88
Space, Form, and Urbanity
Greig Charnock
(Social) space is a (social) product. (Lefebvre,
1991: 26)
By its actions, this society no longer accepts space
as a container, but produces it; we do not live, act
and work ‘in’ space so much as by living, acting,
and working we produce space. (Smith, 2008: 116)
In its most general sense, Critical Theory
aims to critique existing society as well as
‘traditional’ theories of that society: more
precisely, it aims to ‘penetrate the world of
things to show the underlying relations
between persons’ (Aronowitz, 2015: 106) –
to reveal the ‘human bottom of nonhuman
things’ (Horkheimer, 2002: 142). Critical
Theory thus attaches to ‘critique’ a very specific meaning (Bonefeld, 2001). Given that in
a capitalistically constituted society, social
reproduction is regulated by the production
and exchange of ‘things’ by (formally) ‘free’
and ‘equal’ commodity producers, a good
deal of Critical Theory’s critique has justifiably focused upon the social constitution of
economic forms, and upon demystifying
BK-SAGE-BEST_ET_AL_V3-180084-Chp88.indd 1450
common consciousness of economic relations on a human basis (Backhaus 2005;
Bellofiore and Redolfi Riva, 2015; Reichelt,
2005). Following Marx and Adorno, Bonefeld
(2014: 3) argues for instance that ‘the critique of political economy amounts to a critique of ontological conceptions of economic
categories, including the category of labour
as a transhistorically conceived category that
defines the human metabolism with nature in
abstraction from society’. A critical theory of
capitalist society, in other words, should aim
to demystify not only the market as a form of
social reproduction based upon fundamental
relations of un-freedom and in-equality, but
also to expose traditional conceptions of that
society as being rooted in unfounded ontological assumptions about humans’ relation
with nature that are appropriate to the functioning of that society, but which can be
shown to be in the service of the ongoing
reproduction of definite social relations, and
a debasing and destructive social-ecological
condition.
5/11/18 4:37 PM
SPACE, FORM, AND URBANITY
The remit of critique in this sense extends
to cover social forms and ideologies that are
often not considered to be of central, categorical importance to the critique of political economy, per se (see Adorno, 2001). As
this chapter shows, there is already a well
established body of critical social theory that
has sought to critique spatial or geographical
forms of social organisation – especially the
agglomeration and networking of people and
productive and consumptive economic activities in cities or urban centres – and those traditional urban theories that reduce such spatial
or geographical forms to mere containers or
conduits seemingly devoid of a ‘human bottom’.1 For Neil Brenner, a leading contemporary urban theorist, any properly critical
urban theory has to ‘differ fundamentally
from what might be termed “mainstream”
urban theory – for example, the approaches
inherited from the Chicago School of urban
sociology, or those deployed within technocratic or neoliberal forms of policy science’
(2009: 198). Calling for ‘a much more systematic integration of urban questions into
the analytical framework of critical social
theory as a whole’ (2009: 205), Brenner envisions a critical-theoretical project inspired
by the Frankfurt School, among others, but
appropriate to ‘conditions of increasingly
generalised, worldwide urbanisation’ in the
early twenty-first century:
Rather than affirming the current condition of
cities as the expression of transhistorical laws of
social organisation, bureaucratic rationality or economic efficiency, critical urban theory emphasizes
the politically and ideologically mediated, socially
contested and therefore malleable character of
urban space – that is, its continual (re)construction
as a site, medium, and outcome of historically
specific relations of social power … In short, critical
urban theory involves the critique of ideology
(including social-scientific ideologies) and the critique of power, inequality, injustice and exploitation, at once within and among cities. (2009: 198)
The purpose of this chapter is to establish the
basis for a critical theory of space; that is, for
an appreciation of how, to paraphrase Neil
BK-SAGE-BEST_ET_AL_V3-180084-Chp88.indd 1451
1451
Smith, modern society does not exist in space
but actively produces space ‘in its own
image’. It expands on the premise of there
being a ‘human bottom’ to space and geography that has emerged out of an alienating and
contradictory process of social-ecological
metabolism, and in so doing expounds the
basis for the critique of traditional Western
epistemological conceptions and theories of
urbanity. As has been recently underlined,
[if] it is no longer remarkable to speak of space,
nature, and landscapes as socially produced, it is
largely a reflection of the extent to which contemporary spatial and geographical thought has been
transformed … in particular with the ideas – or at
least the language – of the French Marxist philosopher and sociologist Henri Lefebvre. (Kirsch,
2012: 1042)
In the absence of any definitive Frankfurt
School Critical Theory of space and urbanity,
the bulk of this chapter therefore consists of
an exposition and critical evaluation of
Lefebvre’s critical theory of the production of
space. Before visiting Lefebvre, however, the
chapter first follows the late Marxist geographer Neil Smith in looking for a properly
critical-theoretical basis for deciphering spatial forms on a human basis in society’s metabolic relation with nature, and in dialogue
with Alfred Schmidt’s pioneering work on a
critical theory of the relationship between
human labour and nature. This is a necessary
detour since the notion of the production of
nature, which Smith advances as a result of
his engagement with Schmidt’s critical
theory, is largely homologous to that of the
production of space as originally theorised by
Lefebvre. Lefebvre’s contribution is explained
with a focus, first, on his critique of philosophico-epistemologies that fetishise space,
and therefore make possible the representation of space and the instrumentalisation of
spatial modelling that, in Lefebvre’s view,
mediates the survival of capitalism and
the reproduction of capitalist social relations in
and through the urban form. The chapter
then explains Lefebvre’s method of spatial
5/11/18 4:37 PM
1452
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF FRANKFURT SCHOOL CRITICAL THEORY
analysis, paying close attention to the contradictory nature of the process of the production of space and therefore to the emancipatory
political possibilities inherent to it. The fourth
section of the chapter returns to Smith to
subject Lefebvre’s own ‘respatialised critical
social theory’ to critique on the grounds that
it proceeds from unfounded or indefensible
assumptions regarding the relations between
time, space, nature, and therefore politics.
The chapter concludes by reviewing how
Lefebvre has nonetheless influenced more
recent attempts to develop a critical theory of
space under conditions of so-called ‘planetary urbanisation’ characteristic of the early
twenty-first century.
FROM THE PRODUCTION OF NATURE
TO THE PRODUCTION OF SPACE
Within just a couple of years of one another,
the British geographer David Harvey and his
former student Neil Smith published two
books that were to very rapidly transform the
discipline of human geography as well as to
make an enduringly significant impact on the
broader social sciences. With The Limits to
Capital (Harvey, 2007), first published in
1982, and 1984’s Uneven Development
(Smith, 2008), both authors eyed similar
goals insofar as they each sought to challenge basic notions of space characteristic of
traditional Western thought and common
parlance – that of ‘space as field, as a container, or as simple emptiness’ (Smith, 2008:
92) – and to advance instead a systematic,
Marxian understanding of how capital creates space in its own image. Both hold that
geographical space itself becomes an active
moment in the production and reproduction
of a physical landscape bearing the hallmarks
of alienation, exploitation, contradiction, and
therefore politics. In Uneven Development,
Smith surveys a canon of traditional Western
thought about nature and space before outlining an original, critical theory of uneven
BK-SAGE-BEST_ET_AL_V3-180084-Chp88.indd 1452
development in the last two chapters.
Harvey’s Limits, on the other hand, represents his ‘explanatory-diagnostic’ (Castree,
2006) – allegedly ‘neo-classical’ (Kipfer
et al., 2008: 7) – Marxism, insofar as it consists of a more parsimonious attempt to provide an exposé of the crisis tendencies of the
‘capitalist space economy’ drawing almost
exclusively on Marx’s writings on value,
production, exchange, and the circulation of
capital. On the assumption that Harvey’s
contribution to the critical theory tradition is
demonstrably limited, therefore, I concentrate on Smith in this first section, as providing an appropriate introduction to
conceptualising the relation between society
and space in terms of distinctively critical,
non-traditional theory.
