Academia.eduAcademia.edu

Necessary Assumptions

1999, Informal Logic 19 (1):41-61

https://doi.org/10.22329/il.v19i1.2314

In their book EVALUATING CRITICAL THINKING Stephen Norris and Robert Ennis say: “Although it is tempting to think that certain [unstated] assumptions are logically necessary for an argument or position, they are not. So do not ask for them.” Numerous writers of introductory logic texts as well as various highly visible standardized tests (e.g., the LSAT and GRE) presume that the Norris/Ennis view is wrong; the presumption is that many arguments have (unstated) necessary assumptions and that readers and test takers can reasonably be expected to identify such assumptions. This paper proposes and defends criteria for determining necessary assumptions of arguments. Both theoretical and empirical considerations are brought to bear.

Necessary Assumptions1 GILBERT PLUMER Law School Admission Council Abstract: In Evaluating Critical Thinking Stephen Norris and Robert Ennis say: "Although it is tempting to think that certain [unstated] assumptions are logically necessary for an argument or position, they are not. So do not ask: for them." Numerous introductory logic text authors and various highly visible standardized tests (e.g., the LSAT and ORE) presume that Norris and Ennis are wrong; the presumption is that many arguments have (unstated) necessary assumptions and readers and test takers can reasonably be expected to identify them. This paper proposes and defends criteria for determining necessary assumptions of arguments. Both theoretical and empirical considerations are brought to bear. Resume: Dans leur livre, Evaluating Critical Thinking, Stephen Norris et Robert Ennis disent: "Bien qu'on soit tente de croire que certaines suppositions [non-prononcees1 sont necessaires logiquement a un argument ou une position, elles n'en sont pas. Done, n'en demandez pas." Plusieurs auteurs des manuels introductoires de la logique et divers epreuves eta/onnees tres connues (e.g., Ie LSAT at Ie ORE) presument que Norris et Eimis ont tort; la presomption est que plusieurs arguments ont des suppositions necessaires [nonprononceesJet que c'est raisonnable d'attender aux liseurs et ceux qui se presentent aux epreuves de les cons tater. Dans cette communication je propose et defends des criteres pour cons tater les suppositions necessaires des arguments. On met en oeuvre les considerations et theoriques et empiriques. Keywords: Enthymeme, implicit assumption, missing premise, gap-filler, testing, principle of charity. In their book Evaluating Critical Thinking Stephen Norris and Robert Ennis say: "Although it is tempting to think that certain [unstated] assumptions are logically necessary for an argument or position, they are not. So do not ask for them . . . no significant assumptions are logically necessarily made."2 Numerous writers of introductory logic texts,) as well as various highly visible standardized tests, presume without giving much (or any) justification that the Norris-Ennis view is wrong; the presumption is that many arguments have (unstated) significant necessary assumptions and that readers and test takers can reasonably be expected to identify such assumptions. One such standardized test is the Law School Admission Test (LSA T) (another is the Graduate Record Examinations (GRE». This paper will propose criteria for determining necessary assumptions of arguments, criteria that I think are correct in themselves in addition to being appropriate for writers and reviewers of the kind of test that the LSA T represents: a measure of advanced yet nontechnical reasoning and reading abilities using the format of multiple-choice questions. The account will be defended against the kind of objections Norris and ©In/ormaLLogic Vol. 19, No.1 (1999): pp.41-61. 42 Gilbert Plumer Ennis raise, among other objections. Both theoretical and empirical considerations will be brought to bear in the course of my argument. I. Principal Necessary Assumption Criteria On the LSA T a typical necessary assumption question consists of a short argumentative passage, a question stem on the order of "The argument depends on assuming which one of the following?", and five answer choices. Notice that the focus is on the argument, rather than the arguer. Not only is the former more appropriate for logic (as opposed to psychology), but with no context other than the brief passage it would be unreasonable to ask the examinee to peer into the mind of the arguer to determine what the arguer is assuming. This focus on the argument helps to rule out certain necessary assumption pretenders. One kind of pretender is that of a presupposition or implication of a propositional element of the argument, be it a premise or conclusion. The truth of some proposition p may be a necessary condition for the truth of a statement s in an argument or a necessary condition for a term in s to have a referent, etc., but this does not make p a necessary assumption of the argument. One reason is that p is not presupposed by the argument as a whole; a proposition must be integral to the reasoning or inferential structure of an argument, not just to a claim made within the argument, in order for the proposition to be a necessary assumption of the argument (specific examples will be discussed as we proceed). Another, sometimes related, kind of necessary assumption pretender is that of a general presupposition of rationality. For instance, that it is possible to do X is not a necessary assumption of an argument to the effect that X ought to be done, even given that ought implies can. At best, that it is possible to do X would be a presupposition of a propositional element of the argument, viz., the conclusion, and the putative conceptual truth that ought implies can would be a presupposition of something that is so to speak larger than any particular argument, namely, rationality itself (unless, of course, such is the subject matter of the argument). Similarly, neither should we hold that a perfectly general rule of inference such as Modus Ponens is a necessary assumption of an argument that instantiates Modus Ponens. If we do, we embark on an infinite regress akin to Lewis Carroll's (discussed below in §IV). These sorts of considerations function as some antidote to the view that no proposed set of necessary assumptions of an argument, if the set is finite, is big enough.4 A criterion that is at least alluded to by virtually every writer on the subject is the idea that a necessary assumption must somehow fill a 'gap' in the stated argument's reasoning, thereby making the inference stronger than it otherwise would be. Michael Burke provides a more precise way of stating the criterion: a necessary assumption is "any proposition which needs to be Necessary Assumptions 43 true, if the inference is to be justified." However, Burke himself rejects this as unhelpful on the grounds that there are "infinitely many" such propositions. "Examples: that there is at least one inference; that there is at least one justified inference; that there is at least one thing that is either an inference or a polar bear."5 What this fact indicates is not that the gap-filling criterion is useless; instead, it indicates that the gap-filling criterion needs to be supplemented by other criteria. Because all of Burke's examples are presuppositions of rationality, or at least of the existence of rationality, none are necessary assumptions of any particular argument (unless, of course, such is the subject matter of the argument). As far as I can see, the most precise and perspicacious way that the subject matter will bear of stating the gap-filling criterion is as follows. GFC: It could not be the case both that the argument aside from the proposed necessary