Introduction: changing views of syntactic change
THERESA BIBERAUER & GEORGE WALKDEN
Department of Theoretical & Applied Linguistics, University
of Cambridge, and Department of Linguistics & English
Language, University of Manchester
NB: This is a post-print version reflecting changes made in the
peer review and editing process, but not the publisher’s PDF.
This chapter appeared in Biberauer & Walkden (eds.) (2015),
Syntax over time, 1–13 (Oxford University Press); when citing,
please use the page numbers given there. The publisher should
be contacted for permission to re-use or reprint the material in
any form.
1. INTRODUCTION
There is no such thing as syntactic change, and this is a book
about it.1
In some approaches and frameworks, change is seen as
integral to the very nature of language: for instance, Bailey’s
(1981, 1996) Developmental Linguistics, or Hopper’s (1987)
Emergent Grammar. By contrast, generative work on historical
linguistics as represented at the Diachronic Generative Syntax
(DiGS) conferences has led to a picture in which, in at least
three respects, syntactic change does not exist.2
1
The first of these respects relates to the object of study
itself. Within the Chomskyan tradition since Aspects (Chomsky
1965), this object has always been the competence of the
individual speaker-hearer, or I-language (Chomsky 1986);
proposed larger-scale entities, such as Saussure’s (1979 [1916])
langue, or the ‘community grammar’ of Weinreich, Labov &
Herzog (1968), have always been firmly rejected as incoherent
or undefinable. But if such entities do not exist, then how can
they change? Hence, Lightfoot (1991: 162) takes the position
that when we speak about a change in, say, the syntax of
French, we are adopting ‘a convenient fiction permitting the
statement of certain generalizations’. Hale (1998: 2–3) argues
that change should be understood simply as a set of differences
between two individual grammars. In the introduction to a
previous DiGS proceedings volume, Crisma & Longobardi
(2009: 5) attempt to understand these relations between
grammars and partially formalize them as historically
significant relations, or ‘H-relations’.3 However, this relational
conception of ‘change’ bears little resemblance to our
pretheoretical understanding of the notion.
In principle, of course, individual grammars are subject
to change, and in this limited sense, syntactic change can be
said to exist. However, one of the results of research into
language acquisition has been the finding that, after the
acquisition period, the possibility for the internalized grammar
2
of an individual to change is severely restricted (see e.g.
Clahsen 1991; Meisel 1995, 2011). Examples of syntactic
change during the lifespan of individual speakers have been
presented: Wagner & Sankoff (2011) present findings
indicating that speakers of Montreal French have moved away
from the periphrastic aller ‘to go’ + infinitive in favour of the
inflectional future tense over a 13-year period, Tagliamonte &
D’Arcy (2007) have demonstrated an increase in the frequency
of use of be like quotatives in Ontario speakers of English over
7 years (see Haddican, Zweig & Johnson, this volume, on
change in the syntactic and semantic components of this
construction). This indicates that some plasticity remains;
nevertheless, “virtually all of the evidence for ongoing
linguistic change in adulthood derives from an increase in
frequency” of one of two pre-existing synonymous options
(Tagliamonte & D’Arcy 2009: 61) rather than from the
introduction or loss of a discrete grammatical possibility (see in
this connection also the striking findings of Heycock, Sorace,
Hansen & Wilson (2013) regarding the on-going loss of V-to-T
movement in modern-day Faroese; as Heycock et al. show, this
option is in fact initially produced and accepted by pre-school
children, before declining as they get older, with ten-year olds
exhibiting adult production and judgements). So true syntactic
change within individual grammars, while a logical possibility,
may not exist in practice either.
3
Even assuming that some notion of syntactic change
beyond the individual is coherent, another perspective on the
non-existence of syntactic change is provided by the Inertial
Theory of Longobardi (2001). Under this perspective, it is
hypothesized that syntactic change must be ‘a well-motivated
consequence of other types of change’ and ‘may only originate
as an interface phenomenon’ (2001: 278).4 In other words,
when syntactic change occurs, it is not primitive but always
parasitic on a change in other linguistic domains, for instance a
phonological, morphological, or semantic innovation. This is a
specific instantiation of a general principle summarized by
Keenan (2002: 149) as ‘Things stay as they are unless acted
upon by an outside force or DECAY’ (see also Keenan 1994,
2009). This idea, though not uncontroversial (see Walkden
2012, and Maling & Sigurjónsdóttir, this volume), has spurred
21st-century diachronic syntacticians to investigate interactions
between different linguistic modules, and the study of these
interactions is a major focus of this volume.
