
parts of Africa, among others (Steigerwald, 1999: 9
Manela 200 b). Similar claims
were already disturbing enough in the case of Central Europe, where political borders did
not coincide with nationalities. In the colonial world, the application of national selfdetermination was not only even more problematic to implement, it also clearly
contradicted the interests of great powers, threatening the stability of their colonial rule.
Recognising this, Wilson himself entered into lengthy explanations, referring
“the un ualified hope that men have entertained everywhere of immediate
emancipation from the things that have hampered them and oppressed them.
ou cannot in human experience rush into the light of self-determination .
(
)
ou have to go through the twilight into the broadening day before the
noon comes and the full sun is on the landscape” (Wilson, 1919b).
A more practical line of reasoning by him argued that “it was not within the privilege of
the conference of peace to act upon the right of self-determination of any peoples except
those which had been included in the territories of defeated empires.” (Wilson, 192 :
2
). These statements undoubtedly meant that the principle of national self-
determination was initially not designed for colonies. Even if some of the imperial powers
(the German, the Austro-Hungarian and the Ottoman empires), which were defeated in
WWI, collapsed, the British and the French empires were actually strengthened as a
.
AI
i
.
.
v
CO O RN
conse uence of Versailles, leading to an unprecedented era of European colonial
expansion (Manela, 200 b: 12 ).
Several scholars argue that Versailles and the surrounding debates are textbook
illustrations of the inherently colonial and Eurocentric nature of IR since its very
beginnings. Undeniably, in spite of Wilson’s high-toned ideas about the e uality of
nations, Versailles reflected great power interests that were based on a “colonizer’s model
of the world” (Saurin, 200 : 2 ), and the decisions were made in an atmosphere of
Western and European supremacy. There are manifold criticisms concerning the
motivations and intentions of Wilson, accusing him of supporting American imperialism
in the Western Hemisphere (Healy, 19
Hall, 199 ), emphasizing the principles of free
trade and free navigation to foster the exploitation of the colonies (Steigerwald, 1999), or
the controversial nature of the Wilsonian idea of interventions (Calhoun, 19
Belloni,
200 ), all imbued with traces of colonialism, Eurocentrism, and racism (Steigerwald,
1999).
Principles, however, can often enhance their discursive spaces and gain additional
meanings in different contexts regardless of the motivations and intentions of their
initiators. It was not otherwise in the case of national self-determination, either: in the
colonial world, the resonance of the notion contributed to the development of the
theoretical foundations of anti-colonial nationalist movements. On the other hand, the
following disillusionment with Wilson’s ideas fostered nationalist upheavals all over the
colonized world, which made it clear that the peoples of the colonies strived for
recognition in the new world order, and international society has begun its turn “from an
imperial world order to a postcolonial one” (Manela 200 b: 12 ). The decline of colonial
powers reached its peak several decades later. The principle of national self-determination
and Wilsonian nationalism’ not only contributed to bring about the events of WWII, but
may thus (rather paradoxically) be named as an important turning point in the history of
anticolonial movements, providing them with a comprehensive theoretical background to
channel the manifold tensions and dissatisfaction stemming from the colonial world
order. These movements, furthermore, have been used as case studies in the theoretical
reflections of the postcolonial criti ues of IR, further contributing to the development of
IR as a discipline (see Manela, 200 b).
.
AI
i
.
.
v
CO O RN
Con lusions
There is no need to elaborate on the events of the 1920s–19 0s in detail to prove the fact
that the direct aims of the Treaty of Versailles were not fulfilled, let alone the excessive
hopes of liberal internationalism about the instant creation of a more peaceful and ust
world on the blood-soaked ruins after WWI. The eague of Nations itself is also often
considered to be a failure, at least in reaching its declared practical ob ectives, while the
principle of self-determination may be said to have only ignited tensions in both Europe
and the colonial world in the interwar period and after. With a view to the development
of IR, revisionist historians and IR theorists have also proven that the great narrative about
the glorious overnight’ birth of the discipline in 1919 is, in the strict sense, mostly a
blend of the superficial reading of the historical events and the extrapolation of the
discipline’s contemporary state in the Cold War. However, if we consider the long-term
impact of Versailles and the surrounding controversies, it is clearly visible that this era
meant an un uestionably significant and formative time for the study of international
relations and the establishment of IR as a discipline.
