Zeitschrift für Politikwissenschaft
https://doi.org/10.1007/s41358-024-00390-w
FOCUS
Academic freedom: normative ideals, contemporary
challenges
Elif Özmen
Accepted: 9 August 2024
© The Author(s) 2024
Abstract There is broad agreement within both science and society about the value
of academic freedom. There is disagreement, however, about which forms or degrees,
if any, of political and moral regulation might harm or benefit science. Academic
freedom, just like free speech in general, has turned into a contentious issue within
society as a whole. Competing ideas about science and its social functions, as well
as the norms of justice and legitimacy, are debated.
Keywords censorship · Academic freedom · Freedom of speech · Scientific ethos ·
Academic discourse culture
Wissenschaftsfreiheit: Normative Ideale, aktuelle Herausforderungen
Zusammenfassung Über den Wert der Wissenschaftsfreiheit herrscht innerhalb der
Wissenschaft wie auch der Gesellschaft weitgehend Einigkeit. Uneinigkeit besteht
dagegen bezüglich der Frage, ob und welche Formen, gegebenenfalls auch welche
Grade der politischen und moralischen Steuerung der Wissenschaft zuträglich oder
schädlich sind. Unterdessen hat sich Wissenschaftsfreiheit, ebenso wie die allgemeine Meinungsfreiheit, zu einem gesamtgesellschaftlichen Konfliktthema entwickelt.
Hierbei werden sowohl konkurrierende Vorstellungen von Wissenschaft und ihrer
gesellschaftlichen Funktion als auch gesamtgesellschaftliche Normendiskurse um
Gerechtigkeit und Legitimität verhandelt.
Prof. Dr. Elif Özmen
Institute of Philosophy, University Gießen, Gießen, Germany
E-Mail:
[email protected]
K
E. Özmen
Schlüsselwörter Zensur · Wissenschaftsfreiheit · Meinungsfreiheit ·
Wissenschaftsethos · Wissenschaftliche Diskurskultur
1 The public debate
There is broad agreement within both science and society about the value of academic freedom. It is also agreed that the freedom of science and research from the
state’s interference is to the benefit of the scientific striving towards truth and insight.
The autonomy of science—i.e., the freedom to search for knowledge—is necessary
for finding significant truths; for understanding, explaining, and justifying natural
and social phenomena and processes; the development of adequate theories and their
practical application. There is disagreement, however, about which forms or degrees,
if any, of political and moral regulation might harm or benefit science; what counts
as an extra-scientific (“political”, “moral”, “ideological”) amendment; and whether
academic freedom is actually threatened and harmed in individual cases.
The public debate about academic freedom does not so much concern its restriction or violation by state actors—which has been a constant since the beginnings
of science (Daston 2019)—nor the current worldwide increasing tendencies towards
autocratization (Spannagel and Kinzelbach 2023; Kinzelbach et al. 2024). It rather
concerns “softer” ways of social influencing, a tyranny of the majority or, alternatively, a tyranny of strangely powerful minorities that allegedly leads to perceived or
real restrictions on science, including sanctions against, and the self-regulation of,
free speech and academic exchange at universities, conferences, and academic communication. Evidence of this are retracted invitations, calls for boycott, preventing
events from taking place, campus occupations, threats and denunciations against academics, sanctioning concepts and dismissing works, contents, and traditions because
of political or moral flaws. It is claimed that—just as with cases of state control,
censorship, and coercion—these practices of scandalization and “cancelling” jeopardize academic freedom and discourse culture, and hence the thriving of science
in general (Downs and Surprenant 2018; Scott 2019; Özmen 2021; Borsche 2023;
Sunstein 2024).
Academic freedom has become an issue of conflict for the whole of society, because the freedom of research, teaching, and speech goes far beyond academia. This
debate, which involves academic institutions and their political affiliations, officeholders, and individuals, but also media, journalists, book publishers, activist groups
and self-declared free speech warriors, started in the US, but has been smoldering in
Germany for several years now too. The high number of contributions in the press,
radio, and social media about the “politicization” and “moralization” of academic
freedom shows the great public interest in potential dangers to a free science and
academic debates.
In what follows, I will put forward some remarks and claims concerning the current debate about academic freedom. I am convinced that we can better understand
this debate and the extra-academic interest in it, if we see it as a dispute about the
conditions for successful science. Academic freedom should therefore not only be
regarded as a legally protected right, but as a comprehensive normative ideal. The
K
Academic freedom: normative ideals, contemporary challenges
latter can only be made concrete and proven to be valuable within an institutional
practice—in research, teaching, and universities—and within a social context, the
liberal pluralistic democracy.