assumption is fully cogent and the proposed necessary assumption is false. In the GFC the central meaning of the clause that 'the argument aside from the proposed necessary assumption is fully cogent' is that given the truth of what I will call the received premises (i.e., all of the implicit and explicit premises, considered apart from the proposed necessary assumption), the conclusion can be inferred to be true. The standard of an allowable inference here is to be taken as varying in stringency according to whether the argument is deductive (in which case validity is the standard) or nondeductive. Of course a nondeductive argument may have a conclusion that is in fact false, yet it still be reasonable to infer that it is true from the truth of the premises. Cogency is perhaps a loose evaluative concept, but I take it to pertain only to an argument's reasoning or logic, not also to the truth value of its propositional elements (unlike the technical concept of soundness). And in no case is cogency purely a matter of formal validity. For example, adding the stated conclusion or the contradictory of a stated premise to the stated premises would make any argument formally valid. But the argument would lack cogency insofar as it grossly begs the question or engages in self-contradiction. In order to be fully cogent, it seems an argument must not commit any informal fallacy (that pertains to its reasoning). I would hope that the rationale behind the GFC is fairly clear. Suppose the GFC is violated. That is, suppose that the proposed necessary assumption is false, and given the truth of the argument's received premises-premises that might, but need not, include an alternative to the proposed necessary assumption-the conclusion can still be inferred to be true in a fully cogent way. Then surely, the proposed assumption does not figure in the argument's reasoning; for the proposed assumption does not have to be presumed to be true in order to so-infer that the argument's conclusion is true. Hence, it is not in fact a necessary assumption of the argument. 44 Gilbert Plumer Notice that the GFC does not deny the logical truth that it could be the case both that an argument as a whole is fully cogent and an assumption of it is false. Unlike the GFC, this logical truth involves the notion that if all of the argument's premises, including the assumption, were true, the conclusion could be inferred to be true. Similarly, the question stem in Example I (next section) says, in effect, 'if the argument as a whole is fully cogent, then it must be assuming which one of the following?, (and Example 3's question stem is just shorthand for 1's); it does not say 'ifthe argument as a whole is fully cogent, then which one of the following must be true?'. However, the point of the GFC is that the most critical and heuristically useful part of what the question stem means here is 'if the explicitly given argument is fully cogent, then which one of the following must be true?'. The GFC thereby treats a necessary assumption as an 'inference license'. The general idea is that the same proposition may be treated both as an implicit element of an argument that as a whole is fully cogent and as a fact that helps to justify the inference in a stated argument that itself is fully cogent.6 There is apparently no better way of determining necessary assumptions. Consider the following criterion: NAC: A proposition is a necessary assumption of an argument if and only if it could not be the case both that the argument is fully cogent and the proposition is not included as a member of the argument's premise set. While this criterion would not overtly need to be taken in conjunction with other criteria, unlike the GFC, in fact it does not get us substantially beyond the question stem in Example 1. The NAC does clearly indicate that cogency is what assuming the proposition is necessary for. But circularity is a problem since the members of an argument's premise set are its explicitly stated premises and its implicit premises (if any), and a premise that is determined to be implicit by logical means just is a necessary assumption. The reader is warned that there will be little further theoretical treatment of the concept of cogency itself. A cogent argument is an argument that exhibits good reasoning, as determined by informal and, in the case of deduction, formal standards. It is not the point of this paper to elaborate in general terms on what makes an argument a good one, in this familiar sense. Indeed, it is hard to see how any mere paper could have this as a topic, since it is the defining subject matter ofthe discipline of logic. 7 Of course in elaborating and defending my criteria for determining necessary assumptions I will have to wield a concept of a good (cogent) argument. Yet I do not think that my concept contains anything particularly controversial or unusual. Of course if your concept differs from mine in some reasonable respect, you may make different reasonable judgments in the application of the criteria to individual Necessary Assumptions 45 cases. That is to be expected. But what is more important is the structure, not the details of how it is applied. Besides, logic is hardly distinguished among the various fields of philosophy and other humanities by its lack of intersubjective agreement. The very opposite is true. II. Application to LSAT Examples Example 1(6191 LSAT)** Train service suffers when a railroad combines commuter and freight service. By dividing attention between its freight and commuter customers, a railroad serves neither particularly well. Therefore, if a railroad is going to be a successful business, then it must concentrate exclusively on one of these two markets. For the argument to be logically correct, it must make which one of the following assumptions? (A) Commuter and freight service have little in common with each other. (B) The first priority of a railroad is to be a successful business. *(C) Unless a railroad serves its customers well, it will not be a successful business. (D) If a railroad concentrates on commuter service, it will be a successful business. (E) Railroad commuters rarely want freight service as well. P-H Example II (6191 LSAT)** It is even more important that we criticize democracies that have committed human rights violations than that we criticize dictatorships that have committed more violent human rights offenses. Human rights violations are always inexcusable, but those committed by governments that represent the will of the people are even more reprehensible than those committed by dictators. Further, our criticism is more likely to have an effect on the former than on the latter. Which of the following is the proper inference from the passage? 