From the
iberal point of view, Versailles served as a forum where the
foundations of the main principles and approaches of liberal internationalism were
summarized and canonized, contributing to the development of the discipline of IR to
further the uest of mankind for a more peaceful and ust future. From the Realist point
of view, it symbolises the time and the place where the strawman’ image of the Idealist
was born, against which Realist scholars were able to refine and develop their own ideas
during the aftermath of WWII, in the time of the Cold War. The circumstances under
which the Treaty of Versailles was discussed, signed and implemented, have also inspired
the criti ues of IR, especially in the form of anti- and postcolonial theories. The principles
and approaches that the article has discussed above are typical sub ects of extensive and
often heated discourses within the discipline, which have emerged from the context of
Versailles and the surrounding controversies, and keep influencing the development of
IR since then. From this point of view, the most important achievement of Versailles –
deserving to be celebrated on the 100th anniversary – lies in the creation of a wide
discursive space in which the emergence of the principles of IR theory, defining principles
for the course of the 20th century, was made possible.
All things considered, the Treaty of Versailles was built upon a discourse about a
set of ideas which, in the course of time, developed to define the central field of analysis
of the discipline. In the meantime, the attempts at the practical implementation of the
.
AI
i
.
.
CO O RN
v
treaty during the 1920s–19 0s provided IR with a range of instructive case studies to
analyse and lessons to learn. In this sense, the conclusions support the claim of Anievas
that “the theoretical significance of Versailles for IR can hardly be overstated” (Anievas,
201 : 19).
eferen es
Anievas, A. (201 ). International Relations between War and Revolution: Wilsonian
Diplomacy and the Making of the Treaty of Versailles. nternational Politi , 1,
pp. 19–
Ashworth,
.
. M. (2002). Did the Realist–Idealist Great Debate Really Happen A
Revisionist History of International Relations. nternational elation , 1 (1): pp.
– 1.
Baranyi, T. (2019). Reassembling a World Order: Toward a New Historiography of the
Paris Peace Conference.
i
or in
air , ( ), in t i
o rnal o nternational
e.
Baylis, J., Smith, S., and Owens, P. (201 ). T e Glo alization o
orld Politi
n
ntrod tion to nternational elation . Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Belloni, R. (200 ). Rethinking “Nation-Building:” The Contradictions of the NeoWilsonian Approach to Democracy Promotion. T e
ite ead
o rnal o
i loma y and nternational elation , (1): 9 –109.
Boemeke, M. E., Feldman, G. D., and Glaser, E. (199 ). T e Treaty o
ea e ment
er aille
ear . Washington DC and Cambridge: German Historical
ter
Institute and Cambridge University Press.
Buell, R. . (192 ). nternational elation . New ork: Henry Holt and Co.
Bull, H. (199
19
). T e
nar i al So iety
St dy o
rder in
orld Politi .
ondon: Macmillan Press td.
Calhoun, F. (19
). Po er and Prin i le
rmed nter ention in
il onian
oreign
Poli y. Kent: Kent State University Press.
Carr, E. H. (19
19 9 ). T e T enty ear
ri i
n ntrod tion to t e
St dy o nternational elation . ondon: Macmillan
arter
o
t e
nited
ation
Co. td.
ne
https: www.un.org en charter-united-nations Accessed
.
Available
August 2019 .
at:
.
AI
i
.
.