Thirdly and finally, theoretical developments within the
Principles & Parameters framework have independently led to
the conclusion that syntactic change does not exist. Early
Principles & Parameters work hypothesized that there existed a
set of syntactic principles that could be parameterized: for
instance, Subjacency (stated in Chomsky 1973 as a condition;
later reformulated as a principle) states that there exist
4
bounding nodes inhibiting movement, and is parameterized as
to which nodes count as bounding nodes in a given language.
With the move to Minimalism, Chomsky (1995a: 131) adopted
a suggestion originally made by Borer (1984): the syntactic
computational component of human language is invariant, with
inter-speaker variation existing only within the lexicon, and
perhaps only within the functional subset of the lexicon. This
proposal, dubbed the Borer-Chomsky Conjecture by Baker
(2008: 353), has an immediate conceptual advantage, lucidly
stated by Borer (1984: 29):
The inventory of inflectional rules and of grammatical
formatives in any given language is idiosyncratic and
learned on the basis of input data. If all interlanguage
variation is attributable to that system, the burden of
learning is placed exactly on that component of
grammar for which there is strong evidence of learning:
the vocabulary and its idiosyncratic properties.
The consolidation of linguistic variation in the lexical
component has an obvious consequence for the study of syntax
diachronically: if there can be no such thing as lexiconindependent syntactic variation, then there can be no such thing
as lexicon-independent syntactic change, and developments
previously classed as syntactic changes must be
5
reconceptualized as lexical changes. Interestingly, the same
conclusion results if we adopt Chomsky’s more recent
argument in favour of the idea that parameters may in fact be
exclusively located at PF, the interface leading to the sensorymotor systems. On this view, there is once again, no variation
internal to the syntactic component, with ‘diversity resulting
from complex and highly varied modes of externalization,
which, furthermore, are readily susceptible to historical change’
(Berwick & Chomsky 2011). Here, then, ‘syntactic change’ is
actually morphophonological.
If, as we have suggested here, developments within
generative syntactic theory have led to the view that syntactic
change does not exist, one might conclude that the theory is
worthless for the investigation of diachronic issues, or, at the
very least, question the validity of continuing to adopt it. We
would argue, however, that the opposite is true, and that the
perspectives afforded by these theoretical developments have
shed new light on the phenomenon of syntactic change as
pretheoretically understood. In the remainder of this
introduction we will explain why we think this is the case.
Mirroring the structure of the volume, the three following
sections outline three main directions in which we feel progress
is being made: lexical, morphological, and informationstructural interactions.
6
2. SYNTAX AND THE LEXICON
Though the adoption of the Borer-Chomsky Conjecture, in
which syntactic variation is understood as lexical, may at first
glance seem to be a trivial terminological matter, we would
argue that it has in fact led to advances in understanding and to
a widening of the field’s scope of inquiry.
In early DiGS work, the focus was overwhelmingly on
macro-level properties of languages; thus the proceedings
volume from the first DiGS conference, Battye & Roberts
(1995), had clause structure as its theme, and was heavily
focused on the verb-second property, the null subject
parameter, the Head Parameter and related issues. These
properties are still the subject of detailed work in the current
literature, though the focus has shifted towards the interpretive
correlates of these different constructions (see section 4).
Complementing these big-picture issues, however, the DiGS
literature has increasingly seen investigations of the syntactic
properties of individual lexical items and their interactions with
the larger system of which they form a part, with authors
making existential, rather than universal, claims about the
languages under investigation. This development, a natural
consequence of the Borer-Chomsky approach to syntactic
variation, is paralleled by a renewed focus on microvariation in
synchronic syntax along the lines sketched in Kayne (2005a). It
also opens the door to a better formal understanding of
7
processes of grammaticalization, which fell largely outside the
remit of traditional ‘macrodiachronic’ syntax: foundational
works here, arguing that grammaticalization can be understood
as change in the featural makeup of lexical items, include
Roberts & Roussou (1999, 2003) and van Gelderen (2004,
2011). This focus is a hallmark of 21st-century DiGS work,
with an entire proceedings volume (Batllori et al. 2005) themed
around the relationship between grammaticalization and
parametric variation.