46 Gilbert Plumer (A) All governments commit some inexcusable and reprehensible acts. *(B) Some human rights violations are more reprehensible than other, more violent human rights violations. (C) Criticisms of human rights violations is certain to have no effect on a dictatorship. (D) Human rights violations are more likely to occur in democracies than in dictatorships. (E) Those who do represent the will of the people are less likely to be moved by criticism than are those who merely claim to represent the will of the people. Example III (2/92) LSAT)** The brains of identical twins are genetically identical. When only one of a pair of identical twins is a schizophrenic, certain areas of the affected twin's brain are smaller than corresponding areas in the brain of the unaffected twin. No such differences are found when neither twin is schizophrenic. Therefore, this discovery provides definitive evidence that schizophrenia is caused by damage to the physical structure of the brain. Which of the following is an assumption required by the argument? (A) The brain of a person suffering from schizophrenia is smaller than the brain of anyone not suffering from schizophrenia. * (B) The relative smallness of certain parts of the brains of schizophrenics is not the result of schizophrenia or of medications used in its treatment. (C) The brain of a person with an identical twin is no smaller, on average, than the brain of a person who is not a twin. (D) When a pair of identical twins both suffer from schizophrenia, their brains are the same size. (E) People who have an identical twin are no more likely to suffer from schizophrenia than those who do not. **Copyright © 1991, 1992 by Law School Admission Council Let us consider the examples from actual LSA Ts in more detail. Optiori (C) in Example I is (I claim) the necessary assumption in a fairly straightforward case of Hypothetical Syllogism, a deductive pattern. (C) pretty clearly satisfies all the criteria discussed thusfar. And specifically with respect to the GFC, consider that the conclusioin in the argument claims that if a railroad Necessary Assumptions 47 combines commuter and freight service (-r), it will not be a successful business (-:-p). Why? The stated grounds are that combining commuter and freight service leads to a railroad's not serving its customers well (-q). Ifnot serving its customers well did not in turn mean that a railroad will not be a successful business, i.e., if(C) were false, then even given the truth of the stated premise, the conclusion could not be inferred to be true-it could be either true or false. This is not a matter of claiming that アセイ@ .'. セイ@ is invalid or that MセアIL@ アセイ@ .'. ーセイ@ is invalid, although these claims are true. Nor is it a matter of claiming that MHーセアI@ logically or strictly implies MHアセイIーL@ which is a false claim. Rather, the claim is that if (C) were false, there would be no logically acceptable conclusion-warranting link between a problem that the argument describes as arising from a railroad's combining commuter and freight service, viz., not serving its customers well, and the question of whether a railroad will be a successful business: In addition to being (I claim) necessary, (C) in Example I is of course also a sufficient assumption. It wholly fills the gap in the argument's reasoning. Certain other statements would be sufficient but not necessary, e.g., the broader statement formed by substituting 'a business' for "a railroad" in (C); such a statement would go beyond providing everything implicit that the given argument depends on for full cogency. However, nothing in the context provided by the passage would justify attributing this greater generality to the argument; the passage is about railroads, not businesses in general. Indeed, nothing in the context would justify attributing any assumption other than (C) to the argument. To take another sort of case, suppose (C) said 'unless a railroad serves its customers well and stays in business for at least twenty years (s), it will not be a successful business' セHア@ & s). To attribute this proposition to the argument as an assumption would be either to make the given argument lack cogency (which is contrary to the point of determining assumptions) or to construct a different (albeit cogent) argument, since a requirement for a railroad's being a successful business, viz., s, would be imported 'out of the blue' into the context. Perhaps the clearest way of seeing why (C) alone satisfies the GFC is to consider the fact that every other sufficient assumption of the argument (with the exception of degenerate cases such as the conclusion or the associated conditional ofthe explicit argument-these will be discussed later) implies (C), but none are implied by (C).8 Intuitively, it seems that option (B) in Example 2 is clearly not a necessary assumption of the passage's argument. This is hardly because (B) is a presupposition of rationality generally or of a single propositional element of the argument. Giving an account that at once both supports the sort of intuition we have in a case like (B) here and supports holding that the credited responses in cases like Examples I and 3 are necessary assumptions is perhaps the most interesting and vexing problem to be encountered in dealing with argument assumptions. (B) in Example 2 follows from the conjunction of the 48 Gilbert Plumer first and second sentences in the passage, which are the argument's conclusion and (first) premise, respectively (the passage's third sentence is a premise that is independent of the first premise). (B) follows from these two sentences considered as independent statements, that is, in abstraction from the fact that they are related as premise and conclusion. This means that (B) has nothing to do with the argument's reasoning, i.e., its inferring the first sentence from the rest. (B) rectifies no lacuna in the argument's reasoning; it makes no contribution to the argument's cogency. (It may be worth remarking that the overt existential commitment of (B) derives from the argument in the passage through the fact that it could not be important to criticize democracies for certain actions unless those actions existed.) A principal virtue of the GFC is that in general it rules out contingent (i.e., neither necessarily true nor necessarily false) implications or presuppositions of any propositional element of an argument or conjunction ofthese elements; Example 2 (B) is a case in point. (In considering this it is to be understood that these elements are taken as independent propositions; they are taken in abstraction from any associated implicit or explicit argument-indicator terms such as 'thus' and 'since'. Otherwise, an implication could very well be a necessary assumption: the GFC gives a relatively clear meaning to the notion of being implied by an argument qua argument, i.e., without the abstraction performed. 9) Since by definition such implications are already part of the content of the argument, the argument could quite well be fully cogent without reintroducing them into the argument individually as further members of its premise set. Such implications violate the GFC in the following way: Although if such a proposed necessary assumption is false the conjunction of the argument's conclusion and received premises is also false, this does not rule out the possibility that if the received premises were true the conclusion could be inferred to be true in a fully cogent way. Just as it is a logical truth that it could be the case both that an argument as a whole is fully cogent and the conjunction ofits propositional elements is false, it is a logical truth that it could be the case both that an argument, considered apart from such an implication, is fully cogent and the implication is false. (Of course an exception arises from the curiosity that every proposition logically implies itself. If it is already established of something that it is a necessary assumption of an argument and is hence a propositional element of the argument, this curiosity does not mean that the proposition is not a necessary assumption of the argument.) However, the GFC is not so powerful as to preclude any arbitrarily selected necessary truth from being counted as a necessary assumption; the same applies, for example, to the proposition that there is at least one fully cogent argument. So we still need, respectively, the criteria that a necessary assumption not be an implication of a propositional element of the argument or a general presupposition of rationality (assuming that not all general presuppositions of rationality are necessary truths). This points to a limitation of the Necessary Assumptions 49 account: it cannot be used to determine any necessarily true necessary assumptions, as of an