CO O RN
v
Davies, T. R. (2012). A “Great Experiment” of the eague of Nations Era: International
Nongovernmental Organizations, Global Governance, and Democracy Beyond
the State. Glo al Go ernan e, 1 ( ): pp. 0 – 2 .
de Carvalho, B., eira, H., and Hobson, J. M. (2011). The Big Bangs of IR: The Myths
That
our Teachers Still Tell
ou about 1
nternational St die , 9( ), pp.
–
. Millenni m
o rnal o
.
Donnelly, J. (199 ) Realism and the Academic Study of International Relations. In: J.
Farr, J. S. Dryzek, and S. T.
eonard, eds., Politi al S ien e in
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 1
Drinkwater, D. (200 ). Sir
arold
i tory.
–19 .
i ol on and
nternational
elation
T e
Pra titioner a T eori t. New ork: Oxford University Press.
Fleury, A. (199 ). The eague of Nations: Toward a New Appreciation of Its History. In:
M. E. Boemeke, G. D. Feldman, and E. Glaser, eds., T e Treaty o
ea e ment
er aille
ear . Washington DC and Cambridge: German Historical
ter
Institute and Cambridge University Press, pp. 0 – 22.
Goodrich,
. M. (19
). From
eague of Nations to United Nations. nternational
rganization, 1(1): pp. –21.
Guilhot, N. (200 ). The Realist Gambit: Postwar American Political Science and the Birth
of IR Theory. nternational Politi al So iology, 2( ): pp. 2 1– 0 .
Hall, . B. (199 ).
il Bank
T e
nited State and Po tre ol tionary
. Austin, The University of Texas Press.
Me i o
Healy, D. (19
and Politi
).
ri e to
egemony T e
nited State in t e ari
.
ean
Madison: The University of Wisconsin Press.
Hobsbawm, E. J. (1992).
ation and
ationali m
in e
Programme Myt
eality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Holsti, K. J. (199
1991 ). Pea e and
ar
rmed
on li t and nternational
rder
. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
nternational o enant on i il and Politi al ig t
e em er
https: www.ohchr.org en professionalinterest pages ccpr.aspx
. Available at:
Accessed
August 2019 .
Jackson, R., S rensen, G., and M ller, J. (201 ): ntrod tion to nternational elation
T eorie and
roa e . Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Keylor, W. R. (199 ). Versailles and International Diplomacy. In: M. E. Boemeke, G. D.
Feldman, and E. Glaser, eds., T e Treaty o
er aille
ea e ment
ter
.
AI
i
.
.
CO O RN
v
ear . Washington DC and Cambridge: German Historical Institute and
Cambridge University Press, pp.
Knock, T. J. (199 ). To nd ll
ar
9– 0 .
oodro
il on and t e
e t or a e
orld
rder. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Knock, T. J. (199 ). Wilsonian Concepts and International Realities at the End of the
War. In: M. E. Boemeke, G. D. Feldman, and E. Glaser, eds., T e Treaty o
er aille
ea e ment
ear . Washington DC and Cambridge:
ter
German Historical Institute and Cambridge University Press, pp. 111–129.
ynch, A. (2002). Woodrow Wilson and the Principle of National Self-Determination :
A Reconsideration. e ie o nternational St die , 2 (2): pp. 19–
Manela, E. (200 a). T e
rigin o
il onian Moment Sel
.
etermination and t e nternational
nti olonial ationali m. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Manela, E. (200 b). Dawn of a New Era: The “Wilsonian Moment” in Colonial Contexts
and the Transformation of World Order, 191 –1920. In: S. Conrad and D.
Sachsenmaier, eds.,
om eting
i ion o
orld
rder Glo al Moment and
. New ork: Palgrave Macmillan, 121–1 0.
Mo ement
Moon, P. T. (192 ). Sylla
elation . New
on nternational
ork: The Macmillan
Company.
Morgenthau, H. J. (19
). Politi
mong ation
T e Str ggle or Po er and Pea e.