This ‘microdiachronic syntax’ is also well represented
in the present volume by the six chapters that constitute Part 1,
Syntax and the Lexicon. Light, for instance, is a treatment of
expletives in the West Germanic languages, with particular
reference to Early New High German and Old English, and is a
fine example of how careful analysis of the properties of
individual lexical items can inform bigger-picture issues. The
Early New High German da and its Old English cognate þær
are both analysed as SpecTP expletives. As a consequence,
Light argues that the EPP, as a requirement for subjects to fill
SpecTP, was more broadly active across early Germanic than
previously thought.
The key tool of the DiGS trade has always been careful
philological and corpus-based study of historical texts. Finegrained microdiachronic research, however, necessitates the
development of new ways of studying syntactic variation and
8
change. Maling & Sigurjónsdóttir contribute to a lively debate
about the Icelandic ‘new’ construction, which has been
analysed as both a passive and an impersonal. Their aim is to
assess various more nuanced predictions of the two analyses,
taking into account how the new construction interacts with
different lexical items such as bound anaphors and nonagentive verbs. To this end, they employ the methodology of
dialect syntax, basing their conclusions on acceptability
judgement questionnaires. The results – demonstrating
extensive variability – inform our understanding not only of
modern Icelandic, but of syntactic change in general, on the
basis that ‘the same mechanisms which operated to produce the
large-scale changes of the past may be observed operating in
the current changes taking place around us’ (Labov 1972: 161).
Haddican, Zweig & Johnson similarly focus on a present-day
construction undergoing change, namely the be like quotative
in English. Their chapter supplements earlier corpus-based
studies with experimental results, demonstrating that be like,
originally stative, is increasingly acceptable for younger
speakers with an eventive, quotative function; nevertheless,
they argue that the spread of stative and eventive be like is part
of a single process of change along the lines of the Constant
Rate Hypothesis of Kroch (1989). The analysis of the
construction – involving a null lexical item SOMETHING (see
Kayne 2007) – furthermore has interesting implications for the
9
interaction of syntax, semantics and the lexicon. Clearly, both
dialect-syntactic and experimental methodology constitute a
valuable addition to the diachronic syntactician’s toolbox.
Prepositions are of special interest from the point of
view of the Borer-Chomsky Conjecture, since they have always
occupied an uneasy middle ground between functional and
lexical categories. Within Minimalism, the study of the fine
structure of prepositions and prepositional phrases has
flourished, particularly in work by Svenonius (2008, 2010),
applied to the history of English by Waters (2009). Hegedűs
extends this approach to the grammaticalization of
postpositions from nouns in the history of Hungarian, arguing
that here, too, we see a clear case of an ‘adposition cycle’.
Using a structure proposed by Svenonius, Hegedűs
demonstrates that the grammaticalization process does not
proceed directly from noun to postposition but rather through
an intermediate category of AxialPart. This chapter, then, offers
an excellent illustration of how a theoretical approach that
draws fine-grained featural (categorial) distinctions allows us to
understand grammaticalization in a more articulated fashion
than is usual in more traditional approaches. As pointed out in
Roberts (2010), this type of approach may also facilitate novel
insight into notoriously challenging synchronic and diachronic
questions of gradience and gradualness.
10
Negation has always been the poster-child for formal
approaches to cyclical change, and the literature on the subject
from the 21st century alone is extensive: see Larrivée (2011)
and Willis, Breitbarth & Lucas (2013) for overviews. In the
present volume, too, negation is well represented. The chapters
by É. Kiss and Martins both seek to understand the emergence
of negative indefinites, in Hungarian and Portuguese
respectively. The se-indefinites discussed by É. Kiss originally
arose through univerbation of a negative particle with a (nonnegative) indefinite, but over time their negative semantics
were bleached, such that in Modern Hungarian they are
required to occur in a Negative Concord configuration with an
independent negative particle. É. Kiss argues that word order
changes played a role in this development. The indefinite
quantifier algum discussed by Martins, on the other hand,
develops into a negative indefinite without overt univerbation,
and is argued to be so by virtue of its incorporation (along with
the noun) into an abstract DP-internal negative head; the
proposal thus has consequences for the debate surrounding the
cartography of the nominal domain generally (see Alexiadou,
Haegeman & Stavrou 2009, and Alexiadou 2014 for overview
discussion) and the internal structure of negative DPs more
specifically (see i.a. Déprez 2000, Martins 2000, Poletto 2008,
and Biberauer & Roberts 2011).
