Literary Criticism from Plato to the Present
Literary Criticism from Plato to the Present: An Introduction
© 2011 M. A. R. Habib. ISBN: 978-1-405-16034-6
M. A. R. Habib
Also available:
The Blackwell Guide to Literary Theory
Gregory Castle
Literary Theory: An Introduction, 25th Anniversary Edition
Terry Eagleton
A History of Literary Criticism: From Plato to the Present
M. A. R. Habib
Modern Literary Criticism and Theory: A History
M. A. R. Habib
Literary Theory: An Anthology, Second Edition
Edited by Julie Rivkin and Michael Ryan
Literary Theory: A Practical Introduction, Second Edition
Edited by Michael Ryan
The Encyclopedia of Literary and Cultural Theory
Edited Michael Ryan, Gregory Castle, Robert Eaglestone and
M. Keith Booker
LITERARY CRITICISM
from Plato to the Present
AN INTRODUCTION
M. A. R. HABIB
This edition first published 2011
Ó 2011 M. A. R. Habib
Blackwell Publishing was acquired by John Wiley & Sons in February 2007. Blackwell’s publishing
program has been merged with Wiley’s global Scientific, Technical, and Medical business to form
Wiley-Blackwell.
Registered Office
John Wiley & Sons Ltd, The Atrium, Southern Gate, Chichester, West Sussex, PO19 8SQ, United
Kingdom
Editorial Offices
350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148-5020, USA
9600 Garsington Road, Oxford, OX4 2DQ, UK
The Atrium, Southern Gate, Chichester, West Sussex, PO19 8SQ, UK
For details of our global editorial offices, for customer services, and for information about how
to apply for permission to reuse the copyright material in this book please see our website at
www.wiley.com/wiley-blackwell.
The right of M. A. R. Habib to be identified as the author of this work has been asserted in accordance
with the UK Copyright, Designs, and Patents Act 1988.
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system,
or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording,
or otherwise, except as permitted by the UK Copyright, Designs, and Patents Act 1988, without the
prior permission of the publisher.
Wiley also publishes its books in a variety of electronic formats. Some content that appears in print may
not be available in electronic books.
Designations used by companies to distinguish their products are often claimed as trademarks.
All brand names and product names used in this book are trade names, service marks, trademarks or
registered trademarks of their respective owners. The publisher is not associated with any product or
vendor mentioned in this book. This publication is designed to provide accurate and authoritative
information in regard to the subject matter covered. It is sold on the understanding that the publisher is
not engaged in rendering professional services. If professional advice or other expert assistance is
required, the services of a competent professional should be sought.
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Habib, Rafey.
Literary criticism from Plato to the present : an introduction / M.A.R. Habib.
p. cm.
Revised ed. of: A history of literary criticism : from Plato to the present. Malden, Mass. :
Blackwell Pub., 2005.
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 978-1-4051-6034-6 (hardcover : alk. paper) – ISBN 978-1-4051-6035-3 (pbk. : alk. paper)
1. Criticism–History. I. Habib, Rafey. History of literary criticism. II. Title.
PN86.H23 2011
801’.9509–dc22
2010021915
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library.
Set in Sabon 10/12pt by Thomson Digital, Noida, India.
Printed in Singapore
1
2011
For Mughni Tabassum
Contents
Acknowledgments
Introduction
xi
1
Part I Classical Literary Criticism and Rhetoric
7
1 Classical Literary Criticism
Introduction to the Classical Period
Plato (428–ca. 347 BC)
Aristotle (384–322 BC)
9
9
10
15
2 The Traditions of Rhetoric
Greek Rhetoric
Roman Rhetoric
The Subsequent History of Rhetoric: An Overview
The Legacy of Rhetoric
23
23
27
30
31
3 Greek and Latin Criticism During the Roman Empire
Horace (65–8 BC)
Longinus (First Century AD)
Neo-Platonism
35
35
37
39
Part II The Medieval Era
47
4 The Early Middle Ages
Historical Background
Intellectual and Theological Currents
49
49
51
5 The Later Middle Ages
Historical Background
Intellectual Currents of the Later Middle Ages
The Traditions of Medieval Criticism
Transitions: Medieval Humanism
57
57
58
60
71
Part III The Early Modern Period to the Enlightenment
6 The Early Modern Period
Historical Background
77
79
79
viii
Contents
Intellectual Background
Confronting the Classical Heritage
Defending the Vernacular
Poetics and the Defense of Poetry
Poetic Form and Rhetoric
7 Neoclassical Literary Criticism
French Neoclassicism
Neoclassicism in England
80
86
89
91
94
98
100
102
8 The Enlightenment
Historical and Intellectual Background
Enlightenment Literary Criticism: Language, Taste,
and Imagination
114
114
9 The Aesthetics of Kant and Hegel
Immanuel Kant (1724–1804)
Hegel (1770–1831)
129
129
134
Part IV Romanticism and the Later Nineteenth Century
119
143
10 Romanticism
Germany
France
England
America
145
148
151
153
160
11 Realism, Naturalism, Symbolism, and Aestheticism
Historical Background: The Later Nineteenth Century
Realism and Naturalism
Symbolism and Aestheticism
168
168
169
174
12 The Heterological Thinkers
Arthur Schopenhauer (1788–1860)
Friedrich Nietzsche (1844–1900)
Henri Bergson (1859–1941)
Matthew Arnold (1822–1888)
181
181
182
185
185
Part V The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
Introduction
13 From Liberal Humanism to Formalism
The Background of Modernism
The Poetics of Modernism: W. B. Yeats, Ezra Pound, and T. S. Eliot
Formalism
Russian Formalism
The New Criticism
189
189
193
194
196
197
197
202
Contents
ix
14 Socially Conscious Criticism of the Earlier Twentieth Century
F. R. Leavis
Marxist and Left-Wing Criticism
The Fundamental Principles of Marxism
Marxist Literary Criticism: A Historical Overview
Early Feminist Criticism: Simone de Beauvoir and
Virginia Woolf
206
206
207
208
210
15 Phenomenology, Existentialism, Structuralism
Phenomenology
Existentialism
Heterology
Structuralism
219
220
220
223
224
16 The Era of Poststructuralism (I): Later Marxism,
Psychoanalysis, Deconstruction
Later Marxist Criticism
Psychoanalysis
Deconstruction
230
231
233
240
17 The Era of Poststructuralism (II): Postmodernism,
Modern Feminism, Gender Studies
J€
urgen Habermas (b. 1929)
Jean Baudrillard (1929–2007)
Jean-François Lyotard (1924–1998)
bell hooks (Gloria Jean Watkins; b. 1952)
Modern Feminism
Gender Studies
247
250
251
252
253
253
258
18 The Later Twentieth Century: New Historicism,
Reader-Response Theory, Postcolonial Criticism,
Cultural Studies
The New Historicism
Reader-Response and Reception Theory
Postcolonial Criticism
Cultural Studies
264
265
268
270
276
Epilogue New Directions: Looking Back, Looking Forward
279
Index
289
212
Acknowledgments
I would like to thank the following people for their encouragement, inspiration, and support or endorsement: Michael Payne, John Carey, Mughni
Tabassum, Joe Barbarese, Robert Grant, Ron Bush, Peter Widdowson, Frank
Kermode, Emma Bennett, and Yasmeen.
Introduction
Our English word “criticism” comes from the ancient Greek noun krites,
meaning “judge.” But what does it mean to be a “judge” of literature? We
might break this down into several basic questions: what is the purpose of
literary criticism? How broad is this field of inquiry, and who gets to define it?
What are its connections with other disciplines such as philosophy and
religion? How does it relate to the realms of morality, of knowledge, and
of learning? Does it have any political implications? How does it impinge on
our practices of reading and writing? Above all, what significance does it
have, or could it possibly have, in our own lives? Why should we even bother
to study literary criticism? Is it not enough for us to read the great works of
literature, of poetry, fiction, and drama? Why should we trouble ourselves to
read what people say about literature? And surely, after all the obscure
“theory” of the last 50 years or so, what we need to get back to is the texts
themselves. We need to appreciate literature for its beauty and its technical
artistry. In short, we need to read literature as literature – without the interference of some “judge” telling us what to look for or how to read.
How can we answer such skepticism? We might begin by recalling that
“theory” and critical reflection on literature began at least 2500 years ago,
and have been conducted by some of the greatest Western thinkers and
writers, ranging from Plato and Aristotle, through Augustine and St Thomas
Aquinas, Johnson, Pope, and the great Romantics to the great modern figures
such as Locke, Hume, Kant, Hegel, Freud, W. B. Yeats, and Sartre. Until 200
years ago, most great thinkers, critics, and literary artists would not have
understood what was meant by reading literature as literature. They knew that
literature had integral connections with philosophy, religion, politics, and
morality; they knew, in other words, that literature was richly related to all
aspects of people’s lives.
If we had no tradition of critical interpretation, if we were left with the
“texts” themselves, we would be completely bewildered. We would not
Literary Criticism from Plato to the Present: An Introduction
© 2011 M. A. R. Habib. ISBN: 978-1-405-16034-6
M. A. R. Habib
2
Introduction
know how to classify a given writer as Romantic, classical, or modern. We
would not know that a given poem was epic or lyric, mock-heroic, or even
that it was a poem. We would be largely unaware of which tradition a given
writer was working in and how she was trying to subvert it in certain ways.
We would not be able to arrive at any comparative assessment of writers in
terms of literary merit. We would not even be able to interpret the meanings
of individual lines or words in any appropriate context. It has been the long
tradition of literary interpretation – refined and evolved over many centuries –
which has addressed these questions. It is surely naive to think that we are
all endowed with some superior sensibility which can automatically discern
which writers are great and which are mediocre. We do not even know for
certain how the ancient Greek of Homer was pronounced; most of us cannot
read the Greek of Plato or the Latin of Aquinas or the Italian of Dante or
the Arabic of al-Ghazzali. How would we ever, independently, arrive at
any estimation of these writers or their backgrounds or their contributions
without a body of critical apparatus, without a tradition of critical expertise and interpretation, to help us? Shakespeare “is” a great writer because
that has been the enduring consensus of influential critics. The reputations
of writers can vary quite dramatically. At the beginning of the twentieth
century, T. S. Eliot was a powerful critical voice, denigrating the Romantics,
extolling the metaphysical poets and revaluating the very idea of tradition.
Nowadays, Eliot commands far less critical authority, though his high status
as a poet endures.
We can try to illustrate our actual reliance on the traditions of criticism and
theory by using a particular example, Matthew Arnold’s famous poem
“Dover Beach”:
The sea is calm to-night.
The tide is full, the moon lies fair
Upon the straits; on the French coast the light
Gleams and is gone; the cliffs of England stand;
Glimmering and vast, out in the tranquil bay.
Come to the window, sweet is the night-air!
Only, from the long line of spray
Where the sea meets the moon-blanched land,
Listen! you hear the grating roar
Of pebbles which the waves draw back, and fling,
At their return, up the high strand,
Begin, and cease, and then again begin,
With tremulous cadence slow, and bring
The eternal note of sadness in.
Sophocles long ago
Heard it on the Aegean, and it brought
Introduction
3
Into his mind the turbid ebb and flow
Of human misery; we
Find also in the sound a thought,
Hearing it by this distant northern sea.
The Sea of Faith
Was once, too, at the full, and round earth’s shore
Lay like the folds of a bright girdle furled.
But now I only hear
Its melancholy, long, withdrawing roar,
Retreating, to the breath
Of the night-wind, down the vast edges drear
And naked shingles of the world.
Ah, love, let us be true
To one another! for the world, which seems
To lie before us like a land of dreams,
So various, so beautiful, so new,
Hath really neither joy, nor love, nor light,
Nor certitude, nor peace, nor help for pain;
And we are here as on a darkling plain
Swept with confused alarms of struggle and flight,
Where ignorant armies clash by night.
A conventional reading of this poem based on the immediate “text” might go
like this: “Dover Beach” is a lyric poem which expresses the painful doubt and
disorientation of the Victorian age. The poem is unified by the image and
symbolism of the sea, which is used to express the decline of religious faith.
In the first section the calm of the sea is complemented by the “grating roar,”
and the motion of the waves, which the poem’s language imitates, symbolizes
the cyclical movement of human history, an idea which Arnold may have
derived from his father, Thomas Arnold. This symbolism is intensified as the
sea meets the “moon-blanched” land, the moon also symbolizing change,
in which case “moon-blanched land” might refer to a civilization bleached
or made colorless by change or progress. The picturesque opening presents a
visual scene of the moonlit ocean whose calm is interrupted only when it is
heard, as a “grating roar” which prepares the transition from the sea as physical image to symbol, infused with “The eternal note of sadness.” The second
section makes more precise the sea’s significance: the “hearing” of the sea,
and the “finding” of “a thought” in its sound, has a classical precedent, not
only inscribing Arnold within a literary tradition going back to Sophocles but
also stressing the universality of the human predicament. The third section
uses the sea as a powerful symbol of both religious faith, which once clothed
the world, and the process of secularization, which leaves the world “naked”;
4
Introduction
the symbolic “long, withdrawing roar” echoes the literal “roar” of the first
section, once again creating a fusion of general and particular. The last section warns of the deceptive nature of the world’s apparent beauty and variety
(as presented in the poem’s opening): beneath these “glimmering” surfaces
are other, more threatening sounds, foreboding chaos, war, and destruction.
On a technical level, we might observe that the poem is written as a
dramatic monologue, melancholy in tone, in four sections. It has no regular
rhythm or rhyme scheme but traces of a sonnet form may be discernible in the
first two sections; we might discern the ghost of an eroded blank verse in the
gesture of many lines toward iambic pentameter, with the preceding and
subsequent lines cut short to achieve various effects, as in “The Sea of Faith”
which, in its present eroded state, stands alone as merely four syllables, while
its comforting fullness in the past is evoked in two full pentameters beginning
“Was once, too, at the full, and round earth’s shore.” We might also point
out that the already irregular rhyme scheme abacdbdc breaks down in the
middle of the first section: there is no word to rhyme with “roar,” which might
also mimic the fragmentation of the Victorian world. The poem employs
numerous literary devices, most notably the metaphors (inherited from
Romanticism) ascribing intelligence or sentience to elements of nature such
as the sea and the night wind, the simile comparing the sea of faith to a
protective “girdle,” and various obvious devices such as anaphora, as in the
repetition of “so” and “nor” in the final section.
It is simply not possible to ascribe any meaning to the poem without
referring its words to broader trends in Victorian society. We might say that
the poem represents the anxiety of a world where religious faith was called
into question by numerous developments in science, scholarship, and technology: the various theories and philosophies of evolution, the German
Higher Criticism which discredited much of the Bible, and the Industrial
Revolution which caused a mass migration of people from the country to the
towns, displacing a village life centered around the parish with a life revolving
around the factory or office. Arnold was reacting against a mechanical,
industrial society which prided itself on progress. The only security left is that
of personal relationships. But the feelings expressed in the poem are universal:
we have the theme of man’s alienation and isolation, and his inability to
change the world. Arnold’s poem still applies today, just as it applied in the
ancient Greek world of Sophocles; that is why it is a great poem. It represents
its age as well as being timeless.
Already, even at this most basic level of interpretation, we have gone far
beyond the “words on the page.” Our reading already presupposes a knowledge of the Victorian era, its intellectual and religious currents, a knowledge
of literary tradition going back to classical times, a knowledge of Arnold’s
biography, and an awareness of theories of poetic form, genre, and rhetorical
theories of literary figures. And much literary and rhetorical theory – both
Introduction
5
ancient and modern – would challenge the view that Arnold is expressing a
universal human predicament, as well as any sharp distinction between literal
and figurative language. In fact the poem is very much conditioned by its
historical context, a context governed by the French Revolution of 1789 and
the rise to power of the middle classes through much of Europe. In England,
the Reform Bill of 1832 established the power of the middle classes over
the landed aristocracy. The Liberal Party, representing the middle classes,
came to power in 1830. In 1867, the year in which Arnold’s poem was
published, the vote was extended to urban industrial workers, and in 1884
to most agricultural laborers. What Arnold expresses is perhaps his despair
over the rise of middle-class society, whose narrowness and mechanical ideals
he criticizes eloquently in his prose writings. Who are the “ignorant armies”
that Arnold has in mind? The poem gives the impression that all such struggle
is futile and ignorant but it was written in 1851, after violent revolutions
in 1830 and 1848 had convulsed Europe: the main aim of these revolutions
was to establish constitutional monarchies or governments where the
people had some say in how they were ruled. Also, there is a contradiction
between the form and content of the poem: the poet urges sentimentally that
his relationship with his beloved must be one of mutuality and truth; yet
there is no interaction with the woman addressed, who remains without
character or voice. The very form of the dramatic monologue enacts the
alienation expressed in the poem’s content. Arnold was at Dover with his
wife in June of 1851 and again in October, after a continental honeymoon.
In the poem, which is presumably addressed to his wife, she is given no
personality or individuality at all. She is reduced to a mere occasion for
his grandiose reflection from his privileged vantage point on the cliffs of
Dover. The poem thus invites consideration from many other perspectives,
including those of feminism, Marxism, psychoanalysis and various
branches of rhetoric.
None of this is to deny that “Dover Beach” is a fine poem; it is, rather,
intended to show that the process of “reading” – even at the most basic level –
involves vast presuppositions and ever-broadening contexts. It is the task of
criticism and theory to articulate these presuppositions and to furnish the
contexts in which literary “judgments” can be appropriately made. Hence the
practice of literary criticism as applied to given texts is underlain by complex
assumptions and principles. Theory is devoted to examining these principles.
As such, theory is a systematic explanation of practice or a situation of
practice in a broader framework; theory brings to light the motives behind our
practice; it shows us the connection of practice to ideology, power structures,
our own unconscious, our political and religious attitudes, our economic
structures; above all, theory shows us that practice is not something natural or
neutral but is a specific historical construct, resting on specific assumptions
and motives, even if these are unacknowledged.
6
Introduction
This book aims to offer a concise introduction to the major tendencies and
figures of literary criticism and theory from ancient Greek times until the
present. An endeavor of such broad scope is bound to be incomplete: there is
not enough room to include, or even to do justice to, all of the important
figures. I do hope, however, that the following account will have the virtues
of clarity, close reading, and appropriate contextualization, in making
accessible to a general reader these sometimes difficult theories, their philosophical premises and their historical contexts. We will see, in the chapters
that follow, that the questions raised at the beginning of this introduction
have been addressed in a rich variety of ways by great thinkers and great
literary artists and critics for more than 2000 years.
Part I
Classical Literary Criticism
and Rhetoric
Literary Criticism from Plato to the Present: An Introduction
© 2011 M. A. R. Habib. ISBN: 978-1-405-16034-6
M. A. R. Habib
Chapter 1
Classical Literary Criticism
Introduction to the Classical Period
The story of Western literary criticism begins shortly after 800 BC in ancient
Greece, the era of the great Homeric epics, the Iliad and the Odyssey, as well
as the poets Hesiod and Sappho. The so-called “classical” period, starting
around 500 BC, witnessed the great tragedies of Euripides, Aeschylus, and
Sophocles, and the comedies of Aristophanes. It was around this time that the
foundations of Western philosophy were laid by Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle; the discipline of rhetoric and the political system of democracy were
established in Athens. The classical period is usually said to end in 323 BC with
the death of Alexander the Great. After this is the “Hellenistic” period,
witnessing the diffusion of Greek culture through much of the Mediterranean
and Middle East, a diffusion vastly accelerated by Alexander’s conquests, and
the various dynasties established by his generals after his death. The city of
Alexandria in Egypt, founded by Alexander in 331 BC, became a center of
scholarship and letters, housing an enormous library and museum, and
hosting such renowned poets and grammarians as Callimachus, Apollonius
Rhodius, Aristarchus, and Zenodotus. We know of these figures partly
through the work of Suetonius (ca. 69–140 AD) who wrote the first histories
of literature and criticism.
The Hellenistic period is usually said to end with the battle of Actium in
31 BC in which the last portion of Alexander’s empire, Egypt, was annexed by
the increasingly powerful and expanding Roman republic. After his victory at
Actium, the entire Roman world fell under the sole rulership of Julius Caesar’s
nephew, Octavian, soon to become revered as the first Roman emperor,
Augustus. During this span of almost a thousand years, poets, philosophers,
rhetoricians, grammarians, and critics laid down many of the basic terms,
concepts, and questions that were to shape the future of literary criticism as it
evolved all the way through to our own century. These include the concept of
“mimesis” or imitation; the concept of beauty and its connection with truth
and goodness; the ideal of the organic unity of a literary work; the social,
Literary Criticism from Plato to the Present: An Introduction
© 2011 M. A. R. Habib. ISBN: 978-1-405-16034-6
M. A. R. Habib
10
Classical Literary Criticism and Rhetoric
political, and moral functions of literature; the connection between literature,
philosophy, and rhetoric; the nature and status of language; the impact of
literary performance on an audience; the definition of figures of speech such as
metaphor, metonymy, and symbol; the notion of a “canon” of the most
important literary works; and the development of various genres such as epic,
tragedy, comedy, lyric poetry, and song.
The first recorded instances of criticism go back to dramatic festivals in
ancient Athens. A particularly striking literary critical discussion occurs in
Aristophanes’ play The Frogs, first performed in 405 BC. This comedy stages a
contest between two literary theories, representing older and younger generations; it is also a contest in poetic art.1 The two competing poets are
presented as Aeschylus and Euripides. Aeschylus represents the more traditional virtues of a bygone generation, such as martial prowess, heroism, and
respect for social hierarchy – all embodied in a lofty, decorous, and sublime
style of speech – while Euripides is the voice of a more recent, democratic,
secular, and plain-speaking generation (Frogs, l. 1055). Aristophanes’ play
reveals that for the ancient Greeks poetry was an important element in the
educational process; its ramifications extended over morality, religion, and
the entire sphere of civic responsibility. By the time of Plato and Aristotle,
poetry had achieved considerable authority and status. Plato rejected poetry’s
vision of the world as unpredictable, ruled by chance, and always prone to the
whims of the gods. Much of Plato’s philosophy is generated by a desire to view
the gods as wholly good, to impose order on chaos, to enclose change and
temporality within a scheme of permanence, and to ground our thinking
about morality, politics, and religion on timeless and universal truths. So
Greek philosophy begins as a challenge to the monopoly of poetry and the
extension of its vision in more recent trends such as sophistic and rhetoric
which offered a secular, humanistic, and relativistic view of the world. Plato’s
opposition of philosophy to poetry effectively sets the stage for more than
2000 years of literary theory and criticism.
Plato (428–ca. 347
BC)
It is widely acknowledged that the Greek philosopher Plato laid the foundations of Western philosophy. The mathematician and philosopher A. N.
Whitehead stated that Western philosophy is “a series of footnotes” to Plato,
who indeed gave initial formulation to the most fundamental questions: how
can we define goodness and virtue? How do we arrive at truth and knowledge? What is the connection between soul and body? What is the ideal
political state? Of what use are literature and the arts? What is the nature of
language? Plato’s answers to these questions are still disputed; yet the
questions themselves have endured.
Classical Literary Criticism
11
At the age of 20, like many other young men in Athens, Plato fell under the
spell of the controversial thinker and teacher Socrates. In a story later to be
recounted in Plato’s Apology, Socrates had been hailed by the Oracle at
Delphi as “the wisest man alive.” He devoted his life to the pursuit of
knowledge, wisdom, and virtue. Using a dialectical method of question and
answer, he would often arouse hostility by deflating the pretensions of those
who claimed to be wise and who professed to teach. A wide range of people,
including rhetoricians, poets, politicians, and artisans, felt the razor edge of
his intellect, which undermined conventional views of goodness and truth.
Eventually he was tried on a charge of impiety and condemned to death in
399 BC. After the death of his revered master, Plato eventually founded an
Academy in Athens.
Most of Plato’s philosophy is expounded in dialogue form, using a
dialectical method of pursuing truth by a systematic questioning of received
ideas and opinions (“dialectic” derives from the Greek dialegomai, “to
converse”). Socrates is usually cast as the main speaker. The canon attributed
to Plato includes 35 dialogues and 13 letters. The early dialogues are devoted
to exploring and defining concepts such as virtue, temperance, courage, piety,
and justice. The major dialogues of Plato’s middle period – Gorgias, Apology,
Phaedo, Symposium, Republic – move into the realms of epistemology
(theory of knowledge), metaphysics, political theory, and art. What unifies
these various concerns is Plato’s renowned theory of Forms, which sees the
familiar world of objects which surrounds us, and which we perceive through
our senses, as not independent or real but as dependent upon another world,
the realm of pure Forms or ideas, which can be known only by reason and not
by our bodily sense-perceptions. Plato says that the qualities of any object in
the physical world are derived from the ideal Forms. For example, an object in
the physical world is beautiful because it partakes of the ideal Form of Beauty
which exists in the higher realm. And so with Tallness, Equality, or Goodness,
which Plato sees as the highest of the Forms. The connection between the two
realms can best be illustrated using examples from geometry: any triangle or
square that we construct using physical instruments is bound to be imperfect.
At most it can merely approximate the ideal triangle which is perfect and
which is perceived not by the senses but by reason: the ideal triangle is not a
physical object but a concept, an idea, a Form.
According to Plato, the world of Forms, being changeless and eternal, alone
constitutes reality. It is the world of essences, unity, and universality, whereas
the physical world is characterized by perpetual change and decay, mere
existence (as opposed to essence), multiplicity, and particularity. A central
function of the theory of Forms is to unify groups of objects or concepts in the
world by treating them as belonging to a class, by referring them back to a
common essence, and thereby making sense of our innumerably diverse
experiences. A renowned expression of Plato’s theory occurs in the seventh
12
Classical Literary Criticism and Rhetoric
book of the Republic where he recounts the “myth of the cave” where people
have lived all their lives watching shadows of reality cast by a fire, with their
backs to the true light of the sun.2 Plato makes it clear that the cave in which
men are imprisoned represents the physical world, and that the journey
toward the light is the “soul’s ascension” to the world of Forms (Republic,
517b–c). In his later dialogues, Plato himself severely questioned the theory of
Forms.
Plato on poetry: the Ion
Plato’s most systematic comments on poetry occur in two texts, separated by
several years. The first is Ion, where Socrates cross-examines a rhapsode
(a singer and interpreter) called Ion on the nature of his art. The second, more
sustained, commentary occurs in the Republic. In the Ion, Socrates points out
that the rhapsode, like the poet himself, is in a state of “divine possession,”
and speaks not with his own voice which is merely a medium through which a
god speaks. The Muse inspires the poet, who in turn passes on this inspiration
to the rhapsode, who produces an inspired emotional effect on the spectators
(Ion, 534c–e). Socrates likens this process to a magnet, which transmits its
attractive power to a series of iron rings, which in turn pass on the attraction
to other rings, suspended from the first set. The Muse is the magnet or
loadstone, the poet is the first ring, the rhapsode is the middle ring, and the
audience the last one (Ion, 533a, 536a–b). In this way, the poet conveys and
interprets the utterances of the gods, and the rhapsode interprets the poets.
Hence, the rhapsodes are “interpreters of interpreters” (Ion, 535a).
The poet, insists Socrates, is “a light and winged thing, and holy, and never
able to compose until he has become inspired, and is beside himself, and
reason is no longer in him” (Ion, 534b). Not only poetry, according to
Socrates, but even criticism is irrational and inspired. Hence, in this early
dialogue, Plato has already sharply separated the provinces of poetry and
philosophy; the former has its very basis in a divorce from reason, which is the
realm of philosophy; poetry in its very nature is steeped in emotional
transport and lack of self-possession.
Poetry in Plato’s Republic
Plato’s theory of poetry in the Republic is much less flattering. His main
concern in this text is to define justice and the ideal nature of a political state.
Interestingly, his entire conception of justice arises explicitly in opposition to
poetic authority and tradition. Socrates mentions “an ancient quarrel”
between philosophy and poetry (Republic, 607b). Plato views poetry as a
powerful force in molding public opinion, and sees it as a danger to his ideal
city, ordered as this is in a strict hierarchy whereby the guardians
Classical Literary Criticism
13
(philosophers) and their helpers (soldiers) comprise an elect minority which
rules over a large majority of farmers, craftsmen, and “money-makers”
(415a–b; 434c). The program of education that he lays out for the rulers
or guardians of the city consists of gymnastics and music. The Greek word
mousike, as its form suggests, refers broadly to any art over which the Muses
preside, including poetry, letters, and music (401d–e).
Just how seriously Plato takes the threat of poetry is signaled by the fact that
it is music which primarily defines the function of guardianship: “It is here . . .
in music . . . that our guardians must build their guardhouse and post of
watch” (IV, 424b–e). Plato advocates an open and strict censorship of poetry
on the grounds of: (1) the falsity of its claims and representations regarding
both gods and men; (2) its corruptive effect on character; and (3) its
“disorderly” complexity and encouragement of individualism in the sphere
of sensibility and feeling. Socrates stresses that poets must not present the
gods as deceitful since “there is no lying poet in God” (II, 382d). This phrase
suggests that poetry by its very nature is a falsifying rhetorical activity. What
also emerges here is a conflict between philosophy and poetry in the right to
name the divine, to authorize a particular vision of the divine world: for
poetry, that world is presented as an anthropomorphic projection of human
values centered on self-interest, a world of dark chance, irrational, in flux, and
devoid of a unifying structure. The project of philosophy, in Plato’s hands, is
to stabilize that world, drawing all of its scattered elements into the form of
order and unity under which alone they can be posited as absolute and
transcendent.
Plato draws a powerful analogy between the individual and the state. In
book X, it will emerge explicitly that poetry appeals to the “inferior” part of
the soul, the appetitive portion (X, 603b–c). It is, in other words, an
encouragement toward variety and multiplicity, toward valuing the particular for its own sake, thereby distracting from contemplation of the universal.
In projecting this model onto the state as a whole, Plato aligns the mass of
people with the unruly “multitude” of desires in the soul, and the guardians
considered collectively with the “unity” of reason. The individuality of the
guardians is to be all but erased, not merely through ideological conditioning
but through their compulsory existence as a community: they are to possess
no private property or wealth; they must live together, nourished on a simple
diet, and receiving a stipend from the other citizens (III, 416d–417b).
Collectively, then, the guardians’ function in the city is a projection of the
unifying function of reason in the individual soul.
We now approach the heart of Plato’s overall argument concerning justice
and poetry. The definition of justice in the state is reached in book IV: justice is
a condition where “each one man must perform one social service in the state
for which his nature was best adapted” (IV, 433a–b). Predictably, justice in an
individual is defined as a condition of the soul where “the several parts . . .
14
Classical Literary Criticism and Rhetoric
perform each their own task,” and where reason rules. In political terms,
poetry’s greatest crime is its refusal or inability to confine itself to one kind of
task. Plato urges that the same man ought not to imitate “many things”: any
poetic imitation involving “manifold forms” will, says Socrates, “be ill suited
to our polity, because there is no twofold or manifold man among us, since
every man does one thing” (III, 397b–e). Plato then arrives at the renowned
passage urging banishment of the “manifold” poet:
If a man . . . who was capable by his cunning of assuming every kind of shape and
imitating all things should arrive in our city, bringing with himself the poems
which he wished to exhibit, we should fall down and worship him as a holy and
wondrous and delightful creature, but should say to him that there is no man of
that kind among us in our city, nor is it lawful for such a man to arise among us,
and we should send him away to another city, after pouring myrrh down over his
head and crowning him with fillets of wool. (III, 398a)
This general charge against poetry is elucidated in book X, where Plato
presents the poet as a “most marvelous Sophist” and a “truly clever and
wondrous man” who “makes all the things that all handicraftsmen severally
produce” (X, 596c–d). The political implication here is that poetry can have
no definable (and therefore limited) function in a state ordered according to a
strict hierarchy of inexchangeable function. Poetry literally does not know its
place: it spreads its influence limitlessly, dissolving social relations as it pleases
and recreating them from its own store of inspired wisdom whose opacity to
reason renders it resistant to classification and definition. In this sense, poetry
is the incarnation of indefinability and the limits of reason. It is in its nature a
rebel, a usurper, which desires to rule; and as such it is the most potent threat
to the throne of philosophy, which is also the throne of polity in the state of the
philosopher-king.
In political terms, Plato sees poetry as pandering primarily to a democratic
constitution (VIII, 568a–d). Like democracy, poetry fosters genuine individuals, “manifold” men who are “stuffed” with differences and resist the
reduction of their social function, or indeed their natural potential, into one
exclusive dimension. Also, like democracy, poetry nurtures all parts of the
soul, refusing obeisance to the law of reason. By implication, then, poetry
itself is spurred by the “greed” for liberty which is the hallmark of a
democratic society (X, 604e–605c).
All in all, Plato’s indictment of poetry has been based on (1) its intrinsic
expression of falsehood, (2) its intrinsic operation in the realm of imitation,
(3) its combination of a variety of functions, (4) its appeal to the lower aspects of
the soul such as emotion and appetite, and (5) its expression of irreducible
particularity and multiplicity rather than unity. The notion of imitation, in
fact, complements truth as the basis of Plato’s opposition of philosophy and
Classical Literary Criticism
15
poetry. In book X the poet is held up as a Sophist, a “marvelous” handicraftsman who can “make” anything (X, 596c–d). And what the poet imitates is of
course the appearance, not the reality, of things, since he merely imitates what
others actually produce (X, 596e, 597e). Plato elaborates his famous triad: we
find three beds, one existing in nature, which is made by God; another which is
the work of the carpenter; and a third, the work of the painter or poet. Hence,
the carpenter imitates the real bed and the painter or poet imitates the physical
bed. The poet’s work, then, like that of the rhapsode, is the “imitation of an
imitation.” It is thrice removed from truth (X, 597e).
The influence and legacy of Plato
The influence of Plato on many fundamental areas of Western thought,
including literary theory, continues to the present day. First and foremost
has been the impact of the theory of Forms: discredited though this may have
been since the time of Aristotle, it nonetheless exerted a powerful attraction
through its implications that the world was a unity, that our experience of
manifold qualities in the world could be brought under certain unifying
concepts, that the physical world itself is only a small part of, or manifestation
of, a higher reality, and that there exists a higher, ideal pattern for earthly
endeavors. Some of these elements have been integral in both Judeo-Christian
and Islamic theology and philosophy. The distinctions between reason and
sense, reason and emotion, soul and body, while not original to Plato,
continued through his influence to provide some of the basic terminology
of philosophical and religious thinking. Plato’s impact on literary critics and
theorists has embraced many issues: the doctrine of imitation; the educational
and didactic functions of poetry; the place of poetry in the political state and
the question of censorship; the treatment of poetry as a species of rhetoric; the
nature of poetic inspiration; and the opposition of poetry to various other
disciplines and dispositions, such as philosophy, science, reason, and
mechanism. We are still grappling with the problems laid down by Plato.
Aristotle (384–322 BC)
The most brilliant student at Plato’s Academy was Aristotle, whose enormous
contribution to the history of thought spans several areas: metaphysics, logic,
ethics, politics, literary criticism, and various branches of natural science. In
343 BC King Philip of Macedon invited Aristotle to serve as tutor to his son
Alexander at his court in Pella. Later, Aristotle opened his own school of
rhetoric and philosophy, the Lyceum, in Athens. Plato’s Academy placed
emphasis on mathematics, metaphysics, and politics, while at the Lyceum
natural science predominated.
16
Classical Literary Criticism and Rhetoric
At the heart of Aristotle’s metaphysics and logic is the concept of
“substance,” which he views as the primary reality, underlying everything
else. Aristotle basically holds that there are 10 categories through which we
can view the world: whatness (substance), quantity, quality, relation, place,
time, position, state, action, and affection.3 A mere glance at these categories
tells us that they still permeate our own thought about the world at the
profoundest levels, especially the notion of substance.
Reversing the Platonic hierarchy, Aristotle urges that universals (qualities,
such as “redness” or “tallness”) depend on particular things for their
existence, not vice versa. Though Aristotle would agree with Plato that
reason has access to a higher knowledge than our senses, he insists that the
senses are the starting point and the source of knowledge. He attempts to
balance Plato’s unilateral emphasis on reason with due attention to our actual
experience and to close observation of the world. In a broad sense, the history
of Western thought has often emerged as a conflict between these two visions:
the idealistic Platonic vision which views reality as above and beyond our own
world, and the more empirical Aristotelian view which seeks to find reality
within our world.
Aristotle’s logic
Aristotle’s greatest contribution to philosophy lies in the realm of logic.
Aristotle was the first philosopher to formalize the rules and methods of logic.
The basis of his logic, which acted as the foundation of the discipline for over
2000 years, was the syllogism. This typically consists of a major premise, a
minor premise, and an inferred conclusion, as in the classic example: “All men
are mortal; Socrates is a man; therefore, Socrates is mortal.” Aristotle
classified a number of different kinds of syllogism, ranging from this simple
“if . . . then” structure to far more complex formats.
Even more fundamental than the syllogism are the three so-called laws of
logic (sometimes called the “laws of thought”) as formulated by Aristotle and
developed by numerous subsequent thinkers into our own day. The first of
these is the law of identity, which states that A is A; the second is the law of
non-contradiction, which dictates that something cannot be both A and notA; and the third, the law of the excluded middle, holds that something must be
either A or not-A. These “laws,” which can be regarded as the same law
expressed from three different perspectives, have served for over two millenia
as the (almost) unshakeable foundation of Western thought. As such, they
bear examination in a little more detail. What does it mean to say that A is A?
Is this not an obvious and empty tautology? We can see that it is no trite
proposition the moment we substitute any important term for the letter A. Let
us, for example, use the term “man.” When we say that “a man is a man,” we
are appealing to certain qualities which compose the essence of man; we are
Classical Literary Criticism
17
saying that this essence is fixed and unalterable; we are also saying that a man
is somehow different from a woman, from an animal, from a plant, and so
forth. We can quickly begin to see how our definition will have vast economic
and political implications: if we define our “man” as rational, as political, as
moral, and as free, it will seem natural to us that he should partake in the
political process. The woman, whom we define as lacking these qualities, will
by our definition be excluded. That this law of identity is highly coercive and
hierarchical will become even clearer in the case of the terms “master” and
“slave.” The master might be defined in terms of attributes that collectively
signify “civilized,” while the slave is constricted within designations of
“savage” (Aristotle, who owned many slaves, himself defines a slave as a
“speaking instrument”). Such hierarchical oppositions have in history embraced the terms Greek and barbarian, Christian and Jew, white and black,
noble and serf.
The second and third laws of logic will merely confirm our implicit
degradation of the woman or slave. The second law, the law of noncontradiction, on which Aristotle insists,4 tells us that something/someone
cannot be both a man and not a man. Again, is this not obvious? Surely it tells
us nothing new? In fact, we are stating a further implication of the law of
identity: that a certain set of qualities is attributed to “man” and a different set
of qualities is accorded to woman, there being no overlap between these two
sets of qualities. According to this logic, we cannot speak of a person who
might come in between these two poles: a man who had womanly qualities or
a woman with manly attributes. The third law, the law of the excluded
middle, explicitly forbids this middle ground (Met. I–IX, 1011b–23) in its
urging that something must be either A or not-A. One must be either a man or
not a man; either American or not-American; either Muslim or Jew; either
good or bad; either for or against. Hence, these “laws,” which unfortunately
still largely govern our thinking today, are not only coercive but encourage a
vision of the world as divided up sharply into categories, classes, nations,
races, and religions, each with its own distinctive essence or character. So
deeply rooted is this way of thinking that even attempted subversions of it,
such as those issued from Marxism, feminism, deconstruction, and
psychoanalysis, must operate within a broader network of complicity with
what they challenge.
Aristotle’s Poetics
In contrast with Plato, Aristotle sees poetry as having a positive function in the
political state, which exists not merely for utilitarian purposes but to promote
what Aristotle calls the “good life,” or the achievement of virtue and
phronesis or practical wisdom.5 For Aristotle, poetry and rhetoric had the
status of “productive” sciences; these disciplines had their place in a hierarchy
18
Classical Literary Criticism and Rhetoric
of knowledge; and Aristotle viewed them as rational pursuits, as seeking a
knowledge of “universal” truths (rather than of random “particular” things
or events), and as serving a social and moral function. The entire structure of
the Aristotelian system was governed by the notion of substance, from the
lowest level to God as the First Cause, or Unmoved Mover. Each element
within this hierarchical order had its proper place, function, and purpose.
Aristotle’s universe is effectively a closed system where each entity is guided
by an internalized purpose toward the fulfillment of its own nature, and
ultimately toward realization of its harmony with the divine. Poetry, in this
system, is analyzed and classified in the same way as the other branches of
human knowledge and activity. Our modern notions of poetic autonomy
would have been meaningless to Aristotle. In Nicomachean Ethics, he states
quite clearly concerning productive activity that “the act of making is not an
end in itself, it is only a means, and belongs to something else.” The purpose of
art, like that of metaphysics, is to attain to a knowledge of universals.6
At the core of Aristotle’s Poetics are two complex notions: imitation and
action. Like Plato, Aristotle holds that poetry is essentially a mode of
imitation. In contrast with Plato, Aristotle invests imitation with positive
significance, seeing it as a basic human instinct and as a pleasurable avenue to
knowledge.7 Aristotle asserts that all the various modes of poetry and music
are imitations. These imitations can differ in three ways: in the means used, in
the kinds of objects represented, and in the manner of presentation. As against
popular notions which equate poetry with the use of meter, Aristotle insists
that the essential characteristic of the poet is imitation, in which all human
beings take pleasure (Poetics, I). For Aristotle, the poet is an integral part of
human society, rationally developing and refining basic traits which he shares
with other human beings.
What is common to all arts, says Aristotle, is that they imitate men involved
in action (Poetics, II). For Aristotle, “action” has a moral end or purpose. Art
imitates human action; but human action must have as its ultimate purpose
“the Supreme Good.”8 The actions imitated, says Aristotle, must be either
noble or base since human character conforms to these distinctions (Poetics,
II). Tragedy represents men as better than the norm; comedy as worse than the
norm. Aristotle allows only two basic types: narration, where the poet speaks
in his own person or through a character; and dramatic presentation, where
the story is performed and acted out (Poetics, III).
Aristotle makes an important contrast between poetry and history. It is not
the function of the poet to narrate events that have actually happened, but
rather “events such as might occur . . . in accordance with the laws of
probability or necessity” (Poetics, IX). He infers that poetry is more
“philosophical” and “serious” (spoudaioteron) than history because poetry
expresses what is universal (ta kathalou), while history merely deals with
individuals. Another way of putting this is to say that poetry yields general
Classical Literary Criticism
19
truths while history gives us particular facts and events. The poet expresses
the inner structure of probability or causality which shapes events and, as
such, is universalizable and applicable to other sets of events.
Later in the Poetics Aristotle seems to broaden his definition of poetic
imitation. He says that the poet must imitate in one of three ways. He must
imitate things that were, things that are now or things that people say and
think to be, or things which ought to be. Aristotle’s earlier definitions, we may
recall, referred poetic imitation not to morality or realism but to probability
and universality. The emphasis now, however, is upon realism: the poet
represents events which happened in the past or occur in the present.
Moreover, two important factors are introduced. The first is an appeal to
the moral imperative of imitation, whereby the poet should represent an ideal
state of affairs. The second is an appeal to conventional opinions. For
example, while a poet may not represent the gods truthfully, he is justified
in presenting them in accordance with prevailing opinions and myths which
are told about the gods. This is a huge step toward suggesting that truth is not
somehow transcendent and that it is realized within, not beyond, a human
community. In his Rhetoric, Aristotle states that “truth is not beyond human
nature.”9
Aristotle’s view of tragedy
Aristotle’s analysis of tragedy remained influential until the eighteenth
century. It is here that the connections between imitation, action, character,
morality, and plot emerge most clearly, as in Aristotle’s famous definition:
Tragedy is, then, an imitation of an action that is serious, complete and of a
certain magnitude – by means of language enriched with all kinds of ornament,
each used separately in the different parts of the play: it represents men in action
and does not use narrative, and through pity and fear it effects relief to these and
similar emotions. (Poetics, VI.2–3)
The Greek word used for “action” is praxis which here refers not to a
particular isolated action but to an entire course of action and events that
includes not only what the protagonist does but also what happens to him. In
qualifying this action, Aristotle again uses the word spoudaios which means
“serious” or “weighty.” This is essentially a moral seriousness. It seems, then,
that the subject matter of tragedy is a course of action which is morally
serious, presents a completed unity, and occupies a certain magnitude not
only in terms of importance but also, as will be seen, in terms of certain
prescribed constraints of time, place, and complexity. Moreover, since a
tragedy is essentially dramatic rather than narrative, it represents men in
action, and a properly constructed tragedy will provide relief or katharsis for
20
Classical Literary Criticism and Rhetoric
various emotions, primarily pity and fear. Hence the effect of tragedy on the
audience is part of its very definition.
The notion of “action” is central to Aristotle’s view of tragedy because it
underlies the other components and features, which include plot, character,
diction, thought, spectacle, and song. These elements include the means of
imitation (diction and song), the manner of imitation (spectacle), and the
objects of imitation (actions as arranged in a plot, the character and thought
of the actors). Aristotle also prescribes other requirements such as completeness of action, artistic unity, and emotional impact. The element of tragedy
which imitates human actions is not primarily the depiction of character but
the plot, which Aristotle calls the “first principle” and “the soul of tragedy”
(Poetics, VI.19–20). Aristotle accords priority to action in poetic representation: tragedy is not a representation of men or of character; rather it
represents a sphere “of action, of life” (Poetics, VI.12). Because tragedy is
essentially dramatic, its basis cannot be the depiction of character; as Aristotle
points out, one cannot have a tragedy without action, but a tragedy without
character study is quite feasible (Poetics, VI.14–15). A tragedy must be based
on a certain structure of events or incidents to which the specific actions of
given characters contribute. This overall dramatic structure, the plot, is
“the end at which tragedy aims” (Poetics, VI.13).
For Aristotle, the most important feature of the plot is unity: “the component incidents must be so arranged that if one of them be transposed or
removed, the unity of the whole is dislocated and destroyed” (Poetics, VIII.4).
Aristotle sees the entire complex as one unified action. How is such organic
unity achieved? Aristotle offers the following definition: “A whole is what has
a beginning and middle and end” (Poetics, VII. 2–3). A beginning, for
Aristotle, is that which is not necessarily caused by anything else, but itself
causes something else. A middle both follows from something else and results
in something else. An end is what necessarily follows from something else but
does not produce a further result. Hence the unity of the plot is based on a
notion of causality (Poetics, VII.7). Aristotle’s formulae concerning beginning, middle, and end have been profoundly influential, extending far beyond
the confines of tragedy or drama, and deeply infusing modes of thinking and
writing even into our own times.
Aristotle explains unity of plot in terms of both the plot’s formal structure
and the emotions produced in an audience. While he divides the formal
structure of the plot into prologue, episode, exode, parode, and stasimon, it is
clear that for him the real structure of the plot consists in the movement of the
action. He divides plots into simple plots, which exhibit a continuous action,
and complex plots – as exemplified in Oedipus Rex – whose action is marked
by a movement through reversal, recognition, and suffering. Much later in his
text, he divides the action into two parts, the “complication” which includes
all of the events until the change in fortune, and the “denouement”
Classical Literary Criticism
21
or unravelling which proceeds from the change in fortune until the end of the
play. In this way, the change in fortune is indeed placed at the center of the
play: the action as divided both leads to it and flows from it; and it is in relation
to it that reversal, recognition, and suffering take their significance. Aristotle
prefers complex plots because it is through the processes of reversal, recognition, and suffering that the emotions of pity and fear are evoked, which
themselves contribute to the plot’s unity.
The plot’s unity, then, integrates not only causality, probability, and
change of fortune but also the emotions of fear and pity which are generated
in an audience. Aristotle explains that pity is aroused by undeserved misfortune; fear is aroused when we realize that the man who suffers such
misfortune is “like ourselves” (Poetics, XIII.4). Hence these emotions cannot
be inspired by a wicked man prospering; nor can they issue from seeing the
misfortune suffered by either an entirely worthy man or a thoroughly bad
man (Poetics, XIII.2–4). Rather, the character in question must occupy a
mean between these extremes: he must be a man “who is not pre-eminently
virtuous and just, and yet it is through no badness or villainy of his own that
he falls into the misfortune, but rather through some flaw in him”
(Poetics, XIII.5–6).
The legacy of Aristotle’s Poetics
The Poetics is usually recognized as the most influential treatise in the history
of literary criticism. The legacy of Aristotle’s aesthetics, like that of his
philosophy as a whole, is a distinctly classical one. The most fundamental
premise of Aristotle’s classicism is a political one, namely that the individual
achieves his or her nature and purpose only within a society and a state.
Poetry, for Aristotle, does not express what is unique about individuals but
rather their universal characteristics, what they share with other members of
society. While Aristotle grants to poetry a certain autonomy, it yet occupies a
definite place within the state as an instrument of education and moral
edification. Poetry is not, as in Romantic thought, exalted to an eminence
beyond other pursuits.
Poetry is also subject to the classical principles of Aristotle’s philosophy in
general. From the most minute level of diction to the highest level of plot
construction, poetry is held to be a rational, deliberative activity which must
always observe the central Aristotelian principle of moderation. Like philosophy, poetry seeks to express universal truths, which are not constrained
by reference to particular situations. Its relation to reality is governed by the
notions of probability and necessity. Also classical in outlook is Aristotle’s
insistence on distinguishing clearly between different genres in a hierarchical
manner: comedy, which deals with “low” characters and trivial matter, ranks
lowest; epic, which includes various plots and lengthy narration, falls below
22
Classical Literary Criticism and Rhetoric
tragedy which is more concentrated and produces a greater effect of unity.
Again, the insistence on propriety and consistency of character is classical.
Aristotle’s notions anticipate developments in several areas of literary
criticism: the issue of poetic imitation, the connection between art and reality,
the distinction between genres as well as between high and low art, the study
of grammar and language, the psychological and moral effects of literature,
the nature and function of the audience, the structure and rules of drama, as
well as the notions of plot, narrative, and character. All of these notions are
still profoundly pervasive in our thinking about literature and the world.
Above and beyond all of these influences, however, is his doctrine of
substance, a notion that continues to underlie our thinking, and even our
attempts to undermine conventional modes of thought.
Notes
1. Frogs, ll. 786, 796, in Aristophanes Volume II: The Peace, The Birds, The Frogs,
trans. Benjamin Bickley Rogers, Loeb Classical Library (Cambridge, MA and
London: Harvard University Press/Heinemann, 1968). Hereafter cited as Frogs.
2. Republic, in Collected Dialogues of Plato, ed. Edith Hamilton and Huntington
Cairns (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1969), 514a–c. Hereafter cited as
Republic.
3. Aristotle, The Categories; On Interpretation; Prior Analytics, trans. Harold P.
Cooke and Hugh Tredennick, Loeb Classical Library (Cambridge, MA and
London: Harvard University Press/Heinemann, 1973), pp. 16–19.
4. Aristotle, The Metaphysics I–IX, trans. Hugh Tredennick, Loeb Classical Library
(Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard University Press/Heinemann, 1947),
1011b–13. Hereafter cited as Met. I–IX.
5. Aristotle, Politics, trans. T. A. Sinclair (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1986), VII.i.
6. Nicomachean Ethics, trans. H. Rackham, Loeb Classical Library (London and
New York: Heinemann/Harvard University Press, 1934), VI.ii.5–VI.iii.4–6.
7. Aristotle: Poetics; Longinus: On the Sublime; Demetrius: On Style, trans.
W. Hamilton Fyfe (Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard University Press/
Heinemann, 1965), IV.2–3. Hereafter cited as Poetics.
8. Aristotle, Posterior Analytics; Topica, trans. Hugh Tredennick and E. S. Forster,
Loeb Classical Library (Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard University Press/
Heinemann, 1976), p. 171.
9. Aristotle, The Art of Rhetoric, trans. H. C. Lawson-Tancred (Harmondsworth:
Penguin, 1991), 1355a.
Chapter 2
The Traditions of Rhetoric
The word “rhetoric” derives from the Greek word rhetor, meaning
“speaker,” and originally referred to the art of public speaking. This art
embraced the techniques whereby a speaker could compose and arrange a
speech that would be persuasive through its intellectual, emotional, and
dramatic appeal to an audience. Over the last two millennia, rhetoric has been
important in a number of spheres: the political sphere, where this art was
born; philosophy, which has often placed rhetoric below logic and metaphysics; theology, which has used rhetoric for its own ends; education, where
rhetoric has often assumed a central role, extending into our own composition classrooms; and, of course, literary criticism, which continues to draw
upon rhetoric in its focus on language, tropes, and audience.
Greek Rhetoric
Rhetoric originated in ancient Greece in the fifth century BC. It owed its early
development to the Sophists, Aristotle, and then, in the Roman world, to
Cato, Cicero, and Quintilian. Classical rhetoric, as developed until the time of
Cicero, had five parts or “offices”: invention, arrangement, style, memory,
and delivery. “Invention”(heuresis/inventio) referred to the content of a
speech: a statement of the issue at stake and the means of persuasion, which
embraced direct evidence, an account of the speaker’s character, logical
argument, consideration of the emotions of the audience as well as of the
ethical and political premises of the speech. The second office was the
“arrangement” (taxis/dispositio) of the speech into a given order. The speech
would begin with an “introduction” to arouse audience interest and sympathy; then a “narration” of a given background and relevant facts; a “proof”
which would include logical arguments and a refutation of objections or
counterarguments; its “conclusion” might recapitulate the essential argument and appeal further to the emotions of the audience. The third office,
Literary Criticism from Plato to the Present: An Introduction
© 2011 M. A. R. Habib. ISBN: 978-1-405-16034-6
M. A. R. Habib
24
Classical Literary Criticism and Rhetoric
“style” (lexis/elocutio), conventionally had two elements: diction (or word
choice) and composition, which referred to various elements of sentence
construction, such as structure, rhythm, and the use of figures.
These three offices were common to both public speaking and written
composition. There were two further offices, identified by Aristotle, peculiar
to speaking: “memory,” which signified the memorization of the speech for
oral performance; and “delivery,” which embraced control of voice and
gesture. Style was conventionally evaluated on the basis of four virtues of style
formulated by Aristotle’s student Theophrastus: correctness (of grammar and
language usage); clarity; ornamentation (using tropes and figures of speech);
and propriety. Styles were classified as grand, middle, and plain.
According to one tradition, the art of rhetoric was formally founded in
476 BC by a native of Syracuse, Corax, whose student Tisias transmitted his
master’s teachings to the mainland.1 Rhetoric was an integral part of the
political process in ancient Greece, especially in Athens and Syracuse of the
fifth century BC. It has profound and perhaps intrinsic ties to the political
system of democracy, since it presupposes the freedom for a range of viewpoints to be expressed in public discourse. On the ability to speak persuasively
could depend the entire future of a state, family, or individual. On rhetoric
often hung the balance of life or death, war or peace, prosperity or destruction, freedom or slavery.
Given that rhetoric was so vital in ancient Athens, there emerged a group of
professional teachers, called Sophists (from sophos, meaning “wise”), who
taught this art for use in the courts, the legislature, and political forums, as
well as for philosophical reflection and debate. Through their influence,
rhetoric came to assume a central role in Greek education. The most
influential of the Sophists were Protagoras, Gorgias, Antiphon, Lysias, and
Isocrates. Protagoras’ most famous belief was that “man is the measure of all
things.” This was essentially a secular humanistic and individualistic idea. He
also taught that every argument had two sides, which could be equally
rational. Hence he encouraged relativism, skepticism, and agnosticism.
Another powerful figure among the Sophists was Gorgias (ca. 485–380 BC),
who stressed the need for rhetoric to borrow figures of speech from poetry.
Like Protagoras, he subordinated the notion of truth to the presentation of a
particular viewpoint and to the persuasion of a given audience. Isocrates
(436–338 BC) was influential in his emphasis on rhetoric as the basis of
education. He viewed the essential purpose of oratory as political, to train
politicians in promoting the values and unity of Greek culture.
Plato’s Critique of Rhetoric
Given the importance of rhetoric in Athenian public life, it is hardly surprising
that this art was subject to abuse. The Sophists nurtured in their students an
The Traditions of Rhetoric
25
ability to argue both or many sides of a case; they were consequently accused
of training people in “making the worse cause appear the better” and in
thereby sacrificing truth, morality, and justice to self-interest. Aristophanes
satirized the Sophists in his comedy The Clouds. A more serious, and
permanently damaging, challenge was issued by Plato, especially in his
dialogues Gorgias and Phaedrus.
Plato’s critique of rhetoric in Gorgias (through the persona of Socrates) is
premised on a sharp opposition between the spheres of philosophy and
rhetoric. There are two kinds of persuasion, maintains Socrates: one which
confers conviction without understanding and one which confers knowledge.
Rhetoric, he insists, leads to conviction without educating people as to right
and wrong.2 He argues that the rhetorician is a non-expert persuading other
non-experts. He never need know the actual facts of a situation; he needs no
expertise, merely a persuasive ploy (Gorgias, 459a–c). Socrates’ criticism is
underlain by Plato’s notion of truth as transcending human opinion. In the
law courts, says Socrates, rhetoric relies on producing a large number of
eminent witnesses; but such argument or refutation is worthless in the context
of truth. In effect, suggests Socrates, the rhetorician and the politician are
forced to pander to the existing power structure and the views of the majority
(Gorgias, 481d–482c).
Aristotle and the Further Development of Rhetoric
Aristotle’s influential treatise Rhetoric states that rhetoric is the
“counterpart” of dialectic or logical argument. Whereas dialectic uses logical
syllogisms, rhetoric uses the enthymeme, which is a syllogism whose premises
are not certain or necessary but probable.3 In contrast with Plato, Aristotle
urges that rhetoric is a useful skill precisely because it can promote the causes
of truth and justice. In fact, the true position is naturally superior and more
easily argued (Rhet., 1355b). Moreover, we need the capacity to argue
contradictory positions so that we have a fuller understanding of the case
and can refute unjust counterarguments (Rhet., 1355a).
Again in pointed contrast with Plato, Aristotle contends that rhetoric, like
dialectic, is not concerned with any single field. Whereas each of the other arts
is persuasive and instructive about a special province, rhetoric deals with the
element of persuasiveness in any field (Rhet., 1355b). Aristotle classifies
proof, the most important component of rhetoric, into three basic types, as
these relate to (1) the character of the speaker, who must establish his
credibility; (2) the audience, which must be induced into a certain emotional
state; and (3) the persuasive nature of the speech itself (Rhet., 1356a). To
master these various proofs, one must master the syllogism, one must have a
scientific understanding of character and virtue, and one must understand
each emotion and how it is brought about. Given that rhetoric requires this
26
Classical Literary Criticism and Rhetoric
broad mastery, Aristotle considers it to be an offshoot of dialectic and ethics.
He in fact suggests that rhetoric “is quite properly categorized as political”
(Rhet., 1356a).
Aristotle distinguishes three genres of rhetoric. The first genre is
“deliberative” rhetoric, whose province is politics, concerning which future
actions should be taken by the state. “Forensic” rhetoric is used in the law
courts; it concerns actions already performed in the past, and it employs
prosecution and defense in its objective of achieving justice. The final genre is
“display” rhetoric which focuses on the present and involves praise and
denigration in its aim of displaying nobility (Rhet., 1358b–1359a).
Aristotle urges that the chief virtue of “style” is to be clear and to be
appropriate to the subject. Metaphor is a central element of style but must
be used moderately (Rhet., 1405a–b). Another prime attribute of style is
propriety, which means that a given content must be expressed in a
suitable manner. Also integral to propriety are the use of emotion and
tailoring of the speech to the audience’s character, as well as timeliness, the
use of the appropriate expression at the appropriate time (Rhet., 1408a–b).
In the final section of the Rhetoric, concerning composition, Aristotle
explains that a speech will have four parts: the introduction; the presentation or main narrative; the proof of the speaker’s claims, which includes
refutation of counterarguments; and finally a summarizing epilogue
(Rhet., 1414b).
Hellenistic Rhetoric
Classical Greek culture based on the polis or city-state effectively ended with
the defeat of Athens by Philip of Macedon at the battle of Chaeronea in
338 BC. Shortly after Aristotle’s death in 332 BC his “student” Alexander the
Great, son of Philip, conquered the vast Persian Empire in its entirety. The
Hellenistic period is said to begin with Alexander’s death in 323 BC, after
which his empire was divided up among his generals, who initiated various
dynasties: Ptolemy in Egypt (and later Phoenicia and Palestine), Seleucus in
Syria, Persia, and Mesopotamia, and Cassander in Macedonia. Notwithstanding these divisions, Greek language and culture were spread all across
the conquered territories. This new Hellenistic era was characterized by a
merging of Greek and Oriental traditions.
The great library and museum of Alexandria in Egypt was a center of
scholarship in the fields of science, textual criticism, and poetic composition.
Hellenistic scholars working here further systematized the content and rules
of rhetoric. A major surviving text of this period is the Rhetorica ad
Alexandrum (dedicated to Alexander the Great), written in Greek in
the fourth century BC. Greek rhetoricians of this period include Theophrastus
(ca. 370–285 BC) who may have initiated the study of figures of speech and
The Traditions of Rhetoric
27
figures of thought, and who may have founded the notion of three levels of
style – high, middle, and plain. The most important Greek rhetorician of this
time was Hermagoras of Temnos, who influenced Cicero and Quintilian,
especially through his doctrine of stasis, which identified the “position” or
“stance” toward the issue at stake in an argument.4
Roman Rhetoric
Greek rhetoric made its entry into Rome in the second century BC. Hermagoras had a great influence on two of the major early Roman texts of
rhetoric, the Rhetorica ad Herennium (Rhetoric for Herennius, ca. 90 BC)
and Cicero’s De inventione (87 BC). The Rhetorica, attributed for several
centuries to Cicero, is the first text to present a detailed discussion of the
five-part system which was central to the Roman tradition of rhetoric.5 The
author defines these parts as follows: invention is the devising of matter
which will make a given case convincing; arrangement is the ordering of the
matter; style is the adaptation of words and sentences to the matter
invented; memory is the firm retention in the mind of the content; and
delivery refers to the regulation of voice, countenance, and gesture (RH,
I.ii.3). The most complete argument, he tells us, has five parts: proposition,
reason, proof of the reason, embellishment, and resume or conclusion.
A conclusion is tripartite, and includes summary, amplification, and appeal
to pity.
The author suggests that there are three levels of style: the grand or high
style, which uses ornate arrangements of impressive words; the middle style,
which uses a lower class of words which, however, are not colloquial; and the
simple or plain style, which uses the most current idiom of standard speech
(RH, IV.viii.11). This concept of the three styles was adapted by critics in the
Middle Ages, who saw the three levels respectively as applying to narratives
about the court, the town, and the peasantry.
Finally, the author provides a long list of “figures of speech” and “figures of
thought.” The former are produced by an adornment of language; the latter
by a distinction in the idea or conception itself (RH, IV.xii.18). Metonymy is
defined as a figure which draws from an object closely akin to the intended
object but substitutes a different name. Synecdoche occurs when the whole is
understood from the part or vice versa, or when the singular is understood
from the plural or vice versa (RH, IV.xxxii.43–xxxiii.45). Metaphor is said to
occur when a word applying to one thing is transferred to another, on the
basis of a given similarity; it is used to create vividness, brevity, to avoid
obscenity, to magnify or diminish, or to embellish. Finally, allegory is defined
as a manner of speech denoting one thing by the letter of the words but
another by their meaning.
28
Classical Literary Criticism and Rhetoric
Cicero’s Rhetorical Theory
Marcus Tullius Cicero (106–43 BC) is the most renowned of the classical
rhetoricians. As a student in Rome, he entered an educational system which
was centered on rhetoric and assigned exercises in writing, speaking, arguing
a thesis, legislative and judicial declamations, the exercise of memory, and the
proper delivery of a speech. He published his rhetorical treatise De inventione
in the early part of the first century BC. This was followed by other rhetorical
texts, De oratore (55 BC), Brutus (46 BC), a history of Roman oratory, Orator
(46 BC), De optimo genere oratorum [On the Ideal Classification of Orators]
(46 BC), and Partitione oratoria [On the Divisions of Rhetoric] (45 BC).
In De inventione Cicero stresses the political importance of rhetoric. He
also affirms that the function of rhetoric is to help promote a society based on
justice and common welfare rather than physical strength. As such, the
speaker must possess not only eloquence but also wisdom.6 Cicero divides
a speech into six parts, beginning with the exordium, intended to make the
audience well disposed, moving on to body which consists of a narrative of
events, argumentation, refutation of counterarguments, then ending with a
peroration which has three parts: a resume of the speech’s substantial points,
arousal of animosity against the opponent, and the arousing of sympathy for
one’s own case. A peroration might also include personification as well as
appealing to the pity of the jury (DI, I.80.100–105). Cicero considers delivery
to be the supreme factor in successful oratory (DI, III.213). The orator is
defined in general as someone who can express ideas clearly to an “ordinary”
audience (DI, I.85).
What is most interesting about the De oratore is the way it addresses two
important topics: the cultural value of rhetoric, and the connection between
rhetoric, philosophy, and other forms of knowledge. Cicero maintains that
the art of rhetoric has flourished especially in states which have enjoyed
freedom, peace, and tranquility. Moreover, this art above all others distinguishes men from animals; it is this art which has brought unity and
civilization to humanity.7 Cicero also takes issue with Plato’s criticism of
rhetoric. Where Plato sees rhetoric as focused on style and divorced from
philosophy, Cicero insists that the good rhetorician must speak on the basis of
knowledge and understanding of his subject, and that philosophy and
rhetoric are complementary.
Quintilian
It is reputed that Cicero’s last words were “With me dies the republic!”
Cicero’s rhetorical successors saw the death of the Roman republic and the
imposition of imperial rule, where one man, the emperor, had absolute
power. There was a consequent decrease in personal and political freedom,
The Traditions of Rhetoric
29
including the ability to speak freely. This led to a general decline of rhetoric in
the first century AD in Rome. Nonetheless, this era produced in Quintilian a
figure whose Institutio oratoria was a major contribution to rhetorical and
educational theory as well as to literary criticism; its influence has been vast,
second only to Cicero’s in the Renaissance, and reaching into our own
educational systems.
In the Institutio Quintilian offers a program for the education of an ideal
orator from childhood. He stresses what is perhaps the most original theme of
his text, the dependence of true oratory on moral goodness: “the perfect
orator . . . cannot exist unless he is above all a good man.”8 Like Cicero,
Quintilian opposes Plato’s separation of rhetoric and philosophy.
Quintilian’s integration of these activities is based on morality: the orator
cannot leave the principles of moral conduct to the philosophers because he is
actively involved as a citizen in the various enterprises of the state, civil, legal,
judicial, private, and public. Like Cicero, then, Quintilian views wisdom and
eloquence as naturally and necessarily accompanying each other.
Quintilian urges that once a child has learned how to read and write, he
must next learn grammar (IO, I.ii.31). He defines the province of grammar as
comprising two parts, the art of speaking correctly and the interpretation of
literature. Quintilian suggests that the passages chosen for reading should
portray moral goodness. In analyzing poetry, the student must be taught to
read closely, to specify the parts of speech, the feet and meter, to identify the
correct usage of words, to know the various senses of a given word, to
recognize all kinds of tropes, figures of speech, and figures of thought, to be
acquainted with relevant historical facts, and, above all, to understand the
merit in the way the whole work is organized (IO, I.viii.5–18). In general, the
stories told by poets should be used to increase students’ knowledge rather
than simply treated as models of eloquence (IO, I.ix.2–6).
Quintilian’s foremost point is that the teacher of rhetoric, receiving boys at
an impressionable age, should be of exemplary morality:
Let him [the teacher] adopt, then, above all things, the feelings of a parent
toward his pupils . . . Let him neither have vices in himself, nor tolerate them in
others. Let his austerity not be stern, nor his affability too easy, lest dislike arise
from the one, or contempt from the other . . . Let him be plain in his mode of
teaching, and patient of labor . . . Let him reply readily to those who put
questions to him, and question of his own accord those who do not . . . In
amending what requires correction, let him not be harsh, and, least of all, not
reproachful . . . Let him speak much every day himself, for the edification of his
pupils. (IO, II.ii.4–8)
The best teachers, adds Quintilian, will be people of good sense who know
how to adapt their teaching to the standards of their pupils. Above all, their
command of their learning will enable them to achieve in their teaching the
30
Classical Literary Criticism and Rhetoric
virtue of clarity, which is “the chief virtue of eloquence.” The less able a
teacher is, the more obscure and pretentious he will be (IO, II.iii.2–9). He
must be practical, adaptable, kind, moderate, and maintain a Stoic sense of
his duty to his country. In general, it can be seen that Quintilian’s major
contribution to the fields of rhetorical and educational theory lies in his
insistence that all aspects of these fields are underlain by morality.