For Smith, an essential preliminary step
in the appreciation of how capital produces
space at various interrelational scales – from
the local to the world market – is to first
examine the production of nature in capitalist
society. This, he underlines, is a reflexively
critical endeavour since it must penetrate the
‘delusive appearance of things’ (Marx, quoted
in Smith, 2008: 49), and must question a core
tenet of traditional Western thought in which
‘nature is generally seen as precisely that
which cannot be produced; it is the antithesis of human productive activity’ (Smith,
2008: 32). With this in mind, Smith mounts
his construction of a theory of the production
of nature on the basis of a critical reading of
the Frankfurt School and a close reading of
Alfred Schmidt’s The Concept of Nature in
Marx (1971), in particular. Ultimately, Smith
is unconvinced by Schmidt’s dualistic positing of two coterminous natures (one the
external object of labour, the other a universal
unity of nature and society), and of a resulting thesis he finds at the same time both utopian and, in ‘characteristic’ Frankfurt School
fashion, despairing of ‘the inexorable necessity of human domination over nature’ (2008:
47; see also Foster, 2000: 245). Yet, Smith
also finds much to commend in Schmidt’s
book. For instance, Schmidt alerts us to the
5/11/18 4:37 PM
SPACE, FORM, AND URBANITY
central importance of the concept of socioecological metabolism in Marx’s own work:
the key point being that ‘the whole of nature
is socially mediated and, inversely, society is
mediated through nature as a component of
the total reality’ (Schmidt, 1971: 79).2 Smith
also picks up on Schmidt’s ‘useful distinction
between “first nature” and a “second nature”’
(Smith, 2008: 33), which he subsequently
re-fashions in Uneven Development so as to
claim that ‘we must now consider there to be
a social priority of nature; nature is nothing
but social’ (2008: 47), and that ‘instead of
the domination of nature, therefore, we must
consider the more complex process of the
production of nature’ (2008: 48).
For Smith, the term ‘second nature’ captures the result of the historical generalisation
of production for exchange characteristic of
capitalism, and subsequently – as part-andparcel of the completion of the world market –
the result of the ‘real subsumption of nature
to capital’ (Smith, 2006). With the development of capitalism as a genuinely worldwide form of social production, ‘nature is
progressively produced from within and as
part of the so-called second nature’ (Smith,
2008: 77). While it is true that any physical
commodity produced remains subject to the
laws of gravity and physics that apply in first
nature, that commodity is at the same time
an exchange-value subject to the abstract
laws of the market and therefore, for Smith,
‘travels in second nature’ (2008: 79). In
search of profit, capital ‘attaches a price tag
to everything it sees and from then on, it is
this price tag which determines the fate of
nature’ (2008: 78); ‘no part of the earth’s surface, the atmosphere, the oceans, the geological substratum, or the biological substratum
are immune from transformation by capital’
(2008: 79). Indeed, for Smith, such was the
degree to which capital had subsumed nature
in this manner that the distinction between
first and second nature was, by the late twentieth century, practically obsolete.
While this universalising tendency of
capital to produce second nature on a world
BK-SAGE-BEST_ET_AL_V3-180084-Chp88.indd 1453
1453
scale carries with it important homogenising
tendencies (and Smith here discusses wagelabour, globalised production, the privatised
and gendered form of the reproduction of
labour-power, and bourgeois consciousness),
it is nevertheless one that is rooted in the specifically capitalistic production process and
specifically capitalist relations of production.
As such, the production of nature on a universal scale is rife with internal contradictions
that are manifest in barriers to ‘capital’s own
nature’ (to paraphrase Marx, 1993: 410), both
in terms of the production of scarcity and
‘natural’ crises (such as climate change), and
in terms of the production of a specific barrier to capital in the form of a global working
class which confronts the unity of society and
nature in alienated forms on a daily basis –
the labour market, the labour process, the
wage-form, and so on (Smith, 2008: 84–5).
Having laid out a theory of the production
of nature, Smith then turns his attention to the
question of space, and the core problematic of
Uneven Development: namely, how to explain
the ongoing production of a highly variegated and dynamic geographical landscape
in capital’s own image – that is, to decipher
produced space as means and end of capital’s
socio-ecological metabolism.3 Smith’s line
of argument is unequivocal: ‘Unless space
is conceptualised as a quite separate reality from nature, the production of space is a
logical corollary of the production of nature’
(2008: 92). His own theory of the uneven
development of capitalism therefore builds
upon the argument that the produced space,
or socio-ecological landscape, of capitalist
‘second nature’ emerges out of a determined,
incessant ‘dialectic of equalisation and differentiation’ of the development of capital’s
productive forces. As capital extends its reach
over the whole globe, the landscape is wholly
subsumed within and therefore produced by
the production of nature and capital’s pricetagging of everything, yet consists of myriad
particularised spaces/places – at a variety of
spatial scales – whose relative past, present
and future development is conditioned by
5/11/18 4:37 PM
1454
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF FRANKFURT SCHOOL CRITICAL THEORY
geographically specific degrees of the concentration and centralisation of capital, the
agglomeration and socialisation of labourpower, and differing degrees of resilience
to the perpetual rhythms of accumulation
that periodically threaten the devaluation of
geographically concentrated fixed capital
and localised working classes bearing specific productive and cost attributes. As Smith
explains,
the drive towards universality in capitalism brings
only a limited equalisation of levels and conditions
of development. Capital produces distinct spatial
scales – absolute spaces – within which the drive
towards equalisation is concentrated. But it can do
this only by an acute differentiation and continued
redifferentiation of relative space both within and
between scales. The scales themselves are not fixed
but develop (growing pangs and all) within the
development of capitalism itself. They are not
impervious; the urban and national scales are products of world capital and continue to be shaped by
it. But the necessity of discrete scales and of their
internal differentiation is fixed. (2008: 196)
‘Uneven development’, he concludes, ‘is the
product and geographical premise of capitalist development’.
HENRI LEFEBVRE’S CRITIQUE OF
FORMALISM AND OF URBAN FORM4
Smith’s arrival at a general theory of uneven
development as a necessary premise and
product of capitalist development owes a
significant debt to the work of Henri
Lefebvre, who first coined the term ‘the production of space’ and theorised spatial forms
in largely homologous terms to the production of nature thesis. For Stanley Aronowitz
(2015: 133), the Anglo-American academy’s
ignorance of Henri Lefebvre while he was
alive amounts to ‘a classic case of mis-recognition’, insofar as most failed to appreciate
his significance as
the ecophilosopher of the 21st century, for he
made the connection between the massive
BK-SAGE-BEST_ET_AL_V3-180084-Chp88.indd 1454
despoiling of the global ecosystems, the new
shape of social time and space and the struggle for
the transformation of everyday life which, he
claims, is the key to the project of changing life
and repairing our collective relationship to nature.5
Yet, in recent years, Lefebvre’s work has
become incredibly influential in its own
right, and his ideas and concepts have become
common currency among critical urban
theorists.6
Prior to the posthumous discovery of the
works of Henri Lefebvre by Anglophone
scholars since the 1990s,7 and of his popularisation by Marxists such as Smith, on the
one hand, and cultural theorists of ‘postmodernism’ on the other (see Kipfer et al.,
2008: 6–10), his reception in France and
elsewhere was primarily as someone who
wrote about dialectical method and Marx
in the Hegelian, humanist tradition common to much ‘Western Marxism’ (Shields,
1999: 109; also Jay, 1984).8 A hallmark of
Lefebvre’s writings is the extent to which
they are consistently methodologically
minded, the dialectic being the thread that
runs through his prolific and thematically
varied output over several decades. This is
certainly the case with his writings on space,
originally published in France between 1968
and 1974. In these, and in addition to arguing
persuasively that space should be thought of
in dialectical terms of its social production –
rather than in purely Cartesian and Euclidean
terms9 – one of Lefebvre’s signal criticaltheoretical contributions is to highlight the
anti-representational orientation of Hegelian
Marxism. That is, his critique of formal logic
and epistemology emphasised at once the
dialectic’s ability to reconcile social analysis with flux, internal relations, determinate
negation, mediation and Becoming, while
also exposing the violence or ‘terrorism’
inherent to dominant, representational norms
of analysis based upon purely formal epistemologies and methods of formal abstraction.