11
It is clear, then, that, far from stifling inquiry into
syntactic change, adoption of a lexicocentric perspective on
variation has enriched diachronic syntax in terms of both
methodology and empirical coverage. We began this section by
highlighting the ‘macro’ orientation of the earliest DiGS work,
which was very centrally concerned with properties associated
with parameters – the verb-second parameter, the null subject
parameter, and the head parameter, for example. Interestingly,
the term ‘parameter’ is not mentioned in any of the six
contributions in this section of the volume. On the one hand,
one might interpret this as indicative of the notion having
outlived its usefulness (see Newmeyer 2004, Boeckx 2010)
Alternatively, this can be seen as a reflection of the way in
which the notion has been refined in the context of Chomsky’s
(2005) ‘three factors’ approach to language design (see
Biberauer 2008, Roberts & Holmberg 2010, Biberauer &
Roberts 2014, and the work of the “Rethinking Comparative
Syntax” project more generally). On this latter view, all of the
phenomena discussed in this section would instantiate lexically
specified parameters of different sizes (see again Biberauer &
Roberts 2014 on the question of ‘parameter size’).
3. SYNTAX AND MORPHOLOGY
Exploring the interactions between morphology and syntax is
not a new endeavour. Within Principles and Parameters, a
12
series of works have proposed strong (often biconditional)
relationships between aspects of morphological paradigms and
syntactic parameter settings. For instance, the richness of case
morphology has been linked to the possibility of certain word
orders or word-order variation, implementing ‘the traditional
idea that inflectional morphology and positional constraints are
functionally equivalent elements of grammatical structure’
(Kiparsky 1997: 461; see also Weerman 1988, 1997).
Similarly, V-to-T movement has been linked to the richness of
verbal morphology (Roberts 1985, 1993; Bobaljik &
Thráinsson 1998; Rohrbacher 1999; Vikner 1997), as has the
availability of null subjects (Taraldsen 1978; Rohrbacher 1999;
Müller 2005, 2008; Tamburelli 2006). A full review of this
literature can be found in Biberauer & Roberts (2010), who
suggest that the properties licensing V-to-T and null subjects
should be kept apart, though they retain the connection between
morphology and both properties.
The diachronic consequences of such deterministic
interrelationships between morphology and syntax are obvious:
if certain morphological changes occur, then syntactic changes
will necessarily follow. Thus, if we assume (following
Biberauer & Roberts 2010) that V-to-T movement requires rich
tense morphology, then if such morphology is lost then V-to-T
movement must also be lost. Since morphological change can
often be motivated independently (e.g. through regular sound
13
change, or language contact), this gives us a ready-made causal
chain for syntactic developments. A whole DiGS volume
(Lightfoot 2002) has previously been dedicated to precisely this
issue.
This simple picture, in which morphological change
triggers syntactic change, is intuitively appealing, but evidence
has emerged in recent years that suggests that it is in fact too
good to be true. For instance, in modern standard English,
indirect objects precede direct objects in neutral declaratives,
but in the history of the language this was not always the case;
a strong version of the morphology-syntax link would then
predict that word-order variability was possible as long as case
morphology distinguished accusative and dative. Allen (2001),
however, shows that the modern order did not become fixed
until the last quarter of the fourteenth century, whereas the
dative/accusative distinction had been lost in most dialects by
the first quarter of the thirteenth. Unless we want to posit that
for a period of 150 years learners entertained morphologically
unsupported and thus impossible grammars, then, the
deterministic relationship between morphology and syntax
must be rethought. Similarly, empirical difficulties with
deterministic proposals lead Holmberg (2005: 560) to propose
that the correlation between null subjects and rich agreement is
‘due not to a rule or condition of (narrow) syntax … but to
sentence processing’ (see also Ackema & Neeleman 2007).
14
The five contributions collected in part two of this
volume all point towards the conclusion that the traditional
hypothesis, in which morphology drives syntax, is at best only
partially correct. Reintges, for instance, observes that there
exists another logical possibility in a Minimalist framework:
syntactic changes may lead to morphological changes, the
opposite of the traditional view. He illustrates this ‘exogenous’
morphological change with reference to two developments in
Later Egyptian, arguing that the emergence of discourseconfigurationality (itself contact-induced) triggers the
grammaticalization of new evidential and modal marking and
new relative tenses.