2 Why is academic freedom contested? Four observations
The debate about academic freedom shows striking similarities to another issue of
social conflict: the objects and limits of the freedom of speech. It is no coincidence
that these two basic rights, academic freedom and freedom of speech, are addressed
in the same article of the German Basic Law (Art. 5 Abs. 1 GG). As basic rights of
communication, they are a fixed element of liberal democracies that are based on
a pluralism of opinions and the competition between arguments for the better opinion
(Bollinger 1986; BVerfGE 65, 1 (41)). However, there are also important differences
that might be obscured by the equation of the general right to free speech with
the specific right to academic freedom (Gärditz 2021). The often-invoked ideal of
academic freedom is—just like the common right of the freedom of speech—claimed
by different actors with different academic (and non-academic) intentions.
Equally striking about the debate is the frequency of English or American terms
that are used in non-English languages. That is also no coincidence. In many US
universities, progressive reforms have been implemented since the late 1980s that
find their current expression in the demands for speech codes, trigger warnings, safe
spaces, or no platforming (Menand 1996; Lackey 2018; Gordon 2022). These buzzwords refer to measures that have been brought forward against certain academic
claims, texts, questions, figures of thought, or uses of language by members of the
scientific community (i.e., students, lecturers, university leadership), but also by external groups (such as social movements, social media activists). And the reason
for that is not that these views are scientifically wrong, dishonest, or fraudulent, but
because they contradict the “correct” political and moral norms. This goes along
with a sometimes deeply disturbing willingness to oppose with great harshness academics who defend a certain position, or do not comply with certain demands. This
opposition takes the form of merciless anger directed at their academic reputation,
often becoming personal and even threatening.
Third, the debate about academic freedom has, from the beginning, been conducted in the logic and language of political antagonism—in we/you terms and
enmity. This does not only apply to the debates about science, in which activists,
politicians, journalists or also the common Wutbürger get worked up about allegedly
elitist, irresponsible, decadent, or corrupt scientists. The malady of political antagonism also exists within the scientific community, for instance when colleagues are
defamed as enemies of science (or even enemies of freedom), because they allegedly
support academic “virtue terror”, “gender madness” or a “dictatorship of political
correctness” at the universities (for Germany, see Hopf 2019; Kostner 2022).
Finally, it is also noticeable in the inner-academic debates that a “liberal” concept of academic freedom is put in opposition to a “progressive”, “emancipatory”, or
“critical” concept of academic freedom (Schubert 2023). This means that two competing ideas about science and its social function—or: two competing ideas about
K
E. Özmen
the legitimacy of science—are being discussed here. Academic freedom is thus
a contested battleground of discourses about norms in society in general. Academia
is acknowledged as a social subsystem that follows its own logic of functions, which
includes academic freedom. At the same time, goes the progressive-critical demand,
science has to adapt to social norms and transformations. It is therefore allegedly
possible and legitimate to add normative ideals and values next to academic freedom,
or even to prioritize them, such as justice, equality, anti-discrimination, affirmation,
intersectional inclusion, pluralism, and diversity. The liberal side, however, insists
on the defensive character of academic freedom against such “external” norms and
points out the social value of an independent science that is only committed to truth
and reality.
3 Normative ideals: constitutional right and scientific ethos
Academic freedom is, at least in the tradition of the German constitution, a legal
concept. It is also part of the constitution of many other countries (such as Italy,
Switzerland, Austria, Greece, Portugal)—including states that have in recent years
severely restricted universities’ autonomy and academic self-determination (Hungary, Turkey). However, the imperative of free science is also present in countries
where it is not protected by the law (e.g., Great Britain, France, the US). The normative force of academic freedom does not seem limited to a legal issue. A look at the
German Basic Law and the verdicts of the Federal Constitutional Court of Germany
further illustrates the philosophically relevant relationship between science, truth,
and freedom.
Academic freedom is guaranteed as a defensive and constitutive individual right
without legal reservation in Article 5 of the German Basic Law. Restrictions of
academic freedom can only be justified by a conflict with equivalent laws. These
include laws concerning human dignity, life, freedom from physical harm, health,
animal and environmental protection. Of course, legally relevant opinions, theories,
and actions by scientists such as hate speech, Holocaust denial, glorification of
violence, libel, blasphemy are not protected by academic freedom (Britz 2013).
