Journal of Indian and Buddhist Studies Vol. 61, No. 3, March 2013
(171)
DignAga on AvIta and PrasaGga
Watanabe Toshikazu
0. In the SaSTitantra, the fundamental text of the SAGkhya school before the time of the
SAGkhyakArikA, two modes of reasoning for proving invisible things such as the existence
of primordial matter(pradhAna)etc. are explained, i.e., vIta and AvIta. Of these two, AvIta
reasoning is formulated after vIta reasoning in order to support the same conclusion drawn
by the vIta reasoning through a reductio ad absurdum-style argument(prasaGga). 1)
In the third chapter of his PramANasamuccaya, DignAga(ca. 480–540)mentions the
SAGkhyas’ AvIta reasoning as being a prasaGga argument, and criticizes its definition, its
way of being formulated, and its independence from vIta reasoning. While other prasaGga
arguments are classified as refutation(dUSaNa/parihAra)because they are formulated by
provisionally relying on the opponent’s position, AvIta reasoning is presented on the basis
of the proponent’s own view and hence its logical reason is regarded as fulfilling the three
characteristics of a proper logical reason(trairUpya), at least for the proponent.
In this paper I will first attempt to clarify DignAga’s explanation of the structure of AvIta
reasoning and its reformulation into vIta reasoning, and then examine the influence of DignAga’s analysis of AvIta reasoning on DharmakIrti’s theory of prasaGgaviparyaya, as well
as on BhAviveka’s criticism of BuddhapAlita.
1. In PS 3.16, DignAga mentions two characteristics of AvIta reasoning, and argues that
AvIta reasoning is not different from vIta reasoning.
hetvabhAvaprasaGgas tu yatrAvItena kathyate | sa dRSTAntadvayAt siddhes tasmAd vItAn na bhidya
te || 2)
On the other hand, in a certain proof[a-1]the negation of the logical reason(hetvabhAva)
[adduced in the vIta reasoning]is stated as an undesired consequence(prasaGga)by means of AvIta
reasoning. Such a proof is[a-2]based on the establishment[of the pervasion]by two modes of
exemplification(i.e., positive and negative concomitance). Therefore,[AvIta reasoning]is not differentiated from vIta reasoning.
Because of these two characteristics, i.e.,[a-1]and[a-2], AvIta reasoning can be reformu─ 1229 ─
(172)
DignAga on AvIta and PrasaGga(T. Watanabe)
lated into vIta reasoning. DignAga presupposes the following vIta formulation in the process of exemplifying this.
〈VIta-D〉bhedAnAm ekakAraNatvam, anvayadarZanAt.
Various individual things possess one and the same cause; Because homology(anvaya)
[concerning three constituents, i.e., pleasure(sukha), pain(duHkha), and confusion(moha)]is observed.
3)
DignAga formulates this〈VIta-D〉by revising the following original formulation found in
the ST in order to make the logical reason “homology”(anvaya)possess the three characteristics of a proper logical reason 4):
〈VIta-1〉asti pradhAnam, bhedAnAm anvayadarZanAt.
5)
The AvIta reasoning derived by DignAga from〈VIta-D〉is as follows:
6)
〈AvIta-D 1〉*na vyaktasyaikapUrvakatvAbhAvaH, bhedaprasaGgAt.
It is not the case that evolutes do not arise from one and the same cause, because[if they would not
arise from the same cause,]it would follow that[all evolutes would]differ[from each other completely].
This〈AvIta-D 1〉is also an improvement on the following AvIta reasoning set forth by the
SAGkhya 7):
〈AvIta-1〉na vyaktasyAsata utpattiH, bhedaprasaGgAt.
8)
With〈VIta-D〉and〈AvIta-D 1〉in mind, DignAga explains his reformulation of AvIta reasoning into vIta reasoning as follows:
[1]yasmAd anvaya ekapUrvakatve dRSTaH, tadabhAve ca na dRSTaH, ata ekapUrvakatvam.[2]
tadanabhyupagame cAnvayAbhAvaprasaGgaH. sa ca nAsti[3]iti sa evAnvaya ukto bhavati. . . . ko
hy atra viZeSo bhedaprasaGgAnvayayoH. 9)
[1]Since homology[among evolutes]is seen[only]when[they]come from one and the same
cause and is not seen when[they]do not,[evolutes that possess homology as their property]come
from one and the same cause.[2]And if it(i.e., their coming from one and the same cause)is not
accepted, the negation of homology would follow. But there is no[negation of homology in
reality].[3]Therefore,[in the AvIta reasoning,]that very[undesired consequence of negation of
homology(anvayAbhAvaprasaGga)]becomes spoken of as “homology[in vIta reasoning].” . . .
For, in this case what difference is there between “bhedaprasaGga” and “anvaya”?
In passage[1], it is shown that “homology,” which is the logical reason of〈VIta-D〉, is
pervaded by “coming from one and the same cause.” Since “ekapUrvakatva” and “ekakAra
Natva” are regarded as conveying the same meaning, this pervasion(vyApti)is the same
one as presupposed by the〈VIta-D〉. If the pervasion of the logical reason(H)by the
property to be proved(S)is represented as “H → S,” the positive concomitance(an
─ 1230 ─
DignAga on AvIta and PrasaGga(T. Watanabe)
(173)
vayavyApti)of this pervasion can be described as follows:
〈VyApti-A〉anvaya → ekapUrvakatva
And if the fact that pervasion “H → S” held with regard to the subject “P” is represented as
“P(H → S),” then〈VIta-D〉can be described as follows:
〈VIta-D 1〉Individual things(anvaya → ekapUrvakatva)
In contrast, the contraposition of〈VyApti-A〉, i.e., negative concomitance(vyatirekavy
Apti), can be described with the negative sign “¬” as follows:
〈VyApti-B〉¬ekapUrvakatva → ¬anvaya
Passage[2]expresses〈VyApti-B〉in the form of a prasaGga-style argument and denies
the possibility of the negation of homology(¬anvaya)in reality. This is the explanation
of the characteristics of AvIta reasoning referred to in PS 3.16. Comparing these descriptions, we can get clearer view of DignAga’s understanding of AvIta reasoning: it has the
same pervasion as〈VIta-D〉
(see above PS 3.16[a-2])because〈VyApti-B〉 is logically
equivalent to〈VyApti-A〉and results in the undesired consequence of the negation of “homology,” i.e., the logical reason of〈VIta-D〉
(see above PS 3.16[a-1]). Moreover, it is
known from passage[3]that the negation of “homology” means the complete difference
(bheda)of every evolute. Therefore, the undesired consequence of complete difference
(bhedaprasaGga)is derived from the negation of coming from one and the same cause
(¬ekapUrvakatva).
Now let us return to〈AvIta-D 1〉. This formulation apparently consists of the thesis and
its reason. However, the phrase “bhedaprasaGgAt” should not be regarded as the logical
reason for proving the thesis “na vyaktasyaikapUrvakatvAbhAvaH” because it cannot prove
the thesis by itself. In order to derive the thesis, “bhedaprasaGga” requires two things:
First, the negation of coming from one and the same cause(¬ekapUrvakatva)must be understood as the condition of “bhedaprasaGga,” because, as seen above, the latter can be
held only if the former is established. In addition, since “bhedaprasaGga” is an undesired
consequence, it must be negated. Consequently, in〈AvIta-D 1〉the following process of
proof is seen with regard to evolutes(vyakta):
〈AvIta-D 2〉Evolutes(¬ekapUrvakatva → bheda)∧ ¬bheda ∴ ¬¬ekapUrvakatva
Since for the SAGkhya there is no difference between “individual things”(bheda)and
“evolutes”(vyakta), and since the negation of homology(¬anvaya)means complete difference(bheda), it is obvious that〈AvIta-D 2〉does not differ from〈VIta-D 1〉in its
─ 1231 ─
(174)
DignAga on AvIta and PrasaGga(T. Watanabe)
content. Therefore, insofar as the phrase “bhedaprasaGgAt” in〈AvIta-D 1〉indicates the
logical reason “homology” in〈VIta-D〉which is, for the SAGkhya, accepted as possessing
the three characteristics of a proper logical reason(trairUpya), it can also be regarded as
equivalent to a proper logical reason. Even though for the Buddhist the logical reason “homology” is not accepted as a proper logical reason, 10)it is worth noting that DignAga accepts the possibility that AvIta reasoning, i.e., a type of prasaGga argument, becomes a
proper proof(sAdhana).
2.〈AvIta-D 1〉, even though it can be reformulated into the〈VIta-D〉, is not a proper
proof(sAdhana)if it is put forth to the Buddhist disputant, because the logical reason “homology,” which is adduced in〈VIta-D〉and which guarantees the adequacy of the assumed logical reason “bhedaprasaGgAt” in〈AvIta-D 1〉, is accepted only by the SAGkhya
proponent as possessing the three characteristics of a proper logical reason(trairUpya).
However, DignAga’s explanation of the reformulation of AvIta reasoning into vIta reasoning opens up the possibility that AvIta reasoning, a type of prasaGga argument, can thus be
regarded as a proper proof. This had a great influence on the later Indian logicians, including Buddhist philosophers BhAviveka(ca. 6th cent.)and DharmakIrti(ca. 600–660), as
well as within Tibetan Buddhism.
Let us first consider the process of formulating prasaGgaviparyaya(the contraposition
of prasaGga)from prasaGga. This process is often used in the treatises of DharmakIrti’s
successors. As earlier studies have shown, the structures of prasaGga and prasaGgavipary
aya can be described as follows: 11)
PrasaGga: A(B → C)∧ ¬C ∴¬B
PrasaGgaviparyaya: A(¬C → ¬B)
Both prasaGga and prasaGgaviparyaya are presented with regard to the same subject(A).
The pervasion presupposed in prasaGgaviparyaya(i.e., ¬C → ¬B)is the contraposition
of that which is presupposed in the prasaGga argument(i.e., B → C). Even though DharmakIrti does not clearly explain these two structures, because his successors commonly refer to the above-mentioned structure, it is likely that these structures represent DharmakIrti’s own idea. And it is easily recognized that the structures of DharmakIrti’s prasaGga and
prasaGgaviparyaya correspond completely to those of DignAga’s vIta and AvIta arguments,
respectively. 12)The identification of these structures is supported by the fact that Jinendrabuddhi explains the reformulation of AvIta reasoning into vIta reasoning in the PS(V)
─ 1232 ─
DignAga on AvIta and PrasaGga(T. Watanabe)
(175)
by using the term “prasaGgaviparyaya.” 13)Accordingly, it can be said that the germ of
DharmakIrti’s theory of prasaGgaviparyaya can be found in DignAga’s interpretation of
AvIta reasoning.
Another Buddhist philosopher who owes much of his theory of proof to DignAga is
BhAviveka. As has been pointed out by Ueda[1995], it seems that BhAviveka makes use
of DignAga’s interpretation of AvIta reasoning in order to criticize BuddhapAlita’s prasaGga
argument. As an example, we will examine the discussion of the negation of arising from
other.
On the other hand, the Master BuddhapAlita says: It is not the case that things arise from other, because[if they arise from other,]it would follow that everything would arise from everything.[To
this,]the Master BhAviveka states the refutation[as follows]: Then, in this case, because[it is]a
statement of[undesired]consequence, when the contraposition of the[property]to be proved and
the logical reason is made, contradiction[of your prasaGga argument]with[your]original
position[become evident because the contraposition states that]things arise from self, or from
both(i.e., self and other), or without any cause, because a particular thing arises from a particular
thing.(PrasannapadA 36,11–37,2).
As the structure of〈AvIta-D 1〉is described as〈AvIta-D 2〉, the structure of BuddhapAlita’s prasaGga argument is described as follows 14):
〈PrasaGga-BP〉Things(parata utpadyante → sarvataH sarvasambhava)∧ ¬sarvataH sar
vasambhava ∴ ¬parata utpadyante
BhAviveka reformulates this〈PrasaGga-BP〉as the following argument, and points out
that it contradicts the MAdhyamika’s central thesis that things do not arise from self, from
other, from both, or without any cause.
〈Viparyaya-BV〉Things(kutaZcit kasyacid utpatti → svata ubhayato ’hetuto votpadyante)
What is the “viparyaya” by way of which BhAviveka derives〈Viparyaya-BV〉from
〈PrasaGga-BP〉? Judging from the fact that he regards〈Viparyaya-BV〉as conveying the
same meaning as〈PrasaGga-BP〉, it must express the contraposition of the pervasion. That
is, “kutaZcit kasyacid utpatti” in〈Viparyaya-BV〉is the negation of “sarvataH sarvasam
bhava” in〈PrasaGga-BP〉, and “svata ubhayato ’hetuto votpadyante” in〈Viparyaya-BV〉
is the negation of “parata utpadyante” in〈PrasaGga-BP〉. Taking this point into consideration,〈Viparyaya-BV〉can be formulated as follows:
Things(¬sarvataH sarvasambhava → ¬parata utpadyante)
Although in the case of BhAviveka’s reformulation of〈PrasaGga-BP〉into〈Viparyaya─ 1233 ─
(176)
DignAga on AvIta and PrasaGga(T. Watanabe)
BV〉the negation is interpreted as a implicative negation(paryudAsa), while in the case of
DignAga it is taken as being a simple negation(prasajyapratiSedha), it can be said that the
process of BhAviveka’s reformulating〈PrasaGga-BP〉into〈Viparyaya-BV〉has a close
similarity to that of DignAga’s reformulation of AvIta reasoning into vIta reasoning.
3. When discussing AvIta reasoning, DignAga accepts a possibility of reformulating pra
saGga argument as a proper proof(sAdhana)
. This enables him to incorporate the prasaGga
argument into the framework of the trairUpya theory. It can be said that his view about
prasaGga marks a turning point in the development of the theory of prasaGga, which until
then had merely been regarded as a means for refuting the views of opponents. By making
use of DignAga’s explanation of AvIta reasoning, BhAviveka and DharmakIrti further developed their theory of prasaGga.
DignAga’s theory of trairUpya became widely accepted, causing the SAGkhya to relinquish their leading position in Indian logic to DignAga and his followers. Since DignAga
developed his theory of prasaGga by criticizing the SAGkhya theory of AvIta, it can be said
that DignAga is their most ingenious successor and, at the same time, their most severe
critic.
――――――――――――――――
* I would like to thank Ms. Peck-Kubaczek for correcting my English and Dr. Anne MacDonald for
giving me many invaluable suggestions.
Notes: 1)For the characteristics of “vIta” and “AvIta,” see Watanabe[forthcoming].
2)
See Katsura[2009: 158]. Words of PS(V)in Roman typeface are attested in Jinendrabuddhi’s Sanskrit manuscript or in fragments, whereas those in italics have been reconstructed from Tibetan translations.
3)See NMu(Katsura[1978: 110]).
4)For DignAga’s modification of vIta
reasoning, see Watanabe[2008]
.
5)See Frauwallner[1958: 125]
.
6)Since DignAga
does not give this formulation, this is my conjecture based on his description.
7)For
DignAga’s criticism of the formulation of AvIta reasoning propounded by the SAGkhya, see Watanabe
[forthcoming].
8)PSV 3.16(K[P128a8], V[D44a5–6, P47a5–6]).
9)PSV 3.16
(K[P129b1–3], V[D44a6–44b1, P47a6–8]).
10)See Watanabe[2008].
11)See
Tani[1983: 7–12]and Iwata[1997: 427–428].
12)Since Ueda[1995: 113–117]takes the
phrase “bhedaprasaGgAt” in〈AvIta-D 1〉as the direct reason for proving its thesis, his interpretation
of the structure of〈AvIta-D 1〉is different from mine.
13)See PST B122b4–6(D159a5–7,
P182b3–6): tadanabhyupagame ceti tasya vyApakasyaikapUrvakatvasyAnabhyupagame. anvayAbhA
vaprasaGga iti vyApyasyAnvayasyAbhAvaprasaGgaH syAd ity arthaH. . . . sa cAnvayAbhAvaprasaGgo
nAstIti prasaGgaviparyayeNa sa evAnvaya ukto bhavati-anvayAd ekakAraNapUrvakA bhedA iti. etc.
─ 1234 ─
DignAga on AvIta and PrasaGga(T. Watanabe)
(177)
14)Avalokitavrata gives different interpretation. See Ueda[1995: 119].
Abbreviations: K: PS(V). Trans. KaNakavarman and Dad pa’i shes rab. P5702. NMu: NyAyamukha.
See Katsura[1978]. PrasannapadA: MUlamadhyamakakArikAs de NAgArjuna avec la PrasannapadA.
Ed. L. de La Vallée Poussin. St. Pétersbourg. 1903–1913. PST: PramANasamuccayaTIkA. D4268,
P5766. PS(V): PramANasamuccaya(vRtti). See K and V. ST: SaSTitantra. See Frauwallner[1958]. V:
PS
(V)
. Trans. VasudararakSita and Seng rgyal. D4204, P5701. Frauwallner, Erich. “Die Erkenntnislehre
des klassischen SAMkhya-Systems.” Wiener Zeitschrift für die Kunde Süd- und Ostasiens 2(1958):
84–139. Iwata Takashi. “On PrasaGgaviparyaya in DharmakIrti’s Tradition-PrajJAkaragupta and
gTsaG nag pa.” In Tibetan Studies: Proceedings of the 7th Seminar of the International Association for
Tibetan Studies, Graz 1995. Vol. I, 427–437. Wien: Verlag der Österreichschen Akademie der Wissenschaften, 1997. Katsura ShōryU 桂紹隆. “Inmyō shōri monron kenkyU(2)
” 因明正理門論研究〔二〕
.
: 110–130. Katsura Shoryu. “ReHiroshima daigaku bungakubu kiyō 広島大学文学部紀要 37(1978)
discovering DignAga through Jinendrabuddhi.” In Sanskrit Manuscripts in China. Ed. E. Steinkellner,
153–166. Beijing: China Tibetology Publishing House, 2009. Tani Tadashi 谷貞志. “PrasaGga-sAdhana
(kibyU ronshō)dōnyU ni yoru ronrikei no kōzō henkan: Dharmottara to PrajJAkaragupta no kaishaku
no sai” プラサンガ・サーダナ(帰謬論証)導入による論理系の構造変換: ダルモッタラとプ
: 1–27. Watanabe Toshikazu
ラジュニャーカラグプタの解釈の差異. Bukkyōgaku 仏教学 15(1983)
渡辺俊和. “DignAga to SAGkhya gakuha to no ronsō: PradhAna no sonzai ronshō o megutte” ディグ
ナーガとサーンキヤ学派との論争: プラダーナの存在論証をめぐって. Indogaku Bukkyōgaku
kenkyU 印度学仏教学研究 57, no. 1(2008): 295–291. Watanabe Toshikazu. “On the Sanskrit Fragments of the Early SAGkhya Theory of Proof.” In the proceedings of the Japan-Austria International
Symposium on Transmission and Tradition, Matsumoto, 20–24 August 2012, forthcoming. Ueda Noboru 上田昇. “Viparyaya kō: Bukkyō ronrigaku ni okeru kibyU ronshō” Viparyaya考: 仏教論理学に
おける帰謬論証. Tōhōgaku 東方学 90(1995): 119–110.
(Work on this paper has been generously supported by the Austrian Science Fund(FWF)in the
framework of the FWF project P23196-G15 “Buddhist literature and its context.”)
〈Key words〉 DignAga, SAGkhya, AvIta, vIta, prasaGga, prasaGgaviparyaya, BhAviveka
(Research Fellow, The Institute for the Cultural and Intellectual History
of Asia of the Austrian Academy of Sciences)
─ 1235 ─