Another logical possibility is for morphophonologically
conditioned alternations to become syntacticized, and this is
exactly what Ledgeway argues has happened in the dialects of
the Salento region in Italy. In these dialects, the
complementizer cu can be deleted under certain conditions.
This deletion appears to be ordered after raddoppiamento
fonosintattico, a process which lengthens the first consonant of
a following word, suggesting that deletion is a purely
phonological process. Ledgeway argues that this is correct for
southern Salentino, but not for the northern dialects, for which
he adduces evidence to show that raddoppiamento
fonosintattico has been reanalysed as an irrealis marker. This
sort of syntacticization of an originally phonological process is
15
consistent with what has been reported in the literature on the
life cycle of phonological processes (see, for example,
Bermúdez-Otero & Trousdale 2012).
Julien looks at a case in which a morphological form
takes on a new function. In some Uralic languages, a past
participle can be used in the negated past without giving rise to
a perfective reading. Julien argues that the introduction of a
new copula was central to this development as it led to surface
forms which a new generation of acquirers could analyse as
including an overt realisation requirement on finiteness.
Confronted with conservative, copula-lacking present perfect
negative structures featuring just a participle alongside the
negation element, the new generation thus concluded that these
forms in fact contrast with the likewise copula-lacking, but
crucially finite-marked negative presents. This resulted in the
original non-finite participial form being reanalysed as a finite
past form. This reanalysis of the verbal inflection marking, in
turn, triggered a reordering of the heads in the clausal
hierarchy, with Tense and Polarity being inverted in the
innovative grammar. Morphological reanalysis, then, drives
syntactic reanalysis, with a domain that has been shown to vary
crosslinguistically, rather than following a universally fixed
hierarchical ordering – negation and polarity (see Cinque 1999,
and Laka 1994) – being affected by the change.
16
Migdalski’s chapter provides another illustration of how
morphology may drive syntax. He shows that in some Slavic
languages, such as Serbo-Croatian, clitics changed from being
verb-adjacent to occupying second position. Migdalski relates
this to the loss of tense distinctions in verbal morphology,
which was contemporaneous with the shift to second-position
clitics in various Slavic dialects. These changes he interprets as
signalling the loss of T, a category which has been argued not
to be universally present (see, for example, Bošković 2012, and
also Ritter & Wiltschko in press). Strikingly, T-less languages
are predicted to lack expletives, subject-object asymmetries,
and, Migdalski argues, sequence of tense effects, i.e. a diverse
cluster of properties of the type that one might have expected of
a classical parameter. If Migdalski’s analysis is on the right
track, it is clear that morphological change may have farreaching and diverse consequences.
Like Allen (2001), Michelioudakis deals with a change
in which the supposed syntactic effects of a morphological
change seem to lag behind. While morphological dative case is
lost during the Hellenistic Greek period, Michelioudakis traces
the effects of abstract, inherent, interpretable dative Case into
Medieval Cypriot Greek; a later reanalysis as uninterpretable is
merely facilitated by, and not deterministically triggered by, the
earlier morphological change.
17
What the contributions in this section signal, then, is,
that despite the proliferation of work on morphology-syntax
interactions over the last thirty years, much more still remains
to be done. Diachronic data are of particular interest for the
study of these interactions, as they allow the investigation of
temporally adjacent varieties that differ only minimally. The
contributions in this section represent a small step towards this
goal.
4. SYNTAX, PROSODY AND INFORMATION
STRUCTURE
One of the most striking features of this volume is the number
of contributions that go beyond the ‘core functional categories’
C, T and v to assume a more articulated functional domain.
This type of work is typical of the ‘cartographic’ research
programme, which has its roots in papers like Pollock (1989)
but which crystallized in the late 1990s with the decomposition
of the IP-domain by Cinque (1999) and of the CP-domain by
Rizzi (1997); see Cinque & Rizzi (2010) for an overview. Most
of the chapters in this volume exhibit the influence of the
cartographic enterprise: as we have already noted, Hegedűs is
inspired by cartographic analysis of the PP, while Julien makes
use of an articulated IP. Most influential, however, has been the
work of Rizzi (1997) on the clausal left periphery: the chapters
by Reintges, Ledgeway, Hill, Walkden, Cormany, Danckaert,
18
Hinterhölzl, and Wallenberg all make explicit reference to a
Rizzian left periphery in their analyses. This reflects a broader
concern with information structure that is showcased in the
third and longest part of this book, and also a recognition that
the facts of historically attested languages – within and outside
the Indo-European family – are not easily accounted for using
only the limited palette of functional categories provided in
Chomsky (1995a).5
Information structure as object of study sits uneasily
between pragmatics, semantics and syntax: Vallduví (1992)
and Lambrecht (1994) are key early works, and Krifka (2008)
provides a readable introduction. That the field is still in its
infancy is attested by the fact that there is still substantial
disagreement over the crucial theoretical primitives involved.
