Abstract
Review of Peter Gordon’s Adorno and Existence.
Volume 1, Issue 2, July 2018
Keywords
Review of Peter Gordon’s
Adorno and Existence
Rick Elmore
Appalachian State University
[email protected]
Theodor W. Adorno; Peter E. Gordon, existentialism, Adorno and
Existence; philosophy
2 | Elmore Review
Gordon, Peter. Adorno and Existence. Cambridge:
Harvard University Press: 2015. 272. pp. $29.95.
0674734785 ISBN.
Peter Gordon’s Adorno and Existence is a beautiful and
compelling piece of philosophical and intellectual history.
Elegantly written and immaculately researched, Gordon’s text
stages Adorno’s complicated and conspicuously undertheorized relationship to “existentialism,” or to an entire
tradition of thinkers from Kierkegaard and Husserl to
Heidegger and Sartre in whom Adorno saw “a paradigmatic but
unsuccessful attempt to realize what would become his own
philosophical ambition, to break free of the systems of
idealism and to turn [...] ‘toward the concrete.’”1 For Gordon, it
is Adorno’s thoroughgoing commitment to materialism that
“explains his particular fascination with existential ontology,”
Adorno seeing in these ontologies a reflection, even if a failed
one, of his own insistence on the “preponderance of the
object.”2 Read in this light, Adorno’s encounter with
existentialism provides a background against which to
illuminate his own particular form of materialism, one that
rejects any forced reconciliation of subject and object. Setting
aside by and large the question of whether Adorno gets these
existential ontologies “right,” this broad framing makes Adorno
and Existence a text of interest to anyone working on or around
Adornian critical theory. It also forces Gordon to walk a fine
line between generous exegesis and uncritical fidelity. I think it
is one of the triumphs of this book to have combined
seamlessly the most charitable defense of Adorno’s readings of
Kierkegaard, Husserl, and Heidegger with a critical distance
1
Peter Eli. Gordon, Adorno and Existence (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 2015), xi.
2
Ibid., 196.
that will no doubt lead to renewed scholarly work on this
aspect of Adorno’s thought. In short, Adorno and Existence is a
must read for scholars in Adorno Studies, illuminating a little
discussed aspect of Adorno’s thought and shedding new light
on the character of his materialism.
Gordon’s text is organized around Adorno’s career-long
engagement with the work of Søren Kierkegaard and Martin
Heidegger, from his 1933 habilitation, Kierkegaard:
Construction of the Aesthetic and his 1932 lecture, “The Idea of
Natural History” to his 1963 Frankfurt Address published
under the title “Kierkegaard once more,” and his lengthy
confrontations with Heidegger in both The Jargon of
Authenticity (1964) and Negative Dialectics (1966). In addition,
there is a fascinating chapter dedicated to Adorno’s little
discussed book on Husserl, Against Epistemology, and
numerous short and illuminating sections on Adorno’s
relationship to the works of Beckett, Sartre, Hölderlin, Jaspers,
Benjamin, and Kafka among others. These shorter sections are
among my favorite of the book. Brimming with original
insights, they show that Adorno’s general concern with
existentialism’s return to the concrete was widely shared in the
philosophical and literary milieu of the post-war era.
Throughout the book, Gordon illustrates the textual
rigor of Adorno’s critique of Heidegger, Husserl, and
Kierkegaard, contesting the commonly held notion that
Adorno was simply a poor reader of these thinkers, and that
his encounter with existentialism was primarily polemical.
Instead, Gordon argues, Adorno reads Heidegger, Husserl, and
Kierkegaard as exemplars of what Gordon names “the
philosophy of bourgeois interiority,” or the “tendency to
esteem the contents of isolated consciousness over and against
Adorno Studies | 2018 | 1:2
3 | Elmore Review
the material world.”3 In Adorno’s estimation, existential
ontologies represented a covert form of bourgeois idealism, a
consistent privileging of subjectivity over objectivity that
necessarily undercut their stated goal of returning to the
concrete. Yet, he could not simply reject this idealism outright,
as such a move would uncritically resolve the dialectical
tension between thought and the world.4 Hence, Adorno’s
constant return to the critique of these philosophies was,
Gordon argues, an attempt to find in them “a paradoxical
simultaneity, between their manifest failure and their real—if
unrealized—promise.”5 In other words, it was an attempt to
articulate a materialism cognizant of the necessarily
unresolvable relationship between thought and the world
under capitalism, precisely by scrutinizing the failures of other
such attempts.