The Subsequent History of Rhetoric: An Overview
After the civil war in which Octavius defeated Antony at the battle of Actium,
Octavius became emperor of the entire Roman world in 27 BC and ruled until
AD 14. The Republic had permanently collapsed and Rome was ruled by
emperors until its fall in AD 410. In this period, the freedom to speak – and the
art of rhetoric – was profoundly constrained: speakers focused on style and
delivery and rhetorical ornamentation rather than substance. The period is
generally referred to as the Second Sophistic (27 BC–AD 410), named after a
new generation of sophists who advocated a return to the language and style
of classical Athens. The Second Sophistic produced no major rhetorical
treatises, with the exception of Longinus’ On the Sublime. Given that rhetoric
had effectively been denuded of its social and political functions, it henceforth
lost its public role, focusing increasingly on imitation of earlier models and
the formalization of rules for literary composition, which was seen through
the Middle Ages as part of the province of rhetoric.
By the end of the fourth century, Christianity had risen to a predominant
status in the Roman Empire. This process had been initiated by a series of
edicts issued by Emperor Constantine in AD 313 allowing Christianity to be
tolerated; Emperor Theodosius I had issued a decree in 380 making
Christianity the official religion of the Empire. A reaction set in against
the use of Classical pagan methods and mythology in education. Augustine
produced his De doctrina christiana in 426, in which he argued for the
importance of rhetoric as an instrument of explaining and conveying the
Christian message. Eventually, the Church adopted Cicero’s rhetoric as a
guide for preachers. Augustine thus provides a link between classical and
medieval rhetoric.
In the Middle Ages rhetoric was one part of the educational “trivium,” the
other two components being grammar and logic. Rhetoric was concerned
primarily with the means of persuasion of an audience, whereas the focus of
grammar was on the rules of linguistic correctness, and that of logic on valid
argumentation. The boundaries between poetics and rhetoric were somewhat
blurred. In general, rhetoric in the Middle Ages took second place to the
development of logic, especially in the hands of the scholastic theologians
such as Thomas Aquinas.
The Traditions of Rhetoric
31
In the Renaissance, which returned to classical sources, rhetoric enjoyed a
revived centrality in the educational curriculum. The Renaissance humanists
drew profusely on the teachings of Cicero9 as well as Quintilian’s newly
recovered treatise, in their emphasis on content and the strategies of invention
(“RP,” 1048–1049). As the Renaissance progressed, however, rhetoric – itself
reduced to style – was subsumed under poetics, inspired partly by the
rediscovery of Aristotle’s Poetics: the rhetorical concern with audience,
modes of argumentation, and persuasion were all lost. Rhetoric as such was
dead. Poetic invention of course retained its importance but it was not, as in
traditional rhetoric, oriented primarily toward an audience. Rather, it became a private, meditative act, the composition of a solitary mind in isolation.
The figures of speech were less directed toward the passions of an audience;
composition was viewed more as a form of self-expression, an indication of
the author’s psyche, and began to be examined by the new discipline of
psychology (“RP,” 1049).
This mode of thinking achieved a new intensity in Romanticism, which
offered a new account of poetic creation on the basis of the faculty of
imagination. The Romantics tended to draw upon Plato and Longinus,
attacking the remnants of Aristotelian poetics and rhetoric that infused
neoclassical poetics. The profusion of written culture encouraged the theory
and practice of invention and creativity as an isolated and solitary process.
After the Renaissance, the rise of bourgeois economy and modes of thought in
the late eighteenth and nineteenth centuries contributed to the disintegration
of rhetoric in several ways, firstly through increasing specialization, whereby
each area of inquiry aspired to a relative autonomy, possessing not only its
own unique content but its own methods. Moreover, the predominance of
rationalist, empirical, and experimental outlooks promoted a more straightforward and literal use of language, divesting language of its allegorical
potential as so richly realized in medieval texts. By the end of the nineteenth
century and indeed into present times, “rhetoric” became a derogatory term,
signifying emptiness of content, bombast, and superfluous ornamentation.
Nonetheless, as indicated below, rhetoric has experienced some significant
revivals during the twentieth century.
The Legacy of Rhetoric
In the Western world, rhetoric has played a central role in politics and law; for
two millennia rhetoric has been at the center of the educational system in
Europe, and its influence in education is still visible in its continued domination of the teaching of composition. Approaches to teaching composition
have begun to feel the reverberations of a rhetorical revival in literary studies.
Rhetoric has recently exercised a renewed impact on cultural and critical
32
Classical Literary Criticism and Rhetoric
theory, spanning numerous disciplines, especially those such as speech act
theory which are directly concerned with the nature of communication. The
influence of rhetoric on literary criticism and theory extends much further
than the stylistic analysis of figures of speech. A rhetorical approach to a text
must concern itself not only with the author’s intentions but with all the
features implicated in the text as a persuasive use of language: the structure of
the text as a means of communication, the nature and response of the
audience or reader, the text’s relation to other discourses, and the social and
political contexts of the interaction between author, text, and reader, as well
as a historicist concern with the differences between a modern reception of the
text and its original performative conditions. In short, a rhetorical approach
views a literary text not as an isolated act (merely recording, for example, the
private thoughts of an author) but as a performance in a social context.
In this broad sense, rhetoric has been an integral element in many
approaches to literature and philosophy, ranging from Marxist and feminist
perspectives through hermeneutic to reception theories. A study of the nature
of language has been central to the project of much formalism, including the
New Criticism. But as with earlier formalisms, this modern formalism –
expressed partly in manifesto slogans such as “a poem should not mean, but
be” – tended to undermine a rhetorical approach to literature as an effective
form of communication, and to view the literary text as an isolated verbal
structure. One of the figures associated with New Critical tendencies, I. A.
Richards, produced a book, Philosophy of Rhetoric (1936), in which he made
a distinction, deriving partly from John Locke, between poetry, which draws
on the multiple meanings of words, rhetoric, designed to persuade, and
expository language in which the meaning of each word should be clear and
the language used neutral or impartial. Given the impossibility of avoiding
polysemy or multiple meaning, Richards suggests that it is the task of rhetoric
to examine the semantic richness of language.
To a large extent, Richards’ insights gave way before the predominance of
New Critical and other formalisms during the 1940s. A subsequent revival of
rhetoric was heralded by Kenneth Burke’s reaction against these various
modern formalisms and his call for the renewal of a rhetorical approach to
literary form and interpretation. Writers such as T. S. Eliot and Wayne Booth
tended to focus on the author’s relation to the text, as in Eliot’s essay “The
Three Voices of Poetry”; Northrop Frye’s Anatomy of Criticism (1957) also
ultimately rejected any sharp distinction between a literary or rhetorical use
of language that made use of figures and tropes, and a philosophical and
expository use of language. Reception and reader-response theorists, including Iser, Holland, and Fish, have focused on the role and situation of the
reader; other critics, such as Burke, Jakobson, Lacan, Derrida, and Paul de
Man, resurrected the idea of certain foundational rhetorical tropes such as
irony, metaphor, and metonymy, some arguing that these tropes are integral
The Traditions of Rhetoric
33
to language and the process of thought. Linguists and structuralists such as
Todorov, Genette, and Barthes have often modified rhetorical classifications
of tropes. A rhetorical perspective is explicitly acknowledged in the so-called
Law and Literature movement: the narrative of a prosecution or defense in a
courtroom will employ many literary and rhetorical strategies. But the
influence is not one-sided: literary and other texts can themselves be viewed
in the light of rhetorical strategies designed for the courtroom. The entire
arsenal of “literary” figures, in fact, was devised by rhetoricians. In this broad
sense, then, rhetoric might be viewed as an inevitable component of all kinds
of discourse.
This rhetorical heritage in Western literature and education has been
countered by a long tradition of philosophy which has seen itself as devoted
to the rational pursuit of truth, the definition of the good life, and happiness; in
short, the mainstream Western philosophical tradition has tended to reject
rhetorical considerations of style, passion, and effect on audience, in favor of
an emphasis on content. This tradition was effectively inaugurated by Plato; it
runs through medieval logic and theology, as well as disputes in the Middle
Ages concerning the status of logic, grammar, and rhetoric in the educational
trivium; it continues through Renaissance attempts to stress the formal
elements of poetry as well as through Ramist logic in the seventeenth century
into the empiricist and rationalist philosophy of the Enlightenment, as expressed in Locke’s insistence that philosophical language be free of figures and
tropes; it survives into the twentieth century in the analytic philosophy of G. E.
Moore and Bertrand Russell, as well as logical positivism, speech act theory,
and various branches of semiology. Interestingly, whereas the philosophical
disparagement of rhetoric has usually aligned the latter with poetry, sometimes the advocates of poetry have themselves opposed the alleged rigidity and
prescriptiveness of rhetoric, as in Romanticism, late nineteenth-century symbolism, and modern formalism. These struggles continue into the present day
in conflicts between rhetoric and more conventional analytic and empirical
modes of philosophizing. As against the latter, rhetoric holds that truth
cannot be abstracted from all practical and political concerns but is intrinsically tied to prevailing political structures and an appeal to consensus.
Notes
1. George A. Kennedy, A New History of Classical Rhetoric (Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1994), p. 34.
2. Plato, Gorgias, trans. Robin Waterfield (New York and Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 1994), 455a.
3. Aristotle, The Art of Rhetoric, trans. H. C. Lawson-Tancred (Harmondsworth:
Penguin, 1991), 1355a. Hereafter cited as Rhet.
34
Classical Literary Criticism and Rhetoric
4. George A. Kennedy, ed., The Cambridge History of Literary Criticism: Volume I:
Classical Criticism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), p. 198.
Rawson (1997); V.V: Volume V: Romanticism, ed. Marshall Brown (2000).
5. [Cicero] Ad C. Herennium: De ratione dicendi (Rhetorica ad Herennium), trans.
Harry Caplan (Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard University Press/
Heinemann, 1968), I.ii.2. Hereafter cited as RH.
6. Marcus Tullius Cicero, De inventione; De optimo genere oratorum; Topica, trans.
H. M. Hubbell, Loeb Classical Library (Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard
University Press/Heinemann, 1968), I.5. Hereafter cited as DI.
7. Cicero, De oratore, in Cicero on Oratory and Orators, trans. J. S. Watson
(Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1970), I.viii.
8. Quintilian: On the Teaching of Speaking and Writing: Translations from Books
One, Two, and Ten of the Institutio oratoria, ed. James J. Murphy (Carbondale:
Southern Illinois University Press, 1987), p. 6. Hereafter cited as IO.
9. Some of the insights in this section are indebted to the extremely learned article,
“Rhetoric and Poetry,” by Thomas O. Sloane in The New Princeton Encyclopedia
of Poetry and Poetics, ed. Alex Preminger and T. V. F. Brogan (Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1993). Hereafter cited as “RP.”
Chapter 3
Greek and Latin Criticism
During the Roman Empire
Horace (65–8 BC)
The influence of Horace’s Ars poetica has been vast, exceeding the influence
of Plato, and in many periods, even that of Aristotle. Horace (Quintus
Horatius Flaccus) is known primarily as a poet, a composer of odes, satires,
and epistles. In the realm of literary criticism, he has conventionally been
associated with the notions that “a poem is like a painting,” that poetry
should “teach and delight,” as well as the idea that poetry is a craft which
requires labor. Horace’s text takes the form of an informal letter from an
established poet giving advice to the would-be poets of the wealthy Piso
family in Rome. Though the Ars poetica is technically a work of literary
critical and rhetorical theory, it is itself written as a poem, a mode that was
imitated by several men of letters, including the medieval writer Geoffrey de
Vinsauf, the Renaissance writer Pierre de Ronsard, the neoclassical poets
Nicolas Boileau-Despreaux and Alexander Pope, the Romantic poet Lord
Byron, and twentieth-century poets such as Wallace Stevens. Horace was
introduced by the poet Vergil to Gaius Maecenas, an extremely wealthy
patron of the arts. Eventually, Horace enjoyed the patronage of the emperor
Augustus himself.
Horace’s text, though casual in tone, can be seen as focused on the
following issues: (1) the relation of a writer to his work, his knowledge of
tradition, and his own ability; (2) the moral and social functions of poetry,
such as establishing a repository of conventional wisdom, providing moral
examples through characterization, and promoting civic virtue and sensibility, as well as affording pleasure; (3) the contribution of an audience to the
composition of poetry, viewed both as an art and as a commodity; (4) an
awareness of literary history and historical change in language and genre.
These are the largely conventional themes that preoccupy Horace’s text,
whose principles claim to be drawn from practical experience rather than
theory.
Literary Criticism from Plato to the Present: An Introduction
© 2011 M. A. R. Habib. ISBN: 978-1-405-16034-6
M. A. R. Habib
36
Classical Literary Criticism and Rhetoric
Among Horace’s most salient views is his insistence on the moral function
of literature. In drama, for example, the depiction of good character is
indispensable. This function, he says, should be effected partly by the
chorus.1 He also stresses the then standard rhetorical principle of
“decorum,” which calls for a “proper” relationship between form and
content, expression and thought, style and subject matter, diction and
character (AP, 312–315). As against Plato, who had regarded the poet as
necessarily distorting reality by offering a mere imitation of it, Horace insists
that the “principal fountainhead of writing correctly is wisdom” (AP, 309)
and he sees poetry as a repository of social and religious wisdom (AP,
396–407). In the depiction of character, the poet must be aware of the various
characteristics of men from childhood, youth, manhood to old age (this
repertoire of the ages of man is taken from rhetoric) (AP, 158–174). Hence,
the poet’s work must be based on knowledge; not bookish knowledge but
a detailed empirical knowledge derived from acute observation of actual life.
Horace demands a high degree of realism from the poet, as expressed in this
statement: “My instruction would be to examine the model of human life
and manners as an informed copyist and to elicit from it a speech that lives”
(AP, 317–318).
In a famous statement, Horace remarks that
a poet has matched every demand if he mingles the useful with the pleasant
[miscuit utile dulci], by charming and, not less, advising the reader; that is
a book that earns money for the Sosii [publishers]; a book that crosses the
sea and, making its writer known, forecasts a long life for him. (AP,
342–346)
Horace’s call for literature to be socially useful as well as pleasing was vastly
influential; as was his insistence that a poem not only charm the reader but
also offer moral advice. Horace stresses the amount of labor required for
composing good poetry. Part of this labor is seeking out valid criticism of
one’s work from sincere and qualified people. Horace admonishes the poet to
store his work away for nine years. He warns that, once a poem is published,
the words used by the poet will forever become public property, part of a
language inescapably social: “it will be permissible to destroy what you have
not published: the voice once sent forth cannot return” [nescit vox missa
reverti] (AP, 386–390). Horace’s argument seems strikingly modern in
rejecting an author’s intention as the sole determinant or ultimate criterion
of a poem’s meaning. It may, indeed, be his combination of classical and
newer attitudes, as well as his ability to give striking poetic and epigrammatic
expression to a body of accumulated wisdom or “common sense,” the critic
speaking with the authority of a poet, that ensured the classic status of
Horace’s text.
Greek and Latin Criticism During the Roman Empire
Longinus (First Century
37
AD)
After the period of the early Roman Empire, two broad intellectual currents
emerged during the first four centuries. The first of these was known as the
Second Sophistic (27 BC–AD 410), named after a new generation of sophists
and rhetoricians who took for their model the classical language and style
of Attic Greece. The second was the philosophy of Neo-Platonism, whose
prime exponent Plotinus will be considered in the next section. The major
rhetorical treatise of this period was written in Greek: entitled peri hupsous
or On the Sublime, it is conventionally attributed to “Longinus,” and dates
from the first or second century AD. It was the most influential rhetorical
text through much of the period of the Second Sophistic, and has subsequently exerted a pronounced influence on literary criticism since the
seventeenth century, somewhat against the grain of the classical heritage
derived from Aristotle and Horace. It has fascinated critics of the modern
period on account of its treatment of the sublime as a quality of the soul or
spirit rather than as a matter of mere technique. In the later classical period
and the Middle Ages, the treatise appeared to be little known. Initially
published during the Renaissance by Robotelli in 1554, it was subsequently
translated into Latin in 1572 and then into English by John Hall in 1652.
In modern times the concept of the sublime owed its resurgence to a
translation in 1674 by Nicolas Boileau, the most important figure of
French neoclassicism. The sublime became an important element in the
broad Romantic reaction in Europe against neoclassicism as well as in the
newly rising domain of aesthetics in the work of thinkers such as Immanuel
Kant.
Longinus offers an initial definition, stating that the sublime consists “in a
consummate excellence and distinction of language . . . the effect of genius is
not to persuade the audience but rather to transport them out of themselves.”
He adds that “what inspires wonder casts a spell upon us and is always
superior to what is merely convincing and pleasing.”2 We can control our
reasoning but the sublime exerts a power which we cannot resist (I.4).
Longinus distinguishes dramatically between other compositional skills and
the sublime. Inventive skill and appropriate use of facts, for example, are
expressed through an entire composition. But the sublime, he says, appears
like a bolt of lightning, scattering everything before it and revealing the power
of the speaker “at a single stroke” (I.4).
Longinus’ subsequent definition of the sublime appeals to experience in
a manner later echoed by Arnold, Leavis, and others. The true sublime will
produce a lasting and repeated effect on “a man of sense, well-versed in
literature” (VII.1–3). As with Arnold and Leavis, Longinus’ view of greatness
in literature appears to be an affective one: we judge it by its emotional effects
38
Classical Literary Criticism and Rhetoric
on the reader or listener (the Latin affectus as a noun means “disposition”
or “state,” and as a verb, “affected by”). Longinus broadens his definition
to say that the “truly beautiful and sublime . . . pleases all people at all
times” (VII.4).
According to Longinus, there are five “genuine sources” of the sublime:
(1) the command of “full-blooded” or robust ideas (sometimes expressed by
translators as “grandeur of thought”); (2) the inspiration of “vehement
emotion”; (3) the proper construction of figures – both figures of thought
and figures of speech; (4) nobility of phrase, which includes diction and the
use of metaphor; (5) the general effect of dignity and elevation which
embraces the previous four elements. More fundamental than anything else
in creating sublimity is the arrangement of the various elements of a passage
into a unified, single system. Longinus advocates an artistic organicism, using
an analogy which has subsequently served countless writers: just as with the
members of the human body, so it is with the elements of sublimity: “None
of the members has any value by itself apart from the others, yet one with
another they all constitute a perfect organism”(XL.1).
Longinus’ examples of sublimity here are intended to express what might
be viewed as his fundamental position: citing Homer, he reflects that “a great
style is the natural outcome of weighty thoughts, and sublime sayings
naturally fall to men of spirit” (IX.1–3). Those passages in Homer are sublime
“which represent the divine nature in its true attributes, pure, majestic, and
unique” (IX.8). Interestingly, Longinus also cites early passages from the Old
Testament (“Let there be light. . .”) as expressing “a worthy conception of
divine power” (IX.9). In these passages Longinus seems to find sublimity in
the expression of profound and appropriate religious sentiment which displays a sense of decorum and which justly marks the relation of divine and
human. Great writers, then, achieve sublimity through their grandeur of
thought, by expressing a vision of the universe that is morally and theologically elevated.
Indeed, in a famous passage, Longinus states that “Nature” has distinguished us over other creatures, and has
from the first breathed into our hearts an unconquerable passion for whatever is
great and more divine than ourselves. Thus within the scope of human enterprise
there lie such powers of contemplation and thought that even the whole universe
cannot satisfy them, but our ideas often pass beyond the limits that enring us.
(XXXV.2–3)
Hence, the sublime embodies the highest purpose of humankind. This
purpose, far from according with a classical Aristotelian recognition of our
finitude and proper place in the cosmic scheme, is to strive beyond our own
human nature toward the divine, on the wings of “unconquerable passion.”
Greek and Latin Criticism During the Roman Empire
39
Longinus subsequently says that sublimity lifts men “near the mighty mind of
God” (XXXVI.1).
The final surviving part of the manuscript is perhaps the most revealing of
Longinus’ world view. He laments that truly great or sublime literature is no
longer being produced because of the “love of money, that insatiable sickness
from which we all now suffer, and the love of pleasure,” both of which
“enslave us.” He goes on to say that “men no longer then look upwards . . .
they value that part of them which is mortal and consumes away, and neglect
the development of their immortal souls.” Longinus’ account is quite clear in
its system of priorities: the soul over the body, the immortal, permanent and
selfless over the perishable, transient, and self-interested. The world view is
Stoic and Platonic – even Neo-Platonic – but also somewhat Christian in its
emphasis. The parallels between Longinus’ world view and those of the
Romantics are clear. Moreover, if we view Longinus’ influence as moving in a
broadly “aesthetic”direction toward notions of relative artistic autonomy,
we can see that the debate between classicism and Romanticism was played
out not only from the eighteenth through the twentieth centuries but in the
Hellenistic world itself and in the early Roman Empire. Especially influential
was Longinus’ recognition of the power of language – founded on grandeur
of thought and the skillful use of figures – to attain sublimity, thereby
transforming our perception of the world.
Neo-Platonism
The philosophy of Neo-Platonism was predominant during the third and
fourth centuries of the Christian era. It derived some inspiration from the
doctrines of Philo Judaeus and was developed systematically by Plotinus,
the Syrian philosopher Porphyry, and Proclus. The Neo-Platonists held the
classical authors in the highest esteem, and attempted to reconcile discrepancies between various classical authors such as Plato and Aristotle, as
well as between philosophy and poetry; they attempted in particular to
reconcile Plato’s theories of poetry with the poetic practice of Homer and
other poets. Their fundamental method of achieving this was through
allegorical and symbolic modes of interpretation, opening the way for
Christian medieval conceptions of allegory which viewed the physical
world as inherently symbolic of a higher world. It was a Latin writer,
Macrobius, who transmitted these essentially Greek developments in the art
of interpretation to the Middle Ages. From a literary critical perspective, the
great achievement of the Neo-Platonists was to reformulate Plato’s metaphysical framework so as to rehabilitate and accommodate the arts. The
three major exponents to be considered here are Plotinus, Macrobius, and
Boethius.
40
Classical Literary Criticism and Rhetoric
Plotinus (AD 204/5–270)
The third-century philosopher Plotinus has been variously called the greatest
metaphysician of antiquity, the founder of Neo-Platonism, and the most
profound single influence on Christian thought. Neo-Platonism takes from
Plato, but also modifies, the idea that ultimate reality subsists in a transcendent and spiritual realm, from which the physical world takes its existence
and meaning. After Plotinus’ death, his teaching was continued by his
disciples Porphyry and Iamblichus; its last great expression as an independent
philosophy was in the work of Proclus (411–485), after which it was
integrated into Christian thought.3 Plotinus’ vast influence extends from
Augustine, Macrobius, Boethius, and medieval Christian Platonism through
Italian Renaissance humanism, the seventeenth-century Cambridge Platonists, and the Romantic poets to modern thinkers and critics such as William
James, Henri Bergson, A. N. Whitehead, and Harold Bloom.
While Plotinus basically accepts Plato’s division of the world into a higher
intellectual realm of eternal Forms and a lower sensible world of time and
change, what distinguishes his scheme from Plato’s is his elaboration of a more
refined hierarchy of levels of reality. His scheme can be represented as follows:
The One
Embodies: Unity/Truth/Origin/Good
Is Source of Essence and Existence
Eternal
Act/Utterance
Divine Mind: Presides Over
Intellectual Realm
“There”
Act/Utterance
Inner
All-Soul/World-Soul/Great Soul
Outer (Nature-Principle)
World of Matter, Sense, Time
“Here”
Soul
Humans
Body
According to Plotinus, all the phases of existence emanate from the
divinity; the goal of all things is ultimately to return to the divine. Reality
is basically divided into an eternal spiritual and intellectual realm (which
consists of the One, the Intellectual Realm and the All-Soul), and a physical
realm of matter, sense, space, and time. Human beings belong to both of these
worlds: their souls belong to the higher realm of All-Soul, while their bodies
occupy the spatial and temporal world of matter, sense, and extension. The
task of philosophy is to facilitate the soul’s transcendence of the physical
realm, to rise to intellectual intuition and ultimately to attain an ecstatic and
mystical union with the One.
Greek and Latin Criticism During the Roman Empire
41
In Plotinus’ system, the divinity itself is a hierarchical triad expressed in
three principles or “hypostases”: the One, the Divine Mind or Intellect, and
the All-Soul. The One can also be termed the Absolute, the Good, or the
Father. From this One emanates the Divine Mind which presides over
the realm of Divine Thought or Intellection (this intellectual realm is equivalent to Plato’s Ideas or Forms). The intellectual forms in this realm are
the archetypes of all that exists in the lower, sensible sphere. Moreover, the
Divine Intelligence is an expression of the One which is unknowable by
mere intellect or reason. From the Divine Mind emanates the All-Soul, or Soul
of all things. The All-Soul has three phases: the intellective soul, which
contemplates the Divine Thought of the intellectual realm; the Reasoning
Soul, which generates the sensible universe on the model of the archetypes in
the intellectual realm; and the Unreasoning Soul, which is the principle of
animal life. Hence the All-Soul forms and orders the physical world. Unlike
Plato, Plotinus does not view these relationships as imitation; rather each
phase is an “emanation” from the preceding phase, retaining the latter’s
archetypal imprint as a goal to which it must return on its path toward its
ultimate reunion with the One.
Plotinus’ views of art and beauty must be understood in the context of
his scheme as outlined above. In his essay “On the Intellectual Beauty,” he
establishes that beauty is ideal: in other words, it belongs essentially to
the realm of ideas, rather than the realm of sensible, physical objects. And
as an idea it is more beautiful in its pure form than when it is mingled
with matter. Indeed, it is only as an idea that beauty can enter the
mind. Hence, beauty is not in the concrete object but in “soul or mind”
(Enneads, V.viii.2).
Plotinus explains the origin of beauty with reference to his cosmological
hierarchy. The Nature, he says, which creates beautiful things must itself be
produced by a “far earlier beauty.” The “Nature-Principle” (which lies below
the level of the All-Soul) contains “an Ideal archetype of the beauty that is
found in material forms.” But this archetype itself has its source in a still more
beautiful archetype in Soul. And this archetype, in turn, has its source in the
Intellectual-Principle, in the realm of pure intellectual Forms. Plotinus’ term
for this intellectual realm is “There.” He designates the sensible world as
“Here” (Enneads, V.viii.3). The world of “There” or the intellectual realm is
a world of complete unity, where all the beings merge into an infinite divine
identity. Moreover, the wisdom of “There” is “not a wisdom built up by
reasonings but complete from the beginning.” It is a unity, complete, selfenclosed, and acting as the measure of all subsequent wisdom. Plotinus calls
this “wisdom in unity” (Enneads, V.viii.4, 6).
In the world of “Here,” the sensible world, things are very different.
Everything is “partial,” including our knowledge, which exists as “a mass
of theorems and an accumulation of propositions” (Enneads, V.viii.4). The
kind of wisdom we possess is only an image of the original “wisdom in unity,”
42
Classical Literary Criticism and Rhetoric
an image that reproduces the original in discursive form, in language, using
reasoning (Enneads, V.viii.6). The one exception to this limitation lies in art:
the artist goes back to “that wisdom in Nature,” enjoying a more direct
intuitive access into that earlier wisdom than the philosopher or scientist
(Enneads, V.viii.5). Earthly beauty, then, derives from the perfect beauty of
the divine world. Whereas Plato sees poetry as appealing to man’s lower
nature, his desires and passions, Plotinus sees in art a means of access to the
divine world, based on art’s reproduction of the beauty of that world, a
beauty discernible not to the senses and passions but to the intellect. Where
Plato thought of art as imitating what was already an imitation (of eternal
Forms), Plotinus sees art as directly imitating the Forms themselves, with a
directness inaccessible to the discursive reasoning of philosophy.
Plotinus ends his treatise with what is perhaps one of the most beautiful and
insightful passages ever composed by a philosopher. The perception of beauty
is not a passive act, of gazing upon a beautiful object that is external to the
spectator. If our souls are “penetrated by this beauty,” we cannot remain
mere gazers, mere spectators: “one must bring the vision within and see no
longer in that mode of separation but as we know ourselves” (Enneads,
V.viii.10). Plotinus offers an account of mystical union with God. If we
submit ourselves to the vision of God, we will lose our own self, and be unable
to see our own image; possessed by God, we will see our own image “lifted to a
better beauty”; progressing further, we will “sink into a perfect self-identity,”
forming “a multiple unity with the God silently present” (Enneads, V.viii.11).
Hence the first stage of this ascent to union with God is separation, a state in
which we are aware of self; but if we turn away from sense and desire, we
become “one in the Divine”: instead of remaining in the mode of separation,
of mere spectator, we ourselves become “the seen,” the object of our own
vision or self-knowledge. So, truly to know beauty is to become it: we must
put behind us reliance on sense or sight, which “deals with the external.”
Plotinus states that we are “most completely aware of ourselves when we are
most completely identified with the object of our knowledge” (Enneads,
V.viii.11). In these passages, Plotinus anticipates not only numerous forms
of mysticism, both Christian and Islamic, but also the thought of Kant and
Hegel who regard all consciousness as self-consciousness. For Plotinus,
knowledge – of beauty or anything else – is a form of interaction, a mode
of unity rather than separation, a manner of internalizing the object and being
transformed by it, a process of mutual adaptation of self and object, losing the
one in the other, in a merged identity.
Macrobius (b. ca. 360)
Another influential Neo-Platonic vision and perspective toward literature is
contained in two texts by Macrobius that were widely influential in the
Greek and Latin Criticism During the Roman Empire
43
Middle Ages, the Saturnalia (ca. 395) and Commentary on the Dream of
Scipio (ca. 400). The latter came to be regarded for many centuries as an
authoritative account of the significance of dreams. Much later, Freud was
rightly to remark that ancient cultures attached various kinds of serious
significance to dreams whereas modern science had relegated them to the
realm of superstition.
Macrobius’ Commentary takes as its starting point Cicero’s work
De republica (the Republic). The last book of this treatise narrates a dream
of Scipio Africanus the Younger, a Roman general, in which he is visited by his
grandfather Scipio Africanus the Elder, the famous general who defeated the
Carthaginian leader Hannibal. Macrobius’ text, while ostensibly analyzing
Scipio’s dream, engages far broader issues. Its explanation of the NeoPlatonic scheme of reality and knowledge was influential through the Middle
Ages; it considers the connections between literary and philosophical language, between figurative or allegorical uses of language and their role in
providing an avenue to the truths of the higher realm; finally, it provides a
systematic account of the meaning of dreams.
Scipio’s dream in Cicero’s text offers a poignant summary of a medieval
cosmology that was influential for many centuries:
These are the nine circles, or rather spheres, by which the whole is joined.
One of them, the outermost, is that of heaven; it contains all the rest, and is
itself the supreme God, holding and embracing within itself all the other
spheres; in it are fixed the eternal revolving courses of the stars. Beneath it
are seven other spheres which revolve in the opposite direction to that of
heaven. One of these globes is that light which on earth is called Saturn’s.
Next comes the star called Jupiter’s, which brings fortune and health to
mankind. Beneath it is that star, red and terrible to the dwellings of man,
which you assign to Mars. Below it and almost midway of the distance is the
Sun, the lord, chief, and ruler of the other lights, the mind and guiding
principle of the universe, of such magnitude that he reveals and fills all things
with his light. He is accompanied by his companions, as it were – Venus and
Mercury in their orbits, and in the lowest sphere revolves the Moon, set on
fire by the rays of the Sun. But below the Moon there is nothing except what
is mortal and doomed to decay, save only the souls given to the human race
by the bounty of the gods, while above the Moon all things are eternal. For
the ninth and central sphere, which is the earth, is immovable and the lowest
of all, and toward it all ponderable bodies are drawn by their own natural
tendency downward.4
This vision was highly influential in the Middle Ages, underlying the widespread notion that occurrences in the world have not only a literal significance
in earthly terms, but also an even greater significance that reverberates
through the higher realms.
44
Classical Literary Criticism and Rhetoric
Boethius (ca. 480–524)
The Roman philosopher Boethius had a seminal impact on medieval thinking,
especially in the field of logic. He translated the four logical treatises
comprising Aristotle’s Organon, and also translated and commented on
Porphyry’s Introduction to the Categories of Aristotle. He composed five
essays on logic. Also of vast influence was The Consolation of Philosophy
(524), where Boethius places his own life within the larger context of
questions about God’s providence, the injustice of the world, human free
will and the order and purpose of the world. He expresses, through a
character who personifies philosophy, the following poem which was widely
influential through the Middle Ages:
Oh God, Maker of heaven and earth, Who govern the world with eternal reason,
at your command time passes from the beginning. You place all things in
motion, though You are yourself without change. No external causes impelled
you to make this work from chaotic matter. Rather it was the form of the highest
good, existing within You without envy, which caused you to fashion all things
according to the eternal exemplar. You who are most beautiful produce the
beautiful world from your divine mind and, forming it in your image, You order
the perfect parts in a perfect whole.
You bind the elements in harmony so that cold and heat, dry and wet are
joined, and the purer fire does not fly up through the air, nor the earth sink
beneath the weight of water.
You release the world-soul throughout the harmonious parts of the universe
as your surrogate, threefold in its operations, to give motion to all things. . .
. . . The sight of Thee is beginning and end; one guide, leader, path, and goal.5
The characteristic medieval notions expressed here include: divine reason
ruling the world; God as the “unmoved Mover”; the intrinsic beauty of the
created world; the relation of the four elements; the Neo-Platonic notion of
the World-Soul as intermediary between God and material things; and the
circle of beginning and end, whereby God is not only the source but the end
and goal of all created things. This vision remained deeply ingrained within
the medieval psyche for many centuries.
Notes
1. Horace, The Art of Poetry, trans. Burton Raffel (Albany, NY: State University
of New York Press, 1974), pp. 196–201. Hereafter cited as AP, using line
numbers.
Greek and Latin Criticism During the Roman Empire
45
2. Aristotle: Poetics; Longinus: On the Sublime; Demetrius: On Style, trans. Stephen
Halliwell, W. Hamilton Fyfe, Doreen C. Innes, and W. Rhys Roberts (Cambridge,
MA and London: Harvard University Press/Heinemann, 1996), I.3–4.
3. “Introduction,” in The Essence of Plotinus: Extracts from the Six Enneads and
Porphyry’s Life of Plotinus, trans. Stephen Mackenna, ed. Grace H. Turnbull
(New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1948), pp. xvi–xix. Hereafter
cited as Enneads.
4. Cicero, De re publica; De legibus, trans. Clinton Walker Keyes (Cambridge, MA
and London: Harvard University Press/Heinemann, 1966), VI.xvii.
5. Boethius, The Consolation of Philosophy, trans. Richard H. Green (New York:
Dover, 2002), 53–54.
Part II
The Medieval Era
Literary Criticism from Plato to the Present: An Introduction
© 2011 M. A. R. Habib. ISBN: 978-1-405-16034-6
M. A. R. Habib
Chapter 4
The Early Middle Ages
Historical Background
Until quite recently, the Middle Ages were perceived as an era of darkness,
ignorance, and superstition. The term “Middle Age” (medium aevum) was
devised by Italian humanist thinkers who wished to demarcate their own
period – of renaissance, rebirth, and rediscovery of classical thinkers – from
the preceding era. The Renaissance humanists’ rejection of medieval thought
was reinforced by the Protestant Reformation which associated it with
Roman Catholicism.1 While it is true that the early Middle Ages, from the
fall of Rome at the hands of Germanic tribes in the fifth century until around
AD 1000, saw a reversion to various forms of economic and intellectual
primitivism, recent scholarship has shown that much Renaissance thought
and culture was in fact a development from the medieval period, which was by
no means ignorant of the Classical Greek and Roman traditions.
A number of factors contributed to the making of the Middle Ages: the
evolving traditions of Christianity; the social and political patterns of the
Germanic tribes who overran the Roman Empire; vestiges of the Roman
administrative and legal system; the legacy of the classical world; and contact
with Islamic civilization (which lies beyond the scope of this study). The most
powerful force in the development of medieval civilization was Christianity.
Even before the fall of Rome in 410, Christianity had been increasingly
tolerated, as stipulated in a series of edicts, initiated by the emperor Constantine, from 313 onward; by 381 it was recognized as the official religion of
the Roman Empire.
Early Christianity had been heterogeneous, containing a large number of
sects with disparate beliefs and practices. The Arians and Nestorians, for
example, rejected the notion of the Trinity which was advocated by the
Athanasians. The Docetae and Basilidans rejected the factuality of Christ’s
crucifixion. The Pelagians denied the notion of original sin and espoused
human free will. In order to settle these doctrinal disputes, a number of
Literary Criticism from Plato to the Present: An Introduction
© 2011 M. A. R. Habib. ISBN: 978-1-405-16034-6
M. A. R. Habib
50
The Medieval Era
worldwide Church councils were convened, beginning with the Council of
Nicaea in 325, which condemned the views of most of these sects as heretical
and established the Athanasian view of the Trinity as orthodox Christian
doctrine. The doctrine of the Incarnation was not formally adopted until the
Council of Chalcedon in 451. These debates were shaped by such figures
as Athanasius of Alexandria (293–373), Gregory of Nyssa, St. Basil
(ca. 330–379), Gregory of Nazianzus (ca. 330–ca. 389), John Chrysostom
(ca. 347–407), Ambrose (ca. 339–397), and Augustine of Hippo (354–430).
One of the greatest Christian thinkers of this period was Jerome (ca.
347–420), who translated the Bible from its original languages into Latin
(known as the Vulgate edition). Other steps were taken to promote unity of
belief and practice: the promulgation of standard sermons, the training
of bishops, and the growth of the papacy in power and prestige into a focus
of allegiance and obedience. Having said this, Christian doctrine was never
fully formalized in the early Middle Ages, and many of the Eastern churches
adhered to unorthodox beliefs. It took further ecumenical councils until 681
for major schisms between the churches at Rome and Constantinople to be
healed.
Notwithstanding these difficulties, after the collapse of the empire it was
left to the Church to preserve unity, order, and guidance in many spheres. It
was the Church, increasingly sophisticated in its organization and increasingly dominated by the leadership of the pope in Rome, which promoted
moral values, fostered appropriate social conduct, and transmitted classical
learning. Latin remained the language of scholarship and law during the
Middle Ages. One particularly important aspect of Christianity was monasticism, with its roots in early Christian asceticism. Founded in the East by
St. Basil and in the West by St. Benedict, monasticism entailed a strict regimen
of poverty, obedience, humility, labor, and devotion. It was largely monks
who were responsible for writing books, transmitting early manuscripts and
maintaining schools, libraries, and hospitals. The monks would later develop
into the regular clergy (following a strict rule or regula), as opposed to the
secular clergy who operated in the worldly sphere (saeculum meaning
“world” or “time”).
Another force which overwhelmed the Western Roman Empire was the
Germanic tribes, who included Scandinavians, Goths, Vandals, Franks, and
Anglo-Saxons. Many of these peoples had already settled in various parts of
the Empire long before the fall of Rome. Eventually revolting against Roman
rule, the Visigoths led by Alaric sacked Rome in 410 BC. The city was taken
again by the Vandals in AD 455. The lifestyle, as well as the legal, economic,
and political structure of the Germanic peoples, was primitive in many
respects. This structure, amalgamating with the administrative legacy of the
Roman Empire, eventually developed into the system of feudalism, which
involved contractual obligations between rulers and subjects, lords and
The Early Middle Ages
51
vassals, obligations based on values such as courage, honor, loyalty, protection, and obedience. We see these values repeatedly expressed in poems such
as Beowulf, often in uneasy commerce with Christian values such as humility
and trust in divine providence. In the early Middle Ages, commerce and
industry declined, and land became increasingly concentrated in the hands of
a few, with famine and disease often widespread. The economic system was
limited largely to local trade. Ancient Roman culture gave way before a life
centered on villages, feudal estates, and monasteries. This hierarchical and
largely static way of life was sanctioned by the Church; the social order, where
each person had his place, was seen as part of the larger, divinely established,
cosmic order.
Intellectual and Theological Currents
Christianity and classicism
The intellectual currents of the early Middle Ages were driven by two broad
factors: the heritage of classical thought, and the varying relation of developing Christian theology to this heritage. The secular critics of the late Roman
period included some influential figures: Macrobius and Servius, who contributed to the prestige of Vergil and the knowledge of Neo-Platonism,
Servius also being the author of the standard grammar of this period; the
grammarian Aelius Donatus, who wrote handbooks entitled Ars minor and
Ars maior, used throughout the Middle Ages; Priscian, whose Institutio
grammatica was also widely used; and Diomedes, who produced an exhaustive account of grammatical tropes and poetic genres. Vergil was the basic
text in schools of grammar, while Cicero held a privileged place in the
teaching of rhetoric. One of the rhetoricians of the early fifth century,
Martianus Capella, was known in the Middle Ages by his authoritative
encyclopedia of the seven liberal arts. Later influential encyclopedias were
produced by Cassiodorus and Isidore of Seville who transmitted “the sum of
late antique knowledge to posterity.”2 These compendia anticipated the
eventual formalization of the liberal arts curriculum at medieval universities.
Of these developments, two were especially germane to the early Middle
Ages: Neo-Platonism (which, beginning prior to the Middle Ages, is considered in the previous chapter) and the closely related Christian tradition of
allegorical interpretation, as embodied in the work of Augustine, which will
be considered below.
In the early Middle Ages, the Church’s “other-worldly” disposition tended
to subordinate the position of literature and the arts to the more pressing
issues of salvation and preparation for the next life. In general, the widespread
instability, insecurity, and illiteracy intensified religious feeling and promoted
52
The Medieval Era
ideals of withdrawal from the world, condemning earthly life as worthless
and merely a means of passage to the next life, to eternal salvation and bliss.
As the theological content of Christianity developed, two broad approaches
to classical literature emerged. The first of these sought to distance Christianity from paganism and accordingly frowned on the pagan origins of the
arts in the cultures of Greece and Rome, while the second sought to continue
the Christian appropriation of classical rhetoric and philosophy. The former
stream of Christian thought, deriving from the third-century theologian
Tertullian (ca. 160–ca. 225) and enduring until the last patristic author Pope
Gregory the Great (540–604), laid stress on the authority of faith and
revelation over reason. Both Tertullian and Gregory renounced all secular
knowledge and viewed literature as a foolish pursuit. The ascetic dispositions
of monasticism intensified Christian anxiety concerning worldly beauty and
art: St. Jerome, St. Basil, St. Bernard, and St. Francis all turned away from the
beauty of nature as a distraction from the contemplation of things divine.
Christian thinkers such as Boethius also echoed Plato’s concern that the arts
expressed unsavory emotions and that they could seduce men from the
righteous path. There was also in the eighth and ninth centuries an
“iconoclastic controversy” concerning the portrayal of images. Christians
held that it debased their spiritual doctrines to represent them to the senses. It
was not until the Council of Nicaea in 787 that devotional images were
deemed a legitimate resource for religious instruction.
The second stream of Christian thought, from its beginnings in the letters of
St. Paul and the Gospel of St. John, through the third-century Alexandrian
theologians Clement and Origen, displayed a rationalist emphasis and attempted to reconcile ancient Greek thought with the tenets of Christianity.
Clement believed that reason was necessary for the understanding of scripture,
and that the Greek philosophers had anticipated the Christian conception of
God. Origen (ca. 185–ca. 254) was the Greek author of On First Principles, the
first systematic account of Christian theology. The most renowned biblical
scholar of the early Church, Origen formulated a vastly influential system of
allegorical interpretation, according to three levels – literal, moral, and
theological – corresponding to the composition of man as body, soul, and
spirit. This stream of thought continued through Gregory of Nazianzus,
Gregory of Nissa, John Chrysostom, and Ambrose, reaching unprecedented
heights in the work of St. Augustine, St. Bonaventura, and St. Thomas
Aquinas. These thinkers had a more accommodating view of classical learning
and literature. While poetry and history gained some acceptance, the Church
remained for a long time opposed to drama, as well as to visual art, which was
associated with idolatry. Augustine referred to stage-plays as “spectacles of
uncleanness3” whose speeches were “smoke and wind.4”
George Kennedy usefully suggests that the Christian Fathers writing prior to
the Council of Nicaea in 325 exhibited a broad agreement on certain general
The Early Middle Ages
53
principles: that a Christian must acquire literacy, which must entail some
reading of classical texts; that examples can be taken from classical works, and
read allegorically so as to accord with Christian teaching; that classical
philosophy and literature do contain certain truths; and that the Bible, being
divinely inspired, is true at a literal level, but also harbors moral and theological
levels of meaning.5 In fact, it might be argued that Christian allegory had its
origins in the need to confront classical thought, as well as in the imperative to
reconcile the Old and New Testaments. We can now consider how these
attempts toward synthesis were given a classic formulation by St. Augustine.
St. Augustine (354–430)
It is in Augustine’s work (along with that of later writers such as Aquinas and
Dante) that the profoundest synthesis of classical and Christian notions
occurred. More than any other early Christian thinker, Augustine influenced
the traditions of both Roman Catholic and Protestant thought. Chief of the
Latin Church Fathers, he was born in North Africa. After studying in
Carthage, Rome, and Milan, he was made bishop of Hippo in 395. In his
Confessions (400), Augustine described the long and arduous process of his
conversion to Christianity, a path which had included belief in Manicheism
and skepticism. He expounded his theology in City of God (412–427), where
he viewed human history as the unfolding of a divine plan. Here he was
essentially defending Christianity against those who attributed the fall of
Rome to the abandonment of the pagan gods. Augustine’s views often
accommodate those of Plato, whom he regarded as the greatest philosopher.
But he subordinated philosophy to divine revelation, urging that the task of
reason was to promote a clearer understanding of things already accepted on
faith. He affirmed the supreme importance of original sin as responsible for
man’s departure from God and the depraved state of human nature. The cause
of original sin, he affirmed, was pride, which he equated with man’s self-love
and desire for self-sufficiency, whereby man regards himself as his own light.
Augustine divided spiritual life into the “earthly city,” characterized by “selflove reaching the point of contempt for God,” and the “Heavenly city,”
which rests on “the love of God carried as far as contempt of self” (CG,
XIV.10–14). Though Augustine does not deny human free will (since it was
man’s depraved will which led to the original sin), he is often characterized as
believing in determinism since only those who belong to the heavenly city, the
elect, will attain salvation. The elect are chosen not on account of their
goodness but for unknown reasons. This deterministic doctrine, originating
in St. Paul, was later revived by Calvin. Augustine asserts that only God can
restore the natural state of goodness in which man was created. The vehicle
for man’s redemption from sin is the Incarnation; only through Christ, who is
the “mediator between God and men,” can man have access to grace.
54
The Medieval Era
In his Confessions Augustine had retrospectively regretted his own
“foolish” immersion in classical literature (Confessions, I.xiii; III.ii). He
condemned liberal studies, suggesting that only the scriptures were truly
liberating. While he sympathized with Plato’s arguments for banishing poets
and dramatists on moral grounds, his views of poetry’s connection with truth
were somewhat different. He suggests that paintings, sculptures, and plays
were necessarily false, not from any intention to be such but merely from
inability to be that which they represent. Paradoxically, the artist cannot be
true to his artistic intent unless he enacts falsehood. One of the problems of
medieval aesthetics was to reconcile earthly beauty with spiritual preoccupations. For Augustine and other medieval philosophers such as Albertus
Magnus and Bonaventura, beauty was not specifically concerned with
physical objects; rather, it implied a relationship of harmony between certain
terms, whether these were material, intellectual, or spiritual. Influenced by
Cicero, Augustine viewed the essential elements of beauty as, firstly, harmonious wholeness and, secondly, unity of parts which are ordered in due
proportion (Confessions, IV.xiii).
Augustine’s aesthetics rely on a modified Platonic framework appealing to a
higher spiritual realm to which the physical world is subordinated. As such,
art, composed of sensuous elements, was assigned a lower degree of reality
than spiritual life, far removed from God, the ultimate source of being, and the
ultimate standard of reality. The early Church, then, harbored a metaphysical
idealism descended in part from Plato, insisting that reality is spiritual and that
sense-perception and observation of the world were not reliable avenues to
truth. However, the world of matter was not rejected as unreal but was
admitted into the divine scheme of creation, occupying nonetheless a humble
position. The beauty of earthly things was viewed as an expression of their
divine origin, and rested on their unity – a unity in diversity – which imitated the
Oneness of God. This relation expressed the medieval Christian vision of the
One and the Many: it is ultimately God’s unity which confers unity and
harmony on the vast diversity of the world. The world is God’s poem which
proclaims its beauty through harmony and correct proportion (CG, XI.18).
Augustine’s strategy of adapting classical thought and literature to Christian purposes is expressed in his important work De doctrina christiana [On
Christian Doctrine] (397–426). In this text are some surprisingly modern
insights. Augustine initially distinguishes between signs and things: “every
sign is also a thing . . . but not every thing is also a sign.”6 He asserts that some
things are for use while others are for enjoyment. The only objects for pure
enjoyment are God and those which are “eternal and unchangeable” (DDC,
I.22). All other objects are for use, being merely the means whereby we arrive
at enjoyment of God (DDC, I.22). The distinction between use and enjoyment embraces the distinctions of means and end, adjective and substantive,
temporal and eternal, physical and spiritual, journey and goal. Essentially,
The Early Middle Ages
55
these distinctions are based on a broad distinction of “this-worldliness” and
“other-worldliness” that was central to Christian theology for centuries: this
world can never rise above the status of a means; even the beauty of the world
can never be an end in itself. The world is thus divested of any literal
significance: its meaning resides not in its isolated parts nor even in the
system of relations connecting all of its parts, but in its potential to point
beyond itself to what it signifies in another realm, a transcendent goal. No
object in the world can have any significance, importance, or meaning except
in reference to God. Only God is to be loved for his own sake, and all other
things are to be loved in reference to God (DDC, I.27).
Hence, according to Augustine, the world as experienced by a Christian is
not essentially a thing or a series of things since it is transformed into a sign or
a series of signs (DDC, I.13). Many centuries before Saussure, Augustine
distinguished between natural and conventional signs, the former embodying
no human intention (as when smoke signals fire) and the latter devised by
human beings to communicate (DDC, II.1–2). Even the signs given by God in
the scriptures, says Augustine, were made known through men, and need to
be studied. The difficulties of scripture, he thinks, spring largely from two
sources, unknown and ambiguous signs. The main remedy is knowledge of
the languages of scripture (Latin, Hebrew, Greek); Augustine even admits
that a diversity of interpretations is useful inasmuch as these will often throw
light on obscure passages (DDC, II.11, 12). Nonetheless, we must “believe
that whatever is there written, even though it be hidden, is better and truer
than anything we could devise by our own wisdom” (DDC, II.7). Hence,
knowledge is viewed as a closed system, bounded by God’s omniscience and
foreknowledge. What would otherwise be the conventional nature of human
knowledge is forever a partial emulation of, and aspiration after, what is
already known to God.
Augustine is concerned to furnish rules which will guide the reader in
knowing whether to interpret given passages of scripture literally or figuratively. The general rule is that whatever passage taken literally is inconsistent
with either “purity of life” or “soundness of doctrine” must be taken as
figurative (DDC, III.10). Augustine warns against taking a figurative expression literally. It is “a miserable slavery of the soul,” he says, “to take signs for
things, and to be unable to lift the eye of the mind above what is corporeal and
created, that it may drink in eternal light” (DDC, III.5). These comments
throw an interesting light on the foundations of Christian allegory. Literal
meaning, whereby “things are to be understood just as they are expressed”
(DDC, III.37), corresponds with the realm of materiality and bodily sensation. Figurative expressions, “in which one thing is expressed and another is
to be understood,” attempts to raise perception toward a spiritual and
intellectual realm. Literal meaning is arrested at the opacity of “things”
whereby figurative meaning looks through things, treating them as only signs
56
The Medieval Era
of more exalted levels of truth, abolishing the thinghood of the world and
imbuing it with a symbolic significance which refers all of its elements to the
life hereafter. Thus is laid the foundation of various levels of meaning in
allegory. All significant knowledge and wisdom is contained in the scriptures,
which were inspired by the Holy Spirit; men can use their human faculty of
reason and various branches of secular knowledge to a certain degree in
understanding the Word of God. But ultimately, this Word stands above
human language and reason, and men must ascend allegorically from a literal
understanding of their world to a symbolic view of it as a small part in a vast
scheme which both subsumes and gives meaning to it. The world must be
understood as the Word of God.
Augustine advises that pagan knowledge, if useful, should be appropriated
for Christian use (DDC, II.31). But he cautions: “whatever man may have
learnt from other sources than Scripture, if it is hurtful, it is there condemned;
if it is useful, it is therein contained” (DDC, II.42). In the final book of
De Doctrina Augustine establishes that it is lawful for a Christian teacher to
use the art of rhetoric. However, while eloquence is useful to the Christian
preacher, it is less important than wisdom, especially since the wisdom being
dispensed is not human wisdom but a “heavenly wisdom which comes down
from the Father,” The Christian preacher, then, is but a minister of this higher
wisdom (DDC, IV.5). If the preacher can speak with eloquence as well as
wisdom, however, he will be of greater service. Augustine’s view of truth itself
as the basis of good style underlies his new, Christianized, definition of
rhetoric (DDC, IV.28).
Notes
1. Cambridge Companion to Aquinas, ed. Norman Kretzmann and Eleonore Stump
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), pp. 4–5.
2. Ernst Robert Curtius, European Literature and the Latin Middle Ages, trans.
Willard R. Trask (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1979), p. 23.
3. St. Augustine, City of God, trans. Henry Bettenson (Harmondsworth: Penguin,
1984), I.31. Hereafter cited as CG.
4. The Confessions of St. Augustine, trans. Rex Warner (New York: Mentor, 1963),
I.xvii.
5. George Kennedy, ed., The Cambridge History of Literary Criticism: Volume I:
Classical Criticism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), pp. 339–340.
6. Saint Augustine, De Doctrina Christiana (Calvin College: Christian Classics
Ethereal Library, 2003), I.2. This translation, which I find to be particularly
effective, is in the public domain and can be found in electronic format at:
www.ccel.org/ccel/augustine/doctrine.iii.html. Hereafter cited as DDC.
Chapter 5
The Later Middle Ages
Historical Background
During the early Middle Ages it had largely been left to the Church (and
certain rulers such as Charlemagne) to attempt some kind of social and moral
cohesion and to preserve and transmit the various intellectual and literary
traditions. The later Middle Ages, beginning around 1050, witnessed
considerable progress on many levels. Most fundamentally, there was an
economic revival. It was in this period that the system of feudalism achieved
a relatively stable formation. The term “feudalism” derives from the word
“fief” (the medieval term being feudum or “feud”), which means a piece of
land held in “fee”: in other words, the land was not owned, but a person had
the right to cultivate it in return for rent or certain services performed for the
landlord. Perry Anderson defines “fief” as “a delegated grant of land, vested
with juridical and political powers, in exchange for military service.”1
The basic contractual relation in feudal society was between a lord and
a vassal: the lord, owning the land, would provide protection, in return for
the vassal’s obedience, taxes or rent, and military or other service. Usually,
fiefs (tracts of land or certain offices) were hereditary, and the feudal system
was in general a static hierarchy, ranging from the highest lord, the
monarch, through the various ranks of nobility such as castellans, barons,
counts, and principals to the knights. Hence, each member of this hierarchy
was both a lord and a vassal, involved in an intricate nexus of relationships
with those above and below him. In a broader sense, however, society
was increasingly divided into two classes, the one a landed aristocracy
and clergy, the other composed of the mass of peasants, with a small middle
class of merchants, traders, and craftsmen. The peasantry itself existed as
a hierarchy, from villeins or tenant farmers through serfs (who were bound
to a particular tract of land) to the poorest people who hired out their labor
on an occasional basis. Clearly, this legal and political structure, as Hegel
would observe later, was not rational but an outgrowth of hereditary status,
existing practices, traditions, and customs. The basic unit of production in
Literary Criticism from Plato to the Present: An Introduction
© 2011 M. A. R. Habib. ISBN: 978-1-405-16034-6
M. A. R. Habib
58
The Medieval Era
the feudal system was the manor or manorial estate: this comprised the
lord’s manor house and demesne (that part of his land not held by tenants),
the parish church, one or more villages, and the land divided into strips
between a multitude of peasants. The manor was largely self-contained, selfgoverned, existing in relative economic isolation, with minimal foreign trade
(PF, 137).
Another important element in feudalism was the city. By the later Middle
Ages, significant urban communities had grown. Major European cities
included Palermo, Venice, Florence, Milan, Ghent, Bruges, and Paris. Economically, the cities were dominated by two types of organizations –
merchant guilds and artisan guilds – whose purpose was to regulate the
means of production, attempting to preserve a stability and freedom from
competition, with standard wages and prices, and even frowning on new
technology or greater efficiency. The members of the artisan guilds formed
a hierarchy composed of master craftsmen, who owned their own businesses,
and the “journeymen” who worked for them, as well as the apprentices, for
whose training and upbringing the masters were responsible. The guilds had
a paternalistic attitude toward their members, sustaining them in times of
hardship, providing for their widows and orphans, as well as exercising
broader religious and social functions. The guild system rested partly on
Christian doctrines, stemming from the Church fathers and Aquinas, which
frowned on excessive wealth or private property, condemned usury or the
taking of interest, advocated fair prices, and encouraged an orientation
toward the welfare of the community as a whole rather than that of the
individual. At least, these were the ideals in theory.
Intellectual Currents of the Later Middle Ages
The medieval curriculum
The major intellectual currents of this period were: various forms of humanism deriving from the classical grammatical tradition; the heritage of
Neo-Platonism and allegorical criticism; and the movement known as scholasticism, based on a revived Aristotelianism mediated through Islamic
thinkers such as Ibn Rushd (Averro€es). These later intellectual streams were
enabled by educational developments, primarily the rise of the cathedral
schools and the universities.2 The universities were usually composed of
faculties of liberal arts as well as medicine, law, and theology. The notion
of the liberal arts can be traced as far back as the Sophist Hippias of Elis,
a contemporary of Socrates, as well as to the rhetorician Isocrates who
opposed Plato’s insistence on a purely philosophical training in favor
of a broader system of education. The locus classicus for the system of
The Later Middle Ages
59
artes liberales is a letter by the Roman thinker Seneca, who called these arts
“liberal” because they are worthy of a free man, their purpose not being to
make money.
By the end of antiquity, the number of the liberal arts had been fixed at
seven, and arranged in the sequence that they were to retain through the
medieval period. The first three – grammar, rhetoric, and dialectic (or logic) –
were known from the ninth century onwards as the “trivium” (“three
roads”); the remaining four mathematical arts – arithmetic, geometry, music,
and astronomy – had been designated by Boethius as the “quadruvium”
(“four roads”), later known as the “quadrivium.” Of the seven liberal arts,
the most exhaustively studied was grammar, which comprised the study of
both language and the interpretation of literature. The authors studied
included Vergil, Ovid, Donatus, Martianus Capella, Horace, Juvenal,
Boethius, Statius, Terence, Lucan, Cicero, as well as Christian writers
such as Juvencus, Arator, and Prudentius. This list continued to expand into
the thirteenth century, with the pagan authors subjected to allegorical
interpretation.
It was the authority of this curriculum which was dislodged by the
dialectical or logical methods of the scholastic thinkers. As mentioned earlier,
these rational methods had been fostered by the growth, from the beginning
of the twelfth century, of the cathedral schools and the universities. The
cathedral schools effectively displaced the surviving monasteries as centers of
education. They were located in towns, the most renowned being at Paris,
Chartres, and Canterbury. Perhaps the single greatest force animating these
schools was the revival of philosophy, which, at the end of antiquity, had
given way to the liberal arts. This revival was spearheaded in the late eleventh
and early twelfth centuries by Anselm of Canterbury (1033–1109), the French
theologian Roscelin (ca. 1045–ca. 1120), his student Peter Abelard
(1079–1142), and the Italian theologian Peter Lombard (ca. 1100–1160).
These were the pioneers of scholasticism. They drew on Boethius’ logic to
attempt a rational and coherent interpretation of Christian doctrine, viewing
logic as the preeminent Christian science.
Even more important in this twelfth century “renaissance” of thought was
the widespread growth of universities. Ancient universities had been largely
devoted to the teaching of grammar and rhetoric. It was in the Middle Ages
that our modern notion of the university was born, with various faculties,
a regular curriculum and a hierarchy of degrees. The oldest universities were
in Italy, France, and England, and included Bologna (1158), Oxford (ca.
1200), Paris (1208–1209), and Naples (1224). Through these universities
swept the philosophy of the “new” Aristotle, the recently recovered works of
Aristotle on natural history, metaphysics, ethics, and politics, made available
to the West through translations from Arabic and Greek. The foremost of
the Arab Aristotelian thinkers was Ibn Rushd (Averro€es). At the instigation of
60
The Medieval Era
the pope, the study of the “new” Aristotle was forbidden in 1215, but the
stricture had little force. It was the Dominican scholars who attempted to
reconcile the Christian faith with Greek philosophy.3 Thus came into being
the great impetus of scholasticism, reaching its height in Albertus Magnus and
then his student Thomas Aquinas. By the efforts of the Dominicans at the
University of Paris, “the dangerous Aristotle was purified, rehabilitated, and
authorized. Even more: his teaching was incorporated into Christian philosophy and theology, and in this form has remained authoritative” (Curtius,
56). This new prominence of philosophy and theology pushed the study of
grammar, rhetoric, and literature somewhat into the background.
A historical overview of medieval criticism
The various kinds of medieval criticism can be classified in terms of the broad
divisions of knowledge in the curriculum. All three elements of the medieval
trivium – grammatica, rhetorica, dialectica – were sciences of language and
discourse, concerned with interpretation and signification; their boundaries
often overlapped and the status and placement of literature was often
disputed. Since the late classical era, poetry had been treated as a branch
of rhetoric; in the later Middle Ages, the study of poetry was increasingly
absorbed under grammar, but in the hands of scholastic thinkers it became
part of the province of logic or dialectic. These various streams of medieval
criticism can now be examined through one or two of the major writers
representing each tendency. We can begin by considering the medieval
disposition to situate literature within the entire scheme of knowledge, as
in the work of Hugh of St. Victor. We can then consider the nature and value
of the grammar curriculum (of which literature was an important part) in the
work of John of Salisbury. We can then proceed to the placement of poetry
first within rhetoric (in the texts of Geoffrey de Vinsauf) and then within logic
(as expressed in the scholastic thinkers Ibn Rushd and Aquinas, as well as in
Dante); and finally, we can see the placement of poetry as a part of philosophy
or theology in the writings of Boccaccio and Christine de Pisan who effect
a humanistic revival of allegorical traditions.
The Traditions of Medieval Criticism
Literature and grammar
Most of the intellectual currents of the Middle Ages are founded on the
grammatical tradition of textual exegesis or interpretation, extended by
Christian scholars to scriptural exegesis. Poetry was seen as a part of
grammar, a fact which spawned three kinds of treatise. The first was the
The Later Middle Ages
61
commentary or gloss. In medieval manuscripts the pages had wide margins to
accommodate substantial commentary; this fostered a textual fluidity and
a blurring of boundaries between text and commentary. The text was
elaborately encoded – and even contained – within a broader system of
meaning handed down by traditional interpretation.4 A second type of
grammatical treatise was the ars metrica (metrical art), since the grammar
curriculum included prosody and a study of the standard poetic forms.
Notable among medieval Latin treatises of this type was Dante’s De Vulgari
Eloquentia (ca. 1304–1307). The third type of grammatical treatise was the
accessus or “prologue” to an author.
All three types of grammatical treatise – the commentary, the ars metrica,
and the accessus – were vehicles of medieval humanism.5 It should be said that
medieval grammar or grammatica was much broader than our modern notion
of “grammar,” and has great importance in the entire scheme of medieval
thought and ideology. As Martin Irvine has recently argued, from late
classical times until the early Renaissance, grammar had a foundational role,
furnishing a model of learning, interpretation, and knowledge. It was a social
practice that provided exclusive access to literacy, the understanding of
scripture, knowledge of the literary canon, and membership of an international Latin textual community. Grammatica was sustained by the dominant
social and political institutions of medieval Europe; in turn, grammatica
functioned in support of those institutions: the courts, cathedrals, and all the
major centers of power. As such, the authority of grammatica was a textual
reflex of religious and political authority (GLT, 2, 13, 20).
Anticipating modern literary theory, grammatica had many centuries
earlier replaced the world of things by the world of signs; it had already
reduced thinghood to language, in a vast and hierarchical system of signification that spanned many levels. This system was just as relational as any
view of language to be found in Saussure. In other words, no element in that
system was presumed to have any isolated or independent significance. In all
these ways, medieval literary theory was far more sophisticated – and more
foundational in our own ways of thinking – than was previously thought.
Literature in the Scheme of Human Learning: the Sacred Hermeneutics of
Hugh of St. Victor (ca. 1097–1141) The medieval tendency to situate
literature as one component in an ordered and hierarchical scheme of learning
was expressed in a widely influential educational treatise composed in the late
1120s by Hugh of St. Victor, the Didascalicon (a Greek word meaning
“instructive” or “fit for teaching”). In general, Hugh argues that the ultimate
purpose of all the arts is to “restore within us the divine likeness.”6 He
provides a scheme for reading both secular texts and the sacred scriptures.
Unlike many authors in the tradition of allegorical exegesis (such as
Augustine, Bede, Aquinas, and Dante), Hugh proposes a threefold (rather
62
The Medieval Era
than fourfold) understanding of scripture. Sacred scripture has “three ways of
conveying meaning – namely, history, allegory and tropology.” History
represents the literal level of meaning; allegory refers to the spiritual or
mystical sense; and tropology refers to the moral level of interpretation
(DHV, V.ii).
Hugh insists that a literal or historical reading be mastered before proceeding to the other levels of allegorical interpretation. Summarizing the
threefold layers of interpretation, he suggests that history provides “the
means through which to admire God’s deeds”; allegory, the means through
which “to believe his mysteries”; and morality, the means to “imitate his
perfection” (DHV, VI.iii). Hugh cautions against imposing our own opinion
on the text: we should attempt to make our own thought identical with that of
the scriptures, rather than coercing scripture into identity with our own
thought (DHV, VI.xi). In all of these assumptions Hugh is effectively
adhering to mainstream medieval literary critical practice: novelty and
individuality are discouraged, and the meanings of words must be constrained ultimately by the semantic field circumscribed by scripture.
Defending and Defining the Grammar Curriculum: John of Salisbury (ca.
1115–1180) The work of John of Salisbury was symptomatic of the
broadening of the grammar curriculum in the twelfth century and the revived
centrality of logic. John’s Metalogicon (1159) is not only a defense of
grammar, logic, and rhetoric, but also an attempt to define these disciplines
and their interconnection. He articulates the overwhelming importance of
the grammar curriculum: “Grammar is the cradle of all philosophy, and . . .
the first nurse of the whole study of letters . . . it fosters and protects the
philosopher from the start to the finish [of his pursuits].”7 John insists that the
study of poetry belongs to grammar. Moreover, it is precisely the system of
grammar that is the index of civilization and its distinctness from barbarianism (ML, 51–52).
An important principle of analysis for John is that a text should be
analyzed in such a way that “the author’s meaning is always preserved.” The
text should be “studied with sympathetic mildness, and not tortured on the
rack” (ML, 146, 148). Typically of medieval exposition, there is much
emphasis on authorial intention. A further principle is the imitation of
distinguished authors, in an endeavor to educate students not only in
technical skills but also in fostering faith and morality (ML, 68–69). Also
characteristic of medieval educational methods was obliging students to
memorize passages from the eminent authors. Such emphasis on imitation of
past masters means effectively that the authorized modes of viewing the
world are already determined and classified; all the student can do is to
emulate precisely and repeat these world views, not only installed within his
memory but codified by grammar and rhetoric so as to determine from the
The Later Middle Ages
63
depths of the classical past the fundamental features of any future composition (ML, 92).