Some notion of topic and focus is assumed by just about
everyone, though definitions differ: while the chapters in this
section by Hill, Walkden and Cormany largely focus on topics,
focus is the topic of the chapters by Danckaert, Taylor &
Pintzuk, Hinterhölzl, and Wallenberg. In addition, contrast
deserves some mention here: while Rizzi (1997) makes no
reference to it, it has been argued to exist as a primitive
information-structural feature by Molnár (2001) and others
(e.g. É. Kiss 1998; see also the contributions to the (2010)
Lingua special edition on ‘Contrast as an information-structural
notion in grammar’), and Neeleman, Titov, van de Koot &
19
Vermeulen (2009) assume that [contrast] is a privative feature
which can be present or absent on topics and foci.
The study of information-structural interactions in
formal diachronic syntax is a recent development, but one that
has proven extremely productive, as the collections of papers in
Hinterhölzl & Petrova (2009a), Ferraresi & Lühr (2010) and
Meurman-Solin, López-Couso & Los (2012) illustrate. The
crucial notions, however, are not new at all. Work by the
Prague School (e.g. Firbas 1966; Halliday 1967) assumes a
principle of given-before-new. A similar principle is present in
Behaghel’s (1932: 4) Second Law: ‘Es stehen die alten Begriffe
vor den neuen’ (old expressions come before new ones). The
broadening of generative studies to include notions of
information status as possible determinants of syntactic
structure thus represents something of a unification of two
traditions.
If one assumes the existence of purely informationstructural functional projections, a further important question
is: where are they located? Rizzi’s (1997) original proposal
locates them at the left periphery of the clause. Belletti (2001,
2004) has argued that there also exists a ‘low left periphery’
above vP, with Poletto (2006, 2014) motivating a clauseinternal left periphery of this kind for Old Italian; Danckaert
and Wallenberg further explore this possibility. Hill, in turn,
proposes a further left periphery: one that lies at the edge of the
20
DP. Focusing on the development of the Romanian object
marker pe, Hill shows that it is no longer a preposition, as it
was in Old Romanian, but now serves to mark contrastive
topics. If CP, vP and DP may each have a separate informationstructurally active left periphery, it is tempting to suggest that
this possibility is definitive of non-defective phasehood.
Another indication of the immaturity of studies on
syntax-information structure interactions is the fact that Rizzi’s
(1997) model of the left periphery has been adapted in two
different, and fundamentally incompatible, ways, by Benincà &
Poletto (2004) on the one hand and Frascarelli & Hinterhölzl
(2007) on the other, based largely on exactly the same language
(Italian). The information-structural part of Rizzi’s original
split CP is given in (1), that of Benincà & Poletto in (2), and
that of Frascarelli & Hinterhölzl in (3).
(1)
Top* > Foc > Top*
(Rizzi 1997: 297)
(2)
Hanging Topic > Scene Setting > Left Dislocated > List
Interpretation > Contrastive Focus (adverbs/objects) >
Contrastive Focus (circumstantial adverbs) >
Information Focus
(Benincà & Poletto 2004: 71)
(3)
Aboutness Topic > Contrastive Topic > Focus >
Familiar Topic*
21
(Frascarelli & Hinterhölzl 2007: 112–113)
As can be seen, Benincà & Poletto (2004) and Frascarelli &
Hinterhölzl (2007) decompose the upper Topic field in
different ways. Furthermore, while Benincà & Poletto (2004)
do away with the lower Topic field entirely, Frascarelli &
Hinterhölzl (2007) argue that it is reserved for ‘familiar’ topics,
i.e. those that are simply given information, as opposed to those
which define ‘what the sentence is about’ (Reinhart 1981). If
progress is to be made, tensions like these must be resolved.
Walkden argues that the preverbal element in early West
Germanic V3 constructions meets the description of Frascarelli
& Hinterhölzl’s (2007) Familiar Topic, thus providing some
small support for the notion of a Topic field in the lowest part
of the CP-domain. Walkden argues that the V3 pattern is a
retention from Proto-West Germanic, and that generalized V2
was most likely a later development.
If a left-peripheral ‘template’ such as that proposed by
Rizzi (1997), Benincà & Poletto (2004), and Frascarelli &
Hinterhölzl (2007) turns out to be the right way to analyse
interactions between syntax and information structure at the left
periphery, a further question arises: are all of the functional
projections present in all languages, or can they be syncretized
in some languages, as proposed by Giorgi & Pianesi (1997) for
the IP-domain? Cormany suggests that syncretism is possible
22
through a process of conflation of left-peripheral projections
diachronically, drawing his evidence from a corpus study of
historical Friulano. Specifically, doubling of various types of
subjects becomes increasingly possible in the history of
Friulano, and the emergence of the possibility of doubling each
kind of subject occurs in just the order that an account based on
conflation of left-peripheral projections would suggest.
Little has been said about focus so far in this section,
though this is probably the information-structural category on
which the most has been written. The remaining chapters in
part three of this volume all address accounts based on focus.
Like topic, focus is likely not an irreducible notion: É. Kiss
(1998), for example, distinguishes identificational focus –
representing the exhaustive subset of the set of contextually or
situationally given elements for which the predicate phrase
holds – from information focus (or presentational focus), which
simply represents new or non-presupposed information (see
also Cruschina 2012 for illuminating overview discussion).
Belletti (2001, 2004) then argues that identificational focus is
associated with the FocP in the clausal left periphery, while
information focus is associated with the ‘low’ left-peripheral
FocP above vP. However, as Danckaert observes, Latin seems
to counterexemplify this insofar as information foci may occur
in the high left periphery of subordinate clauses in the Archaic
and early Classical periods of this language. Rather than
23
abandon Belletti’s generalization, Danckaert suggests that the
apparent violation in Latin occurs because the lower FocP is
made unavailable by independent movement operations;
movement to the higher FocP, which is normally a position for
identificational foci, then represents the syntax – or, recalling
Berwick & Chomsky’s (2011) take on the actual locus of what
is typically described as ‘syntactic variation’, PF – making the
best out of a bad situation. For Batllori & Hernanz, too, the
opposition between two types of focus is crucial. Their
empirical starting point is the fact that, while both Old Spanish
and Old Catalan allow weak (=information) focus fronting,
modern Catalan only allows it with quantifier phrases. Batllori
& Hernanz analyse weak focus fronting as movement to a
dedicated specifier position in the lower part of the clausal left
periphery, following Benincà & Poletto’s (2004) cartography.
They hypothesize that in Catalan this position was lost, and that
weak focus fronting was consequently reanalysed as targeting
the specifier of a Polarity Phrase just below it, accounting for
the restriction of fronting to quantifier phrases in this language.
As well as information structure, Hinterhölzl addresses
a further important interaction: the interplay between syntax
and prosody. The ambitious goal of his chapter is to reduce all
word-order variation to the requirements of prosodic and
information-structural conditions. Hinterhölzl argues that Old
High German, like the other early Germanic languages,
24
exhibited mixed OV/VO properties, and analyses this in terms
of a Kaynean universal base combined with the possibility to
spell out lower copies in movement chains. The choice of
which copy to spell out is then resolved with reference to
prosodic requirements, e.g. whether the constituent is
branching or non-branching, and information-structural
requirements, e.g. given vs. new.
It is clear that investigating information-structural and
prosodic interactions in diachrony is a productive line of
inquiry. However, it is only intellectually responsible to do so
if reliable, replicable methods for identifying informationstructural categories can be developed. Taylor & Pintzuk
outline such a method, annotating objects in Old English for
their prosodic weight and for whether they represent given or
new information. Their findings, they argue, provide evidence
that a one-to-one correspondence between VO order and new
information status cannot be maintained. Instead two
postverbal object positions must be postulated for Old English:
one associated exclusively with new information, and another
that is more information-structurally promiscuous. Taylor &
Pintzuk do not appeal to a cartographic template, instead
representing the position for new objects as right-adjunction to
TP; however, the data they present is consistent with an
account in which information-structural movement is to
25
specifiers of dedicated functional projections rather than
adjunction, and this is the topic of Wallenberg’s chapter.