Although framed by Adorno’s shifting reading of
Kierkegaard, to which I shall return in a moment, it is Adorno’s
critique of Heidegger that lies at the heart of Gordon’s
analysis. This is because, as Gordon carefully shows, it was in
Heidegger’s work that Adorno saw the full-blown social and
political costs of the philosophy of bourgeois interiority.
Adorno’s critique of Heidegger rests on the claim that
fundamental ontology ultimately turns history into nature,
naturalizing existing social formations as necessary and
unavoidable.6 Furthermore, for Adorno, this naturalizing of
history results from the fact “that Heidegger’s neo-ontology
subscribes to idealism in two key respects.” On the one hand,
Heidegger’s thought contains an implicit commitment to the
“fantasy of holism,” and on the other hand, “neo-ontology
stresses ‘possibility’ over ‘reality,’ since it describes existence
primarily as a ‘project [Entwurf]’ that presses forward into the
future.”7 With respect to the first point, Adorno sees in
Heidegger’s implicit holism a tendency towards ontological
tautology, fundamental ontology telling the story of how
Dasein comes to be what it always already was, a logic that
affirms what is as the very expression of being.8 In the context
of Nazism and fascism, this naturalizing of existing social
realities takes on a particularly horrifying character, the real
hell of these social realities coming to be the implied
realization of being itself.
Now Gordon is quick to point out that Adorno’s
reading of Heidegger is far from uncontroversial.9 However, he
provides a compelling defense of this reading. For example, he
gives an absolutely marvelous account of Adorno’s essay
“Parataxis: On Hölderlin’s Late Poetry,” in which Adorno
shows that Heidegger misappropriates Hölderlin’s work by
reading “the poems as affirmations of ‘unity [Einheit]’ and
‘total identity [totale Identität]’” in a way that is completely at
odds with Hölderlin’s use of parataxis.10 Moreover, Gordon
shows the influence of other critics of Heidegger, in particular
Karl Löwith and Günther Anders, on Adorno’s critique.11 For
Gordon, one sees in Adorno the development of Anders’s
“claim that Heidegger was an idealist malgré lui,” this implicit
idealism leading to a dangerous naturalizing of the categories
7
3
Ibid., 4.
4
Ibid., 5-6.
5
Ibid., 6.
6
Ibid., 50.
Ibid., 55.
Ibid., 101.
9
Ibid., 50.
10
Ibid., 116-117.
11
Ibid., 129-136.
8
Adorno Studies | 2018 | 1:2
4 | Elmore Review
of Being.12 Gordon concedes that, in light of the growing
question of Heidegger’s Nazism, Adorno’s critique of
Heidegger develops a sharper, more polemical character in the
thirty years between “The Idea of Natural History” and
Negative Dialectics. At the same time, his reading nicely
illuminates how Adorno’s critique was hardly unprecedented, a
fact that contests the oft-cited claim by defenders of Heidegger
that Adorno was simply a poor reader of Heidegger’s project.
Importantly, Gordon emphasizes the role Adorno’s
own intellectual biography plays in his critique of
existentialism. This aspect of Gordon’s project is foregrounded
in his chapter on Husserl. Written during his years of exile at
Oxford (1934-1937) and published in 1956, Against
Epistemology is Adorno’s little discussed critique of
transcendental phenomenology. As Gordon notes, for Adorno,
“the key problem of Husserlian phenomenology is that it seeks
to discover the foundations of objectivity within the horizon of
the subject” remaining necessarily “locked within the
constitutive thesis of transcendental idealism.”13 The
constitutive thesis of transcendental idealism is not merely a
privileging of subject over object but, more crucially, a
commitment to “constitutive subjectivity,” the more or less
“seamless reconciliation between subject and object.”14 It is
this supposed reconciliation that Adorno fundamentally rejects
in existential ontologies as a whole.
Gordon draws attention to the way in which this
commitment to reconciliation must be thought not only within
the context of the rising tide of fascism in Europe, but also
against “the background of [Adorno’s] exile and isolation” in
Oxford. Alone in strange surroundings, having been forced out
of Germany, and confronted by the death of both his Aunt
Agathe and his long time mentor Alban Berg, it is perhaps little
wonder that Adorno would be ready to “bury himself in the
texts of classical phenomenology” and that the irreconcilability
of the subject with the world would be foremost in his
thoughts.15 These materialist moments of intellectual
biography are fantastic, not simply for the insights they offer
into Adorno’s intellectual life, but also for the way they
foreground Adorno’s own insistence that theorizing existing
social relations must be materialist through and through.
This question of what materialist insights Adorno
garners from his encounter with existentialism brings us to
what Gordon takes to be the lesson of Adorno’s reading of
Kierkegaard. Having tirelessly traced Adorno’s critique of
existentialism, a critique that began with his 1933 dissertation
on the role of the aesthetic in Kierkegaard’s philosophy, Adorno
and Existence ends with an analysis of Adorno’s final essay on
the Danish philosopher, “Kierkegaard once more” delivered in
Frankfurt in 1963. In this essay, Adorno reads Kierkegaard as
offering a critical resistance to existentialism’s theme of
constitutive subjectivity and the naturalization of history.
More specifically, this lecture contests the prevailing
glorification of Kierkegaard by Karl Jaspers and Emanuel
Hirsch, who saw in him an expression of a nationalistic,
German Christianity. For Adorno, this reading totally misses
“the truth content of Kierkegaard’s work” by obscuring his
insistence on radical individualism in the face of logic of social
12
Ibid., 134.
Ibid., 41.
14
Ibid., 38.
13
15
Ibid., 59.
Adorno Studies | 2018 | 1:2
5 | Elmore Review
conformity.16 In fact, Gordon argues that for Adorno one must
“distinguish Kierkegaard from all of the so-called
existentialists who appeared in the twentieth century,” as his
“‘open’ style of philosophical argumentation [...] cultivates
paradox and tarries with the negative, foregoing any
premature bid for resolution.”17 Despite his commitment to a
Christian theological framework, one that Adorno saw as
fundamentally idealist, there is nonetheless a basic resistance
to the reconciliation of subject and object in Kierkegaard’s
thought. It was this fundamental resistance, Gordon argues,
that Adorno wished to rescue from existentialism as a whole.
Through a fascinating reading of Kafka’s “Die Sorge des
Hausvaters” (The care of a family man), Gordon illustrates that
Adorno was already thinking through this element of rescue, in
the form of an “inverse theology,” from his very first work on
Kierkegaard.18
object.”20 However, while I agree that one can articulate
Adorno’s materialism through the lens of an inverse theology,
reversing the traditional theological notion of redemption in
order to take “an unflinching and unapologetic view of social
suffering,” I am not convinced that the language of inverse
theology helps us to concretize Adorno’s materialism as much
as Gordon suggests.21 Why is the notion of an inverse theology
better equipped than the language of Marxist political
economy or the language of the commodity form to illuminate
Adorno’s materialism? For example, when Adorno writes in
Negative Dialectics, “[i]f no man had part of his labor withheld
from him any more, rational identity would be a fact, and
society would have transcended the identifying mode of
thinking,” this directly Marxist assertion seems to me a much
more concrete way of articulating Adorno’s materialism than
inverse theology.22
Now, I do question how useful it is to articulate
Adorno’s materialism in the term of “inverse theology.” There
is no doubt that, as Adorno and Existence powerfully shows,
Adorno’s encounter with existentialism crystallizes what would
be the central commitment of Adorno’s materialism, namely,
stalwart resistance to any form of reductive or “positive”
materialism that promises a seamless reconciliation between
subject and world.19 It is this commitment that Adorno saw as
the unfulfilled promise of the philosophies of bourgeois
interiority and which Gordon’s text convincingly connects to
Adorno’s own insistence on the “preponderance of the
This is not to suggest that Gordon does not,
throughout Adorno and Existence, assert the importance of
Adorno’s Marxism in his encounter with existentialism. Yet
this key aspect of Adorno’s thought is never fully engaged,
limited primarily to a few pages towards the end of the text.23
This element remains the central issue that I wish Gordon had
developed further. Now this is in part a selfish wish, as I would
have loved to see what Gordon would have done with such an
analysis. However, I also suspect that part of the reason this
issue remains underdeveloped is that a more concrete, Marxist
account of Adorno’s materialism would sit uneasily with a
20
Ibid., 196.
Ibid., 181.
22
Theodor W. Adorno, Negative Dialectics (London: Bloomsbury, 1981),
16
Ibid., 183.
17
Ibid., 182.
18
Ibid.,173-182
19
Ibid., 197.
21
147.
23
Gordon, Adorno and Existence, 150, 161-162, 187-188.
Adorno Studies | 2018 | 1:2
6 | Elmore Review
materialism framed as an inverse theology. In any case, a fuller
account of this theme would have only added to what is a truly
spectacular book, and its absence does not change my
assessment that Adorno and Existence will lead to renewed
interest in Adorno’s relationship to Kierkegaard, Husserl, and
Heidegger, as well as existentialism more generally, and that it
will inspire an entirely new and exciting body of literature.
Works Cited
Adorno, Theodor. Negative Dialectics. London: Bloomsbury,
1981.
Gordon, Peter Eli. Adorno and Existence. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 2016.
Adorno Studies | 2018 | 1:2