For Lefebvre, representational knowledge
about the world is an abstraction from concrete, lived experience [du vécu] and as such
5/11/18 4:37 PM
SPACE, FORM, AND URBANITY
ideological (for instance, Lefebvre, 1991:
230). In various works, Lefebvre reveals the
limits to formal epistemology, but also at
the level of serviceable representations that
have a ‘real’ and violent effect in the hands
of planning agencies and policymakers. In
his work on space and urbanism, Lefebvre
therefore railed against ‘models’ – abstract
but concretely applicable representations of
a projected, planned society in which some
kinds of social and spatial practice are condoned and others dismissed as pathological
or dysfunctional. Lefebvre is highly critical
of the intellectual division of labour characteristic of the modern university system,
as well as of the social role of ‘techniques,
technicians, technocrats, epistemology, and
the research of a purely technical or epistemological order’ (Lefebvre, 2009: 175) that
serve to dissect the total movement of human
social praxis, compartmentalise various
spheres or activities of everyday life (paradigmatically, in the circuit … production …
consumption … production …), and mould
concrete space according to the logic of pure
form, recurrence and coherence. To deny
particularity and difference, for Lefebvre, is
to be dogmatic, and to aim to reduce differences and close the circuit of everyday life
is to be implicated in the generalised ‘terrorism’ of the bourgeoisie (Lefebvre, 2000).
He writes ‘the physician of modern society
sees himself as the physician of a sick social
space … The cure? It is coherence … he will
systematise the logic of the habitat underlying the disorder and apparent incoherence’
(Lefebvre, 1996: 82–3).10 There is violence
intrinsic to such abstraction: ‘the “plan” …
does not remain innocently on paper. On
the ground, the bulldozer realizes “plans”’
(Lefebvre, 1996: 191). In terms of critique,
then, Lefebvre is certain that ‘to clear a path,
we have to destroy the models’ (Lefebvre,
2003: 163).
Lefebvre’s antidote to traditional epistemologies of urbanity, formal logic, speculative philosophies, Althusserian structuralism,
Sartre’s existentialism, and Soviet Diamat
BK-SAGE-BEST_ET_AL_V3-180084-Chp88.indd 1455
1455
was what he repeatedly calls ‘metaphilosophy’ (see Lefebvre, 2016). At root,
metaphilosophy is concerned with praxis:
‘Production produces man. So-called “world
history” or the “history of the world” is nothing but the history of man producing himself,
of man producing both the human world and
the other man, the (alienated) man of otherness, and his self (his self-consciousness)’
[sic] (Lefebvre, 2008: 237). The purpose of
critique, for Lefebvre, is therefore to illuminate and decipher human alienation on the
basis of praxis (2008: 137); it is to ask: ‘How
can men [sic] live as they are living, and how
can they accept it?’ (2008: 30). Lefebvre’s
own exploration of this question led him to
develop his critique of everyday life over the
course of four decades, and to his work on the
production of space.
The continuities of thought from Hegel
and Marx to Lefebvre are evident in the latter’s long-term preoccupation with everyday
life [la vie quotidienne], the practical problem of alienation that arises out of human
social practice in the historical form of bourgeois society, and an investigation into the
potential for realising an as yet only possible dis-alienated society through praxis. The
consideration of the broadest possible notion
of production (to include signs, writing, culture, space, etc.) as well as the problem of
re-production of the mode of production and
its associated forms of alienation, is central
to understanding Lefebvre’s long-term project as best represented by the three volumes
of his Critique of Everyday Life, published
between 1947 and 1981. As Lefebvre writes,
According to Marx’s early works … production is
not merely the making of products … it also signifies the self-production of the ‘human being’
in the process of historical self-development,
which involves the production of social relations.
Finally, in its fullest sense, the term embraces
re-production … [this] being the outcome of a
complex impulse rather than of inertia or passivity;
this impulse … this praxis and poiesis does not
take place in the higher spheres of a society (state,
scholarship, ‘culture’) but in everyday life.
(Lefebvre, 2000: 30–1)
5/11/18 4:37 PM
1456
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF FRANKFURT SCHOOL CRITICAL THEORY
This project yielded the substance of
Lefebvre’s lasting contribution to critical
social theory – a theory of social (re-)production
in which ‘everyday life has become an object
of consideration and is the province of organisation; the space–time of voluntary programmed self-regulation, because when
properly organised it provides a closed circuit (production–consumption–production),
where demands are foreseen because they are
induced and desires are run to earth’
(Lefebvre, 2000: 72). In recognising this, the
dialectic of everyday life builds upon the
Marxian critique of alienation, yet, in
Lefebvre’s view, broadens its parameters
beyond the critique of political economy
which hinges too narrowly on the question of
linear time. ‘Workers do not only have a life
in the workplace’, explains Lefebvre (1988:
78), ‘they have a social life, family life,
political life; they have experiences outside
the domain of labour’, and this would suggest, for Lefebvre, a closer examination of
how urban form guarantees the everyday
domination of the linear time of labour and
accumulation over the rhythmic time of biology, ecology, and art (Aronowitz, 2015).
The idea that the sphere of everyday life
can explain the survival of capitalism into
the late twentieth century – as well as illuminate the role of formal logic, modelling, and social planning as ideology, as we
explain later – leads Lefebvre (1976: 21)
to his now well-known thesis: that ‘capitalism has found itself able to attenuate (if
not resolve) its internal contradictions for a
century … by occupying space, by producing a space’. Lefebvre reveals that capitalism
produces its own (urban) space and, in so
doing, creates the permissive conditions for
the reproduction of the totality of bourgeois
society (an argument that implicated the former communist bloc as much as the West).
Time, understood in the abstract as concerning work, the production of commodities and
of surplus value, has been ‘reduced to constraints of space’ – circumscribed and suppressed within the urban form. The process
BK-SAGE-BEST_ET_AL_V3-180084-Chp88.indd 1456
of mediation that re-produces the social relations of production in a contradictory form,
according to Lefebvre, is therefore that of
urbanisation.
In The Urban Revolution (2003), Lefebvre
explains how the growth of industry and of the
forces of production on an increasingly global
scale has come to be subsumed by the more
encompassing process of urbanisation. In and
through the urban-form, capitalism is able
to reproduce itself by relativising all
particularities – a dialectical necessity Marx
identified in terms of the division of labour,
the factory system, and so on, but into which
Lefebvre introduces spatial determinations and
in so doing offers an explanation of the survival
of the capitalist mode of production to date.
The urban form totalises all particular labour
and space in an internal and ‘centralising’ relationship: ‘piles of objects and products in warehouses, mounds of fruit in the marketplace,
crowds, pedestrians, goods of various kinds,
juxtaposed, superimposed, accumulated –
this is what makes the urban urban’ (Lefebvre,
2003: 116). There is, according to Lefebvre,
‘no urban reality without a centre, without a
gathering together of all that can be born into
space and that can be produced in it, without an
encounter, actual or possible, of all “objects”
and “subjects”’ (Lefebvre, 1996: 195). Yet
despite this intrinsic centralisation, and despite
the urban being a creation of socio-ecological
metabolism, the urban-form is determined as
a ‘product’ (corresponding to exchangeability
and price signals) rather than an ‘ouvre’ – a
place of dwelling and of playful, poetic, and
artistic sociality and imagination. Perversely,
urbanised ‘citizens’ are concentrated together
in bodily proximity like never before, yet they
have never been more segregated, alienated, and
atomised in their everyday lives. For Lefebvre,
nowhere was this constraining and alienated
mode of everyday life within the urban habitat more evident than in the state-planned new
towns and housing projects erected in many
European cities in the post-war period. Here,
‘humiliation and the lack of freedom resulting
from the presence (and absence) of the centres
5/11/18 4:37 PM
SPACE, FORM, AND URBANITY
of decision-making and social life are keenly
felt’ (Lefebvre, 1969: 99).
Lefebvre’s critique of everyday life places
emphasis upon the extent to which, by the
1970s, time had become dominated by space,
the growth of the forces of production by the
development of the social relations of production,11 and in the urban-form. Moreover,
this reproduction occurs by means of the
totalising drive by capital to subsume the
entire world to abstract space (Lefebvre,
1991; Stanek, 2008), which is ‘abstract inasmuch as it has no existence save by virtue
of the exchangeability of all its component
parts, and concrete inasmuch as it is socially
real and as such localised’ (Lefebvre, 1991:
341–2). Lefebvre termed this process of
global subsumption [mondialisation], that
of the self-realisation of a spatial totality –
of the world ‘becoming worldwide’, of ‘planetary urbanisation’ (Lefebvre, 2009).