argument that has other necessarily true propositional elements, e.g., a mathematical argument. This is just a c;onsequence of a socalled 'paradox' of logical implication-a necessary truth is implied by any proposition whatsoever. As far as I can see, the only alternative for determining such assumptions is the NAC (above). As for arguments that have necessarily false propositional elements, insofar as they would lack cogency in virtue of having such elements, it is not clear that these arguments could even have necessary assumptions (where cogency is what assuming the proposition would be necessary for). In Example 3, a clear case of nondeduction, I interpret the causal relationships propounded by the argument to be that damage to the physical structure of the brain is the common cause of both schizophrenia and the relative smallness of certain parts of the brains of schizophrenics. This is how the argument explains the "discovery," i. e., the apparently perfect correlation of schizophrenia and the relative smallness, after in effect ruling out a genetic explanation. Option (B) contributes to the argument's cogency in an essential way by ruling out two further salient alternative explanations of this correlation. Ifthe negation of (B) were the case, then (at least) one of these alternative explanations would be true, and it would fully explain the discovery or evidence without any need to appeal to a damaging mechanism, contrary to the claim made through the argument-indicator term "Therefore, this discovery provides definitive evidence that." So the GFC is satisfied. Note that (B) is not merely an implication of the statements in the passage since these statements, considered in abstraction from the fact that they constitute an argument (excise "Therefore, this discovery provides definitive evidence that"), are entirely compatible with the negation of (B): the damage causes schizophrenia, and schizophrenia or the medications used in its treatment in tum cause the smallness. All of this presumes that the damage and the smallness are not the same phenomenon; if they were the same phenomenon, then (B) would not be a necessary assumption ofthe argument. (B) would simply be a presupposition or implication of the statement in the argument that "schizophrenia is caused by damage to the physical structure of the brain," i.e., the argument's conclusion. (B) in Example 3 has the logical form -(t v u). Does the GFC or the criterion that a necessary assumption not be a presupposition or implication of a propositional element of the argument mean that -t and -u each are not necessary assumptions? If -(t v u) is taken to be a necessary assumption, then of course neither -t nor -u is also a necessary assumption-the argument could quite well be fully cogent without either being included as a further member of its premise set. Conversely, if -t and -u are each taken to be necessary assumptions, then of course -(t V u) is not an additional necessary assumption. We can take either sort of approach in determining necessary 50 Gilbert Plumer assumptions, but we cannot take both. Detennining necessary assumptions should not be confused with proving validity, which by definition involves the application of theorems and rules of inference such as those that fonn the backdrop of the present discussion, i.e., De Morgan's, Simplification, and Conjunction. Nor, it seems, is it a necessary assumption of the argument (e.g.) that the relative smallness is not the result of visitors from outer space picking out schizophrenics and shrinking parts of their brains with some ray gun. Allowing such propositions as necessary assumptions-propositions that are insufficiently relevant to the evident concerns of the argument (which have to do with science rather than science fiction)-would to some significant extent make the argument lack cogency. So they could hardly be necessary for the argument's cogency. If indeed the scenario envisioned is one of science fiction, then the proposed necessary assumption violates the GFC in that it could very well be the case both that the argument aside from this proposition is fully cogent in a scientifically respectable way and yet this proposition is 'false' , i.e., the alternative explanation is true only in science fiction. Moreover, the set of propositions that individually rule out questionably salient alternative explanations would be open-ended or infinite, and the set would be fonned by applying a rule of Universal Instantiation to a supposed assumption in the argument to the effect that no other explanation is true. But this would amount to treating an argument that is manifestly nondeductive as deductive. ITI. Narrowness Objection It might be thought that no putatively necessary assumption (n) of an argument is actually necessary because there is always an alternative candidate (c)-a narrower version of n, or the explicit argument's associated conditional or even its conclusion-that logically would serve just as well as an assumption. It might appear that the existence of c makes it the case that n violates the GFC as follows: n could be false, yet if the received premisestaken as including c-were true, the conclusion could be inferred to be true. Let us first examine the question of narrowness. Ennis says: The basic idea is that any incomplete argument can be completed in a number of different ways. Consider the simple argument, "Since Mike is a dog, Mike is an animal." To suggest the range of possible gap-fillers, I shall note two, the one that first occurs to most people [note this admission] and another one: 1. All dogs are animals. 2. All dogs whose name begins with "M" are animals. A person is not logically prohibited from offering the argument, denying 1, and using 2 as a gap-filler. This shows that 1 is not logically necessary for the offering of the argument. So long as the offered gap-filler is more general than a statement establishing connection between the offered Necessary Assumptions 51 premise and conclusion, one can deny the offered gap-filler and derive the conclusion from the offered premise by using a narrower gap-filler. The limiting case is the simple statement that the offered premise was assumed in the circumstances to be sufficient to establish the conclusion. 1O Though this view has its appeal, I think that it is highly misleading. It is a principle of rationality that similar cases are to be treated similarly. There is nothing in the context to indicate that Mike is in any way special with respect to being a dog. Qua dog, Mike is an arbitrarily selected individual. In logic the injunction to treat similar cases similarly is the rule of Universal Generalization (UG). The necessary (and sufficient) assumption here, 1 (x)(Dx-+Ax) , is determined by the fact that UG applies to the stated argument's inference (Dm-+Am). Therefore, it does not seem too strong to hold in this case that both "offering the argument" and "denying 1" would be self-contradictory. This means that 1 satisfies the GFC: it could not be the case both that the argument aside from 1 is fully cogent and 1 is false. 