The robust defensive right of academic freedom is not a general right. It protects
the persons, practices, and institutions engaged in academic speech, research, and
publications against, primarily, the state’s influence aimed at directing, controlling,
and sanctioning science. It is not the state’s decision who and what can claim to have
a scientific character, neither is it a legal, political, or social decision. This is solely an
issue regulated by the control and sanctions mechanism of the scientific community
(BVerfGE 90, 1 (12)). Anything that is, in its form and content, to be regarded as
a serious attempt at finding the truth is protected by academic freedom (BVerfGE 90,
1 (13)), including minority views, faulty research approaches, unconventional, failed,
erratic hypotheses, theories, and positions (BVerfGE 65, 1 (41)). The idea of science
and the idea of free science thus refer to each other. If you restrict, ignore, or violate
the freedom of science, you jeopardize science as an insight-oriented practice—and
also as institutions of research, teaching, and education. Moreover, you jeopardize
K
Academic freedom: normative ideals, contemporary challenges
science as a broadly acknowledged and supported social subsystem. Simply put:
you curtail the endeavor for truth that is constitutive for science.
Science as the systematic method of searching for insights and as the practice
of forming knowledge is guided by an ethos of epistemic rationality. The latter is
thought to ensure the quality of the research and its results, and hence the scientific
character of science. Systematic coherence, internal consistency, clarity, but also
austerity and elegance (Ockham’s Razor), exactness, and verifiability are common
and accepted elements of this ethos. They define what are good scientific practices
and good scientists. Second, this ethos guarantees the autonomy and independence
of science from political and social interests. Third, with its peculiar epistemic
and ethical values and virtues, it constitutes a common ground connecting scientists. Robert Merton, the founder of the sociology of science, has analyzed this socio-epistemic arrangement—which he calls scientific ethos—with reference to four
normative principles: communism, universalism, disinterestedness, and organized
skepticism (Merton 1942). Since the practical turn of the 1980s, the philosophy
of science has explicitly addressed the interaction between epistemic, ethical, and
socio-political norms in the establishment and justification of scientific knowledge
(Schurz and Carrier 2013; Elliot and Steel 2017).
The task of the scientific ethos is, among others, to guarantee the normative basis
that allows for our scientific discussion, the tough argumentative dispute, the heated
argument about the correct view, thesis, and theory, to flourish (Füger and Özmen
2023; Özmen 2023). Acknowledging the normative premises for scientific discourse
has beneficial effects on academic freedom. However, this acknowledgement cannot
be enforced. Academic freedom is based on, and needs, requirements that cannot be
guaranteed by this right, or can be guaranteed only partially. One could call it the risk
of epistemic openness, which is taken for the sake of freedom. This means, on the one
hand, it must not matter for granting academic freedom whether scientific views,
theories, or persons are crude, unpopular, inconvenient, bigoted, or reactionary;
whether they can be shown to be unreasonable, unjustified, or absurd; or if they are
perceived as disquieting, shocking, or offensive. For scientific activity and academic
agents, binding limits of academic freedom can only be set with respect to the legal
order. At the same time, it is not academic freedom itself that will (ideally) lead to
a preliminary victory of the better belief and a long-term evolution of the truth, but
the confrontation between views, hypotheses, and theories, their competition and
argument with each other. Hence academic freedom is not exhausted by a negative
concept of freedom in the sense of freedom from coercion. Instead, it concerns the
positive freedom to participate in the scientific practice of improving one’s own, and
the collective, beliefs.
4 Contemporary challenges: How (not) to deal with conflict
What follows from these considerations about the normative basis of academic freedom for the current debate? First of all: the question about possible limits of academic freedom can be clearly answered. For scientific activity and scientific agents,
binding limits of academic freedom can only be set by reference to the legal order.
K
E. Özmen
Science does have to be politically and morally “correct” in the sense of a liberaldemocratic order, the protection of basic rights, and criminal law. Further attempts
at exerting social—for example political, religious, or ideological—influence, sanctioning, and discrediting, however, are as problematic as they are popular. With
respect to the good of a free science and a critical university, this presumed right to
limit academic freedom in the interest of other values must be clearly rejected.
Second, it seems undeniable that a common scientific ethos and a shared academic
culture form the basis for the possibility and continuation of epistemic freedoms.
These freedoms, which science requires and that cannot be guaranteed by the legal
order alone, are spaces of reasons. Here, the standards of rationality are high, and
ideally, opposing positions and serious reflection on those are anticipated. Speech is
followed by criticism and opposing speech. Factual insistence (instead of diversion,
changing subjects, and bullshitting) is the discursive standard. Antagonistic positions, as sometimes cultivated in the debate about academic freedom (e.g., left vs
right, woke vs boomers, old vs young), are alien to science. The first sentence of an
ode to science should warn: O Freunde, nicht diese Töne!