THE PRODUCTION OF SPACE AND
THE POLITICS OF DIFFERENCE
As a dialectical theorist, Lefebvre is adamant
that the urbanisation process also provides
clues as to the possibility of a dis-alienated
totality that already exists, albeit in the mode
of being denied. Analytically, this poses the
question of form and content. The key here is
to recognise that ‘urban space–time, as soon
as we stop defining it in terms of industrial
rationality – its project of homogenisation –
appears as differential’ (Lefebvre, 2003: 37).
That is, ‘abstract space is not homogenous; it
simply has homogeneity as its goal, its orientation, its “lens”’ (Lefebvre, 1991: 287). For
Lefebvre the Marxist, the identification of
the potentially revolutionary content of the
analysis of the production of space and critique of everyday life follows from the
insight that the production of space can only
proceed via a relational process of homogenisation-differentiation (Lefebvre, 1991:
308, 342; Stanek, 2008: 71–2). Urbanisation
BK-SAGE-BEST_ET_AL_V3-180084-Chp88.indd 1457
1457
brings human subjects together in space in
such a way that is necessary for the reproduction of the social relations of production, but
which also exacerbates the contradictions of
this abstract space – for example, it creates
centres in which ‘once groups and classes
succeed in meeting face to face, once they
come to grips, a free dialogue explodes under
the dialectical impetus’ (Lefebvre, 2000:
185). Homogenising abstract space is therefore constituted by social relations that
simultaneously constitute a ‘differential
space’, which ‘is different because it celebrates particularity – both bodily and experiential’ (Merrifield, 2000: 176). So, while
Lefebvre explains the necessity of urbanisation from the point of view of capital, he also
identifies ‘the existence of irreducibles, contradictions and objections that intervene and
hinder the closing of the circuit [of everyday
life], that split the structure’ (Lefebvre, 2000:
75). For Lefebvre, there is some residuum of
human subjectivity and style that capital has
been unable to subsume, invert or control,12
and it is this insight which holds the key to
understanding the limits to the production of
abstract space in an urban-form. Everyday
life is, according to Lefebvre, the sphere in
which such irreducibles are to be found. It is
‘the sociological point of feedback’
(Lefebvre, 2000: 32); ‘the ill-defined, cutting
edge where the accumulative and the nonaccumulative intersect’ (Lefebvre, 2008:
335); and ‘the point of delicate balance and
that where imbalance threatens’ (Lefebvre,
2000: 32). And, critically, it is the sphere that
holds the key to revolutionary action: ‘a revolution takes place when and only when, in
such a society, people can no longer lead
their everyday lives’.13
‘Urbanisation’ is for Lefebvre a determined, dialectical, systematic theoretical
category and not simply an empirical, immediate product. In general terms, it is a process in which the determinations ‘centrality’
(homogeneity) and ‘polycentrality’ (fragmentation, difference) are mediated, (un-)
fixed within the urban-form (Lefebvre, 2003:
5/11/18 4:37 PM
1458
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF FRANKFURT SCHOOL CRITICAL THEORY
119; Rui Martins, 1982: 171). The means of
critically analysing urban form as a mediating space which attains a ‘certain cohesiveness, if not a logical coherence’ (Lefebvre,
1991: 378) is laid out by Lefebvre in The
Production of Space (1991). Lefebvre outlines a unitary ‘spatial triad’ consisting of
three relational moments, or conceptions of
space, which allow the analyst to grasp both
the generative, diachronic constitution of
urban space as well as to behold, synchronically, the material appearance of socio-physical space at a given time. As one exponent
of such a Lefebvrean urbanist methodology summarises, this theory ‘has at its core
a three-level process of production: first,
material production; second, the production
of knowledge; and third, the production of
meaning’ (Schmid, 2006: 169) – corresponding to the three-fold determination of space
out of practical, mental, and symbolic dimensions. Lefebvre termed these dimensions;
first, the ‘perceived space’ [espace perçu] of
‘spatial practice’ based in the concrete and
networked social and physical infrastructures of production, exchange and social
reproduction that materialise under urbanisation. Second, the ‘conceived space’ [espace
conçu] of ‘representations of space’, comprised of ‘scientific’ and ‘official’ knowledge
that reduces space in functionalist terms –
diagnosing its utility and pathology and prescribing models to remould space. Third, the
‘spaces of representation’, or ‘lived space’
[espace veçu], in which inhabitants and users
of the city inscribe their own symbolic content and meaning to space in the course of
their everyday lives – producing an elusive
space of art, play, imagery, incoherence,
inconsistency, and everything that is surplus
or residual once the dissection of space by
traditional epistemological means has been
exhausted (Schmid, 2006: 168–9; see also
Merrifield, 1993: 522–5). Put another way,
Urban space is, first of all, material, perceivable
space. As such, it is a space of material interaction
and of physical meeting that is opened up by networks and information flows …
BK-SAGE-BEST_ET_AL_V3-180084-Chp88.indd 1458
Second, … [w]hat we understand of the city is
dependent on the social definition of the urban
and thus on the image of the city, on the blueprint
of the map, but also on the plan that tries to
define and pin down the urban.… Depending on
one’s perspective – scientific, planning, media, or
political – the city is understood to mean different
units. All these various definitions are specific representations of space. They describe discursive
demarcations of the content of the urban and
entail corresponding strategies of inclusion and
exclusion. Definitions of the city become a field in
which a variety of strategies and interests are
employed.
Third, the city is always a lived space as well, a
place of residents who use it and appropriate it for
their practices. The urban identifies the place of
difference: the specific quality of urban space
results from the simultaneous presence of quite
distinct worlds and concepts of value, of ethnic,
cultural, and social groups, of activities, functions,
and knowledge. (Schmid, 2006: 169–70)
Lefebvre’s analysis of urbanisation, and of
the production of abstract yet differential
space inherent to this process, points towards
a virtual, or possible, urban society – one in
which cyclical time is no longer subordinated
to space, and which is ‘based upon the elimination of antagonisms that find their expression in segregation; it must involve differences
and be defined by these differences’
(Lefebvre, 2000: 190).14 Lefebvre concluded
the means and end of revolutionary praxis in
an urbanised world to be ‘generalised selfmanagement’ [autogestion] and the ‘withering away of the state’ (Lefebvre, 2009: 149):
in short, ‘the end of politics’ (Lefebvre,
1970: 8). Lefebvre (2009: 246) considers the
logicians and modellers of space to be ‘agents
of the state’ precisely because they persist
despite the fact that the production of space
is a contradictory process in which difference
cannot be wholly reduced. Chief responsibility for suppressing the realisation of a disalienated urban society through the
concretisation of abstract space lies in the
Modern State (‘the quintessential limiter’ for
Lefebvre, 2003: 163). The state has, for
Lefebvre, assumed ever-increasing responsibility for circumscribing and cohering the
5/11/18 4:37 PM
SPACE, FORM, AND URBANITY
process of urbanisation and sustaining the
alienation inherent to programmed everyday
life (Lefebvre, 2008: 124–5). For Lefebvre
(2009: 174), then, ‘there is a politics of space
because space is political’. Lefebvre’s general critique of the process of urbanisation
carries along with it a politically focused
critique of reductive forms of knowledge,
instrumental representations of space – and
of their social and political function on an
increasingly global (or worldwide) scale. By
identifying autogestion as ‘orienting’ us to a
path towards dis-alienation by means of the
end of politics (Lefebvre, 1978: 295),
Lefebvre envisions a possible future beyond
capitalism (Lefebvre, 1968: 183) – a posture
which Aronowitz (2015: 154) claims distinguishes Lefebvre from the Frankfurt School’s
pessimistic stance arising out of its refusal of
the ideology of progress.