1 satisfies the other criteria proposed above for determining necessary assumptions of arguments if we presume, as Ennis apparently does (p. 75), that 1 is not a necessary truth. If I were taken to be a necessary or conceptual truth such that the concept of animal is involved in the concept of dog, then it would not be at all clear that the stated argument has any gap that needs filling. II Notice that the argument "Since Mike is a dog, Mike is an animal" with 2 as the supposedly sufficient assumption (Ennis supposes it 'completes' the argument) is invalid. It would be valid if it had the more specific or narrower claim 'Mike is a dog whose name begins with "M'" as the explicit premise (such dogs constitute a proper subset of all dogs). Indeed, if this were the explicit premise, 2 would be the (unstated) necessary and sufficient assumption. The general principle operating here is that specificity that restricts the inferences licensed by the assumption is introduced by the narrower explicit premise, and the case becomes similar to that of Example 1, as contrasted to a more general argument that has as a necessary assumption (C) with its "a railroad" replaced by 'a business'. Yet in the original argument ("Since Mike is a dog, Mike is an animal") and context the only evidentiary claim made about Mike is that he is a dog. So what follows from this about Mike (that he is an animal) follows for any dog. Similarly, as Irving Copi puts it, "In the geometer's proof the only assumption made about ABC is that it is a triangle, hence what is proved true of ABC is proved true of any triangle."12 Again, this is just UG at work. Govier writes: "Consider: Abortion is wrong because it's killing. What does this sentence, which encapsulates an extremely simple-minded argument, entail? Does it entail that all killing is wrong? ... that most killing is wrong? ... that killing something unborn is wrong? I don't know what the 52 Gilbert Plumer answer is, and if somebody else does, I wish he'd tell me how he worked it In the absence of any further context other than that provided by the argument itself, and being faithful to the 'extreme simple-mindedness' of the argument, the answer is that through UG the argument 'entails' or has as a necessary assumption that all killing is wrong. If this were not the case, it would be irrelevant to object to the argument by pointing out that just because an action involves killing, that does not make the action wrong-after all, for example, killing a murderous home invader in self-defense does not appear to be wrong. A cost of adopting an Ennis-like view on necessary assumptions is a severe restriction on the legitimate use of counterexample and refutation by logical analogy. Ennis appears to hold that aside from what he calls "The limiting case," there is always a logically viable narrower alternative to any putatively necessary assumption that renders it unnecessary. I have just argued that this view is false, mainly by arguing that the specificity of the context and explicitly given argument determines the specificity of the necessary assumption; so if the former is in certain respects general, the necessary assumption is accordingly general. Let us now consider "The limiting case." OUt."13 IV. Associated Conditional Objection Presumably, "The limiting case" is the explicit argument's associated or corresponding conditional; in Ennis' example Dm :.Am it is Dm-?>Am. Ennis indicates that "an arguer is committed to at least this minimal claim" (p. 83), although such a claim is apparently only an 'insignificant' necessary assumption (as I quoted Norris and Ennis at the beginning of this paper). So the view I wish to consider, one that is suggested by Ennis' remarks, is that no putatively necessary assumption of an argument is actually necessary, unless it is already the explicit argument's associated conditional, since that conditional itself would make the argument fully cogent. This view has the consequence that every natural language argument that is enthymematic with respect to its explicit premises is construable as an instance of pure Modus Ponens, which I think is absurd. Although in formal logic there are systems that incorporate only one rule of inference such as Modus Ponens,14 this hardly means that this sort of system could be an adequate representation of fundamental argument structure in ordinary discourse. In Example I it is difficult to conceive of the whole argument in natural language where the assumption is taken to be the associated conditional of the argument stated in the passage. It is not at all clear that the whole argument would be fully cogent; it seems quite trivialized. From my point of view this is no surprise: the whole argument is a paradigm case of an everyday Hypothetical Syllogism. The same kind of remarks are perhaps even more convincing with respect to Example 3, where there is the added specter of treating an obviously nondeductive argument (to the best explanation) as deductive. Logic Necessary Assumptions 53 is in part a study of arguments as they actually appear in ordinary discourse. Numerous distinct patterns of reasoning or regularities in argument structure have been identified. To allow this, yet hold that all ordinary arguments that are enthymematic with respect to their explicit premises could exhibit the single pattern, Modus Ponens, seems inconsistent. Why should recognizing the. pattern of reasoning in such an enthymematic argument be so radically different from pattern recognition in other endeavors where the explicit or presented pattern is only partial (e.g., continuing a numerical sequence or recognizing a friend in a photographic profile)? The patterns identified are hardly all the same in any of these latter endeavors. In such a way as this at least, the credited responses in cases like Examples 1 and 3 are assumptions that are 'logically necessarily made'. Let P stand for the conjunction of an argument's explicit premises; C stand for the argument's conclusion (taken to be explicit); and I stand for the conjunction of the argument's implicit premises or necessary assumptions, if any. That an argument has the form P, I :. C rather than simply P:. C by itself provides no particular reason for identifying I with pセcL@ i.e., the explicit argument's associated conditional. The only thing that could warrant this identification would be some aspect of the argument's context, such as that Mike is somehow a special, nonarbitrarily selected dog in the case of Dm :.Am. In that case the whole argument would be the pure Modus Ponens dュセaL@ Dm:. Am, rather than as I am construing it, viz., HゥクIdセaL@ Dm:. AmY But instances of pure Modus Ponens wherein the ュセッイ@ premise implicit) must constitute the exception and not is implicit (P:. C, with pセc@ the rule, especially if we take, as many do (see below), the implicit premise here to simply replicate or be "reiterative" of the implication relationship of the explicit argument. This reiteration would make the argument self-referential, and the self-referential case's being exceptional is to be expected in light of the numerous paradoxes of self-reference (e.g., the liar paradox concerning the claim 'this statement is false', and Russell's paradox, which concerns the set property of being self-membered). I!> The rule, on the other hand, would have to be that it is in fact incoherent to identify I with pセcZ@ That an argument is enthymematic with respect to its explicit premises means that the conclusion is not implied by these premises alone; more premise material is needed in order to properly infer the conclusion-that is precisely how the argument is enthymematic or "incomplete." This is to say pセc@ only if SI v ... S,,-where S, v ... S" is the disjunction of the possible sufficient assumptions of the So if none of enthymematic argument, none of which is identical to pセcN@ Sr"S" were acceptable, neither would pセc@ be acceptable. (The criteria proposed in this paper are meant to be usable to determine which of SrS" is necessary, i.e., is identical to I.) It is therefore at least very misleading to affirm the widespread view that "we may add the reiterative candidate [i.e., add pセc@ to an argument that has 54 Gilbert Plumer the form P, I:. C]. This is always unobjectionable, since the acceptability of the reiterative candidate is a necessary condition of the acceptability of the argument." (The view does correctly go on to say that this adding is "never useful, in regard to facilitating evaluation, since it is never easier to evaluate the reiterative candidate than to evaluate the corresponding inference.")17 We have just seen the problem with identifying I with P 4C. Yet if these are not identified, then adding P4C would at least make I superfluous with respect to drawing the conclusion, so in what sense could I be a set of implicit premises or necessary assumptions? I think the view is confused about why the enthymematic argument or arguer is, as Ennis puts it, "committed" to P4C. It is not because P:. C is stated and P4C just 'reiterates' the implication relationship of this statement. Instead, as a rule it is because the argument's being enthymematic means that it has an implicit premise set I(:t:P4C), and that P, when conjoined with I, implies C «P & 1)4C). By Commutation and Exportation this is equivalent to 14(P4C), and of course there is commitment to I; as in Example I, p4Q implies (Q4r)4(p4r). (It seems that these points apply to nondeductive arguments where '4' is read as, e.g., 'probabilifies'.) However, even though there is commitment to P4C, P4C is not a further necessary assumption of the argument precisely because it is implied by what is already, by supposition, a propositional element or conjunction of such elements of the argument, viz., I. Some may even think that one can freely add the associated conditional (P4C) to nonenthymematic arguments. If this is done with the justification that "all arguments depend upon the 'assumption' that you can get from their specific premises to their specific conclusions,"18 then one has embarked on Lewis Carroll's infinite regress, which in the example Carroll presents l9 has the form: A; (\ix)(\iy)(\iz)«(x = z) & (v = Z»4(X = y» B: (a = c) & (b = c) C: (A & B)4Z D: (A & B & C)4Z Z: a = b The vertical margin dots represent an infinite series of recursive iterations in the manner of premises C and D. V. Charity Let us briefly consider how charity enters the picture. To attribute Ennis' "gap-filler" 2, "All dogs whose name begins with 'M' are animals," to the argument "Since Mike is a dog, Mike is an animal" would violate any reason- Necessary Assumptions 55 able principle of charity. This is not merely because this "gap-filler" would make the argument invalid; it is more generally because the attribution would come totally' out of the blue'. There is simply nothing in the barren context presented to justify such an attribution. The attribution of 2 would make the argument as a whole very strange-how could the character of a dog's given proper name have anything to do with the dog's being an animal? It was noted in §II that necessary truths trivially satisfy the GFC. The other half of the story is that any proposed necessary assumption of an argument that is wholly or irredeemably fallacious will trivially satisfy the GFC, simply because the argument could not be fully cogent and remain the same argument. The avoidance ofthis trivial satisfaction constitutes one reason it is crucial to see that in the very act of attributing a proposition to an argument as a necessary assumption (in the sense explained above) one presumes that the argument is cogent, and thereby interprets it charitably, to at least some extent. Cogency is what assuming the proposition is necessary for; the proposition fills a gap in the explicit argument's reasoning, thereby making the reasoning stronger than it otherwise would be (although it could still be weak or fallacious in other respects). A necessary assumption contributes to an argument's cogency, and a necessary and sufficient assumption completes the argument so that it is fully cogent. This means that it would be incoherent to treat as necessary and/or sufficient assumptions of arguments such propositions as the argument's stated conclusion or the contradictory of a stated premise. For this would be to uncharitably treat the argument as irredeemably fallacious in grossly begging the question or engaged in self-contradiction, even though such candidates would make the argument formally valid. Moreover, therefore, one cannot maintain that any putatively necessary assumption is rendered unnecessary by the fact that such an alternative candidate logically would serve just as well as an assumption. It seems that for arguments that are enthymematic with respect to their explicit premises, the question of which are cogent enough to have necessary assumptions and which are wholly fallacious is a matter that is determined by the application of a reasonable principle of charity. It is true that attempts have been made to determine this matter solely by examining features of the explicit arguments themselves and not invoking a principle of charity.20 A starting point is the proposition that a gross nonsequitur does not have any content expression or nonlogical constant in common between the conclusion and the stated premises (and such an expression could not be produced by making definitionally equivalent substitutions). However, the attempts have been limited to deduction, and even there they seem unsatisfactory.2! Govier presents what I regard as an adequate and insightful theory of argumentative charity. After reviewing the literature, Govier proposes and defends in detail a moderate principle of charity (that takes its cue from H.P. Grice's "Logic and Conversation"): 56 Gilbert Plumer We presume, other things being equal, that others are participating in the social practise of rational argumentation. . .. They are operating within the purpose of the exchange: that is, it is their purpose to communicate information, acceptable opinions and reasonable beliefs, and to provide good reasons for some of these opinions and beliefs by offering good arguments. '" The basis for charity is to be found not in ethics, prudence, or epistemology, but in the nature and purpose of the activity in which participants are engaging: argumentative discourse. That people are doing this when they appear to be is a rebuttable presumption . . . , Iffor one reason or another, the presumption would not be appropriate-the people lacking all credibility, or the context being one where people seek persuasion at any cost-then there is no reason for approaching the discourse charitably-not even moderately charitably.22 In ordinary situations this principle can be effectively applied because the context of the enthymematic argument is rich enough to determine whether the arguer is engaged in the social practice of rational argumentation. However, with respect to short passages that appear on an examination like the LSAT (and other comparably attenuated situations), the matter is often indeterminate. Then it is up to the test writer to somewhat arbitrarily decide whether to develop the rest of the test item as a necessary assumption question or as a question that asks the examinee to identify a way in which the argument is fallacious; Example 3 is a case of this. From the point of view of examinees the charity issue is already decided for them by which of these two sorts of questions they confront. VI. Theory Summary To summarize, in determining necessary assumptions of arguments one first applies the principle of charity; only ifthis yields the result that the argument is not wholly fallacious does one apply the other criteria, viz., that a necessary assumption must not be a presupposition of rationality generally or of a propositional element of the argument, and that it must satisfy the GFC. I think these criteria are appropriately used by writers and reviewers of a test like the LSA T to determine or check the credited response in a question that asks for a necessary assumption of an argument. This is not to say, however, that kinds of cases like what have been identified above as 'necessary assumption pretenders' could legitimately be used as noncredited responses in such test questions. The ordinary concept of an assumption seems too vague or amorphous to reasonably permit, for instance, a presupposition or implication of an argument's stated conclusion as a noncredited response. VII. Empirical Considerations So much for the theory. How have the principles articulated fared in practice? It is fairly rare that a philosophical theory can be (even indirectly) tested against Necessary Assumptions 57 systematic empirical data, but with some qualification this is the case here. Consider Table 1:23 Percent Rejected Item Subtype Number Pretested For Statistical For Content Reasons Reasons Percent Identified as Marginal Assumption 288 6 18 16 Inference 350 8 24 13 Flaw 271 7 18 13 Evidence 388 5 18 9 Table ]. The column farthest left includes names of the three test item subtypes that are most akin to the Assumption subtype. All four subtypes appear within the "Logical Reasoning" (informal logic) sections of the LSA T. One qualification is that the Assumption category includes a minority of sufficient assumption test items; they ask of a given enthymematic argument, e.g., "The conclusion above follows logically if which one of the following is assumed?" Test questions of the Inference subtype ask the examinee to identify allowable inferences from given passage material; Example 2 is an item of this subtype. Flaw questions typically ask the examinee to identify a way in which an argument is fallacious. In Evidence questions the task is to determine the logical effect of additional or independent evidence--whether it supports or undermines-a given argument, conclusion, or hypothesis, etc.24 The Number Pretested column gives the number of test items of the subtype that were pretested from 6/91 to 2/96. Before any test item is used in a scored section of an LSA T exam, it appears in an unscored section of a previous LSA T; this is known as "pretesting." The purpose is to determine the item's psychometric statistical characteristics so that if these are acceptable, the item can later be incorporated according to specification into a section that will be scored. The next column gives the percentage of the test items of the subtype that were pretested and thereby found to be statistically unusable on the basis of a threeparameter Item Response Theory modeL The three parameters are measures, roughly speaking, of (a) how well the item discriminates among examinees of differing ability , (b) how difficult the item is, and (c) the probability of examinees of very low ability answering the item correctly, perhaps by guessing.2S The next column gives the percentage of the test items of the subtype that 58 Gilbert Plumer were rejected in a content review conducted subsequent to pretesting (most content reviews are performed prior to pretesting). Usually, the reason for rejection is that the item was found to have more than one correct answer on a certain interpretation or to have no correct answer that is clearly defensible. The column farthest right gives the percentage of the test items of the subtype that were pretested and thereby found to be statistically marginal, primarily by using the various measures of Item Response Theory, as well as Classical theory26 (e.g., how well performance on the item correlates with performance on the test section as a whole). There is some overlap between the test items that were rejected for statistical reasons and those that were rejected for content reasons, and between those identified as marginal and those that were rejected for content reasons. The point is, if a view about necessary assumptions like Norris and Ennis' were correct, one might very well expect that the performance of the Assumption SUbtype would be significantly worse than that of the other subtypeskinds of questions to which they raise no comparable objections. Indeed, Norris and Ennis say, "the word 'necessarily' [or an equivalent] in the direction would at least slow down some good critical thinkers and force them to waste time. It might also force them to omit the item or guess wildly" (p. 123). But I have seen no evidence of this in the nine years that I have participated in developing and applying the kind of criteria advocated in this paper to the LSA T; as Table I indicates, content and psychometric statistical analyses of necessary assumption test questions yield results that are as good as those for other comparable kinds of questions designed to assess reasoning abilities. 27 Another consideration is that aside from the case of a special administration of the LSA T, every examinee receives a copy of the LSA T test questions along with her or his scored answer sheet. This convenience leads to careful scrutiny of the test questions, if for no other reason than that law schools assign a great deal of weight to the candidate's test score in the admission process. There is an established procedure under which examinees can challenge test questions and written defenses of test questions, including asking for a review by a panel of outside experts. 28 If this panel rules against the test, then an expensive process of re-scoring and issuing new score reports is initiated (a relatively rare circumstance in which philosophical theory is concretely and publicly accountable). And developing any standardized test item is an expensive process anyway. So if necessary assumption test items were challenged, let alone successfully challenged, proportionately more often than other kinds of questions designed to assess reasoning abilities, or if they performed significantly worse in content or statistical review, there would be a strong incentive to simply not use them. But we do. This context of developing a standardized reasoning and reading test 'has provided an organized setting in which actually to engage in the Goodmanian-Rawlsian project of Necessary Assumptions S9 endeavoring to achieve a "reflective equilibrium,"29 where theoretical criteria or principles on the one hand, and particular judgments (about arguments) on the other, are brought into coherence with one another, and thereby each is afforded justification. Notes Earlier versions of this paper were presented at Law School Admission Council, and at the Third International Conference on Argumentation at the University of Amsterdam, The paper has benefited from discussion on these occasions and from written comments by Rod Bertolet, Anton Bures, Robert Ennis, David Kary, Deborah Kerman, and Brian MacPherson, 2(Pacific Grove, CA: Midwest Publications, 1989), pp. 122-23. Cf. Ennis' "Identifying Implicit Assumptions," Synthese 51 (April 1982), pp, 82-83. Ennis is also the principal author of the Cornell Critical Thinking Tests and is very influential in the field of critical thinking education, 3For example: Michael Scriven, Reasoning (New York: McGraw-Hili, 1976), e.g., pp. 43, 83, 166; Irving Copi, Introduction to LogiC, 5th Edn. (New York: Macmillan, 1978), p. 242; Robert Fogelin, Understanding Arguments, 3rd Edn. (New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1987), pp. 120-21; David Kelly, The Art of Reasoning (New York: W.W. Norton & Co., 1988), p. 100. 4This view is apparently held by (e.g.) Trudy Govier, Problems in Argument Analysis and Evaluation (Dordrecht: Foris, 1987), pp. 92-94; Wayne Grennan, "Are 'Gap-Fillers' Missing Premises?," Informal Logic 16 (Fall 1994), p. 190. Interestingly, after the criteria for determining necessary assumptions discussed in this paragraph were developed, an LSAT examinee challenged a question on the grounds that the statement "the credited response refers to is not an assumption but something that is true by definition ... [It is] a given that is inherently true." (The statement in question was not actually a definitional truth.) S"Unstated Premises," Informal Logic 7 (Spring & Fall 1985), p. 114. 