New ork: A.A. Knopf.
Osiander, A. (199 ). T e State Sy tem o
ro e
Pea emaking and t e
ondition o nternational Sta ility. Oxford, Clarendon Press.
Pre ident
oodro
il on
o rteen Point
Available at:
an ary
https: avalon.law.yale.edu 20th century wilson1 .asp Accessed
August 2019 .
uirk, J., and Vigneswaran, D. (200 ). The Construction of an Edifice: The Story of a
First Great Debate. e ie o nternational St die , 1(1): pp. 9–10 .
Saurin, J. (200 ). International Relations as the Imperial Illusion or, the Need to
Decolonize IR. In: B. G. Jones, ed.,
anham: Rowman
e olonizing nternational
elation ,
ittlefield, 2 – 2.
Schmidt, B. (199 ). T e Politi al
i o re o
nar y
nternational elation . State University of New
i i linary
i tory o
ork Press: Albany.
Schweller, R. . (2001). The Problem of International Order Revisited: A Review Essay.
nternational Se rity, 2 (1), pp. 1 1–1
.
.
AI
i
.
.
CO O RN
v
Sharp, A. (201 ). The New Diplomacy and the New Europe, 191 –1922. In: Nicholas
Doumanis, ed., T e
ord
Handbooks
and ook o
Online,
ro ean
. Oxford
i tory
1–22.
Available
https: www.oxfordhandbooks.com view 10.109 oxfordhb 9
.0001 oxfordhb-9
0199 9
9 Accessed
at:
0199 9
9.001
August 2019 .
Smith, . V. (201 ). So ereignty at t e Pari Pea e on eren e o
. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Smith, S., Hadfield, A., and Dunne, T. (201 ): oreign Poli y T eorie
ae .
tor
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Steans, J., Pettiford, ., Diez, T., and El-Anis, I. (2010). n ntrod tion to nternational
elation T eory Per e ti e and T eme . ondon: Pearson Education imited.
Steigerwald, D. (1999). Historiography: The Reclamation Of Woodrow Wilson
i tory, 2 (1): pp. 9–99.
i lomati
T e
o enant
o
t e
eag e
o
ation
.
ne
https: avalon.law.yale.edu 20th century leagcov.asp Accessed
Treaty o Pea e
it
Germany Treaty o
er aille
ne
Available
August 2019 .
. Available at:
https: www.loc.gov law help us-treaties bevans m-ust000002-00
Accessed
at:
.pdf
August 2019 .
Vitalis, R. (200 ). Birth of a Discipline. In: D. ong and B. C. Schmidt, eds., m eriali m
and nternationali m in t e i i line o nternational elation . State University
of New ork Press: Albany, pp. 1 9–1 2.
Weisbrode, K. (201 ).
ld
i loma y
e i ited
St dy in t e Modern
i tory o
i lomati Tran ormation . New ork: Palgrave Macmillan.
Wilson, W. (191 ). President Wilson s Address to Congress, Analyzing German and
Austrian Peace Utterances. Delivered in Joint Session, February 11, 191 .
Available
at:
https: wwi.lib.byu.edu index.php President Wilson 2 s Address to Congress
, Analyzing German and Austrian Peace Utterances
Accessed
August
2019 .
Wilson, W. (1919a). Address from Rear Platform, Richmond, Ind., September , 1919.
Available
at:
https: archive.org stream addressesofpresi00wilsuoft addressesofpresi00wilsuof
t d vu.txt Accessed
August 2019 .
.
AI
i
.
.
v
CO O RN
Wilson, W. (1919b). After-Dinner Remarks, Paris, May 9, 1919. In: A. S. ink, ed., T e
Pa er o
oodro
Wilson, W. (192 ). T e P
Harper
Brothers.
il on. Princeton: Princeton University Press,
li Pa er o
oodro
il on
: 9 .
ar and Pea e. New
ork: