Journal of Philosophy of Education, Vol. 35, No. 1, 2001
Schools and Moral Education: Conformism
or Autonomy?
WILLEM L. WARDEKKER
In pluralistic Western societies, schools have a specific task in
moral education. This task is to be understood neither as the
transmission of specific values, nor as the development of
moral reasoning skills or universal values, but as teaching
pupils to handle plurality in an autonomous way. The concept
of autonomy is interpreted from a Vygotskian and Deweyan
position, where learning in school means learning to
participate in cultural activities in a reflective and critical
way. Participation has both intellectual and moral aspects,
and thus moral education can never be separated from
cognitive education.
UNCERTAINTY IN MORAL EDUCATION
To judge from some rather alarming publications (for example, Ritzen,
1992), it seems that public morality and responsibility in Western
countries are in danger of becoming extinct. While the more pessimistic
commentators point to an increase in public excesses and vandalism,
others see an increase in the number of people who base their behaviour
on calculation of personal gains and losses rather than on a feeling of
responsibility. Both sets of commentators, however, tend to diagnose
these problems as caused by a decline in the function and importance of
moral education in the family and in schools.
The causes of this decline, in its turn, are found in changes in the
structure of society and the associated functions of the nuclear family.
Traditional family structures are dissolving; parents are no longer the
only or even the most obvious objects of identification. Their role is said
to have been taken, in part, by superficially much more attractive film
and television heroes, not to mention football stars. Moreover, the
traditional authority of parents over their children is declining.
According to De Swaan (1982), Western societies are changing from
authority-based relations to negotiation-based relations. This applies to
parent±child relations too.
One would expect such loss of traditional authority to lead to feelings
of uncertainty in parents. This supposed uncertainty of parents has been
& The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain 2001. Published by Blackwell Publishers, 108
Cowley Road, Oxford OX4 1JF and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA.
102
W. L. Wardekker
the subject of many discussions. Ritzen, the Dutch Minister of
Education, for instance, inferred from the decline of the traditional
family and the lack of certainty in those traditional families that can still
be found, that more than ever schools have a role in moral education.
However, such uncertainty is not evident from a recent nationwide
survey among Dutch parents in The Netherlands (Rispens, Hermanns
and Meeus, 1996), or from similar data from other countries. Neither is
it plausible that the number of children that are not raised within a
family that contributes to the children's developing moral and cultural
identity could alone account for the extent of the perceived problem.
Rather, the problem may be the development of traditional society
into a plural society. By plurality, I mean not only the ever more
manifest presence of ethnic groups with different cultural patterns.
However much multiculturality and multi-ethnicity may occupy our
attention, they are only one aspect of plurality. The wider phenomenon
is that people in Western societies (and probably globally) are confronted
continuously with numerous possibilities for structuring their lives and
with the necessity of making choices (Giddens, 1991). It is becoming
more difficult to ground these decisions in accepted rules and patterns;
there is not just one authority, like the Church in earlier times, to which
one can look for guidance. There is now a plethora of groups and
institutions of which people may consider themselves members, often at
the same time; and within them, ideals and values shift quicker and
stable patterns are difficult to find, as the advertising business has found
out to its chagrin.
In this situation, a traditional moral education, which emphasises
loyalty to established values and points of view, becomes problematic.
The unavoidable confrontation with other points of view leaves developing persons in a state of uncertainty and even possibly of anomie. This, I
think, may be the background to discussions about the task and role of
the schools in the moral education of their pupils.
It is significant in this context that Minister Ritzen made his plea
for moral education in the schools in The Netherlands, which is
characterised by a structural diversity originally based on religion. The
Dutch school system was built on the idea that moral education is a
prerogative of parents, and schools may only occupy themselves with it
insofar they can be seen as extensions of parental authority, organised
along the lines of religious denominations. State influence in moral
education matters has always been viewed as suspect. Minister Ritzen,
on the other hand, advocated a stronger role for schools in moral
education, especially in universal values, or at least those shared widely
within Dutch society. The implication seems to be that Ritzen is
suggesting a way to overcome the differences in cultural points of view
and values which are inherent in a plural society, thereby showing pupils
a clear way to a normal life.
This plea, while on the whole received favourably, generated a lively
discussion about the nature and content of values and norms to be
taught in the schools. Although a few discussants took the position that
& The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain 2001.
Schools and Moral Education: Conformism or Autonomy?
103
moral education does not belong in the schools at all, most of them seem
to hope that schools will be able to identify and teach at least a minimum
of universal values and norms which every well-meaning person should
adhere to. As an example of this, `respect for other people and their
beliefs' is often mentioned as a value of special importance in a plural
society. Schools, rather than parents, are then seen as being the adequate
institutions for transmitting and defending such universal values, as an
extension of their task in transmitting universally valid knowledge and
rational thinking and acting. For there seems to be a direct connection
between rationality, right-mindedness and the `good' life. Still others, of
course, argue for a continued and enhanced function of the schools in
transmitting the values of specific (religious) groups and traditions,
either by themselves or as an addition to and specification of universals.
In this paper, I will examine and reject all three positions mentioned
thus far. I do think that moral education is a task for schools; but neither
the transmission of universal values, nor that of specific traditions, is a
valid interpretation of that task. Instead, I will defend the idea that the
task of moral education is to teach pupils to handle the plurality of our
society in an autonomous way. This is in line with my belief that a plural
society is not just to be considered a threat to morality. Rather, it presents
people with opportunities and advantages over the rigid morality of
traditional societies. Where everybody has the same outlook on things,
and deviation is punished, often by exclusion from the community, no
freedom of thought and action is possible. Such freedom is essential
for finding new ways of working and living together; and finding such
ways is necessary because a community that excludes change, excludes
differences, will eventually become dangerously unresponsive to outside
changes. This is not to say, of course, that any new way of life is better
just because it is new.
DO SCHOOLS HAVE A MORAL TASK?
I will start this discussion by considering the arguments of those who
would deny the school a task in moral education. Many of these arguments have been worded by the Dutch educational psychologist Hofstee
(1992). His text is especially relevant because it was written as advice to
the National Advisory Board on Education on the subject of the role of
civic education in schools. (The Board, by the way, did not adopt the
advice.) Moreover, although his actual text is limited to the situation in
The Netherlands, I think his arguments have a more general application.
Hofstee's position is that schools should abstain from transmitting
values and norms, except for those school rules that are instrumental in
making a teaching and learning process possible. Of course, he knows
that schools are actually engaged in a lot of value-transmission activities,
but in his opinion this should stop forthwith. Education may teach you
to use your mother language in a `civilised' way, but it may not require
you always to speak that way; it may teach about Rembrandt or
Shakespeare, but it cannot require pupils actually to see them as
& The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain 2001.
104
W. L. Wardekker
beautiful. Incidentally, although he does not say so, Hofstee's ideas
ultimately imply the abolishment of the present Dutch school system
with its 65% of denominationally-bound schools.
Hofstee uses multiple arguments to underpin his position. First, the
relationship between teachers and pupils is not of the kind required for
the transmission of values and norms. Moral education calls for a
personal and emotional tie, while the transmission of knowledge asks for
a more objective stance. The two positions interfere with each other.
Moreover, schools and teachers are geared primarily to the task of
knowledge transmission; even if they want to, they hardly know how to
provide for effective moral education.
Second, attitudes and values cannot be tested adequately. Even if a
pupil does not demonstrate a particular moral attitude, this does not
imply that no learning has taken place. Indeed, the pupil may have
decided autonomously and on good grounds not to accept a
particular value. And what we cannot test for, we should not try
to teach, Hofstee argues. (Note that Hofstee assumes a capacity for
making moral decisions, while teaching in his view is about specific
values. As will become clear, in my view teaching is about creating
this capacity.)
Hofstee's third argument is complementary to the second. Even if the
teaching of values, norms and attitudes has the desired result, that is not
something to boast of: for in fact it implies that the school has been
indoctrinating pupils. It must have chosen specific values (the parents',
for instance) which have been forced on the pupils. Thus, the teaching of
values is contrary to the aim of attaining freedom to make your own
choices in a plural world.
These arguments are not to be dismissed lightly. Indoctrination, if
practised in schools (or any other context), is indeed inadmissible
(Spiecker, 1991). As a consequence, Hofstee is also right in believing that
it is problematical when schools adopt a specific set of values and norms,
for instance those of parents or of a religious community, with the
intention of inducing pupils to accept them. And finally, he is right in
assuming that the results of this effort of inducing cannot be tested in
any simple way. But does that really mean that all forms of moral
education in schools are taboo, and moral education ought to be the
exclusive domain of parental education (where, presumably, indoctrination is admissible according to Hofstee)? Hofstee certainly thinks so. In
his advice on civic education in schools, he offers the alternative of a
course in social psychology, which would enable pupils to foresee the
effects of their actions better and thus improve their relations with other
people. (The result of this learning process Hofstee calls wisdom, a term I
hesitate to use in this context because of the rather instrumental nature
of his intended outcome.) Of course, schools may not force pupils to
apply such knowledge: for Hofstee, moral decisions are the exclusive
domain of each individual.
I do not, however, agree with Hofstee on this conclusion. As I said
earlier, I think that moral education in schools is not only possible, but a
& The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain 2001.
Schools and Moral Education: Conformism or Autonomy?
105
necessary element of the curriculum. But how can I uphold this opinion
against the strength of Hofstee's arguments?
The problem here is that Hofstee's arguments are relevant only if we
accept his tacit assumptions about the nature of moral education in
schools. I interpret his position as one that holds the task of moral
education to be to transfer to the pupils a set of precisely formulated
values, norms and points of view. The contents of this set would depend
on choices made by the school and/or parents, choices anchored in
tradition. In this way, his arguments really concern the position of those
who want the school to be an agent of traditional morality. And his
arguments do a good job of showing why that position is problematical.
In the light of what will follow here, I will add my own argument to
his: an education intended to socialise pupils into rigid and pre-set,
traditional patterns of norms and values does not enable them to cope
with a plural society and will therefore have ever-increasing problems in
legitimising itself. Moreover, it does not encourage reflection, let alone
dissent, but aims for adaptation to existing values. If it succeeds, its
effect will be a separation of societal groups that at best tolerate each
other, but do not interact in any real moral sense. I do not think these
are acceptable aims for education in schools in present society. On this
point I fully agree with Hofstee.
I cannot agree, however, with another of his assumptions. This is the
idea that there is a fundamental difference between knowledge and the
transmission of knowledge on the one hand, and moral values and their
transmission on the other. Knowledge, in the opinion of Hofstee, is
value-free and has (in the ideal case) universal value. Therefore, the
transmission of knowledge and abilities does not imply moral choices.
(The choice of what knowledge and abilities to teach may imply moral
choices; therefore, in this view such choices should be the responsibility
of a democratic government.) For the pupil, then, values come into play
only when the application of knowledge in action situations is called for;
but schools cannot concern themselves with the courses of action pupils
take in such situations. In Hofstee's view, schools prepare pupils for reallife action by giving them the cognitive instruments to act wisely; they
cannot direct the actual course of action. Transmission of moral values,
however, depends on moral choices, and as these are the individual's
responsibility, such transmission should not take place in schools.
This difference between knowledge and values seems to disappear if
we can assume the possible existence of universally valid norms and
values. In that case, the necessity of making moral choices is reduced to
the necessity of confining teaching to universal values. As with all
knowledge, teachers might leave the legitimation of such allegedly
universal values to specialists. I think even Hofstee would not object to
this form of moral education in schools. And indeed, this is the course
the discussion on the moral task of schools in The Netherlands has
taken. After some initial hesitation, both the vice-minister of education
and the president of the most prestigious advisory board have made
suggestions as to which values would represent a minimum list that
& The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain 2001.
106
W. L. Wardekker
everybody could agree on and that supposedly would ensure a peaceful
coexistence in a plural society (Netelenbos, 1996; Leune, 1996). Needless
to say, values like `respect for others' figure prominently on these lists.
Reaching an (even provisional) agreement on the contents of such lists
would thus seem to solve the problem of the legitimation of moral
education in schools. We could then go on to questions concerning the
how: should we devise moral education curricula? Or should moral
education be integrated somehow in other disciplines? Or should we
leave it, as happens now in most cases, to extra-curricular contacts
between teachers and pupils?
For the moment, I will not go into the discussion about whether the
universality of such values could ever be adequately legitimised. The
same problem pertains to knowledge too. There would be a lot to say
about the assumption of the possibility of value-free and universally
valid knowledge, as well as of universal values and norms. However, I
will leave that discussion to the epistemologists for now. Here I want to
concentrate on another problem, more directly related to the educational context. This is the question of whether the difference between
the teaching of facts and of values would really disappear in the case
of universal values. This question leads us to a discussion of the
`anthropology of learning' that is behind both Hofstee's argument and
that of the `universalists': their views of the relation between learning
and acting. I will show that this is not just a discussion about the nature
of teaching; it has implications for the legitimation of moral education.
VALUES, KNOWLEDGE AND AGENCY
It is a common enough idea that the task of the school is the transmission of valid knowledge, competencies and (moral) attitudes to a new
generation. Education provides pupils with a stock of knowledge about
the world, and with abilities they will need later on to maintain a
position in that world. Normally, but (witness Hofstee) not always,
values and moral rules, and the ability to make moral decisions, are
considered part of this equipment not only by parents but also by
teachers. Pupils will need moral rules as well as knowledge in order to
live in society. In this connection it is important to note that Minister
Ritzen's initiative met with a lot of agreement from teachers. Evidently
they too are somewhat at a loss as to what the right or most useful rules
and values would be for a future society in which their present pupils will
have to live.
Two elements are important in this view. First is the necessary trust in
the validity of knowledge, procedures and values, which implies they
should be learned `as given' and leaves no room for personal interpretation by pupils. Every cognitive question has one right answer; and
in the same way, moral questions can be decided by reference to
accepted values, be they the values of a specific cultural group or values
that are considered universally valid. The emphasis on validity, which
implies all pupils are to learn the same things, means that schools have a
& The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain 2001.
Schools and Moral Education: Conformism or Autonomy?
107
task in the formation of personal identity only insofar as this is a group
identity; pupils are taught to adhere to the values chosen by the school
management. Differentiation according to the preferences the pupils
themselves have is foreign to this model. The model stresses performance,
in the sense of (measurable) adherence to the `right' answers in all
activities. The consequence is that every person is seen as a separate
individual in competition with all others: the best position in this
competition is held by that person who has obtained the most and best
resources (knowledge and abilities). Also, every person is understood as
a calculating citizen, out to attain his or her own ends by a precise
calculus of possible courses of action and their consequences. Morality is
then mostly reduced to a number of rules that should limit the courses of
action that are open, on the grounds of ill effects for others, tradition or
taboo, or other types of conviction. It is what forces us to take the social
context of our actions into account.
The emphasis on preparation means that the school places pupils `in
limbo' and effectively denies that they are already participating in
society. School is a `social moratorium', a place where pupils are `fitted
out' before being turned loose on the world. The idea behind this is that
you first need to know a lot of things before you can rationally
participate in social activities. Thinking comes before action, and in
order to think you need to know.
In earlier years, this way of thinking led schools to expect a quite
literal passivity on the part of pupils: be still and listen. Nowadays, pupils
are expected to acquire the necessary knowledge, abilities and values in
an active and often independent way, for instance by looking for
information in knowledge centres, encyclopedias and the Internet. This
is a less teacher-centred way of thinking, in which direct transmission
is replaced by the construction of co-ordinated `maps of the world' by
the pupil. The development of such maps is dependent not only on
the information available, but also on reasoning abilities that develop
according to age-related stages as suggested by Piaget for the cognitive
domain, and by Kohlberg (1981, 1984) for the moral domain. The
educational consequence is that information should not be forced on
pupils, but they should be allowed to discover the world and construct their cognitive maps stimulated by a `rich environment'. Thus,
`transmission' is an inadequate description of what happens in
classrooms: `construction' is what education is all about. Pupils are,
however, never supposed to participate in the construction of knowledge
itself, let alone of values; they just construct their own images of preexisting knowledge. The test is still whether they can come up with the
`right' answers.
However, many educationists more or less intuitively take the
position that in the case of learning norms and values this model is too
restrictive in not allowing for a personal contribution by the pupil. As
an example of this position, I quote from the introduction of a recent
book by Klaassen in which he tries to chart the terrain of values
education:
& The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain 2001.
108
W. L. Wardekker
Opinions dier on the ways in which values education can be structured
as to its form and content. What people agree about is that education
for norms and values is complicated. Other than in the case of the
transmission of knowledge and insight, these are not educational
processes in which certain contents are just transmitted and which can
be evaluated and measured in a relatively exact way. Values and norms
form a complex terrain of the construction of personal sense, of principles
that give meaning to the life and co-existence of people and rules that
regulate interactions between humans. (Klaassen, 1976, p. 7; my
translation)
It is exactly this supposed difference that leads Hofstee to take his
position that schools cannot concern themselves validly with the
development of a moral sense in pupils. While knowledge (in intention,
at least) describes the world outside us in an objective way and does not
admit any constructive activity by the pupil, values are interpreted as
being subjective, or at least as in need of a personal acceptance which
goes beyond recognising them as objectively valid. Knowledge `maps'
belong to the cognitive domain; norms and values are related to the
development of personality, and pupils must make their own choices
here rather than unthinkingly accept the choices of others. In our
society, we value personal development that results in autonomous
agency. It is for this very reason that the question of whether schools can
contribute to this development process becomes difficult to answer: can
schools be seen as a place for individual self-realisation? Autonomy is
not something schools can transmit, or that pupils can show in a test.
For Hofstee, this apparent contradiction is a reason not to admit
personality development as a valid aim of education. Kohlberg, who sees
the attainment of autonomy as a developmental stage where norms and
values have been internalised, thinks schools can help pupils in this
development by offering a positive `moral climate' where reasoning
about moral questions is stimulated. Others have suggested didactic
forms like `values clarification'.
I do not think that we are now in a position to make an informed
choice between these positions. For there is still a fundamentally unclear
element in both concerning the relation between values as communal
`goods' and as personal choices. In the next section, I will develop this
problem into a different view of what education is about.
TWO TASKS FOR EDUCATION?
In the last section, I discussed two positions on the subject of values
education. One conceives of it as not very different from education in
knowledge and cognitive insights; the other sees the two `tasks of
education' as fundamentally different. What, exactly, is the difference in
points of view that these positions are based on? Superficially, the
second position seems to interpret values education as a form of
personality development, making the first look suspiciously like a
& The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain 2001.
Schools and Moral Education: Conformism or Autonomy?
109
form of indoctrination. Alternatively, the first can be interpreted as
emphasising (even creating) unity in society, while the second values
diversity and differences in choices between persons. However, I think a
third interpretation is preferable, which reduces the difference to a
problem of contextualisation. On this interpretation, the first position
thinks of values and norms as abstract, decontextualised entities, just
like knowledge is decontextualised; and thus, like knowledge, they can
be transmitted `for later use'. At that later moment, the pupil will need
to contextualise the abstract rules and concepts, which presumably
entails personal choices as well as rational conduct; but making such
choices is not something pupils are to be prepared for and is possibly
seen as something everybody can do `naturally'. The second position, on
the other hand, emphasises precisely the contextualised use of values,
when pupils in a concrete situation need to make choices as to a specific
course of action, and therefore sees values as belonging in the domain of
personal sense-giving, but it does not deny that this sense may be based
on a more general rule or concept. The difference now looks more like a
question of timing than of principle.
But from the point of view of teaching and learning, this is not an
innocent difference. Indeed, the question whether one can learn to act
wisely by being taught general guidelines and facts is fundamental for
education. The positive answer constitutes the first position, characteristic of traditional thinking about education and strongly based on
rationalism, where rationality is interpreted narrowly as the autonomous
ability (and the will) to make adequate ends±means connections and to
act upon these. It represents a classical view of education which sufficed
as long as more or less stable societal structures assured that assistance
in personality development was seen as a task for and by the family and
other institutions. In our present less stable society, however, it becomes
evident that personality development is not natural, but is a social
learning process, which moreover becomes more important as living in
such a society becomes more and more dependent on a `reflexive selfidentity' (Giddens, 1991). This position, however, in fact denies that
schools have a task in assisting children to develop such an identity, and
therefore it seems unsuitable in present conditions. (I will repeat here
that this way of thinking also rests on the assumption of the existence of
universal knowledge and values, an assumption which would merit a
discussion in itself.)
The second position, on the other hand, asserts that being able to act
adequately depends both on the availability of knowledge and on
personality development, the latter being a matter of having acquired a
certain self-identity in which norms and values have become `your own'.
Thus it seems to acknowledge the necessity of identity development. In
educational practice, it is much more common than the first position:
many schools and teachers see themselves as having a twofold task, one
side concerned with the transmission of knowledge and skills, the other
with their pupils `as persons'. This position, however, has problems of its
own. It is a strange hybrid that assumes the co-existence of two totally
& The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain 2001.
110
W. L. Wardekker
different types of learning processes: one concerned with decontextualised knowledge, the other with contextualised values and personality
development. Creating the right connections between knowledge and
values at the appropriate moment is a task left to pupils. The model,
moreover, assumes the existence of `value-free' knowledge and the
possibility of discriminating in every instance between knowledge and
values. This assumption, though sometimes thought basic to modern
social science, may be difficult to substantiate.
The problems with both models, it turns out, are not problems of
values education or personality development as such. Rather they are
problems of the relation between moral education and the transmission
of knowledge and skills. I suggest that such problems disappear when we
think of the acquisition of `knowledge and skills' in terms not of
transmission, but of transformation.
PLURALITY AND TRANSFORMATION
The transformation model has grown out of the classical Bildung model
with the help of the development theories of Vygotsky. In many respects
it also profited from the views on education and democracy of John
Dewey. This model interprets human beings not as natural or rational,
but as social, beings. Social life is considered constitutive of the
possibility of action. All human actions are socially situated and
structured, even if at the moment of action no other persons are actually
present. As a consequence, the aim of education is formulated as that of
enabling humans to participate in socially, societally and culturally
structured and situated activities. And learning means being enabled to
participate in activities in an ever more adequate and competent way (cf.
John-Steiner and Mahn, 1996). However, what is learned is not just
elements of knowledge and ability. Neither can it be described as gaining
the competence to act in accordance with the objective properties of the
world. This is not a constructivist, but a culturally constructivist, theory:
we do not act in the world as such but within socially and culturally
constructed activities, and therefore the task of learning is to construct a
view of these activities and your own place in them. Construction
characterises both the individual and the social level of development.
In individual learning, the contents of the school curriculum are only
a starting point. The pupil needs to make these contents into a part of
the image she builds of concrete activities and her own position and
possibilities within these in relation to other participants. Curriculum
contents need to be transformed into the personal `property' of the pupil,
into `personal knowledge' (in the sense of Polanyi, 1958). The perspectives
on the world and on actions that are the outcome of this construction
process are different for each individualÐand it is these differences that
keep a culture alive (Bruner, 1996). A perspective is not an objective
cognitive map of the world or of objective possibilities for action. It is
integrated with other aspects of personality like motivation, preference,
valuation and moral views. In such a perspective, there is no boundary
& The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain 2001.
Schools and Moral Education: Conformism or Autonomy?
111
between `objective' and `valuated' components. In fact, the construction
of such perspectives is part of the task of identity formation.
I want to draw special attention to the fact that learning is not about
possible or future participation in activities, but about actual activities.
Two consequences of this are important in speaking of the moral task of
schools. First, it does not make much sense to limit this task to the
teaching of universal values, even assuming these can be found. For (just
like `universally valid' knowledge) such universal values are by necessity
decontextualised. There is then a distinct danger they will be memorised,
will maybe even function in abstract moral reasoning, but will not
actively function in concrete contexts of action. As soon as we try to
contextualise them, the characteristics of that context come into play:
values need to be interpreted, and lose their universality. Take the
example of `respect for others'. If this value is considered in classroom
discussion in general terms only, there is a risk pupils will see no
connection with their bullying of classmates. If one wants to show what
it means in an actual activity setting, it will turn out that what one
person calls respectful behaviour may be for another a matter of the
utmost disrespect. This probably holds true for the lists of desirable
values formulated in the discussion in The Netherlands.
The second point is that learning to participate in socially structured
activities, including the normative elements of participating, is without
doubt done best by participating in those same activities in a guided
way. In fact, it is probably best to conceive of school as a place defined
by this learning to participate. If we think of it that way, it becomes clear
that, normally, the dominant activity in which pupils learn to participate
is `being-in-school'. Most pupils learn very fast what is expected of them,
how to survive with minimum costs and other school-related skills. If, as
is often the case, explicit moral education is restricted to maintaining the
school rules, this serves to reinforce the idea that school does not have a
purpose beyond itself. The transformation model thus calls for a
restructuring of school activity in such a way that it represents the
essential moments in worthwhile social activities that go on outside the
school, including their normative and moral elements. School is, or at
least it should be, not only about books; it is about life.
I will not go into the general consequences of the transformation
model here, but concentrate on the opportunities for moral education it
offers. It will be clear from the above discussion that in learning to
participate, cognitive and moral learning cannot be separated. In an
effective learning process, a cognitive, affective and moral bond is
created between pupils and practices. This is, in fact, another way of
saying that education is an enculturation process: pupils become
members of the culture by participating in it.
PLURALITY, PARTICIPATION AND AUTONOMY
The above formulation which sees education as an enculturation process
appears to contradict the notions from Critical Theory introduced
& The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain 2001.
112
W. L. Wardekker
before. Indeed, if education is confined to learning to participate in preselected social activities, there is a risk that pupils will only learn to
adapt to accepted ways of thinking and acting within those activities.
These accepted ways may never be taught explicitly; by participating,
pupils may adopt values and views without thinking, without being
conscious of them: participation has a strong `hidden curriculum'. This
implicit acceptance, however, can never be the aim of education in a
plural society; it would in fact imply a form of indoctrination. How can
the transformation model handle plurality? Can it accommodate the
idea of (moral) autonomy?
The transformation model states that learning is not the same thing as
accumulating knowledge and skills. It is about making sense of those
elements, a sense that depends on the personal position and possibilities
of the learner. In this activity of making sense, cognitive, moral and
affective dimensions become one. The sense somebody attaches to
participating in an activity does not coincide with his or her role or
position in that activity; it is an interpretation of that position in the
context of the whole activity, and in relation to other activities one
participates in. This interpretation differs from person to person; and
these differences are one source of change in the activity itself. Thus, the
concept of transformation does not only mean that knowledge is transformed into personal sense. It also means that learners engaging in this
process of sense-making are transformed themselves: by transforming
their outlook on the world they are changing their identities. And
moreover, activities are transformed by the participation of persons with
different interpretations.
Now such transformations in personal identity and in the character of
social activities may remain haphazard and chance products of learning
and participation. But human beings can also try to consciously change
themselves and their world. We can, to a certain extent, become coauthors of our own identity and of the cultural practices we participate
in (cf. Harre and Gillett, 1994). This requires that we become conscious
of our interpretations of the world, and of the values and points of view
that direct our actions. Participation and reflection are not mutually
exclusive: they belong together. This implies that schools should
encourage a reflective way of participating in activities, including
reflection on the moral side of activities. In critical reflection,
knowledge, values and morals may be scrutinised and compared. This
makes it possible also to generalise values and rules to other practices, to
re-contextualise them.
A plural society, because of its possible clashes between points of
view, offers many opportunities to start a process of reflection. Every
member of such a society participates in multiple communities. These
may be more or less alike, but there may also be rather sharp differences
between them. (There is no real need to assume, as many do (cf.
Halstead, 1996), that there must be some minimum set of values that all
communities within a given society share. Rather, there will be `family
likenesses' where A is like B in some respects, and B is like C in other
& The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain 2001.
Schools and Moral Education: Conformism or Autonomy?
113
respects, without the implication that A and C must have something in
common too.) These differences may cause conflicts. Although this does
not make life easy, such conflicts can become starting points for
reflection on the differences between different communities, or between
ourselves and others, or even between different loyalties and different
points of view in our own thinking. Reflecting and valuing differences
may lead to conscious transformations in our thinking, even in our
identity, and in the way we participate in activities.
Within this model, then, we would call an `autonomous person'
somebody who, when co-operating with others, is able to defend his or
her actions and the values and points of view that guide it, but is also
willing to reflect critically on them. It is somebody who contributes to
the maintenance of rules but also to their changing and to the creation of
new rules. It is somebody who is dedicated to something, but is also able
to change principles if necessary. The autonomous person is always
learning and contributing to the learning of others, both cognitively and
morally. He or she is a conscious co-author of his or her own biography
and of the history of social groups and cultural practices in which he or
she participates. Sometimes these changes may be convergent, in the
sense that more unity between groups, or between various points of view
within the same person, is reached. But at other times divergence may be
called for. Achieving personal identity does not necessarily mean that all
elements of thinking, all opinions held, must become consistent with
each other. Identity is never completed; its formation is a lifelong
project, in which at every moment a balance must be struck between
continuity and change (cf. Harre and Gillett, 1994). In a rapidly
changing and plural society, a person who never changes and is totally
consistent over time, a person who holds on to once-adopted points of
view and does not test them against the ideas of others, is someone who
becomes fossilised and in fact contributes to the fossilisation of society
into separate groups that at best tolerate each other, but do not learn
from each other.
This view of autonomy differs from that of Kohlberg in that it does
not refer to a formal reasoning ability, or any other telos of development
inherent in reality, but to a contextualised way of participating in social
activities. Also, it does not necessarily apply to all terrains of life at the
same time. One may function in an autonomous way in some respects,
and in a heteronomous way in others. And finally, autonomy is not
reached as the result of a more or less automatic development. It has to
be learned, and schools can make an important contribution to this
learning process, even though it may not be the kind of learning process
that parents, or governments, expect.
This brings us back to the earlier problem of a continuity in moral
outlook and practice between the home and the school. I think that as a
starting point, such continuity (as, for instance, indicated in the `mission
statement' or the denominational adherence of a school) may be
important. If the moral climate in school initially differs too much
from that in the home, pupils may be at a loss and feel unsafe, with
& The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain 2001.
114
W. L. Wardekker
detrimental results for both moral and intellectual development. But the
above discussion leads me to stress two points. First, the `moral quality'
of a school is not restricted to, or even primarily about, life in school. It
is about the way pupils are taught to participate in cultural activities.
We should not expect automatic transfer from the practice of beingin-school to other practices. Such `transfer' is effected only through
reflection and the development of autonomy. Second, reflection and
autonomy need a confrontation with other practices, other possibilities.
A school that adheres strictly to a chosen set of values, that does not
admit plurality, is one that impedes the development of autonomy.
Correspondence: Willem L. Wardekker, Department of Education, Free
University of Amsterdam, Van der Boechorststraat 1, 1081 BT
Amsterdam, The Netherlands. E-mail:
[email protected]
REFERENCES
Bruner, J. (1996) The Culture of Education (Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press)
De Swaan, A. (1982) De mens is de mens een zorg [People are a concern to people] (Amsterdam,
Meulenho)
Giddens, A. (1991) Modernity and Self-identity. Self and society in the late modern age (Cambridge,
Polity Press)
Halstead, J. M. (1996) Values and value education in schools, in: J. M. Halstead and M. J. Taylor
(eds) Values in Education and Education in Values (London, Falmer)
HarreÂ, R. and Gillett, G. (1994) The Discursive Mind (Thousand Oaks, CA, Sage)
Hofstee, W. K. B. (1992) Een curriculum voor burgerschap [A curriculum for citizenship], in: H. R.
van Gunsteren and P. den Hoed (eds) Burgerschap in Praktijken, I, 257±279 (Den Haag, SDU)
John-Steiner, V. and Mahn, H. (1996) Sociocultural approaches to learning and development: a
Vygotskian framework, Educational Psychologist, 31, 191±206
Klaassen, C. (1996) Socialisatie en moraal. Onderwijs en waarden in een laat-moderne tijd
[Socialisation and morality: education and values in late modernity] (Leuven/Apeldoorn, Garant)
Kohlberg, L. (1981, 1984) Essays on Moral Development 1 & 2 (San Francisco, CA, Harper & Row)
Leune, H. (1996) Over de normatieve taak van de school [On the normative task of the school].
Paper for Congress `Onderwijs, moraal en burgerschap', Nijmegen, 11 June
Netelenbos, T. (1996) Untitled paper for Congress `Opvoeding, Onderwijs en Sociale Integratie',
Amsterdam, 17 and 18 October
Polanyi, M. (1958) Personal Knowledge (London, Routledge & Kegan Paul)
Rispens, J., Hermanns, J. M. A. and Meeus, W. H. J. (eds) (1996) Opvoeden in Nederland
[Upbringing in the Netherlands] (Assen, Van Gorcum)
Ritzen, J. M. M. (1992) The moral task of education. A call for joint action (Zoetermeer, Netherlands
Ministry of Education and Science)
Spiecker, B. (1991) Indoctrination: the suppression of critical dispositions, in: B. Spiecker and R.
Straughan (eds) Freedom and Indoctrination in Education. International Perspectives (London,
Cassell)
& The Journal of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain 2001.