John regards language as enjoying an intimate correspondence with reality
or the world of objects, a correspondence authorized ultimately by God, by
the “thoughts of the Most High” (ML, 262–263). Human learning and
the human faculties of perception are gradated within this divine plan. Our
knowledge of the material world, says John, begins with our senses; the
imagination operates upon and orders the data received by sensation; our
faculty of reason transcends sense-perception and contemplates heavenly
things; our highest faculty is a kind of intuitive understanding which leads to
a spiritual wisdom (ML, 227–230). Our reason itself is divinely endowed:
we possess reason because we participate in the “original reason,” which is
the “wisdom of God” (ML, 225). Hence all human learning – which must be
directed by our striving toward goodness and wisdom – is circumscribed,
from the outset, by religious categories. And it is the original reason of God
which “embraces the nature, development, and ultimate end of all things”
(ML, 250). All in all, the Metalogicon provides us with a revealing picture not
only of the medieval curriculum but also of the religious world view and the
conceptions of human nature underlying this curriculum.
Literature and rhetoric
Much literary criticism of the classical period – including the work of Horace
and “Longinus” – was actually rhetorical criticism applied to poetry. The
heritage of rhetoric since late classical times included the system of the three
styles (high, middle, low), the division of figures into schemes and tropes,
the division of figures of thought from figures of speech, the relative importance of genius and art in poetic composition, the doctrine of imitation of
the masterpieces, the distinction between content and language, as well as the
concept of “decorum” or mutual suitability of form and content (MLC, 5).
The concept of a sharp distinction between poetic and rhetoric was not even
available until the renewed circulation of Aristotle’s Poetics in the sixteenth
century. The artes poeticae or manuals on the art of poetry were part of the
grammar curriculum, even though they had been heavily influenced by
rhetoric. One of the best examples of such manuals is Geoffrey de Vinsauf’s
Poetria Nova.
Geoffrey de Vinsauf (ca. 1200) Geoffrey de Vinsauf derives his name (de
Vino Salvo in Latin) from a treatise on the preservation of wine which was
attributed to him. However, it was not wine but poetics which earned him
renown.8 His treatise Poetria Nova (New Poetics), designed to provide
guidance in the rules and practice of poetry, along with the study and
imitation of great poets, became one of the standard training manuals of
64
The Medieval Era
poets in Europe from the thirteenth century until well into the Renaissance.
Characteristically of medieval writers, Geoffrey viewed poetry as a branch of
rhetoric, dividing his treatise according to the five rhetorical “offices” of
invention, arrangement, style, memory, and delivery. Geoffrey’s treatise
Poetria Nova echoes the title of a rhetorical manual Rhetorica Nova,
indicating that he wishes to propound a new poetics. It also echoes the title
of Horace’s Ars poetica, which was known in the Middle Ages as the Poetria.
Like Horace’s text, Geoffrey’s treatise is written in Latin verse.
The bulk of Geoffrey’s treatise is devoted to style and the various
“ornaments” that create given styles in poetry. In contrast with the long
tradition of aesthetics which saw poetry as mere imitation of nature, Geoffrey
places considerable emphasis on the transformation of nature by poetry, and
the need for the poet to attain novelty. The resources of art provide “a means
of avoiding worn-out paths and of travelling a more distinguished route”
(PN, IV.982–983). While much of Geoffrey’s text clearly points to a more
modern poetics, he nonetheless sustains the classical precepts of moderation,
decorum, propriety, and the appeal to reason, as well as to the important
classical distinction between prose and verse and a hierarchy of genres.
Literature and logic
Scholasticism initially worked with a commonly accepted background of
Christian orthodoxy. However, during the twelfth and thirteen centuries the
works of Aristotle, transmitted largely by the Islamic philosophers Ibn Rushd
(Averro€es) and Ibn Sina (Avicenna), were translated into Latin and became
increasingly well known. Eventually, Aristotle was taken as the fundamental
philosophical foundation of the scholastics, and he replaced Plato as the
primary philosophical basis of Christian theology. The scholastic philosophers relied primarily on dialectic (logic) and syllogistic reasoning. By the
fourteenth century, scholasticism was eclipsed by nominalism which, along
with the work of thinkers such as Roger Bacon (ca. 1214–1294), paved the
way for the more scientific tenor of Renaissance thought, and an increasing
separation of philosophy and theology.
Scholasticism’s emphasis on logic extended to its treatment of literature,
which was seen as a branch of logic, an instrument for the manipulation of
language. Literature was seen as a form rather than as having any specific
content. This conception was heavily influenced by Islamic philosophers such
as al-Farabi and Ibn Rushd, especially the latter’s Commentary on the Poetics
of Aristotle, translated into Latin in 1256. Significantly, Ibn Rushd’s commentary – in its Latin rendering – was far more widely read in the Middle Ages
than Aristotle’s Poetics itself (translated in 1278 and 1536). As such, it was
the most important theoretical literary critical statement of the scholastic
period (MLC, 14–15). In viewing poetry as a branch of logic, the scholastics
The Later Middle Ages
65
accorded it a definite place in a hierarchy of sciences crowned by theology.
They eventually fostered a new and more liberal critical vocabulary, allowing
for a more comprehensive treatment of author, material, style, structure, and
effect. In this section, we will consider Ibn Rushd’s Commentary as well as the
aesthetics of Aquinas in the context of his vastly influential world view, and
finally Dante’s Epistle to Can Grande della Scala, which is one of the foremost
practical applications of scholastic criticism.
Ibn Rushd (Averro€es) (1126–1198) In the medieval West, the Islamic
philosopher and jurist Ibn Rushd gained wide recognition among both
Christian and Jewish scholars. Nearly all of his commentaries on Aristotle’s
major works were translated into Latin, and some into Hebrew. It was
through Ibn Rushd that the main corpus of Aristotle’s texts was transmitted to
Europe. The central endeavor of Ibn Rushd’s own major philosophical
treatises was to reconcile philosophy and religion, reason and revelation.
Ironically, and sadly, Ibn Rushd’s influence on Islamic thought was far
smaller than his impact on Christian Europe; he failed to convince Islamic
theologians of the propriety of philosophy within their religious visions.9
In Ibn Rushd’s Commentary on the Poetics of Aristotle, we can distinguish
three broad themes (bearing in mind that these themes intersect at times only
tangentially with the Greek text of Aristotle, and that Ibn Rushd’s text is
written in Arabic, its immediate audience comprising Arab scholars and
writers): (1) poetry is defined broadly as the art of praise or blame, based on
representations of moral choice; (2) the purpose of poetry is to produce
a salutary effect upon its audience, through both excellence of imitative
technique and performative elements such as melody, gesture, and intonation; and (3) poetry is viewed as a branch of logical discourse, which is
compared and contrasted with rhetorical discourse.
Ibn Rushd’s central thesis that “Every poem and all poetry are either blame
or praise” is developed only tangentially from Aristotle’s comment in the
Poetics that the first forms of poetry were praises of famous men and satire.
Ibn Rushd states that the subjects proper to poetry are those that “deal with
matters of choice, both good and bad.”10 Like Aristotle, he holds that all
action and character are concerned with either virtue or vice (MLC, 91).
Regarding poetic imitation, he places great emphasis on realism. Like
Aristotle, he suggests that the poet is close to the philosopher inasmuch as
he speaks “in universal terms” (MLC, 99). But whereas Aristotle talks of the
poet representing what is probable, Ibn Rushd insists that, just as “the skilled
artist depicts an object as it is in reality . . . the poet should depict and form the
object as it is in itself” (MLC, 105). It seems that Ibn Rushd prescribes
a broader pursuit of poetic objectivity, which was strangely modern; he goes
so far as to say that poetry is most truthful when it is based on direct
experience: the poet “does best in reporting those things that he has
66
The Medieval Era
understood for himself and almost seen first-hand with all their accidents and
circumstances” (MLC, 110). The impact of these insights was restricted to the
West, and did not extend to the majority of Islamic thinkers and poets.
Ibn Rushd’s emphasis on truth may derive partly from the fact that, like
many Islamic thinkers, he appears to treat the Qur’an as the archetypal text.
He sees the Qur’an as exceptional in Arabic literature inasmuch as it praises
“worthy actions of the will and blame of unworthy ones.” The Qur’an, he
states, prohibits “poetic fictions” except those which rebuke vices and
commend virtues (MLC, 109). In a striking commensurability with much
medieval poetics, then, Ibn Rushd’s views might be said to have a scriptural
foundation: just as Vergil and the Bible were revered as authoritative texts
(stylistically and grammatically, as well as in their content), so the Qur’an is
invoked as a literary exemplar. Hence, Ibn Rushd’s treatise is archetypal
of scholastic views of poetry, situating it as one form of discourse among
a hierarchy of discourses, at whose pinnacle stood theology.
What would later medieval and Renaissance writers have gleaned about
Aristotle from Ibn Rushd’s text? Certainly an emphasis on the moral function
and the truth value of poetry; in formal terms, a stress on unified poetic
organization, and the need for poetry to produce a powerful impact on its
audience. But Ibn Rushd fails to distinguish between drama and narrative,
between tragedy and epic, a conflation also found in writers such as Dante and
Chaucer (MLC, 85). Moreover, readers would have found in Ibn Rushd’s text
a highly un-Aristotelian description of the components of tragedy. Whereas
Aristotle had insisted that the plot was the most important element and that
action took priority over character, Ibn Rushd, characterizing tragedy along
with epic as a “song of praise,” sees as its most important component
“character and belief.” The reader would also seek in vain for Aristotle’s
characterizations of “reversal” and “recognition,” though he would find the
notion that pity and fear are inspired by the spectacle of undeserved misfortune (MLC, 102).
Notwithstanding these sometimes drastic alterations of Aristotle, Ibn
Rushd’s text was widely influential, met with the approval of figures such
as Roger Bacon, and was used extensively by critics such as Benvenuto da
Imola, the fourteenth-century commentator on Dante, who saw Dante’s
Commedia as essentially a work of praise and blame. It also influenced
Petrarch’s humanist disciple Coluccio Salutati, who also made use of the
principle of praise and blame, as well as of Ibn Rushd’s definition of imitation.
The influence is traceable in sixteenth-century writers such as Savonarola,
Robortelli, and Mazzoni, who all believed that poetry was to some degree
a branch of logic, and who all cited Ibn Rushd in support of their own
positions. Ibn Rushd’s version of Aristotle was congenial to the moralistic
attitudes of the humanists. Ironically, then, Ibn Rushd’s version of Aristotle
was for a long time given more credit than the views of Aristotle himself.
The Later Middle Ages
67
St. Thomas Aquinas (1224/5–1274) Aristotle also assumes a prominent
position in the thought of Thomas Aquinas, the greatest of the scholastic
philosophers as well as the greatest philosopher of the Roman Catholic
Church. Eventually, Aquinas was proclaimed to be an official “doctor” of
the Church and his works were deemed to be the expression of orthodox
doctrine. His system is still widely taught in Catholic educational institutions.
Aquinas was born into a noble family in 1224 or 1225 in Italy near the city of
Naples, where he joined the order of the Dominican friars, whose central
scholarly endeavor was to reconcile the teachings of Aristotle and Christ.
Aquinas studied with the renowned Dominican Albertus Magnus. Through
the efforts of such figures, the Church established Aristotle, rather than Plato
(who had been promoted by the Church Fathers for many centuries), at the
center of Christian thought.
Aquinas is known primarily for two major works. The first, Summa contra
Gentiles, was written between 1259 and 1264. Its essential purpose was to
defend the truth of Christianity against gentiles who did not accept the
authority of the scriptures. In the first four books of the Summa, Aquinas
relies, therefore, not on scripture but on “natural reason,” which can be used
to prove God’s existence and the soul’s immortality. The truths of the
Incarnation, the Trinity, and the Last Judgment, however, are beyond the
grasp of natural reason. Indeed the provinces of reason and revelation need,
according to Aquinas, to be clearly distinguished. He holds that these two
provinces, while distinct, cannot contradict and must accord with each other.
Religious truths capable of demonstration (for the learned) can also be known
by faith, as in the case of simple people or children.
Ironically, it was misinterpretations of Ibn Rushd’s teachings by the Latin
“Averroists” – who viewed him as believing that faith and reason were
irreconcilable – that provoked the response of Aquinas’ philosophy, which
labored to harmonize these domains. Aquinas sees theology as a divine
science, to which all of the other elements of human knowledge are hierarchically ordered. While his scheme places theology at the apex of the human
sciences, it also accommodates these sciences and views them as preparatory
for man’s last end as an intellectual creature, which is to know God.11
In his second major work, Summa Theologica, Aquinas offers five proofs of
the existence of God. The first is the argument of the unmoved mover: in order
to avoid an infinite regress, there must be something which “moves” or sets
into motion other things without being moved itself. Second is the argument
from First Cause, which follows a similar logic: there must be a primal cause
of the world, which itself is not caused. Thirdly, there must be a primal source
of all necessity. Fourthly, the various types and degrees of perfection which
actually exist in the world must have their source in something absolutely
perfect. Finally, even lifeless things serve a purpose, which must be directed
68
The Medieval Era
toward some being beyond them. Some of the major characteristics of God,
according to Aquinas, are as follows: God is eternal, unchanging, and he has
no parts or composition since he is not material. In God, essence and existence
are identical, and there are no accidents or contingencies in God. He does not
belong to any genus and cannot be defined. God’s intellection is his essence; he
understands himself perfectly and in so doing understands the various
elements of the world, which are like him in certain ways. As Aquinas puts
it, “God himself, in knowing Himself, knows all other things” (MTA, 114).
God’s knowledge is comprehensive, holistic, and instantaneous; it is not
discursive, piecemeal, and rational. But Aquinas acknowledges that there is
a “community of analogy” between God and human beings (MTA, 36). He
believes that God created the world ex nihilo or out of nothing; and that God
is the end or purpose of all things, which tend toward likeness of God. The
human intellect, which aspires after God, is a part of each man’s soul, the soul
being the form of the body. On the questions of sin and predestination,
Aquinas basically agrees with Augustine that only God’s grace can redeem
man from sin and that the election of some men for salvation is a mystery.
The picture of the world which emerges here is one which is rigidly coherent
and closed off from all possible intrusion of accidence. It is also one which is
balanced precariously on the narrow ground of overlap of revelation and
reason, God’s providence and natural law, essence and existence. Moreover,
all things except God have their true being outside of themselves, in their end,
which is God. And God effectively acts as the boundaries of the universe since
all thingsare replicated – in their true significance – in the sphere of God, his selfknowledge encompassing knowledge of them. In other words, things achieve
their true identity only in God, and then only in God’s act of self-knowledge, in
the coerced relation of dependence to him in which they are obliged to subsist.
They achieve identity, then, not as objects of knowledge in their own right, but
as projections or rather introjections of God’s subjectivity. Man’s ultimate
happiness consists in contemplation of God. Hence God’s essence delimits the
world in several ways: as origin and purpose, as beginning and end, as subject
and object, as knower and known, as center and circumference.
Aquinas’ world view furnished the context of much medieval thought and
aesthetics. In his study of Aquinas, Umberto Eco describes Aquinas as “the
person who gave most complete expression to the philosophical and theological thinking of the age.”12 Influential in medieval conceptions of beauty
were Aquinas’ belief that God’s creation is intrinsically beautiful, and his
intellectual conception of beauty as requiring three components: integrity or
perfection, right proportion or consonance (consonantia), and splendor of
form (claritas) (MTA, 90–92).
Medieval Allegory and Aquinas There was a widespread tendency throughout the medieval period to view all things in the world and the universe as
The Later Middle Ages
69
essentially symbolic, as signs in a vast lexicon through which God speaks to
humanity. Everything points beyond itself, beyond its immediate worldly
significance, toward a higher level of significance in a more comprehensive
pattern of events and divine purpose. Among the influential proponents of
such a view were pseudo-Dionysius, the Roman writer Macrobius, and John
Scotus Eriugena who wrote that “there is nothing among visible and corporeal things which does not signify something incorporeal and intelligible”
(Eco, 139). Such all-embracing symbolism provided a vision of a world
constrained by unity, order, and purpose. In such a vision, human beings are
obliged to read and decipher the book of the world or the book of the universe.
Christian allegory arose initially from the attempts by writers such as
Origen to reconcile the Old and New Testaments. Allegory also had its basis
in the endeavor to restrict the potentially infinite meanings of the scriptures,
by subjecting them to a code of interpretation. Hence the Church Fathers
devised an allegorical theory of interpretation of the Bible, according to three
levels of meaning: the literal, the moral, and the mystical. Later, this system
was expanded to include four levels, summarized by Nicholas of Lyre: “The
literal sense tells us of events; the allegorical teaches our faith; the moral tells
us what to do; the anagogical shows us where we are going” (Eco, 145).
In his Summa Theologica, Aquinas explained allegory in a formulation
which comprehends the foregoing tendencies:
that first signification whereby words signify things belongs to the first sense, the
historical or literal. That signification whereby things signified by words have
themselves also a signification is called the spiritual sense, which is based on the
literal, and presupposes it. Now this spiritual sense has a threefold division . . . so
far as the things of the Old Law signify the things of the New Law, there is the
allegorical sense; so far as the things done in Christ, or so far as the things which
signify Christ, are types of what we ought to do, there is the moral sense. But so
far as they signify what relates to eternal glory, there is the anagogical sense.
(Summa Theologica, Q.I, Tenth Article)13
What is notable about Aquinas’ definition of allegory is the movement from
the signification of things to that of words. The literal or historical sense
denotes the connection between language and the world. But the remaining
levels of significance are contained within the realm of language and literary/
biblical tradition. The most general name for this symbolism is the “spiritual
sense.” The three divisions of this comprehend Christianity’s attempt to
appropriate the pre-Christian past into its own historical and theological
framework (the allegorical sense); they also affirm the moral authority of
Christ’s own example (the moral sense); finally, they stress the Christian view
of the transient, partial, and finite nature of this world, which has significance
only in relation to the totality of God’s eternal scheme which is accessible only
by revelation and not by human reason (the anagogical or mystical sense).
70
The Medieval Era
Aquinas held that poetry was infima doctrina or an inferior kind of teaching
to that of scripture because it dealt with objects which were imagined or
invented. But, as Eco observes, such a view does not imply contempt for
poetry on Aquinas’ part – it expresses his sense of the hierarchy of various
modes of knowledge (Eco, 148–149). After Aquinas, thinkers began to stress
the particularity and uniqueness, rather than the universal qualities, of
beauty, a view realized in many modern conceptions of art which emphasized
art as creation rather than merely imitation, and stressed the particularity and
uniqueness of beautiful things (Eco, 215–216).
Dante Alighieri (1265–1321) and the Allegorical Mode Allegory is integral
to the work of Dante Alighieri (1265–1321), arguably the greatest poet the
Western world has produced. He is best known for his epic poem Divina
Commedia (1307–1321) and his earlier cycle of love poems published as La
Vita Nuova (The New Life, ca. 1295), written in honor of Beatrice Portinari.
Dante also wrote literary criticism. In De Vulgari Eloquentia (Eloquence in
the Vernacular Tongue, ca. 1304–1308), he defended the use of the vernacular Italian as appropriate for the writing of poetry. In Il Convivio (The
Banquet, 1306–1309), he produced a collection of 14 odes with prose
commentaries, designed to clear him of the charge of “unrestrained passion”
in these odes and to explain the principles of allegory. And in 1319 he wrote
a now famous letter, also treating of allegory, to his patron Can Grande della
Scala, though the authenticity of this has been questioned. In Il Convivio,
Dante states that allegory has four senses:
The first is called the literal, and this is the sense that does not go beyond the
surface of the letter, as in the fables of the poets. The next is called the allegorical,
and this is the one that is hidden beneath the cloak of these fables, and is a truth
hidden beneath a beautiful fiction. . .
The third sense is called moral, and this is the sense that teachers should intently
seek to discover throughout the scriptures, for their own profit and that of their
pupils. . .
The fourth sense is called anagogical, that is to say, beyond the senses; and this
occurs when a scripture is expounded in a spiritual sense which, although it is
true also in the literal sense, signifies by means of the things signified a part of the
supernal things of eternal glory.14
Dante insists that, in allegorical explication, “the literal sense should always
come first, as being the sense in whose meaning the others are enclosed.”
Literal meaning is the foundation of the other senses. He pictures the literal
meaning as being on the “outside,” enclosing the other senses which are
within (IC, II.i.65–80). In insisting on including literal meaning, Dante is
following many theologians who affirmed the truth of all four levels of
meaning, as against rhetorical and poetic views of allegory which might view
The Later Middle Ages
71
even the literal meaning as fictional. But, clearly, one of the functions of
allegory is to express “darkly” and in a hidden manner what is otherwise
ineffable concerning the mysteries of God, which even philosophy, the
noblest human pursuit, cannot fathom (IC, III.xv.58–69).
In the “Letter to Can Grande” Dante dedicates his Divine Comedy to his
patron and explains the allegorical structure of his poem. Dante begins by
reiterating Aristotle’s position that some things are self-sufficient, having
being in themselves, while the being of other things is relational, lying beyond
themselves in their connections with other things.15 Dante explains that his
text is “polysemous, that is, having several senses.” The literal sense necessarily signifies beyond itself to higher senses which complete it. The nonliteral senses, although they are called by various names (allegorical, moral,
anagogical) “may all be called allegorical, since they are all different from the
literal or historical” (“LCG,” 7). Hence he sees the structure of allegory as
broadly dualistic, the literal sense being a narrative of this world and the
allegorical sense referring to the spiritual domain.
In accordance with this duality, Dante sees the subject of the poem as
twofold, corresponding to literal and allegorical senses. The subject of the
work, taken literally, “is the state of souls after death.” Allegorically, “the
subject is man, in the exercise of his free will, earning or becoming liable to
the rewards or punishments of justice” (“LCG,” 8). Dante views the end or
ultimate aim of the work as spiritual, namely to lead souls from a state of sin
and misery to a state of blessedness (“LCG,” 15). The twofold structure of
allegory as given in Dante’s text informs every aspect of the reading process,
from the author’s intentions and use of language to the reader’s response.
Allegory expresses at its profoundest level a vision of the world in which the
existence of things is not self-sufficient but always depends ultimately,
through a series of mediating relationships, on God as the prime and
absolutely self-sufficient existent. All worldly goals are subordinated to the
ultimate goal of human life, which is to achieve blessedness by beholding
God, the “Origin of Truth” (“LCG,” 33).
Transitions: Medieval Humanism
Two medieval figures, Giovanni Boccaccio and Christine de Pisan, were
important forerunners of the Renaissance humanism that eclipsed (but also
grew out of) scholasticism. As will be seen in the accounts below, Boccaccio
saw an urgent need to defend poetry and a humanistic curriculum against the
onslaughts not so much of scholastics as of the rising mercantile classes who
saw no practical value in literature and the arts. Christine was a powerful
humanistic voice in the medieval era, who dared to enter into a literary debate
with established male authorities.
72
The Medieval Era
The defense of poetry: Giovanni Boccaccio (1313–1375)
Boccaccio is most widely known for his Decameron (1358), a collection of
100, sometimes bawdy, stories told by 10 characters against the background
of the bubonic plague which overtook Italy in 1348. Like Dante, he pressed
the cause of Italian vernacular literature. Yet, through his scholarly works,
written in Latin, he was an influential forerunner of Renaissance humanism.
His De Mulieribus Claris (Concerning Famous Women) (1361) was a source
of Christine de Pisan’s City of Ladies (1405). In terms of literary criticism, his
most influential work was Genealogia Deorum Gentilium (Genealogy of the
Gentile Gods) (1350–1362), a huge encyclopedia of classical mythology in 15
books, the last two of which are devoted to a comprehensive defense of
poetry.16 Hence, this work is not only an endeavor to expound the virtues
of classical literature but also an attempt by a practicing poet to defend his art,
in a tradition that stretches from Horace, through Ronsard, Du Bellay,
Sidney, Boileau, and Pope, to Wordsworth, Coleridge, Shelley, and Arnold.
Boccaccio defends poetry against charges that it is an “unprofitable” activity
by urging that poetry rejects worldly pursuits and “devotes herself to something greater . . .she moves the minds ofa few men from on high toa yearning for
the eternal” (GDG, XIV.iv). He is modern in claiming that poetry is an inspired
art, for which there can be no rigid rules and formulae, and also in defining
poetry in terms ofits effect (GDG, XIV.vii).As for the charge that poets are talemongers or liars, Boccaccio retorts that poetry is imbued with the classical
functions of teaching and delighting. It is also imbued with a theological
function, that of cloaking divine mysteries. Poets, he says, must “sacrifice the
literal truth in invention” (GDG, XIV.xiii). But while he sees poetry as sharing
some aims with philosophy and theology, he is nonetheless concerned to mark
out its domain as an autonomous province, finally extricated from rhetoric:
“oratory is quite different, in arrangement of words, from fiction, and that
fiction has been consigned to the discretion of the inventor as being the
legitimate work of another art than oratory” (GDG, XIV.xii). A large part
of Boccaccio’s endeavor is to show that poetry is not somehow contrary to the
principles of Christianity. But, for all his defense of poetry, Boccaccio situates
this art in a hierarchy wherein it is subservient to both philosophy and theology.
Feminism: Christine de Pisan (ca. 1365–1429)
Christine de Pisan was perhaps the most articulate and prolific female voice
of the European Middle Ages. Being widowed at the age of 25 without an
inheritance and with three children, she was obliged to earn her living as
a writer. She was commissioned as biographer of Charles V. Her patrons
included King Charles VI of France, King Charles of Navarre, and two dukes
The Later Middle Ages
73
of Burgundy. Her publications, which were translated into English, Italian,
and other languages, included Epistle of the God of Love (1399) where she
impugned the misogynistic portrayals of women and the dearth of morality in
the popular French work Roman de la Rose, an allegorical love poem written
by Guillaume de Lorris and expanded by Jean de Meun. The controversial
quarrel surrounding these texts was known as the Querelle de la Rose, with
Christine and Jean Gerson, chancellor of the University of Paris, allied
against the esteemed humanist royal secretaries Jean de Montreuil and Pierre
Col. In a further work, Christine’s Vision (1405), she complained against her
fortune as a female writer and scholar burdened by the conventional
obligations of womanhood. Another work produced in the same year, Livre
des Trois Vertus (Book of Three Virtues), concerns the status and role of
women in society. Her most renowned work was The Book of the City of
Ladies (1405), which was influenced by Boccaccio’s Concerning Famous
Women (1361) and Augustine’s City of God (to which Christine’s title
alludes). Almost uniquely among women of her time, Christine was enabled
to obtain a fine education through her family’s connections to the court of
Charles V.17 Christine also published a poem on Joan of Arc, Ditie de la
pucelle (1429).
The Book of the City of Ladies attempts effectively to rewrite the history of
women, its scope extending through past and future, as well as over pagan
and Christian eras. Such rewriting entails an explosion of age-long male
myths about women, such as their inability to govern, their unfitness for
learning, and their moral deficiencies. The nature of Christine’s feminism has
been a disputed issue, with some scholars pointing to her conservatism, her
espousal of the medieval class structure, her appeals to tradition, and above
all to Christianity. But others have seen her invocation of Christianity as her
very means of resisting oppression.
The Book is written as a conversation between Christine and three
allegorical virtues: Reason, Rectitude, and Justice. Just as Virginia Woolf,
some 600 years later, began A Room of One’s Own by reflecting on the
enormous number of books written about women by men, so Christine opens
her text by wondering why so many treatises by men contain “so many
wicked insults about women and their behavior.” What puzzles Christine is
the disparity between these male theories about women and her own practical
experience of women of all social ranks, “princesses, great ladies, women of
the middle and lower classes” (BCL, I.1.1). As Christine ponders, debilitated,
by these thoughts, there appears to her a vision of “three crowned ladies”
(BCL, I.2.1). The first of these, Lady Reason, explains that she and her two
companions are embarked on a mission: to provide a refuge for “ladies and all
valiant women” against the numerous assailants of the female sex. In this
mission, she tells Christine that she must, with the help of the three ladies,
build a city, “which has been predestined,” and where only ladies of fame and
74
The Medieval Era
virtue will reside (BCL, I.3.3). Christine was chosen for her “great love of
investigating the truth” (BCL, I.3.2).
As against the disparagement of women by revered males such as Cicero
and Cato, Lady Reason explains that woman was created from a rib of Adam,
which signified that “she should stand at his side as a companion and never lie
at his feet like a slave,” and that woman “was created in the image of God.”
Lady Reason observes, regarding Cato: “You can now see the foolishness of
the man who is considered wise” (BCL, I.8.3). Ironically, what the divine
authorizes here is the validity of female experience. And the personification of
“Reason” as a woman extricates the faculty of reason from its history of male
appropriation and abuse. So Christine’s appeal to Christianity might be
viewed as broadly humanistic. In this manner, Christine’s rewriting of history
is conducted on several concurrent levels: theological exegesis, the literary
tradition as defined by males, and the male appropriation of “reason.”
Lady Reason also extols the virtues of experience: “there is nothing which
so instructs a reasonable creature as the exercise and experience of many
different things” (BCL, I.27.1). Again, what is remarkable about this statement is that, despite its ostensibly theological framework, it anticipates the
major strands of Enlightenment thought, combining a proposed rationalism
with actual experience of the variety of the world. Talking of writers who
have disparaged women, Christine herself admonishes: “From now on let
them keep their mouths shut” (BCL, I.38.4–5). Christine’s stance has now
become outspoken. She raises a variety of other charges brought against
women by men, all of which are refuted by Lady Rectitude’s appeal to
experience and numerous examples. These include women’s inconstancy,
infidelity, coquettishness, and greed (BCL, II.66.1–67.2).
Eventually, Rectitude announces that she has finished building the houses
and palaces of the city: “Now a New Kingdom of Femininity is begun” (BCL,
II.12.1). She explains that after it has been populated with noble citizens –
women of “integrity, of great beauty and authority” – Lady Justice leads in
the high princesses and the “Queen of Heaven” who announces: “I am and
will always be the head of the feminine sex. This arrangement was present
in the mind of God the Father from the start, revealed and ordained previously
in the council of the Trinity” (BCL, III.1.3).
Christine ends the book in a manner that must disappoint modern feminists. She advises the women not to “scorn being subject to your husbands”
(BCL, III.19.1–2). If their husbands are good or moderate, they should praise
God; if their husbands are “cruel, mean, and savage,” they should display
forbearance and attempt to lead them back to a life of reason and virtue
(BCL, III.19.2). She admonishes: “all women – whether noble, bourgeois,
or lower-class – be well-informed in all things and cautious in defending
your honor” (BCL, III.19.6). Modern feminists might also view the city as
a form of ghettoization, whereby women are protected from the evils of male
The Later Middle Ages
75
institutions at the cost of foregoing any active and transformative participation. The reverse side is that women are allowed the space they need, the
room, to extricate themselves from the male writing of their history and to
rearticulate that history without interference.
Notes
1. Perry Anderson, Passages from Antiquity to Feudalism (London: Verso, 1985),
p. 140. Hereafter cited as PF.
2. “Introduction,” in Medieval Literary Theory and Criticism, c.1100–c.1375: The
Commentary Tradition, ed. A. J. Minnis, A. B. Scott, and David Wallace (Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1988), p. 5.
3. Ernst Robert Curtius, European Literature and the Latin Middle Ages, trans.
Willard R. Trask (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1979), pp. 54–55.
Hereafter cited as Curtius.
4. See Martin Irvine, The Making of Textual Culture: “Grammatica” and Literary
Theory, 350–1100 (Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press,
1994), pp. 17–19. Hereafter cited as GLT.
5. See “Introduction,” in Medieval Literary Criticism: Translations and Interpretations, ed. O. B. Hardison, Jr. (New York: Frederick Ungar, 1974), p. 10. Hereafter
cited as MLC.
6. The Didascalicon of Hugh of St. Victor, trans. Jerome Taylor (New York:
Columbia University Press, 1991), II.I. Hereafter cited as DHV.
7. The Metalogicon of John of Salisbury: A Twelfth-Century Defense of the Verbal
and Logical Arts of the Trivium, trans. Daniel D. McGarry (Gloucester, MA:
Peter Smith, 1971), pp. 9–12. Hereafter cited as ML.
8. “Introduction,” in Geoffrey of Vinsauf, Poetria Nova, trans. Margaret F. Nims
(Toronto and Wetteren, Belgium: Universa Press, 1967), pp. 10–11. Hereafter
cited as PN.
9. See W. Montgomery Watt, Islamic Philosophy and Theology (Edinburgh:
Edinburgh University Press, 1985), pp. 117–119.
10. Averro€es, “The Middle Commentary of Averroes of Cordova on the Poetics of
Aristotle,” in MLC, 89.
11. An Introduction to the Metaphysics of St. Thomas Aquinas: Texts Selected and
Translated, preface by James F. Anderson (Indiana: Regnery/Gateway, 1953),
pp. 109–117. Hereafter cited as MTA.
12. Umberto Eco, The Aesthetics of Thomas Aquinas, trans. Hugh Bredin
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1988), p. 140. Hereafter cited as Eco.
13. Summa Theologica, trans. Fathers of the English Dominican Province,
1920–1931.
14. Dante, Il Convivio: The Banquet, trans. Richard H. Lansing (New York and
London: Garland, 1990), II.i.1, 20–60. Hereafter cited as IC.
15. “The Letter to Can Grande,” in Literary Criticism of Dante Alighieri, trans.
Robert S. Haller (Nebraska: University of Nebraska Press, 1973), par. 5. Hereafter cited as “LCG,” with numbers referring to paragraphs.
76
The Medieval Era
16. Charles G. Osgood, “Introduction,” in Boccaccio on Poetry: Being the Preface
and the Fourteenth and Fifteenth Books of Boccaccio’s Genealogia Deorum
Gentilium (Indianapolis and New York: Bobbs-Merrill, 1956), p. xxx. Hereafter
cited as GDG.
17. “Introduction,” in Christine de Pizan, The Book of the City of Ladies, trans. Earl
Jeffrey Richards (New York: Persea Books, 1982), pp. xix, xxvii. Hereafter cited
as BCL.
Part III
The Early Modern Period to the
Enlightenment
Literary Criticism from Plato to the Present: An Introduction
© 2011 M. A. R. Habib. ISBN: 978-1-405-16034-6
M. A. R. Habib
Chapter 6
The Early Modern Period
Historical Background
The period from around the fourteenth until the mid-seventeenth century has
conventionally been designated as the Renaissance, referring to a “rebirth” or
rediscovery of the values, ethics, and styles of classical Greece and Rome. The
term was devised by Italian humanists who sought to reaffirm their own
continuity with the classical humanist heritage after an interlude of over a
thousand years, a period of alleged superstition and stagnation known as the
Dark Ages and Middle Ages. In this view, the Renaissance overturned the
medieval theological world view, replacing it with a more secular and
humanist vision, promoting a newly awakened interest in the temporal world
both in economic and in scientific terms, and according a new importance to
the individual – all inspired by a rediscovery of the classics. This view has been
somewhat shaken, with even the term “Renaissance” often being replaced by
the broader and more neutral term “early modern.” Historians and scholars
now recognize that many developments in the Renaissance were in fact
continuations or modifications of medieval dispositions. For example, medieval scholasticism and Renaissance humanism are no longer viewed as entirely
distinct. Nonetheless, as David Norbrook argues, the term “Renaissance”
may facilitate our understanding of how modernity changed the world.1
The early modern period certainly bore distinctive traits marking it as an
era of profound transformation. The most dominant trait has conventionally
been identified as “humanism,” a term ultimately deriving from Cicero and
used by Italian thinkers and writers to distinguish themselves from the
medieval scholastics. The term “humanism” implies a world view and a set
of values centered around the human rather than the divine, using a selfsubsistent definition of human nature (rather than referring this to God), and
focusing on human achievements and potential rather than theological
doctrines and dilemmas; the term also retained its Ciceronian connection
with the liberal arts (one of the original definitions of a humanist was a teacher
Literary Criticism from Plato to the Present: An Introduction
© 2011 M. A. R. Habib. ISBN: 978-1-405-16034-6
M. A. R. Habib
80
The Early Modern Period to the Enlightenment
of the humanities) and in general with secular and independent inquiry in all
fields, as opposed to viewing these areas of study as hierarchically bound
within a theological framework.
However, Renaissance humanism itself was only one manifestation of a
more profound shift in sensibility, from a broadly “other-worldly” disposition – viewing this earthly life as a merely transitory phase, as a preparation
for the life hereafter – to a “this-worldly” attitude which saw actions and
events in this world as significant in their own right without referring them to
any ultimate divine meaning and purpose. This shift from “otherworldliness” to “this-worldliness” both underlies and reflects the major
transformations of the early modern period. The most fundamental of these
changes were economic and political: the fundamental institutions of the later
Middle Ages – the feudal system, the universal authority of the pope, the Holy
Roman Empire, and the system of trade regulated by medieval guilds – were
all undermined. As a result of large-scale investment of capital, booming
manufacture, and expanding trade and commerce, the focus of economic life
increasingly shifted away from the manorial estates of the feudal nobility to
the newly emerging cities such as Florence, Milan, Venice, Rome, Paris, and
London, whose affluence enabled their prominence as centers of cultural
efflorescence. Many factors contributed to the decline of feudalism: the rise of
monarchies and centralized governments; the weakening of the feudal nobility; the rise of an increasingly powerful middle class; and the birth of our
modern secular conception of the state which promoted a new “civic consciousness,” returning to classical political ideals of civic humanism.
These developments were decisive in shaping the literature and criticism of
the period. There was a more pronounced focus on style and aesthetics, as
opposed to theology or logic. Most of the literary and artistic accomplishments of this period were achieved by laymen rather than clergy, with secular
patrons. Nearly all of the poets of this era were actively involved in the
political process, and formed an important constituent of the “public
sphere,” the arena of public debate and discourse which began to emerge
during the later Renaissance. English poets, for example, wrote vehemently in
favor of both royalist and parliamentary sides during the English Civil War;
Milton (1608–1674) was the leading literary advocate of the Puritan revolution, and his epic Paradise Lost celebrated the Protestant notion of the
individual’s moral responsibility, while his Areopagitica (1644) was a passionate defense of free speech.
Intellectual Background
Humanism and the Classics
The early modern period witnessed the growth of a new secular class of
educated people and a more secular employment of the classics in fields such
The Early Modern Period
81
as rhetoric and law. The most distinguished humanists of this period included
Albertino Mussato, who is credited with writing the first tragedy of this
period, and, even more important, Francesco Petrarca (1304–1374), who
outlined a curriculum of classical studies. A major difference between
medieval and humanist attitudes to the classics was that the latter insisted
upon a thorough knowledge of the classical languages: not only Latin, but
also Greek. The humanists also insisted on the direct study – without glosses –
of ancient texts, which were now far more widely disseminated. Finally, the
monopoly of Latin as the language of learned discourse and literature was
undermined, and in the works of Dante, Petrarch, Boccaccio, and many
humanists, the rules of grammar and composition were adapted to theorize
about vernacular tongues. In general, the humanists supplanted the scholastic
aversion to poetry and rhetoric with an emphasis upon the moral value of
these disciplines and upon worldly achievement in general.
The new poets not only theorized about the vernacular but wrote in it and
cultivated its elegant expression. Petrarch’s friend Giovanni Boccaccio
(1313–1375) adapted classical forms to the vernacular, developing literary
forms such as the pastoral, idyll, and romance. Through his best-known
works such as the Decameron, Boccaccio provided models of Italian prose
which influenced both Italian writers such as Tasso and writers in other
countries such as Chaucer. The cultivation of prose – in narratives, epistles,
and dialogues – was an important achievement of the humanists. A renowned
example is Baldassare Castiglione’s treatise entitled The Courtier, a discussion of attitudes toward love, and of the courtly behavior and education
appropriate for a gentleman. The Renaissance epic reached its height in the
Orlando Furioso of Ludovico Ariosto (1474–1533), which departs from the
idealistic and moralistic nature of medieval epics. Historiography and political writing also achieved a new level of realism: Machiavelli wrote a
history of Florence that was free of theological explanations and based upon
“natural” laws. Machiavelli’s political writings entirely undermined medieval notions of government: in his treatise The Prince (1513), he saw the state
as an independent entity, whose prime goal was the promotion of civic rather
than religious virtue, and self-preservation at any cost. An even more
important figure in historiography was Francesco Guicciardini
(1483–1540) whose History of Italy is characterized by realistic, detailed
analysis of character, motive, and events. Lorenzo Valla (1406–1457) applied
critical methods of scholarship and analysis to biblical texts, and he challenged the authenticity of certain authoritative documents, opening the way
for later attacks upon Christian doctrine.
Humanism flourished also in other parts of Europe. The Dutch thinker
Desiderius Erasmus (1466–1536) was renowned for his strong humanistic
convictions in reason, naturalism, tolerance, and the inherent goodness of
man, which led him to oppose dogmatic theology and scholasticism, and to
propound instead a rational religion of simple piety based on the example of
82
The Early Modern Period to the Enlightenment
Christ. His most famous work, Encomium moriae (The Praise of Folly,
1509), satirized theological dogmatism and the gullibility of the masses.
France also produced notable figures such as François Rabelais (1490–1553),
whose Gargantua and Pantagruel expounded a naturalistic and secular
philosophy glorifying humanity and ridiculing scholastic theology, Church
abuses, and all forms of bigotry. In England, the most renowned humanist
was Sir Thomas More (1478–1535), whose Utopia (1516) was a thinly veiled
condemnation of the social and economic defects of his time: religious
intolerance, financial greed, the glaring discrepancy between rich and poor,
the notions of conquest, imperialism, and war.
The humanist tradition was richly expressed in the rise of English vernacular literature of this period. Even Chaucer, often treated as a medieval writer,
expressed a somewhat secular humanistic vision in his Canterbury Tales,
which tends to bypass simple moralism in the interest of broader stylistic ends
such as verisimilitude and realistic portrayal of character, situation, and
motive. English drama achieved unprecedented heights in the work of
Christopher Marlowe (1564–1593), Ben Jonson (1573–1637), and William
Shakespeare (1564–1616). Marlowe’s Doctor Faustus expresses an overwhelming craving for experience and a humanistic desire to subjugate the
world to human intellection and ingenuity. Shakespeare’s plays expressed not
only a profound analysis of human character and emotion but embodied the
vast struggle between the values of a declining feudal system and an emerging
bourgeois structure of values. The rise of national consciousness in many
countries during this period was reflected in the growth of vernacular
literatures in Italy, England, France, Germany, and Spain.
Philosophy and science
As well as returning to classical rhetoric, the humanists promoted the revival
of other ancient philosophies such as Platonism. In fact, the major philosophers of this period, such as Marsilio Ficino (1433–1499) and Pico della
Mirandola (1463–1494), were Neo-Platonists. Other thinkers such as Lorenzo Valla revived the ancient movements of Epicureanism, Stoicism, and
skepticism. In France, Michel de Montaigne (1533–1592) expounded a
philosophy of skepticism. The most renowned English philosopher of this
period was Sir Francis Bacon (1561–1626), who was the forerunner of the
empiricist tradition in Britain, urging the use of the inductive method and
direct observation as against scholastic reliance upon authority, faith, and
deductive reasoning.
A major distinction between the medieval and early modern periods lies in a
momentous transformation in scientific outlook. Medieval cosmology and
scholastic theology were premised on a Ptolemaic geocentric view of the earth
as being at the center of the universe, surrounded by a series of seven
The Early Modern Period
83
concentric spheres (the orbits of the planets), beyond which was the Empyrean and the throne of God, who was the “unmoved Mover” and the “First
Cause” of all things. The universe was thought to be composed of four
elements – earth, air, fire, and water – combined in varying proportions; and
human beings were constituted by four “humors.” The earth, as in Dante’s
Divine Comedy, was thought to be populated only in its northern hemisphere,
which was composed of Asia, Africa, and Europe. This world view, based
largely on the physics and metaphysics of Aristotle, was shattered in the early
modern era by the heliocentric theory of Nicholas Copernicus (1473–1543),
whose truth was demonstrated by Galileo Galilei (1564–1642), and thus
paved the way for modern mechanistic (rather than spiritual) conceptions of
the universe. A particularly significant invention of this time was that of
printing, developed in Germany by Johannes Gutenberg and spreading
quickly through Europe.
Religion
One of the most profound and vast transformations in the early modern
period was the Protestant Reformation, erupting in 1517 and resulting in a
major schism in the Christian world. Most of Northern Europe broke away
from Roman Catholicism and the authority of the pope. There also occurred
the Catholic Reformation (sometimes known as the Counter-Reformation)
which reached its most fervent intensity in the mid-sixteenth century, changing the shape of Catholicism considerably from its medieval character.
National consciousness played an even more integral role in the Reformation
since the Protestant cause was affiliated with reaction against a system of
ecclesiastical control at whose apex sat the pope.
While it may have been immediately incited by abuses within the Catholic
Church – such as the amassing of wealth for private self-interests, the sale of
indulgences, and the veneration of material objects as holy relics – the
Protestant Reformation was directed in essence against some of the cardinal
tenets of medieval theology, such as its theory of the sacraments, its elaborate
ecclesiastical hierarchy of intermediation between God and human beings,
and its insistence that religious faith must be complemented by good deeds. As
seen earlier, medieval theology had been broadly propagated through two
systems: the theology of the early Middle Ages had been based on the
teachings of St. Augustine that man is fallen (through original sin), his will
is depraved, and that only those whom God has so predestined can attain
eternal salvation. This somewhat fatalistic system was largely supplanted in
the twelfth and thirteenth centuries by the theologies of Peter Lombard and
Thomas Aquinas, which acknowledged man’s free will, but urged that he
needed divine grace to attain salvation. Such grace was furnished to man
through the sacraments, such as baptism, penance, and the Eucharist or mass.
84
The Early Modern Period to the Enlightenment
It was the ecclesiastical hierarchy, tracing its authority all the way through the
pope to the apostle Peter, which had the power to administer these sacraments
and hence to gain access to divine grace.
The Protestant Reformers such as Martin Luther reacted against this
complex system of intermediation between God and man, advocating a
return to the actual doctrines of the scriptures and the writings of the Church
Fathers such as Augustine. They rejected the theory of the priesthood as well
as worship of the Virgin, the intermediation of the saints, and the reverence
for sacred relics. In general, they returned to the Augustinian visions of
original sin, the depraved state of man’s will, and, in the case of Calvinism, a
strong belief in predestination.
Martin Luther’s central doctrine was “justification by faith”: man’s sins are
remitted and his salvation achieved through faith alone, not through good
works. In effect, Luther emphasized the primacy of individual conscience, and
the directness of man’s relation with God, unmediated by priests, saints,
relics, or pilgrimages to shrines. Luther’s views were denounced as heretical
and in 1521 he was excommunicated. Germany was swept by a series of
uprisings culminating in the Peasants’ Revolt of 1524–1525. A Protestant
Revolution in Switzerland was incited by Ulrich Zwingli (1484–1531) and
the Frenchman John Calvin (1509–1564); the latter strongly reaffirmed the
Augustinian doctrine of predestination, whereby God has already predestined his elect for salvation, and the remainder to damnation. However,
Calvin taught that, while none can know whether he is of the elect or damned,
a “sign” of election is a life of piety, good works, and abstinence. Ironically, as
Max Weber was to argue, the influence of Calvin’s world view and the
“Protestant ethic” – which could be used to sanction the worldly activities of
disciplined trading and commerce – played an integral role in the rise of
capitalism. The Catholic Reformation resulted eventually in a redefinition of
Catholic doctrines at the Council of Trent (1545–1563), convened by Pope
Paul III.
These momentous religious transformations induced a vast schism in the
Christian world: northern Germany and Scandinavia became Lutheran;
England adopted a compromise, integrating Catholic doctrine with allegiance to the English crown; Calvinism held sway in Scotland, Holland,
and French Switzerland. The countries still expressing allegiance to the
pope now numbered only Italy, France, Spain, Portugal, Austria, Poland,
Ireland, and southern Germany. The Protestant Reformation promoted not
only individualism but also nationalism (as coextensive with independence
from the Church at Rome), increased sanction for bourgeois thought and
practice, as well as a broader education accessible to more of the masses.
Many of the values of Protestantism and humanism overlapped or reinforced each other: these included self-discipline, industry, and intellectual
achievement.
The Early Modern Period
85
Literary criticism
Just as many of our own institutions are descended from the early modern
period, much of our own literary criticism, and indeed the very notion of
criticism as a relatively autonomous domain, derives from this era. In
particular, the rise of the independent state and of a liberal bourgeoisie
enabled the pervasive growth of humanist culture and of national sentiment;
the literature and criticism of the period tends to reflect civic values, a sense of
national identity, and a sense of place in history, especially as gauged in
relation to the classics. The technology of the period, such as the development
and dissemination of printing, transformed the conditions of reading, facilitating the process of editing (of especially classical texts), and vastly extending the sphere of the reading public. The innovative characteristics of
Renaissance literary criticism included moving away from the scholastic
fourfold allegorical structure to a view of language as historically evolving.
Such a shift entailed new approaches to reading and interpretation.2
In our own day, and especially in Western culture, where poetry and good
literature have been marginalized, it is easy to forget how deeply poetry and
literary criticism were embroiled in the political process during the Renaissance. As David Norbrook explains, poets engaged fervently in the emerging
“public sphere,” a realm of debate in which citizens could participate as
equals, independently of pressure from monopolies of power.3 The expansion of the public sphere enabled the poet to create fictive and utopian
worlds, to mold the image of public events (as in Marvell’s “Horatian
Ode”), and to assert an individualism that was also promoted by Protestantism; the translation of the Bible into vernacular languages shifted
interpretative authority away from the clergy to the individual reader. In
such a climate, poets and critics inevitably placed emphasis on the practical
and social functions of poetry and its dependence on rhetorical strategies
(PBRV, 9, 11, 13–15).
Indeed, much Renaissance criticism was forged in the struggle to defend
poetry and literature from charges – brought within both clerical and secular
circles – of immorality, triviality, and irrelevance to practical and political
life. The types of criticism proliferating in the early modern period also
included a large body of humanist commentary and scholarship on classical
texts. The most influential classical treatises during the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries were Aristotle’s Poetics and Horace’s Ars poetica. A third
important body of criticism in this period is comprised of commentaries on
Aristotle’s Poetics and debates between the relative virtues of the Aristotelian
and Horatian texts as well as attempts to harmonize their insights. Alongside
Aristotle and Horace, the influential rhetorical voices of Cicero and Quintilian were recovered in the early fifteenth century: Renaissance critics tended
to adapt, and even distort, these voices to their own needs.
86
The Early Modern Period to the Enlightenment
Almost all of these defenses, commentaries, and debates concern a number
of fundamental notions: imitation (of both the external world and the tradition
of classical authors); the truth-value and didactic role of literature; the classical
“unities”; the notion of verisimilitude; the use of the vernacular; the definition
of poetic genres such as narrative and drama; the invention of new, mixed
genres such as the romantic epic and the tragicomedy; the use of rhyme in
poetry; the relative values of quantitative and qualitative verse; and the place of
literature and poetry in relation to other disciplines such as moral philosophy
and history. In the sections below, we shall look at the treatment of these issues
by some of the influential writers of the period. It will be useful to divide them
into three broad categories. The first set of writers, all Italian (Giraldi,
Castelvetro, Mazzoni and Tasso), are concerned to reformulate their connections with the classical tradition; the second group, comprising both French
and English writers (Du Bellay and Sidney), endeavors to defend poetry and the
use of the vernacular; the third, represented here by Gascoigne and Puttenham,
aims to define the art of poetry, drawing on the traditions of rhetoric. In many
of these writers, the promotion of the vernacular and the very definition of the
poetic is intrinsically tied to their political and often nationalistic affiliations.
Confronting the Classical Heritage
A new and powerful stimulus to literary criticism arose when the Greek text of
the Poetics was made available in 1508 and translated into Latin in 1536
(previously it had been available only through an Arabic commentary by the
Islamic philosopher Ibn Rushd). A number of editions of Horace’s Ars poetica
were circulated. While poetics had overlapped increasingly with rhetoric, as
evident in the work of Renaissance writers such as Minturno, Scaliger, Du
Bellay, and Puttenham, the recovery of Aristotle’s text fostered a new
examination of literary form and organic unity that was not wholly grounded
in rhetoric. Many commentaries on Aristotle appeared during the sixteenth
century. Somewhat ironically (given the availability of the actual text of
Aristotle’s Poetics), many writers saw literature as Ibn Rushd had, as
exercising a moral function through the depiction of virtue and vice; they
combined this with Horace’s precept that literature should also please; hence
the formula that literature should “teach and delight” (used by Sidney)
pervaded the thinking of this era.
Renaissance writers added the doctrine of the unity of place to Aristotle’s
original demand for the unity of action and time; debates over these unities
encompassed the discussion of classical genres, notably the lyric, epic,
tragedy, and comedy, as well as mixed genres such as the romantic epic and
the tragicomedy. The newer, characteristically humanist, genres also included the essay and the dialogue form, as well as increasing focus on the epigram
The Early Modern Period
87
as an instrument of wit. As will be seen in the writers now to be examined, the
treatment of these issues displayed emphatically how each writer’s adaptation
of classical norms was fueled by specific contemporary agendas.
Giambattista Giraldi (1504–1573)
The Italian dramatist, poet, and literary critic Giraldi advocated a new genre,
the romance, a lengthy narrative poem which combined elements of the
classical epic with those of medieval romances. The most noteworthy
contemporary example of such a romance was Ariosto’s Orlando Furioso
(1516). Hence Giraldi was effectively involved in a quarrel between
“ancients” and “moderns” which was to last for many centuries. Giraldi’s
leaning toward the modern is shown in a number of ways. To begin with, he
tends to view literature in a historical context, which means that classical
values are not necessarily applicable to all ages. He also reacted, both in his
dramas and in his theory, against many of Aristotle’s prescriptions for
tragedy, such as unity of action and unity of time. His literary criticism, of
which his Discorso intorno al comporre dei romanzi (1554; Discourse on the
Composition of Romances) was the most controversial and influential,
anticipates the views of Coleridge, Mazzoni, and Du Bellay.
In his Discourse Giraldi states unapologetically that romances directly
contravene Aristotle’s precept that an epic should imitate a single action.
Romances deal not only with many actions but with many characters,
building “the whole fabric of their work upon eight or ten persons.”4 Giraldi
pointedly remarks that the romance came neither from the Greeks nor from
the Romans but “laudably from our own language.” The great writers of this
language, he adds, gave to this genre “the same authority” that Homer and
Vergil gave to their epics. Giraldi strikes a Romantic and modern tone when
he insists that authors should not limit their freedom by restricting themselves
within the bounds of their predecessors’ rules (DCR, 39). His arguments here
have a nationalistic strain: the Tuscan poets, he maintains, need not be bound
by the poetic forms or literary confines of the Greeks and Romans (DCR, 40).
As regards the civil function of the poet, Giraldi insists that poetry must
“praise virtuous actions and censure the vicious” (DCR, 52). But the poet
should observe the classical virtues of decorum and moderation in the use of
figures such as allegory (DCR, 56, 67). Hence, Giraldi attempts a balance or
compromise between classical virtues and contemporary artistic needs.
Lodovico Castelvetro (1505–1571)
Castelvetro is best known for his stringent reformulation of Aristotle’s unities
of time and place in drama, his rigid approach being subsequently endorsed
by neoclassical writers. As against a long critical tradition, deriving in part
88
The Early Modern Period to the Enlightenment
from Horace, that the function of poetry was to be “useful” as well as to
entertain, Castelvetro insisted, in a strikingly modern pose, that the sole end
of poetry was to yield pleasure, especially for the common people. Moreover,
the poet, he insisted, is made, not born or possessed by a Platonic furor: his
creations are the product of study, training, and art.5 In general, Castelvetro
agrees with Aristotle’s doctrine of the unities but offers a different rationale.
On the unity of time, he agrees with Aristotle that a tragic plot must not
exceed “one revolution of the sun,” which Castelvetro takes to be 12 hours.
But the real reason for this is not, as Aristotle held, the audience’s limited
memory, but the requirement of realism (PA, 82, 87).
Castelvetro accepts Aristotle’s definition of the unity of a plot as consisting
of a “single action of a single person” or, at most two actions which are closely
interrelated (PA, 87, 89). But he finds no rationale in Aristotle for this; his own
rationale is, firstly, that the temporal limitation of 12 hours on tragedy will
not allow the representation of many actions; and, secondly, that the epic poet
who restricts his representations to one action will all the more exhibit his
“judgment and skill” (PA, 89–90). Moreover, Castelvetro appears to extrapolate the Aristotelian unity of time to extend to space: the action “must be
set in a place no larger than the stage on which the actors perform and in a
period of time no longer than that which is filled by their performance” (PA,
243). As this last sentence indicates, Castelvetro reformulates Aristotle’s
notion of the unities into a prescription for detailed realism. However, he
agrees with Aristotle’s general requirement that the poet represent the
probable and the necessary.
Giacopo Mazzoni (1548–1598)
In his essay Della difesa della Commedia di Dante (1587; On the Defense of
the Comedy of Dante), the Italian scholar Giacopo Mazzoni defended
Dante’s allegory against critics who condemned it as fantastic and unreal;
he also formulated a comprehensive and systematic aesthetics of poetic
imitation. Mazzoni draws upon a distinction made by Plato in his dialogue,
the Sophist, between two kinds of imitation. The first, which imitates actual
things, is “icastic”; the second, which imitates things of the artist’s invention,
is “phantastic.”6 In general, Mazzoni sees poetry as a “sophistic” or rhetorical art, whose proper genus is imitation, whose subject is the “credible,” and
whose end or purpose is delight (DCD, 85). According to Mazzoni, poetry
can be viewed, in three different modes, as having three different ends or
purposes: in its mode of imitation, its end is to provide a correct imitation or
representation; considered as amusement, poetry’s purpose is simply to
produce delight; thirdly, it can be considered as “amusement directed, ruled,
and defined by the civil faculty” (DCD, 95). In this mode, poetry has
usefulness or moral betterment as its purpose: it “orders the appetite and
The Early Modern Period
89
submits it to the reason” (DCD, 98). Mazzoni uses this threefold definition of
poetry to answer Plato’s charges against poetry. The sort of poetry banished
by Plato, says Mazzoni, was that which, unregulated by the civil faculty,
produced a “free” delight which “disordered the appetite . . . producing
complete rebellion against reason and bringing damage and loss to a virtuous
life” (DCD, 97).
A final strategy of Mazzoni’s text is its attempt to rescue rhetoric from its
scandalous reputation and to name poetry as a species of such a redeemed
rhetoric. The redemption of both rhetoric and poetry rests upon Mazzoni’s
redefinition of their connection with truth; he deploys Aristotle’s text to show
that, as far as these disciplines are concerned, it is credibility rather than truth
which stands as an appropriate ideal. In this insistence also, Mazzoni is
modern, rescuing sophism, relativism, and author–audience interaction from
the tyranny of absolute truth imposed by Plato and his successors.
Torquato Tasso (1544–1595)
Tasso is best known for his epic poem Jerusalem Delivered (1581), revised
into a longer version, Jersualem Conquered. Tasso also wrote a long critical
treatise Discorsi del Poema Eroica (1594; Discourses on the Heroic Poem),
which defended his vernacular epic and which had a considerable impact not
only on Renaissance but also on subsequent literary theory in Italy, England,
and France.
In this text Tasso takes up the question of the relative merits of epic and
tragedy, and of course, for him, it is the epic poem that must be accorded the
higher honor. The epic poem provides its own distinctive delight, a delight
produced through metaphor and the other figures of speech.7 In arguing the
superiority of epic, Tasso is challenging the authority of Aristotle who urged
the superiority of tragedy given that it has all of the elements of epic but in
greater concentration and unity. Tasso suggests that he is parting company
with Aristotle in a few matters so that he “may not abandon him in things of
greater moment, that is, in the desire to discover truth and in the love of
philosophy” (DHP, 205). It is perhaps characteristic of his status as a
Renaissance theorist that Tasso builds his own theory of epic on the foundation of Aristotle’s poetics by refashioning that very foundation to serve his
own purpose.
Defending the Vernacular
Notwithstanding the humanist reverence for the classics, many of the most
illustrious minds of the Renaissance and Middle Ages, including such writers
as Dante, Petrarch, Boccaccio, William Langland, John Gower, and Geoffrey
90
The Early Modern Period to the Enlightenment
Chaucer, wrote in the vernacular; some of these, such as Petrarch and Dante,
felt called upon to theorize and defend their practice. Ironically, humanism
itself had done much to undermine the authority of grammatica by dismantling the edifice of late medieval scholasticism and the peculiar legacy of
Aristotle informing it. Much of the impetus for this self-extrication from the
imperial language of Latin lay in nationalist sentiment, and the sixteenth
century witnessed the growth of national literatures in several countries,
notably Italy, England, France, and Germany. The Protestant Reformation
not only fueled such nationalist sympathy but fostered vernacular translations of the Bible as well as of liturgies and hymns, which in some cases laid
broad foundations for the development of national languages. “National”
epics were written by many of the major poets of the period, including
Ariosto, Tasso, Ronsard, Spenser, and Milton. These writers were obliged to
address controversial issues of meter, rhyming, and versification in vernacular
tongues, as can be seen in the work of Du Bellay.
Joachim Du Bellay (ca. 1522–1560)
Du Bellay’s Defence and Illustration of the French Language (1549) aimed to
justify the French vernacular by basing it upon a new poetics such that it could
match the gravity and decorum of the classical Greek and Latin languages. Du
Bellay acknowledges that some languages have indeed become richer than
others, but the reason for this is not their intrinsic virtue but the “artifice and
industry of men.”8 He argues that the degradation of the French language is
deeply rooted in a history of imperialism, not only in the military subjugation
of other nations but in their cultural and linguistic subjugation. Du Bellay
expresses the hope – no less political than cultural – that “when this noble and
puissant kingdom will in its turn obtain the reins of sovereignty,” the French
language may “rise to such height and greatness, that it can equal the Greeks
themselves and the Romans” (NTC, 283–284). Again, Du Bellay’s text
clearly connects cultural greatness with political and economic power. In
a lengthy apostrophe to the future French poet, Du Bellay calls upon him to
leave behind all popular verse forms and songs; to “turn the leaves of your
Greek and Latin exemplars”; and, following Horace, to “mingle the profitable with the agreeable.” For his subject matter, the poet should take praises
of the gods and virtuous men, and the “immutable order of earthly things”
(NTC, 289).
In some ways, Du Bellay’s message is deeply conservative and traditional.
While he calls for a renovation and enrichment of French language and
literature, such elevation is focused entirely on a return to classical seriousness, gravity, and form. The only novel feature of his vision is the insistence
that, by returning to the resources and archetypes of the classical languages,
the French language might fulfill its potential to displace them and dislodge
The Early Modern Period
91
them from their positions of cultural sovereignty. Together with Ronsard and
other members of the Pleiade, Du Bellay helped inaugurate a new era of
French poetry.
Poetics and the Defense of Poetry
Following Boccaccio’s and Du Bellay’s endeavors, notable defenses of poetry
were undertaken by many writers. Such apologiae and defenses have been
obliged to continue through the nineteenth century into our own day,
highlighting the fact that the category of the “aesthetic,” as a domain
struggling to free itself from the constraints of theology, morality, politics,
philosophy, and history, was in part a result of Renaissance poetics. Integral
to many of these defenses was a formula adapted from Horace that poetry
must teach and delight, as in the work of Sidney.
Sir Philip Sidney (1554–1586)
Sir Philip Sidney is often cited as an archetype of the well-rounded
“Renaissance man”: his talents encompassed not only poetry and cultivated
learning but the virtues of statesmanship and military service. He was
involved in a war waged by Queen Elizabeth I against Spain and died from
a wound at the age of 32. He wrote a pastoral romance, The Countess of
Pembroke’s Arcadia (1581), and he was original in producing a sonnet cycle
in the English language, entitled Astrophil and Stella (1581–1582).
Sidney’s Apologie for Poetrie (1580–1581) is in many ways a seminal text
of literary criticism. While its ideas are not original, it represents the first
synthesis in the English language of the various strands and concerns of
Renaissance literary criticism, drawing on Aristotle, Horace, and more recent
writers such as Boccaccio and Julius Caesar Scaliger. It raises issues – such as
the value and function of poetry, the nature of imitation, and the concept of
nature – which were to concern literary critics in numerous languages until
the late eighteenth century. Sidney’s writing of the Apologie as a defense of
poetry was occasioned by an attack on poetry entitled The School of Abuse
published in 1579 by a Puritan minister, Stephen Gosson.
In the Apologie, Sidney produces a wide range of arguments in defense of
“poor Poetry,” based on chronology, the authority of ancient tradition, the
relation of poetry to nature, the function of poetry as imitation, the status of
poetry among the various disciplines of learning, and the relationship of
poetry to truth and morality. Sidney’s initial argument is that poetry was the
first form in which knowledge was expressed, the “first light-giver to
ignorance,” as bodied forth by figures such as Musaeus, Homer, Hesiod,
Livius, Ennius, Dante, Boccaccio, and Petrarch.9 His point is that an
92
The Early Modern Period to the Enlightenment
essential prerequisite of knowledge is pleasure in learning; and it is poetry
that has made each of these varieties of knowledge – scientific, moral,
philosophical, political – accessible by expressing them in pleasurable forms
(APP, 218).
Sidney’s second argument is an “argument from tradition” since it appeals
to the ancient Roman and Greek reverence for poetry. The Roman term for
the poet was vates, meaning “diviner, fore-seer, or prophet.” The ancient
Greek definition of poetry is even more important: the Greek origin of the
English word “poet” was the word poiein, meaning “to make.” Whereas
other arts and sciences are constrained, examining a particular area or aspect
of nature, the poet ranges freely “within the zodiac of his own wit.” As such,
the poet’s “making” or production is superior to nature: “Nature never set
forth the earth in so rich tapestry, as divers poets have done . . . Her world is
brazen, the poets only deliver a golden” (APP, 219–221).
Sidney situates this human creativity in a theological context. Though man
is a “maker” or poet, his ability derives from his “heavenly Maker . . . who
having made man to his own likeness, set him beyond and over all the works
of that second nature, which in nothing he showeth so much as in poetry:
when with the force of a divine breath, he bringeth things forth far surpassing
her doings.” Sidney goes on to refer to original sin, as a result of which “our
erected wit, maketh us know what perfection is, and yet our infected will,
keepeth us from reaching unto it” (APP, 222). Significant here is the intrinsic
connection between man’s ability to “make” poetry and his status in relation
to God. That man is made in the image of God is most profoundly expressed in
man’s replication, on a lower level, of God’s function as a creator. It also
implies that man is elevated above the world of physical nature (which Sidney
calls “second nature”).This God-like activity in man which exalts him above
the rest of nature is expressed above all in poetry.
Sidney defines poetry as “an art of imitation, for so Aristotle termeth it in
his word mimesis, that is to say, a representing, counterfeiting, or figuring
forth: to speak metaphorically, a speaking picture: with this end, to teach and
delight.” Sidney suggests that there have been three kinds of poetic imitation.
The first is religious, imitating “the inconceivable excellencies of God, as in
the Old Testament. The second is effected by poetry that deals with subjects
whose scope is philosophical, historical or scientific, such as the works of
Cato, Lucretius, Manilius, or Lucan. The third kind, urges Sidney, is produced by “right poets . . . who having no law but wit, bestow that in colors
upon you which is fittest for the eye to see.” These are the poets who “most
properly do imitate to teach and delight, and to imitate, borrow nothing of
what is, hath been, or shall be: but range only . . . into the divine consideration
of what may be, and should be” (APP, 223–224). Hence the poet is free of
dependence on nature in at least two ways: firstly, he is not restricted to any
given subject matter, any given sphere of nature. Secondly, his “imitation”
The Early Modern Period
93
does not actually reproduce anything in nature, since his concern is not with
actuality but with portrayals of probability and of idealized situations.
The ultimate aim of this kind of poetry is moral: the poet imitates, says
Sidney, in order “both to delight and teach.” The object of both teaching and
delighting is goodness. However, Sidney sees all learning, and not just poetry,
as directed to this final end or purpose. While all sciences have “a private end
in themselves,” the “ending end of all earthly learning” is “virtuous action.”
In leading the soul toward good, poetry is superior to its chief competitors,
moral philosophy and history. Both disciplines are one-sided: the philosopher
sets down the “bare rule” in difficult terms that are “abstract and general”;
the historian, conversely, lacks the force of generalization and is “tied, not to
what should be, but to what is, to the particular truth of things.” Sidney says
that “the one giveth the precept, and the other the example.” It is the “peerless
poet,” according to Sidney, who performs both functions: “he coupleth the
general notion with the particular example.” It is poetry which can strike the
soul and the inward sentiments by means of “a true lively knowledge” (APP,
226–230). The power of poetry to move or influence people, says Sidney, “is
of a higher degree than teaching.” For all of these reasons, proclaims Sidney,
we must set “the laurel crown upon the poet as victorious, not only of the
historian, but over the philosopher.” Sidney’s tone is repeatedly triumphalistic and persistent in attempting to overturn the conventional hierarchy of
knowledge: “of all sciences . . . is our poet the monarch” (APP, 235–236). The
irony here is that Sidney uses a theological justification for poetry to dethrone
theology and philosophy from their preeminent status. This is unmistakably a
step in the direction of secular humanism.