What distinguishes Lefebvre’s critical philosophy
from Critical Theory of the Frankfurt School is that
it understands that categories such as the ‘totally
administered society’ and the ‘eclipse of reason’ are
accurate as tendencies, but when taken as a new
totality, are one-sided. Lefebvre’s most urgent goal
is to recapture genuine experience and free the
concrete from its subsumption under the abstract,
represented most powerfully by technology and its
companion, administration. (2015: 154)
Aronowitz concludes that:
Lefebvre’s philosophy refuses the thesis that the
defeats of the past century are permanent and justify the refusal of the intellectual to engage in social
and political practice; in this respect, Lefebvre
stands with Sartre who insisted that the intellectual
must commit oneself to an historical standpoint,
even as one recognises the pitfalls. (2015: 154)
QUESTIONING LEFEBVRE’S CRITICAL
THEORY OF SPACE
Kanishka Goonewardena (2008: 131) incisively surmises that Lefebvre’s ‘basic contribution to Marxism’, was to make ‘the simple
point that there can be no revolution without
BK-SAGE-BEST_ET_AL_V3-180084-Chp88.indd 1459
1459
an urban revolution, no urban revolution
without a revolution, and neither without a
revolution of everyday life’. The pre-eminent
critical geographer Edward W. Soja (1980:
215) agreed: ‘[Lefebvre] argues that no social
revolution can succeed without being at the
same time a conscious, spatial revolution’.
Yet Lefebvre’s critique of space, and of his
faith in the emancipatory potentialities inherent to the production of spatialities that are
saturated with contradiction and therefore
political, has been subjected to scrutiny and
rejected by some on fundamental theoretical
grounds.15
As noted earlier, Neil Smith was very
much influenced by Lefebvre’s work. He
confessed that he remained ‘convinced by
the brilliance of his proposal of “the production of space”’ (Smith, 1998: 56), and later
maintains in his Foreword to The Urban
Revolution that ‘Lefebvre was seeing things
at the end of the 1960s that many of us, often
with his help, came to see clearly only in
more recent years and now are still recovering’ (Smith, 2003: viii). Yet Smith also
expressed deep-seated reservations about
Lefebvre’s version of a ‘respatialised social
theory’ (Smith, 1998: 51). In short, Smith
accuses Lefebvre of operating with precisely the kind of bifurcation between space
and nature that his own work warns against.
In Smith’s reading, Lefebvre ‘leaves nature
largely unreconstructed’ (1998: 59), much as
one of his influences Martin Heidegger did,
and such that ‘nature is reduced to a substratum’ (1998: 60). Space takes priority over
an external nature, and in Lefebvre’s somewhat bucolic and romanticist vision is lost
to time as the production of abstract space
proceeds with greater intensity and extensity.
For Smith, on the other hand – and as noted
earlier, ‘the production of space is integral
to the production of nature and fashioned
within it. It is the corollary of the production
of nature rather than the other way round’
(1998: 61). Ironically, then, Lefebvre’s treatment of nature bears all the hallmarks of the
same fetishisms that pervade the traditional
5/11/18 4:37 PM
1460
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF FRANKFURT SCHOOL CRITICAL THEORY
social and environmental sciences insofar as
he is apparently unable to comprehend the
production of second nature (and beyond, to
the extent that ‘the ongoing history of physical intervention … has already socialised – in
beautiful or grotesque form – what there is to
be apprehended’, 1998: 62).
Smith then questions the very necessity for
respatialised social theory in the first place:
‘Why, to put it most simply, is politics now
a question of space?’ (Smith, 1998: 52). In
Smith’s reading, Lefebvre mounts a formidable ‘anti-philosophical’ critique of traditional
philosophico-epistemological thought and its
fetishisation of space, but only to then himself
assert dogmatically that space ought to be the
ontological centre of properly critical theory
of societal development. ‘Lefebvre leans to
Hegel’s “end of history” and takes his stand
there, on “space” as the product and residue
of “historical time”’ (1998: 55). ‘History’ as
Marx, Bergson, Husserl, or Lukács knew it
therefore disappears in Lefebvre’s theory, to
be replaced by a strikingly teleological ‘spatial history’ (see Lefebvre, 1991) in which
‘the history of society is indeed the story of
class struggle, … but of class struggle for
space’ (Smith, 1998: 57). Smith’s concerns
here chime with those of Derek Kerr, writing in the now defunct journal Common
Sense just a few years earlier. He surmises of
Lefebvre’s works (1976 and 1991) that:
Class struggle and history are reduced to abstract
time and exist in the container of abstract space,
while this space has contradictions of its own
which can then externally ‘envelop historical contradictions’. But by separating out contradictions
of space from those in space and by reducing class
struggle and history to the latter, it is not clear
what constitutes the contradictions of space (Kerr,
1994: 32).
Against Lefebvre, he argues: ‘If social relations are inherently spatial and temporal then
there can be no separation in/of dualism’
(1994: 32); furthermore, to ‘displace time by
space merely obscures the dynamic and contradictory nature of the capital relation and
the ways in which this expresses itself in a
BK-SAGE-BEST_ET_AL_V3-180084-Chp88.indd 1460
spatially uneven way through … “the production of space in its own image”’ (1994:
34). For Kerr, then:
Marx was not limiting himself to time, but to
uncovering the contradictory constitution of the
capital relation (see Bonefeld, 1993) as it attempts
to transform and express itself through spatial and
temporal modalities of existence. It is the capital
relation that continually attempts to subordinate
the whole (space) of society to the abstract logic of
linear time, the ticking of the factory clock. This
abstract time is not the concrete history of capitalism, but rather is the dominant and contradictory
tendency through which that history expresses
itself, one which continually attempts to reduce the
internally related and qualitative nature of both
space and time to the quantitative metric of value.
As such the form, nature and very existence of
‘capitalist space’ expresses and adheres in and
through the contradictory presence of labour in
capital. This is the dialectic, not one of time nor
of space but … a negative dialectic, a dialectic of
negation with no certain synthesis … The history
of capitalism is, therefore, none other than the
struggle over and through space as capital attempts
to transform the entire spatial existence of society
into a machine for the production and quantitative
expansion of surplus value in terms of the metric of
socially necessary labour time. (1994: 32)
Finally, Smith begs of Lefebvre’s work the
more practical political question of providing
some insight into what an alternative, spatialised politics would look like. In addition to
proposing that any viable emancipatory project would have to be based upon a more
convincing dialectic of nature than that with
which Lefebvre operates, Smith also
highlights the inadequacy of Lefebvre’s
‘reproductionism’ – that is, the insistence that
whatever crisis might confront the capitalist
system and bring an urban politics of difference to the fore would be a crisis of the reproduction of the social relations of production
in and through space, rather than a crisis of
capital’s necessity to self-valorise on the basis
of the exploitation of living labour and its
metabolic relation with nature. In the last
instance, even if one accepts a reproductionist
posture such as Lefebvre’s, it is unclear
exactly how space per se – rather than the
contradictory socio-ecological nature of
5/11/18 4:37 PM
SPACE, FORM, AND URBANITY
capital, however mediated – will determine
substantive political change. As Smith puts it,
‘where Lefebvre closes in on the political
conclusions of his analysis, … space seems to
fall entirely out of the picture … it is nowhere
to be seen. The dualism of space and society
lingers on’ (Smith, 2008: 125).
LEFEBVRE’S LEGACY: FROM THE
RIGHT TO THE CITY TO PLANETARY
URBANISATION
Notwithstanding the criticisms levelled at his
work on space, Lefebvre retains significant
influence in debates surrounding urban
development, governance, and politics – and
his theories and concepts have had a demonstrably enduring impact on critical social and
urban theory.16 For instance, in the wake of
urban social mobilisations in 2010 – ranging
from the Arab Spring, to the Occupy! movement – commentators and activists sought to
make sense of what was happening with
recourse to familiar Lefebvrean concepts.
David Harvey paid homage to ‘Lefebvre’s
vision’ (2012: ix), concluding that: ‘Perhaps,
after all, Lefebvre was right, more than forty
years ago, to insist that the revolution in our
times has to be urban – or nothing’ (2012:
25). Harvey, like many others,17 attaches
great political importance to the notion of the
‘right to the city’ (Lefebvre, 1996) – which
Harvey reinterprets as ‘to claim some kind of
shaping power over the processes of urbanisation, over the ways in which our cities are
made and remade, and to do so in a fundamental and radical way’. Andy Merrifield
similarly builds his own theory of urban
theory and protest around this Lefebvrean
concept, but also argues that Lefebvre forewarned us of the degree to which the substantive realisation of the right to the city – ‘a
new form of centrality and citizenship’ (2013:
34, italics in original) – would become a
pressing need for the majority of humanity
under the socio-ecological condition of
BK-SAGE-BEST_ET_AL_V3-180084-Chp88.indd 1461
1461
‘planetary urbanisation’. ‘Planetary urbanisation is creating a whole new spatial world
(dis)order’, he writes (2013: 3). ‘The more
the city grows, develops, extends itself, and
spreads its tentacles everywhere, [Lefebvre]
says, the more social relations get degraded
and the more sociability is torn apart at the
seams’ (2013: 15).
It would appear, then, that Lefebvre has
bequeathed a politically effective lexicon of
urbanity to the contemporary scholar-activist.
But while Merrifield himself is open to a
more experimental, perhaps less systematic,
approach to urban theory and politics (see
also Merrifield, 2011), others have picked
up on Lefebvre’s methodological relevance
for research in a world that is, as many suggest, more urbanised than ever before. Neil
Brenner and Christian Schmid (2014, 2015),
for example, have in recent years sought to
subvert accepted ‘mainstream’ definitions
and epistemologies of the so-called ‘urban
age’ (e.g. UN-Habitat, 2007) in accordance
with Lefebvre’s metaphilosophy (Brenner,
2013a: 95; see also Angelo and Wachsmuth,
2015). They posit, as but one of seven theses
on an epistemology of ‘the urban’, that:
No longer conceived as a form, type or bounded
unit, the urban must now be retheorised as a process that, even while continually reinscribing patterns of agglomeration across the earth’s terrestrial
landscape, simultaneously transgresses, explodes
and reworks inherited geographies (of social interaction, settlement, land use, circulation and sociometabolic organisation), both within and beyond
large-scale metropolitan centres. (Brenner and
Schmid, 2015: 166)
The critical intent of such a critique of existing, ‘methodologically cityist’ (Angelo and
Wachsmuth, 2015), epistemologies of ‘the
urban’ is to ‘illuminate the manifold ways in
which the users of urbanizing spaces produce
and transform their own urban worlds through
everyday practices, discourses, and struggles,
leading to the formation not only of new
urban spatial configurations, but of new
visions of the potentials being produced and
claimed through their activities’ (Brenner and
5/11/18 4:37 PM
1462
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF FRANKFURT SCHOOL CRITICAL THEORY
Schmid, 2015: 178). For Brenner (2013a: 89),
and others, Lefebvre’s critical theory remains
hugely influential as a ‘rallying cry’ for many
wishing to play an active role in reshaping
‘the future of capitalism, politics, and the
planetary ecosystem’, since it posits that ‘the
urban is thus no longer a site or arena of contentious politics, but has become one of its
primary stakes. Reorganising urban conditions is increasingly seen as a means to transform the broader political-economic structures
and spatial formations of early twenty-first
century world capitalism as a whole’.
Foundational work by Brenner and others18 is
already yielding fresh research producing
new cartographies and politico-economic
accounts of planetary urbanisation – and
which seek to subvert the methodological
cityism inherent to traditional urban theory
(see e.g. Arboleda, 2015; Brenner, 2013b;
Kanai, 2014; Wilson and Bayón, 2015).
CONCLUSION
In the absence of a definitive Frankfurt
School theory of space, form and urbanity,
this chapter has focused on the theory of the
production of space developed by the French
contemporary of Adorno and Horkheimer,
Henri Lefebvre. Initially by means of a detour
to the work of the geographer Neil Smith –
who insisted that the production of space is a
corollary of the production of nature – the
chapter expounded the dialectical relation
between humans, nature and space, as developed by Smith in dialogue with Alfred
Schmidt’s work on human labour and nature,
before moving on to Lefebvre. Lefebvre’s
theory of the production of space – itself spun
out of a longer-term preoccupation with everyday life in mid-twentieth-century capitalism –
was shown to parallel the Critical Theory of
the Frankfurt School insofar as it subjected
traditional theories of space to critique in
accordance with Marx’s insistence that it is the
definite social relations between humans that
BK-SAGE-BEST_ET_AL_V3-180084-Chp88.indd 1462
manifest themselves in social forms, and not
nature or history abstractly conceived. The
chapter then outlined Lefebvre’s contribution
to the analysis of space as a social product, his
theory of urbanisation, and his writings on the
politics of space, before reviewing significant
criticisms of that contribution – not least by
Smith, who identified weaknesses that can be
traced back to Lefebvre’s inadequate dialectic
of nature and space. Regardless of such issues,
the chapter concluded by acknowledging
Lefebvre’s lasting legacy; first, in terms of the
longevity of his key terms and concepts, such
as the production of space and the right to the
city, but also in his role as a key interlocutor in
an emergent literature on planetary urbanisation. By questioning the methodological cityism of traditional urban theory and policy,
such work illuminates the degree to which
even the ostensibly ‘non-urban’ world is today
subsumed to the destructive process of capital
accumulation, rendering the traditional urban–
rural distinction problematic in epistemological but also political terms (Arboleda, 2016;
Brenner, 2016). As such, it echoes Lefebvre’s
concern to develop a critique of space and of
urbanity that is not reducible to a concern with
‘the city’ as a mere container, or form of
human settlement that poses certain governance problems (such as overcrowding or sanitation and infrastructure) to which technocratic,
market-based fixes might be found. Rather,
this emergent literature seeks to build upon the
theorising of Lefebvre and others so as to highlight the dangers of traditional urban theory’s
formal methods of abstraction so as to open up
more substantive and subversive debate about
urbanity, citizenship and social nature beyond
the city and on a biospheric, planetary scale.
Notes
1
2
See e.g. the important appeal to consider the violence of real geographical abstractions by Loftus
(2015).
For useful discussion of the concept of ‘metabolism’ [Stoffwechsel] in Marx’s writings, see Foster
(2000: chapter 5); and for further discussion of
5/11/18 4:37 PM
SPACE, FORM, AND URBANITY
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
the concept in the work of Adorno, Schmidt, and
Foster, see Cook (2014).
Smith’s more empirical interest in the 1980s was in
advancing a Marxian explanation for how and why
localised instances of ‘gentriication’ were becoming common to many ‘postindustrial’ inner-cities in
the United States and Western Europe.
This and the subsequent sections draw upon my
earlier work on Lefebvre (Charnock, 2010, 2014;
Charnock and Ribera-Fumaz, 2011).
Lefebvre’s life story makes for fascinating reading. It is often remarked that he ‘lived the adventure of the twentieth century’ (Hess, 1988; Kipfer
et al., 2008: 2). For accounts of Lefebvre’s life
and work in English, see Elden (2004), Merriield
(2006), and Shields (1999); and for the deinitive
account of his interest in space and urbanity in
particular, see Stanek (2011).
See e.g. Peter Marcuse (2009), son of Frankfurt
School theorist Herbert Marcuse.
This surge in interest in Henri Lefebvre in Anglophone social science followed, and encouraged,
the irst publication of several of his major works in
English: notably, The Production of Space (1991),
The Right to the City (published in Writings on
Cities (1996)), Everyday Life in the Modern World
(2000), The Urban Revolution (2003), three volumes of Critique of Everyday Life (2008), and the
collection of essays in State, Space, World (2009).
Stanek (2011: 63, 272) notes how Lefebvre was in
various instances engaged in personal dialogue with
Georg Lukács in the 1940s and 1950s, and participated in events with the likes of Kostas Axelos, Ernst
Bloch, Jürgen Habermas, Herbert Marcuse, and
Alfred Sohn Rethel among others in the 1960s.
What Dimendberg (1998: 19) terms the paradigm
of ‘containerism’, with its roots in ‘the Aristotelian
category of topos, the res extensa of Descartes,
Newton’s void, and the absolute of Leibniz’, and
which presupposes that ‘space is essentially empty
and static, a passive and inert vessel’.
See Elden (2004) on Martin Heidegger’s inluence
upon Lefebvre’s argument that ‘inhabiting [habiter]
has been reduced to the notion of habitat [habitat]’.
For Lefebvre’s own clariication of these Marxian categories, see The Sociology of Marx (1968: 19–20).
See Kouvelakis (2008: 711) on Lefebvre and
‘modernity’: ‘the “shadow” cast over bourgeois
society by the failure of revolution, at once a
compensatory substitute and the ineliminable
trace of vanquished hopes’.
Such instances are theorised by Lefebvre in terms
of ‘moments’. ‘The moment is a philosophical
anticoncept’, writes Merriield (2009: 939), ‘an
afirmation of residue, or remainders, of marginal leftovers, of the power and radicality of the
ragged and the irreducible’.
BK-SAGE-BEST_ET_AL_V3-180084-Chp88.indd 1463
1463
14 This conclusion is rendered politically programmatic
in Lefebvre’s (1970) Le manifeste différentialiste. In
this, Lefebvre champions a politics of maximal difference (‘total subversion of the mental and social
totality’), and juxtaposes this with the minimal difference characteristic of programmed everyday life
(which ensures ‘the cohesion of a society divided
into sectors, levels, aspects, groups and classes of
unequal development and in conlict’).
15 The concerns of Critical Theory aside, there are
several possible objections to Lefebvre’s arguments. One might justiiably criticise Lefebvre
for merely asserting, and never substantively
accounting for, both the salience of the urban
problematique and the obsolescence of the critique of political economy (Harvey, 1974: 239).
One might also raise concerns about the ‘contextual boundedness’ of aspects of Lefebvre’s work
(Brenner, 2008: 242), insofar as his work is of its
time (steeped in frustration with everyday life in
Gaullist France) and failed to anticipate so-called
‘neoliberal globalisation’ and the transition to
‘post-Fordism’. Alternatively, Lefebvre has been
dismissed on Deleuzian grounds as but another
Marxist whose ‘social critique’ has been rendered
obsolete by the transformation to lexible capitalism and the transformation of the ‘subaltern
subjectivity’ of the ‘liberated individual’ (Ronneberger, 2008). Perhaps Lefebvre’s most vehement critic, however, was Manuel Castells – a still
prominent sociologist – who rejected Lefebvre’s
thesis on urbanity on Althusserian, structuralist grounds in The Urban Question (1979). For
an instructive comparison of the urban theories
of Castells and Lefebvre, see Gottdiener (1994:
chapter 4).
16 For example, see the discussions of how Lefebvre’s
ideas were appropriated into mainstream urban
planning discourse from the 1970s onwards in Gilbert and Dikeç (2008) and Stanek (2011).
17 See e.g. Boyer (2014) and Purcell (2013).
18 For examples of other research in these areas, see
the website of the Urban Theory Lab at www.
urbantheorylab.net (accessed 31 August 2016).
REFERENCES
Adorno, Theodor W. (2001) The Culture Industry. London: Routledge (1st edn, 1991).
Angelo, Hillary and David Wachsmuth (2015)
‘Urbanizing Urban Political Ecology: A Critique of Methodological Cityism’, International Journal of Urban and Regional Research,
39(1): 16–27.
5/11/18 4:37 PM
1464
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF FRANKFURT SCHOOL CRITICAL THEORY
Arboleda, Martín (2015) ‘Spaces of Extraction,
Metropolitan Explosions: Planetary Urbanization and the Commodity Boom in Latin
America’, International Journal of Urban and
Regional Research, 40(1): 96–112.
Arboleda, Martín (2016) ‘In the Nature of the
Non-City: Expanded Infrastructural Networks
and the Political Ecology of Planetary Urbanisation’, Antipode, 48(2): 233–51.
Aronowitz, Stanley (2015) Against Orthodoxy:
Social Theory and its Discontents. New York:
Palgrave Macmillan.
Backhaus, Hans-Georg (2005) ‘Some Aspects
of Marx’s Concept of Critique in the Context
of his Economic-Philosophical Theory’, in W.
Bonefeld and K. Psychopedis (eds), Human
Dignity: Social Autonomy and the Critique of
Capitalism. London: Routledge, 13–30.
Bellofiore, Riccardo and Tommaso Redolfi Riva
(2015) ‘The Neue Marx-Lektüre: Putting the
Critique of Political Economy Back into the
Critique of Society’, Radical Philosophy, 189:
24–36.
Bonefeld, Werner (1993) The Recomposition of
the British State During the 1980s. Aldershot: Dartmouth.
Bonefeld, Werner (2001) ‘Kapital and its Subtitle: A Note on the Meaning of Critique’,
Capital & Class, 25(3): 53–63.
Bonefeld, Werner (2014) Critical Theory and
the Critique of Political Economy: On Subversion and Negative Reason. New York:
Bloomsbury.
Boyer, M. Christine (2014) ‘Reconstructing
New Orleans and the Right to the City’, in
Ł. Stanek, C. Schmid and Á. Moravánsky
(eds), Urban Revolution Now: Henri Lefebvre
in Social Research and Architecture. London:
Routledge, 173–89.
Brenner, Neil (2008) ‘Henri Lefebvre’s Critique
of State Productivism’, in S. Kipfer, et al. (eds),
Space, Difference, Everyday Life: Reading Henri
Lefebvre. New York: Routledge, 231–49.
Brenner, Neil (2009) ‘What is Critical Urban
Theory?’, City, 13(2–3): 198–207.
Brenner, Neil (2013a) ‘Theses on Urbanization’,
Public Culture, 25(1): 85–114.
Brenner, Neil (ed.) (2013b) Implosion/Explosion:
Towards a Study of Planetary Urbanization.
Berlin: JOVIS-Verlag.
Brenner, Neil (2016) ‘The Hinterland Urbanised?’, Architectural Design, 86(4): 118–27.
BK-SAGE-BEST_ET_AL_V3-180084-Chp88.indd 1464
Brenner, Neil and Christian Schmid (2014) ‘The
“Urban Age” In Question’, International
Journal of Urban and Regional Research,
38(3): 731–55.
Brenner, Neil and Christian Schmid (2015)
‘Towards a New Epistemology of the Urban?’,
City, 19(2–3): 151–82.
Castells, Manuel (1979) The Urban Question: A
Marxist Approach. Tr. Alan Sheridan. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Castree, Noel (2006) ‘The Detour of Critical
Theory’, in N. Castree and D. Gregory (eds),
David Harvey: A Critical Reader. Oxford:
Blackwell, 247–69.
Charnock, Greig (2010) ‘Challenging New
State Spatialities: The Open Marxism of Henri
Lefebvre’, Antipode, 42(5): 1279–303.
Charnock, Greig (2014) ‘Lost in Space? Lefebvre, Harvey and the Spatiality of Negation’,
South Atlantic Quarterly, 113(2): 313–25.
Charnock, Greig and Ramon Ribera-Fumaz
(2011) ‘“A New Space for Knowledge and
People?” Henri Lefebvre, Representations of
Space, and the Production of “22@Barcelona”’, Environment and Planning D: Society
and Space, 29(4), 613–32.
Cook, Deborah (2014) Adorno on Nature.
Abingdon: Routledge (1st edn, 2011).
Dimendberg, Edward (1998) ‘Henri Lefebvre on
Abstract Space’, in A. Light and J. M. Smith
(eds), Philosophy and Geography II: The Production of Public Space. Oxford: Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers, 17–47.
Elden, Stuart (2004) Understanding Henri Lefebvre: Theory and the Possible. London:
Continuum.
Foster, John Bellamy (2000) Marx’s Ecology:
Materialism and Nature. New York: Monthly
Review Press.
Gilbert, Liette and Mustafa Dikeç (2008) ‘Right
to the City: Politics of Citizenship’, in
S. Kipfer et al. (eds), Space, Difference, Everyday Life: Reading Henri Lefebvre. New
York: Routledge, 250–63.
Goonewardena, Kanishka (2008) ‘Marxism and
Everyday Life: On Henri Lefebvre, Guy Debord
and Some Others’, in S. Kipfer et al. (eds),
Space, Difference, Everyday Life: Reading Henri
Lefebvre. New York: Routledge, 117–33.
Gottdiener, Mark (1994) The Social Production
of Urban Space. Austin: University of Texas
Press (1st edn, 1985).
5/11/18 4:37 PM
SPACE, FORM, AND URBANITY
Harvey, David (1974) ‘Class-Monopoly Rent,
Finance Capital and the Urban Revolution’,
Regional Studies, 8(3–4): 239–55.
Harvey, David (2007) The Limits to Capital.