6Compare A. Sloman's conclusion that "any analysis of a particular argument in terms of a suppressed premiss may be replaced by an equally general analysis in terms of a rule of inference and vice versa." "Rules ofInference, or Suppressed Premisses?," Mind 73 (Jan. 1964), p. 88. (Cf. Scriven, op. cit., pp. 83, 178; David Hitchcock, "Enthymematic Arguments," Informal Logic 7 (Spring & Fall 1985), esp. pp. 94-95; Timothy Smiley, "A Tale of Two Tortoises," Mind 104 (Oct. 1995), esp. pp. 730-32.) However, because such a proposition must contain at least one content expression (given the criterion that a necessary assumption not be a general presupposition of rationality), insofar as it is a rule of inference at all, it is a nonformal or specific rule of inference. Contrast, e.g., Modus Ponens, which as topic-neutral is a formal or general rule of inference. 7But see, e.g., John Slaney, "A General Logic," Australasian Journal of Philosophy 68 (March 1990), pp. 74-88; Trudy Govier, "What is a Good Argument?," Metaphilosophy 23 (Oct. 1992), pp. 393-409. Note that in this paper I shall also not be directly concerned with the matter of how one, in the first place,jintiY necessary assumption candidates (that can then be subjected to my criteria). For a procedure that is designed to help with this and that embodies a version, albeit a narrower one, of the GFC, see Mike Donn, "Help in Finding Missing Premises," Teaching Philosophy 13 (June 1990), pp. 159-64. I 60 Gilbert Plumer 8Another degenerate case is r. The assumption of r would make the stated argument formaJly valid. It has actually been objected to this paper that only through an ad hoc judgment about the cogency of arguments can r be ruled out as a rival to (C). However, the :. ーセイ@ read with the passage's verbal substitutions is incoherent. This argument r, アセイ@ entirely superis probably because the assumption of r renders the stated premise HアセイI@ follows formally simply from r), fluous in deductively drawing the conclusion Hーセイ@ making the argument commit a gross fallacy of irrelevance. I should like to insist that making such cogency judgments is an everyday occurrence that is well-grounded in the defining subject matter ofthe discipline oflogic, and hence is hardly ad hoc. '1C! the view of David Hitchcock. According to Trudy Govier, Hitchcock's view is that in order to be a necessary assumption a proposition "must follow 'deductively and reasonably immediately' from the combination ofthe stated premises, the stated conclusion, and the 'drawing ofthe conclusion from the premises'." "What is a Good Argument?," op. cit., p. 401, which summarizes Hitchcock's "Methodological Deductivism," presented at the Eastern Division meetings of the American Philosophical Association in Dec. 1986. lO"Identifying Implicit Assumptions," op. cit., p. 82. \lC! Govier, Problems in Argument Analysis and Evaluation, op. cit., pp. 96-97: We need to distinguish "formal deductive inference" from "substantive deductive inference. (Substantive deductive inference depends on meaning rather than on form.) ... Nor should a necessary truth which relates the meanings of terms used in an argument already deductively valid without the addition of such a truth ... be regarded as a missing premise." Also see, e.g., Hitchcock, "Enthymematic Arguments," op. cit., pp. 85-86. 120p. cit., p. 357. 13"What is a Good Argument?," op. cit., p. 404. 14E.g., system R.S. in Irving Copi, Symbolic Logic, 5th Edn. (New York: Macmillan, 1979), p.228ff. lsIn my construal, dュセa@ is not also a necessary assumption of the argument since it is an Recall the implication of a propositional element of the argument, viz., HvクIdセaN@ point in §II that determining necessary assumptions should not be confused with proving validity. 16For discussion, see, e.g., Graham Priest, "The Structure of the Paradoxes ofSeif-Reference," Mind 103 (Jan. 1994), pp. 25-34. 17Burke, op. cit., pp. 108, 116. See also Scriven, op. cit., pp. 84, 163-64; Hitchcock, "Enthymematic Arguments," op. cit., pp. 86, 89; Michael A. Gilbert, "The Enthymeme Buster: A Heuristic Procedure for Position Exploration in Dialogic Dispute," Informal Logic 13 (Fall 1991), p. 160; Dale Jacquette, "Charity and the Reiteration Problem for Enthymernes," Informal Logic 18 (Winter \996), pp. 3, 8. The idea that in a pure Modus Ponens an implicit major premise simply 'reiterates' the implication relationship of the explicit argument is subject to the following kind of objection: The implication relationship between the premises and conclusion of the argument is strict or tautological implication, whereas the implication between the antecedent and consequent of the major premise may be something less, such as causal implication or truth-functional (material) implication. This point raises hoary issues that cannot be addressed here, such as how adequate a representation of natural language is the purely truth-functional account of conditionality. 18Scriven, op. cit., p. 84. 19"What the Tortoise Said to Achilles," Mind 4 (April 1895), pp. 278-79. 2°Rolf George, "Enthymematic Consequence," American Philosophical Quarterly 9 (Jan. 1972), pp. 113-16 and "Bolzano' s Consequence, Relevance, and Enthymemes," Journal of Philosophical Logic 12 (Aug. 1983), pp. 298-318; Hitchcock, "Enthymematic Arguments," op. cit. Necessary Assumptions 61 21Tomis Kapitan, "A Definition of Enthymematic Consequence," International Logic Review 9 (1980), pp. 56-59; Hitchcock, ibid.; Govier, "What is aGood Argument?," op. cit., p.402n9. 22 Problems in Argument Analysis and Evaluation, op. cit., p. 150. 23Source: Law School Admission Council statistical databases. 24For more discussion of the kinds of questions that appear on the LSAT, see the LSATI LSDAS Registration and Information Book, which is updated yearly and is available from Law School Admission Council, P.O. Box 40, Newtown, PA 18940. 23 A standard reference work is F. M. Lord, Applications ofItem Response Theory to Practical Testing Problems (Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum, 1980). 26A standard reference work is F. M. Lord and M. R. Novick, Statistical Theories ofMental Test Scores (Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley, 1968). 27The Norris-Ennis alternative to asking for the identification of necessary assumptions, since they think that no significant assumptions are actually necessary, is to ask of several options "which is probably taken for granted or assumed" (p. 124). Such a question would be seriously unclear: the assumption is probable relative to what? Certainly, the given argument. But why not also psychological facts about arguers and facts about relevant aspects of the world in general? Such questions would appear to take a large step in the direction of achievement (knowledge) testing, as opposed to the intended aptitude testing for a particular reasoning skill (assumption recognition). 28In a review of a recent challenge and defense of a necessary assumption test question, a panel member (a philosopher of language and logic) wrote: '''depends on' is hardly a technical term requiring training in logic ... The Law Services response that (A) is the only assumption on which the argument depends is correct. (A), and only (A), is such that if we presume it to be false the argument is undercut." Note the language of the GFC. 29NeJson Goodman, Fact, Fiction, and Forecast, 4th Edn. (Harvard University Press, 1983), part m.2; John Rawls, A Theory ofJustice (Harvard University Press, 1971), p. 20ff. Gilbert Plumer, Senior Test Specialist-Logical Reasoning Law School Admission Council 661 Penn Street, Box 40, Newtown, PA 18940-0040 U.S.A.