Sidney now addresses the specific charges brought against poetry. One of
the main charges is that poetry “is the mother of lies.” Sidney’s famous retort
is that “the poet . . . nothing affirms, and therefore never lieth.” Unlike the
historian, the poet does not claim to be telling the truth; he is not relating
“what is, or is not, but what should or should not be.” He is writing “not
affirmatively, but allegorically, and figuratively” (APP, 247–249). The most
serious charge that Sidney confronts is that Plato banished poets from his
ideal republic. He argues that Plato opposed the abuse of poetry rather than
the art itself (APP, 253–255). Sidney concludes by admonishing the reader
that “there are many mysteries contained in poetry, which of purpose were
written darkly, least by profane wits, it should be abused.” And he curses
those who are possessed of “so earth-creeping a mind, that it cannot lift itself
up, to look to the sky of poetry” (APP, 269–270). The metaphor here truly
encapsulates the entire thrust of Sidney’s text: formerly, sacred scripture was
spoken of in this fashion, as written “darkly,” so as to lie beyond the reach of
unworthy eyes; in Sidney’s text, poetry is elevated to that sacred status: in its
very nature it is opposed to worldliness and “earth-creeping” concerns; it is
the newly appointed heaven of human invention.
94
The Early Modern Period to the Enlightenment
Poetic Form and Rhetoric
Until the recovery of Aristotle’s Poetics which fostered a new examination
of literary form that was not wholly grounded in rhetoric, the domains of
poetics and rhetoric had increasingly overlapped. During the Renaissance,
rhetoric enjoyed a renewed centrality in educational institutions. Many of
the writers we have looked at, such as Du Bellay and Sidney, treated poetry
as a higher form of rhetoric and took from rhetorical theory an emphasis on
persuasiveness and the power to move an audience or reader. In returning to
classical precedents, Renaissance poets confronted other issues. They rejected the regular stress-based alliterative meter of medieval poets. Some
experimented with the idea of classical quantitative meters, based on length
of syllables rather than stress. In general, the humanists rejected rhyme as an
unclassical barbarism; the controversy over rhyme was salient in the debate
between Samuel Daniel, who wrote a Defence of Rhyme (1603), and
Thomas Campion, who rejected rhyme in favor of classical forms. The
aversion to rhyme on the part of figures such as William Webbe and George
Puttenham, who went so far as to affiliate the use of rhyme with a Roman
Catholic mentality, led to the search for a new metrical basis for English
poetry and eventually fueled the growth of blank verse. These tendencies,
including a rhetorical approach to poetic form, can now be considered as
they occurred on the English literary scene in the work of Gascoigne and
Puttenham.
George Gascoigne (1542–1577)
The poet and dramatist George Gascoigne is credited with having written the
first literary-critical essay in the English language, entitled “Certayne Notes of
Instruction Concerning the Making of Verse or Ryme in English” (1575).
Here, Gascoigne offers advice on a range of rhetorical issues, including
invention, prosody, verse form, and style. He stresses the need for “fine
invention,” or the finding of appropriate theme and material. It is not enough,
he says, “to roll in pleasant words,” or to indulge in alliterative “thunder.”10
Gascoigne insists that the poet must employ “some depth of device in the
invention, and some figures also in the handling thereof,” or else his work will
“appear to the skilful reader but a tale of a tub” (i.e., some trite or ordinary
matter) (ER, 163).
Gascoigne cautions against the use of “rhyme without reason” and advises
the poet to be consistent in his use of meter throughout a poem (ER, 164). He
admonishes the poet to situate every word such that it will receive its “natural
emphasis or sound . . . as it is commonly pronounced or used.” He indicates
the three types of accent, gravis (\) or the long accent, levis (/) or the short
The Early Modern Period
95
accent, and circumflexa () which is “indifferent,” capable of being either
long or short (ER, 164). He notes that the most common foot in English is the
foot of two syllables, the first short and the second long (the iambic foot), and
he encourages the use of the iambic pentameter (in which, as many other
writers have noted, the English language seems naturally to fall). Also
furthering the cause of a distinctive English verse is Gascoigne’s advice that
the poet avoid words of many syllables, since “the most ancient English words
are of one syllable, so that the more monosyllables that you use the truer
Englishman you shall seem, and the less you shall smell of the inkhorn” (ER,
166).11 Gascoigne urges the poet to find a middle ground between “haughty
obscure verse” and “verse that is too easy” (ER, 167). Much of the advice
offered by Gascoigne moves in the direction of both standardizing certain
English poetic and metrical practices and differentiating these from “foreign”
practices.
George Puttenham (d. 1590)
A long and influential treatise entitled The Arte of English Poesy, published
anonymously in 1589, is attributed to George Puttenham. The central
purpose of this treatise is to justify the use of the vernacular language for
poetry, and specifically to establish English vernacular poetry as an art,
requiring serious study and labor. The Arte is divided into three books, the
first justifying poetry as expressing the needs of individual and society; the
second, “Of Proportion,” devoted to the craft of poetry; and the third, “Of
Ornament,” offering a renaming of the figures and tropes of classical rhetoric.
Puttenham was writing at the advent of a great period of English letters, and
his text amply exhibits how early English criticism was tied to certain
controversies over language (such as the desirability of importing terms from
Greek, Latin, and other languages), as well as to the emerging perception of
certain features of English verse, such as the emphasis on stress of syllables. It
might be said that Puttenham’s treatise not only contributed to the idea of a
“standard” English, but also founded and enabled some of the terminology of
early modern literary criticism in English. Terms such as “ode,” “lyric,” and
“epigrammatist” were brought into standard currency partly through the
agency and influence of Puttenham’s text.12
Importantly, Puttenham sees the English line of verse as based on meter and
rhyme, and moves toward a perception of the function of stress in English
verse (AEP, 78–80). Classifying the various meters used at this time, he
furnishes effectively the first English prosody. His chapter “Of Language” is a
locus classicus of the issue of standard English. He sees a point at which a
language achieves a general consensus and standardization, a point beyond
which only minor changes are admissible. Like Sidney, Puttenham urges that
96
The Early Modern Period to the Enlightenment
poetry is unique among the arts inasmuch as it is enabled by “a cleare and
bright phantasie and imagination.” The poet, in fact, is “most admired when
he is most naturall and least artificiall” (AEP, 307). Puttenham’s text
represents in many ways an important stage in the development of modern
English criticism, long anticipating what will become Romantic reactions
against neoclassicism, and even moving toward a notion of art as primarily
offering pleasure. The overt emphasis on pleasure, as opposed to moral
instruction, is an implicit – though not at this stage a consciously or precisely
formulated – gesture toward poetic autonomy.
Notes
1. David Norbrook, “Introduction,” in The Penguin Book of Renaissance Verse
1509–1659, ed. H. R. Woudhuysen (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1993), pp.
xxii–xxv. Hereafter cited as PBRV.
2. Glyn P. Norton, ed., The Cambridge History of Literary Criticism: Volume III:
The Renaissance (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), pp. 3–4.
3. David Norbrook, Poetry and Politics in the English Renaissance, revised edition
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002), p. 1. Hereafter cited as PER.
4. Giraldi Cinthio on Romances: Being a Translation of the Discorso intorno al
comporre dei romanzi, trans. Henry L. Snuggs (Lexington: University of
Kentucky Press, 1968), p. 11. Hereafter cited as DCR.
5. Castelvetro, On the Art of Poetry: An Abridged Translation of Lodovico
Castelvetro’s Poetica d’Aristotele Vulgarizzata et Sposta, trans. Andrew
Bongiorno (Binghamton, NY: Medieval and Renaissance Texts and Studies,
1984), pp. 42–43. Hereafter cited as PA.
6. Giacopo Mazzoni, On the Defense of the Comedy of Dante: Introduction and
Summary, trans. Robert L. Montgomery (Tallahassee: University Presses of
Florida, 1983), p. 46. Hereafter cited as DCD.
7. “Introduction,” in Torquato Tasso, Discourses on the Heroic Poem, trans.
Mariella Cavalchini and Irene Samuel (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1973), p.
172. Hereafter cited as DHP.
8. Joachim Du Bellay, La Deffence et Illustration de la Langue Francoyse (Paris:
Societe des Textes Français Modernes, 1997). Since the English translation, The
Defence and Illustration of the French Language by Gladys M. Turquet, is not
easily available, I have referred to the selections from this translation reprinted in
The Norton Anthology of Theory and Criticism, ed. Vincent B. Leitch (New York
and London: W. W. Norton, 2001). Hereafter cited as NTC.
9. The Selected Poetry and Prose of Sir Philip Sidney, ed. David Kalstone (New York
and Toronto: New American Library, 1970), pp. 216–217. Hereafter cited as
APP.
10. George Gascoigne, “Certayne Notes of Instruction,” reprinted in English Renaissance Literary Criticism, ed. Brian Vickers (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1999),
p. 162. Hereafter cited as ER.
The Early Modern Period
97
11. Around this time there was raging the “Inkhorn” controversy concerning the use
of foreign words in English. The inkhorn was an inkwell, and came to signify
figuratively a certain pedantry associated with foreign, often polysyllabic,
words.
12. George Puttenham, The Arte of English Poesie, ed. Gladys Doidge Willcock and
Alice Walker (1936; rpt. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970), p. xcii.
Hereafter cited as AEP.
Chapter 7
Neoclassical Literary Criticism
Neoclassicism refers to a broad tendency in literature and art enduring from
the early seventeenth century until around 1750. Most fundamentally,
neoclassicism comprised a return to the classical models, literary styles, and
values of ancient Greek and Roman authors. In this, the neoclassicists were to
some extent heirs of the Renaissance humanists. But many of them reacted
sharply against what they perceived to be the stylistic excess, superfluous
ornamentation, and linguistic oversophistication of some Renaissance writers; they also rejected the lavishness of the Gothic and Baroque styles.
Many major medieval and Renaissance writers, including Dante, Ariosto,
More, Spenser, and Milton, had peopled their writings with fantastic and
mythical beings. Authors such as Giraldi had attempted to justify the genre of
the romance and the use of the “marvelous” and unreal elements. Sidney and
others had even proposed that the poet’s task was to create an ideal world,
superior to the world of nature. The neoclassicists, reacting against this
idealistic tendency in Renaissance poetics, might be thought of as heirs to the
other major tendency in Renaissance poetics, which was Aristotelian. This
latter impetus had been expressed in the work of Minturno, Scaliger, and
Castelvetro, who had all stressed the Aristotelian notion of probability, as
well as the “unities” of action, time, and place.
However, whereas many Renaissance poets had labored toward an individualism of outlook, the neoclassicists were less ambiguous in their emphasis
upon the classical values of objectivity, impersonality, rationality, decorum,
balance, harmony, proportion, and moderation. Whereas many Renaissance
poets were beginning to understand the importance of invention and creativity, the neoclassical writers reaffirmed literary composition as a rational
and rule-bound process, requiring a great deal of craft, labor, and study.
Where Renaissance theorists and poets were advocating new and mixed
genres, the neoclassicists tended to insist on the separation of poetry and
prose, the purity of each genre, and the hierarchy of genres (though, unlike
Literary Criticism from Plato to the Present: An Introduction
© 2011 M. A. R. Habib. ISBN: 978-1-405-16034-6
M. A. R. Habib
Neoclassical Literary Criticism
99
Aristotle, they generally placed the epic above tragedy). The typical meters
and verse forms of the neoclassical poets were the alexandrine in France and
the heroic couplet in England. Much neoclassical thought was marked by a
recognition of human finitude, in contrast with the humanists’ (and, later, the
Romantics’) assertion of almost limitless human potential.
Two of the concepts central to neoclassical literary theory and practice were
“imitation” and “nature,” which were intimately related. In one sense, the
notion of imitation – of the external world and, primarily, of human action –
was a reaffirmation of the ideals of objectivity and impersonality. But it also
referred to the imitation of classical models, especially of Homer and Vergil. In
fact, these two aspects of imitation were often identified, as by Pope. The
identification was based largely on the concept of “nature,” which had a
number of senses. It referred to the harmonious and hierarchical order of the
universe, including the various social and political hierarchies within the
world. In this vast scheme of nature, everything had its proper and appointed
place. The concept also referred to human nature: to what was central,
timeless, and universal in human experience. Hence, “nature” had a deep
moral significance, comprehending the modes of action that were permissible
and excluding certain actions as “unnatural” (a term often used by
Shakespeare to describe the murderous and treacherous behavior of characters
such as Lady Macbeth). Clearly, the neoclassical vision of nature was very different
from the meanings later given to it by the Romantics. The neoclassical writers saw
the ancients such as Homer and Vergil as having already expressed the fundamental laws of nature. Hence, the external world could best be expressed by
modern writers if they followed the path of imitation already paved by the ancients.
Invention was allowed but only as a modification of past models.
But some neoclassical writers, such as Ben Jonson, Corneille, and Dryden,
were more flexible in their assimilation of classical values. Indeed, there raged
at the beginning of the eighteenth century various debates over the relative
merits of “ancients” and “moderns.” The ancients were held to be the
repository of good sense, natural laws, and the classical values of order,
balance, and moderation. Such arguments were found in Jonathan Swift’s
The Battle of the Books (1710) and in the writings of Boileau and Pope.
Proponents of the “modern” laid stress on originality of form and content,
flexibility of genre, and the license to engage in new modes of thought.
The connection of neoclassicism to recent science and to the Enlightenment
was highly ambivalent and even paradoxical. On the one hand, the neoclassical
concept of nature was informed by Newtonian physics, and the universe was
acknowledged to be a vast machine, subject to fixed analyzable laws. On the
other hand, the tenor of most neoclassical thought was retrospective and
conservative. On the surface, it might seem that the neoclassical writers shared
with Enlightenment thinkers a belief in the power of reason. But, while it is true
that some neoclassical writers, especially in Germany, were influenced by
Descartes and other rationalists, the “reason” to which the neoclassical writers
100
The Early Modern Period to the Enlightenment
appeal is in general not the individualistic and progressive reason of the
Enlightenment;rather,itisthe“reason” oftheclassical philosophers, auniversal
human faculty that provides access to general truths and which is aware of its
own limitations. Alexander Pope and others emphasized the finitude of human
reason, cautioning against its arrogant and unrestricted employment. Reason
announced itself in neoclassical thought largely in Aristotelian and sometimes
Horatian terms: an adherence to the requirements of probability and verisimilitude, as well as to the three unities, and the principle of decorum (harmony of
form and content). But the verisimilitude or realism that neoclassical writers
sought was different from nineteenth-century realism: they sought to depict the
typical elements and the universal truths about any given situation; their realism
did notoperatevia accumulation of empiricaldetail ora random recording ofsocalledreality.ItwasreasoninthisAristoteliansensethatlaybehindtheinsistence
on qualities such as order, restraint, moderation, and balance.
This general tendency of neoclassicism toward order, clarity, and standardization was manifested also in attempts during the seventeenth and eighteenth
centuries to regulate the use of language and the meanings of words. In France,
the Academie Française was established for this purpose in 1635. Samuel
Johnson’s Dictionary was published in 1755. The impetus behind these
endeavors was reflected in John Locke’s theory of language, and his insistence
on philosophy using “clear and distinct” ideas and avoiding figurative language. This ideal of clarity, of language as the outward sign of the operations of
reason, permeated neoclassical poetry which was often discursive, argumentative, and aimed to avoid obscurity. This movement toward clarity has been
variously theorized as coinciding with the beginnings of bourgeois hegemony,
as reacting against a proliferation of vocabulary and meanings during the
Renaissance, and as marking a step further away from a medieval allegorical
way of thinking toward an attempted literalization of language. The following
sections will consider some of the major figures of neoclassical literary criticism
in the countries where it was most pronounced: France and England.
French Neoclassicism
Neoclassical literary criticism first took root in France from where its
influence spread to other parts of Europe, notably England. The mission of
the French Academy, founded in 1635, was partly to standardize language
through the creation of a dictionary and grammar, and to foster an eloquence
deemed necessary to the public sphere and the growth of civil society.1
The major figures of French neoclassicism were Corneille, Racine, Moliere,
and La Fontaine. Corneille’s theories grew out of the need to defend his
dramatic practice against strict classicists such as Scudery and Jean
Chapelain. The most prominent theorists were Dominique Bouhours, Rene
Rapin, and Nicolas Boileau.
Neoclassical Literary Criticism
101
Pierre Corneille (1606–1684)
Pierre Corneille’s most important piece of literary criticism, Trois Discours
sur le Poeme Dramatique (Three Discourses on Dramatic Poetry, 1660), was
produced in response to the charge that his play, Le Cid (1637), despite its
popularity, violated the classical unities – of action, time, and place – as well
as the Aristotelian precepts of probability and necessity, and thereby
undermined the morally didactic function of drama.
In his third Discourse, entitled “Of the Three Unities of Action, Time, and
Place,” Corneille agrees with Aristotle that “there must be only one complete
action,” but he insists that “action can become complete only through several
others . . . which . . . keep the spectator in a pleasant suspense.”2 As for the
number of acts, this was not prescribed by Aristotle; and though Horace limits
a play to five acts, we do not know for sure, says Corneille, how many acts
ancient Greek plays contained (“TU,” 107–108). Nor was there a rule for the
unity of place; and the unity of time, prescribed by Aristotle as “one
revolution of the sun,” must be interpreted liberally according to what is
practical on the stage and for the audience (“TU,” 109, 114–115).
In general, Corneille explains that it is easy for critics to be strict in their
censure; but if they themselves had to produce plays, if they themselves
“recognized through experience what constraint their precision brings about
and how many beautiful things it banishes from our stage,” they might
reconsider their own severity. The test, Corneille insists, is experience, actual
practice. Corneille’s overall aim, as he suggests, is to “make ancient rules
agree with modern pleasures” (“TU,” 115). In this endeavor, he is not so
much making those rules more liberal as reformulating them in the light of the
needs and requirements of the audience, especially the modern audience.
Corneille effectively rescues the importance of performance from the peripheral status it meekly occupies in Aristotle’s text.
Nicolas Boileau (1636–1711)
The French poet and critic Boileau had a pervasive influence not only on
French letters (of the old-fashioned kind) but also on English and German
poets and critics, notably Pope. His L’Art Poetique (The Art of Poetry), first
published in 1674, was translated into English by John Dryden. Boileau’s text
represents a formal statement of the principles of French classicism and
enjoyed such prestige that he was known as the legislateur du Parnasse,
credited with the formation of French literary taste. Just as Moliere’s plays
effect a balance between religious belief and rationalism, arguing for an
enlightened rather than authoritarian religion, so Boileau’s Art of Poetry is
marked by a central affirmation of the importance of reason, as well as
observation. It reacts against Christian puritanism, submitting the claims of
102
The Early Modern Period to the Enlightenment
the latter to the judgment of reason. But, as with Moliere and Pope, the
“reason” espoused by Boileau is not the individualistic reason of the Enlightenment but a classical view of reason as a common human faculty which
perceives what is universally true.
Boileau’s text is written as a poem, in the tradition of Horace’s Ars poetica.
In canto I, he reiterates the Horatian formula:
In prudent lessons everywhere abound,
With pleasant join the useful and the sound;
A sober reader a vain tale will slight,
He seeks as well instruction as delight.3
Where Boileau’s text moves beyond Horace is in its insistence on the centrality
of reason to the poetic enterprise: “Love reason then; and let whate’er you
write/Borrow from her its beauty, force, and light” (APB, I, ll. 37–38). Boileau
is skillful in drawing out the widely varied ramifications of the reliance on
reason, which enablespoetic control, moderation, the unities of time and place,
and the imitation of classical examples. For Boileau, reason also urges against
the subjection of poetry to religious puritanism. He states: “Our pious fathers,
in their priest-rid age, / As impious and profane abhorred the stage.” But “At
last right reason did his laws reveal, / And showed the folly of their ill-placed zeal
(APB, III, ll. 79–80, 85–86). In his desire to return to classical models, Boileau
countenances even those aspects of classical paganism that directly contradict
Christian teaching, on the grounds that the gospels are not a fitting subject for
verse and that removal of classical ornament will impoverish a poem.
Anticipating Pope, Boileau appeals to nature: “To study nature be your
only care.” The poet, he says, must know human nature and the “secrets of the
heart.” He must observe and be able to paint all kinds of people, at all stages in
life. But even here, the following of nature is seen as obeying the rules of
reason: “Your actors must by reason be controlled; / Let young men speak like
young, old men like old” (APB, III, ll. 390–391). Reason has one final aspect
in Boileau’s text: a harmony with the passions, which it must “move” by
entertaining them (APB, III. ll. 15–21, 25–26). Boileau is here repeating an
old formula, used earlier by many Renaissance writers such as Sidney:
inasmuch as poetry instructs, it must first delight.
Neoclassicism in England
The main streams of English neoclassical criticism were inspired by (and
reacted against) the French example. French influence in England was
intensified by the Restoration of 1660, whereby Charles II, exiled in France
after the English Civil War, returned with his court to England. Boileau’s
Neoclassical Literary Criticism
103
influence was most pronounced on Pope; Dryden defended English drama
against some of the French critics. As noted earlier, the France of Louis XIV
had embarked upon a neoclassical program of national proportions. While
neoclassical criticism in England was not so systematic, many saw the
adoption of neoclassical ideals as integral to a stable and orderly political
state. The classical tendency in England embraced a number of major prose
writers who laid the foundations of the modern English novel such as Daniel
Defoe (1660?–1731), Jonathan Swift (1667–1745), and Henry Fielding
(1707–1754). In general, the critics ranging from Jonson to Dryden
effectively advanced the notion of a viable English literary tradition.
John Dryden (1631–1700)
Samuel Johnson termed Dryden “the father of English criticism,” and
affirmed of his Essay of Dramatic Poesy (1668) that “modern English prose
begins here.” Dryden’s critical work was extensive, treating of various genres
such as epic, tragedy, comedy and dramatic theory, satire, the relative virtues
of ancient and modern writers, as well as the nature of poetry and translation.
Dryden was also a consummate poet, dramatist, and translator. He was
appointed poet-laureate in 1668 and his major poems included the mockheroic “Mac Flecknoe” (1682), and a political satire Absalom and Achitophel
(1681). Dryden’s Essay of Dramatic Poesy is written as a series of debates on
drama conducted by four speakers – Eugenius, Crites, Lisideius, and Neander
– who have conventionally been identified with four of Dryden’s
contemporaries, with Neander (“new man”) representing Dryden himself.4
Like Tasso and Corneille, Dryden attempted to strike a compromise
between the claims of ancient authority and the needs of the modern writer.
In Dryden’s text, this compromise subsumes a number of debates, concerning: the classical “unities,” of time, place, and action; the rigid classical
distinction between various genres, such as tragedy and comedy; classical
decorum and propriety; and the use of rhyme in drama. Dryden also
undertakes an influential assessment of the English dramatic tradition.
As against the neoclassical virtues of French drama, Neander urges the
virtues of English tragi-comedy, thereby overturning nearly all of the ancient
prescriptions concerning purity of genre, decorum, and unity of plot. Neander poignantly repeats Corneille’s observation that anyone with actual
experience of the stage will see how constraining the classical rules are.
Neander states that Shakespeare “had the largest and most comprehensive
soul.” He was “naturally learn’d,” not through books but by the reading of
nature and all her images: “he looked inwards, and found her there.” In an
important statement he affirms that “Shakespeare was the Homer, or father
of our dramatic poets; Johnson was the Vergil, the pattern of elaborate
writing” (DP, 76–82). What Neander – or Dryden – effectively does here is to
104
The Early Modern Period to the Enlightenment
stake out an independent tradition for English drama, with new archetypes
displacing those of the classical tradition. In the final debate, concerning
rhyme, Dryden suggests that blank verse and rhyme are equally artificial: in
everyday life, people do not speak in blank verse, any more than they do in
rhyme (DP, 100–101).
If Dryden is neoclassical, it is in the sense that he acknowledges the classics
as having furnished archetypes for drama; but modern writers, he says, are at
liberty to create their own archetypes and their own literary traditions. Again,
he might be called classical in insisting that the unity of a play, however
conceived, be a paramount requirement; that a play present, through its use of
plot and characterization, events and actions which are probable and express
a semblance of truth; that the laws of “nature” be followed, if not through
imitation of the ancients, then through looking inward at our own profoundest constitution; and finally, that every aspect of a play be contrived with the
projected response of the audience in mind. But given Dryden’s equal
emphasis on the poet’s wit, invention, and imagination, his text might be
viewed as expressing a status of transition between neoclassicism and
Romanticism.
Indeed, in his 1666 preface to Annus Mirabilis, he states that the
“composition of all poems is, or ought to be, of wit; and wit . . . is no other
than the faculty of imagination in the writer” (DP, 14). Again, the emphasis
here is on wit and imagination rather than exclusively on the classical precept
of imitation. In fact, Dryden commends rhyme for the delight it produces:
“for delight is the chief, if not the only, end of poesy: instruction can be
admitted but in the second place, for poesy only instructs as it delights.” If in
such statements Dryden appears to anticipate certain Romantic predispositions, these comments are counterbalanced by other positions which are
deeply entrenched in a classical heritage. Later in the “Defence” he insists that
“moral truth is the mistress of the poet as much as of the philosopher; Poesy
must resemble natural truth, but it must be ethical.”5 Hence, notwithstanding
the importance that he attaches to wit and imagination, Dryden still regards
poetry as essentially a rational activity, with an ethical and epistemological
responsibility. This stance effectively embodies both Dryden’s classicism and
the nature of his departure from its strict boundaries.
Alexander Pope (1688–1744)
Pope’s An Essay on Criticism (1711) is perhaps the clearest statement of
neoclassical principles in any language. It expresses a world view which
synthesizes elements of a Roman Catholic outlook with classical aesthetic
principles and with deism. The prevailing anti-Catholic laws constrained
many areas of Pope’s life: he could not obtain a university education, hold
public or political office, or even reside in London. However, Pope was
Neoclassical Literary Criticism
105
privately taught and moved in an elite circle of London writers which
included the dramatists Wycherly and Congreve, the poet Granville, the
critic William Walsh, as well as the writers Addison and Steele, and the deistic
politician Bolingbroke. Pope produced some of the finest verse ever written.
His most renowned publications include several mock-heroic poems such as
The Rape of the Lock (1712; 1714), and The Dunciad (1728). His philosophical poem An Essay on Man (1733–1734) was a scathing attack on
human arrogance or pride in failing to observe the due limits of human
reason, in questioning divine authority and seeking to be self-reliant; Pope
espouses an ethic based on an ordered and hierarchical universe yet depicts
this order in terms of Newtonian mechanism and expresses a broadly deistic
vision.
An Essay on Criticism is written in verse, in the tradition of Horace’s Ars
poetica. Pope here not only delineates the scope and nature of good literary
criticism, but redefines classical virtues in terms of “nature” and “wit,” as
necessary to both poetry and criticism. Pope’s call for a “return to nature”
is complex. On a cosmic level, nature signifies the providential order of the
world and the universe, a hierarchy in which each entity has its proper
assigned place. In An Essay on Man Pope expounds the “Great Chain of
Being,” ranging from God and the angels through man and the lower
animals to plants and inanimate objects. Nature can also refer to what is
normal, central, and universal in human experience, encompassing the
spheres of morality and knowledge, the rules of proper moral conduct as
well as the archetypal patterns of human reason. The word “wit” in Pope’s
time could refer in general to intelligence; it also meant “wit” in the
modern sense of cleverness, as expressed in figures of speech and especially
in discerning unanticipated similarities between different entities. By Pope’s
time, literature generally had come to be associated with wit and had come
under attack from the Puritans, who saw it as morally defective and
corrupting.
While Pope cautions that the best poets make the best critics, and while
he recognizes that some critics are failed poets (l. 105), he points out that
both the best poetry and the best criticism are divinely inspired: “Both
must alike from Heav’n derive their Light” (ll. 13–14). Pope sees the
endeavor of criticism as a noble one, provided it abides by Horace’s advice
for the poet:
But you who seek to give and merit Fame,
And justly bear a Critick’s noble Name,
Be sure your self and your own Reach to know,
How far your Genius, Taste, and Learning go;
Launch not beyond your Depth. . .
(ll. 46–50)
106
The Early Modern Period to the Enlightenment
Apart from knowing his own capacities, the critic must be conversant with
every aspect of the author whom he is examining. Pope insists that the critic
base his interpretation on the author’s intention: “In ev’ry Work regard the
Writer’s End, / Since none can compass more than they Intend” (ll. 233–234,
255–256).
Pope specifies two further guidelines for the critic. The first is to recognize
the overall unity of a work, and thereby to avoid falling into partial assessments based on the author’s use of poetic conceits, ornamented language,
meters, as well as judgments which are biased toward either archaic or
modern styles or based on the reputations of given writers. Finally, a critic
needs to possess a moral sensibility, as well as a sense of balance and
proportion, as indicated in these lines: “Nor in the Critick let the Man be
lost! / Good-Nature and Good-Sense must ever join (ll. 523–525). Pope ends
his advice with this summary of the ideal critic:
But where’s the Man, who Counsel can bestow,
Still pleas’d to teach, and yet not proud to know?
Unbiass’d, or by Favour or by Spite;
Not dully prepossest, nor blindly right;
Tho learn’d, well-bred; and tho’ well-bred, sincere;
. . . Blest with a Taste exact, yet unconfin’d;
A Knowledge both of Books and Humankind;
Gen’rous Converse; a Soul exempt from Pride;
And Love to Praise, with Reason on his Side?
(ll. 631–642)
It is clear that these qualities of a good critic are primarily attributes of
humanity or moral sensibility rather than aesthetic qualities. Indeed, the only
specifically aesthetic quality mentioned here is “taste.” The remaining virtues
might be said to have a theological ground, resting on the ability to overcome
pride. Pope effectively transposes the language of theology (“soul,” “pride”)
to aesthetics. The “reason” to which Pope appeals is (as in Aquinas and many
medieval thinkers) a universal archetype in human nature, and is a corollary
of humility. It is the disposition of humility – an aesthetic humility, if you will
– which enables the critic to avoid the foregoing faults.
Now comes Pope’s central advice to both poet and critic, to “follow
Nature,” whose restraining function he explains:
Nature to all things fix’d the Limits fit,
And wisely curb’d proud Man’s pretending Wit;
. . . One Science only will one Genius fit;
So vast is Art, so narrow Human Wit. . .
(ll. 52–53, 60–61)
Neoclassical Literary Criticism
107
Hence, even before he launches into any discussion of aesthetics, Pope
designates human wit generally as an instrument of pride, as intrinsically
liable to abuse. In the scheme of nature, however, man’s wit is puny and
occupies an apportioned place. It is in this context that Pope proclaims his
famous maxim:
First follow NATURE, and your Judgment frame
By her just Standard, which is still the same:
Unerring Nature, still divinely bright,
Once clear, unchang’d, and Universal Light,
Life, Force, and Beauty, must to all impart,
At once the Source, and End, and Test of Art.
(ll. 68–73)
The features attributed to nature include permanence or timelessness and
universality. Ultimately, nature is a force which expresses the power of the
divine, not in the later Romantic sense of a divine spirit pervading the physical
appearances of nature but in the medieval sense of expressing the order,
harmony, and beauty of God’s creation. As such, Nature provides the eternal
and archetypal standard against which art must be measured.
Pope does not believe, like many medieval rhetoricians, that poetry is an
entirely rational process. In poetry, as in music, he points out, are “nameless
Graces which no Methods teach” (l. 144). Indeed, geniuses can sometimes
transgress the boundaries of judgment and their very transgression or license
becomes a rule for art (ll. 152–156). Pope here seems to assert the primacy of
wit over judgment, of art over criticism, viewing art as inspired and as
transcending the norms of conventional thinking in its direct appeal to the
“heart.” The critic’s task here is to recognize the superiority of great wit.
While this emphasis strides beyond many medieval and Renaissance aesthetics, it must of course be read in its own poetic context: he immediately
warns that modern writers should not rely on their own insights but draw on
the common store of poetic wisdom, established by the ancients, and
acknowledged by “Universal Praise” (l. 190).
Pope’s exploration of wit aligns it with the central classical virtues, which
are themselves equated with nature: “True Wit is Nature to Advantage drest, /
What oft was Thought, but ne’er so well Exprest” (ll. 297–298). Pope
subsequently says that expression is the “Dress of Thought,” and that “true
expression” throws light on objects without altering them (ll. 315–318). The
lines above are a concentrated expression of Pope’s classicism. If wit is the
“dress” of nature, it will express nature without altering it. The poet’s task
here is twofold: not only to find the expression that will most truly convey
nature, but first to ensure that the substance he is expressing is indeed a
“natural” insight or thought. What the poet must express is a universal truth
108
The Early Modern Period to the Enlightenment
which we will instantly recognize as such. This classical commitment to the
expression of objective and universal truth is echoed a number of times
through Pope’s text. For example, he admonishes both poet and critic:
“Regard not then if Wit be Old or New, / But blame the False, and value
still the True” (ll. 406–407).
Another classical ideal urged by Pope is that of organic unity and wholeness. The expression or style must be suited to the subject matter and
meaning: “The Sound must seem an Eccho to the Sense” (l. 365). An essential
component in such unity and proportion is the classical virtue of moderation.
Pope advises both poet and critic to follow the Aristotelian ethical maxim:
“Avoid Extreams.” Those who go to excess in any direction display “Great
Pride, or Little Sense” (ll. 384–387). And, once again, the ability to overcome
pride – humility – is implicitly associated with what Pope calls “right Reason”
(l. 211). Indeed, the central passage in the Essay on Criticism, as in the later
Essay on Man, views all of the major faults as stemming from pride:
Of all the Causes which conspire to blind
Man’s erring Judgment, and misguide the Mind,
. . . Is Pride, the never-failing Vice of Fools.
(ll. 201–204)
It is pride which leads critics and poets alike to overlook universal truths in
favor of subjective whims; pride which causes them to value particular parts
instead of the whole, pride which disables them from achieving a harmony of
wit and judgment, and pride which underlies their excesses and biases. As in
the Essay on Man, Pope associates pride with individualism, with excessive
reliance on one’s own judgment and failure to observe the laws laid down by
nature and by the classical tradition.
Pope’s final strategy in the Essay is to equate the classical literary and
critical traditions with nature, and to sketch a redefined outline of literary
history from classical times to his own era. Pope insists that the rules of nature
were merely discovered, not invented, by the ancients: “Those Rules of old
discover’d, not devis’d, / Are Nature still, but Nature Methodiz’d” (ll. 88–89).
Pope’s advice, for both critic and poet, is clear: “Learn hence for Ancient
Rules a just Esteem; / To copy Nature is to copy Them” (ll. 139–140). Pope
traces the genealogy of “nature,” as embodied in classical authors, from
Aristotle through the Roman authors Horace, Petronius, Quintilian, and
Longinus. After these, a dark age ensued with the collapse of the western
Roman Empire at the hands of the Vandals and Goths, an age governed by
“tyranny” and “superstition,” an age where “Much was Believ’d, but little
understood” (ll. 686–689). What is interesting here is that, even though he
was himself a Catholic, Pope sees the Catholic medieval era as a continuation
of the so-called Dark Ages. Even more striking is his subsequent praise of the
Neoclassical Literary Criticism
109
Renaissance humanist thinker Erasmus, who “drove those Holy Vandals off
the Stage” (ll. 693–694).
Pope’s implicit allegiance to Erasmus (and in part to contemporary figures
such as Bolingbroke) points in the direction of a broad deism which, on the
one hand, accommodates the significance of pride in secular, rather than
theological, contexts, and, on the other hand, accommodates reason within
its appropriate limits. His historical survey continues with praises of the
“Golden Days” of the Renaissance, and suggests that the arts and criticism
thereafter flourished in Europe, especially in France which produced the critic
and poet Nicolas Boileau (1636–1711). Given Boileau’s own impact on
Pope’s critical thought, we can see that Pope now begins to set the stage for
his own entry into the history of criticism. The writers Pope now cites were
either known to him or his tutors. All in all, Pope’s strategy here is remarkable: in retracing the lineage of good criticism, as based on nature and the true
use of wit, he traces his own lineage as both poet and critic, thereby both
redefining or reaffirming the true critical tradition and marking his own entry
into it.
Aphra Behn (1640–1689)
Aphra Behn was a pioneer in many respects. Because of her family circumstances and her husband’s early death, she was obliged to support herself as a
writer – one of the first women to do so. She is one of the founders of the
English novel; her extended stay in Surinam inspired her to write Oroonko
(1688), the first novel to oppose slavery. And her experience as a female
playwright exposed her to the enormous obstacles faced by a woman in this
profession, resulting in her highly unorthodox and controversial views about
drama. These views are expressed largely in the prefaces to her plays, such as
The Dutch Lover (1673), The Rover (1677), and The Lucky Chance (1687).
If figures such as Pierre Corneille took a step away from the authority of
classical rules by appealing to experience, Aphra Behn’s appeal to experience
– to specifically female experience – was far more radical. Moreover, she
(perhaps unwittingly) elevates to a newly important status the performative
dimensions of drama, such as the ability and integrity of the actors.
In one of her prefaces, Behn strikes a tone of utter defiance. She defends the
value of drama by contrasting it favorably with traditional learning as taught
in the universities.6 But equally, she denies that dramatic poets can perform a
moral function: “no Play was ever writ with that design.” Behn’s own,
carefully unstudied, opinion is that drama represents the best entertainment
that “wise men have”; to discourse formally about its rules, as if it were “the
grand affair” of human life, is valueless. Behn’s own purpose, in writing her
play The Dutch Lover, was “only to make this as entertaining as I could,” and
the judges of her success will be the audience (Behn, I, 223).
110
The Early Modern Period to the Enlightenment
Behn now takes up the murky issues surrounding female authorship. She
heaps a barrage of insulting criticism (“ill-favour’d, wretched Fop” and more)
upon a man who warned the audience for her play to expect “a woful Play . . .
for it was a womans.” Replying to his presumption, she asserts that women, if
given the same education as men, are just as capable of acquiring knowledge
and in as many capacities as men. Further, given that “affectation hath always
had a greater share both in the actions and discourse of men than truth and
judgment have,” women might well reach the heights attained by men”
(Behn, I, 224). The classical rules of drama she dismisses in a breath: these
“musty rules of Unity, . . . if they meant anything, they are enough intelligible,
and as practicable by a woman” (Behn, I, 224). With no apology, she ends
with: “Now, Reader, I have eas’d my mind of all I had to say” (Behn, I, 225).
In her preface to The Lucky Chance, written some 15 years later, Behn
states that she will defend her comedy against “those Censures that Malice,
and ill Nature have thrown upon it, tho’ in vain.”7 It is the very success of her
play, she exclaims, that caused critics to “load it with all manner of Infamy.”
And they heap upon it, she says, “the old never failing Scandal – That ’tis not
fit for the Ladys” (Behn, III, 185). She hastens to point out that many works of
poetry have long treated the subject of women in an indecent fashion, but the
offense is overlooked “because a Man writ them.” She admonishes her critics
not simply to condemn her work because it is a woman’s; but to “examine
whether it be guilty or not, with reading, comparing, or thinking” (Behn, III,
185). Moreover, she points out several great plays with allegedly indecent
scenes which are artistically justified (Behn, III, 186).
What Behn effectively does here is to place the virtues of good judgment,
critical reading, and thinking, beyond the pale of traditional masculine
learning and the conventional male literary establishment, which have both,
on account of their transparent bias and maliciousness, forfeited their right to
speak with authority. Behn presents another voice, a woman’s voice, speaking
not from a position below that establishment but rather from above; she takes
no great pains to dislodge male assumptions about women writers; rather, she
appropriates for woman’s use the categories of common sense and reason,
extricating them from the tradition of male prejudice in which they have been
abused and occluded.
Behn’s originality lies as much in the way she speaks as in what she speaks:
her texts adopt a tone and a style unprecedented in the history of literary
criticism. Defiant, unapologetic, and placing herself entirely outside of the
traditional canons of male learning and literature (an externality achieved
often by her very tone), her writing does not follow a logical pattern; it seems
to be punctuated, rather, by the movement of her righteous anger, her
deliberate outpourings of emotion, the nodal points of her rebuttals of
insubstantial criticism, and the flow of particularity or detail – of names,
and particular circumstances – which itself infuses her general statements
Neoclassical Literary Criticism
111
with substance in a newly immediate and transparent manner, the general
being treated as on the same level as the particulars which it comprehends
rather than loftily coercing particulars (in what she would regard as a
conventionally male fashion) into the exemplifying service of its own predetermined and prescriptive nature.
Samuel Johnson (1709–1784)
Samuel Johnson is perhaps best remembered for his two-volume Dictionary
of the English Language, first published in 1755. Of almost equal renown are
his Lives of the English Poets (1783) and his eight-volume edition of
Shakespeare (1765). His most famous poem is The Vanity of Human Wishes
(1749), a speculation on the emptiness of worldly pursuits. He also wrote
drama and a fictional work, The History of Rasselas (1759), as well as
numerous essays in periodicals such as The Rambler, The Adventurer, and
The Idler. Johnson’s own biography was recorded by his friend James
Boswell, who published his celebrated Life of Samuel Johnson in 1791.
Johnson’s “Preface” to, and edition of, Shakespeare’s plays played a large
part in establishing Shakespeare’s reputation; his account of the lives of
numerous English poets contributed to the forming of the English literary
canon and the defining of qualities such as metaphysical “wit”; his remarks on
criticism itself were also to have an enduring impact.
In his fictional work, The History of Rasselas, Johnson expresses through
one of his characters called Imlac a statement which has often been regarded
as a summary of neoclassical principles. The business of the poet, says Imlac,
is “to examine, not the individual, but the species; to remark general
properties and large appearances . . . He is to exhibit in his portraits of nature
such prominent and striking features, as recall the original to every mind.”
The poet must “divest himself of the prejudices of his age or country; he must
consider right and wrong in their abstract and invariable state . . . and rise to
general and transcendental truths, which will always be the same.”8
Johnson’s classical commitment to reason, probability and truth was
complemented by his equally classical insistence on the moral function of
literature. In 1750 he urged that modern writers require not only the learning
that is to be gained from books but also “that experience which . . . must arise
from general converse, and accurate observation of the living world.”9
However, the prime concern of the author should not be verisimilitude but
moral instruction (Rambler, 11). Johnson acknowledges that “the greatest
excellency of art” is to “imitate nature; but it is necessary to distinguish those
parts of nature, which are most proper for imitation” (Rambler, 12–13). The
author must not “confound the colors of right and wrong,” and must indeed
help to “settle their boundaries.” Vice must always produce disgust, not
admiration; and virtue must be shown in the most perfect form that
112
The Early Modern Period to the Enlightenment
probability will allow (Rambler, 14–15). Like Aristotle, Johnson desires
literature to express truth in general and universal terms, but its choice of
material and manner should be circumscribed by moral imperatives. However, he acknowledges that rules should be drawn from reason rather than
from mere precedent (Rambler, 197–199).
Johnson’s “Preface” to his edition of Shakespeare’s plays is informed by
three basic concerns: how a poet’s reputation is established; the poet’s
relation to nature; and the relative virtues of nature and experience of life
as against a reliance on convention. Inquiring into the reasons behind
Shakespeare’s enduring success, Johnson makes an important general statement: “Nothing can please many, and please long, but just representations of
general nature.”10 Once again, by “general nature,” Johnson refers to the
avoidance of particular manners or customs and the foundation of one’s work
on universal truths. Shakespeare, above all writers, is “the poet of nature: the
poet that holds up to his readers a faithful mirrour of manners and of life.” His
characters are not molded by the accidents of time, place, and local custom;
rather, they are “the genuine progeny of common humanity,” and they “act
and speak by the influence of those general passions and principles by which
all minds are agitated” (Preface, 62).
Johnson acknowledges that Shakespeare’s plays “are not in the rigorous
and critical sense either tragedies or comedies.” Shakespeare “has united
the powers of exciting laughter and sorrow not only in one mind but in one
composition” (Preface, 66–67). It is here, in his defense of tragicomedy,
that Johnson appeals to nature as a higher authority than precedent.
He allows that Shakespeare’s practice is “contrary to the rules of criticism
. . . but there is always an appeal open from criticism to nature. The end of
writing is to instruct; the end of poetry is to instruct by pleasing. That the
mingled drama may convey all the instruction of tragedy or comedy cannot
be denied, . . . and approaches nearer than either to the appearance of life”
(Preface, 67).
Johnson does concede, however, that Shakespeare had many faults: the
looseness of his plots, the lack of regard for distinction of time or place, the
grossness and licentiousness of his humor; the coldness and pomp of his
narrations and set speeches; and a digressive fascination with quibbles and
wordplay (Preface, 71–74). He argues that Shakespeare does observe unity of
action, but he had no regard for the unities of time and place, a point on which
Johnson defends Shakespeare by questioning these unities themselves. Johnson concludes that these unities are “to be sacrificed to the nobler beauties of
variety and instruction,” the greatest virtues of a play being “to copy nature
and instruct life” (Preface, 80). In this text, Johnson’s appeal to nature and
direct experience and observation over classical precedents and rules, as well
as his assessment of Shakespeare as inaugurating a new tradition, effectively
set the stage for various broader perspectives of the role of the poet, the poet’s
Neoclassical Literary Criticism
113
relation to tradition and classical authority, and the virtues of individualistic
poetic genius.
Another area in which Johnson exerted great influence on his successors
was that of biography and comparative estimation of the poets in the English
canon. In his Lives of the English Poets (1781), he raises biography to an art:
far from being slavishly adherent to facts, Johnson’s text is replete with all the
apparatus of imaginative texts: figures of speech, imaginative insights,
hypothetical argumentation, vivid descriptions, and speculative judgments;
he appeals not only to the intellects of his readers but to their emotions,
backgrounds, and moral sensibilities.
Notes
1. Glyn P. Norton, ed., The Cambridge History of Literary Criticism: Volume III:
The Renaissance (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), p. 500.
2. Pierre Corneille, “Of the Three Unities of Action, Time, and Place,” trans. Donald
Schier, in The Continental Model: Selected French Critical Essays of the Seventeenth Century, in English Translation, ed. Scott Elledge and Donald Schier
(Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press, 1970), pp. 101–102. Hereafter
cited as “TU.”
3. Nicolas Boileau, The Art of Poetry, IV, ll. 86-89. The text used here is the
translation by William Soame and John Dryden. It is reprinted in The Art of
Poetry: The Poetical Treatises of Horace, Vida, and Boileau, trans. Francis
Howes, Christopher Pitt, and Sir William Soames, ed. Albert S. Cook (Boston:
Ginn, 1892). Hereafter cited as APB.
4. John Dryden, “Defence of An Essay of Dramatic Poesy,” in Essays of John
Dryden: Volume I, ed. W. P. Ker (New York: Russell and Russell, 1961), p. 133.
Hereafter cited as DP.
5. Essays of John Dryden: Volume II, ed. W. P. Ker (New York: Russell and Russell,
1961), pp. 113, 121.
6. The Works of Aphra Behn: Volume I, ed. Montague Summers (New York:
Benjamin Blom, 1967), p. 221. Hereafter cited as Behn, I.
7. The Works of Aphra Behn: Volume III, ed. Montague Summers (New York:
Benjamin Blom, 1967), p. 185. Hereafter cited as Behn, III.
8. Samuel Johnson, The History of Rasselas, Prince of Abyssinia (Harmondsworth:
Penguin, 1986), ch. X.
9. Samuel Johnson, Essays from the Rambler, Adventurer, and Idler, ed. W. J. Bate
(New Haven and London: Yale University Press, 1968), p. 10. Hereafter cited as
Rambler.
10. The Yale Edition of the Works of Samuel Johnson: Volume VII: Johnson on
Shakespeare, ed. Arthur Sherbo, introd. Bertrand H. Bronson (New Haven and
London: Yale University Press, 1968), p. 61. Hereafter cited as Preface.
Chapter 8
The Enlightenment
Historical and Intellectual Background
The Enlightenment was a broad intellectual tendency, spanning philosophy,
literature, language, art, religion, and political theory, which lasted from
around 1680 until the end of the eighteenth century. Conventionally, the
Enlightenment has been called the “age of reason,” though this designation
fails to comprehend the various intellectual trends of the period. The
Enlightenment thinkers were by no means uniform in their outlooks, but in
general they saw themselves as initiating an era of humanitarian, intellectual,
and social progress, underlain by the increasing ability of human reason to
subjugate analytically both the external world of nature and the human self.
They viewed it as their mission to rid human thought and institutions of
irrational prejudice and superstition, as well as to foster a society free of
feudal caprice, political absolutism, and religious intolerance, where human
beings could realize their potential through making moral and political
choices on the foundations of rationality and freedom. In political and
economic terms, Enlightenment thought was integral to the rise of liberalism
and the French Revolution of 1789, which initiated the displacement of the
power of the king and nobility by the power of the bourgeoisie or middle
classes. The feudal world was characterized by values of static hierarchy,
loyalty, reverence for authority, and religious faith. These were increasingly
displaced by bourgeois ideology, which was predominantly secular, stressing
reason, individual experience, efficiency, usefulness, and, above all, political
liberalism based on a free rational economy aided by technology and science.
The main streams of the Enlightenment continue to have a profound effect
on our world. Much Enlightenment thought was underlain by a new scientific
vision of the universe inspired by the work of the English mathematician Sir
Isaac Newton (1642–1727): this conception of a mechanical universe ordered
by laws which were scientifically ascertainable eventually displaced the view
of the universe as ordered and historically directed by a benevolent divine
Literary Criticism from Plato to the Present: An Introduction
© 2011 M. A. R. Habib. ISBN: 978-1-405-16034-6
M. A. R. Habib
The Enlightenment
115
providence. The very concept of reason issued a profound challenge to
centuries-old traditions of thought and institutional practice. Reliance on
reason was in itself nothing new; the classical philosophers such as Plato and
Aristotle had urged reason as the faculty through which we could gain access
to truths which were universal and certain. Medieval Christian philosophy
acknowledged that reason was a necessary component of a proper spiritual
disposition, but it was only one element and needed to be balanced by faith
and revelation. What was novel to the Enlightenment was its insistence on
reason as the primary faculty through which we could acquire knowledge,
and on its potentially limitless application. The exaltation of man’s individual
capacity for reasoning effectively undermined reliance on any form of
authority, whether it be the authority of the Church, the state, or tradition.
This way of thinking is particularly marked in modern democracies even
today: as Alexis de Tocqueville noted about America, people in general prefer
to rely on their own insight (however uninformed) rather than submit to the
authority or testimony of others, even of experts.
Three seminal precursors of Enlightenment thought were the English
thinker Francis Bacon (1561–1626), the French rationalist philosopher Rene
Descartes (1596–1650), and the Dutch rationalist thinker Benedict (or
Baruch) Spinoza (1632–1677). Bacon’s major philosophical works were The
Advancement of Learning (1605) and The New Organon (1620), where he
formulated the method of induction whereby we generalize on the basis of
actual observation of a number of particular occurrences. He favored
induction, as the method of modern science, over the medieval reliance on
deduction and a priori reasoning, whose premises were handed down by
tradition. For centuries, Bacon warns, the human mind has been misled by
four classes of “idols” or false notions. The first type are “Idols of the Tribe,”
or the distorted impressions of nature caused by common human deficiencies
of sense and understanding; the next are “Idols of the Cave”: each man has a
private cave or den – his subjective background and experience – from which
he sees the world; the third kind of idols are those of the “marketplace,” the
vulgar notions formed through social intercourse. Finally, there are “Idols of
the Theatre,” the philosophical systems which are “merely stage plays”
because they represent “worlds of their own creation” rather than the actual
world.1 The upholders of these previous systems urge us to view the world
through those fictions rather than experiencing it directly for ourselves.
Rene Descartes (1596–1650) is often called the “father” of modern
philosophy. Like Bacon, Descartes challenged the basic principles of medieval
philosophy. In his Discourse on Method he began his thinking in a skeptical
mode, doubting all things, including his own senses, understanding and the
reality of the external world, until he could find a secure and certain
foundation of knowledge. He imagined that the entire world might be a
delusion. But Descartes realized that he could not doubt that very element in
116
The Early Modern Period to the Enlightenment
himself which was engaged in doubting or thinking, hence his conclusion
“I think, therefore I am.” Descartes proceeded to identify his essential nature
or self with the process of thinking, calling himself a “thinking being.” In this
way, he made his famous dualism or distinction between mind and body. The
mind is a thinking substance, whereas the body belongs to the world of space,
time, and material extension. Descartes inferred as a general rule that the
things which we conceive very “clearly and very distinctly” are all true.2 He
took mathematics as his model of knowledge given that its ideas were clear
and distinct and that its truths were certain.
The third seminal figure, Spinoza, was a Jew born in Amsterdam, whose
own rationalist and unorthodox views led to his expulsion from the Jewish
community in 1656 for heresy. Like Descartes, he believed in the primacy of
deduction and in a mechanistic view of the universe; however, he did not
adopt Cartesian dualism, arguing instead that the universe is composed of a
single substance, which he viewed as God, and which is refracted differently
in the attributes of mind and matter. In his major work, the Ethics (1677), he
urged that the highest good consists in the rational mastery over one’s
passions and ultimately in the acceptance of the order and harmony in nature,
which is an expression of the divine nature. Subsequent Enlightenment
thinkers, such as John Locke (1632–1704) and David Hume (1711–1776)
in Britain, Voltaire (1694–1778), Diderot, and d’Alembert in France, as well
as Gotthold Lessing (1729–1781) in Germany, encouraged more skeptical,
rational, and tolerant approaches to religion. The most common approach
was “deism,” which saw divine laws as natural and rational, and dismissed all
superstition, miracles, and sacraments.
It is worth looking briefly at the empiricist philosopher John Locke
(1632–1704), whose most influential works were An Essay Concerning
Human Understanding and Two Treatises on Civil Government, both published in 1690. In the Essay Locke denied Descartes’ view that the mind has
“innate ideas,” ideas that it is simply born with. Rather, the mind is initially a
tabula rasa or blank slate upon which our experience of the world is written.3
Locke argues that all our ideas come from experience, through either sensation
or reflection. We receive distinct ideas of the objects in the external world
through our senses, such as the ideas of yellow, white, hard, cold, or soft; we
also receive ideas through reflection on the internal operation of our own
minds; these ideas include perception, thinking, doubting, reasoning, and
believing. These two operations, he says, are “the fountains of knowledge”
and there is no other source of knowledge or ideas (Essay, 89–90, 348).
The Scottish philosopher David Hume (1711–1776) developed some of
Locke’s empiricist notions toward more radical, skeptical, conclusions.
Where Locke had urged that our minds know the external world through
ideas, Hume argued that we know only ideas, not the external world itself. We
can know external objects only by the “perceptions they occasion” whether
The Enlightenment
117
they indeed are real or merely “illusions of the senses.”4 In fact, Locke himself
acknowledged that the real essence of things is unknowable (Essay, 271–273,
287, 303). Both Locke and Hume rejected the Aristotelian concept of
“substance” or essence as the underlying substratum of reality. Hume
develops the skepticism implicit in Locke’s rejection of substance: there are
no essences actually in the world, whether we are talking of external objects
such as a table, or human identity, or moral concepts such as goodness. All of
these are ultimately constructions of our minds, informed largely by custom
and habit. Indeed, in Hume’s view, even the human self or human identity was
not a fixed datum but a construction through a “succession of perceptions”
(THN, 135). In Hume’s eyes, the law of causality, on which modern science
was based, has merely a conventional validity, based on nothing more than
the authority of custom or the habitual, “constant conjunction” of phenomena (THN, 316).
In France, the main figures of the Enlightenment were Voltaire
(1694–1778), Denis Diderot (1713–1784), and Jean d’Alembert. Perhaps
more than anyone else, Voltaire popularized the ideas of Newton and Locke.
His numerous works included the Philosophical Dictionary (1764) and a
fictional philosophical tale, Candide (1759), in which he promulgated the
necessity of reason and experience, and the notion that the world is governed
by natural laws. He mocked the optimism, determinism, and rationalism of
the German philosopher Gottfried Leibniz who believed in a preestablished
harmony in the world, lampooning the latter’s position in the phrase
“Everything is for the best in this best of all possible worlds.” The implication
is that abstract reason of itself does not comprehend the infinite variety of
human situations. In this sense, reason is held up as a kind of comforting
fiction, pandering to the human need for order. Voltaire satirizes the
“rational” justifications for war, the intolerance of religions, the institutions
of inequality, the search for a utopia, the greed which undermines human
contentment, the gullibility of the masses, and the strength of human selfdeception; one of the two stark lessons to emerge is the need to experience the
world directly: “to know the world one must travel,” concludes Candide. The
other lesson is the need to work, in order to stave off the “three great evils,
boredom, vice and poverty.” In general, Voltaire championed liberty and
freedom of speech, though his sympathies did not extend to the common
man. The other French Enlightenment rationalists, Diderot and d’Alembert,
were the leading members of the group which produced the Encyclopedia,
a compendium of the latest scientific and philosophical knowledge. In
Germany, the tendencies of the Enlightenment were expressed by Gotthold
Lessing (1729–1781) and Moses Mendelssohn (1729–1786) who both
propounded philosophies of religious tolerance.
In political terms, several Enlightenment philosophers drew up a theory of
the ideal state or “social contract,” the contract that might be agreed upon
118
The Early Modern Period to the Enlightenment
by citizens of a state so that social life would be governed by laws and that
both the ruler’s power and the rights of his subjects would be defined. Many
of these thinkers postulate what men would be like in a state of nature, prior
to the formation of a social contract. Hobbes’ view of this state, as expressed
in his Leviathan (1651) is bleak: men would be in a perpetual state of war.
There would be merely “continual fear, and danger of violent death; and the
life of man, solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short.” The most important
philosopher in the formulation of political liberalism was John Locke, and
certain Enlightenment philosophies had a formative influence on the ideals
behind the French Revolution. Locke’s Second Treatise of Civil Government
(1690) condemned despotic monarchy and the absolute sovereignty of
parliaments, affirming that the people had a right to resist tyranny. Voltaire
advocated an enlightened monarchy or republic governed by the bourgeois
classes. Baron de Montesquieu (1689–1755) also influenced the French
Revolution, advancing a liberal theory based on a separation of executive,
legislative, and judicial powers. Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712–1778) exerted a powerful impact on the more radical stages of the Revolution
through his theories of democracy, egalitarianism, and the evils of private
property, as advocated in his Social Contract and Discourse on the Origin of
Inequality. However, in some ways, Rousseau hardly belongs to the main
trends of rationalist Enlightenment thought; he is often hailed as the father
of Romanticism on account of his exaltation of the state of nature over
civilization, and of the emotions and instincts over reason and conventional
learning.
In general, the major tendencies of Enlightenment philosophy were toward
rationalism, empiricism, pragmatism, and utilitarianism; these formed the
core of liberal-bourgeois thought. The main philosophical assumptions
behind this tradition of thought were: that the world is composed of
particular things which are distinct and separate from one another (philosophical pluralism); that consciousness (the human self) and the world are
mutually distinct, and there is an external reality independent of our minds;
and that general ideas are formed from the association and abstraction of
particular ones (in other words, general ideas are constructions of our minds
and are not found in the world). It is these assumptions that underlie the other
trends of Enlightenment thinking: that the world is a machine, subject to laws;
that human society is an aggregate of atomistic or separate individuals; that
the individual is an autonomous and free rational agent; that reliance on
reason and experience or observation will enable us to understand the world,
the human self, and enable historical progress in humanitarian, moral,
religious, and political terms.
These assumptions not only permeate Enlightenment discussions of literature, but have continued to inform many literary critical perspectives,
ranging from the experiential theories of literature advanced by figures such
The Enlightenment
119
as Matthew Arnold and Henry James to the New Criticism and other
movements of the twentieth century such as neo-Aristotelianism. The rationalist disposition of the Enlightenment has in various modifications informed
the aesthetics of Kant, Hegel, Marx, and Croce. Equally, much criticism
flowing from the Romantics and French symbolists, as well as from thinkers
such as Schopenhauer, Nietzsche, Bergson, Heidegger, and Sartre, has urged
the problematic nature of Enlightenment assumptions. The psychoanalytic
criticism inspired by Freud and Jung, and more recent movements such as
structuralism, deconstruction, and postcolonial criticism have subjected
Enlightenment rationalism and empiricism to searching intellectual and
ideological scrutiny. They have questioned the idea that entities exist independently, the epistemological validity of subject–object dualism, the idea of
an independent external world, and the notion that language somehow
reflects or corresponds with reality. It should be remembered, however, that
many of these critiques were initiated by the Enlightenment philosophers
themselves and were most articulately expressed by Hegel long before the
advent of more modern developments.
Enlightenment Literary Criticism: Language, Taste, and
Imagination
A very direct connection between Enlightenment philosophy and literary
criticism occurs through the various philosophies of language in the eighteenth century, the most important being the theory of John Locke. Many
scholars have argued that Locke’s empiricism stimulated in literature a
relatively novel preoccupation with sensory detail, scientific description, and
particularity. This influence undermined the neoclassical conception, stretching all the way back through Renaissance and medieval writers to Aristotle,
that poetry speaks a universal language and expresses general truths. Also
influential were the psychological aspects of empiricism, presenting the mind
as not merely receiving ideas passively from the external world but as active in
constructing experience through associating those ideas in various combinations. Poetry attempted to express human psychology and to register the
mind’s association of ideas. In fact, the doctrine of “associationism,” running
through thinkers such as Locke, Hume, Hartley, and Condillac, became a
force in literary critical discussions of poetic language.5
The philosophical assumptions of the Enlightenment can now be examined
in the literary and cultural criticism of some major thinkers. We can consider
the views of language formulated by Locke and Vico; the popularization of
Locke’s ideas and their integration with neoclassical and even precursive
Romantic notions in the work of Addison; the theories of taste and judgment
offered by Hume and Burke (whose thinking, specifically opposed to many
120
The Early Modern Period to the Enlightenment
Enlightenment values, can fruitfully be considered here); and the analysis of
women’s social and educational status undertaken by Mary Wollstonecraft,
who effectively extends Enlightenment ideals to the notion of gender.
John Locke (1632–1704)
John Locke laid the foundations of classical British empiricism, and his
thought is often characterized as marked by tolerance, moderation, and
common sense. The implications of Locke’s empiricism are still with us: many
ideological forces still encourage us to look at the world as an assemblage of
particular facts, yielding sensations which our minds then process in arriving
at abstract ideas and general truths.
Locke’s philosophy of language anticipates a great deal of modern literary
critical thinking about language. His fundamental endeavor is to show how
closely language is connected with the process of thought and he therefore
urges the need to use language in the most precise way so as to avoid
unnecessary confusion in our concepts. In an influential passage that impinges
profoundly on literature, Locke makes his famous distinction between two
faculties, wit and judgment:
men who have a great deal of wit, and prompt memories, have not always the
clearest judgment or deepest reason. For wit lying most in the assemblage of
ideas, and putting those together with quickness and variety . . . thereby to make
up pleasant pictures and agreeable visions in the fancy; judgment, on the
contrary, lies quite on the other side, in separating carefully, one from another,
ideas wherein can be found the least difference, thereby to avoid being misled . . .
This is a way of proceeding quite contrary to metaphor and allusion; wherein for
the most part lies that entertainment and pleasantry of wit, which strikes so
lively on the fancy. . . (Essay, II, xi, 2)
Locke effectively revives the age-old antagonism between philosophy and
poetry (or rhetoric). The domain of poetry is governed by wit, which sees
identities and affinities between disparate things, an imaginative and fictive
operation designed to please the fancy. The realm of philosophy, on the
other hand, is presided over by judgment, by the clear, cool ability to
separate what does not belong together, to distinguish clearly between
things, in the interests of furthering knowledge. The impulse of one lies
toward confusion and conflation, while the impetus of the other is toward
clarity. The poetic realm is the realm of fancy, of figurative language, of
metaphor and allusion; the language of philosophy shuns adornment, and
engages with the real world. Locke attempts to dismantle the poetic effort of
many centuries to fuse the claims of delight and instruction, viewing these as
opposed rather than allied.
The Enlightenment
121
Indeed, Locke urges that figurative speech comprises one of the “abuses” of
language, and calls rhetoric a “powerful instrument of error and deceit”
(Essay, III, x, 34). Locke defines language as “the instrument of knowledge”
(Essay, III, ix, 21). The imperfection of words lies in the uncertainty of what
they signify. He lists a number of willful faults which contribute to the failure
of communication: the use of words without “clear and distinct ideas,” or the
use of “signs without anything signified”; affecting obscurity, by using words
in new and unusual ways; and using obscurity to cover up conceptual
difficulties and inadequacies (Essay, III, x, 2–22). Locke speculates that if
there were a dictionary to standardize and clarify all language usage, many of
the current controversies would end (Essay, III, xi, 9–26). Locke is effectively
calling for a literalization of language, an extrication of words from their
metaphorical and allegorical potential, a potential accumulated over many
centuries. Locke’s voice is perhaps the most pronounced sign of the bourgeois
refashioning of language into a utilitarian instrument, a scientistic tendency
that still infects some of our composition classrooms to this day.
Locke’s seemingly harsh views of figurative speech need to be appraised in
the context of his skeptical empiricism. Anticipating Saussure and many
modern theorists of language, Locke emphasizes that the connection between
signs (words) and ideas is not natural but is made by “a perfectly arbitrary
imposition” which is regulated by “common use, by a tacit consent” (Essay,
III, ii, 8). He emphasizes that “general” and “universal” do not belong to
“real existence” or to “things themselves”: they are inventions of the human
mind, designed to facilitate our understanding of the world (Essay, III, iii,
11–12). The essence of any general idea such as “man” is not found in the
world; it is a purely verbal essence; Locke denies that there are in the world
any “real essences” that we can know (Essay, III, iii, 13). Nature itself
contains only particulars, and its apparent regularity and order are projections of our own thought processes whose medium is language.
All of this points to a “coherence” theory of language, whereby language is
not referential (referring to some external reality), but acquires meaning only
through the systematic nature and coherence of its expression of our perceptions. Indeed, Locke’s urgent desire for linguistic clarity is perhaps a reaction
to the failing system of referentiality: the entire edifice, the entire equation and
harmony of language and reality, promulgated through centuries of theological building on the notion of the Logos (embracing the idea of God as both
Word and the order of creation expressed by this), is about to crumble.
Joseph Addison (1672–1719)
Joseph Addison contributed much to the development of the essay form,
which, like the literary form of the letter, flourished in the eighteenth century.
Together with his friend and colleague Richard Steele, he authored a series of
122
The Early Modern Period to the Enlightenment
articles in the periodicals The Tatler (1709–1711) and The Spectator
(1711–1714). Steele referred to his age as “a corrupt Age,” devoted to luxury,
wealth, and ambition rather than to the virtues of “good-will, of Friendship,
of Innocence.”6 He urges that people’s actions should be directed toward the
public good rather than merely private interests, and that these actions should
be governed by the dictates of reason, religion, and nature (Spectator, 68–70).
In The Spectator there are several essays or articles dealing with specifically
literary-critical issues, such as the nature of tragedy, wit, genius, the sublime,
and the imagination. As far as tragedy goes, Addison and Steele advise
following the precepts of Aristotle and Horace. Their general prescription
is to follow nature, reason, and the practice of the ancients (Spectator, 87).
Addressing themselves to a broad middle-class public immersed in the
materialist and pragmatist ideologies of bourgeois thought, their insistence
on classical values might be seen as part of their endeavor to cultivate the
moral, religious, and literary sensibilities of this class; they were nonetheless
obliged to accommodate the more recent attitudes toward beauty and the
imagination, attitudes gesturing in the direction of Romanticism, which
equally undermined the conventional values of this political class.
Giambattista Vico (1668–1744)
The Italian philosopher Vico articulated a historical view of the progress of
human thought, language, and culture that anticipates the evolutionary
perspectives of Hegel, Marx, and others. His major work was Scienza nuova
(New Science), first published in 1725. He was affiliated with a group of
radical intellectuals who reacted against the central tenets of medieval
philosophy and who espoused the rationalist and empiricist values of the
Enlightenment. He urges that the “new science” must be “a rational civil
theology of divine providence,” demonstrating in its analysis of human
institutions, “what providence has wrought in history.”7
In a strikingly new fashion, Vico’s insights into poetry form an integral part
of his attempt to explain the origins and development of human society. Vico
sees the progression of wisdom or knowledge as moving from the senses (the
province of poetry) through reason (the sphere of philosophy) to revelation.