London: Verso (1st edn, 1982).
Harvey, David (2012) Rebel Cities: From the
Right to the City to the Urban Revolution.
London: Verso.
Hess, Rémi (1988) Henri Lefebvre et l’aventure
du siècle. Paris: A. M. Métailié.
Horkheimer, Max (2002) Critical Theory:
Selected Essays. Tr. Herder & Herder, Inc.
New York: Continuum (1st edn, 1972).
Jay, Martin (1984) Marxism and Totality: The
Adventures of a Concept from Lukács to
Habermas. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Kanai, Juan Miguel (2014) ‘On the Peripheries
of Planetary Urbanization: Globalizing
Manaus and its Expanding Impact’, Environment and Planning D: Society and Space,
32(6): 1071–87.
Kerr, Derek (1994) ‘The Time of Trial by Space?
Critical Reflections on Henri Lefebvre’s Epoch
of Space’, Common Sense, 15: 18–35.
Kipfer, Stefan et al. (2008) ‘On the Production
of Henri Lefebvre’, in S. Kipfer et al. (eds),
Space, Difference, Everyday Life: Reading
Henri Lefebvre. New York: Routledge, 1–23.
Kirsch, Scott (2012) ‘Book Review: State,
Space, World: Selected Essays, by Henri Lefebvre’, Antipode, 44(3): 1042–9.
Kouvelakis, Stathis (2008) ‘Henri Lefebvre,
Thinker of Urban Modernity’, in J. Bidet and
S. Kouvelakis (eds), Critical Companion to
Contemporary Marxism. Brill: Leiden,
711–27.
Lefebvre, Henri (1968) The Sociology of Marx.
London: Penguin.
Lefebvre, Henri (1969) The Explosion: Marxism
and the French Upheaval. Tr. A. Ehrenfeld.
New York: Monthly Review Press.
Lefebvre, Henri (1970) Le Manifeste Différentialiste. Paris: Éditions Gallimard.
Lefebvre, Henri (1976) The Survival of Capitalism: Reproduction of the Relations of Production. London: Allison and Busby.
Lefebvre, Henri (1978) De l’État, tome IV: Les
contradictions de l’État moderne. La dialectique et/de l’État. Paris: Union Générale
d’Éditions.
Lefebvre, Henri (1988) ‘Toward a Leftist Cultural Politics: Remarks Occasioned by the
BK-SAGE-BEST_ET_AL_V3-180084-Chp88.indd 1465
1465
Centenary of Marx’s Death’, in C. Nelson and
L. Grossberg (eds), Marxism and the Interpretation of Culture. Tr. D. Reifman. Champaign: University of Illinois Press, 75–88.
Lefebvre, Henri (1991) The Production of
Space. Tr. D. Nicholson-Smith. Oxford:
Blackwell.
Lefebvre, Henri (1996) Writings on Cities. E.
Kofman and E. Lebas (eds). Oxford:
Blackwell.
Lefebvre, Henri (2000) Everyday Life in the
Modern World. Tr. S Rabinovitch. London:
The Athlone Press.
Lefebvre, Henri (2003) The Urban Revolution.
Tr. R. Bononno. Minnesota: University of
Minnesota Press.
Lefebvre, Henri (2008) Critique of Everyday
Life, Volume 2: Foundations for a Sociology
of the Everyday. Tr. John Moore. London:
Verso.
Lefebvre, Henri (2009) State, Space, World:
Selected Essays. N. Brenner and S. Elden
(eds). Minnesota: University of Minnesota
Press.
Lefebvre, Henri (2016) Metaphilosophy. N.
Brenner (ed). Tr. D. Fernbach. London: Verso.
Loftus, Alex (2015) ‘Violent Geographical
Abstractions’, Environment and Planning D:
Society and Space, 33(2): 366–81.
Marcuse, Peter (2009) ‘From Critical Urban
Theory to the Right to the City’, City, 13(2–
3): 185–97.
Marx, Karl (1993) Grundrisse: Foundations of
the Critique of Political Economy. Tr. M. Nicolaus. London: Penguin.
Merrifield, Andy (1993) ‘Place and Space: A
Lefebvrian Reconciliation’, Transactions of
the Institute of British Geographers, 18(4):
516–31.
Merrifield, Andy (2000) ‘Henri Lefebvre: A
Socialist in Space’, in M. Crang and N. Thrift
(eds), Thinking Space. London: Routledge,
167–82.
Merrifield, Andy (2006) Henri Lefebvre: A Critical Introduction. New York: Routledge.
Merrifield, Andy (2009) ‘Review Essay: The
Whole and the Rest: Remi Hess and les lefebvriens français’, Environment and Planning
D: Society and Space, 27(5): 936–49.
Merrifield, Andy (2011) Magical Marxism: Subversive Politics and the Imagination. London:
Pluto.
5/11/18 4:37 PM
1466
THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF FRANKFURT SCHOOL CRITICAL THEORY
Merrifield, Andy (2013) The Politics of the
Encounter: Urban Theory and Protest under
Planetary Urbanization. Athens: University of
Georgia Press.
Purcell, Mark (2013) ‘The Right to the City: The
Struggle for Democracy in the Urban Public
Realm’, Policy & Politics, 41(3): 311–27.
Reichelt, Helmut (2005) ‘Social Reality as
Appearance: Some Notes to Marx’s Conception of Reality’, in W. Bonefeld and K. Psychopedis (eds), Human Dignity: Social
Autonomy and the Critique of Capitalism.
London: Routledge, 31–67.
Ronneberger, Klaus (2008) ‘Henri Lefebvre and
Urban Everyday Life: In Search of the Possible’, in S. Kipfer et al. (eds), Space, Difference, Everyday Life: Reading Henri Lefebvre.
New York: Routledge, 134–46.
Rui Martins, Mario (1982) ‘The Theory of Social
Space in the Work of Henri Lefebvre’, in R. Forrest, J Henderson and P. Williams (eds), Urban
Political Economy and Social Theory: Essays in
Urban Studies. Aldershot: Gower, 160–85.
Schmid, Christian (2006) ‘Theory’, in R. Diener
et al., Switzerland: An Urban Portrait. Basel:
Birkhäuser, 163–224.
Schmidt, Alfred (1971) The Concept of Nature
in Marx. Tr. B. Fowkes. London: NLB.
Shields, Rob (1999) Lefebvre, Love and Struggle: Spatial Dialectics. London: Routledge.
Smith, Neil (1998) ‘Antinomies of Space and
Nature in Henri Lefebvre’s The Production of
Space’, in A. Light and J. M. Smith (eds),
Philosophy and Geography II: The Production
BK-SAGE-BEST_ET_AL_V3-180084-Chp88.indd 1466
of Public Space. Oxford: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 49–69.
Smith, Neil (2003) ‘Foreword’, in H. Lefebvre,
The Urban Revolution. Minnesota: University
of Minnesota Press, vii–xxiii.
Smith, Neil (2006) ‘Nature as Accumulation
Strategy’, in L. Panitch and C. Leys (eds),
Coming to Terms with Nature: Socialist Register, 2007. London: Merlin Press, 16–36.
Smith, Neil (2008) Uneven Development:
Nature, Capital, and the Production of Space.
3rd edn. Athens: University of Georgia Press
(1st edn, 1984).
Soja, Edward W. (1980) ‘The Socio-Spatial Dialectic’, Annals of the Association of American Geographers, 70(2): 207–25.
Stanek, Łukasz (2008) ‘Space as Concrete
Abstraction: Hegel, Marx and Modern
Urbanism in Henri Lefebvre’, in S. Kipfer
et al. (eds), Space, Difference, Everyday Life:
Reading Henri Lefebvre. New York: Routledge, 62–79.
Stanek, Łukasz (2011) Henri Lefebvre on Space:
Architecture, Urban Research, and the Production of Theory. London: University of
Minnesota Press.
UN-Habitat (United Nations Human Settlement
Programme) (2007) The State of the World’s
Cities Report 2006–2007: 30 Years of Shaping the Habitat Agenda. London: Earthscan.
Wilson, Japhy and Manuel Bayón (2015) ‘Concrete Jungle: The Planetary Urbanization of
the Ecuadorian Amazon’, Human Geography, 8(3): 1–23.
5/11/18 4:37 PM