Heavy NP Shift across Germanic is the empirical
domain of this chapter, which lays out a Kaynean cartographic
analysis in which ‘rightward’ focus movement is to FocP at the
clausal left periphery followed by remnant movement of the
rest of the clause to TopP. Using a quantitative approach,
Wallenberg compares this account to a traditional analysis in
terms of right-adjunction to either TP or vP, and finds that the
frequency of Heavy NP Shift is higher in Early Middle English
than in either Old or Early Modern English – a result predicted
under the traditional analysis, but not under the new one.
The closing chapter in this section is something of an
outlier, in that it explicitly argues against an informationstructural or prosodic analysis. Aldridge looks at pronominal
object shift in Archaic Chinese, which previous authors have
attempted to account for in terms of prosodically-motivated
cliticization (Feng 1996) or focus movement (Djamouri 1991,
2000). Aldridge shows that these analyses do not account for
the particular distribution of pronominal object shift, and
presents an alternative in which the pronoun is fronted in order
to value structural accusative Case. The analysis receives
support from diachronic facts: pronominal object shift declined
at the same time as morphological case was being lost on
pronouns. The chapter thus serves as a salutary reminder that
26
appealing to information-structural or prosodic motivations is
not the solution to all our problems, and that sometimes a more
traditional morphosyntactic account better fits the facts.
5. SUMMARY
The chapters collected in this volume show that historical work
within generative frameworks is branching out. Syntax within a
Minimalist framework may remain an autonomous module, but
it is ultimately responsible to its interfaces. This volume
showcases interactions between the syntactic component and
the lexicon, morphology, prosody and information structure.
Working on these interactions is not a simple task, and requires
interdisciplinary knowledge as well as new methods for
investigating change. The results of such work, however, can
shed new light on previously poorly-understood syntactic
alternations both synchronically and diachronically. Historical
work of this kind can also contribute to the ongoing
investigation of the Strong Minimalist Thesis: the claim that
language is an optimal solution to legibility conditions
(Chomsky 2000: 96). Studying lexical, morphological and
information-structural interactions will help us establish what
these legibility conditions are, and how individual languages
are configured to meet them in different places and at different
times – whether or not syntactic change, in the narrow sense,
really exists.
27
Acknowledgements
This volume has its origins in the 12th Diachronic Generative
Syntax Conference, held in Cambridge, 14th–16th July 2010.
The editors would like to express their gratitude to the staff of
Queens’ College, Cambridge, to the conference helper, Tim
Bazalgette, and particularly to our co-organizers, Alastair
Appleton, Elliott Lash, Dimitris Michelioudakis, and Ioanna
Sitaridou. Theresa Biberauer also gratefully acknowledges the
financial support of European Research Council Advanced
Grant No. 269752 “Rethinking Comparative Syntax” (ReCoS).
Thanks, too, to Anna Hollingsworth for her careful and
efficient creation of the index to this volume.
1
The first line of this introduction is a homage to Shapin
(1996: 1).
2
Cf. also, from a different perspective, Coseriu (1985). The
Diachronic Generative Syntax (DiGS) conference series, of
which the Cambridge instalment marked the 20th anniversary,
shares a set of core principles: an emphasis on rigorous
synchronic description, an emphasis on reliable and wellunderstood data, and scepticism towards independent
diachronic processes. A clear introduction to, and manifesto
for, the “DiGS approach” can be found in Whitman, Jonas &
Garrett (2012). In this introduction we focus only on those
trends in the field that have made themselves apparent over the
28
last few years and that seem to us to be the most exciting
directions of research.
3
Though it is important to recognize that, from an I-language
perspective, such relations are just as fictional and inchoate as
community grammars, as they depend crucially on the primary
corpus available to the learner, itself not easily definable or
delimitable. See Walkden (2014: 31–3) for discussion.
4
Interestingly, Stockwell (1976) makes exactly the same claim
a quarter of a century earlier: ‘the notion of ‘pure syntactic
change’ ... implies that there exists a class of formal changes
which are not motivated by semantic change or phonetic
change. I do not believe that is possible.’
5
Chomsky (2008: 143) explicitly states that CP in his work is
shorthand for the clausal region that Rizzi (1997) refers to as
the left periphery. Nevertheless, approaches to information
structure have been developed within Minimalism that do not
rely on an expanded cartographic left periphery: see Neeleman,
Titov, van de Koot & Vermeulen (2009), Fanselow &
Lenertova (2011), and Abels (2012), among others. Mensching
(2012) is a recent attempt to capture information-structural
generalizations in diachrony without additional functional
projections.
29