The first poets, says Vico, not having our power of abstraction, used a “poetic
logic” of four basic tropes: metaphor, metonymy, synecdoche, and irony (NS,
para. 409, p. 131). In their initial use among primitive peoples, these four
tropes represented the only engagement with the world, which had no
underlying literal basis. As the human mind developed, a more rational,
scientific, and literal expression of our relationship with the world was
established and the tropes were reduced to a figurative status, articulated in
relation to this literal level. They remained, however, as integrally related to
the literal and endured as its foundation. Thus, Vico attributes two important
The Enlightenment
123
historical functions to poetry, or what he calls “poetic wisdom”: on it were
founded the religious and civil institutions of the first peoples; and it provided
the embryonic basis for all further learning.
David Hume (1711–1776)
As noted earlier, the Scottish empiricist and skeptical philosopher David
Hume was one of the major figures of the Enlightenment. His essay “Of the
Standard of Taste” (1757) raises questions about the standards of aesthetic
judgment that are still pertinent today: how do we reconcile people’s conflicting judgments about taste? Can we arrive at an objective standard? Hume
stresses that the rules of art are not fixed by a priori reasonings but by
experience, by “general observations, concerning what has been universally
found to please in all countries and all ages.”8 True taste, according to Hume,
is a rational process; we rely on good sense to check our prejudices, and reason
is requisite to the formation of good taste in a number of ways. We must be
aware of the structure of the work, of the way the various parts relate to the
whole, of the “consistence and uniformity of the whole,” as well as the end or
purpose of the work of art. Even poetry, says Hume, “is nothing but a chain of
propositions and reasonings . . . however disguised by the colouring of the
imagination.” Hence the poet himself needs not only taste and invention but
judgment; likewise, the “same excellence of faculties” is required by the critic
who would achieve good taste (“OST,” 494). The standard of taste, then, is
not objective; rather, it is based on subjective consensus – but only the
consensus of “qualified” people.
In attempting to rescue artistic taste from mere subjectivism, Hume appeals
to a number of factors, all of which are based on experience. First, there is a
canon of literature and art that has survived the judgment of various times and
cultures, a canon established by consensus. Next, this consensus points to a
common human nature which responds universally to certain features of art,
such as elegance and organic unity. Finally, this consensus is the consensus of
a qualified elite of critics who, through their ability to reach a disinterested
aesthetic perspective, are authorized to act as the arbiters of true taste, as the
voice of that common human nature in its intact, cultivated, and unbiased
state.
Edmund Burke (1729–1797)
Edmund Burke is best known for his political writings and his activities as a
statesman. By far his most famous work was his Reflections on the Revolution
in France (1790), a scathing attack on numerous aspects of the French
Revolution of 1789. Here Burke expresses a desire to conserve the essential
economic and political fabric of feudalism. He appeals to the authority of the
124
The Early Modern Period to the Enlightenment
past and opposes the collective wisdom and experience of the past to what he
sees as the abstract rationalism of the French revolutionists. Like all conservatives, he maintains that, in reforming society, we must adopt a policy of
gradual change, and our starting point must be the actual status quo rather
than an idealistic and abstractly rational set of principles which may not be
related at all to actual social and economic conditions. He insists on the
validity and legitimacy of the feudal hierarchy, a hereditary monarchy, with a
hereditary nobility and clergy occupying dominant positions. And finally, he
insists that liberty is indissolubly tied to social responsibility and duty.
These political dispositions are somewhat anticipated in Burke’s much
earlier text, A Philosophical Enquiry into the Origins of Our Ideas of the
Sublime and Beautiful (1757). Burke is here writing in a tradition that goes
back to Longinus’ treatise On the Sublime (which Burke had read), and which
was revived in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries largely under the
auspices of Kant and Romantic writers. Burke’s essay draws on the insights of
Addison and Hume, and like these thinkers, he adopts a broadly empiricist
perspective. Burke’s comments on the sublime and beautiful anticipate in
some respects the account later offered by Kant. He says that whatever excites
ideas of pain, danger, and terror is a source of the sublime; and the sublime is
the “strongest emotion which the mind is capable of feeling,” far more
powerful than emotions of pleasure.9 Ultimately, pain is so potent in force
because it is “an emissary” of death, the “king of terrors.” It is when we are
able to distance ourselves from such pain and terror that we can find them
delightful; and it is this feeling which is sublime (PE, 550). The sublime differs
from the beautiful in fundamental ways: sublime objects are vast, rugged,
obscure, dark; beautiful objects are small, smooth, light, and delicate.
Sublime objects are founded on pain while beautiful objects give pleasure
(PE, 550).
Mary Wollstonecraft (1759–1797)
Acknowledged as one of the first feminist writers of modern times, Mary
Wollstonecraft was a radical thinker whose central notions were framed by
the French Revolution of 1789. Her Vindication of the Rights of Men (1790),
like Thomas Paine’s The Rights of Man, was a defense of the Revolution
against the scathing attacks expressed in Burke’s Reflections on the Revolution in France (1790). Wollstonecraft has rightly been characterized as an
Enlightenment thinker, propounding arguments in favor of reason, against
hereditary privilege and the entire inequitable apparatus of feudalism. Yet
Wollstonecraft added to these conventional Enlightenment elements an
important concern for the economic and educational rights of women, as
expressed in the work for which she is best known, A Vindication of the
Rights of Woman (1792).
The Enlightenment
125
Wollstonecraft’s troubled life reflects and underlies her ideological dispositions. One of six children, she suffered, with the rest of her family, at the
hands of a somewhat despotic father. She experienced first hand the economic
disadvantages to which women were subject, attempting to earn a living in the
conventional female occupations as a governess and lady’s maid; she was a
victim of unfortunate romantic encounters, first with the painter Henry Fuseli
and then with an American businessman, Gilbert Imlay, with whom she
conceived a child and whose infidelity led her to two suicide attempts; she
eventually married the political philosopher William Godwin (whose Political Justice appeared in 1793); a few days after giving birth to a daughter (who
would marry the poet Shelley and write the novel Frankenstein), she died.
Notwithstanding her turbulent life, she mixed with some of the prominent
radical figures of her day: the dissenter Dr. Richard Price (who initially
provoked Burke’s anti-revolutionary sentiments), Thomas Paine, and of
course William Godwin himself.
The issues Wollstonecraft raises in A Vindication of the Rights of Woman
have remained crucial to much feminist literary criticism. Her central argument is that if woman “be not prepared by education to become the
companion of man, she will stop the progress of knowledge and virtue; for
truth must be common to all.”10 She points out that woman can cooperate in
this enterprise only if she understands why she ought to be virtuous, and only
if “freedom strengthens her reason till she comprehends her duty,” part of
which is to be a “patriot.” If the rights of man merit consideration, claims
Wollstonecraft, then by a “parity of reasoning,” women’s rights also claim
attention. These claims are founded on two fundamental principles: firstly,
that not only men but also women have “the gift of reason”; and secondly,
that no authority can simply coerce women into fulfilling a given set of duties
(VRW, 86–88). Like Christine de Pisan many centuries earlier, Wollstonecraft endeavors to redeem the notion of reason from its history of male abuse.
For many centuries “deeply rooted prejudices have clouded reason, and . . .
spurious qualities have assumed the name of virtues.” Wollstonecraft sees the
entire history and structure of feudalism as based on irrational expediency
and prejudice, rather than on reason: “Such, indeed has been the wretchedness that has flowed from hereditary honours, riches, and monarchy” (VRW,
91–93). Wollstonecraft makes a powerful assertion: “the rights of Woman
may be respected, if it be fully proved that reason calls for this respect, and
loudly demands JUSTICE for one-half of the human race” (VRW, 89). What
she is essentially appealing to are the Enlightenment principles of reason,
duty, freedom, self-determination, and even patriotism; her feminism consists
in the demand that these same principles extend to women; she is not, like
later feminists, devaluing these principles themselves as outgrowths of a
patriarchal history.
126
The Early Modern Period to the Enlightenment
Women are taught, says Wollstonecraft, to nurture qualities such as
cunning, an appearance of weakness, and a duplicitous “outward” obedience; they are encouraged to develop “artificial graces” whereby “their sole
ambition is to be fair, to raise emotion instead of inspiring respect.” Such
attributes, they are advised, will earn them the “protection of man” (VRW,
100, 121). Even Rousseau, whom Wollstonecraft otherwise admires, suggests
that woman should exercise cunning and coquetry to make herself “a more
alluring object of desire.” Wollstonecraft’s retort is simple: “What nonsense!” (VRW, 108). A more recent example of such “nonsense” is to be
found in John Gregory’s handbook on proper female behavior, entitled A
Father’s Legacy to his Daughters (1774). Gregory advises women to cultivate
such “virtues” as a “fondness for dress,” a capacity for dissimulation, and the
avoidance of “delicacy of sentiment” (VRW, 111, 116). Wollstonecraft also
attacks female writers such as Hester Lynch Thrale Piozzi, Mme. de Sta€el and
the celebrated French writer Mme. Felicite Genlis, as effectively reiterating
“masculine sentiments” (VRW, 202–205).
Underlying all of these prescriptions for female behavior, Wollstonecraft
sees one fundamental principle, rooted in educational strategy: an endeavor
to “enslave women by cramping their understandings and sharpening their
senses” (VRW, 104). In Wollstonecraft’s view, women are effectively constrained within particularity, forced to look at the world as a series of discrete
and unrelated phenomena, whose connections might as well be random. In
being deprived of the ability to generalize, women are, in effect, deprived of
the ability to think (VRW, 116, 118). There are degrading and injurious
consequences of women being given such a haphazard education: women are
unable to act as genuine moral agents: without the power of reason, they
cannot make moral choices and are disposed to blind obedience of whatever
power structure can claim authority over them. Another prerequisite of moral
action is freedom; Wollstonecraft wisely states that liberty “is the mother of
virtue” (VRW, 121).
Hence, the national education of women is of the “utmost consequence”
(VRW, 297). Wollstonecraft recommends national day schools which will
be free to all classes of society, and where both sexes will be educated
together. Such a system will cultivate friendship and love between the sexes.
Instead of rote-learning of what they do not comprehend, children must be
encouraged to think for themselves, by exchanging and testing their ideas
against those of their peers. Religion, history, and politics “might also be
taught by conversations in the Socratic form” (VRW, 283–288). Such
intellectual independence bears similarities with her view of the artist’s
independence. The true artist does not simply make a “servile copy” of
nature but uses an “exalted imagination, . . . fine senses and enlarged
understanding” to form an ideal picture or harmonious whole. As a result
The Enlightenment
127
of the education she prescribes, woman will acquire a “dignified beauty . . .
physical and moral beauty ought to be attained at the same time” (VRW,
290–291). Wollstonecraft here effectively redefines female beauty as an
integral product of a rational, affectionate, and independent disposition, a
quality behind which lies not merely the accident of appearance but a
revolutionizing of gender relations. She also urges: “Make women rational
creatures and free citizens, and they will quickly become good wives and
mothers” (VRW, 299).
Hence, Wollstonecraft seeks to extend to women the Enlightenment
principle of basing both knowledge and morality upon reason, which itself
presupposes access to the right kinds of information, a nurturing of
coherent thinking, and, above all, the freedom to think and judge for
themselves. Wollstonecraft implicitly rejects any sharp distinction between
the private, “domestic” sphere of women and the public sphere of men.
Later feminists have often diverged from Wollstonecraft’s views of marriage, her view that morality and virtue should be founded on eternal
principles and even her appeal to reason. What is enduring about her
vision, however, is its insistence that female equality in any sphere depends
ultimately on a radical restructuring of the social and political order; her
arguments for education remain pertinent today; and her view that genuine
morality cannot be based on ignorance and blind obedience retains its
inspiring force.
Notes
1. Francis Bacon, The New Organon, ed. Fulton H. Anderson (Indianapolis: BobbsMerrill, 1960), pp. 47–50.
2. The Philosophical Works of Descartes: Volume I, trans. E. S. Haldane and
G. R. T. Ross (NP: Dover Publications, 1955), p. 101.
3. John Locke, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. A. D. Woozley
(Glasgow: Fontana/Collins, 1975), p. 89. Hereafter cited as Essay.
4. David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature: Book One, ed. D. G. C. Macnabb
(Glasgow: Fontana/Collins, 1978), pp. 113, 130–131. Hereafter cited as
THN.
5. William Keach, “Poetry, after 1740,” in The Cambridge History of Literary
Criticism, Volume IV: The Eighteenth Century, ed. H. B. Nisbet and Claude
Rawson (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), pp. 129–133.
6. Addison and Steele, Selections from the Tatler and the Spectator, ed. Robert J.
Allen (New York: Holt, Rhinehart, and Winston, 1961), pp. 67–68. Hereafter
cited as Spectator.
7. The New Science of Giambattista Vico, revised translation of third edition,
Thomas Goddard Bergin and Max Harold Fisch (Ithaca and New York: Cornell
University Press, 1968), para. 364, p. 110. Hereafter cited as NS.
128
The Early Modern Period to the Enlightenment
8. David Hume, “Of the Standard of Taste,” in David Hume, Four Dissertations
(New York: Garland, 1970), para. 488. Hereafter cited as “OST”; numbers refer
to paragraphs.
9. Edmund Burke, A Philosophical Enquiry into the Origins of Our Ideas of
the Sublime and Beautiful (New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1990), p. 549. Hereafter cited as PE.
10. Mary Wollstonecraft, Vindication of the Rights of Woman, ed. Miriam Brody
Kramnick (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1985), pp. 85–86. Hereafter cited as
VRW.
Chapter 9
The Aesthetics of Kant and Hegel
Immanuel Kant (1724–1804)
Much modern literary and cultural theory has encouraged us to view
literature and art within their historical and ideological contexts. However,
in both academia and popular culture, we are still today very familiar with
terms such as “art for art’s sake” and we still hear poetry, music, and art
spoken of as “ends in themselves,” to be enjoyed for their own sake. The idea
behind such expressions is that literature must be free from any specific moral
obligations, or political purposes: its primary purpose is to give pleasure.
Most thinkers from Plato to the eighteenth century would have been puzzled
or exasperated at such an idea: while they might admit that one function of
literature is to “delight” us, they would insist that literature has an important
moral, religious, or social dimension.
The idea of literature as autonomous, as having no purpose beyond itself,
received its first articulate expression by a philosopher, Immanuel Kant, in his
Critique of Judgment (1790). This book proved to have a vast influence on
subsequent aesthetics and poetry, extending into our own day. Kant is usually
considered, along with G. F. W. Hegel, as one of the two greatest philosophers
of modern times. By far the most important and groundbreaking of Kant’s
works was the Critique of Pure Reason (1781). Kant himself saw this work as
initiating a “Copernican Revolution” in philosophy, in virtue of its threefold
endeavor: firstly, Kant wished to define the boundaries of human reason and
knowledge: what kinds of things can reason tell us about and what kinds of
things are beyond its grasp? Secondly, he wished to establish a secure
foundation for metaphysics. The empiricist philosophers Locke and Hume
had argued that, since all of our knowledge comes from experience, this
knowledge cannot be grounded on any necessary laws. In the wake of Hume’s
skepticism – a skepticism which, as Kant recalls, aroused him from his
“dogmatic slumbers” – Kant was concerned to ground metaphysics on
principles which were a priori (independent of experience) and necessary.
Literary Criticism from Plato to the Present: An Introduction
© 2011 M. A. R. Habib. ISBN: 978-1-405-16034-6
M. A. R. Habib
130
The Early Modern Period to the Enlightenment
In other words, such knowledge as we do have must be shown to possess
absolute certainty. Finally, Kant made a distinction between phenomena and
noumena. Phenomena refer to the world of objects which we experience,
objects as they appear to us; noumena, or objects as they might be in
themselves, are objects which are merely “thinkable” and outside of our
possible experience. This distinction served not only to secure the world of
phenomena on a sure foundation but also to provide a feasible basis for the
world of morality which for Kant is the noumenal realm (the project of Kant’s
next work, the Critique of Practical Reason, 1788), and which he wishes to
protect against the rationalist and empiricist onslaught of the Enlightenment
thinkers. Kant held that only the phenomenal world, grounded in sense
experience, could be known by the intellectual faculty of pure reason. The
noumenal entities, which he named as God, freedom, and immortality, were a
function of the “practical” moral faculty, the will. Causality indeed reigns in
Kant’s phenomenal realm, which is effectively the world bequeathed by
modern science; but its grasp cannot extend into the noumenal world, which
is essentially the domain of morality and faith.
The nature of aesthetic judgment
In his Critique of Judgment, Kant acknowledges the subjective character of
our aesthetic judgments but wishes to show that they are still based on
necessary and universal principles. Central to his view of aesthetic judgment
is the concept of “purposiveness.” This refers to the fact that we must
assume a certain coherence and connection among the appearances of the
external world or nature so that we can reflect coherently upon it. We
presuppose a harmony between nature and our cognitive powers, as if they
were suited or adapted to each other. It is this presumed harmony, which
Kant calls “purposiveness,” which gives us pleasure.1 According to Kant,
when we make an aesthetic judgment, we make a judgment about the form
of an object (not its content as given through our senses); the object’s form
gives rise to pleasure because it exhibits a harmony with our cognitive
powers, namely our understanding and imagination. We then call the object
“beautiful” and our ability to judge the object by such a pleasure is “taste”
(CJ, 30). An aesthetic judgment is not a judgment of cognition; it does not
refer to the object and gives us no knowledge of it. It refers only to the
perceiving subject, to our self and its feeling of pleasure or displeasure. It
tells us only about how we, as subjects, are affected by our mental
representation of the object.
There are, according to Kant, certain distinctive features of aesthetic
judgment as we use it in describing an object as beautiful. To begin with,
a judgment of taste is “disinterested.” In other words, when we judge an
object to be beautiful, we have no interest, no ulterior motive, in the object’s
The Aesthetics of Kant and Hegel
131
actual existence. We do not care if the object produces certain effects in the
world, or if it has some kind of utility or even a positive moral value. In
Kantian terms, we have no interest in the object’s practical purpose in the
world. In an aesthetic judgment we regard an object or any aspect of nature as
having “purposiveness without purpose.” We are content simply to contemplate the object and to take pleasure in it. As Kant says, beautiful things have
no meaning, and he defines beauty as the object of a disinterested judgment
of taste.
Do aesthetic judgments have universal validity?
However, if aesthetic judgment is subjective, if our perception of beauty says
nothing about the object but reflects merely our feeling of pleasure, how can
we make others agree with our judgment? Kant’s answer to this dilemma
reverberates through much of modern literary theory. If our judgment of an
object’s beauty is disinterested, this means that our judgment doesn’t rest on
any subjective inclination or private conditions, a feature which implies a
ground of pleasure for all people. For example, if I like a particular portrait,
I cannot base this liking on the fact that the portrait reminds me of my father,
or that I see a certain moral significance in it: these would be private motives
which obviously cannot apply to everyone. My judgment of the portrait as
beautiful must be free of all such private reasons and conditions. According to
Kant, we can claim that our judgment is universal – i.e., that others must agree
with our judgment – if we separate from it everything which has to do with
mere sensory pleasure (which is based on private feeling) or with our ideas of
the morally good (CJ, 379).
Kant also states that taste is a kind of sensus communis, a sense shared
by all of us. The principles of this “common sense” are to think for oneself,
in an unbiased way; to think from the perspective of everyone else; and to
think consistently. We can thereby override the private conditions of our
judgment and reflect on our own judgment from a “universal” point of
view (CJ, 160–161). However, aesthetic judgments have merely a subjective
universality (CJ, 378). Even though we speak of beauty as though it were
a characteristic of the object, what we are really claiming is that the
connection between the object and the subject’s feeling of pleasure will be
the same in everyone. Kant offers a related insight here which is still highly
pervasive today: no rule or rational argument can enforce our recognition
of beauty. In aesthetic judgments we always want to submit the object to
our own eyes, to see whether or not we find it beautiful (CJ, 59). We can see
here not only the overwhelming importance Kant attaches to direct experience in aesthetic judgments, but the grounds he establishes for arriving at a
notion of beauty based on consensus. An object we consider beautiful will
give rise to a harmonious interplay of the cognitive powers, imagination and
132
The Early Modern Period to the Enlightenment
understanding, in everyone. Such harmony between these two faculties, he
says, is required not only for aesthetic judgments but for cognition in general,
hence we can assume that this harmony is a universal feature of our subjective
apparatus (CJ, 62, 159).
The role of imagination in aesthetic judgment
Kant’s account of the role of imagination in an aesthetic judgment laid
the foundation for a great deal of Romantic theory and literary practice.
He defines an aesthetic judgment as an ability to judge an object in reference
to the “free lawfulness” of imagination (CJ, 91). In our everyday knowledge of objects, imagination is reproductive: it reproduces the information
given to us by our senses into images; and this reproduction is subject
to certain laws of association, and to the rules of the understanding.
However, when we approach the world from an aesthetic perspective, our
imagination is not required to undergo the same constraints. In this case,
understanding serves imagination rather than vice versa (CJ, 91–92). The
imagination can now be productive and spontaneous; it can combine
images differently from their sequence in our ordinary experience, to yield
new and surprising combinations. What gives us pleasure is this free play
of imagination. However, even in this creative role, imagination is not
entirely free: its creations must still not violate the basic laws of understanding. This is why Kant refers to the “free lawfulness” of the imagination: it is a lawfulness (an adherence to the basic laws of understanding)
which is not imposed on the imagination but self-exercised, even in its
free play. This seems to be what Kant means when he talks of a subjective harmony of imagination and understanding, which he equates with
a “purposiveness without purpose.” It is this felt harmony between our
cognitive powers which gives us aesthetic pleasure. Because it is felt, each
person must experience it for herself and there can be no objective rule as to
what constitutes beauty. Kant defines beauty as “the form of the purposiveness of an object, so far as this is perceived without any representation
of a purpose” (CJ, 384–386). He is not somehow averse to using art and
literature for moral purposes; he is simply concerned to establish that these
spheres have a certain autonomy and that, when they are connected with
other spheres such as morality and practical usefulness, the nature of the
connection be clearly understood. We see here an important departure on
Kant’s part from Enlightenment thought, indeed a point of transition to
Romantic thought. Not only is an aesthetic judgment freed from the bondage
of morality, not only is art transformed into an autonomous province, but it
is also made the province of subjective experience, at the heart of which
stands imagination in its supremely creative role, triumphing to some extent
over our conceptual faculty.
The Aesthetics of Kant and Hegel
133
The sublime
To grasp Kant’s vastly influential views on the sublime, we need to consider
some important statements he makes in the Critique of Pure Reason: just as
the concepts of the understanding give unity to the data of sense experience,
so the concepts of reason (which Kant calls ideas) give unity to the concepts
of the understanding. The concepts of reason are “transcendental” ideas
because they are not derived from experience and indeed they transcend
experience. For example, the idea of “virtue” or the idea of “humanity” is an
idea of reason, not derived from experience, but held up by reason as an ideal
to be aimed at. Reason sets forth an ideal of unity and totality toward which
the understanding can aspire.
Kant acknowledges that the beautiful and the sublime are similar in that
they are both concerned with pleasure rather than knowledge, a pleasure
that arises from the way in which the object is presented to us (rather than the
object itself). However, there are striking differences. To begin with, beauty
concerns the form of an object, which consists of definite boundaries; the
sublime concerns formless objects, which represent boundlessness. Beauty is
accompanied by a feeling of charm, of the furtherance of life, as well as by the
play of our imagination; the sublime gives rise to a different response: we feel a
momentary checking of our vital powers and then a stronger outflow of them.
Kant characterizes our feeling about the sublime as a “negative pleasure”: we
feel not charm or love but admiration or respect (CJ, 386–387).
These differences between the beautiful and the sublime rest on the connection between understanding and reason: when we judge natural beauty
as beautiful, we attribute to it a formal “purposiveness” whereby the object
in nature seems to be preadapted to our cognitive powers, producing a
harmonious interplay between our imagination and understanding that gives
pleasure. But the sublime presents a challenge to our cognitive faculties:
nature appears as contrapurposive: in its might and magnitude, it seems
beyond the reach and control of our mental apparatus. But this very
inadequacy of our imagination to represent such a magnitude of disordered
nature forces us to realize that we have another faculty, namely reason, which
transcends the entire world of nature and whose ideas are supersensible
(above the sphere of sensation). As Kant puts it, we realize that we have a
faculty of mind which surpasses every standard of sense. It is this realization
or ability to which Kant gives the name “sublime.” So the sublime is not in fact
a quality of nature but of our own minds. When nature appears to us as
infinite, this intuition excites in us the realization of an infinite power in
ourselves, namely the power of reason. Kant equates this feeling of the
sublime with moral feeling and with respect for our own supersensible or
spiritual destination. Our judging nature as sublime, says Kant, may initially
excite our fear, since we recognize our physical impotence as natural beings;
134
The Early Modern Period to the Enlightenment
but in consequence our imagination is elevated by referring itself to reason;
hence we call forth our strength, “to regard as small the objects of our natural
concerns, such as property, health and life” (CJ, 388–391).
The legacy of Kant
Kant’s philosophy and aesthetics have had vast influence, especially on
Romantic thought and Romantic conceptions of the literary imagination.
His notions of aesthetic freedom, artistic form, genius, and the non-utilitarian,
non-moral character of art exerted, for example, a profound impact on his
contemporaries Goethe and Schiller, as well as on Coleridge, the American
transcendentalists, and Poe. Both Romantic and non-Romantic thought attempted to overcome Kant’s absolute distinction between phenomena and
noumena: the noumenal world was brought back within the grasp of imagination and intellect. Indeed, in Kant’s work lay the very possibility of Hegel’s
system whose profound influence encompassed philosophy and aesthetics.
The philosophical problems raised by Kant heavily influenced Anglo-American
idealists such as Josiah Royce, and inspired the growth of the Marburg School,
whose prominent members included Ernst Cassirer (1874–1945) and Rudolph
Stammler (1856–1938). Kant’s ideal of aesthetic “disinterestedness” was
applied by subsequent writers such as Matthew Arnold and T. S. Eliot to the
sphere of literary criticism, which they saw as an activity ideally unencumbered
by immediate political and social exigencies. The influence of Kant’s aesthetics
extended to Russian criticism, in the views of Leo Tolstoy and others. In their
emphasis upon form and artistic autonomy these aesthetics also held considerable attraction for late nineteenth-century proponents of aestheticism, modernist writers and the New Critics. Kant’s treatment of the sublime is an
important component in the work of more recent writers such as Paul de Man
and Jean-François Lyotard. In more general terms, Kant’s philosophy has been
profoundly influential in its distinction of phenomena and noumena, its
insistence that the world is in fundamental ways our own construction, and
its grounding of morality on rationality and freedom. Finally, in Kant’s
thought, the notion of substance – the metaphysical foundation of Christian
theology – is subjectivized and reduced to one of 12 basic categories of human
understanding, thereby reduced to one of the viewpoints through which the
world can be apprehended.
Hegel (1770–1831)
Historical context of Hegel’s thought
The Hegelian philosophical system occupies a central place in the history and
genesis of modern Western thought. Hegel’s system was initially inspired by
The Aesthetics of Kant and Hegel
135
the French Revolution of 1789 which for him embodied the revolutionary
struggle of the bourgeois class throughout Europe to gain supremacy over
the feudal aristocracies and the clergy, and to replace the decaying and
irrational hierarchy of feudalism with a society based on reason, where both
social institutions and the human community embodied a rational outlook.
Revolutionary bourgeois philosophy and ideals received their most articulate
expression in Hegel’s work. In this sense, Hegel is a product of the Enlightenment, stressing as he does the supreme value of reason, which he brings into
confluence with the other main impulse of Enlightenment philosophy, empiricism, or the doctrine that knowledge derives from experience. However,
Hegel’s system, while not itself Romantic, is also deeply informed by certain
attributes derived from Romanticism: a commitment to the idea of unification
or totality and a concomitant belief that subject and object, the human self
and the world, are created and determined in their nature by each other.
Hence Hegel’s thought effects a vast synthesis of two major currents in
European intellectual and social history, the Enlightenment and Romanticism, which are conventionally seen to be opposed in many respects. In its
inheritance of both of these trends, Hegel’s philosophy was profoundly
influenced by the work of Kant.
The historical and philosophical consequences of Hegel’s thought were
even more momentous. His system influenced a wide range of philosophies
whose effects are still with us today: Marxism, the Anglo-American idealism
of the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, various branches of
existentialism, as well as the thought of many twentieth-century theorists
ranging from feminists such as Simone de Beauvoir and Julia Kristeva to
so-called “poststructuralist” thinkers such as Jacques Lacan and Jacques
Derrida. Hegel’s doctrines have informed much Protestant theology, and his
philosophy of history has profoundly affected numerous disciplines, including political and cultural theory. Equally, the Hegelian system has provoked
much opposition to itself, in the form of the nineteenth-century positivism of
Auguste Comte and Émile Durkheim, the early twentieth-century realism of
Bertrand Russell, G. E. Moore, and others, as well as the logical positivism,
the analytic philosophies and the various brands of empiricism which have
survived through the twentieth century.
Hegel’s first major publication was The Phenomenology of Spirit (1807),
perhaps the most difficult philosophical work ever written; this was followed
by his three-volume Science of Logic, published between 1812 and 1816. His
subsequent Encycoplaedia of the Philosophical Sciences was essentially a
restatement of his philosophy as a whole; and the final work published in his
lifetime was his Philosophy of Right (1821). After his death, his students and
disciples edited and published his lectures on various subjects, including
Lectures on the Philosophy of History, Lectures on Aesthetics, Lectures on
the Philosophy of Religion, and Lectures on the History of Philosophy.
136
The Early Modern Period to the Enlightenment
The Hegelian dialectic
All aspects of Hegel’s philosophy, logical, metaphysical, political, and aesthetic, are intimately tied to his philosophy of history. Hegel was the most
articulate and influential advocate of what was later called “historicism,” the
belief that nothing can be examined in abstraction from its particular history,
its causes, its effects, and its specific position in a broader historical scheme, a
scheme often said to be driven toward specific goals through the operation
of inexorable laws. In general, Hegel sees human history as a progress of
absolute mind or consciousness toward self-conscious freedom. The movement toward freedom is equated by Hegel with a movement toward greater
rationality, in both the operations of the human mind and the social and
political arrangements which express these. Essentially, when our own minds
have become rational and the laws and institutions that we live under are also
rational, we shall freely consent to live by those laws. Hegel also characterizes
this general movement as toward self-consciousness; in other words, as
consciousness moves to higher levels, it perceives increasingly that what it
previously took as the external world, as something alien and foreign to it, is
in fact essentially constituted, at its deepest rational core, by its own operations. What was previously confronted as substance is now recognized as
subjectivity. Hence Hegel also describes this entire movement as a progression from substance to subject.2
The most comprehensive avenue into understanding Hegel’s philosophy as
a whole is the notion of the dialectic, a notion which operates on three broad
levels: logical, phenomenological (the forms taken by consciousness), and
historical. The dialectic moves through three stages. Initially an object is
viewed in its given particularity as self-identical. In the second stage the
object’s “identity” is viewed as externalized or dispersed through the totality
of its social and historical relations: it is viewed in its universal aspect. In the
third stage the object’s identity is viewed as mediated (rather than immediately given) and as a combination of universal and particular. Hence the
dialectic is a mode of thinking that recognizes that the self and world stand in
necessary connection, that thought is not a static system of classification but
a self-criticizing process, and that the world as simply given to our senses is
not worthy of the name “reality.” Things in the world are to a large extent
defined by their relations; they cannot be understood in isolation, abstracted
from their connections with other things, but must be understood within
their historical contexts. As Hegel states in his Philosophy of Right, “What is
real is rational, and what is rational is real.” Reality is not simply a vast and
possibly incoherent assemblage of unrelated and unalterable facts (as crude
empiricism would have it); rather, in its core, it is rational, historically
progressive, and potentially unified, answering to the deepest demands of
our own rational selves. Hence the dialectic is a mode of thought that is not
The Aesthetics of Kant and Hegel
137
only rational but relational and historical.3 In fact, the dialectic as formulated
by Hegel is a historically cumulative process. As he states in his Lectures on
the History of Philosophy, Hegel sees this movement toward freedom operating historically, from the Oriental world, where only one person – the
emperor – is free, to the Greek and Roman world, where some people are free,
to the modern world where all are free.4
Hegel’s aesthetics
Hegel’s aesthetics are very closely tied to his philosophy of history. As we have
seen, Hegel sees human history as a progress of absolute mind or consciousness toward self-conscious rationality and freedom. Hegel sees art as one of
the stages traversed by the absolute idea or spirit on this journey. Art, like
religion and philosophy, is one of the modes through which spirit is expressed.
Like Kant, Hegel sees art and beauty as a realm that belongs to “sense, feeling,
intuition, imagination.” Its sphere is essentially different from that of
thought, and it is “precisely the freedom of production and configurations
that we enjoy in the beauty of art . . . the source of works of art is the free
activity of fancy which in its imaginations is itself more free than nature is.”5
True art, Hegel says, must be free (IA, 7). Rather than subserving the ends of
religion or morality, it must, like religion and philosophy, be a valid mode
of expressing the universal truths of the spirit:
in this its freedom alone is fine art truly art, and it only fulfils its supreme
task when it has placed itself in the same sphere as religion and philosophy, and
when it is simply one way of bringing to our minds and expressing the Divine,
the deepest interests of mankind, and the most comprehensive truths of the
spirit. (IA, 7)
In other words, art must fulfill the same functions and ends as these other
disciplines in its own way, and stand with relative independence, rather than
its end falling within those other disciplines. What distinguishes art from
other modes of expression is its ability to present even the most abstruse ideas
in sensuous form, such that our feelings and senses will be affected. Hence art
reconciles the worlds of sense and intellect, nature and thought, the external
and the internal. Art actually helps us to perceive reality by organizing the
chaos and contingency of the world such that we can see the “true meaning”
of appearances (IA, 9). Hence the reality embodied in art is higher than
“ordinary reality,” infected as the latter is with contingency and chance.
Like Aristotle and Sidney, Hegel points out that history is burdened with
the “contingency of ordinary life and its events,” whereas art evinces the
universal and “eternal powers that govern history” (IA, 9). Hegel is careful
to point out, however, that art is not the highest mode of expressing the truths
138
The Early Modern Period to the Enlightenment
of the spirit; in this function, it is superseded by both religion and philosophy
(IA, 9–10). Hegel here appears to suggest that art no longer serves the “real”
functions of being the primary form through which we can apprehend truth,
morality, cultural history, and ambition. And we no longer rely on art to
shape our view of the world, to shape our very modes of feeling and
perception.
Art’s vocation, Hegel says,
is to unveil the truth in the form of sensuous artistic configuration, to set forth
the reconciled opposition [between the worlds of thought and sense] . . . and so
to have its end and aim in itself. For other ends, like instruction, purification,
bettering, financial gain, struggling for fame and honour, have nothing to do
with the work of art as such, and do not determine its nature. (IA, 55)
Within the context of Hegel’s overall thesis that art must express the truths of
spirit, he nonetheless insists on the autonomy of art: its expression of spiritual
truth is not in the interests of pleasure, morality, or instruction; rather, this
expression of truth is an end in itself, the end and purpose of art.
Hegel considers how the absolute idea has been expressed historically in
particular forms of art. He cites three progressive configurations or stages of
art: symbolic, classical, and romantic. At the first stage, that of symbolic art,
the spiritual content or idea is still indefinite, obscure, and not well understood. Spiritual meaning is attached randomly to objects in nature, and a true
correspondence between content and form does not occur. For example, a
block of stone might symbolize the divine but it does not truly represent it.
This art exaggerates natural phenomena, distorting them into grotesqueness,
hugeness, and diversity in attempting to raise them to a spiritual level. The
spirit, says Hegel, “persists sublime above all this multiplicity of shapes which
do not correspond with it” (IA, 76–77). Hegel characterizes this stage as the
“artistic pantheism” of the Orient, which attempts to coerce any object,
however trivial, into bearing a spiritual significance. This, then, is the first,
symbolic, form of art, “with its quest, its fermentation, its mysteriousness,
and its sublimity” (IA, 77).
The second form is classical art which, says Hegel, annuls the twofold
defect of symbolic art: the indeterminate nature of the Idea embodied in it,
and the inadequate nature of this embodiment itself, the inadequate
“correspondence of meaning and shape” (IA, 77). In contrast, classical art
“is the free and adequate embodiment of the Idea in the shape peculiarly
appropriate to the Idea itself in its essential nature” (IA, 77). Hegel sees this
“appropriate” shape as the human form, his reasoning being that God, or the
“original Concept,” created the human form as an expression of spirit. Hence
art advances to anthropomorphism and personification, since the human
form is the only sensuous expression appropriate to spirit (IA, 78). Such
The Aesthetics of Kant and Hegel
139
personification, however, constitutes precisely the limitation of classical art:
“here the spirit is at once determined as particular and human, not as purely
absolute and eternal” (IA, 79). In other words, while the human form is the
most appropriate to expressing spirit, it nonetheless expresses it in a limited
manner, weighed down by its particular and material nature.
This defect demands a transition to a higher stage, the romantic form of
art. The unity which had been achieved between the idea and its reality is
here cancelled or annulled once again; and the opposition or difference of
these is reinstated, though at a higher plane than that of symbolic art.
Hegel acknowledges that the classical mode is the “pinnacle” of artistic
form, and its limitation is inherent in art itself, which must use sensuous forms
to express a spiritual content. For spirit, Hegel reminds us, is pure thought or
ideality whose infinite and organic expansiveness cannot be restrained or
expressed by outward, sensuous means (IA, 79). Hence romantic art cancels
the “undivided unity” of classical art because it expresses a higher content, it
expresses spirit or idea at a higher stage of self-development, coinciding with
Christianity’s view of God, a stage of self-conscious knowledge that enables
man to rise above his animal nature and to know himself as spirit (IA, 80).
If, then, we are confronted with spirit at this higher stage, what could be the
appropriate form for its embodiment or expression? The medium which will
express such spiritual content can no longer be sensuous and material; rather,
it must be the “inwardness of self-consciousness.” In this way, Hegel suggests,
“romantic art is the self-transcendence of art.” In this third stage, then,
the object or subject matter of art is subjectivity itself, the inner world of
emotion, spirituality, and thought (IA, 81). And yet, even if the romantic
artist is concerned to express the depths of human subjectivity, how can
she do this without an external, material medium of expression? Hegel’s
answer is that an external medium is indeed utilized but is recognized as
“inessential and transient,” a merely contingent circumstance employing
expedient devices such as plot, character, action, incident, as devised by the
imagination (IA, 81). What Hegel appears to be saying here is that elements
of the external world are used by the romantic artist not for their own
meaning but symbolically and metaphorically to express human thoughts and
emotions; they are recognized as merely contingent occasions for expressing
the inner world of subjectivity.
Hegel now passes on to the third part of his subject, which concerns the
realization of the three general forms of art in specific arts, namely, architecture, sculpture, painting, music, and poetry. The first (and lowest) of
the specific arts is architecture, which manipulates external organic nature
as “an external world conformable to art,” thereby making this world
cognate with spirit. Hence architecture is the fundamentally symbolic art
because spirit cannot be realized in such material. However, architecture
levels a space for the god and builds his temple, an enclosure for spiritual
140
The Early Modern Period to the Enlightenment
congregation (IA, 84). The next phase of art is contained in sculpture: into this
temple, the “god enters himself as the lightning-flash of individuality striking
and permeating the inert mass” (IA, 84). So sculpture, embodying the spirit,
fundamentally expresses the classical form of art: through sculpture, the spirit
stands in bodily form, in immediate unity with it (IA, 85).
So far, then, architecture has built the temple, and sculpture has set up
therein the image of the god. In the third stage, the spirit moves to a higher
level: instead of being embodied in material form, God – as spiritual
knowledge – passes into the subjectivity of the community, into the beliefs,
thoughts, and feelings of the community. God is seen as alternating between
his own “inherent unity” and his realization in the knowledge of the individuals within a community. This third phase of God’s development coincides
with romantic art, for the object of artistic representation is now the inner
world of human thought and feeling (IA, 85–86).
The sensuous material used in romantic art must be appropriate to such
“subjective inwardness.” What is this material? It is of three broad types:
color, musical sound, and “sound as the mere indication of inner intuitions
and ideas.” The modes of art corresponding to these materials are, respectively, painting, music, and poetry. The third and highest realization of
romantic art is poetry, which completes the liberation of spirit from sensuousness that was begun by painting and music (IA, 88). Hegel sees the proper
element of poetic representation as the imagination; and poetry itself “is the
universal art of the spirit,” which is not bound by sensuous material; instead,
“it launches out exclusively in the inner space and the inner time of ideas and
feelings” (IA, 89). And it is precisely at this stage that “art now transcends
itself . . . and passes over from the poetry of the imagination to the prose of
thought” (IA, 89).
The legacy of Hegel’s aesthetics
Hegel’s aesthetics have had a pervasive influence on both literature (as, for
example, on the dramas of Friedrich Hebbel) and criticism. The late nineteenth-century thinker and aesthetician Wilhelm Dilthey was profoundly
influenced by Hegel in his historicism; the modern aestheticians Benedetto
Croce and Giovanni Gentile developed many of Hegel’s insights. Hegel
anticipated some of the insights of Freud concerning the development of
identity, and the insights of Saussure concerning the nature of language. The
work of the Hungarian philosopher and aesthetician Gy€
orgy Lukacs is
informed by an intimate knowledge of the entire corpus of Hegel’s work.
The leading members of the Frankfurt School, such as Max Horkheimer,
Walter Benjamin, Theodor Adorno, Herbert Marcuse, and J€
urgen Habermas,
have stressed the debt of Marxism to certain features of Hegel’s thought,
such as the role of consciousness in creating the world, and have developed
The Aesthetics of Kant and Hegel
141
Marxist critique in aesthetic, cultural, and linguistic dimensions. Hegel’s
thought was fundamental to the articulation of existentialism, as in the work
of Jean-Paul Sartre, and of feminism, as expounded by Simone de Beauvoir.
Jacques Lacan, Jacques Derrida, and Jean Lyotard have continued to develop
or react against the insights originally offered by Hegel. Much of this recent
criticism has reacted against what it sees as the totalizing nature of Hegel’s
vision, stressing instead the local, the particular, and the notion of
“difference.” But it was Hegel who first articulated the notion of difference,
of relatedness, of human identity as a reciprocal and social phenomenon, of
the world as a social and historical human construction, of identity as
intrinsically constituted by diversity, of language as a system of human
perception, and of the very idea of otherness or alterity as it informs much
modern thought.
Notes
1. Immanuel Kant, Critique of Judgment, trans. Werner S. Pluhar (Indianapolis and
Cambridge: Hackett, 1987), pp. 22–25. Hereafter cited as CJ.
2. G. W. F. Hegel, Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. A. V. Miller (Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 1979), p. 17. Hereafter cited as PS.
3. Hegel’s Science of Logic, trans. A. V. Miller (London and New York: George Allen
and Unwin/Humanities Press, 1976), pp. 128–132, 479.
4. Hegel’s Lectures on the History of Philosophy, III, trans. E. S. Haldane and Frances
H. Simson (London and New York: Routledge and Kegan Paul/Humanities Press,
1963), pp. 217–218, 295, 363–369, 427–428.
5. Hegel’s Introduction to Aesthetics: Being the Introduction to the Berlin Aesthetic
Lectures of the 1820s, trans. T. M. Knox (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1979),
p. 5. Hereafter cited as IA.
Part IV
Romanticism and the Later
Nineteenth Century
Literary Criticism from Plato to the Present: An Introduction
© 2011 M. A. R. Habib. ISBN: 978-1-405-16034-6
M. A. R. Habib
Chapter 10
Romanticism
Romanticism was a broad intellectual and artistic disposition that arose
toward the end of the eighteenth century and reached its zenith during the
early decades of the nineteenth century. The ideals of Romanticism included
an intense focus on expressing human subjectivity, an exaltation of nature,
of childhood and spontaneity, of primitive forms of society, of human passion
and emotion, of the poet, of the sublime, and of imagination as a more
comprehensive and inclusive faculty than reason. The most fundamental
philosophical disposition of Romanticism has often been seen as irony, an
ability to accommodate conflicting perspectives of the world. Developing
certain insights of Kant, the Romantics often insisted on artistic autonomy
and attempted to free art from moralistic and utilitarian constraints.
It was in the fields of philosophy and literature that Romanticism – as a
broad response to Enlightenment, neoclassical, and French Revolutionary
ideals – initially took root. Romanticism bore a complex connection to the
predominating bourgeois world views, which were broadly rationalist, empiricist, individualist, and utilitarian. Some of the Romantics, such as Blake,
Wordsworth, and H€
olderlin, initially saw the French Revolution as heralding
the dawn of a new era of individual and social liberation. Schiller and Goethe
in their own ways exalted the struggle for human freedom and mastery of
knowledge. Shelley, Byron, Heine, George Sand, and Victor Hugo were
passionate in their appeals for justice and liberation from oppressive social
conventions and political regimes. Underlying nearly all Romantic views of
literature was an intense individualism based on the authority of experience
and, often, a broadly democratic orientation, as well as an optimistic and
sometimes utopian belief in progress. Moreover, the Romantics shared
Enlightenment notions of the infinite possibility of human achievement,
and of a more optimistic conception of human nature as intrinsically good
rather than as fallen and theologically depraved. In all these aspects, there was
some continuity between Enlightenment and Romantic thought.
Literary Criticism from Plato to the Present: An Introduction
© 2011 M. A. R. Habib. ISBN: 978-1-405-16034-6
M. A. R. Habib
146
Romanticism and the Later Nineteenth Century
However, many of the Romantics, including some of the figures cited above
such as Blake, Wordsworth, Shelley, and Byron, reacted against certain
central features of the new bourgeois social and economic order. Appalled
by the squalor and the mechanized, competitive routine of the cities, as well as
by the moral mediocrity of a bourgeois world given over to what Shelley
called the principles of utility and calculation, they turned for spiritual relief
to mysticism, to nature, to Rousseauistic dreams of a simple, primitive, and
uncorrupted life, which they sometimes located in an idealized period of
history such as the Middle Ages. Wordsworth held that the poet should
emulate the language of real life; he, along with Blake and Coleridge, exalted
the state of childhood and innocence of perception, untainted by conventional education; and many Romantic writers – in tune with growing
nationalistic sentiments – revived primitive forms such as the folktale and
the ballad. Nature, for the Romantics, departed from the conception of nature
held by neoclassical writers such as Pope, for whom the term signified an
eternal unchangeable and hierarchical order of the cosmos as well as certain
criteria for human thought and behavior. For the Romantics, nature was
transfigured into a living force, held together as a unity by the breath of the
divine spirit. It was infused with a comprehensive symbolism resting on
its profound moral and emotional connection with human subjectivity.
Coleridge referred to nature as the “language of God.”
Perhaps the most fundamental trait of all Romanticism was its shift of
emphasis away from classical objectivity towards subjectivity: in the wake
of the philosophical systems of Fichte, Schelling, and, above all, of Hegel, the
worlds of subject and object, self and world, were viewed as mutually
constructive processes, human perception playing an active role rather than
merely receiving impressions passively from the outside world. Such an
emphasis placed a high value on uniqueness, originality, novelty, and exploration of ever-expanding horizons of experience, rather than the filtering
of experience through historically accumulated layers of tradition and
convention. The emphasis on uniqueness is amply exemplified in Rousseau’s
Confessions. Moreover, the “self” which is exalted in Romanticism was a far
cry from the bourgeois individualistic notion of the self as an atomistic (and
economic) unit. The Romantic self was a profounder, more authentic ego
lying beneath the layers of social convention, a self which attempted through
principles such as irony to integrate the increasingly fragmented elements of
the bourgeois world into a vision of unity. The Romantics exalted the status of
the poet, as a genius whose originality was based on his ability to discern
connections among apparently discrepant phenomena and to elevate human
perception toward a comprehensive, unifying vision.
The most crucial human faculty for such integration was the imagination,
which most Romantics saw as a unifying power, one which could harmonize
the other strata of human perception such as sensation and reason. It should
Romanticism
147
be noted that Romanticism is often wrongly characterized as displacing
Enlightenment “reason” with emotion, instinct, spontaneity, and imagination. To understand what is at issue here, it is necessary to recall that much
Romantic thought took Kant’s philosophy (which itself was not at all
Romantic) as its starting point, notably his distinction between phenomena
and noumena, his treatment of imagination, and his establishing of a relative
autonomy for the category of the aesthetic. Kant declared that the categories
of the understanding applied throughout the phenomenal world, but did
not extend into the world of “noumena.” The only objects in the noumenal
realm – God, freedom, and immortality – were merely presuppositions
required for our moral behavior. Kant had, moreover, viewed imagination
as a mediating principle which reconciled sense-data with the categories of the
understanding. The Romantics, like Hegel (who himself was not a Romantic),
placed the noumenal realm within the reach of human apprehension, and
often exalted the function of imagination, viewing it as a vehicle for the
attainment of truths beyond the phenomenal world and beyond the reach of
reason alone. But they did not attempt to dismiss or discard the findings
of logic and reason, merely to place these within a more embracing scheme of
perception. Shelley even saw imagination as having a moral function, as a
power enabling the self to situate itself within a larger empathetic scheme, as
opposed to reason which expressed the selfish constraints of the liberal
atomistic self. Hence the relation between Romanticism and the mainstreams
of bourgeois thought, which had risen to hegemony on the waves of the
Enlightenment, the French Revolution, and the Industrial Revolution, was
deeply ambivalent. Our own era is profoundly pervaded by this ambivalent
heritage.
This ambivalent connection of Romanticism to bourgeois thought operated through both the notion of imagination and the equally archetypal
notion of Romantic irony. By the end of the eighteenth century, irony had
risen from being a mere rhetorical device to an entire way of looking at the
world. Schlegel’s Fragments of 1797 accords irony an epistemological and
ontological function, seeing it as a mode of confronting and transcending the
contradictions of the finite world. The theorizing of irony in this direction was
furthered by numerous writers including Heine, Kierkegaard, and Nietzsche.
At the core of irony as formulated by most nineteenth-century thinkers was
a Romantic propensity to confront, rather than overlook, the obstinate
disorder, contingency, flux, and mystery of the world. In this sense, an ironic
vision accepts that the world can be viewed from numerous irreconcilable
perspectives, and rejects any providential, rational, or logical foreclosure of
the world’s absurdity and contradictions into a spurious unity. Yet such
Romantic irony is not entirely negative: while it rejects the “objective” order
imposed upon experience or the word by religious or rational means, it seeks a
higher transcendent unity and purpose, grounded ultimately in subjectivity.
148
Romanticism and the Later Nineteenth Century
Irony was essentially an idealistic reaction against the reductively mechanistic, utilitarian, and commercial impetus of bourgeois thought. Irony was
a means of reinvesting the world with mystery, of limiting the arrogant claims
of reason, of denying the ideals of absolute clarity and definition, of reaffirming the profound interconnection of things, and of seeking for the human
spirit higher and more spiritual forms of fulfillment than those available
through material and commercial efficiency. Yet irony could merely voice
subjective protests against colossal historical movements which were already
in process of realization. The Romantics’ only recourse was to an ironic vision
which insisted that reality is not confined to the here and now but embraces
the past or is located in a Platonic ideal realm.
Germany
During the 1760s and 1770s, Germany witnessed the rise of the Sturm und
Drang (“Storm and Stress”) movement in which writers and critics such as
Johann Gottfried von Herder (1744–1803), Goethe, and Schiller experimented with new subjective modes of expression. The major figures of Romanticism included Schiller and Heinrich Heine (1797–1856), who were both
critics of conservatism and staunch advocates of freedom. The greatest poet of
this period was Friedrich H€
olderlin (1770–1843), whose view of history was
mythical. The poetry and prose of Friedrich Novalis (1772–1801) explored
the preconscious depths of human nature and looked back to the Middle Ages
as an ideal. Another towering figure, Johann Wolfgang von Goethe
(1749–1832) was in some respects an advocate of classicism; yet some of
his major works, such as Faust and The Sorrows of Young Werther, express
human subjectivity, creativity, passion, and the thirst for boundless experience with a Romantic intensity. The dramas of Ludwig Tieck (1773–1853)
expressed a Romantic ironic vision. Many poets looked back to primitive and
fantastic forms of literature such as folktale and romance.
It was in Germany that Romantic philosophy and literary criticism
achieved their foundation, in the work of Kant and Friedrich von Schlegel.
The poet Schiller, influenced by Kant, viewed the aesthetic per se as a mode of
freedom. The philosopher Johann Gottlieb Fichte (1762–1814) saw Kant’s
distinction of phenomena and noumena as harboring an irreconcilable chasm
between appearance and reality, as well as between self and world; to
overcome this, Fichte posited the ego or self as the primary reality, and held
that the external world was posited by this as its appearance or projection.
This notion profoundly influenced the Romantics. The main philosopher of
Romanticism, however, was Friedrich Schelling (1775–1854), who argued in
his System of Transcendental Idealism (1800) that consciousness essentially
knows only itself, and its knowledge of the external world is a mediated form
Romanticism
149
of self-consciousness. The systems of both Fichte and Schelling effectively
merge the realms of subject and object, self and nature. Schelling held that the
mind achieves its highest self-consciousness in art, in a process of intuition.
Schelling’s influence extended to Coleridge and the other English Romantics.
Hegel’s philosophy offered a historicized account of the construction of the
world by human categories, as well as of the progress of art through various
forms, symbolic, classical, and romantic. Hegel was influenced by Goethe,
Schelling, and Solger, and his impact extended to many literary figures,
beginning with the literary history written by Gervinus. Hegel’s friend
Friedrich H€
olderlin also emphasized the historical dimensions of aesthetic
experience.
It is clear, then, that one lineage of Romantic thought went back to Kant,
pursuing the nature of subjectivity, examining aesthetics and the notion of the
imagination. Another, overlapping, strand, can be traced to Friedrich von
Schlegel, whose influential definition of Romantic irony occurs as a recasting
of Socratic irony: “In this sort of irony, everything should be playful and
serious, guilelessly open and deeply hidden . . . It contains and arouses a
feeling of indissoluble antagonism between the absolute and the relative,
between the impossibility and the necessity of complete communication.”1
Hence, irony harbors a movement between shifting perspectives of the world,
relative and absolute, instinctive and rational, held together not by some
higher order of harmony but by an acknowledgment of contradiction and
paradox. In an essay of 1800, Schlegel speaks of the “irony of irony” which
pervades discourse at such a profound level that “one can’t disentangle
oneself from irony anymore.” Schlegel’s general point is that the communication of ideas can never occur unequivocally and completely.2 His notion of
irony as informing even philosophy and literary criticism is reenacted in the
hermeneutic theory of Friedrich Schleiermacher. The work of Schiller and
Schleiermacher can now be considered briefly.
Friedrich von Schiller (1759–1805)
Schiller was a poet, dramatist, and literary theorist; writing in the aftermath
of the most violent phase of the French Revolution (known as the Reign of
Terror, 1793–1794), he saw art and letters as the solution to the malaise of a
world corrupted by the principles of mechanism and utility; he was a staunch
advocate for freedom. His two most well-known pieces in the realm of literary
theory are On the Aesthetic Education of Man (1795) and On Naive and
Sentimental Poetry (1795–1796). In the former, Schiller urges that his own
epoch is not conducive to art: it is mired beneath the “tyrannical yoke” of
material needs: “Utility is the great idol of the time, for which all powers
slave and all talents should pay homage.”3 What is needed, says Schiller, is to
place “Beauty before Freedom”: the political problem must be approached
150
Romanticism and the Later Nineteenth Century
“through the aesthetical, because it is beauty, through which one proceeds to
freedom” (“AEM,” 226).
Schiller draws an idealistic but astute contrast between the ancient Greek
world and modern civilization. The Greeks, he says, combined both imagination and reason “in a glorious humanity” (“AEM,” 232). In the modern
world, however, these aspects are fragmented, with not only individuals but
entire classes developing only one part of their potential while the rest remains
stunted. Greek society, says Schiller, received its form from “all-uniting
Nature,” whereas modern culture is based on “all-dividing understanding”
(“AEM,” 232). Schiller blames this divisiveness and fragmentation on the
process of civilization itself. As knowledge increased, and modes of thought
became more precise, sharp divisions between the various sciences, ranks
and occupations ensued, shattering the “inner bond of human nature”
(“AEM,” 233). In the Greek world there was a harmony between individual
and state, an organic wholeness; in contrast, the modern world is torn by
fundamental dualisms:
the state and church, the laws and the customs, were now torn asunder;
enjoyment was separated from work, the means from the end, the effort from
the reward. Eternally chained to only a single fragment of the Whole, man only
develops himself as a fragment . . . and eternally the state remains foreign to its
citizens. (“AEM,” 234)
Schiller anticipates the ideas of both Hegel and Marx on “estrangement” or
alienation.
Schiller’s text is a seminal point of many important Romantic doctrines.
Foremost is his urging of the artist to turn away from reality, to seek
inspiration from an ideal world or from a bygone golden age, and to recreate
the world in the artistic image of such ideality. Such a process lies at the core of
Romantic irony. Also characteristic of much Romantic thought is Schiller’s
retreat from political solutions and his effective substitution of art for
religion, his delineation of the realm of art as possessing moral and spiritual
functions. This recourse will be found also in later critics such as Matthew
Arnold and F. R. Leavis.
Friedrich Schleiermacher (1768–1834)
The German philosopher and Protestant theologian Friedrich Scheiermacher
laid the foundations of modern hermeneutics, or the art of systematic textual
interpretation. His Hermeneutics and Criticism (1838) formulates principles
for the textual interpretation of the New Testament. These principles had
a profound effect on the work of both contemporaries such as Ralph
Waldo Emerson and later thinkers such as Wilhelm Dilthey (1833–1911),
Romanticism
151
Martin Heidegger, Hans Georg Gadamer, and twentieth-century thinkers
such as Lyotard, Rorty, and Derrida.
In Hermeneutics and Criticism Schleiermacher offers a “formula” for
interpretation, whereby we can identify with the author’s overall situation,
a formula which includes: objective historical reconstruction, which considers how a given utterance relates to language as a whole, and how the
knowledge in a text is the product of language; objective divinatory reconstruction, which conjectures how the utterance or discourse itself will
contribute to the language’s development; subjective historical reconstruction, which examines a discourse as a product of an individual writer’s mind;
and, finally, subjective divinatory reconstruction, which assesses how the
process of composition affects the speaker. Strikingly modern in his apparently anti-intentionalist insight, Schleiermacher asserts that the task of
hermeneutics is to understand the text or utterance “just as well and then
better than its author.” All our knowledge of him is not immediate (like his
own) but mediated; and we can therefore attempt to make conscious elements
of which he may have been unconscious. By attaining such knowledge of the
language as he himself had, we will possess a more exact understanding of it
than even his original readers had.4
Schleiermacher expounds the famous “hermeneutic circle” of interpretation or understanding: “Complete knowledge is always in this apparent
circle, that each particular can only be understood via the general, of which
it is part, and vice versa” (HC, p. 24). The point is that, since the particular is
integrally part of a totality, knowledge of the general and knowledge of the
particular presuppose each other. We must initiate, therefore, a “provisional
understanding,” based on the knowledge we obtain about particulars from
a general knowledge of the language (HC, p. 27).
The principles of hermeneutics as formulated by Schleiermacher include
important insights into language and the construction of meaning: that
language is historically determined; that any element of a text must be situated
not only within the text as a totality but in the context of the writer’s work and
historical situation as a whole; that the cultural and psychological constitution
of the subject has an active role in the creation of meaning; that an author’s
work is to a large extent determined by his location within the history of
language and literature, while he himself may exert a reciprocal influence on the
development of both; and that our knowledge itself moves in endless circles
such that we must often acknowledge its provisional and progressive nature.
France
One of the founders of Romanticism, its so-called “father,” was the French
thinker Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712–1778), who espoused a return to
152
Romanticism and the Later Nineteenth Century
nature and equated the increasing refinement of civilization with corruption,
artificiality, and mechanization. Rousseau’s Social Contract espouses democratic principles and begins with the famous sentence “Man is born free,
and everywhere he is in chains.” This statement was as important for
Romanticism as it was for the French Revolution. Romanticism eventually
triumphed over attempted classical revivals, and was expressed in the work
of Germaine de Sta€el (1766–1817) and François de Chateaubriand
(1768–1848). De Sta€el, influenced by Schlegel, essentially rejected classical
ideals as outdated, and identified Romantic notions as progressive, working
in her literary criticism toward cultural relativism and historical specificity.
Charles Augustin Sainte-Beuve (1804–1869) developed a biographical criticism which attempted “scientifically” to contextualize the creative work of
given individuals. His criticism embodies an amalgam of Romantic notions
such as a belief in genius with neoclassical principles of order and decorum.
Chateaubriand, effectively opposed to Enlightenment principles, promoted
a Catholic revival, but exalted the life of the lowly strata of society. George
Sand (1804–1876) also made heroes and heroines of peasants and rustics in
her novels; and Victor Hugo (1802–1885), in Les Miserables, reflects his
relentless opposition to social injustice and oppression. Hugo insisted, as
against the conservatives such as Desire Nisard (1806–1883) and Gustave
Planche (1808–1857), that art and poetry must be autonomous and free, not
restricted by classical constraints. In the famous preface to his Mademoiselle
de Maupin (1835), Theophile Gautier offered his theory of “art for art’s
sake,” deriding any utilitarian conception of art.5
Germaine de Sta€el (1766–1817)
Mme. de Sta€el was one of the heirs of Enlightenment thought; her writings
offended Napoleon, who exiled her from Paris. Politically, she espoused a
constitutional monarchy; in letters she advanced the cause of Romanticism
while anticipating later developments in realism; she was a staunch believer in
freedom and the notion of historical progress. She published two novels,
Delphine (1802) and Corinne, or Italy (1807); her important contributions to
literary criticism are contained in her “Essay on Fictions” (1795) and her
longer work On Literature Considered in its Relationship to Social Institutions (1800). In the latter, de Sta€el examines the various social obstacles to
the success of women writers. She urges that women must be enlightened and
taught together with men, in order to establish any “permanent social or
political relationships.” The development of reason in women will promote
“both enlightenment and the happiness of society in general.” She explains
that women “are the only human beings outside the realm of political interest
and the career of ambition, able to pour scorn on base actions, point out
Romanticism
153
ingratitude, and honor even disgrace if that disgrace is caused by noble
sentiments.”6 She here sees women not only as occupying a position of
externality to the public sphere, but one of disinterestedness, whereby they
can act as a voice of conscience in this sphere since they have no direct interests
vested in it.
England
The early English Romantics included Thomas Gray, Oliver Goldsmith, and
Robert Burns. Like their European counterparts, the English Romantics
reacted at first favorably to the French Revolution and saw their own
cultural and literary program as revolutionary. The first major figure of
English Romanticism, William Blake (1757–1827), had recourse to mysticism and a mythical vision of history; he saw the world as inherently
harboring opposites and contradictions, which it was the poet’s task to
harmonize. His own idiosyncratic religious views were presented in poems
such as The Marriage of Heaven and Hell (1793). In other poems, he
expressed powerfully a vision of the new urban world as plagued by social
injustice, and he railed against what he saw as the oppressive rationality
embodied by figures such as Voltaire and Rousseau. English Romanticism
reached its most mature expression in the work of William Wordsworth
(1770–1850), who saw nature as embodying a universal spirit, and Samuel
Taylor Coleridge who, drawing on the work of Kant, Fichte, and Schelling,
gave archetypal formulation to the powers of the poetic imagination. The
other English Romantics included Dorothy Wordsworth (1771–1855), who
authored letters, poems, and a series of journals, and who had a considerable
influence on her brother and Coleridge; John Keats (1795–1821); Percy
Bysshe Shelley (1792–1822); Mary Shelley (1797–1851), author of
Frankenstein (1818); and George Gordon Lord Byron (1788–1824).
Shelley’s Defence of Poetry is a beautifully expressed manifesto of Romantic
principles, detailing the supremacy of imagination over reason, and the
exalted status of poetry. Keats’s brief literary-critical insights are notable. He
suggests that, in poetic creation, the poet acts as a catalyst for the reaction of
other elements, stating that “Men of Genius are great as certain ethereal
Chemicals operating on the Mass of neutral intellect . . . they have not any
individuality, any determined Character.”7 Deploying what Keats calls the
“negative capability” of abstaining from particular positions or dogmas, the
poet’s mind loses itself wholly among the objects and events of the external
world which are its poetic material (Letters, 184, 386–387). Many of these
issues can now be examined in the literary theories of Wordsworth and
Coleridge.
154
Romanticism and the Later Nineteenth Century
William Wordsworth (1770–1850)
It was Wordsworth who in 1809 wrote the famous lines about the French
Revolution as it first appeared to many of its sympathizers: “Bliss was it in that
dawn to be alive,/. . . When Reason seemed the most to assert her rights”
(Prelude, XI, 108–113). But, later, as he became disillusioned with the effects
of the revolution – such as the “terror” and France’s war with England – he
returned, guided by nature, to his “true self,” his fundamental identity as a
poet. The most elemental factor in Wordsworth’s return to nature was
imagination. In the Prelude he made his celebrated declaration that there
are in our existence “spots of time,” or moments of imaginative insight,
whereby our minds are “nourished” and renovated above the “deadly
weight” of trivial and present occupations (XII, 127–136, 203–206,
222–223). In “Lines Composed a Few Miles above Tintern Abbey,” Wordsworth also recalls his progress from a merely sensual to an imaginative
apprehension of nature, which allows him to see the unity of nature in itself as
well as the unity of humankind with nature: he perceives in “the round ocean
and the living air,/And the blue sky, and in the mind of man:/A motion and
a spirit, that impels /All thinking things, all objects of all thought,/And rolls
through all things” (Tintern Abbey, 95–102). The human mind here is no
longer regarded as a passive receiver of external impressions but as active in
the construction of its world.
Wordsworth’s most important contribution to literary criticism is his
controversial Preface to Lyrical Ballads, a collection of poems published
jointly by Wordsworth and Coleridge in 1798.8 Wordsworth’s Preface
advances what have now become classic statements of Romantic aesthetic
doctrine. He stresses that his poems attempt to present “the real language of
men in a state of vivid sensation” (PLB, 119). What Wordsworth is calling for
is a return to a kind of realism, a descent of poetic language from its stylized
status, from its self-created world of metaphorical expression and artificial
diction to the language actually used by human beings in “common life,”
especially those engaged in “rustic life,” who speak a purer language than
those mired in the squalor and corruption of city life. But he adds that the poet
should throw over these incidents from common life “a certain colouring of
imagination, whereby ordinary things should be presented to the mind in an
unusual aspect” (PLB, 123–125, 160–162).
In Wordsworth’s characterization, the poet is “a man speaking to men”;
but he has a “disposition to be affected more than other men by absent
things as if they were present; an ability of conjuring up in himself passions,”
passions that are closer to those produced by real events than those that most
men can otherwise reproduce (PLB, 138). The power to which Wordsworth
alludes here is imagination, or the “image-making” power (PLB, 138).
In a sense, the very faculty which characterizes the poet – imagination – is
Romanticism
155
not a faculty orientated toward realism in our modern sense; rather, in its
very nature, it is a transformative faculty which uses the “real” world as its
raw material. And yet, the imaginary world created by the poet must
“resemble” that real world (PLB, 139). In support of such realism, Wordsworth cites a classical authority: “Aristotle, I have been told, has said, that
Poetry is the most philosophic of all writing: it is so: its object is truth, not
individual and local, but general, and operative; not standing upon external
testimony, but carried alive into the heart by passion; truth which is its own
testimony” (PLB, 139). Though Wordsworth’s Preface is viewed as archetypally Romantic, his ideal here is a classical one: poetry does not so much
express private emotions and the particulars of a given situation as the
universal truths underlying these. Wordsworth insists that the poet
“converses with general nature,” and directs his attention to the knowledge
and sympathies shared by all human beings (PLB, 140). Again, in classical
fashion, Wordsworth sees poetry as concerned with what is central and
universal in human experience. In transcending his time, the poet reestablishes the unity of humankind, reaffirming the relationship and unity of all
things.
Also classical is Wordsworth’s insistence on poetry as a rational art: he
speaks of the pleasure that “a Poet may rationally endeavour to impart”
(PLB, 119). His statement that “all good poetry is the spontaneous overflow
of powerful feelings” has often been torn from its context to illustrate an
allegedly Romantic view of poetic creation as an expression of immediate
feelings. Yet Wordsworth proceeds to say that “our continued influxes of
feeling are modified and directed by our thoughts, which are indeed the
representatives of all our past feelings” (PLB, 127). Wordsworth sees such a
close connection between thought and feeling that these can actually pass into
each other. What the poet expresses then is neither thought nor feeling alone
but a complex of both; and what appears as spontaneity is the result of long
reflection and practice.
This view of poetry as a meditated craft is elaborated in Wordsworth’s
other renowned comment in the Preface that poetry
takes its origin from emotion recollected in tranquillity: the emotion is contemplated till, by a species of re-action, the tranquillity gradually disappears,
and an emotion, kindred to that which was before the subject of contemplation,
is gradually produced, and does itself actually exist in the mind. In this mood
successful composition generally begins. (PLB, 149)
To put it another way, we leave behind the current emotion as mediated by
thought and retrospection, returning to it in its immediate state. In this sense,
poetic composition begins in feeling, but this feeling will be subsequently
modified again by thought.
156
Romanticism and the Later Nineteenth Century
Wordsworth presses these classical views, however, toward a more
Romantic aesthetic purpose. The poet’s essential focus is not on the external
world, or supposedly “objective” events and actions, but on the connection
between the inner world of human nature and the world of external nature.
Archetypally Romantic is his view that these two worlds are created by
mutual interaction. He also diverges from Aristotle and other classical
thinkers in his view that the purpose of poetry is to give “immediate pleasure”
(PLB, 139). But the principle of pleasure is more profound than at first
appears: it is founded on “the pleasure which the mind derives from the
perception of similitude in dissimilitude” (PLB, 149). This ability signifies a
broader capacity for seeing the world in a new light: we discern patterns in
nature, as well as in thought, emotion, and experience, that were hitherto
overlooked. Wordsworth sees the whole of life as governed by this principle,
from our sexuality to our moral sensibility. So the poet’s task, in giving
“pleasure,” is a difficult one, that of searching for the universal “truths”
which have been clouded by convention, authority, and prejudice. But where
classical thinkers regarded such truths as objective and accessible to reason,
Wordsworth sees them as discernible only through poetic insight.
Samuel Taylor Coleridge (1772–1834)
The genius of Samuel Taylor Coleridge extended over many domains. In
poetry he is best known for compositions such as “The Rime of the Ancient
Mariner,” “Frost at Midnight,” “Christabel,” and “Kubla Khan,” as well as
Lyrical Ballads (1798) which he co-authored with Wordsworth. He also
wrote on educational, social, political, and religious matters in his Lectures
on Politics and Religion (1795), Lay Sermons (1816), and On the
Constitution of the Church and State (1829). Much of his thinking on
philosophical issues is contained in his Logic. His literary criticism includes
detailed studies of Shakespeare and Milton, and a highly influential
text Biographia Literaria (1817), an eclectic work, combining intellectual
autobiography, philosophy, and literary theory.
Two experiences were central to Coleridge’s development as a poet and
thinker: the first was his meeting with the poet Wordsworth in 1795, resulting
in a friendship that lasted until 1810. Coleridge and his wife Sara lived close to
Wordsworth and his sister Dorothy from 1796; in 1800 they all moved to the
Lake District, which proved to be a rich source of poetic inspiration. The
other experience was travel (with the Wordsworths) to Germany in 1798
where Coleridge studied the work of Kant and the German Romantic
thinkers. Like Wordsworth, Coleridge was at first of radical mind, inspired
by the promise of the French Revolution to write such poems as Ode on the
Destruction of the Bastille (1789).9 However, like Wordsworth, Coleridge
became disillusioned with the revolutionary movement, as he records in
Romanticism
157
Biographia10 and in his poem “France: An Ode,” where he finds the spirit of
liberty ultimately not in any form of government but in the mind’s contemplation of its own individuality and the surrounding sublime objects of
nature, as pervaded by the love of God. Shortly after his disillusionment
with French revolutionary principles, he also questioned his own unorthodox
Unitarian views, and by 1805 he had made positive overtures toward
trinitarianism. Coleridge eventually took his place in the tradition of English
conservatism, on which he exerted considerable influence.
At the heart of Coleridge’s conservatism was his insistence, similar to
Edmund Burke’s, that truth cannot be reached by focusing on the present
alone. Rather, both men appealed to what they called universal principles that
would comprehend past, present, and future. Both men reacted against
the prevailing philosophies of the Enlightenment, and especially against what
they saw as the principle of “abstract reason” governing French and other
revolutionary attempts to reform society according to “abstract” principles
rather than on the basis of actual history and culture. Coleridge bemoaned the
modern spirit of commerce and speculation that had thwarted the diverse
potential of human beings.11 Coleridge sought the antidote to these evils
in the universal principles of truth and morality as contained in the Bible,
which he advocated as the “end and center of our reading” (LS, 17, 70). In a
formulation which proved to have great impact on later writers such as Poe
and Baudelaire, Coleridge returned to the medieval idea of the Book of
Nature, whereby the world of nature itself contained the “correspondences
and symbols of the spiritual world” (LS, 70). He made a distinction between
symbol and allegory, defining the latter as merely a “translation of abstract
notions into a picture-language.” A symbol, on the other hand,
is characterized by a translucence of the Special in the Individual or of the
General in the Especial or of the Universal in the General. Above all by the
translucence of the Eternal through and in the Temporal. It always partakes of
the Reality which it renders intelligible; and while it enunciates the whole,
abides itself as a living part in that Unity, of which it is the representative.
Central to Coleridge’s project are his views of the imagination. He seems to
follow Kant (and much eighteenth-century thought) in viewing the imagination as a faculty which unites what we receive through our senses with the
concepts of our understanding; but he goes further than Kant in viewing
imagination as a power which “completes” and enlivens the understanding so
that the understanding itself becomes a more comprehensive and intuitive
(rather than merely discursive) faculty. The Romantics, including Coleridge,
are often characterized as extolling imagination as the supreme human
faculty. Nonetheless, Coleridge appears to view reason as the supreme
faculty, one which contains all the others: “the REASON without being
158
Romanticism and the Later Nineteenth Century
either the SENSE, the UNDERSTANDING or the IMAGINATION contains
all three within itself, even as the mind contains its thoughts, and is present in
and through them all” (LS, 69–70). Hence, just as imagination combines
sense with understanding, so reason, placed at a higher vantage point, unites
the knowledge derived from all three of these. Coleridge insists that each
individual partakes of the light of a reason which is universal and divine.
In Biographia Literaria, Coleridge makes his famous distinction between
fancy and imagination:
The IMAGINATION then I consider either as primary, or secondary. The
primary IMAGINATION I hold to be the living Power and prime Agent of all
human Perception, and as a repetition in the finite mind of the eternal act of
creation in the infinite I AM. The secondary I consider as an echo of the former,
co-existing with the conscious will, yet still as identical with the primary in the
kind of its agency, and differing only in degree, and in the mode of its operation.
It dissolves, diffuses, dissipates, in order to re-create; or where this process is
rendered impossible, yet still at all events it struggles to idealize and to unify. It is
essentially vital, even as all objects (as objects) are essentially fixed and dead.
FANCY, on the contrary, has no other counters to play with, but fixities and
definites. The Fancy is indeed no other than a mode of Memory emancipated
from the order of time and space; and blended with, and modified by that
empirical phenomenon of the will, which we express by the word CHOICE.
But equally with the ordinary memory it must receive all its materials ready
made from the laws of association. (BL, I, 304–305)
What Coleridge designates as the primary imagination is roughly equivalent
to what Kant views as the “reproductive” imagination: it operates in our
normal perception, combining the various data received through the senses
into a unifying image, which can then be conceptualized by the understanding. Even in this primary role, however, imagination as formulated by
Coleridge evokes a wider, cosmic context: the very act of perception
“repeats” on a finite level the divine act of creation. In other words, human
perception actively recreates or copies elements in the world of nature,
reproducing these into images that can be processed further by the understanding. There is no originality in the primary imagination: like Kant’s
reproductive imagination, it is bound by what we actually experience through
the senses.
It is the secondary imagination which is poetic: like Kant’s “productive” or
spontaneous imagination, this is creative and forms new syntheses, new and
more complex unities out of the raw furnishings of sense-data, following its
own rules. Coleridge also stresses in this passage the voluntary and controlled
nature of the secondary or poetic imagination. Nonetheless, this poetic
imagination is still dependent for its raw material on the primary imagination.
Another way of putting this might be to say that even the creative poetic
Romanticism
159
imagination is ultimately rooted in our actual perceptions of the world: it
cannot simply create from nothing, or from the insubstantiality of its own
dreams. For, ultimately, the secondary imagination is perceiving the world at
a higher level of truth, one that sees beneath the surface appearances of things
into their deeper reality, their deeper connections, and their significance
within a more comprehensive scheme that relates objects and events in their
human, finite significance to their symbolic place in the divine, infinite order
of things.
Fancy has a degree of freedom in the way it recalls and combines images; it
is not restricted to the original order of images in time and space. Unlike the
primary imagination, then, fancy is not merely a perceptual agent; rather, it is
a creative power but operates at a lower level of creativity than the secondary
or poetic imagination which has the power to dissolve perceptions entirely
and create new combinations. Elsewhere, Coleridge calls imagination a
“shaping and modifying power,” and fancy “the aggregative and associative
power” (BL, I, 293 and n. 4). Indeed, Coleridge refers to imagination as the
“esemplastic” power, a term he derives from the Greek eis hen plattein
meaning “to shape into one” (BL, I, 168). Collectively, these statements
suggest that imagination unifies material in an internal organic matter,
changing the very elements themselves that are united, whereas the combinations produced by fancy are aggregative, comprising merely external addition, as in the placing of images side by side.
Coleridge’s views on the nature of poetry and poetic language are intrinsically tied to his views of poetic imagination. He holds that poetry is
distinguished from other disciplines such as science and history “by proposing
for its immediate object pleasure, not truth”; it furnishes such pleasure
through its organic unity, whereby each part is integrated into the whole
(BL, II, 12–13). Coleridge sees this pleasure as derived not only from truth as
the ultimate goal but “by the attractions of the journey itself” (BL, II, 14).
This view anticipates many modern conceptions of poetry and poetic autonomy: the primary purpose of poetry is not referential, but rather to draw
attention to itself as a linguistic and material construct, to the journey or
means whereby truth is achieved. Coleridge’s renowned definition of “poetic
faith” as a “willing suspension of disbelief” helps explain this poetic autonomy: the images in poetry have a force and logic of their own that urge the
reader to enter the world of poetic illusion and to suspend judgment as to
whether the images of that poetic world have a real existence.
Coleridge’s most comprehensive definition of the activity of the poet sees it
as relying on the unifying power of imagination, which
reveals itself in the balance or reconciliation of opposite or discordant qualities:
of sameness, with difference; of the general, with the concrete; the idea, with
the image; the individual, with the representative; the sense of novelty and
160
Romanticism and the Later Nineteenth Century
freshness, with old and familiar objects; a more than usual state of emotion, with
more than usual order; judgment ever awake and steady self-possession, with
enthusiasm and feeling profound or vehement. (BL, II, 16–17).
What the mere understanding can perceive only in terms of opposites – such as
general and concrete – imagination has the power to reconcile in a higher
vision of unity. This power distinguishes poetry from prose or from any
discursive activity that brings us conventional perceptions of the world: the
imagination can not only reassemble whatever elements the world presents to
our senses but also see the profounder connection of those elements.
Given Coleridge’s views of the unique status of the poet, it is hardly
surprising that he takes issue with Wordsworth’s insistence that the poet
adopt the “real” language of men, found in its purest form in rustic life.
Coleridge retorts that language varies in every country and every village; given
such variety, what would “real” language mean? Hence, for “real,” thinks
Coleridge, we should substitute the term “ordinary” or lingua communis
(BL, II, 55–56). More importantly, the rustic’s discourse would be impoverished (BL, II, 55–56). The best part of language, according to Coleridge,
“is derived from reflection on the acts of the mind itself” (BL, II, 54). But, like
Wordsworth, Coleridge uses classical Aristotelian precepts – in this case, the
poetic expression of universal truths – toward Romantic ends. What allows
the poet to communicate general and essential truths is the unifying power of
imagination which sees the connections between particular and general,
concrete and abstract, individual and representative.
America
Romanticism in America flowered somewhat later than in Europe, embroiled
as the new nation was in the struggle for self-definition in political, economic,
and religious terms. It was American independence from British rule,
achieved in 1776, that opened the path to examining national identity and
developing a distinctly American literary tradition in the light of Romantically reconceived visions of the self and nature. The major American Romantics included Ralph Waldo Emerson, Walt Whitman, Nathaniel
Hawthorne, Margaret Fuller, Henry David Thoreau, and Herman Melville.
While some of these writers were influenced by European Romantics and
philosophers, nearly all of them were inspired by a nationalistic concern to
develop an indigenous cultural tradition and a distinctly American literature.
Indeed, they helped to define – at a far deeper and more intelligent level
than the crude definitions offered by politicians since then until the present
day – the very concept of American national identity. Like the European
Romantics, these American writers reacted against what they perceived to be
Romanticism
161
the mechanistic and utilitarian tenor of Enlightenment thinking and the
industrial, urbanized world governed by the ethics and ideals of bourgeois
commercialism. They sought to redeem the ideas of spirit, nature, and the
richness of the human self within a specifically American context.
It was Emerson who laid the foundations of American Romanticism.
Utilizing the ideas of Wordsworth, Coleridge, and Thomas Carlyle, he
developed organicist ideas of nature, language, and imagination. Both
Emerson and Whitman referred to America as a “poem” which needed to
be written. In the preface to his Leaves of Grass (1855), Whitman saw himself
as writing “the great psalm of the republic.” Like Emerson, he reacted against
the strictures of genre and form and wrote in a freer form using colloquial
speech, or what Whitman called “the dialect of common sense,” intended to
convey the vastness of the American spirit. He saw the “genius” of the United
States as residing in the common people, and thought that the redemption of
America from its rotten commercialism lay in the realization of its authentic
self.12 Whitman’s Song of Myself begins with the line “I celebrate myself.”
But this narrative “I” is symbolic (“In all people I see myself”). Whitman
celebrates the divine in all dimensions of this common humanity which he
locates in both soul and body, spurning didactic aims and conventional
morality, as in his questioning “What blurt is it about virtue and about vice?”
(l. 468). Whitman moves toward a total acceptance of humanity, free from
the artifice of conventional perception, and the false imposition of coherence:
“Do I contradict myself?/Very well then . . . I contradict myself;/I am large . . .
I contain multitudes” (ll. 1314–1316). Whitman saw the human personality
as integrating and accommodating all kinds of development, scientific,
artistic, religious, and economic.
Another major figure was Henry David Thoreau (1817–1862). In Walden
(1854), based on his sojourn at Emerson’s property at Walden pond, he
advocated a life free of social artifice, routine, and consumerism, simplified in
its needs, devoted to nature and art, imaginatively exploring the depths of the
self, and developing an authentic language. Thoreau’s highly Romantic and
eccentric vision was also expressed in opposition to oppression; he was a
fervent abolitionist, and his essay “Resistance to Civil Government” (1849;
later entitled “Civil Disobedience”) influenced Mohandas K. Gandhi and
Martin Luther King, Jr. Margaret Fuller (1810–1850) also voiced fervent
opposition to what she saw as a society soiled by material greed, crime, and
the perpetuation of slavery. Influenced at various times by Goethe, Carlyle,
Mary Wollstonecraft, and George Sand, and being a friend of Emerson’s, she
edited the transcendentalists’ journal the Dial from 1840 to 1842. She also
published a notable feminist work Woman in the Nineteenth Century (1844),
in which she argued that the development of men and women cannot occur
in mutual independence, there being no wholly masculine man, or purely
feminine woman. This text can be read as an effort to make Emersonian
162
Romanticism and the Later Nineteenth Century
self-reliance an option for women. Nathaniel Hawthorne drew upon
Emerson’s theories, Enlightenment philosophy, and Coleridge’s views on
imagination to define the genre of romance fiction as a locus where the real
and the imaginary intersect and influence each other, in a unified vision. Both
Hawthorne and his friend and admirer Herman Melville reacted, like the
other American Romantics, against the mechanism and commercialism at the
core of American life.
Ralph Waldo Emerson (1803–1882)
Emerson, the most articulate exponent of American Romanticism, was
a poet; but he was distinguished primarily by his contributions to literary
and cultural criticism. He was the leading advocate of American
“transcendentalism” with its insistence on the value of intuition, individuality
of perception, the goodness of human nature, and the unity of the entire
creation. His views of nature and self-reliance not only influenced American
literary figures, as noted above, but also left their mark on European writers
such as George Eliot and Nietzsche, as well as the American pragmatist
philosophers William James and John Dewey. Emerson’s most renowned
essays include “Nature” (1836), “The American Scholar” (1837), the
“Address Delivered before the Senior Class in Divinity College” (1838)
(where he criticized institutional religion for thwarting individual selfdiscovery), “History,” “Self-Reliance,” and “The Poet.”
Emerson’s essay “Nature” is one of the most powerful and succinct
expressions of a Romantic world view. Emerson sees the universe as composed of “Nature” and the “Soul,” taking up a distinction of Carlyle and
Fichte between the “self” and the “not-self.”13 Characteristically of Romanticism, he believes that nature is apprehensible not to most adults but to the
“eye and the heart of the child” (RWE, 25). He stresses that nature is part of
God and through it circulate the “currents of the Universal Being” (RWE, 26).
Whatever is furnished to our senses by nature Emerson calls “commodities.”
A higher gift of nature is the love of beauty, which we know in its lowest form
through our senses (RWE, 29–30). Such nature reflects a higher and divine
beauty which inspires man to virtue. The highest form under which beauty
may be viewed is when it becomes “an object of the intellect,” which
“searches out the absolute order of things as they stand in the mind of God”
(RWE, 32). Hence the beauty in nature “is not ultimate. It is the herald of
inward and eternal beauty” (RWE, 33).
Nature also gives us language, which is “the vehicle of thought” in three
ways. Firstly, words are “signs of natural facts” (RWE, 33). Secondly, “it is
not words only that are emblematic; it is things which are emblematic. Every
natural fact is a symbol of some spiritual facts. Every appearance in nature
corresponds to some state of the mind” (RWE, 34). For example, light and
Romanticism
163
darkness are familiarly associated with knowledge and ignorance. Nature
taken in itself is a mere catalogue of facts. But once it is married to human
history, it becomes alive, expressing a “radical correspondence between
visible things and human thoughts.” In this sense, nature is an “interpreter.”
It remains for wise men and poets to redeem language from its corruption and
to “fasten words again to visible things” (RWE, 35–36). Emerson goes on to
explain that the “world is emblematic. Parts of speech are metaphors, because
the whole of nature is a metaphor of the human mind” (RWE, 36). Hence
things in the world are themselves signs, are themselves allegorical enactments of higher truths; nature or the world does not exist in and for itself but
as a vehicle of man’s spiritual expression. Like Wordsworth, Emerson
advocates the life of the country, a withdrawal from “the roar of cities or
the broil of politics,” in order to facilitate such a rejuvenation of language.
The poet, says Emerson, “proposes Beauty as his main end,” whereas the
philosopher proposes Truth. Nonetheless, they both seek to ground the world
of phenomena in stable and permanent laws, in an idea whose beauty is
infinite. Hence, the “true philosopher and the true poet are one, and a beauty,
which is truth, and a truth, which is beauty, is the aim of both” (RWE, 47).
Whereas later writers such as Poe will subordinate truth and morality to the
overarching aim of beauty, Emerson holds these together in a precarious
balance flown into the modern world directly from Plato’s Athens.
It is Emerson’s essay “The American Scholar” that perhaps best articulates
some of the distinctive concerns of American Romanticism. Emerson declares
that America’s “day of dependence” on foreign learning is drawing to a
close (RWE, 58). He outlines the duties and virtues of the scholar: all of these,
he says, are comprised in “self-trust,” a notion that includes being “selfrelying and self-directed,” being constrained neither by tradition or religion,
nor by fashion and the opinion of popular judgment. Indeed, the scholar
seems to stand in a relation of “virtual hostility” to society (RWE, 67). The
task of Emerson’s heroic scholar, unlike that of Nietzsche’s overman who
rises above common morality, is to reaffirm and reestablish man’s lost
connections with his universal, unified self, to reveal what is “universally
true” (RWE, 68). It is the scholar who wakes people from their sleep-walking
dream in search of money and power, leading them to this fundamental
lesson: “The world is nothing, the man is all; in yourself is the law of all nature
. . . in yourself slumbers the whole of Reason” (RWE, 70–71).
As for the particular duties of the American scholar, Emerson famously
declares: “We have listened too long to the courtly muses of Europe” (RWE,
73). He ends with an eloquent call for an independence that is based on
relation, on integration within a totality: “We will walk on our own feet; we
will work with our own hands; we will speak our own minds . . . A nation of
men will for the first time exist, because each believes himself inspired by the
Divine Soul which also inspires all men” (RWE, 74). Emerson’s is a powerful
164
Romanticism and the Later Nineteenth Century
voice attempting to situate American ideals such as self-reliance and independence (at both national and individual levels) within a pre-capitalist
harmony of self and world, a harmony equated with attunement to the
workings of the divine and thereby precariously balanced between secular
and religious visions.
In his essay “The Transcendentalist” (1842), Emerson explains that
transcendentalism (a term he adapts from Kant) is a form of idealism, and
that the transcendentalist’s experience “inclines him to behold the procession
of facts you call the world, as flowing perpetually outward from an invisible,
unsounded center in himself . . . necessitating him to regard all things as
having a subjective or relative existence” (RWE, 142). Transcendentalists,
says Emerson, are characterized by their withdrawal from society, their
disinclination even to vote, and their passion for “what is great and extraordinary” (RWE, 146, 148). Their attachment is to “what is permanent”
(RWE, 153–154). For Emerson, then, “transcendental” betokens a transcendence that refuses to take the bourgeois world as real, that seeks to locate
reality itself in another, higher, realm insulated from space, time, and history.
In “The Poet” (1844), Emerson defines the poet as a transcendentalist. His
province is language, and he uses the things in nature as types, as symbols;
hence, objects in nature acquire a second value, and nature “is a symbol, in the
whole, and in every part” (RWE, 192). Emerson explains that the “Universe is
the externization of the soul,” and that its symbolic value lies in its pointing
beyond itself, toward the supernatural (RWE, 193). The poet, by “ulterior
intellectual perception,” is able to see the connectedness of things, especially
the symbolic connection between material and spiritual elements. Such
insight is effected by the faculty of imagination, which is effectively “the
intellect released from all service and suffered to take its direction from its
celestial life” (RWE, 196–199). In other words, the intellect is freed from its
bondage to the restrictive bodily sphere of practical interests and survival.
Emerson concludes by calling for poetic universality to comprehend what is
peculiarly American. There exists, as yet, no poet of genius in America: “Yet
America is a poem in our eyes . . . and it will not wait long for meters” (RWE,
204). Emerson’s words proved prophetic in Whitman’s: “I sing America.”
Emerson calls on the poet to “leave the world, and know the muse only.” The
poet is he for whom “the ideal shall be real” (RWE, 206). Emerson is true to
the Romantic inversion of the categories of the bourgeois world: that world
is insular, incomplete, and denuded of all relation, all context in which it
would find its true meaning. To redeem such relation is the poet’s task.
Edgar Allen Poe (1809–1849)
Poe was the first major American writer explicitly to advocate the autonomy
of poetry, the freeing of poetry from moral or educational or intellectual
Romanticism
165
imperatives. He viewed poetry not as an object but as a series of effects on
the reader or listener. Poe’s image as an outcast, his emphasis on beauty
rather than morality or truth, his view of poetry as affording us a glimpse of
an ideal world, as well as his insistence on the close union of poetry and
music, exerted a considerable fascination and impact on writers such as
Baudelaire, who translated a number of his tales, and Mallarme, who
translated his poems, as well as Lacan who in 1966 published his seminar
on Poe’s story, “The Purloined Letter.” Poe’s most famous tales include
“The Black Cat,” “The Fall of the House of Usher” (1839), and “The Cask
of Amontillado” (1846). Some of Poe’s radical insights into poetry are
expressed in his essay “The Philosophy of Composition” (1846), which
purports to explain the origins of his own widely popular poem “The
Raven” (1842). Other critical essays include “The Poetic Principle” and
“The Rationale of Verse.”
Poe’s essay “The Poetic Principle” (1850) urges that a “totality of effect or
impression” is the “vital requisite” in all works of art.14 He attempts to
undermine what he calls “the heresy of The Didactic,” which refers to the
view that “the ultimate object of all Poetry is Truth” and that every poem
“should inculcate a moral.” As against this, Poe insists that the most dignified
and noble work is the “poem per se – this poem which is a poem and nothing
more – this poem written solely for the poem’s sake” (“PP,” 892–893). Poe
makes a sharp distinction between “the truthful and the poetical modes”
(“PP,” 893). In somewhat Kantian fashion, Poe divides the mind into three
aspects: “Pure Intellect, Taste, and the Moral Sense.” He places taste in the
middle, acknowledging that it has “intimate relations” with the other two
aspects, but he observes a distinction between these three offices: the intellect
is concerned with truth; taste apprehends the beautiful; and moral sense
disposes us toward duty (“PP,” 893). Poe admits that the precepts of duty or
even the lessons of truth can be introduced into a poem; but they must
subserve the ultimate purpose of art, and must be placed “in proper subjection
to that Beauty which is the atmosphere and the real essence of the poem”
(“PP,” 895).
Hence poetry should not be realistic, merely copying or imitating the
beauties that lie before us. Poe defines the “poetic principle” in Platonic terms
as “the Human Aspiration for Supernal Beauty,” a quest for an excitement of
the soul that is distinct from the intoxication of the heart or the satisfaction of
reason. Poe defines poetry as
The Rhythmical Creation of Beauty. Its sole arbiter is Taste . . . In the contemplation of Beauty we alone find it possible to attain that pleasurable elevation, or
excitement, of the soul, which we recognize as the Poetic Sentiment, and which
is so easily distinguished from Truth, which is the satisfaction of the Reason,
or from Passion, which is the excitement of the Heart. (“PP,” 895)
166
Romanticism and the Later Nineteenth Century
What is not Platonic is Poe’s isolated exaltation of beauty over truth and
goodness; the Platonic harmony between these has disintegrated into a
desperate craving for a beauty that is not found in the actual world, and a
retreat from the increasingly troubled realms of truth and morality. Nonetheless, the poet, according to Poe, recognizes in many phenomena “holy
impulses . . . generous, and self-sacrificing deeds” (“PP,” 906). Hence, the
very morality that is expelled from the poet’s quest for beauty returns as the
very ground of this quest, resurrected in aesthetic form on the ground of its
own beauty. In other words, morality becomes an integral part of the aesthetic
endeavor, and becomes justified on aesthetic grounds. Once again, art is seen
as salvific, displacing the function of religion in serving as our guide to the
world beyond.
Notes
1. “Critical Fragments,” 108, in Friedrich von Schlegel, Philosophical Fragments,
trans. Peter Firchow (Minneapolis and Oxford: University of Minnesota Press,
1991), p. 13.
2. Friedrich von Schlegel, “On Incomprehensibility,” in German Aesthetic and
Literary Criticism: The Romantic Ironists and Goethe, ed. Kathleen M. Wheeler
(Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press, 1984), pp. 33–38.
3. “On the Aesthetic Education of Man,” in Friedrich Schiller: Poet of Freedom,
trans. William F. Wertz, Jr. (New York: New Benjamin Franklin House, 1985),
p. 225. Hereafter cited as “AEM.”
4. Friedrich Schleiermacher, Hermeneutics and Criticism and Other Writings,
trans. and ed. Andrew Bowie (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998),
pp. 23–24. Hereafter cited as HC.
5. Theophile Gautier, “Preface,” in Mademoiselle de Maupin (1835; rpt. Paris:
Garnier, 1955), pp. 2–3, 11, 22–24.
6. An Extraordinary Woman: Selected Writings of Germaine de Sta€el, trans. Vivian
Folkenflik (New York: Columbia University Press, 1987), pp. 204–205.
7. The Letters of John Keats: Volume I, ed. Hyder Edward Rollins (Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 1958), p. 184. Hereafter cited as Letters.
8. The Prose Works of William Worsdworth: Volume I, ed. W. J. B. Owen and
Jane Worthington Smyser (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1974). Hereafter cited as
PLB.
9. Coleridge: Poetical Works, ed. Ernest Hartley Coleridge (New York and Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1973), p. 11.
10. The Collected Works of Samuel Taylor Coleridge. VII: Biographia Literaria, ed.
James Engell and W. Jackson Bate (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1983),
p. 187. Hereafter cited as BL.
11. The Collected Works of Samuel Taylor Coleridge: Lay Sermons, ed. R. J. White
(Princeton and London: Princeton University Press/Routledge and Kegan Paul,
1972), p. 169. Hereafter cited as LS.
Romanticism
167
12. Walt Whitman, “Introduction,” in Leaves of Grass: The First (1855) Edition,
ed. Malcolm Cowley (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1986), pp. 5, 8, 23.
13. “Nature,” in Ralph Waldo Emerson and Margaret Fuller: Selected Works, ed.
John Carlos Rowe (Boston and New York: Houghton Mifflin, 2003), p. 24.
Hereafter cited as RWE.
14. “The Poetic Principle,” in Complete Tales and Poems of Edgar Allen Poe
(New York: Vintage Books, 1975), p. 889. Hereafter cited as “PP.”
Chapter 11
Realism, Naturalism, Symbolism,
and Aestheticism
Historical Background: The Later Nineteenth Century
In the second half of the nineteenth century, the vast unifying systems of
thinkers such as Hegel, as well as the unifying visions of the Romantics,
collapsed into a series of one-sided systems, such as utilitarianism, positivism,
and social Darwinism. To be sure, there were a number of movements that
continued the oppositional stance of Romanticism to mainstream bourgeois
and Enlightenment ideals: Matthew Arnold criticized the philistinism of
bourgeois society, while Thomas Carlyle promoted his own version of
German idealism, and John Ruskin perpetuated a Romantic idealization
of the Middle Ages. A tradition of alternative philosophy ran from
Schopenhauer through thinkers such as Nietzsche, Kierkegaard, and Bergson.
More politically forceful were the various movements of socialism inspired by
Marx, Engels, and others.
But the values and ideals of the mainstream bourgeois Enlightenment
prevailed. In the later nineteenth century, these values were increasingly
attuned to the rapid progress of science and technology. As the culmination of
a historical pattern beginning in the Renaissance, science effectively displaced
religion and theology as the supreme arbiter of knowledge. The institutional
demise of religion was intensified by broadly scientific endeavors. Charles
Darwin’s Origin of Species (1859) was held by some to undermine the biblical
accounts of creation; the rise of the German Higher Criticism subjected the
gospels to a searching “scientific” scrutiny, exposing many inconsistencies
and contradictions. David Strauss’ The Life of Jesus (1835) saw Christ in
terms of myth rather than fact; Ernest Renan’s book of the same title (1863)
effectively denied the originality of Christ, viewing him as emerging from a
religious context already prepared.
As such, the natural sciences became the model and the measure of other
disciplines. The broadest name for this emulation of science is “positivism,”
Literary Criticism from Plato to the Present: An Introduction
© 2011 M. A. R. Habib. ISBN: 978-1-405-16034-6
M. A. R. Habib
Realism, Naturalism, Symbolism, and Aestheticism
169
which derives its name from the self-proclaimed “positive” philosophies of
thinkers such as Auguste Comte and Émile Durkheim in France, and Herbert
Spencer in England. These thinkers wished to exclude from investigation all
hypotheses that were not empirically verifiable, and they rejected as
“metaphysical” all inquiries that were not amenable to supposedly scientific
terms of analysis, such as “matter,” “motion,” and “force.” In political terms,
Herbert Marcuse has shown how positivism, or “positive philosophy,” was
essentially a conservative reaction against the “negative philosophy” of
Hegel.1 Hegel’s entire dialectic had been premised on a rejection of the world
as given and an imperative to transform the world in the image of our own
rationality. In one sense, positivism was a reaction against the very principles
of Hegelian unity and totality as achieved by some spiritual agency or
absolute idea. Ideologically, positivism, in its manifold guises, was an attempt
to confirm the reality and propriety of the world as given; in other words,
these were essentially conservative modes of thought, sanctioning the status
quo. Positivism pervaded many domains: sociology (as exemplified by
Durkheim, who attempted to isolate a distinctly “social” fact), psychology
(as shown in Freud’s obsession with the scientific status of his work), and
social thought (expressed in the evolutionism of Herbert Spencer). Realism
and naturalism are the literary expressions of this general tendency.
Realism and Naturalism
A tendency toward realism arose in many parts of Europe and in America,
beginning in the 1840s. The major figures included Flaubert and Balzac in
France, Dostoevsky and Tolstoy in Russia, George Eliot and Charles Dickens
in England, as well as William Dean Howells and Henry James in America.
The most general aim of realism was to offer a truthful, accurate, and objective
representation of the real world, both the external world and the human self.
To achieve this aim, realists resorted to a number of strategies: the use of detail;
avoidance of what was imaginary and mythical; adherence to the requirements
of probability; inclusion of characters and incidents from all social strata,
dealing not merely with rulers and nobility; focusing on contemporary life
rather than longing for some idealized past; and using colloquial idioms and
everyday speech. Underlying all these was an emphasis on direct observation,
factuality, and experience. Realism was thus a broad reaction against the
idealization, historical retrospection, and imaginary worlds of Romanticism.
Moreover, realism – to this day – has been not just a literary technique but, as
Fredric Jameson states, “one of the most complex and vital realizations of
Western culture, to which it is . . . well-nigh unique.”2
Naturalism was the ancient term for the physical sciences or the study of
nature. Modern naturalism explicitly endeavors to emulate the methods of
170
Romanticism and the Later Nineteenth Century
the physical sciences, drawing heavily on the principles of causality, determinism, explanation, and experimentation. Some naturalists also drew on
Darwinian notions of the struggle for survival. Hence naturalism can be
viewed as a more extreme form of realism, extending the latter’s scientific
basis still further to encompass extremely detailed methods of description, a
deterministic emphasis upon the contexts of actions and events (which are
seen as arising from specific causes), upon the hereditary psychological
components of their characters, experimenting with the connections between
human psychology and external environment, and refusing to accommodate
any kind of metaphysical or spiritual perspective. It was the literary historian
Hippolyte Taine (1828–1893) who laid the theoretical foundations of naturalism and Émile Zola who first formulated its manifesto.
In Germany, a radical group called the Young Germans, whose prominent
members included Heinrich Heine (1797–1856) and Carl Gutzkow
(1811–1878), voiced their opposition to the perceived reactionary Romanticism of Goethe and Schlegel. Later proponents of realism included Julian
Schmidt (1818–1886), the novelist Gottfried Keller (1819–1890), the dramatist Friedrich Hebbel (1813–1863), and Friedrich Theodor von Vischer
(1807–1887), who endeavored to express a theoretical basis for realism. The
naturalist movement, arising in the 1880s through the influence of Zola, was
advanced by Arno Holz (1863–1929), Heinrich (1855–1906) and Julius Hart
(1859–1930), Wilhelm Bolsche (1861–1939), the social novelist Theodor
Fontane (1819–1898), and Wilhelm Scherer (1841–1886), who attempted to
base literature on scientific principles.
Realism became a force in France during the 1850s. Edmond Duranty
began a journal called Realisme in 1856, in which realism was equated with
truthfulness, sincerity, and the modern. Duranty believed that novels should
reflect the lives of ordinary middle-class or working-class people. In 1857
Jules-François-Felix Husson (know as Champfleury) urged the need for
scrupulous documentation and freedom from moral constraints. Positivism
in France took on a more overt aspect in the work of Taine who sought a
totalizing explanation of the causal operations governing both human beings
and the world. In the famous introduction to his History of English Literature
(1863–1864), he advocated, following Sainte-Beuve, an ideal of scientific
exactness in literary criticism, urging that the task of the critic was to discover
the master characteristic of a writer’s work, as determined by three broad
factors: race, milieu, and moment. The underlying assumption was that art
expresses not only the psychology of its author but also the spirit of its age.
Taine was a major influence on Zola and Ferdinand Brunetiere (1849–1906).
In 1880, Zola, Guy de Maupassant, Joris-Karl Huysmans, and others jointly
published a volume of naturalistic fiction entitled Les Soirees de Meda.
In England, realism had in varying degrees informed the numerous types of
novel – political, historical, religious – which had been written by major
Realism, Naturalism, Symbolism, and Aestheticism
171
figures such as Thackeray and Dickens during the nineteenth century. But it
was with the novels of George Eliot, Anthony Trollope, George Meredith, and
Thomas Hardy that realism flowered. George Eliot’s views were influenced by
Ludwig Feuerbach and Auguste Comte. Eliot’s domestic partner George
Henry Lewes examined human psychology as intimately related to social
conditions. Two other notable realists of this period were George Gissing
(1857–1903) and George Moore (1852–1933), both influenced by Zola. The
subsequent development of photography and the ideal of photographic
accuracy had considerable significance for realism in both art and literature.
While realism in America reacted against the fundamental tendencies of
Romanticism, it perpetuated the latter’s concern with national identity and
defining a native tradition. The foremost theorist was William Dean Howells,
a powerful advocate of verisimilitude in fiction. In his manifesto Crumbling
Idols (1894), Hamlin Garland propounded “veritism,” a version of naturalism, which would express social concerns while respecting local traditions and
individual qualities. The novels of both Theodore Dreiser and Stephen Crane
bear the impact of Zola’s naturalism and social Darwinism. Frank Norris’
influential essay “A Plea for Romantic Fiction” (1901) was a defense of
naturalism which accommodated some Romantic qualities. Another seminal
figure in realist theory was Henry James. What follows is an analysis of central
statements of realism and naturalism made in England, France, and America.
George Eliot (1819–1880)
One of the most succinct yet poignant statements of realism was made by the
major Victorian novelist George Eliot, the latter being the pseudonym of
Mary Ann Evans. Her novels include Adam Bede (1859), The Mill on the
Floss (1860), Silas Marner (1861), Middlemarch (1871–1872), and Daniel
Deronda (1874–1876). Her translation of David Strauss’ controversial work
The Life of Jesus appeared in 1846. She also translated Ludwig Feuerbach’s
The Essence of Christianity (1854). These thinkers promoted a humanistic
and tolerant, as opposed to a rigidly religious, conception of human nature.
This newer conception is expressed in Adam Bede, where the narrator
explains that as a novelist she wishes to “give a faithful account of men and
things as they have mirrored themselves in my mind . . . as if I were in the
witness-box narrating my experience on oath.”3 Hence, the first principle of
Eliot’s realism is the artistic pursuit of truth, based on direct experience of the
world. She is aware, however, of the difficulty of such an enterprise:
“Falsehood is so easy, truth so difficult” (AB, 151–152). Indeed, she imagines
the reader asking for the characters to be portrayed as unproblematically
good or bad, so that they can be admired or condemned “at a glance,” and
without the “slightest disturbance” of their prepossessions or assumptions
(AB, 150–151). So the second principle of her realism is that the
172
Romanticism and the Later Nineteenth Century
representation of experience must be authentic, refusing to pander to current
prejudices and popular taste.
A third principle of Eliot’s realism is its moral basis: we should accept
people in their actual, imperfect, state, rather than holding them up to
impossible ideals: “These fellow-mortals, every one, must be accepted as
they are: you can neither straighten their noses, nor brighten their wit, nor
rectify their dispositions” (AB, 151). Hence Eliot’s artistic focus on ordinary
people and events has both an epistemological basis – the reliance on one’s
own experience – and a moral basis of sympathy or “fellow-feeling” with
other human beings. This sympathy points to a fourth principle of realism,
given in Eliot’s redefinition of beauty as existing in “deep human sympathy,”
whereby we should “see beauty in these commonplace things” (AB, 153).
Hence, Eliot cleverly presents her realism not merely as pertaining to literary
technique but as encompassing an entire way of looking at the world: the
pursuit of truth, the reliance on one’s own experience, the acceptance of
people as they are, the perception of beauty in ordinary things were all aspects
of this vision; and these are all underlain by a religious disposition which itself
is humane and based on human sympathy rather than endless doctrine and
unrealistic ideals.
Émile Zola (1840–1902)
Zola was the leading figure of French naturalism. His essay The Experimental
Novel (1880) attempted a justification of his own novelistic practice, and
became the seminal manifesto of naturalism. In it Zola argues for a literature
“governed” by an experimental or scientific method, a method which overturns and rejects all previous authority and proclaims the liberty of thought.4
A major principle of science, according to Zola, is the belief in “absolute
determinism”: there is no phenomenon, no occurrence in nature, which does
not have a determining cause or complex of causes (EN, 3). Zola neatly
situates literature within the general context of scientific advance:
the experimental novel is a consequence of the scientific evolution of the
century . . . it substitutes for the study of the abstract and the metaphysical
man the study of the natural man, governed by physical or chemical laws, and
modified by the influences of his surroundings; it is in one word the literature of
our scientific age, as the classical and romantic literature corresponded to a
scholastic and theological age. (EN, 23)
Hence, the experimental novel must consider man in both social and psychological aspects, taking account of heredity and social conditions (EN, 21).
Notwithstanding his scientism, Zola attempts to redeem the moral function
of literature. He sees science as progressing toward a state where humanity
Realism, Naturalism, Symbolism, and Aestheticism
173
will be in control of life and be able to direct nature, ultimately toward a moral
purpose: “We shall enter upon a century in which man, grown more
powerful, will make use of nature and will utilize its laws to produce upon
the earth the greatest possible amount of justice and freedom. There is no
nobler, higher, nor grander end” (EN, 25). Zola’s position might well be seen
as an attempt to reincarnate the classical idea of the “highest good” as the
purpose to which all science and art are ultimately directed. This function of
the novel, then, coheres with the paths of science and is also integrated with
the efforts of legislators and politicians “toward that great object, the
conquest of nature and the increase of man’s power” (EN, 31).
William Dean Howells (1837–1920)
William Dean Howells’ chief fictional work was The Rise of Silas Lapham
(1885), and his subsequent novels, such as A Hazard of New Fortunes (1890)
and The World of Chance (1893) move toward both socialism and social
realism, whereby he conducted a critique of American capitalism and
imperialism. Howells’ reputation as the major American theorist of realism
was established by his book Criticism and Fiction (1891), where he formulates a “democratic” theory of realism: the true realist “finds nothing
insignificant” and “feels in every nerve the equality of things and the unity of
men; his soul is exalted, not by . . . ideals, but by realities, in which alone the
truth lives.” For such a person, “no living man is a type, but a character.”5
Howells indicts current critical practice, based on personal feelings and
impressions and a blind adherence to past models (CF, 311). What we need
is a “dispassionate, scientific” study of literature, a study which is restricted
“to the business of observing, recording, and comparing; to analyzing the
material before it, and then synthesizing its impressions. Even then, it is not
too much to say that literature as an art could get on perfectly well without it”
(CF, 311, 314).
Howells directly equates democratic political beliefs with a democratic
aesthetic: the political state, he says, was built “on the affirmation of the
essential equality of men in their rights and duties . . . these conditions invite
the artist to the study and appreciation of the common . . . The arts must
become democratic, and then we shall have the expression of America in art”
(CF, 339). In the spirit of this democratic mission, Howells urges: “let fiction
cease to lie about life; let it portray men and women as they are, actuated by
the motives and the passions in the measure we all know . . . let it speak the
dialect, the language, that most Americans know – and there can be no doubt
of an unlimited future, not only of delightfulness but of usefulness, for it” (CF,
328). Such is the circuitous historical route by which literary aesthetics
returns to the principles of Horace, that the work of art must delight
and teach.
174
Romanticism and the Later Nineteenth Century
Henry James (1843–1916)
Henry James, brother of the pragmatist philosopher William James, is best
known for his novels, which include The American (1877), The Europeans
(1878), Daisy Miller (1879), The Portrait of a Lady (1881), The Ambassadors
(1903), and The Golden Bowl (1904). His influence extended to figures such
as Ezra Pound and T. S. Eliot. In his essay “The Art of Fiction” (1884), James
is concerned, firstly, to establish the novel as a serious art form. Secondly, he
denies that rules can be somehow prescribed for fiction. James’ central claim
is that the novel must be free from moral and educational requirements and
constraints.
This novelistic freedom is first worked out in relation to the kind of realism
on which James insists: “The only reason for the existence of a novel is that it
does attempt to represent life . . . as the picture is reality, so the novel is
history.”6 A novel produces the “the illusion of life” (AF, 173). James suggests
as a broad definition that the novel is “a personal, a direct impression of life,”
and it is successful inasmuch as it reveals a particular and unique mind (AF,
170). Moreover, the enterprise of realism is vastly complex. The writer should
indeed possess “a sense of reality” but “reality has a myriad forms” and cannot
be encompassed within some formula (AF, 171). Like reality, experience is a
complex concept. Experience “is never limited, and it is never complete; it is an
immense sensibility, a kind of huge spiderweb of the finest silken threads
suspended in the chamber of consciousness . . . It is the very atmosphere of the
mind” (AF, 172). A mere glimpse of a situation can afford a perspicacious
novelist an entire perspective based on deep insight. Indeed, James identifies
the very freedom of the novel with its potential for realistic – which for him
might well read “metonymic” – correspondence: the novel has a “large, free
character of an immense and exquisite correspondence with life” (AF, 179).
Notwithstanding the complex nature of both reality and experience, James
states that “the air of reality (solidity of specification) seems to me to be the
supreme virtue of a novel” (AF, 173). He insists that “the province of art is all
life, all feeling, all observation, all vision . . . it is all experience.” As such,
nothing can be forbidden for the novelist, nothing can be out of bounds (AF,
177–178). Finally, in arguing that the novel must be free of all moral obligations, he offers the apparently simple reasoning that “questions of art are
questions . . . of execution; questions of morality are quite another affair.” If art
has a purpose, that purpose is artistic: it must aim at perfection (AF, 181).
Symbolism and Aestheticism
Even as the currents of realism and then naturalism held sway in European
literature, there was also fermenting in the works of poets such as
Realism, Naturalism, Symbolism, and Aestheticism
175
Charles Baudelaire an alternative set of concerns: with language, with poetic
form, with evocation of mental states and ideal worlds, and the most
intimate recesses of human subjectivity. To some extent, these concerns
were inherited from the Romantics, as was the antagonism toward an urban
life regulated by the cycles of modern industry and commerce. The followers
of Baudelaire eventually became associated with a series of reactions against
realism and naturalism: symbolism, aestheticism, and impressionism, which
have sometimes, and in varying combinations, fallen under the label of
“decadence.”
This broad anti-realist and anti-bourgeois disposition had already surfaced
in many writers and movements: in the Pre-Raphaelite Brotherhood of artists
formed in 1848 in England which looked back to the direct and morally
serious art of the Middle Ages prior to the advent of the Renaissance artist
Raphael; in the Parnassian poets of France, inspired by Theophile Gautier and
Leconte de Lisle (1818–1894), who adopted an ethic of “art for art’s sake”;
and in Poe’s theories of poetic composition. Baudelaire and his successors,
such as Paul Verlaine (1844–1896), Arthur Rimbaud (1854–1891), and
Stephane Mallarme (1842–1898), were the heirs of these aesthetic tendencies;
and they have all been associated with French symbolism. This affiliation is
retrospective since the symbolist movement as such arose somewhat later, its
manifesto being penned by Jean Moreas in 1886. The other symbolists
included the poets Jules Laforgue, Henri de Regnier, Gustave Kahn, the
novelist Joris-Karl Huysmans, the dramatist Maurice Materlinck, and the
critic Remy de Gourmont. This movement reached its zenith in the 1890s and
thereafter declined, being often derisively viewed as a form of decadence and
affectation. It is the precursors of the symbolists – Baudelaire, Verlaine,
Rimbaud, and Mallarme – rather than the symbolists themselves who have
had a vast and enduring influence, extending from major poets such as W. B.
Yeats and T. S. Eliot, through writers of fiction such as Marcel Proust, James
Joyce, and Virginia Woolf, and dramatists such as August Strindberg, to
philosophers of language and modern literary theorists such as Roland
Barthes, Jacques Derrida, and Julia Kristeva.
Mallarme’s Divagations (1897) was another important statement of symbolist aesthetics. Mallarme rejected the realist assumption that language was
referential, that words were the signs of a pregiven reality. Reality is an
interpretation from a particular perspective, and for Mallarme, a poem is part
of reality and indeed helps to create reality. He also rejected the Romantic
idea of a poem as expressing an author’s subjectivity; rather, the poet enters
the world of language which determines both his consciousness and the
world. Mallarme drew attention to the material dimensions of words, their
sounds, their combinations on the page, and their ability to create new shades
of meaning and perception. The major critic of the symbolist movement was
Remy de Gourmont, who urged the ideals of subjectivity and artistic purity.
176
Romanticism and the Later Nineteenth Century
He asserted that “only mediocre works are impersonal”7 and advocated a
“pure art” which was “concerned exclusively with self-realization.”8
In general, the symbolists refused to take the material world they had
inherited as the real world. Drawing on Platonic philosophy, they saw the
present world as an imperfect reflection of a higher, infinite, and eternal realm
which could be evoked by symbols. Hence they rejected the descriptive
language of the realists and naturalists in favor of a more suggestive,
symbolic, and allusive language that could evoke states of consciousness.
They also drew on Baudelaire’s notion of “correspondences” between the
senses to elaborate an aesthetic of synaesthesia, and their predominant
analogy for poetry was with music. French symbolism was introduced into
England through Arthur Symons’ book The Symbolist Movement in Literature (1899), which characterized it as a “revolt against exteriority, against
rhetoric, against a materialistic tradition.”9
A more extreme development of this attitude of negation was in aestheticism, the doctrine that art exists for its own sake, or for the sake of beauty.
The phrase “l’art pour l’art” (art for art’s sake) had been coined by the
philosopher Victor Cousin in 1818; this doctrine reverberated through the
aesthetics of Kant, many of the Romantics, the Pre-Raphaelites, the Parnassians, the symbolists, the decadents, and the critical programs of the twentieth-century formalists. The work of some of the seminal figures of symbolism and aestheticism – Baudelaire, Pater, and Wilde – can now be
considered.
Charles Baudelaire (1821–1867)
Known as the founder of French symbolism (though not himself part of the
movement), Baudelaire was born in Paris where he lived a Bohemian life,
adopting the artistic posture of a dandy, devoted to beauty, disdainfully aloof
from the vulgar bourgeois world of materialism and commerce. He also
assumed the pose of the fl^
aneur, frequenter and consumer of the city streets.
Baudelaire expressed a modernistic vision of the sordidness, sensuality, and
corruption of city life, which influenced modernist writers such as T. S. Eliot.
Baudelaire’s infamous collection of poems, Les Fleurs du Mal (The Flowers of
Evil) (1857), became the subject of an “obscenity” trial for including lesbian
poems. He contracted syphilis and was paralyzed by a stroke before his death.
Notwithstanding his lifestyle and his artistic views, Baudelaire was a believer
in original sin, and viewed the modern world as fallen. In his Journaux intimes
he stated that man is “naturally depraved,” and he ridiculed the idea of
progress, viewing commerce as “in its very essence, satanic.”10
Baudelaire’s famous sonnet “Correspondences” is a succinct expression of
his symbolist aesthetic, seeing the material world as a “forest of symbols”
which point to an ideal world. He regards the earth and its phenomena as a
Realism, Naturalism, Symbolism, and Aestheticism
177
“revelation” of heavenly correspondences, and it is the poet who must
decipher these. In an essay he states that “poetry is what is most real, what
is completely true only in another world.” The present world, he maintains, is
merely a “dictionary of hieroglyphics” pointing to the world beyond.11 Much
of Baudelaire’s important criticism is contained in his Salons, which were
reviews of yearly exhibitions at the Louvre museum. In his “Salon” of 1846 he
insisted that criticism of poetry “should be biased, impassioned, partisan,”
though it should be written from a point of view “that opens up the widest
horizons” (BLC, 87–88). Baudelaire sanctions Poe’s fundamental views: that
an essential function of art is to produce a unity of impression or effect, that
poetry “has no other goal than itself” and as such must not be subjected to the
heresies of “teaching . . . of passion, of truth, and of morality.” Baudelaire
acknowledges, however, that poetry can “ennoble manners” and raises “man
above the level of vulgar interests” (BLC, 130–131). He accepts Poe’s
formulation of the “poetic principle” as “human aspiration toward a superior
beauty.” In fact, he adapts Poe’s notion into the statement that the “immortal
instinct for the beautiful . . . makes us consider the earth and its spectacles as a
revelation, as something in correspondence with Heaven” (BLC, 132).
Baudelaire notes that for Poe, “Imagination is the queen of faculties.”
Baudelaire’s own definition implies again a system of correspondences that is
not formulated in Poe’s work: “Imagination is an almost divine faculty which
perceives immediately and without philosophical methods the inner and
secret relations of things, the correspondences and the analogies” (BLC, 127).
Like Coleridge, Baudelaire sees the imagination as destroying conventional
associations and recreating according to primordial imperatives found within
human subjectivity, within the soul itself. But Baudelaire also states that
“Imagination is the queen of truth,” and that “it plays a powerful role even in
morality” (BLC, 182). Hence, even though truth and morality are rigidly
expelled by Poe and Baudelaire from the province of the aesthetic, they
are effectively subsumed under the control of the very power which creates
the aesthetic, the power of imagination. Baudelaire states that the “whole
visible universe is but a storehouse of images and signs to which imagination
will give a relative place and value; it is a sort of food which the imagination
must digest and transform” (BLC, 186). What arranges the world, then, is not
divine providence or the canons of truth or morality; all of these are now
subjected to the aesthetic power of imagination which is newly invested with
the functions of truth and morality in their subjectively reconstituted and
reauthorized form.
Walter Pater (1839–1894)
Walter Pater is best known for his phrase “art for art’s sake.” In his insistence
on artistic autonomy, on aesthetic experience as opposed to aesthetic object,
178
Romanticism and the Later Nineteenth Century
and on experience in general as an ever-vanishing flux, he is a precursor of
modern views of both life and art. His works included Studies in the History of
the Renaissance (1873), Marius the Epicurean (1885), Imaginary Portraits
(1887), and Plato and Platonism (1893).
In the preface to his Studies, Pater advocates a literary criticism based on
subjective experience and impressions. Subverting Arnold’s prescription that
the critic must know the “object as . . . it really is,” Pater insists that as a critic,
one must “know one’s own impression as it really is, to discriminate it, to
realise it distinctly.”12 The kinds of questions we should ask are: “What is this
song or picture . . . to me? What effect does it really produce on me?” (Ren.,
viii). Pater’s views of aesthetic experience are rooted in his account of
experience in general. Given the brevity of our life, experience must be
undertaken for its own sake: “Not the fruit of experience, but experience
itself, is the end . . . To burn always with this hard, gem-like flame, to maintain
this ecstasy, is success in life” (Ren., 236–237). Such intense experience is
furnished foremost by “the poetic passion, the desire of beauty, the love of art
for its own sake” (Ren., 239).
We have here reached a point in Western culture where experience is
dirempted and abstracted from any kind of constraint whatsoever. Hegel
would have regarded such experience as an abstract category, not even
possible; but Pater expresses a desperate attempt to redeem experience from
the weight of centuries of oppression and coercion and molding into various
socially acceptable forms; he effectively aestheticizes experience, equating
the fullness of experience with beauty. Experience is raised from the
mereness of means to the exaltation of end, a celebration of purposelessness,
indirection, relativism, and randomness.
Oscar Wilde (1854–1900)
Another figure in the aestheticist vein, who struck an even more decadent and
dandyish posture, was Oscar Wilde. A dazzling wit and brilliant conversationalist, he was the author of several plays which took the London stage by
storm, as well as of poetry, novels, and criticism. His most notable dramas
were Lady Windemere’s Fan (1892), An Ideal Husband (1895), and, most
successful of all, The Importance of Being Earnest (1895). These plays
powerfully satirized the morals and mores of the English middle classes;
Wilde’s own homosexual practices brought him into conflict with these moral
standards, and he was imprisoned for two years with hard labor. Wilde’s
subversiveness has been a source of inspiration for gay and lesbian studies,
and his refusal of absolutes aligns him not only with figures such as Pater but
also with Nietzsche and indeed the entire heterological tradition.
In the famous preface to his novel The Picture of Dorian Gray
(1890–1891), Wilde offers a brief and provocative manifesto of his aesthetic
Realism, Naturalism, Symbolism, and Aestheticism
179
outlook. He states that the “artist is the creator of beautiful things.”13 Wilde
continues, there “is no such thing as a moral or an immoral book” and “No
artist has ethical sympathies.” Moreover, no “artist desires to prove anything
. . . Books are well written, or badly written. That is all.” Wilde emphasizes
that “All art is quite useless.” And he effectively redefines its imitative
function: “It is the spectator, and not life, that art really mirrors” (OW,
17). This statement and in fact Wilde’s entire account of criticism anticipates
reader-response and some historicist theories.
“The Critic as Artist” (1891) sets forth Wilde’s most important views of art
and criticism. Any proposed antithesis between art and criticism, says Wilde,
is “entirely arbitrary. Without the critical faculty, there is no artistic creation
at all worthy of the name” (OW, 1020). He insists that “Criticism is itself an
art.” And, just as the creative act is critical, so criticism is creative. It is also
independent: “the highest Criticism, being the purest form of personal
impression, is in its way more creative than creation, as it has least reference
to any standard external to itself, and is . . . in itself, and to itself, an end”
(OW, 1027). What this statement makes us realize is the length of the journey
undertaken by literary criticism since Plato and Aristotle. We have now
moved even beyond the demand that art itself be extricated from moral,
religious, and ideological constraints. The demand for autonomy, having
traversed the sphere of art, has now emerged in the realm of criticism, a
demand that threatens to subvert not only previous conceptions of criticism
but also the basic tenets of Western philosophy.
What, then, is the self-contained aim of criticism? Like Pater, Wilde rejects
Arnold’s definition of criticism’s task as attempting “to see the object as in
itself it really is.” On the contrary, criticism “is in its essence purely
subjective” and must express personal impressions (OW, 1028). Wilde insists
that it is through the critic that the performative potential of the art is realized;
it is the critic who gives voice to the work of art. Moreover, it is the critic who
is “always showing us the work of art in some new relation to our age. He will
always be reminding us that great works of art are living things” (OW, 1034).
But criticism has a broader and more basic import. Wilde accepts Arnold’s
claim that criticism is responsible for creating the “intellectual atmosphere”
and culture of an age (OW, 1055). It is criticism that gives us a sense of unity,
that enables us to reconstruct the past, that enables us to rise above provincialism and prejudice into true cosmopolitanism (OW, 1053). Anticipating
important modern insights, Wilde states that it
is Criticism that, recognizing no position as final, and refusing to bind itself by
the shallow shibboleths of any sect or school, creates that serene philosophic
temper which loves truth for its own sake . . . Anything approaching to the free
play of the mind is practically unknown amongst us . . . The artistic critic, like
the mystic, is an antinomian always. (OW, 1057)
180
Romanticism and the Later Nineteenth Century
Notes
1. Herbert Marcuse, Reason and Revolution: Hegel and the Rise of Social Theory
(London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1977), pp. 232–388.
2. It is worth consulting Jameson’s entire discussion, The Ideologies of Theory:
Essays 1971–1986. Volume II: The Syntax of History (London: Routledge,
1989), pp. 118–122.
3. George Eliot, Adam Bede, ed. John Paterson (Boston and New York: Houghton
Mifflin, 1968), p. 150. Hereafter cited as AB.
4. Émile Zola, The Experimental Novel and Other Essays, trans. Belle M. Sherman
(New York: Haskell House, 1964), pp. 2, 26, 44. Hereafter cited as EN.
5. Criticism and Fiction, reprinted in W. D. Howells: Selected Literary Criticism.
Volume II: 1886–1869, ed Donald Pizer and Christoph K. Lohmann (Bloomington
and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 1993), pp. 302–303. Hereafter cited as
CF.
6. Henry James, The Art of Criticism, ed. William Veeder and Susan M. Griffin
(Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press, 1986), pp. 166–167. Hereafter cited as AF.
7. Remy de Gourmont, Selected Writings, trans. and ed. Glenn S. Burne (New York:
University of Michigan Press, 1966), p. 124.
8. Remy de Gourmont, Decadence and Other Essays on the Culture of Ideas, trans.
William Bradley (1922; rpt. London: George Allen and Unwin, 1930), p. 31.
9. Arthur Symons, The Symbolist Movement in Literature (1908; rpt. New York:
Haskell House, 1971), pp. 4, 9.
10. Intimate Journals, trans. C. Isherwood, introd. T. S. Eliot (New York and
London: Blackamore Press, 1930), pp. 48, 51.
11. Baudelaire as a Literary Critic: Selected Essays, trans. Lois Boe Hyslop and
Francis E. Hyslop, Jr. (Pennsylvania: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1964),
pp. 87–88. Hereafter cited as BLC.
12. Walter Pater, The Renaissance: Studies in Art and Poetry (London: Macmillan,
1913), p. viii. Hereafter cited as Ren.
13. The Complete Works of Oscar Wilde: Stories, Plays, Poems, Essays, introd.
Vyvyan Holland (London and Glasgow: Collins, 1984), p. 17. Hereafter cited
as OW.
Chapter 12
The Heterological Thinkers
The main streams of modern European and American thought, such as
rationalism, empiricism, utilitarianism, and pragmatism, stemmed from the
Enlightenment, the American and French Revolutions, as well as the ongoing
Industrial Revolution. Hegel’s philosophy had amalgamated the entire thrust
of modern bourgeois thought from Descartes and Hobbes through the
Enlightenment to Kant. There was, however, an important strand of thought
which reacted against Hegel’s philosophy as the embodiment of bourgeois
principles. This was the “heterological” or alternative tradition initiated by
Schopenhauer, who launched a radical critique of Enlightenment notions.
The tradition was continued by Nietzsche, Kierkegaard, Bergson, Freud,
Husserl, Heidegger, Derrida, and modern feminists. These thinkers challenged the very discipline of philosophy and its claims to arrive at truth
through reason. They emphasized instead the role of emotion, the body,
sexuality, the unconscious, as well as of pragmatic interests. This tradition
exhibits some historical continuity with the Romantics, the symbolists, and
decadents, as well as affiliations with humanists such as Irving Babbitt in
America and Matthew Arnold in England. The aesthetic views of four figures
from this heterodox line of thinking will be considered below in the context of
their world views: Schopenhauer, Nietzsche, Bergson, and Arnold. These
thinkers continue to influence literary debate in our own day at the profoundest levels.
Arthur Schopenhauer (1788–1860)
Schopenhauer – who is the most widely read philosopher in Germany today –
offered an incisive critique of the bourgeois world and its self-abasement
before the “crass materialism” of science.1 He was especially contemptuous
of attempts to historicize and rationalize the evils of the bourgeois world as
part of an ordered teleological plan; he dismissed Hegel’s “philosophy of
Literary Criticism from Plato to the Present: An Introduction
© 2011 M. A. R. Habib. ISBN: 978-1-405-16034-6
M. A. R. Habib
182
Romanticism and the Later Nineteenth Century
absolute nonsense” as comprised of “three-quarters cash and one-quarter
crazy notions” (PW, 79, 81). He saw history as exhibiting no unity beyond
eternal recurrence of the same miserable patterns of events (PW, 108, 290).
Schopenhauer argued that the intellect or reason so hypostatized by Enlightenment thought was actually in bondage to the practical motives of the will to
live, a will concentrated in the sexual act, in the unconscious and irrational
desire to perpetuate life. Schopenhauer viewed will as a force which operated
(1) largely unconsciously, (2) often repressively, and (3) in intimate conjunction with memory and sexuality.
At the heart of Schopenhauer’s philosophy and aesthetics is an attitude
which continues through Nietzsche, Arnold, Bergson, and others: that
rational knowledge can never be adequate to ideas of perception; and that
poetry is the paradigm of disinterested and objective knowledge. As in so
many nineteenth-century theories, epistemology – the science of knowing –
here becomes aestheticized, and the aesthetic becomes a privileged category
of human perception, elevated to a final resource for seeking harmony, unity,
and order in the world. The harmony which was objectively fragmented in the
late industrial world is now internalized as a subjective capacity: it is left to the
aesthetic to attempt what religion, philosophy, and science can no longer
accomplish. The aesthetic is defined as a form of perception of reality: poetry
could no longer take for granted the reality it was to express.
Friedrich Nietzsche (1844–1900)
Friedrich Nietzsche is most often associated with the announcement that
“God is dead” (which in fact is first found in Hegel’s Phenomenology); he is
also remembered by phrases such as the “will to power,” as well as the idea of
the “overman” or “superman” (€
ubermensch) who gloriously rises above the
common herd mentality and morality promoted by modern liberal states. His
ideas have sometimes been aligned with anti-Semitism and Nazism, and with
both extreme individualism and self-annihilating mysticism. Nietzsche himself saw the apparatus of both Church and state as coercing people into
a mediocre conformity; he called for a new conception of humanity, based on
self-creation, passion, power, and subjugation of one’s circumstances.
Nietzsche’s thought stresses the Dionysian side of human nature, fueled by
unconscious impulses and excess, as a counter to the Apollonian side which is
conscious, rational, and individuated; it subverts conventional notions of
truth; it unashamedly displays scorn for women; and it undermines modern
liberal political visions of democracy. Effectively, it challenges the fundamental assumptions of Western philosophy at epistemological, moral,
political, and spiritual levels; for these reasons, as well as for his style –
poetic, ironic, discontinuous, intimate – it has exerted an enormous influence
The Heterological Thinkers
183
on modernism, existentialism, the Frankfurt School of Marxism, the philosophy of science, and various branches of poststructuralism, such as those
associated with Derrida and Foucault. Nietzsche’s works include The Birth of
Tragedy (1870–1871), Ecce Homo (1888), The Antichrist (1895), and his
notebooks published posthumously as The Will to Power (1901).
Nietzsche’s call for a new vision of humanity was profoundly atheistic:
reality, truth, the world, even the self, are constructions, projections of human
needs and interests. His definition of reality is pragmatic: he states that the
world of appearance is created by our “practical instincts” and “is essentially
a world of relationships . . . its being is essentially different from every point.”
He defines an object as “only a kind of effect produced by a subject upon
a subject – a modus of the subject.” Like Schopenhauer, Nietzsche views our
pursuit of knowledge as not impartial but as one manifestation of our “will to
power,” our fundamental motive of self-assertion, subjugation, and conquest, as well as of our need for security.2
The text of Nietzsche’s with the most bearing on literature and criticism is
The Birth of Tragedy (1870–1871), which offers two major theses, one
purporting to explain the origins of tragedy and the other the death of tragedy
at the hands of what Nietzsche calls “Socratism,” a rational and scientific
outlook toward the world taught first by Socrates then by his disciple Plato.
Hence in a treatise ostensibly about tragedy, Nietzsche effectively attempts to
undermine the entire tradition of Western philosophy. Nietzsche’s first thesis is
that the evolution of art is based upon a broad conflict between two dispositions, represented respectively by the Greek gods Apollo and Dionysus. As a
moral deity, Apollo demands self-control, self-knowledge, moderation; in
short, he demands due respect and observance of the limits and status of the
individual.3 Dionysus, on the other hand, represents a condition in which this
principle isshattered,a statewherethe“individual forgetshimselfcompletely,”
and all previous social and religious barriers are annulled, in a universal
harmony (BT, 23). These two forces, the Apollonian and the Dionysian, are
creative tendencies which developed side by side “usually in fierce opposition
. . . until . . . the pair accepted the yoke of marriage and, in this condition, begot
Attic tragedy, which exhibits the salient features of both parents” (BT, 19).
Nietzsche explains that, in order to endure the “terrors and horrors of
existence,” the Greeks had to create “the shining fantasy of the Olympians.”
The Greek deities answered to the Apollonian need for a beautiful and
comforting illusion through this “aesthetic mirror” (BT, 30, 32). Hence the
ancient Greek, though open to the deepest suffering, was “saved by art” (BT,
50–51). One of the “realities” from which art saves us is the Dionysiac
realization, embodied in Hamlet, that no action of ours can alter the “eternal
condition of things . . . Understanding kills action, for in order to act we
require the veil of illusion” (BT, 51). Once we pierce to the truth of existence,
we see its “ghastly absurdity” and are invaded by “nausea” (BT, 52).
184
Romanticism and the Later Nineteenth Century
Nietzsche here anticipates the views and terminology – absurdity, nausea – of
existentialism. He sees such absurdity as a perennial human condition, which
we must always repress. Art is the supreme mechanism at our disposal in
achieving this illusion: our justification of life is ultimately neither religious
nor moral but aesthetic.
Nietzsche’s second thesis has wide-ranging implications for philosophy
and literary and cultural theory. Greek tragedy, he suggests, “died by
suicide,” in the hands of Euripides who, viewing tragedy as a rational matter
of conscious perceptions, attempted to eliminate altogether the Dionysiac
strain, battling against the works of Aeschylus and Sophocles (BT, 75–76,
80). In so doing, he killed both myth and music (BT, 69). What spoke through
Euripides in his endeavor to rebuild the drama on the basis of a non-Dionysiac
art was a new and powerful daimon. His name was Socrates (BT, 77). From
this point on, says Nietzsche, the real antagonism was between the Dionysiac
spirit and the Socratic spirit, and “tragedy was to perish in the conflict” (BT,
77). Euripides and Socrates both were unable to understand tragedy; both
viewed it as chaotic and irrational; and both condemned it along with its
underlying ethics (BT, 82–83). In its place, Euripides must have seen himself
“as the first rational maker of tragedy” (BT, 81).
As for Socrates: who, asks Nietzsche, was this man who dared singlehandedly to “challenge the entire world of Hellenism”? His power, exerted
primarily through his disciple Plato, was such that it forced poetry into a new
status of subordination to philosophy (BT, 88). Nietzsche raises the question,
as indeed Plato had himself, whether “art and Socratism are diametrically
opposed to one another” (BT, 90). Socrates is the “despotic logician,” the
prototype “of an entirely new mode of existence,” the theoretical man who
delights in the very process of unveiling truth, thereby assuring himself of his
own power (BT, 92). In Socrates is the first manifestation of a deep-seated
“grand metaphysical illusion,” that thought can “plumb the farthest abysses
of being,” to make “existence appear intelligible and thereby justified” (BT,
93). In this sense, Socrates is “the vortex and turning point of Western
civilization” (BT, 94–95).
And yet there is hope. Modern man has begun to realize the limits of
Socratic curiosity. And there are, thinks Nietzsche, certain forces that promise
a rebirth of tragedy, as based on myth, on a “deeper wisdom” ineffable in
words and concepts (BT, 103). Nietzsche points to a gradual reawakening of
the Dionysiac spirit in the “German soul,” as expressed in music from Bach
through Beethoven to Wagner, as well as in the philosophies of Kant and
Schopenhauer (BT, 98, 101, 119). Both movements have “authoritatively
rejected science’s claim to universal validity” and thereby initiated a culture of
the tragic (BT, 111). In our present age, man is stripped of myth, and “stands
famished among all his pasts,” in the grip of a hunger that signifies “the loss of
myth, of a mythic home, the mythic womb” (BT, 137).
The Heterological Thinkers
185
Henri Bergson (1859–1941)
Schopenhauer’s thought impinges considerably not only on the thought of
Nietzsche but also on Bergson’s ideas and his theories of art and humor.
Bergson’s philosophy influenced modernist writers such as Proust, T. S. Eliot,
and Virginia Woolf. This philosophy was expressed in Creative Evolution
(1907), where Bergson had argued that what is most real is precisely what
philosophers since Plato have condemned as unreal: time. Plato, Plotinus, and
Christian theology considered the temporal world as a degradation of the
eternal. In affirming the reality of time rather than of eternity, Bergson was
returning to the immediacy and authenticity of experience as against the
conceptual and linguistic reduction of such experience to conventional
categories, whether in the name of feudal Christianity, Enlightenment reason,
or conservative humanism. Bergson’s notion of duree placed emphasis on the
human personality as the locus of the primary reality: “There is at least one
reality which we all seize from within, by intuition and not by simple analysis.
It is our own person in its flowing through time, the self which endures.”4
Schopenhauer, Nietzsche, the French symbolists, and Bergson, as well as
the modernists who were influenced by this tradition, opposed the idea of
literal language, which embodied bourgeois positivism, scientism, and mechanism. For all of these writers, a subversion of literal language was the vehicle
of access into a deeper reality. They tend to emphasize language as a temporal
process rather than viewing it as a spatialized system of conventional concepts. According to Bergson, language is inescapably general; it can never
express the true individuality of an object or situation. The most basic premise
of Bergson’s aesthetics is that art creates novelty. Whereas language is spatial,
art is temporal, expressing duration, expressing the authentic flow of experience which is encrusted over by language. The poet’s business is to rebel
against the generality and conventionality of language. She individuates by
deploying the materiality of language, treating words as sharing the same
individual material status as other objects in the world rather than as
universal meanings or atemporal signs of objects. The reality suggested by
a poem is one where the “knowledge” offered by the intellect clashes with our
sensory experience. For these thinkers, poetry is effectively the conclusion and
resting place of philosophy.
Matthew Arnold (1822–1888)
Matthew Arnold has been regarded by some as one of the founding figures of
modern English criticism. He raised many classical questions about the
function of literature and criticism in the context of a modern industrial
186
Romanticism and the Later Nineteenth Century
society, and they remain with us today. Arnold was not only a cultural critic
but also a poet and an educator. In 1851 he became an inspector of schools
and was deeply concerned with the kind of education suitable for middle-class
and working-class students. In 1857 he was appointed Professor of Poetry at
Oxford. Arnold’s poetry, of which “Dover Beach” is perhaps the most
famous example, expresses isolation and near-despair in a world seemingly
abandoned by divine providence, a world on the brink of disastrous wars,
a world in which the only faith is in other human beings. He described himself
as “wandering between two worlds, one dead,/The other powerless to be
born.” Arnold’s literary and social criticism was produced largely in the
1860’s, comprising Essays in Criticism, first series (1865) and Culture and
Anarchy (1869). A second series of Essays in Criticism was published in 1888.
In the 1870s Arnold wrote on religious and educational matters; he considered his most important prose work to be Literature and Dogma (1873).
Central to Arnold’s literary criticism is the problem of living adequately in
late industrial society. Arnold’s world view is deeply humanist, in a tradition
that will run through figures such as F. R. Leavis and survives to this day.
Arnold’s central terms and phrases – “sweetness and light,” “perfection,”
“inwardness,” “the best that has been thought and said” – all derive
ultimately from his analysis of the spiritual and moral malaise of modern
culture. He deplored the narrow moralism and mercantilism of the bourgeoisie, whom he termed “philistines.”5 His essay “The Function of
Criticism” is concerned to counteract the philistinism of the English bourgeoisie, enshrined in its obsession with practicality, utility, and reason.
In this essay, Arnold holds that, while the “critical faculty is lower than the
inventive,” it nonetheless creates the conditions in which creative genius can
be realized (SP, 132–133). It is also the business of criticism “in all branches of
knowledge . . . to see the object as in itself it really is” (SP, 134). He is calling
for criticism to be “disinterested,” an attitude whose recent deficiency he
attributes partly to the French Revolution. Unlike previous major movements
such as the Renaissance and the Reformation, which were “disinterestedly
intellectual and spiritual movements,” the French Revolution “took a political, practical character” (SP, 136). While Arnold concedes that this Revolution was “the greatest, the most animating event in history,” it was
characterized by a “fatal” exaltation of reason, a “fatal” mania for giving
“an immediate political and practical application” to the ideas of reason (SP,
137). Arnold’s argument is that, while we must value ideas “in and for
themselves,” we cannot “transport them abruptly into the world of politics
and practice” (SP, 138). The “fatal” result, as Arnold states in Culture and
Anarchy, is an inordinate and spiritually stunting “[f]aith in machinery,”
a utilitarian reduction of the world to a practical mechanism (SP, 209).
Arnold’s logic here, like Burke’s, is that abstract ideas cannot simply be
imposed upon a people’s constitution or way of life (SP, 139).
The Heterological Thinkers
187
Arnold suggests that criticism must be “disinterested” by keeping aloof
from “the practical view of things,” by “following the law of its own nature,
which is to be a free play of the mind on all subjects which it touches. Criticism
must attempt to know “the best that is known and thought in the world, and
by in turn making this known, to create a current of true and fresh ideas . . . but
its business is to do no more” (SP, 142). And the purpose of criticism? To lead
man “towards perfection, by making his mind dwell upon what is excellent in
itself” (SP, 144). Finally, Arnold cautions that if the critic is truly devoted to
expanding the stock of true ideas, he will move beyond insularity, recognizing
that much of the “best that is known and thought” will come from outside
England. Criticism must regard “Europe as being, for intellectual and
spiritual purposes, one great confederation” (SP, 156). This statement, in
the view of tradition it implies, echoes Burke and anticipates T. S. Eliot.
In Culture and Anarchy (1869) Arnold redefines “culture” as “a study of
perfection. It moves by the force, not merely or primarily of the scientific
passion for pure knowledge, but also of the moral and social passion for doing
good” (SP, 205). Culture, then, has an intellectual and an ethical component,
and the aims of culture, according to Arnold, are identical with those of
religion, which Arnold calls “the greatest and most important of the efforts by
which the human race has manifested its impulse to perfect itself, – religion,
that voice of the deepest human experience.” What they have in common also
is the cultivation of inwardness: religion preaches that “The Kingdom of God
is within you,” and culture “places human perfection in an internal condition” (SP, 208). Culture expands our gifts of thought and feeling, and
fosters growth in wisdom and beauty. But culture advances beyond religion,
according to Arnold, because, through a “disinterested study of human
nature,” it fosters a “harmonious expansion of all the powers which make
the beauty and worth of human nature.” The implication is, of course, that
religion stresses the moral over the aesthetic, whereas culture promotes their
harmony. Because culture represents for Arnold an inward condition of the
mind and not outward circumstances, he regards its function as especially
crucial in our modern civilization which is “mechanical and external” as well
as strongly individualistic (SP, 209). In uniting beauty and intelligence,
culture effects a harmony of “sweetness and light,” terms taken from
Jonathan Swift’s Battle of the Books (1704). The task of both criticism and
culture, then, is to place the pragmatic bourgeois vision of life in a broader
historical and international context.
Arnold’s essay “The Study of Poetry” (1880) is one of the most influential
texts of literary humanism; it insists on the social and cultural functions of
literature, its ability to civilize and to cultivate morality. According to Arnold,
the status of religion has been increasingly threatened by science, by the
ideology of the “fact.” Philosophy he regards as powerless since it is
hopelessly entrenched in unresolved questions and problems. It is, he claims,
188
Romanticism and the Later Nineteenth Century
to poetry that we must turn, not merely for spiritual and emotional support
and consolation but to interpret life for us. He defines poetry as a criticism of
life. Poetry’s high function is actually to replace religion and philosophy (SP,
340).
If poetry is to serve this exalted office, we must be even more certain, says
Arnold, of our capacity to distinguish good from bad poetry. His essay
contains also the notions of the “classic” and “tradition,” which will be
further developed by writers such as T. S. Eliot and F. R. Leavis. Arnold
suggests that, in the first place, we need to be sure that our estimate of poetry is
“real” rather than based on historical or personal considerations (SP, 341).
How do we arrive at this real estimate of what constitutes a classic? Arnold’s
answer is to offer not a theory but a practice, of using “touchstones.” We
cannot say abstractly what comprises great poetry but we know we are in its
presence when we experience and feel its power. Arnold cites a number of
lines of “great” poets in various languages to illustrate his point. We know
when we are in the presence of a great work because it exhibits truth and
seriousness (SP, 348–349). What is interesting here is Arnold’s lack of
engagement with formal qualities. He implies that if the content is sufficiently
true and serious, it will automatically be expressed in an appropriate form.
Also lacking is any sense of engagement in historical context. His reliance on
some ineffable literary sensibility which somehow knows how to judge is
an appeal to so-called experience and to making judgments on the basis of
a sensibility which defies articulation.
Notes
1. Arthur Schopenhauer, Philosophical Writings, ed. Wolfgang Schirmacher (New
York: Continuum, 1994), pp. 20–22, 69, 86. Hereafter cited as PW.
2. Friedrich Nietzsche, The Will to Power, trans. W. Kaufmann and R. J. Hollingdale
(Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1978), pp. 277–278, 306–307.
3. Friedrich Nietzsche, The Birth of Tragedy and The Genealogy of Morals, trans.
Francis Golffing (New York: Doubleday, 1956), p. 34. Herafter cited as BT.
4. Henri Bergson, The Creative Mind: An Introduction to Metaphysics (New York:
Philosophical Library, 1946), p. 162.
5. Matthew Arnold, Selected Prose (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1970), pp. 177, 179.
Hereafter cited as SP.
Part V
The Twentieth Century:
A Brief Introduction
Introduction
The twentieth century was marked by certain colossal events which profoundly shaped the worlds of literature and criticism. These events included
the Bolshevik Revolution of 1917 in Russia, World War I (1914–1918), the
great economic depression of the 1930s, World War II (1939–1945), the Cold
War between the capitalist nations and the communist bloc, decolonization
of many nations around the mid-century, the predominance of America as a
world power, the emergence of the so-called “third world,” the social and
political unrest of the 1960s, and a general swing in the West toward rightwing politics in the 1980s. Many of these developments culminated in the
collapse of the communist bloc and the Soviet Union by 1991. The 1990s
witnessed a concerted awareness of environmental destruction, while the
beginning of the new century has overseen the emerging narratives of a “New
World Order” and the “war on terror,” as capitalism emerges into a global
phenomenon.
The devastating impact of World War I, fought between Germany and
Austria on the one side (joined by Turkey and Bulgaria), and France, Russia,
and Britain on the other (allied with Japan, Italy, and America), was
unprecedented in history. Eric Hobsbawm states that this war “marked the
breakdown of the (western) civilization of the nineteenth century.”1 The
ideals of the Enlightenment, embodied in the various institutions of the
capitalist world, and its ideologies of rational, scientific advance, material
and moral progress, individualism, and the economic and cultural centrality
of Europe, had culminated in a catastrophe on many levels, economic,
political, and moral. The consequent psychological and material devastation
led thinkers in all domains to question both the heritage of the Enlightenment
and the very foundations of Western civilization. Long-held assumptions –
concerning reason, historical progress, and the moral autonomy of human
beings – were plunged into crisis.
Literary Criticism from Plato to the Present: An Introduction
© 2011 M. A. R. Habib. ISBN: 978-1-405-16034-6
M. A. R. Habib
190
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
Subsequently, the Great Depression of the 1930s represented “a world
economic crisis of unprecedented depth.” Hobsbawm remarks that liberal
democratic institutions declined between 1917 and 1942, as fascism and
various authoritarian regimes rose to power. World War II, waged by the
allies (Britain, America, and France) to contain the expansionist ambitions of
Nazi Germany (aided by the totalitarian regimes of Italy and Japan), wrought
not only a second wave of wide-scale destruction but, in its aftermath, the
disintegration of the huge colonial empires of Britain, France, Belgium, and
the Netherlands, which had subjugated one-third of the world’s population.
Notwithstanding the formation of the United Nations in 1945, and NATO in
1949, the twentieth century “was without doubt the most murderous century
of which we have record” (AE, 11). All of these phenomena – the two world
wars, the rise of fascism, the depression, and decolonization – had a profound
impact on literature and criticism.
Then followed a long period, from 1947 to 1973, of considerable growth
and prosperity, which harbored the greatest and most rapid economic and
cultural transformations in recorded history (AE, 11). Apart from the
unprecedented technological advances, whereby most of the world’s population ceased to live in agricultural economies, this era witnessed numerous
political and social revolutions, whose principles were variously expressed by
Che Guevara in Latin America, Frantz Fanon in Algeria, and the philosopher
Herbert Marcuse, who inspired radical intellectuals in America and Europe.
Political revolutions and movements against colonialism erupted in many
parts of Africa; the earlier black militancy in America, inspired by figures such
as Marcus Garvey and later Malcolm X, broadened into the civil rights
movement of the 1950s and 1960s, whose leaders included Martin Luther
King, assassinated in 1968. Many of the sentiments behind these movements
were powerfully expressed in African-American literature and criticism. In
the Middle East, things were no less turbulent. The termination of the British
mandate in Palestine and the creation of the state of Israel in 1948 led to
persistent conflict between Israel and the Arab nations, fought out in bitter
wars in 1948, 1956, 1967, and 1973. This conflict has profoundly shaped the
literature and criticism of the entire region; it was analyzed in the work of the
Palestinian-American scholar Edward Said, as well as of recent thinkers such
zek.
as Slavoj Zi
Throughout this period, Western capitalism pursued the path of increasing
monopoly and consolidation, often employing the principles advocated by
economists such as John Maynard Keynes, who thought that the inequities of
capitalism could be remedied, and prosperity brought to all, using monetary
control rather than the nineteenth-century principles of laissez-faire. A
generation of students in America and Europe, however, reacted against
what they saw as the repressive, unjust, sexist, racist, and imperialist nature of
the late capitalist world, epitomized for many by American involvement in the
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
191
Vietnam War. In May 1968, left-wing uprisings of students and workers
shook the University of Paris, as well as Berkeley, San Francisco State, Kent
State, and elsewhere. Much literary theory in France and America, including
feminism, took its impetus from this atmosphere of unrest and agitation. The
later twentieth century brought a new awareness of ecology and the extent to
which modern industrial life and production had damaged the environment.
As we enter a new century, the Cold War has been replaced by a new
dynamic, which itself has served as the foundation for much recent criticism
and theory. The relatively stable international system of communism was
succeeded by local ethnic, tribal, and religious conflicts in Yugoslavia and
areas of the former Soviet Union. Since the early 1990s, the core of this new
dynamic has been underlain by America’s unopposed predominance as the
major world power, fueled by formulations of a “New World Order.” The
relative impotence of the political left has left its mark on the nature of theory,
and on what is viewed as radical or conservative. What has occupied center
stage since the attacks of September 11, 2001 on the World Trade Center has
been the “war on terror.” Hobsbawm states three ways in which the world
has changed from the beginning to the end of the twentieth century: it is no
longer Eurocentric, though America, Europe, and Japan are still the most
prosperous; the world has in certain important ways become a “single
operational unit,” primarily in economic terms, but also increasingly in
terms of mass culture; and, finally, there has been a massive disintegration
of previous patterns of human relationships, with an unprecedented rupture
between past and present. Capitalism has become a permanent and continuous revolutionary force that perpetuates itself in time and extends its empire
increasingly in space (AE, 14–16). Modern criticism and theory has broadened to encompass all of these developments.
Note
1. Eric Hobsbawm, The Age of Extremes: A History of the World, 1914–1991
(New York: Pantheon, 1994), p. 6. Hereafter cited as AE.
Chapter 13
From Liberal Humanism
to Formalism
At the end of the nineteenth century, criticism in Europe and America had been
predominantly biographical, historical, psychological, impressionistic, and
empirical. With the establishment of English as a separate discipline in
England, many influential critics, such as George Saintsbury, A. C. Bradley,
and Arthur Quiller-Couch assumed academic posts. By far the most influential
of this early generation of academic critics was A. C. Bradley. In Shakespearean
Tragedy (1904), Bradley’s central thesis, influenced by Hegel, saw Shakespearean tragedy as a dialectic whereby the moral order and harmony of the
world were threatened (by the tragic hero) and then reestablished.
In America, influential theories of realism and naturalism had been propounded by William Dean Howells, Hamlin Garland, and Frank Norris. An
important concern of American critics such as John Macy, Randolph Bourne,
and Van Wyck Brooks was to establish a sense of national identity through
tracing a specifically American literary tradition. In France, the most pervasive critical mode was the explication de texte, based on close readings which
drew upon biographical sources and historical context. In the humanist
tradition of Matthew Arnold, much of this fin-de-siecle criticism saw in
literature a refuge from, or remedy for, the ills of modern civilization.
The humanist tradition of the late nineteenth century, as expressed by
figures such as Matthew Arnold, vociferously reacted against the commercialism and philistinism of bourgeois society. This tradition was continued
and intensified in the polemic of the “New Humanists,” as well as by certain
neo-Romantic and formalistic critics. Led by Harvard professor Irving
Babbitt and including figures such as Paul Elmer More, Norman Foerster,
and Stuart Sherman, the New Humanists were conservative in their cultural
and political outlook, reacting against the predominant tendencies stemming
from the liberal-bourgeois tradition: a narrow focus on the present at the
expense of the past and of tradition; unrestrained freedom in political, moral,
and aesthetic domains; a riot of pluralism, a mechanical exaltation of facts
and an uninformed worship of science.
Literary Criticism from Plato to the Present: An Introduction
© 2011 M. A. R. Habib. ISBN: 978-1-405-16034-6
M. A. R. Habib
194
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
Also reacting against the industrialism and rationalism of the bourgeois
world were the neo-Romantic critics in England, including D. H. Lawrence,
G. Wilson Knight, John Middleton Murry, Herbert Read, and C. S. Lewis.
Lawrence (1885–1930) was an avowed irrationalist, who saw the modern
industrial world as sexually repressive and as having stunted human
potential. Lawrence advocated a vitalism and individualism which often
had parallels in the views of Nietzsche and Freud. Lawrence anticipates the
stress on the unconscious, the body, and irrational motives in various areas
of contemporary criticism. Of the other neo-Romantic critics, G. Wilson
Knight (1897–1985), a Shakespeare scholar, is best known for his The
Wheel of Fire (1930), which interprets Shakespeare’s plays in terms of
certain recurring symbols and motifs. Another significant critic in this broad
Romantic-religious tradition was C. S. Lewis (1898–1963) whose major
critical work, The Allegory of Love (1936), contributed to his mission of
promoting understanding of the formality and didacticism of the literature
of the Middle Ages and the Renaissance. Finally, mention should be made
of the scholar of Milton and Shakespeare, E. M. Tillyard (1889–1962), who
engaged in a debate with C. S. Lewis in The Personal Heresy (1939) and
whose most influential work was The Elizabethan World Picture (1943).
New Critical trends were also anticipated in America where W. C. Brownell
attempted to establish literary criticism as a serious and independent
activity, and where James Gibbons Huneker and H. L. Mencken insisted
on addressing the aesthetic elements in art as divorced from moral
considerations.
Hence, the critical movements of the early twentieth century were
already moving in certain directions: the isolation of the aesthetic from
moral, religious concerns, and indeed an exaltation of the aesthetic (as
transcending reason and the paradigms of bourgeois thought such as
utility and pragmatic value) as a last line of defense against a commercialized and dehumanizing world; and a correlative attempt to establish
criticism as a serious and “scientific” activity. This broadly humanist
trend is far from dead; it has not only persisted through figures such as F.
R. Leavis but also has often structured the very forms of critical endeavors
which reject it.
The Background of Modernism
Modernism comprised a broad series of movements in Europe and America
that came to fruition roughly between 1910 and 1930. Its major exponents
and practitioners included Marcel Proust, James Joyce, Ezra Pound, T. S.
Eliot, William Faulkner, Virginia Woolf, Luigi Pirandello, and Franz Kafka.
These various modernisms were the results of many complex economic,
From Liberal Humanism to Formalism
195
political, scientific, and religious developments over the nineteenth century,
which culminated in World War I (1914–1918). The vast devastation,
psychological demoralization, and economic depression left by the war
intensified the already existing reactions against bourgeois modes of
thought and economic practice. Rationalism underwent renewed assaults
from many directions: from philosophers such as Bergson, from the sphere
of psychoanalysis, from neoclassicists such as T. E. Hulme, the New
Humanists in America, and neo-Thomists such as Jacques Maritain. These
reactions were often underlain by a new understanding of language, as
a conventional and historical construct. The modernist writer occupied
a world that was often perceived as fragmented, where the old bourgeois
ideologies of rationality, science, progress, civilization, and imperialism had
been somewhat discredited; where the artist was alienated from the social
and political world, and where art and literature were marginalized; where
populations had been subjected to processes of mass standardization;
where philosophy could no longer offer visions of unity, and where
language itself was perceived to be an inadequate instrument for expression
and understanding.
A distinct group of artist-critics associated with modernism was the highly
iconoclastic “Bloomsbury Group.” This circle included Virginia Woolf and
her sister Vanessa, daughters of the critic and agnostic philosopher Leslie
Stephen, the art critics Roger Fry and Clive Bell, the economist John
Maynard Keynes, the biographer Lytton Strachey, and the novelist E. M.
Forster. Most members of the group fell under the influence of the Cambridge philosopher G. E. Moore’s Principia Ethica. They saw this text as
affirming an “aesthetic” approach to life inasmuch as it stressed the value of
allegedly timeless states of consciousness which facilitated the enjoyment of
beauty. The group inevitably fell under many of the influences that had
shaped modernism, such as the notion of time advanced in the philosophy of
Bergson. It was during this period also that the foundations of the New
Criticism were laid by figures such as William Empson and I. A. Richards;
the latter’s Principles of Literary Criticism (1924) and Practical Criticism
(1929) were widely and enduringly influential. Here, too, the literary artifact
was treated as an autonomous and self-contained verbal structure, insulated
from the world of prose, as in Richards’ distinction between emotive and
referential language. In France also, the somewhat positivistic earlier mode
of criticism, the explication de texte, was opposed by influential figures such
as Bergson, whose novel conceptions of time and memory, and whose view
of art as uniquely transcending the mechanistic concepts of bourgeois
society, profoundly influenced Proust and other modernists. Paul Valery
(1871–1945) formulated a criticism drawing on the earlier French symbolists, one which prioritized the aesthetic verbal structure over historical and
contextual elements.
196
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
The Poetics of Modernism: W. B. Yeats, Ezra Pound,
and T. S. Eliot
What underlies modernistic literary forms is an awareness that the definition
of reality is complex and problematic. Modernists came to this common
awareness by different paths: Yeats drew on the occult, on Irish myth and
legend, as well as the Romantics and French symbolists. Proust drew on the
insights of Bergson; Virginia Woolf, on Bergson, G. E. Moore, and others;
Pound drew on various non-European literatures as well as French writers;
T. S. Eliot, whose poetic vision was profoundly eclectic, drew on Dante, the
metaphysical poets, Laforgue, Baudelaire, and a number of philosophers.
In general, literary modernism was marked by a number of features: (1) the
affirmation of a continuity between the self and the world, which are viewed
as shaping each other; (2) a perception of the complex roles of time, memory,
and history in the mutual construction of self and world. Time is not
conceived in a static model which separates past, present, and future as
discrete elements in linear relation; rather, it is viewed as dynamic, with these
elements influencing and changing one another; (3) a breakdown of any linear
narrative structure: modernist poetry tends to be fragmented, creating its own
internal “logic” of emotion, image, sound, symbol, and mood; (4) a selfconsciousness regarding the process of literary composition. This embraces
both an awareness of how one’s own work relates to the literary tradition as
a whole, and also an ironic stance toward the content of one’s own work; (5)
finally, and most importantly, an awareness of the problematic nature of
language. Modernists display an aversion to so-called “literal” language
which might presume a one-to-one correspondence between words and
things; modernist poetry relies more on suggestion and allusion, aiming to
construct alternative visions of reality.
Twentieth-century modernism, as manifested in the work of the Irish poet
and critic W. B. Yeats (1865–1939), the American poet Ezra Pound, and the
Anglo-American poet and critic T. S. Eliot, was deeply influenced by symbolism, whether that of the English Romantics such as Blake, Coleridge,
Wordsworth, and Shelley, or French symbolism as developed in the work of
Baudelaire, Mallarme, Verlaine, and Rimbaud. French symbolism was introduced to English and American audiences largely through Arthur Symons’
book The Symbolist Movement in Literature (1899), which saw French
symbolism as a reaction against nineteenth-century scientism and materialism, and as affirming the reality of a higher, spiritual realm which could be
divined not by rational thought but only in glimpses through a pure poetic
language divested of any representational pretension.
Perhaps the most important modernist critic was the poet T. S. Eliot
(1888–1965), whose main critical contributions were (1) to combat
From Liberal Humanism to Formalism
197
provincialism by broadening the notion of “tradition” to include Europe; (2)
to advocate, as against the prevailing critical impressionism, a closely
analytical and even objective criticism which situated literary works alongside one another in the larger context of tradition. In this, he contributed to
the development of notions of artistic autonomy which were taken up by
some of the New Critics; and (3) to foster, by his own revaluation of the
literary tradition (reacting against the Romantics, for example, and highlighting the virtues of the metaphysical poets), a dynamic notion of tradition as
always in the process of change. Eliot’s criticism was in part a manifesto of
literary modernism, characteristically infused with political conservatism.
Formalism
The emphasis on poetic form reached a new intensity not only in European
modernism but also in the critical theories of the early twentieth century,
beginning with the Formalist movement in Russia, extending subsequently
to the New Criticism in England and America and later schools such as the
neo-Aristotelians. In general, an emphasis on form parenthesizes concern for
the representational, imitative, and cognitive aspects of literature. Literature
is no longer viewed as aiming to represent reality or character or to impart
moral or intellectual lessons, but is considered to be an object in its own right,
autonomous (possessing its own laws) and autotelic (having its aims internal
to itself). In this formalist view, literature does not convey any clear or
paraphrasable message; rather it communicates what is otherwise ineffable.
Literature is regarded as a unique mode of expression. Critics have variously
theorized that preoccupation with form betokens social alienation, a withdrawal from the world, an acknowledgment of political helplessness, and
a retreat into the aesthetic as a refuge of sensibility and humanistic values.
Russian Formalism
Along with movements in futurism and symbolism, the Russian Formalists
were a group of writers who flourished during the period of the Russian
Revolution of 1917. The Formalists and the futurists were active in the fierce
debates of this era concerning art and its connections with ideology. The
Formalists and futurists found a common platform in the journal LEF (Left
Front of Art). The Formalists, focusing on artistic forms and techniques on the
basis of linguistic studies, had arisen in pre-revolutionary Russia but now saw
their opposition to traditional art as a political gesture, allying them somewhat with the revolution. However, all of these groups were attacked by the
most prominent Soviet theoreticians, such as Trotsky, Nikolai Bukharin
198
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
(1888–1937), Anatoly Lunacharsky (1875–1933), and Voronsky, who
decried the attempt to break completely with the past and what they saw
as a reductive denial of the social and cognitive aspects of art. V. N. Volosinov
and Bakhtin later attempted to harmonize the two sides of the debate, viz.,
formal linguistic analysis and sociological emphasis, by treating language
itself as the supreme ideological phenomenon, as the very site of ideological
struggle. Other groups, called “Bakhtin Circles,” formed around this
enterprise.
There were two schools of Russian Formalism. The Moscow Linguistic
Circle, led by Roman Jakobson, was formed in 1915; this group also included
Osip Brik and Boris Tomashevsky. The second group, the Society for the
Study of Poetic Language (Opoyaz), was founded in 1916, and its leading
figures included Victor Shklovsky, Boris Eichenbaum, and Yuri Tynyanov.
Other important critics associated with these movements included Leo
Jakubinsky and the folklorist Vladimir Propp.
The Russian Formalists’ emphasis on form and technique was far more
theoretical than that of the later New Critics who were more concerned with
the practice of close reading of individual texts. Though Russian Formalism
as a school was eclipsed with the rise of Stalin and the official Soviet aesthetic
of social realism, its influence was transmitted through the structuralist
analyses of figures such as Jakobson and Tzvetan Todorov to writers such
as Roland Barthes and Gerard Genette.
Shklovsky (1893–1984) became a founding member of one of the two
schools of Russian Formalism, the Society for the Study of Poetic Language,
formed in 1916. His essay “Art as Technique” (1917) introduces defamiliarization, one of the central concepts of Russian Formalism: as our normal
perceptions become habitual, they become automatic and unconscious.
According to Shklovsky, habituation can devour work, clothes, furniture,
one’s wife, and the fear of war. It is against this background of ordinary
perception in general that art assumes its significance:
art exists that one may recover the sensation of life; it exists to make one feel
things, to make the stone stony . . . The technique of art is to make objects
“unfamiliar,” to make forms difficult, to increase the difficulty and length of
perception because the process of perception is an aesthetic end in itself and
must be prolonged. Art is a way of experiencing the artfulness of an object; the
object is not important.1
Boris Eichenbaum (1886–1959)
Like Shklovsky, Eichenbaum was one of the leaders of the Russian Formalist
group known as the Society for the Study of Poetic Language, founded in
1916. His essay “The Theory of the Formal Method’ ” (1926, 1927) explains
that formalism is “characterized only by the attempt to create an independent
From Liberal Humanism to Formalism
199
science of literature which studies specifically literary material.”2 In the
context of early twentieth-century Russia, where there was much pressure
on literature to be revolutionary, Eichenbaum sees this strategy as revolutionary, as attempting to free art from serving ideological and political ends.
Eichenbaum also argued that poetry uses words differently from their
function in ordinary speech, disrupting “ordinary verbal associations”
(“TFM,” 129). The suggestion here is that poetry comprises a kind of speech
of its own, which is cumulatively developed by a tradition of poets. Also, the
Formalists adopted a new understanding of literary history which rejected the
idea of some linear, unified tradition. Rather, literary tradition involves
struggle, a destruction of old values, competition between various schools
in a given epoch, and persistence of vanquished movements alongside the
newly dominant groups. The Formalists insisted that literary evolution had
a distinctive character and that it “stood alone, quite independent of other
aspects of culture” (“TFM,” 134–135). Such a model of literary history
anticipates later theories such as those of Pound and T. S. Eliot.
Mikhail M. Bakhtin (1895–1975)
Bakhtin is perhaps best known for his radical philosophy of language, as well
as his theory of the novel, underpinned by concepts such as “dialogism,”
“polyphony,” and “carnival,” themselves resting on the more fundamental
concept of “heteroglossia.” Bakhtin’s writings were produced at a time of
momentous upheavals in Russia: the Revolution of 1917 was followed by
a civil war (1918–1921), famine, and the dark years of repressive dictatorship
under Joseph Stalin. While Bakhtin himself was not a member of the
Communist Party, his work has been regarded by some as Marxist in
orientation, seeking to provide a corrective to the abstractness of extreme
formalism.
Bakhtin’s major works as translated into English include Art and Answerability: Early Philosophical Essays (1990), Rabelais and his World (1965;
trans. 1968), Problems of Dostoevsky’s Poetics (1929; trans. 1973), The
Dialogic Imagination: Four Essays (1930s; trans. 1981), and Speech Genres
and Other Late Essays (1986). The authorship of some further publications,
such as Marxism and the Philosophy of Language (1929, 1930), which was
published under the name of V. N. Volosinov, is still in dispute.
Bakhtin’s major achievements include the formulation of an innovative
philosophy of language and “theory” of the novel. His essay “Discourse in the
Novel,” furnishes an integrated statement of both endeavors. Indeed, this text
also offers a radical critique of the history of philosophy and an innovative
explanation of the nature of subjectivity, objectivity and the very process of
understanding. Bakhtin defines the novel as a “diversity of social speech types
(sometimes even diversity of languages) and a diversity of individual voices,
200
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
artistically organized.”3 Bakhtin’s view of the novel is dependent upon his
broader view of the nature of language as “dialogic” and as comprised of
“heteroglossia.” In order to explain the concept of dialogism, we first need to
understand the latter term: “heteroglossia” refers to the circumstance that
what we usually think of as a single, unitary language is actually comprised of
a multiplicity of languages interacting with, and often ideologically competing with, one another. In Bakhtin’s terms, any given “language” is actually
stratified into several “other languages” (“heteroglossia” might be translated
as “other-languagedness”). It is this heteroglossia, says Bakhtin, which is “the
indispensable prerequisite for the novel as a genre” (DI, 263).
“Dialogism” refers to the fact that the various languages that stratify any
“single” language are in dialogue with one another; Bakhtin calls this “the
primordial dialogism of discourse,” whereby all discourse has a dialogic
orientation (DI, 275). We might illustrate this using the following example:
the language of religious discourse does not exist in a state of ideological
and linguistic “neutrality.” On the contrary, such discourse might act as
a “rejoinder” or “reply” to elements of political discourse. The political
discourse might encourage loyalty to the state and adherence to material
ambitions, whereas the religious discourse might attempt to displace those
loyalties with the pursuit of spiritual goals. Even a work of art does not come,
Minerva-like, fully formed from the brain of its author, speaking a single
monologic language: it is a response, a rejoinder, to other works, to certain
traditions, and it situates itself within a current of intersecting dialogues (DI,
274). Its relation to other works of art and to other languages (literary and
non-literary) is dialogic.
Bakhtin has a further, profounder, explanation of the concept of dialogism.
He explains that there is no direct, unmediated relation between a word and
its object: “no living word relates to its object in a singular way.” In its path
toward the object, the word encounters “the fundamental and richly varied
opposition of . . . other, alien words about the same object” (DI, 276–277).
Even before we utter the word with our own signification, it is already
invested with many layers of meaning, and our use of the word must
accommodate those other meanings and in some cases compete with them.
Our utterance will in its very nature be dialogic: it is born as one voice in
a dialogue that is already constituted; it cannot speak monologically, as the
only voice, in some register isolated from all social, historical, and ideological
contexts. The word itself becomes the site of ideological conflict: language
is not somehow neutral and transparent: it is the very medium and locus
of conflict.
In formulating this radical notion of language, Bakhtin is also effecting
a profound critique not only of linguistics and conventional stylistics but also
of the history of philosophy: all postulate a unitary language (DI, 263–64,
269). Their historical project has been deeply ideological, exalting certain
From Liberal Humanism to Formalism
201
languages over others, incorporating “barbarians and lower social strata into
a unitary language of culture,” canonizing ideological systems and directing
attention away “from language plurality to a single proto-language.” Nonetheless, insists Bakhtin, these centripetal forces are obliged to “operate in the
midst of heteroglossia” (DI, 271). Even as various attempts are being made
to undertake the project of centralization and unification, the processes of
decentralization and disunification continue (DI, 272).
Even literary language is stratified in its own ways, according to genre and
profession (DI, 288–289). The various dialects and perspectives entering
literature form “a dialogue of languages” (DI, 294). It is precisely this fact
which, for Bakhtin, marks the characteristic difference between poetry and
the novel. Most poetry is premised on the idea of a single unitary language;
poetry effectively destroys heteroglossia; it strips the word of the intentions
of others (DI, 297–298). In the novel, on the contrary, this dialogization of
language “penetrates from within the very way in which the word conceives
its object” (DI, 284). Bakhtin sees the genres of poetry and the novel as
emblematic of two broad ideological tendencies, the one centralizing and
conservative, the other dispersive and radical. The “novel” rejects any
concept of a unified self or world; it acknowledges that “the” world is
actually formed as a conversation, an endless dialogue, through a series of
competing and coexisting languages; it even proposes that “truth” is dialogic.
Hence, truth is redefined not merely as a consensus (which by now is common
in cultural theory) but as the product of verbal-ideological struggles, struggles
which mark the very nature of language itself (DI, 300).
Roman Jakobson (1896–1982)
The work of Roman Jakobson occupies a seminal place in formalism and
structuralism. Essentially a linguist, Jakobson co-founded the Moscow
Linguistic Circle in 1915. He was also involved in a second Russian Formalist
group, the Society for the Study of Poetic Language, formed in 1916. The
Formalists were in some ways precursors of structuralism: in 1926 Jakobson
founded the Prague Linguistic Circle which engaged critically with the
work of Saussure. And, fleeing from Nazi occupation, he moved to America
in 1941 where he became acquainted with Claude Levi-Strauss; in 1943 he cofounded the Linguistic Circle of New York. His ideas proved to be of greatest
impact first in France and then in America.
In his paper “Linguistics and Poetics” (1958) Jakobson argues that poetics
is an integral part of linguistics.4 He argues that, whereas most language is
concerned with the transmission of ideas, the poetic function of language
focuses on the “message” for its own sake (LL, 69). Jakobson’s essay “Two
Aspects of Language and Two Types of Aphasic Disturbances” (1956)
suggests that language has a bipolar structure, oscillating between the poles
202
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
of metaphor and metonymy. This dichotomy, he urges, “appears to be of
primal significance and consequence for all verbal behavior and for human
behavior in general” (LL, 112). The development of any discourse takes
place along two different semantic lines: one is metaphoric, where one topic
leads to another through similarity or substitution. The other is metonymic,
where one topic suggests another via contiguity (closeness in space, time, or
psychological association). In normal behavior, says Jakobson, both processes operate, but one is usually preferred, according to cultural and
personal conditions (LL, 110–111). In verbal art, also, while the two
processes richly interact, one is often given predominance; for example,
the primacy of metaphor in literary Romanticism and symbolism has been
widely acknowledged. Jakobson notes that a competition between metaphoric and metonymic devices occurs in any symbolic process, for example
in dreams. Here Jakobson anticipates Lacan’s analysis of Freud’s contrast
between condensation and displacement in terms of metaphor and
metonymy.
The New Criticism
In the Anglo-American world, formalistic tendencies were most clearly
enshrined in the New Criticism. Some of the important features of this
critical outlook originated in England during the 1920s in the work of
T. S. Eliot and Ezra Pound, as well as in a further generation of professional
critics who helped to rejuvenate the study of English literature. The most
prominent of these, associated with the new English curriculum at Cambridge
University, were I. A. Richards and his student William Empson. In his
Principles of Literary Criticism (1924) and his Science and Poetry (1926),
Richards attempted to establish a systematic basis for the study of literature.
He distinguished, most fundamentally, the emotive language of poetry from
the referential language of non-literary disciplines. In 1929 he published
a book, Practical Criticism, whose influence still endures. Using samples of
students’ often erratic attempts to analyze poetry, he aimed to foster the skills
and techniques necessary for the close reading of literature. The practice of
close reading, sensitive to the figurative language of literature, as established
by Richards later had a profound impact on the New Critics who facilitated
its academic institutionalization. While William Empson himself was not
a New Critic, he produced a book, Seven Types of Ambiguity (1930), which
had an impact on the New Criticism in virtue of its close reading of literary
texts and its stress on ambiguity as an essential characteristic of poetry.
Richards’ Principles of Literary Criticism advanced literary-critical notions
such as irony, tension, and balance, as well as distinguishing between poetic
and other uses of language.
From Liberal Humanism to Formalism
203
Across the Atlantic, New Critical practices were also being pioneered by
American critics, known as the Fugitives and the Southern Agrarians who
promoted the values of the Old South in reaction against the alleged
dehumanization of science and technology in the industrial North. Notable
among these pioneers were John Crowe Ransom and Allen Tate, who
developed some of the ideas of Eliot and Richards. Ransom edited the poetry
magazine the Fugitive from 1922 to 1925 with a group of writers including
Tate, Robert Penn Warren, and Donald Davidson. Other journals associated
with the New Criticism included the Southern Review, edited by Penn Warren
and Cleanth Brooks (1935–1942), the Kenyon Review, run by Ransom
(1938–1959), and the still extant Sewanee Review. During the 1940s, the
New Criticism became institutionalized as the mainstream approach in
academia and its influence, while pervasively undermined since the 1950s,
still persists. Some of the central documents of New Criticism were written by
relatively late adherents: W. K. Wimsatt and Monroe Beardsley’s essays “The
Intentional Fallacy” (1946) and “The Affective Fallacy” (1949); Austin
Warren’s The Theory of Literature (1949); and W. K. Wimsatt’s The Verbal
Icon (1954). It is worth noting also the enormous influence of E. D. Hirsch’s
book Validity in Interpretation (1967), which equated a text’s meaning with
its author’s intention.
John Crowe Ransom (1888–1974)
The seminal manifestos of the New Criticism, however, had been proclaimed
earlier by Ransom, who published a series of essays entitled The New
Criticism (1941) and an influential essay, “Criticism, Inc.,” published in The
World’s Body (1938). This essay succinctly expresses a core of New Critical
principles underlying the practice of most “New Critics,” whose views often
differed in other respects. As Ransom acknowledges, his essay is motivated by
the desire to make literary criticism “more scientific, or precise and systematic”; it must become a “serious business.”5 He urges that the emphasis of
criticism must move from historical scholarship to aesthetic appreciation and
understanding.
In short, Ransom’s position is that the critic must study literature, not
about literature. Hence criticism should exclude: (1) personal impressions,
because the critical activity should “cite the nature of the object rather than its
effects upon the subject”(WB, 342); (2) synopsis and paraphrase, since the
plot or story is an abstraction from the real content of the text; (3) historical
studies, which might include literary backgrounds, biography, literary
sources, and analogues; (4) linguistic studies, which include identifying
allusions and meanings of words; (5) moral content, since this is not the
whole content of the text; (6) “Any other special studies which deal with some
abstract or prose content taken out of the work” (WB, 343–345). Ransom
204
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
demands that criticism, whose proper province includes technical studies
of poetry, metrics, tropes, and fictiveness, should “receive its own charter of
rights and function independently” (WB, 346). Finally, Ransom insists on the
ontological uniqueness of poetry, as distinct from prose. “The critic should,”
he urges, “regard the poem as nothing short of a desperate ontological or
metaphysical manoeuvre,” which cannot be reduced to prose (WB,
347–349). All in all, he argues that literature and literary criticism should
enjoy autonomy both ontologically and institutionally. His arguments have
often been abbreviated into a characterization of New Criticism as focusing
on “the text itself” or “the words on the page.”
William K. Wimsatt, Jr. (1907–1975) and Monroe C. Beardsley
(1915–1985)
The critic Wimsatt and the philosopher Beardsley produced two influential
and controversial papers that propounded central positions of New Criticism, “The Intentional Fallacy” (1946) and “The Affective Fallacy” (1949).
In the first of these, they refuse to accept the notion of design or intention as
a standard of literary-critical interpretation.6 Their central argument runs as
follows:
If the poet succeeded in doing it, then the poem itself shows what he was trying to
do. And if the poet did not succeed, then the poem is not adequate evidence, and
the critic must go outside the poem – for evidence of an intention that did not
become effective in the poem.
They repeat the American poet Archibald MacLeish’s statement that a “poem
should not mean but be.” Wimsatt and Beardsley explain this statement as
follows: “A poem . . . simply is, in the sense that we have no excuse for
inquiring what part is intended or meant. . . . In this respect poetry differs from
practical messages, which are successful if and only if we correctly infer the
intention” (VI, 4–5). This is an effective statement of the New Critical
position that the poem is an autonomous verbal structure which has its end
in itself, which has no purpose beyond its own existence as an aesthetic object.
It is not answerable to criteria of truth, accuracy of representation or
imitation, or morality (VI, 5).
Wimsatt and Beardsley’s later essay “The Affective Fallacy” (1949) is
motivated by the same presupposition, namely that literature or poetry is an
autonomous object, independent not only of author psychology, biography,
and history but also of the reader or audience that consumes it. The word
“affection” is used by philosophers to refer to emotion, mental state, or
disposition. Hence, the “affective fallacy” occurs, according to Wimsatt and
Beardsley, when we attempt to explicate or interpret a poem through recourse
From Liberal Humanism to Formalism
205
to the emotions or mental state produced in the reader or hearer. Just as
the intentional fallacy “is a confusion between the poem and its origins,” so
the affective fallacy “is a confusion between the poem and its results . . . The
outcome of either Fallacy, the Intentional or the Affective, is that the poem
itself, as an object of specifically critical judgment, tends to disappear.”7
Notes
1. Victor Shklovsky, “Art as Technique,” in Russian Formalist Criticism: Four
Essays, trans. Lee T. Lemon and Marion J. Reis (Lincoln: University of Nebraska
Press, 1965), pp. 5, 11–12.
2. Boris Eichenbaum, “The Theory of the Formal Method,’ ” in Russian Formalist
Criticism, trans. Lemon and Reis, p. 103. Hereafter cited as “TFM.”
3. M. M. Bakhtin, The Dialogic Imagination: Four Essays, ed. Michael Holquist,
trans. Caryl Emerson and Michael Holquist (Austin: University of Texas Press,
1981), p. 262. Hereafter cited as DI.
4. “Linguistics and Poetics,” in Roman Jakobson, Language in Literature, ed.
Krystyna Pomorska and Stephen Rudy (Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard
University Press, 1987), p. 63. Hereafter cited as LL.
5. John Crowe Ransom, The World’s Body (Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University
Press, 1968), p. 329. Hereafter cited as WB.
6. W. K. Wimsatt, Jr. and Monroe C. Beardsley, “The Intentional Fallacy,” in W. K.
Wimsatt, Jr., The Verbal Icon (Lexington: University of Kentucky Press, 1967),
p. 4. Hereafter cited as VI.
7. W. K. Wimsatt, Jr. and Monroe C. Beardsley, “The Affective Fallacy,” in VI, p. 21.
Chapter 14
Socially Conscious Criticism
of the Earlier Twentieth Century
F. R. Leavis
With the Great Depression of the 1930s and the rise of fascism, literature and
criticism in both Europe and America took a turn away from formalism
toward a more socially conscious mode, as in socialist and Marxist criticism,
and in the work of many poets. A central figure in English literary criticism,
associated with the new English at Cambridge, was F. R. Leavis (1895–1978),
who might broadly be placed in the moralistic and humanistic tradition of
Matthew Arnold. Leavis edited the journal Scrutiny from 1932 to 1953. His
major works, New Bearings in English Poetry (1932), Revaluation (1936),
and The Great Tradition (1948), demoted Victorian and Georgian verse and
sought to increase general appreciation of Eliot, Yeats, and Pound; he argued
that the main stream of English poetry flowed through Donne, Pope, Johnson,
and Eliot; and he traced the main tradition of fiction from Jane Austen,
George Eliot, Henry James, and Joseph Conrad.
Leavis shared with Eliot and the New Critics the idea that literary criticism
should be a separate and serious discipline. He insisted that we cannot go to
literature in an “external” manner, treating it merely as a social document:
“literature will yield to the sociologist, or anyone else, what it has to give
only if it is approached as literature.”1 What separated him from the
New Critics, however, was an equally forceful counter-insistence that
literary criticism must go well beyond looking at “the words on the page”:
the study of literature, he said, is “an intimate study of the complexities,
potentialities, and essential conditions of human nature.” In his essay
“Sociology and Literature” he affirmed that “a real literary interest is an
interest in man, society and civilization, and its boundaries cannot be drawn”
(CP, 184, 200).
Literary Criticism from Plato to the Present: An Introduction
© 2011 M. A. R. Habib. ISBN: 978-1-405-16034-6
M. A. R. Habib
Socially Conscious Criticism
207
Marxist and Left-Wing Criticism
During the 1930s Marxism became a significant political force. Socially
conscious criticism had a long heritage in America, going back to figures such
as Whitman, Howells, and Emerson and running through the work of writers
noted above such as John Macy, Van Wyck Brooks, and Vernon L. Parrington. Notable Marxist critics of the 1920s and 1930s included Floyd Dell, Max
Eastman, V. F. Calverton, Philip Rahv, and Granville Hicks. Calverton and
Hicks were perhaps the most prominent of the Marxist critics. In The
Liberation of American Literature (1932) Calverton interprets the tradition
of American literature through Marxist categories of class and economic
infrastructure. Granville Hicks became a communist during the depression
and his The Great Tradition (1933) assesses American writers in terms of
their social and political awareness. This period saw the growth of a number
of radical journals as well as the voicing of revolutionary views by nonMarxist critics such as Kenneth Burke and Edmund Wilson. The latter’s
most influential work, Axel’s Castle (1931), traced the development of
modern symbolist literature, identifying in this broad movement a
“revolution of the word.”
In Germany, a critique of modern capitalist culture was formulated by the
Frankfurt School of Critical Theory, whose major figures included Theodor
Adorno (1903–1969), Max Horkheimer (1895–1973), Herbert Marcuse,
and Walter Benjamin. Some of these thinkers drew on Hegel, Marx, and
Freud in attempting to revive the “negative dialectics” or negative, revolutionary potential of Hegelian Marxist thought. They insisted, following
Hegel, that consciousness in all of its cultural modes is active in creating
the world. In general, these theorists saw modern mass culture as regimented
and reduced to a commercial dimension; and they saw art as embodying a
unique critical distance from this social and political world. Walter Benjamin
argued in his “The Work of Art in the Age of Mechanical Reproduction” that
modern technology has transformed the work of art, stripping it of the “aura”
of uniqueness it possessed in earlier eras. Modern works are reproduced for
mass consumption, and are effectively copies which relate to no original form.
However, this new status of art, thought Benjamin, also gave it a revived
political and subversive potential. These thinkers had a large impact on the
New Left and the radical movements of the 1960s.
The tradition of socialist criticism in Britain went back to William Morris,
who first applied Marxist perspectives of labor and alienation to
artistic production. In 1884 the Fabian Society was formed with the aim of
substituting for Marxist revolutionary action a Fabian policy of gradually
introducing socialism through influencing government policy and raising
awareness of economic and class inequalities. The dramatist and critic
208
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
George Bernard Shaw (1856–1950) was a leader of this society and produced
one of its first pamphlets, A Manifesto (1884). Shaw edited Fabian Essays in
Socialism (1899), and advocated women’s rights, economic equality, and the
abolition of private property. George Orwell (1903–1950) in his later career
saw himself as a political writer and a democratic socialist, who, however,
became disillusioned with communism, as expressed in his political satire
Animal Farm (1945).
A group of Marxist thinkers was centered around The Left Review
(1934–1938). The poets W. H. Auden, Stephen Spender, and C. Day Lewis
at various times espoused and propagated left-wing views. The most significant Marxist theorist of this generation was Christopher Caudwell, whose
Illusion and Reality: A Study of the Sources of Poetry (1937) offered
a Marxist analysis, correlating the development of English poetry with
economic phases such as primitive accumulation, the Industrial Revolution,
and the decline of capitalism.
The Fundamental Principles of Marxism
It may be useful to provide here a brief account of the principles of Marxist
thought and literary criticism. The tradition of Marxism has provided a
powerful and sustained critique of capitalist institutions and ethics. Its
founder, Karl Heinrich Marx (1818–1883), was a German political, economic, and philosophical theorist and revolutionist. The influence of Marx’s
ideas on modern world history has been vast. Until the collapse in 1991 of the
communist systems of the USSR and Eastern Europe, one-third of the world’s
population had been living under political administrations claiming descent
from Marx’s ideas. His impact on the world of thought has been equally
extensive, embracing sociology, philosophy, economics, and cultural theory.
Marxism has also generated a rich tradition of literary and cultural criticism.
Many branches of modern criticism – including historicism, feminism,
deconstruction, postcolonial and cultural criticism – are indebted to the
insights of Marxism, which often originated in the philosophy of Hegel. What
distinguishes Marxism is that it is not only a political, economic, and social
theory but also a form of practice in all of these domains.
Marx attempted to understand the structural causes behind what he saw as
a system of capitalist exploitation, and to offer solutions in the spheres of
economics and politics. As with all socialists, Marx’s main objection to
capitalism was that one particular class owned the means of economic
production: “The bourgeoisie . . . has centralized means of production,
and has concentrated property in a few hands.” The correlative of this is
the oppression and exploitation of the working classes: “In proportion as
the bourgeosie, i.e., capital, is developed, in the same proportion is the
Socially Conscious Criticism
209
proletariat, the modern working class, developed; a class of laborers, who live
only so long as they find work, and who find work only so long as their labor
increases capital. These laborers, who must sell themselves piecemeal, are a
commodity.” Marx’s third objection is the imperialistic nature of the bourgeois enterprise: in order to perpetuate itself, capitalism must spread its
tentacles all over the world: “The bourgeoisie cannot exist without constantly
revolutionizing the instruments of production . . . The need of a constantly
expanding market . . . chases the bourgeoisie over the whole surface of the
globe.” Marx explains that the bourgeoisie must necessarily give a cosmopolitan character to production and consumption in every country; that raw
material is drawn from the remotest zones; that demand for new products
ever increases; that the bourgeoisie “compels all nations, on pain of extinction, to adopt the bourgeois mode of production.” In short, the bourgeoisie
“creates a world after its own image.” Finally, capitalism reduces all human
relationships to a “cash” nexus, self-interest, and egotistical calculation.2
Influenced by Hegel but in contrast with his scheme of history as motivated
by a divine or absolute spirit, Marx and Engels developed what they called a
“materialist conception of history,” as driven by class struggle, from the
ancient slave mode of production through feudalism and capitalism to
communism where classes and private property are abolished. In this conception, consciousness itself is viewed as a “social product.” The realms
of ideology, politics, law, morality, religion, and art are not independent
but are an efflux of a people’s material behavior: “Life is not determined
by consciousness, but consciousness by life.”3 Hence an ideological superstructure arises out of a given economic “base” or infrastructure.
Also important is Marx’s concept of ideology. He states that the class which
is the ruling material force in society is also the ruling intellectual force.
Having at its disposal the means of production, it is empowered to disseminate its ideas in the realms of law, morality, religion, and art, as possessing
universal verity. Thus, the dominant ideas of the feudal aristocracy such as
honor and loyalty were replaced after bourgeois ascendancy by ideas of
freedom and equality, whose infrastructure is class economic imperatives
(GI, 64–65). According to Marx’s notion of ideology, the ruling class
represents its own interests as the interests of the people as a whole. The
modern state, as Marx says, “is but a committee for managing the common
affairs of the whole bourgeoisie” (MCP, 45–47).
Marx acknowledged that capitalist society was an unprecedented historical advance over centuries of benighted feudalism. The bourgeois emphasis
on reason, practicality, its technological enterprise in mastering the world, its
ideals of rational law and justice, individual freedom and democracy were all
hailed by Marx as historical progress. His point was not that communism
would somehow displace capitalism in its entirety but that it would realize
these ideals. Sadly, most of what has passed for “communism” has had but
210
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
remote connections with the doctrines of Marx, Engels, or their followers.
As an internal critique of the tendencies of capitalism and its crises, Marxism
is uniquely coherent and incisive. The influence of Marxism has been
fundamental in challenging the claims of the law to be eternal, of the
bourgeoisie to represent the interests of the entire nation, of individuality
and freedom to be universal. It has also been important in the analysis of
women’s oppression as structurally integral to capitalism. And its insights
into language as a social practice with a material dimension, its awareness
that truth is an interpretation based on certain kinds of consensus, its view of
the world as created through human physical, intellectual, and ideological
labor, its acknowledgment of the dialectical nature of all thinking, and its
insistence that analysis of all phenomena must be informed by historical
context were articulated long before such ideas made their way into modern
literary theory.
Marxist Literary Criticism: A Historical Overview
Marx and Engels produced no systematic theory of literature or art. But
Marxist aesthetics has been characterized by a persistent core of predispositions about literature and art deriving from Marx and Engels themselves.
These predispositions include:
(1) The rejection, following Hegel, of the notion of “identity” and a consequent denial of the view that any object, including literature, can
somehow exist independently. The aesthetic corollary of this is that
literature can only be understood in the fullness of its relations with
ideology, class, and economic substructure.
(2) The view that the so-called “objective” world is actually a progressive
construction out of collective human subjectivity.
(3) The understanding of art itself as a commodity, sharing with other
commodities an entry into material aspects of production.
(4) A focus on the connections between class struggle as the inner dynamic of
history and literature as the ideologically refracted site of such struggle.
This has sometimes gone hand in hand with prescriptions for literature as
an ideological ancillary to the aims and results of political revolution.
(5) An insistence that language is not a self-enclosed system of relations but
must be understood as social practice, as deeply rooted in material
conditions as any other practice (GI, 51).
To these predispositions could be added, for example, Engels’ comments on
“typicality,” recommending that art should express what is typical about a
class or a peculiar intersection of ideological circumstances. We might also
Socially Conscious Criticism
211
include the problem raised by Engels’ granting a “relative autonomy” to art,
and his acknowledgment that art and culture are determined only in the “last
instance” by economic relations.
After Marx’s death in 1883, Europe witnessed a widespread nascence of
socialist political parties, together with the impact of Marxism in sociology,
anthropology, history, and political science. The first generation of Marxist
intellectuals included the Italian Antonio Labriola (1843–1904), who viewed
the connection between economic and literary-cultural spheres as highly
mediated; and George Plekhanov (1856–1918), the “father of Russian
Marxism,” who argued in his Art and Social Life (1912) that the idea
of art for art’s sake arises when the individual finds himself in hopeless
disaccord with his society; when there exists a concrete possibility of social
change, art tends to be more utilitarian, promoting the process of political
transformation.
Vladimir Ilyich Lenin (1870–1924) occupied a central role not only in the
Russian Revolution of 1917 but also in the unfolding of Marxist aesthetics.
His controversial piece “Party Organization and Party Literature” (1905)
was later misleadingly claimed to authorize “socialist realism,” adopted in
1934 as the official party aesthetic. But he is not here prescribing partisanship
(partinost) for all literature, only literature which claims to be party literature.
He grants that there should be complete freedom of speech and the press.
Hence the early debates on art during and after the revolutionary period in
Russia focused on questions such as the degree of party control over the arts,
the stance toward the bourgeois cultural legacy, and the imperative to clarify
the connections between the political and the aesthetic. A related question
was the possibility of creating a proletarian or working-class culture. The
other major protagonist in the Russian Revolution, Leon Trotsky
(1879–1940), played a crucial role in these debates. His Literature and
Revolution (1923) stressed that the “domain of art is not one in which the
Party is called upon to command. It can and must protect and help it, but can
only lead it indirectly.”4 Trotsky also urges that the party should give “its
confidence” to what he calls “literary fellow-travelers,” those non-party
writers sympathetic to the revolution (LR, 226). In a 1938 manifesto,
Towards a Free Revolutionary Art, drawn up in collaboration with Andre
Breton, Trotsky urges a “complete freedom for art” while acknowledging
that all true art is revolutionary in nature. Throughout his comments on
aesthetics, Trotsky seems to travel a fine line between granting art a certain
autonomy and viewing it as serving, in a highly mediated fashion, an
important social function.
The Communist Party, initially more flexible, officially adopted the
aesthetic of socialist realism in 1934. This aesthetic was defined by
A. A. Zhdanov as the depiction of “reality in its revolutionary development.
The truthfulness . . . of the artistic image must be linked with the task of
212
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
ideological transformation.”5 Socialist realism received its most articulate
theoretical expression in the work of the Hungarian philosopher Gy€
orgy
acs (1885–1971), the foremost Marxist aesthetician of modern
Luk
acs’ notion of realism collided with that of Bertolt Brecht
times. Luk
acs, modern capitalist society is riven by
(1898–1956). According to Luk
contradictions, by chasms between universal and particular, intelligible and
sensible, part and whole. The realist artist expresses a vision of the possible
totality embracing these contradictions, a totality achieved by embodying
what is “typical” about various historical stages. Brecht, in his notebooks,
also equates realism with the ability to capture the “typical” or “historically
significant.” Brecht holds that realist art battles false views of reality,
thereby facilitating correct views.6 Perhaps the conflict between the two
acs’ (arguably Stalinist-inspired) aversion to modthinkers is rooted in Luk
ernist and experimental art on the grounds that the ontological image of
humanity it portrayed was fragmented, decadent, and politically impotent. In
contrast, Brecht’s experimentalism was crucial to his attempts to combine
theory and practice in a Marxist aesthetic. Contrasting dramatic theater
(which follows Aristotle’s guidelines) with his own “epic” theater, Brecht
avers that the audience’s capacity for action must be roused and, far from
undergoing catharsis, it must be forced to take decisions, partly by its
standard expectations being disappointed (a procedure Brecht called “the
alienation effect”).
Mention should also be made of the notion of “hegemony,” formulated by
the Italian Marxist Antonio Gramsci (1891–1937). The revolutionary potential of the proletariat could only be realized, argued Gramsci, through
political and intellectual hegemony: any economic and political transformation must be facilitated by the working class, through its own “organic”
intellectuals, projecting its own intellectual and ideological vision, thereby
achieving an alternative hegemony to the prevailing bourgeois hegemony.
Gramsci thus affirms the dialectical connection between economic and
superstructural spheres, stressing the transformative role of human agency
rather than relying on the “inevitability” of economic determinism.
The foregoing represents the development of Marxist aesthetics during the
earlier half of the twentieth century. A subsequent generation of Marxist
critics such as Fredric Jameson and Terry Eagleton will be considered in a later
chapter.
Early Feminist Criticism: Simone de Beauvoir
and Virginia Woolf
Apart from Marxism, the other major modern critical outlook grounded in
political practice is feminism, in all of its many currents. Feminism has
Socially Conscious Criticism
213
antecedents going all the way back to ancient Greece, in the work of Sappho
and arguably in Aristophanes’ play Lysistrata, which depicts women taking
over the treasury in the Acropolis, a female chorus as physically and
intellectually superior to the male chorus, and the use of sexuality as a
weapon in an endeavor to end the distinctly masculine project of the
Peloponnesian War. Feminism also surfaces in Chaucer’s Wife of Bath, who
blatantly values “experience” over authority and was more than a match for
each of her five husbands. In the Middle Ages, Christine de Pisan had the
courage to enter into a debate with the predominant male critics of her day.
During the Renaissance a number of women poets such as Catherine
Des Roches emerged in France and England. In the seventeenth century,
poets such as Aphra Behn and Anne Bradstreet were pioneers in gaining
access to the literary profession. After the French Revolution, Mary Wollstonecraft argued that the ideals of the Revolution and Enlightenment
should be extended to women, primarily through access to education. And
the nineteenth century witnessed a flowering of numerous major female
literary figures in both Europe and America, ranging from Mme. de Sta€el,
the Bront€es, Jane Austen, George Eliot, and Elizabeth Barrett Browning
to Margaret Fuller and Emily Dickinson. Modernist female writers
included Hilda Doolittle, Gertrude Stein, Katherine Mansfield, and
Virginia Woolf.
For most of this long history women were not only deprived of education
and financial independence, but had to struggle against a male ideology
condemning them to virtual silence and obedience, as well as a male literary
establishment that poured scorn on their literary endeavors. Indeed, the
depiction of women in male literature – as angels, goddesses, whores,
obedient wives, and mother figures – was an integral means of perpetuating
these ideologies of gender. It was only with women’s struggles in the twentieth
century for political rights that feminist criticism arose in any systematic way.
Since the early twentieth century, feminist criticism has grown to encompass a
vast series of concerns: a rewriting of literary history so as to include the
contributions of women; the tracing of a female literary tradition; theories of
sexuality and sexual difference, drawing on psychoanalysis, Marxism, and
the social sciences; the representation of women in male literature; the role of
gender in both literary creation and literary criticism (as studied in so-called
“gynocriticism”); and the connection between gender and various aspects of
literary form, such as genre and meter. Above all, feminist critics have
displayed a persistent concern with both experience and language: is there
a specifically female experience that has been communicated by women
writers? And how do women confront the task of being historically coerced
into using a language dominated by male concepts and values? Some feminists
have urged the need for a female language, while others have advocated
appropriating and modifying the inherited language of the male oppressor.
214
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
The significance of language rests ultimately on its expression of male ways
of thinking that go all the way back to Aristotle: the laws of logic, beginning
with the law of identity, as well as the Aristotelian categories divide up the
world into strictly demarcated entities. These binary oppositions, as many
modern theorists have argued, are coercive: according to Aristotle’s laws,
either one is a man or one is a woman, either black or white, either master or
slave. Feminists have often rejected these divisive ways of viewing the world,
stressing instead the various shades between female and male, between black
and white, and indeed urging a vision of unity rather than opposition. In this
process, such categories are recognized to be founded on no essence or natural
distinctions, but are viewed as cultural and ideological constructions and
performances. Hence, another fundamental feminist concern has been the
rejection of “theory” as such, since in its very nature it houses these masculine
presuppositions.
Indeed, one of the invaluable accomplishments of feminism has been
utterly to reject the notions of objectivity and neutrality; feminists have
pioneered a new honesty in acknowledging that they write from subjective
positions informed by specific circumstances. This position rests largely on
feminists’ acknowledgment that thought is not somehow a disembodied and
abstract process, but is intimately governed by the nature and situation of the
body in place and time. The “body” has become a powerful metaphor of such
specificity and concreteness, which rejects the male Cartesian tradition that
thinking can somehow occur on a plane of disembodied universality. The
body that I inhabit will shape my thinking at the profoundest levels: if my
body happened to be born into a rich family with political ties, my political,
religious, and social affiliations will inevitably reflect this. Whether my body
is male or female will initially determine my thought and experience at a far
deeper level than which books I read. Notwithstanding these insights of
feminism, the days are still not past in which high-school students are
forbidden to use the word “I” in their compositions, effectively perpetuating
the pretense and self-delusion of objectivity.
It should be remembered that feminism has been broadly international in
scope and its disposition is dictated by many local as well as general factors.