Third, the responsibility for the existence and thriving of science’s safe spaces
also lies with the individual scientists. They are free, for instance, to invite politicians of any orientation to the university. All members of the university (including
students and leadership) are equally free to challenge these. Harsh objections and
criticism do not violate academic freedom. The right to academic freedom is a right
that is taken at one’s own risk and that doesn’t entail a right to affirmation and
solidarity. Hence people must accept being challenged as to why they have invited
a specific person, what the intended didactic or discursive point is and whether the
latter seems justified, fair, legitimate, and acceptable. Critics also have to acknowledge certain questions: which reactions can be responsibly justified in the light of
academic freedom and the related epistemic hopes? And which of these are incompatible with the normative ideals of a free science and critical university? In any
case, part of the answer is: Violent protest—vandalism, forcing the cancellation of
classes and graduations, shutting down campuses, jeopardizing students’ safety—is
not protected.
Nobody has the right not to be objected to. Even unpleasant and harsh scientific
criticism is not a restriction of academic freedom. The academic discourse culture
is, to a large degree, a culture of dissent. However, provocations, polemics, and
emotionalization—which have become established parts of the debate about academic freedom—make it more difficult for everyone involved to be guided by facts
and arguments alone in scientific discourses. The lust at outrage and scandal, the
rhetoric of enmity, the culture of “cancel culture” and wrongness (in subject matters
and persons), but also the flight from discourses and dissent, therefore constitute
academic vices.
Funding Open Access funding enabled and organized by Projekt DEAL.
K
Academic freedom: normative ideals, contemporary challenges
Open Access This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License,
which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as
you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article
are included in the article’s Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the
material. If material is not included in the article’s Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not
permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly
from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.
0/.
References
Bollinger, Lee C. 1986. The tolerant society: freedom of speech and extremist speech in America. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Borsche, Tilman (ed.). 2023. Akademische Freiheit: Orte und Regeln des freien Wortes im Wandel
geschichtlicher Kontexte. Baden-Baden: Karl Alber.
Britz, Gabriele. 2013. Kommentierung zu Art. 5 Abs. 3 GG. In Grundgesetz-Kommentar, ed. Horst Dreier.
Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.
Daston, Lorraine. 2019. Academic freedom—a never-ending story. MaxPlanckResearch 19(3):18–24.
Downs, D.A., and C.W. Surprenant (eds.). 2018. The value and limits of academic speech. Philosophical,
political, and legal perspectives. New York, London: Routledge.
Elliot, Kevin E., and Daniel Steel (eds.). 2017. Current Controversies in Values and Science. New York,
London: Routledge.
Füger, Daniel, and Elif Özmen. 2023. What is scientific criticism for? Some philosophical reflections on
criticism and evidence within the scientific ethos. In Evidence contestation. Dealing with dissent in
knowledge societies, ed. Karin Zachmann, et al. London, New York: Routledge, 33–56.
Gärditz, Klaus Ferdinand. 2021. Die politische Grammatik der Wissenschaftsfreiheit. Aus Politik und Zeitgeschichte 71(46):10–16.
Gordon, Daniel. 2022. What is Academic Freedom? A Century of Debate, 1915—Present. London, New
York: Routledge.
Hopf, Wilhelm (ed.). 2019. Die Freiheit der Wissenschaft und ihre ,Feinde‘. Berlin: LIT.
Kinzelbach, Katrin, et al. 2024. Academic freedom index—2024 update. https://academic-freedom-index.
net/research/Academic_Freedom_Index_Update_2024.pdf.
Kostner, Sandra (ed.). 2022. Wissenschaftsfreiheit. Warum dieses Grundrecht zunehmend umkämpft ist.
Zeitschrift für Politik Sonderband 10.
Lackey, Jennifer (ed.). 2018. Academic freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Menand, Louis (ed.). 1996. The future of academic freedom. Chicago, London: University of Chicago
Press.
Merton, Robert K. 1942. A note on science and democracy. Journal of Legal and Political Sociology
1:115–126.
Özmen, Elif (ed.). 2021. Wissenschaftsfreiheit im Konflikt. Grundlagen, Herausforderungen und Grenzen.
Berlin: J.B. Metzler.
Özmen, Elif. 2023. Wissenschaftliche Diskurskultur zwischen Freiheit und Politisierung. Aus Politik und
Zeitgeschichte 73(43–45):25–30.
Schubert, Karsten. 2023. Zwei Begriffe der Wissenschaftsfreiheit: Zum Verhältnis von Wissenschaft und
Politik. Zeitschrift für Praktische Philosophie 10(1):39–78.
Schurz, Gerhard, and Martin Carrier (eds.). 2013. Werte in den Wissenschaften. Neue Ansätze zum Werturteilsstreit. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.
Scott Wallach, Joan. 2019. Knowledge, power, and academic freedom. New York: Colombia University
Press.
Spannagel, Janika, and Katrin Kinzelbach. 2023. The academic freedom index and its indicators: introduction to new global time-series v-Dem data. Quality & Quantity 5:3969–3989.
Sunstein, Cass. 2024. Campus free speech: a pocket guide. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Publisher’s Note Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps
and institutional affiliations.
K