For example, writers from Arab traditions such as Fatima Mernissi and
Leila Ahmed have attempted to articulate a feminist vision distinctly marked
by their specific cultural concerns; the same is true of African-American
feminists such as Alice Walker and feminists of Asian heritage such as
Gayatri Spivak. Feminism as it developed in French, American, and British
traditions will be considered in a later chapter. The section below will briefly
consider two of the landmark works of the early twentieth century, whose
influence was disseminated through all three of these traditions, Virginia
Woolf’s A Room of One’s Own (1929) and Simone de Beauvoir’s The Second
Sex (1949).
Socially Conscious Criticism
215
Virginia Woolf (1882–1941)
Virginia Woolf was in many ways a pioneer of feminist literary criticism,
raising issues – such as the social and economic context of women’s writing,
the gendered nature of language, the need to go back through literary history
and establish a female literary tradition, and the societal construction of
gender – that remain of central importance to feminist studies. Woolf’s most
significant statements impinging on feminism are contained in two lectures
presented at women’s colleges at Cambridge University in 1928, subsequently
published as A Room of One’s Own (1929), and in Three Guineas (1938), an
important statement concerning women’s alienation from the related ethics
of war and patriarchy. Woolf is also known as one of the foremost modernist
writers of the English-speaking world. The most famous of her many novels
include Mrs. Dalloway (1925), To the Lighthouse (1927), and Orlando
(1928).
As the daughter of the Victorian agnostic philosopher Leslie Stephen,
Woolf had access to his substantial library, and it was here that she received
her education. After her parents’ deaths, she settled, with her brothers and
sisters, in Bloomsbury, a fashionable area of London which later gave its
name to the intellectual circle in which Virginia and her sister Vanessa moved.
The “Bloomsbury Group” included John Maynard Keynes, Lytton Strachey,
Clive Bell, and the writer Leonard Woolf, whom Virginia was to marry in
1912. This group was unconventional in its outlooks and often in its
sexuality. Woolf’s own views of femininity and gender relations must have
been rooted partly in her own sexuality; she was engaged in a relationship
with the writer Vita Sackville-West, on whom Woolf’s novel Orlando was
based. Woolf suffered from nervous breakdowns and was acutely and
sometimes debilitatingly conscious of her status as a female writer in an
intellectual milieu dominated by males and masculine values. In 1941 she
walked into a river, her pockets loaded with stones, and drowned herself,
suffering the same fate as her imaginary character Shakespeare’s sister who
was driven to suicide on account of the overwhelming forces and institutions
thwarting her female genius.
Woolf’s literary criticism, like her fiction, can be approached from at least
two perspectives – those of modernism and feminism. Perhaps the most
fundamental point on which these overlap is their common rejection of the
mainstream legacy of the bourgeois Enlightenment. Woolf reacted against the
Enlightenment presumption that reason could master the world and reduce it
to total intelligibility. At various points in her fiction and essays, Woolf
expresses what has come to be seen as a characteristically feminist distrust of
theorizing, which is seen as imbued with centuries of male values and
strategies. Like most modernists, Woolf questioned the idea of an external
reality that somehow existed independently of our minds. And her emphasis
216
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
on time and change, inspired by Bergson and Proust, is profoundly symptomatic of a modernist perspective.
In A Room of One’s Own Woolf raised a number of issues that would
remain of central concern to feminists. The “room” of the book’s title is a
skillfully used metaphor around which the entire text is woven: Woolf’s
central claim is that “a woman must have money and a room of her own if she
is to write fiction.”7 The most obvious meaning of this claim is that women
need financial and psychological independence in order to exercise their
creative potential. But Woolf’s claim also situates literature within a material
(economic, social, political) context. She compares fiction to a spider’s web:
this web is not spun in midair (literature does not arise in a vacuum) but is
“attached to life at all four corners.” Indeed, it is “attached to grossly material
things” (Room, 43–44). Hence, intellectual freedom, the “power to think for
oneself,” rests on financial freedom (Room, 106). Until the beginning of the
nineteenth century, Woolf notes, women were debarred from any “separate
lodging” which might shelter them “from the claims and tyrannies of their
families” (Room, 52).
But the “room” also represents psychological space. Woolf relates her
famous anecdote of “Shakespeare’s sister” Judith, who, being “wonderfully
gifted,” attempts to seek her fortune in the theater like her brother. The
opposition to her endeavors ranges from her father’s violent anger to the
laughter and exploitation of men in the theater company; such is her
frustration and fragility that she kills herself (Room, 46–48). The room may
also signify resistance to the appropriation of language, history, and tradition
by men. Woolf notes that “women have burnt like beacons in all the works of
all the poets” but in reality they were “locked up, beaten and flung about the
room” (Room, 43). An important task for women, as they look back through
history, is to seek out the hitherto neglected and blurred outlines of a female
literary tradition. “Poetry,” affirms Woolf, “ought to have a mother as well as
a father” (Room, 103). In this broader sense, the “room” might encompass a
female tradition and female perspectives toward history.
A room of one’s own might also represent the ideal of a female language or
at least of appropriating language for female use. The “male” language
women have inherited cannot express their female experience; this language,
habituated to showing women exclusively in their relationship to men, could
not express, for example, the liking of one woman for another (Room, 82).
Woolf notes how woman has been at the “centre of some different order and
system of life,” contrasting sharply with the world inhabited by men (Room,
86). Not only must women craft a sentence, a language that will grasp the
rhythms of their own experience, but also a literary form that is “adapted to
the body” (Room, 78). Woolf’s general point – that language and thought are
ultimately and irreversibly grounded in the rhythms of the body, of one’s
particular situation in place and time – is one that has been richly pursued by a
Socially Conscious Criticism
217
variety of feminisms. Importantly, however, the mental state that Woolf sees
as most creative is what she calls “unity of the mind,” a unity in which the sexes
are not viewed as distinct (Room, 97). She characterizes such “androgyny”
(a Greek term, taken over from Coleridge and, ultimately, from Plato) as
follows: “in each of us two powers preside, one male, one female . . . The
normal and comfortable state of being is that when the two live in harmony
together, spiritually co-operating . . . Coleridge perhaps meant this when he
said that a great mind is androgynous” (Room, 98).
Simone de Beauvoir (1908–1986)
Another classic feminist statement, Le Deuxieme Sexe (1949; translated as
The Second Sex, 1952), was produced by Simone de Beauvoir, a leading
intellectual of her time, whose existentialist vision was forged partly in her
relationship, as companion and colleague, with the existentialist philosopher
Jean-Paul Sartre. De Beauvoir’s text laid the foundations for much of the
feminist theory and political activism that emerged during the 1960s in
Western Europe and America. Since then, its impact, if anything, has
broadened and deepened. The book’s central argument is that, throughout
history, woman has always occupied a secondary role in relation to man,
being relegated to the position of the “other,” i.e., that which is adjectival
upon the substantial subjectivity and existential activity of man. Whereas
man has been enabled to transcend and control his environment, always
furthering the domain of his physical and intellectual conquests, woman has
remained imprisoned within “immanence,” remaining a slave within the
circle of duties imposed by her maternal and reproductive functions. In
highlighting this subordination, the book explains in characteristic existentialist fashion how the so-called “essence” of woman was in fact created – at
many levels, economic, political, religious – by historical developments
representing the interests of men.
In her renowned introduction to The Second Sex, de Beauvoir points out
the fundamental asymmetry of the terms “masculine” and “feminine.”
Masculinity is considered to be the “absolute human type,” the norm or
standard of humanity. A man does not typically preface his opinions with the
statement “I am a man,” whereas a woman’s views are often held to be
grounded in her femininity rather than in any objective perception of things.
Woman “has ovaries, a uterus; these peculiarities imprison her in her
subjectivity, circumscribe her within the limits of her own nature.”8
De Beauvoir quotes Aristotle as saying that the “female is a female by virtue
of a certain lack of qualities,” and St. Thomas as stating that the female nature
is “afflicted with a natural defectiveness” (SS, xvi). Summarizing these long
traditions of thought, de Beauvoir states: “Thus humanity is male and man
defines woman not in herself but as relative to him; she is not regarded as an
218
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
autonomous being . . . she is the incidental, the inessential as opposed to the
essential. He is the Subject, he is the Absolute – she is the Other” (SS, xvi).
Indeed, a long line of thinkers, stretching from Plato and Aristotle through
Augustine and Aquinas to modern bourgeois philosophers, has insisted on
stabilizing woman as an object, on dooming her to immanence, to a life of
subjection to given conditions, on barring her from property rights, education, and the professions (SS, xviii). Men have also consistently promoted
certain myths about women – goddess, whore, mother, the mysterious
“eternal feminine” – all of which have substituted a rigid and unchangeable
idea of woman for actual women (SS, 239).
According to de Beauvoir, two essential factors paved the way for women’s
prospective equality: one was her ability (conferred by technology, which
abrogated any innate male advantages of strength) to share in productive
labor; and the second was her recently acquired freedom from the slavery of
reproduction through contraception, adopted by many of the middle and then
the working classes from the eighteenth century onward (SS, 109). In the
conclusion to her book, de Beauvoir argues that woman’s situation will be
transformed primarily by a change in her economic condition; but this change
must also generate moral, social, cultural, and psychological transformations. Eventually, both man and woman will exist both for self and for the
other: “mutually recognizing each other as subject, each will yet remain for
the other an other.” In this recognition, in this reciprocity, will “the slavery of
half of humanity” be abolished (SS, 688).
Notes
1. F. R. Leavis, The Common Pursuit (1952; rpt. Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1966),
p. 193. Hereafter cited as CP.
2. Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, Manifesto of the Communist Party (1952; rpt.
Moscow: Progress Publishers, 1973), pp. 11–16. Hereafter cited as MCP.
3. Karl Marx, The German Ideology: Part One, ed. C. J. Arthur (London: Lawrence
and Wishart, 1982), pp. 47–51. Hereafter cited as GI.
4. Leon Trotsky, Literature and Revolution (New York: Russell and Russell, 1957),
p. 218. Hereafter cited as LR.
5. A. A. Zhdanov, Essays on Literature, Philosophy, and Music (New York: International Publishers, 1950), p. 15.
6. Berel Lang and Forrest Williams, eds., Marxism and Art: Writings in Aesthetics and
Criticism (New York: McKay, 1972), pp. 226–227.
7. Virginia Woolf, A Room of One’s Own (1929; rpt. San Diego, New York, London:
Harvest/Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1989), p. 4. Hereafter cited as Room.
8. Simone de Beauvoir, The Second Sex, trans. H. M. Parshley (New York: Bantam/
Alfred A. Knopf, 1961), p. xv. Hereafter cited as SS.
Chapter 15
Phenomenology, Existentialism,
Structuralism
The conclusion of World War II formalized the opposition between the
Western powers and the Soviet bloc of nations. While some literature
participated in this ideological conflict, much writing retreated in dismay
from the political sphere. This retreat from an “objective” reality reached a
climax in philosophies such as phenomenology (which parenthesized the
objective world, viewing it as a function of perception) and existentialism
(which called into question all forms of authority and belief). The flight from
reality found voice also in literary developments such as the Theater of the
Absurd, whose major proponents Samuel Beckett and Eugene Ionesco dramatized the existential absurdity, anguish, and ultimate isolation of human
existence. The Italian thinker Benedetto Croce formulated an aesthetic which
revived Hegelian idealist principles as against the tradition of bourgeois
positivism and scientism. The German existentialist philosopher Martin
Heidegger (1889–1976) increasingly saw poetry as transcending the discursive and rational limitations of philosophy. In France, the philosopher Gaston
Bachelard (1884–1962) formulated a phenomenological and surrealist account of poetry, while the existentialist Jean-Paul Sartre (1905–1980) advocated a literature of political engagement. The phenomenological emphasis
was further elaborated by Georges Poulet (1902–1991), Jean-Pierre Richard
(b. 1922), and Georges Bataille (1897–1962); it was given a linguistic
orientation in the work of Maurice Blanchot (1907–2003). It was in the
1950s that structuralism – another tendency which parenthesized the agency
of the human subject by situating it within a broad linguistic and semiological
structure – began to thrive through figures such as the anthropologist Claude
Levi-Strauss and the narratologist A. J. Greimas. Roland Barthes analyzed the
new myths of Western culture and later proclaimed the “death of the author.”
The following sections will briefly consider phenomenology as formulated by
Husserl, existentialism as expounded by Heidegger, the heterology of
Georges Bataille, and structuralism as expressed in its foundations by
Saussure and in its later phases by Barthes.
Literary Criticism from Plato to the Present: An Introduction
© 2011 M. A. R. Habib. ISBN: 978-1-405-16034-6
M. A. R. Habib
220
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
Phenomenology
Edmund Husserl (1859–1938)
One of the foremost philosophies of this period, in which much readerresponse theory had its philosophical origins, was the doctrine known as
phenomenology, whose foundations were laid by the German philosopher
Edmund Husserl. The Greek word phainomenon means “appearance.”
Hence, as a philosophical attitude, phenomenology shifts our emphasis of
study away from the “external” world of objects toward examining the ways
in which these objects appear to the human subject, and the subjective
contribution to this process of appearing. Husserl gives the name
“phenomenological reduction” to this “bracketing” of the external world,
which underlies his attempt to achieve certainty in philosophy. He argues that
we cannot be sure of the nature of the outside world; but we can have certainty
about the nature of our own perception and about the ways in which we
construct the world or the ways in which that world appears to our subjective
apparatus. This emphasis on subjectivity proved to be enormously influential;
it provided the foundations of the Geneva School of phenomenological
criticism (including figures such as Georges Poulet and Jean Starobinski)
which read literature as embodying the consciousness of its author; it exerted
a considerable impact on the reception theories of Wolfgang Iser and Hans
Robert Jauss; and it provided a starting point against which Martin
Heidegger’s thought reacted.
Existentialism
Martin Heidegger (1889–1976)
Husserl’s student Martin Heidegger proved to be the major modern exponent
of existentialism. His impact extends not only to existentialist philosophers
such as Merleau-Ponty, Sartre, and Simone de Beauvoir but also to psychiatrists such as Ludwig Binswanger and to theologians such as Rudolph
Bultmann, Paul Tillich, Martin Buber, and Karl Barth, as well to poststructuralist thinkers such as Jacques Derrida. Heiddegger’s central project in his
major work Sein und Zeit (Being and Time) (1927) consisted in a radical
reexamination of the notion of “being,” in its intrinsic relationship with time.
He developed his own hermeneutic or method of interpretation of texts; his
later work focuses increasingly on the analysis of poetry and language.
Heidegger was appointed Professor of Philosophy at the University of
Marburg in 1923; he was subsequently, in 1929, elected Husserl’s successor
to the Chair of Philosophy at Freiburg and then elected rector in 1933 under
Phenomenology, Existentialism, Structuralism
221
Hitler’s recently inaugurated regime. It was in this year that Heidegger joined
the Nationalist Socialist Party; in his inaugural address at the university, “The
Role of the University in the New Reich,” he decried freedom of speech in the
interests of national unity, and lauded the advent of a glorious new Germany.
He resigned his position as rector in early 1934. Did these events represent
merely a brief flirtation on Heidegger’s part with Nazism or an enduring
collaboration and commitment? The controversy continues.
In Being and Time Heidegger states that what characterizes dasein or
human being is its “thrownness” into the world or “facticity”: a human being
is already cast into a series of relationships and surroundings that constitute
his or her “world.”1 A second feature of being is “existentiality” or
“transcendence,” whereby a human being appropriates her world, impressing on it the unique image of her own existence and potential. In other words,
she uses the various elements of her world as given to realize herself
(BT, 235–236). Yet this positive feature is accompanied by a third characteristic, that of “fallenness”: in attempting to create herself, the human being
falls from true Being, becoming immersed instead in the distractions of dayto-day living, becoming entangled in particular beings (BT, 220). The
authentic being, the authentic self is thus buried beneath the cares and
distractions of life (BT, 166–168).
How does a human being overcome such inauthentic existence, such loss of
true being? Heidegger’s response comprises one of the classic statements of
existentialism. He suggests that there is one particular state of mind which is
unique: “dread” or angst (BT, 227–235). This refers to a sense of nothingness,
of loss, of the emptiness, when we look at life or existence in its totality, as
essentially orientated toward death. In such a mood, the human self attains
knowledge of itself as a whole, as “being-to-death.” In other words, death is
the fundamental fact that shapes our existence and the course of our life. And
the mental state of “dread” enables us to rise above our immanence, our
dispersion in the immediate and transitory affairs of the world, to reflect upon
our life as a whole, in the fullest glare of its finitude and its potential to lack
meaning (BT, 293–299). The vehicle through which we acknowledge this
responsibility to ourselves is “conscience,” which acknowledges both our
facticity, our being placed within a world, and our obligation actively to
fashion our selves in relation to this very world. Conscience makes us aware of
this guilt or obligation (BT, 313, 317–319).
In his later works, such as Introduction to Metaphysics (1953), Heidegger
aims to guide Western man away from his inauthentic immersion in worldly
aims, as well as in technology and gadgetry. In works such as “The Origin of
the Work of Art” (1935), “H€
olderlin and the Essence of Poetry” (1936), and
“Language” (1950), he appeals, in this salvific enterprise, to the power of
poetry to express the truths of authentic being. In his essay “Language,”
Heidegger’s explication of a poem entitled Ein Winterabend (“A Winter
222
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
Evening”) by Georg Trakl anticipates poststructuralist views of language as
well as much reception and reader-response theory. The language of Trakl’s
poem, says Heidegger, does not merely name familiar objects such as “snow,”
“bell,” “window,” “falling,” and “ringing.” Rather, it “calls into the word
. . . The calling calls into itself,” into a “presence sheltered in absence.”2
Inasmuch as we can “explain” this statement, we might take it to indicate that
language does not name things which are somehow already there, waiting to
be named. They achieve their very status as “things” only by being called into
the word, only by being given a status, a position, a situation, in language.
Anticipating Derrida’s notion of difference, Heidegger states that between
“world” and “thing” prevails a condition of “betweenness,” or what Heidegger calls dif-ference where the latter part of this noun may refer to the
“bearing” or “carrying” of world by thing. The intimacy of world and thing,
says Heidegger, “is present in the separation of the between; it is present in the
dif-ference. The word dif-ference is now removed from its usual and customary usage. What it now names is not a generic concept for various kinds of
differences. It exists only as this single difference” (PLT, 202). This formulation anticipates Derrida’s hypostatization of difference – his treating of it as
a primordial essence, a linguistic primum mobile, an aseitic first cause
prescinded from the very relationality into which it plunges all else. Heidegger
tells us that it is language which speaks, language which brings together world
and things in their intimacy which is a relation of absolute difference (PLT,
202). Hence, Heidegger draws attention to the world not as a thing but as an
act. It is language, language that speaks, which brings the processes of worldcomposition and thing-composition into the mutuality in which alone either
can be realized.
Heidegger proceeds to explain that the “dif-ference does not mediate after
the fact by connecting world and things through a middle added on to them.
Being in the middle, it first determines world and things in their presence, i.e.
in their being toward one another, whose unity it carries out” (PLT, 202). In
other words, dif-ference is not an external relation that connects two entities
(world and thing) that are already there: rather, dif-ference is internal to their
relation, shaping the very entities themselves. If dif-ference primordially preexists identity, if dif-ference is prior to the constitution of world and thing,
then language is the vehicle by which world and thing are called into being,
through mutual relation, from this “primordial” dif-ference into the difference which is language itself (PLT, 207). What ultimately takes place in the
speaking of language is the creation of what is human: “mortals live in the
speaking of language” (PLT, 210).
While much of what Heidegger says in these later works leans toward
mysticism, his insights into language overlap with those of many modern
theorists such as Barthes and even Lacan. Heidegger indicates that not only is
the human being “thrown” into the world (his or her particular world) but
Phenomenology, Existentialism, Structuralism
223
that the human is characterized by a thrownness into language. It is the
language that we are born into (not this or that particular language but
language in general) that speaks through us and that speaks to us. At the core
of language is dif-ference, the irreducible relation between world and thing,
the irreducible self-transcendence of all of the elements of our world in a
larger unity toward which they point; it is language which constitutes the
human; all of our attempts to understand and act upon the world and thereby
to create ourselves are mediated by the speaking of language, a speaking in
which we must enter to find our own voice. It is when we arrive at a dialogue
with language that we truly speak.
Heterology
Georges Bataille (1897–1962)
Loosely associated with the surrealist movement in the earlier twentieth
century, Bataille was a radical thinker whose works spanned philosophy,
poetry, economics, and pornography. His major works include La Part
maudite (1949; The Accursed Share) and La Litterature et le Mal (1975;
Literature and Evil). Sometimes called the “metaphysician of evil,” and
condemned as an “excremental philosopher” by the leading surrealist Andre
Breton,3 Bataille engaged in what he himself called “intellectual violence” to
produce writings which were often designed to shock and appall, advancing
his endeavor to write a “heterology,” a science of the other, of the heterogeneous, of all that had been excreted and rejected as waste matter or
undesirable by conventional thought: sacrifice, excrement, violence, blood,
incest, all of this comprising the “accursed share,” pertaining to the bodily
and material part of us that has been suppressed and subordinated. All of
these are constituents of forbidden and tabooed realms whose repudiation
and expulsion are integral to the formation of the tradition of rationalism (as
superordinate to the body), and the structures of transcendence (religious,
social, political) through which order and meaning are imposed and created.
Bataille’s work, revived in the 1960s, heavily influenced poststructuralist
thinkers such as Derrida and Kristeva, as well as theorists of postmodernism
such as Lyotard and Baudrillard.
Bataille drew inspiration from “deviant” figures such as the Marquis de
Sade, who saw the very notion of reason as coercive and violent. The concept
of reason, since at least the time of Plato, has been used to control and
suppress the desires and appetites of the body in the interests of political order
and communal benefit. In the era of capitalism, desires must be subordinated
to the principle of utility and the requirements of the market such as economy
and efficiency. It should be remembered, however, that Bataille’s project of
224
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
heterology was hardly altogether new; he was continuing, with perhaps a
more scatological emphasis, a heterological tradition stretching from Schopenhauer and Nietzsche through Bergson, Freud, Heidegger to feminist
thinkers, which had stressed the role of the body, survival instincts, and
ideology in the very processes of perception and cognition. Bataille’s call is in
some sense fundamental: to overturn the homogenizing project of philosophy, religion, and art. A skeptic might argue that the scatological tendencies
that Bataille wishes to unleash already permeate the capitalist world and are
in fact one of the important directions in which it has extended its markets and
deepened its conditioning of human subjectivity.
Structuralism
Structuralism was to some extent anticipated in the work of the Canadian
Northrop Frye, who was the most influential theorist in America of what is
called Myth Criticism, which was in vogue from the 1940s to the mid-1960s
and whose practitioners included Richard Chase, Leslie Fiedler, Daniel
Hoffman, and Philip Wheelwright. Drawing on the findings of anthropology
and psychology regarding universal myths, rituals, and folktales, these critics
were intent on restoring spiritual content to a world they saw as alienated,
fragmented, and ruled by scientism, empiricism, positivism, and technology.
They wished to redeem the role of myth, which might comprehend magic,
imagination, dreams, intuition, and the unconscious. They viewed the creation of myth as integral to human thought, and believed that literature
emerges out of a core of myth, where “myth” is understood as a collective
attempt on the part of various cultures and groups to establish a meaningful
context for human existence. Frye’s Anatomy of Criticism (1957) continued
the formalist emphasis of the New Criticism but insisted even more strongly
that criticism should be a scientific, objective, and systematic discipline. Frye
held that such literary criticism views literature itself as a system. For
example, the mythoi of Spring, Summer, Autumn, and Winter gave rise to
fundamental literary modes such as comedy, tragedy, irony, and romance.
Given the recurrence of basic symbolic motifs, literary history is a repetitive
and self-contained cycle. Hence the historical element ostensibly informing
Frye’s formalism is effectively abrogated, literature being viewed as a timeless, static and autonomous construct.
Frye’s static model, exhibiting recurrent patterns, is a feature shared by
structuralist views of language and literature. The foundations of structuralism were laid by the Swiss linguist Ferdinand de Saussure, whose insights
were developed by the French anthropologist Claude Levi-Strauss, Roland
Barthes, and others. Saussure saw language as a system of signs, constructed
by convention, which lent itself to synchronic structural analysis. Also
Phenomenology, Existentialism, Structuralism
225
entailed in structuralist analyses was the anti-humanist view that, since
language is an institution, individual human agency is unprivileged, neither
human beings nor social phenomena having essences. Hence, structuralism
diverges sharply from the Romantic notion of the author as the source of
meaning, and shifts emphasis away from authorial intention toward the
broader and impersonal linguistic structure in which the author’s text
participates, and which indeed enables that text. Structuralism was imported
into America from France during the 1960s and its leading exponents
included Roman Jakobson, Jonathan Culler, Michael Riffaterre, Claudio
Guillen, Gerald Prince, and Robert Scholes. Other American thinkers working in the field of semiotics have included C. S. Peirce, Charles Morris, and
Noam Chomsky. The major principles of structuralism can now be examined
briefly in the work of Saussure and Roland Barthes.
Ferdinand de Saussure (1857–1913)
Saussure was effectively the founder of modern linguistics, as well as of
structuralism; and, while much poststructuralism arose in partial reaction
against his thought, it nonetheless presupposed his theoretical advances in
linguistics. His lectures in linguistics, posthumously compiled by his colleagues as Course in General Linguistics (1916), proved to be of seminal
influence in a broad range of fields, including anthropology, as in the work
of Levi-Strauss; the semiological work of Roland Barthes; the literaryphilosophical notions of Derrida; the analyses of ideology by structuralist
Marxists such as Louis Althusser; the psychoanalytic theories of Jacques
Lacan; and the analyses of language conducted by feminists such as Julia
Kristeva.
Prior to Saussure, the predominant modes of analyzing language were
historical and philological. As opposed to a diachronic approach which
studies changes in language over a period of time, Saussure undertook a
synchronic approach which saw language as a structure that could be studied
in its entirety at a given point in time. He pioneered a number of further
influential and radical insights. Firstly, he denied that there is somehow a
natural connection between words and things, urging that this connection is
conventional. This view of language also challenges the view of reality as
somehow independent and existing outside of language, a view which reduces
language to merely a “name-giving system.” Saussure’s view implies that we
acquire an understanding of our world by means of language and view the
world through language. Secondly, Saussure argued that language is a system
of signs in relation: no sign has meaning in isolation; rather its signification
depends on its difference from other signs and generally on its situation within
the entire network of signs. For example, in order to understand the word
“black,” we need to understand not only the other colors such as “white” and
226
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
“red” but the word “color” itself. Finally, Saussure made a distinction
between two dimensions of language: langue, which refers to language as
a structured system, grounded on certain rules; and parole, the specific acts of
speech or utterance which are based on those rules.
Saussure’s exposition of the “Nature of the Linguistic Sign” provides a
reference point for much subsequent literary and cultural theory. He attacks
the conventional correspondence theory of meaning whereby language is
viewed as a naming process, each word corresponding to the thing it names.4
As against this view, Saussure urges that both terms of the linguistic sign
(signifier and signified) are psychological in nature; the sign unites not a thing
with a name but a concept with a sound-image. The latter is not the material
sound but the “psychological imprint of the sound,” the impression it makes
on our senses; hence it too is psychological (CGL, 66). He suggests a new
terminology: signified designates the concept, signifier designates the soundimage, and sign designates the combination of these or the entire construct. As
Saussure states, the linguistic sign in its totality is “a two-sided psychological
entity,” consisting of both signifier and signified. The sign as a whole refers to
the actual object in the world, as displayed in the following diagram:
Signifier (the word or sound-image “table”)
Sign > Actual object: table
Signified (the concept of “table”)
The sign has two primordial characteristics: firstly, the bond between
signifier and signified is arbitrary: by this, Saussure means that the concept (e.
g., “sister”) is not linked by any inner relationship to the succession of sounds
which serves as its signifier (in French, s-o-r). Saussure offers another
clarification: the bond is not natural but unmotivated, based on collective
behavior or convention, fixed by rules. Signifiers and gestures do not have any
intrinsic value. Saussure is careful to suggest that “arbitrary” does not imply
that the choice of the signifier is left entirely to the speaker: the individual has
no power to change a sign in any way once it has become established in the
linguistic community (CGL, 69).
Roland Barthes (1915–1980)
Roland Barthes’ theoretical development is often seen as embodying a
transition from structuralist to poststructuralist perspectives, though certain
of his works are characterized by a Marxian outlook. Barthes effectively
extended structural analysis and semiology (the study of signs) to broad
cultural phenomena, and it was he also who confronted the limits
of structuralism, pointing the way to freer and more relativistic assessments
of texts and their role in culture. It was Barthes who made famous the notion
Phenomenology, Existentialism, Structuralism
227
of the “death of the author,” the idea of the text as a site of free play or
pleasure, and differences such as those between “work” and “text,” and
“writerly” and “readerly” works of art. As such, he anticipates many facets of
poststructuralism, including certain elements of deconstruction, cultural
studies, and queer studies.
Notwithstanding his suffering from tuberculosis, his homosexuality, and
his esoteric and eclectic world view, Barthes was at times affiliated with
mainstream French institutions, such as the National Center for Scientific
Research and the College de France. His early works, Writing Degree Zero
(1953) and Mythologies (1957), derived inspiration from Saussure, Sartre,
and Marxism. His structuralist works include Elements of Semiology (1964)
and “Introduction to the Structural Analysis of Narrative” (1966). His
poststructuralist disposition is marked in his polysemic analysis of Balzac’s
novella Sarrasine in his S/Z (1970) and The Pleasure of the Text (1973).
In Mythologies Barthes undertook an ideological critique of various
products of mass bourgeois culture (ranging from soap through advertising
to images of Rome), attempting to account for this mystification of culture or
history into a “universal nature.”5 Barthes suggests that myth is not an object,
a concept or an idea but a language, a type of speech. It is a mode of
signification (Myth., 109). Barthes saw bourgeois ideology as a process of
myth-making, whereby the bourgeoisie, instead of identifying itself as a class,
merges into the concept of “nation,” thereby presenting bourgeois values as
being in the national interest. Through this depoliticizing and “universalistic
effort” of its vocabulary, the bourgeoisie was able to postulate its own
definitions of justice, truth, and law as universal; it was able to postulate
its own definition of humanity as comprising “human nature”; and
“bourgeois norms are experienced as the evident laws of a natural order”
(Myth., 138–140). According to Barthes, myth can be opposed or undermined either by producing an artificial myth, highlighting its own mythical
status, or by using speech in an explicitly political manner (Myth., 135–136,
145–146).
Barthes challenged classical views of the human subject, and viewed an
author or persona as a grammatical function rather than a psychological
subject. In “The Death of the Author” (1968), he argues that as soon as
narration occurs without any practical purpose, as an end in itself, “this
disconnection occurs, the voice loses its origin, the author enters into his own
death, writing begins.”6 The modern, individual, author, says Barthes, was “a
product of our society insofar as, emerging from the Middle Ages with English
empiricism, French rationalism and the personal faith of the Reformation, it
discovered the prestige of the individual . . . the epitome and culmination of
capitalist ideology.” Even in the present, says Barthes, our studies of literature
are “tyrannically centred on the author” (IMT, 143). According to Barthes,
we can no longer think of writing in the classical ways, as recording,
228
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
representing, or depicting. Rather, it is a “performative” act (IMT, 145–146).
What is more, a text can no longer be viewed as releasing in a linear fashion a
single “theological” meaning, as the message of the “Author-God.” Rather, it
is “a multi-dimensional space in which a variety of writings, none of them
original, blend and clash. The text is a tissue of quotations drawn from the
innumerable centres of culture” (IMT, 146). The writer has only the power to
mix writings. Hence literature, by refusing to assign an “ultimate meaning . . .
to the text (and to the world as text)” facilitates an “anti-theological” activity
which is revolutionary since “to refuse to fix meaning is, in the end, to refuse
God and his hypostases – reason, science, law” (IMT, 147). A text’s unity,
says Barthes, “lies not in its origin but in its destination,” in the reader. Yet
Barthes cautions that the humanism we have rejected via removal of the
author should not be reinstated through any conception of the reader as a
personal and complete entity. The reader of which Barthes speaks is a reader
“without history, biography, psychology; he is simply that someone who
holds together in a single field all the traces by which the written text is
constituted.” In other words, the reader, like the author, is a function of the
text. In this sense “the birth of the reader must be at the cost of the death of the
Author” (IMT, 148).
In a subsequent essay, “From Work to Text” (1971), Barthes provides a
succinct statement of a poststructuralist perspective. He distinguishes between a “work” and a “text.” Whereas a “work” offers up to analysis a closed
signified or definite meaning, a “text” can never allow investigation to halt at
some signified, some concept which represents its ultimate meaning. Like
language, the text “is structured but off-centred, without closure” (IMT,
159). Barthes states an important feature of poststructuralist analysis when he
says that the text is held in “intertextuality,” in a network of signifiers (IMT,
160–161). And, whereas the work is consumed more or less passively, the text
asks of the reader a “practical collaboration” in the production of the work
(IMT, 162–163). The implication here is that the text invites participation in
its own play, its subversion of hierarchies, and its endless deferment of the
definite (IMT, 164).
Notes
1. Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, trans. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson
(New York: Harper and Row, 1962), pp. 19, 21–23, 82–83. Hereafter cited as BT.
2. Martin Heidegger, Poetry, Language, Thought, trans. Albert Hofstadter (New
York and London: Harper and Row, 1975), p. 199. Hereafter cited as PLT.
3. Quoted in Georges Bataille, “Introduction,” in Visions of Excess: Selected Writings
1927–1939, ed. Allan Stoekl (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1985),
pp. x–xi.
Phenomenology, Existentialism, Structuralism
229
4. Ferdinand de Saussure, Course in General Linguistics, ed. Charles Bally, Albert
Sechehaye, and Albert Reidlinger, trans. Wade Baskin (New York: Philosophical
Library, 1959), p. 65. Hereafter cited as CGL.
5. Roland Barthes, Mythologies, trans. Annette Lavers (London: Collins, 1973),
p. 9. Hereafter cited as Myth.
6. Roland Barthes, Image: Music: Text, trans. Stephen Heath (Glasgow: Fontana,
1982), p. 142. Hereafter cited as IMT.
Chapter 16
The Era of Poststructuralism (I):
Later Marxism, Psychoanalysis,
Deconstruction
The broad term “poststructuralism” denotes a range of critical approaches
emerging after the 1960s, which took from structuralism its insights into
language as a system of signs, and the construction of identity, subjects, and
objects through language. They rejected, however, the concept of structure,
the use of binary oppositions, and structuralism’s ahistorical approach,
emphasizing instead the indeterminate and polysemic nature of semiotic
codes and the arbitrary and constructed nature of the foundations of knowledge. These movements, born in a politically more volatile climate, laid
greater emphasis on the operations of ideology and power in the construction
of human subjectivity, which they described in gendered, racial, and economic terms. While Marxism itself cannot be classified as poststructuralist,
Marxist thinking in this era interacted richly with other approaches and
registered the impact of certain poststructuralist insights.
It was, ironically, the period of relative economic prosperity after the
World War II that eventually gave impetus to the civil rights movement and
the women’s movement. The revolutionary fervor of the 1960s gave Marxist
criticism a revived impetus. A group of Marxist critics was centered around
the New Left Review, founded in 1960 and edited first by Stuart Hall and then
by Perry Anderson. Its contributors included E. P. Thompson, Raymond
Williams, and Terry Eagleton. This was also the period in which the radical
journal Tel Quel, established in 1960 in France, fostered an intellectual milieu
in which the writings of Derrida, Lacan, and feminist thinkers such as Julia
Kristeva were fomented, eventually displacing the prominence of French
existentialism. Many of the thinkers associated with the journal challenged
the categories and binary oppositions which had acted as the foundation of
much Western thought since Plato and Aristotle. Some feminists, notably
Luce Irigaray and Helene Cixous, indicted both Freud and Lacan’s own
discourse, which they saw as privileging the male and even as misogynistic.
Literary Criticism from Plato to the Present: An Introduction
© 2011 M. A. R. Habib. ISBN: 978-1-405-16034-6
M. A. R. Habib
Later Marxism, Psychoanalysis, Deconstruction
231
Feminists such as Monique Wittig and Kristeva reflected on the possibility of
an ecriture feminine.
Writers such as Gilles Deleuze, Felix Guattari, and Jean Baudrillard have
variously offered powerful analyses of capitalist society in terms of psychological categories and drives, as well as of the symbolic processes that structure
consciousness, and the lack of foundations for arriving at intellectual or moral
judgment. More recent thinkers such as Clement Rosset, Jacques Bouveresse,
and Richard Rorty have turned away from the tenets of poststructuralism,
such as its reductive view of reality as ultimately linguistic. Feminists such as
Nancy Chodorow and Jessica Benjamin have reacted against the predominant
Freudian–Lacanian accounts of sexuality, seeking instead to trace the formation of gender to the infant’s pre-Oedipal connections with the mother.
Vincent Descombes has returned to the principles of early twentieth-century
analytical philosophers such as Wittgenstein, and whereas many poststructuralists drew heavily on Hegelian notions, thinkers such as Jean-François
Lyotard have turned instead to Kant. Lyotard has theorized influentially about
the “postmodern condition,” seeing it as marked by an absence of totalizing
schemes of explanation, and the dissolution of human subjectivity.
Later Marxist Criticism
From the 1960s, Marxist critics continued to reinterpret and develop the
insights of Marx and Engels. Louis Althusser, Lucien Goldmann, and Pierre
Macherey turned away from Hegel and were heavily influenced by the
structuralist movements of the earlier twentieth century, which stressed the
role of larger signifying systems and institutional structures over individual
agency and intention. Louis Althusser, in his Pour Marx (For Marx, 1965)
and his often cited “Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses,” emphasized
the later Marx’s scientificity and his “epistemological break” from his own
earlier humanism and Hegelianism. He rejected literary critical emphases on
authorial intention and subjective agency. Goldmann also rejected the
Romantic–humanist notion of individual creativity and held that texts are
productions of larger structures representing the mentality of particular social
classes. He developed the notion of “homology” to register the parallels
between artistic and social forms. Pierre Macherey’s A Theory of Literary
Production (1966) saw the literary text as the product of the artist’s reworking of linguistic and ideological raw material, unwittingly exposing, through
its lacunae and contradictions, ideological elements which the author had
attempted to suppress into a false coherence. In this way, a critique of
ideology could emerge through the literary text.
In the Anglo-American world a “cultural materialist” criticism was first
revived by Raymond Williams (1921–1988), notably in Culture and Society
232
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
1780–1950, which analyzed the cultural critique of capitalism in English
literary tradition. Williams rejected a simplistic explanation of culture as the
efflux of material conditions, and stressed the contribution of cultural forms
to economic and political development. The Long Revolution (1961) continued and refined this project using categories such as dominant, residual,
and emergent cultures, mediated by what Williams called “structures of
feeling.” Williams’ work became overtly Marxist with the publication in
1977 of Marxism and Literature, where he attempts to integrate Marxist
conceptions of language and literature. In general, Williams’ work analyzed
the history of language, the role of the media, mass communications, and the
cultural connections between the country and the city.
The major American Marxist critic Fredric Jameson (b. 1934) outlined a
dialectical theory of literary criticism in his Marxism and Form (1971),
drawing on Hegelian categories such as the notion of totality and the
connection of abstract and concrete. Such criticism recognizes the need to
see its objects of analysis within a broad historical context, acknowledges its
own history and perspective, and seeks the profound inner form of a literary
text. Jameson’s The Political Unconscious (1981) attempts to integrate this
dialectical thinking with insights from structuralism and Freud, using the
Freudian notion of repression to analyze the function of ideology, the status of
literary texts, and the epistemological function of literary form. In subsequent
work such as Postmodernism, or the Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism
(1991), Jameson performed the valuable task of extending Marx’s insights
into the central role of postmodernism in determining the very form of our
artistic and intellectual experience.
Terry Eagleton (b. 1943)
In Britain, the most prominent Marxist critic has been Terry Eagleton, who
has outlined the categories of a Marxist analysis of literature, and has
persistently rearticulated the terms of communication, as well as the differences, between Marxism and modern literary theory. Eagleton insists that
there are at least two fundamental premises in Marx from which any Marxist
criticism must begin. In the first place, all forms of consciousness – religious,
moral, philosophical, legal, as well as language itself – have no independent
history and arise from the material activity of men. Secondly, class struggle is
viewed as the central dynamic of historical development. Eagleton adds a
third, Marxist–Leninist, imperative, namely a commitment to the theory and
practice of political revolution.1 According to Eagleton, the “primary task”
of Marxist criticism is “to actively participate in and help direct the cultural
emancipation of the masses.”2 He repeatedly stresses that the starting point of
theory must be a practical, political purpose.3 He emphasizes that the “means
of production” includes the means of production of human subjectivity,
Later Marxism, Psychoanalysis, Deconstruction
233
which embraces a range of institutions such as “literature.” Eagleton regards
the most difficult emancipation as that of the “space of subjectivity,”
colonized as it is by the dominant political order. The humanities as a whole
serve an ideological function that helps to perpetuate certain forms of
subjectivity. Eagleton’s views here imply that for Marxist criticism,
“ideology” is a crucial focus of the link between material and mental means
of production.
Eagleton affirms that, in contrast with Marxist criticism, the allegedly
radical movements of structuralism and deconstruction fail to articulate their
connections with the material infrastructure. As such, they lapse into an
effective, if sometimes unintended, complicity with ruling ideologies
(LT, 141). In a later work, After Theory, he suggests that we need to return
in some respects to a “plain realism.” He cautions that
If cultural theory is to engage with an ambitious global history, it must have
answerable resources of its own, equal in depth and scope to the situation it
confronts. It cannot afford simply to keep on recounting the same narratives of
class, race and gender, indispensable as these topics are.4
Psychoanalysis
Like Marxist criticism, psychoanalysis has its roots in the nineteenth century,
and has interacted richly with many streams of poststructuralist thought. The
psychology of literature is hardly a new concern: ever since Aristotle, critics,
rhetoricians, and philosophers have examined the psychological dimensions of
literature, ranging from an author’s motivation and intentions to the effect of
texts and performances on an audience. The application of psychoanalytic
principles to the study of literature, however, is a relatively recent phenomenon,
initiated primarily by Freud and, in other directions, by Alfred Adler and Carl
Jung. The notion of the “unconscious” can be found in many thinkers prior to
Freud, notably in some of the Romantics such as Schlegel, in Schopenhauer,
and in Nietzsche. Freud’s fundamental contribution was to open up the entire
realm of the unconscious to systematic study, and to provide a language and
terminology in which the operations of the unconscious could be expressed.
To view the unconscious as the ultimate source and explanation of human
thought and behavior represents a radical disruption of the main streams of
Western thought which, since Aristotle, had held that man was essentially a
rational being, capable of making free choices in the spheres of intellection
and morality. To say that the unconscious governs our behavior is to
problematize all of the notions on which philosophy, theology, and even
literary criticism have conventionally rested: the ideal of self-knowledge, the
ability to know others, the capacity to make moral judgments, the belief that
we can act according to reason, that we can overcome our passions and
234
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
instincts, the ideas of moral and political agency, intentionality, and the
notion – held for centuries – that literary creation can be a rational process. In
a sense, Freud postulated that we bear a form of “otherness” within ourselves:
we cannot claim fully to comprehend even ourselves, why we act as we do,
why we make certain moral and political decisions, why we harbor given
religious dispositions and intellectual orientations. Even when we think we
are acting from a given motive, we may be deluding ourselves; and much of
our thought and action is not freely determined by us but driven by unconscious forces which we can barely fathom. Far from being based on reason,
our thinking is intimately dependent upon the body, upon its instincts of
survival and aggression, as well as obstinate features that cannot be dismissed
(as they are in the Cartesian tradition where the mind is treated as a
disembodied phenomenon) such as its size, color, gender, and social situation.
This unbalancing of conventional notions extends to literature: we cannot
presume that our conscious purposes represent our true aim, nor that
language is a transparent medium of communication, of either thought or
emotion.
Freud was aware of the problematic nature of language itself, its opaqueness and materiality, its resistance to clarity and its refusal to be reduced to
any one-dimensional “literal” meaning. Some of his major concepts, such the
Oedipus complex, were founded on literary models such as Oedipus Rex and
Hamlet. Freud’s own literary analyses tend to apply his models of dream
interpretation to literary texts. Subsequent psychologists and literary critics
have extended the field of psychoanalytic criticism to encompass: analysis of
the motives of an author, of readers, and of fictional characters; relating a text
to features of the author’s biography such as childhood memories and
relationship to parents; the nature of the creative process; the psychology
of readers’ responses to literary texts; interpretation of symbols in a text, to
unearth latent meanings; analysis of the connections between various authors
in a literary tradition; examination of gender roles and stereotypes; and the
functioning of language in the constitution of the conscious and unconscious.
What underlies nearly all of these endeavors is the perception of a broad
analogy, fostered by Freud himself, between the psychoanalytic process and
the production of a narrative. In a sense, the psychoanalyst himself creates a
fiction: triggered by a patient’s neurosis and recollection of traumatic events,
the psychoanalyst creates a coherent narrative about the patient within which
the traumatic event can take its place and be understood.
After Freud, psychoanalytic criticism was continued by his biographer
Ernest Jones, whose book Hamlet and Oedipus (1948) interpreted Hamlet’s
indecisive behavior in killing his uncle Claudius in terms of his ambivalent
feelings toward his mother. Another of Freud’s disciples, Otto Rank, produced The Myth of the Birth of the Hero (1909), which reaffirmed Freud’s
notions of the artist producing fantasies of wish fulfillment, and which
Later Marxism, Psychoanalysis, Deconstruction
235
compiled numerous myths on subjects such as incest, and on the notion of
the hero. Ella Freeman Sharpe (1875–1947) treated language and metaphor
from a psychoanalytic perspective. Marie Bonaparte (1882–1962) wrote a
large study of Edgar Allen Poe, attributing much of his creative disposition to
the loss of his mother when he was a child. Melanie Klein (1882–1960)
modified the Freudian theory of sexuality, rejecting the primacy of the
Oedipus complex and elaborating a theory of the drives.
The influence of psychoanalysis has extended into nearly all dimensions of
modern literary theory. I. A. Richards, William Empson, Lionel Trilling,
Kenneth Burke, and Edmund Wilson all in various ways searched texts for
latent content. Harold Bloom’s influential theory of literary influence as
mediated through “anxiety” drew upon Freud’s account of the Oedipus
complex. Simon O. Lesser (1909–1979) furnished a psychoanalytic account
of the reading process. Influenced by Lesser, Norman Holland (b. 1927) used
ego psychology and the notion of the literary text as fantasy to elaborate his
version of reader-response criticism, studying the manner in which texts
appeal to the repressed fantasies of readers. Feminist critics such as Juliet
Mitchell have used Freud’s ideas in their explanations of the operations of
patriarchy; others, such as Kristeva, have modified his notions in their
analyses of language and gender. Members of the Frankfurt School of Marxist
thinkers, such as Herbert Marcuse, have enlisted Freudian concepts in their
analyses of mass culture and ideology. Other significant theorists include
Norman O. Brown (b. 1913), D. W. Winnicott, Gilles Deleuze, and Felix
Guattari, who have explored the ideological bases of psychoanalysis, and
Jacques Lacan. The following account of Freud’s own literary analyses places
them in the context of his theories as a whole.
Sigmund Freud (1856–1939)
Sigmund Freud was born to Jewish parents in Moravia, in a small town in
what is now called the Czech Republic.5 His father was somewhat aloof and
authoritarian while his mother was a warmer and more accessible figure.
When Freud first began his medical studies at the University of Vienna in 1873
he found himself somewhat excluded from the academic community and
looked down upon, on account of his Jewish origins. He saw this period,
where he was forced into the role of outsider, as furnishing the foundation for
his independence of thought. We can briefly look at some of the important
themes in Freud’s work. Among these are repression, whereby thoughts and
impulses which are viewed as alarming, painful, or shameful are expunged or
repressed from the conscious memory. Freud also pioneered the notion of
infantile sexuality: contravening conventional notions of childhood innocence, he viewed normal adult sexual life as the result of a long development
of the sexual function in an individual since infancy. Perhaps the most
236
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
important of Freud’s notions was the Oedipus complex: after the first stage of
auto-eroticism, the first love-object for both sexes is the mother, who is not yet
perceived as distinct from the child’s own body. As infancy progresses, sexual
development undergoes the Oedipus complex: the boy focuses his sexual
wishes upon his mother and develops hostile impulses toward his father. At
this stage, Freud thought that girls underwent an analogous development but
his views on this changed drastically. Under the threat of castration, the male
child represses its desire for the mother and accepts the rules laid down by the
father. Again in the face of established beliefs, Freud saw the constitution of
the human being as “innately bisexual.” Only later was sexuality differentiated in terms of gender, children being initially unclear as to the differences
between the sexes. Freud’s continuing observations led him to believe that the
Oedipus complex was both the climax of infantile sexual life and the
foundation of all the later developments of sexuality.
Freud extended the meaning of sexuality to encompass not merely genital
satisfaction but a broader bodily function, having pleasure as its goal and only
subsequently serving a reproductive function. Sexuality now encompassed all
of the emotions of affection and friendliness traditionally subsumed under the
word “love” (Freud, 23). Freud hoped thereby to foster a greater understanding of sexuality, since it was so restricted in Western civilization, where
object-choice is narrowed to allow only the opposite sex and where there is
basically one standard of sexual life for all (Freud, 746).
Also central to Freud’s work is his interpretation of dreams, which he
claimed psychoanalysis could analyze scientifically. From the associations
produced by the dreamer, the analyst could infer a thought-structure,
composed of latent dream-thoughts. These were expressed not directly but
only as translated and distorted into the manifest dream, which was composed largely of visual images. In The Interpretation of Dreams (1900), Freud
argued that the latent dream thoughts are obliged to undergo alteration, a
process he called dream-distortion, so that the forbidden meaning of the
dream is unrecognizable. Freud defined a dream as the disguised fulfillment of
a repressed wish (Freud, 28). The dream-work, or process by which the latent
thoughts are converted into the manifest or explicit content of the dream,
occurs through a number of functions: condensation of the component parts
of the preconscious material of the dream; displacement of the psychical
emphasis of the dream; and dramatization of the entire dream by translation
into visual images.
Freud’s literary analyses Around 1907 Freud’s interests in the implications
of psychoanalysis began to extend over the entire domain of culture. He
sought to apply psychoanalytic principles to the study of art, religion, and
primitive cultures. Even in his earlier work, he had already viewed Sophocles’
play Oedipus Rex as expressing a “universal law of mental life.” He also saw
Later Marxism, Psychoanalysis, Deconstruction
237
the Oedipus complex as governing the tragedy of Hamlet, though he later
altered his views on this play. In analyzing Leonardo da Vinci’s picture of
“The Madonna and Child with St. Anne” (1910), Freud’s examination of
Leonardo da Vinci’s character generated a prototype for psychoanalytic
biography. In 1914 he published (anonymously) an acute reading of the
“meaning” of Michelangelo’s statue of Moses in Rome. Freud never claimed,
however, that psychoanalysis could adequately explain the process of artistic
creation. In his paper “Dostoevsky and Parricide” (1928), he stated: “Before
the problem of the creative artist analysis must, alas, lay down its arms.”6
We can obtain a sense of Freud’s psychoanalytic “literary-critical” procedure by looking at his paper “Creative Writers and Day-Dreaming” (1907).
Freud suggests that, like the child who fantasizes, the creative writer engages
in a kind of play: “He creates a world of phantasy which he takes very
seriously – that is, which he invests with large amounts of emotion – while
separating it sharply from reality” (Freud, 437). Freud observes that popular
stories typically have “a hero who is the centre of interest,” a hero who is
invulnerable. Through “this revealing characteristic of invulnerability,” says
Freud, “we can immediately recognize His Majesty the Ego, the hero alike of
every day-dream and of every story” (Freud, 441). Freud’s point here is that
the fiction is not a “portrayal of reality” but has all the constituents of a
phantasy or daydream: the hero is invulnerable, women invariably fall in love
with him, and the other characters in the story are “sharply divided into good
and bad” in a manner that contravenes the more subtle variations found in
real life (Freud, 441). Hence the story expresses a phantasy on the part of the
creative writer, who can indulge in this parading and projection of his ego.
Freud surmises that a creative work is “a continuation of, and a substitute
for, what was once the play of childhood” (Freud, 442). His understanding of
play implies a self-created world of language, a language that reconfigures the
conventional idioms that are held to express reality; it implies a kind of
“return” to a Lacanian imaginary realm of infantile security and satisfying
wholeness, where everything is ordered just as we might wish it. In this brief
paper, Freud opens up a number of literary-critical avenues: the linking of a
creative work to an in-depth study of an author’s psychology, using a vastly
altered conception of human subjectivity; the tracing in art of primal
psychological tendencies and conflicts; and the understanding of art and
literature as integrally related to deeper, unconscious, impulses that lie hidden
in recurring human obsessions, fears and anxieties. Such paths will be further
explored by Carl Jung, Northrop Frye, Lacan, and others.
Freud on history and civilization In his later work Civilization and its
Discontents (1930) Freud situates creative art within the broader contexts of
culture and religion. Essentially, the human psyche, frustrated in its attempts
to mold the world in a self-comforting image, resorts to art to create its world
238
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
in phantasy. Art – in a broad sense that includes science, philosophy, and
religion – is the embodiment of civilization itself, which is erected on the
graveyard of repressed instincts. Freud views religion as a form of mass
delusion, which regards “reality as the sole enemy,” and encourages a turning
away from the world (Freud, 732). Indeed, the evolution of civilization is a
struggle between eros (the life instinct, embodied in sexuality) and thanatos
(the death instinct, expressed in aggression) (Freud, 755–756). Civilization
checks both aggression and sexuality by the superego, which internalizes
communal moral standards. The authority of the father or of both parents,
says Freud, is assumed by the larger human community, hence the demands of
an individual’s superego will “coincide with the precepts of the prevailing
cultural super-ego” (Freud, 756–757, 769). The resulting tension between
the superego and the ego is characterized by Freud as the sense of guilt
(Freud, 759).
What Freud gives to, and shares with, much cultural and literary theory is a
view of the human self as constructed to a large extent by its environment, as a
product of familial and larger social forces; a profound sense of the limitations
of reason and of language itself; an intense awareness of the closure effected
by conventional systems of thought and behavior, of the severe constraints
imposed upon human sexuality; a view of art and religion as issuing from
broader patterns of human need; and an acknowledgment that truth-value
and moral value are not somehow absolute or universal but are motivated by
the economic and ideological demands of civilization. Like Schopenhauer
and Nietzsche, Freud has no illusions about where our ideas ultimately
derive from: “man’s judgments of value follow directly his wishes for
happiness – that, accordingly, they are an attempt to support his illusions
with arguments” (Freud, 771).
Jacques Lacan (1901–1981)
The French psychoanalyst Jacques Lacan used insights furnished by linguistics and structuralism to reformulate Freud’s account of the unconscious and
his own account of human subjectivity. Lacan’s reputation was established by
his publication of Écrits (1966). His influence has not only extended over the
field of psychoanalysis but also reaches into the work of Marxists such as
Louis Althusser (whose theories were influenced by Lacan and who, ironically, became Lacan’s patient, after which he killed his wife) and feminists
such as Julia Kristeva and Jane Gallop, as well as deconstructive thinkers such
as Barbara Johnson. Other feminists have reacted strongly against the
phallocentric thrust (a not altogether inapt expression) of Lacan’s own work.
It may be useful to outline some of Lacan’s pivotal views. He posits three
orders or states of human mental disposition: the imaginary order, the
symbolic order, and the real. The imaginary order is a pre-Oedipal phase
Later Marxism, Psychoanalysis, Deconstruction
239
where an infant is as yet unable to distinguish itself from its mother’s body or
to recognize the lines of demarcation between itself and objects in the
world; indeed, it does not as yet know itself as a coherent entity or self.
Hence, the imaginary phase is one of unity (between the child and its
surroundings), as well as of immediate possession (of the mother and objects),
a condition of reassuring plenitude, a world consisting wholly of images
(hence “imaginary”) that is not fragmented or mediated by difference, by
categories, in a word, by language and signs. The mirror phase – the point at
which the child can recognize itself and its environment in the mirror – marks
the point at which this comforting imaginary condition breaks down, pushing
the child into the symbolic order which is the world of predefined social roles
and gender differences, the world of subjects and objects, the world of
language.
In this way, Lacan effectively reformulates in linguistic terms Freud’s
account of the Oedipus complex. Freud had posited that the infant’s
desire for its mother is prohibited by the father, who threatens it with
castration. Faced with this threat, the infant represses his desire, thereby
opening up the dimension of the unconscious, which is for Lacan (and
Freud as seen through Lacan) not a “place” but a relation to the social
world of law, morality, religion, and conscience. According to Freud, the
child internalizes through the father’s commands (what Lacan calls the
Law of the Father) the appropriate standards of socially acceptable thought
and behavior. Freud calls these standards internalized as conscience the
child’s “superego.” The child now identifies with the father, sliding into
his own gendered role, in the knowledge that he too is destined for fatherhood. Of course, the repressed desire continues to exert its influence on
conscious life.
As Lacan rewrites this process, the child, in passing from the imaginary to
the symbolic order, continues to long for the security and wholeness it
previously felt: it is now no longer in full possession of its mother and of
entities in the world; rather, it is distinguished from them in and through a
network of signification. The child’s desire, as Lacan explains it, passes in an
unceasing movement along an infinite chain of signifiers, in search of unity,
security, of ultimate meaning, in an ever elusive signified, and immaturely
clings to the fictive notion of unitary selfhood that began in the imaginary
phase. The child exists in an alienated condition, its relationships with objects
always highly mediated and controlled by social structures at the heart of
whose operations is language. For Lacan, the phallus is a privileged signifier,
signifying both sexual distinction and its arbitrariness. Lacan never accurately describes the “real”: he seems to think of it as what lies beyond the
world of signification, perhaps a primordial immediacy of experience prior to
language or a chaotic condition of mere thinghood prior to objectivity. For
Lacan, the real is the impossible: that which occurs beyond the entire
240
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
framework of signification. The real is a sign of its own absence, pointing to
itself as mere signifier.
Lacan rejects any notion that the mind of either child or adult has any
intrinsic psychical unity; it is merely a “subject” rather than a self or ego,
merely the occupant of an always moving position in the networks of
signification; hence, for Lacan, as he indicates in a famous statement, even
“the Unconscious is structured like a language.” The unconscious is as much a
product of signifying systems, and indeed is itself as much a signifying system,
as the conscious mind: both are like language in their openness, their constant
deferral of meaning, their susceptibility to changing definition and their
constitution as a system of relations (rather than existing as entities in their
own right). In Lacan’s view, the subject is empty, fluid, and without an axis or
center, and is always recreated in his encounter with the other, with what
exceeds his own nature and grasp. Influenced by Hegel’s master–slave
dialectic, as well as by his account of objectivity, Lacan sees the individual’s
relation to objects as mediated by desire and by struggle. Lacan’s extrapolation of what he considered to be the genuine implications of Freud’s theories
was furthered by the structuralist Marxist Louis Althusser, who adapted
Lacan’s insights in his account of the workings of the ideological apparatus of
the political state, thereby exploring the connections – which are merely latent
in Freud – between the unconscious and social structures.
Deconstruction
Jacques Derrida (1930–2004)
The term “poststructuralism” is often identified with “deconstruction,” a
pervasive phenomenon in modern literary and cultural theory originated by
the French thinker Jacques Derrida. While Derrida himself has insisted that
deconstruction is not a theory unified by any set of consistent rules or
procedures, it has been variously regarded as a way of reading, a mode of
writing, and, above all, a way of challenging interpretations of texts based
upon conventional notions of the stability of the human self, the external
world, and of language and meaning.
Derrida was born in Algeria to a Jewish family and suffered intensely the
experience of being an outsider. He studied in France, and then taught in Paris
and at various American universities. Derrida’s transatlantic influence can
be traced to a seminar held at Johns Hopkins University in 1966, where he
presented a paper entitled “Structure, Sign, and Play in the Discourse of
the Human Sciences.” The following year, 1967, marked Derrida’s explosive
entry onto the international stage of literary and cultural theory, with
the publication of his first three books, which included De la grammatologie
(Of Grammatology), whose subject was the “science” of writing, and
Later Marxism, Psychoanalysis, Deconstruction
241
L’Écriture et la difference (Writing and Difference), which contained important essays on Hegel, Freud, and Michel Foucault. Later works included
La Dissemination (Dissemination) (1972) which included a lengthy engagement with Plato’s views of writing and sophistry; Marges de la philosophie
(Margins of Philosophy) (1982), which included essays on Hegel’s semiology
and the use of metaphor in philosophy; and Spectres de Marx (Specters of
Marx) (1994) which looks at the various legacies of Marx.
The most fundamental project of deconstruction is to display the operations of “logocentrism” in any “text.” What is logocentrism? Etymologically
and historically, this term refers to any system of thought which is founded on
the stability and authority of the Logos, the divine Word. The scholar C. H.
Dodd explains that in its ancient Greek philosophical and Judeo-Christian
meaning, the Logos referred both to the Word of God which created the
universe and to the rational order of creation itself.7 In other words, it is in the
spoken Logos that language and reality ultimately coincide, in an identity that
is invested with absolute authority, absolute origin, and absolute purpose or
teleology. If we think of the orders of language and reality as follows, it is clear
that one of the functions of the Logos is to preserve the stability and closure of
the entire system:
LOGOS
Language
Signifier 1
Signifier 2
Signifier 3
Signifier 4
Reality
-a- Signified 1 –––––––––––b––––––––– Object 1
– Signified 2 ––––––––––––––––––––––– Object 2
– Signified 3 ––––––––––––––––––––––– Object 3
– Signified 4 ––––––––––––––––––––––– Object 4
Ad Infinitum
It is because the Logos holds together the orders of language and reality that
the relation between signifier (word) and signified (concept), i.e., relation a, is
stable and fixed; so too is relation b, the connection between the sign as a
whole and the object to which it refers in the world. For example, in a
Christian scheme, the signifier “love” might refer to the concept of “selfsacrifice” in relation to God. And this sign as a whole, the word “love” as
meaning “self-sacrifice,” would refer to object 1 which might be a system of
social or ecclesiastical relationships institutionally embodied in a given
society, enshrining the ideal of self-sacrifice. In other words, the meaning
of “love” is sanctioned by a hierarchy of authority, stretching back through
institutional Church practice, theology, philosophy, as well as political and
economic theory, to the authority of the scriptures and the Word of God
Himself. In the same way, all of the other signifiers and signifieds in language
would be constrained in their significance, making for a stable and closed
242
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
system. The Logos thereby authorizes an entire world view, sanctioned by a
theological and philosophical system and by an entire political, religious, and
social order.
If, now, the Logos is removed from this picture, what happens? The entire
order will become destabilized; historically, of course, this disintegration
does not happen all at once but takes centuries, as indeed does the undermining of the Logos. Once the Logos vanishes from the picture, there is
nothing to hold together the orders of language and reality, which now
threaten to fly apart from each other. The relations a and b both become
destabilized: if we are not constrained by a Christian perspective, we might
attribute other meanings to the word “love,” meanings which may even
conflict with the previously given Christian signification. Moreover, various
groups might give different meanings to the word so that a general consensus
is lost. In this way, signifier 1 may be defined by a meaning attributed to
signified 1. But since there is no authoritative closure to this process, it could
go on ad infinitum: signified 1 will itself need to be defined, and so this
signified will itself become a signifier of something else; this process might
regress indefinitely so that we never arrive at a conclusive signified but are
always moving along an endless chain of signifiers. Derrida attributes the
name of “metaphor” to this endless substitution of one signifier for another:
in describing or attempting to understand our world, we can no longer use
“literal” language, i.e., language that actually describes the object or reality.
We can only use metaphor, hence language in its very nature is metaphorical.
Hence there cannot be a sharp distinction between, say, the spheres of
philosophy and science, on the one hand, which are often presumed to use
a “literal” language based on reason, and literature and the arts, on the other
hand, which are characterized as using metaphorical and figurative language
in a manner inaccessible to reason.
Logocentrism takes a variety of guises: for example, the stabilizing function
of the Logos might be replaced by Plato’s Forms, the Aristotelian notion of
“substance,” or Hegel’s “absolute idea.” Modern equivalents in Western
society might be concepts such as freedom or democracy. All of these terms
function as what Derrida calls “transcendental signifieds,” or concepts
invested with absolute authority, which places them beyond questioning or
examination. An important endeavor of deconstruction, then, is to bring back
these various transcendental signifieds within the province of language and
textuality, within the province of their relatability to other concepts.
Hence, in one sense, the most fundamental project of deconstruction is to
reinstate language within the dualisms that have conventionally dominated
Western thought: the connections between thought and reality, self and
world, subject and object. In deconstructive thought, these connections are
not viewed as already existing prior to language, with language merely being
the instrument of their expression or representation. Rather, all of these terms
Later Marxism, Psychoanalysis, Deconstruction
243
are linguistic to begin with: they are enabled by language. We do not simply
have thought which is then expressed by language; thought takes place in, and
is made possible by, language. This deconstructive view of language is partly
influenced by Saussure’s notion of language as a system of relations; the terms
which are related have no independent meaning; they depend on their
relations with other terms for their significance. Also implicit in this view
of language is the arbitrary and conventional nature of the sign: there is no
natural connection between the sign “table” and an actual table in the world.
Moreover, there is no “truth” or “reality” which somehow stands outside or
behind language: truth is a relation of linguistic terms, and reality is a
construct, ultimately religious, social, political, and economic, but always
of language, of various linguistic registers. Even the human self, in this view,
has no pregiven essence but is a linguistic construct or narrative. Derrida’s
much-quoted statement that “il n’y a pas de hors-texte,”often translated as
“there is no outside of the text,” means precisely this: that the aforementioned
features of language, which together comprise “textuality,” are allembracing; textuality governs all interpretative operations. For example,
there is no history outside of language or textuality: history itself is a linguistic
and textual construct. At its deepest level, the insistence on viewing language
(as a system of relations and differences) as lying at the core of any world view
issues a challenge to the notion of identity, installed at the heart of Western
metaphysics since Aristotle.
An important deconstructive strategy is the undermining of certain oppositions which have enjoyed a privileged place in Western metaphysics.
Derrida points out that oppositions, such as those between intellect and
sense, soul and body, master and slave, male and female, inside and outside,
center and margin, do not represent a state of equivalence between two terms.
Rather, each of these oppositions is a “violent hierarchy” in which one term
has been conventionally subordinated. Intellect, for example, has usually
been superordinated over sense; soul has been exalted above body; male has
been defined as superior in numerous respects to female. Perhaps the most
significant opposition for Derrida is that between speech and writing.
According to Derrida, Western philosophy has privileged speech over writing, viewing speech as embodying an immediate presence of meaning, and
writing as a mere substitute or secondary representation of the spoken word.
For Derrida, “writing” designates all of the differences by which language
is constituted. Writing refers to the diffusion of identity (of self, object,
signifier, signified) through a vast network of relations and differences.
Writing expresses the movement of difference itself. In an attempt to subvert
the conventional priority of speech over writing, Derrida coins the term
differance, which embodies an ambivalence in the French word differer which
can mean both “to differ” and “to defer” in time. Hence Derrida adds a
temporal dimension to the notion of difference. Moreover, the substitution of
244
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
a for e in the word differance cannot be heard in French: it is a silent
displacement that can only be discerned in writing, as if to counter the
superior value previously accorded to speech. The terms that recur in
Derrida’s texts – their meanings often changing according to contexts – are
usually related to the extended significance that Derrida accords to “writing.”
Such terms include “trace,” “supplement,” “text,” “presence,” “absence,”
and “play.”
The privileging of speech over writing has perpetuated what Derrida calls a
“metaphysics of presence,” an assumption that meaning is always stable and
immediately present, effecting a closure and disabling any “free play” of
thought which might threaten or question this structure of meaning. Another
way of explaining the term “metaphysics of presence” might be as follows: an
entity’s content is viewed as coinciding completely with its existence. For
example, an isolated entity such as a piece of chalk would be regarded as
having its meaning completely within itself, completely in its immediate
“presence.” Even if the rest of the world did not exist, we could say what the
piece of chalk was, what its function and constitution were. Such absolute
self-containment of meaning must be sanctioned by a higher authority, a
Logos or transcendental signified, which ensured that all things in the world
had specific and designated meanings. If, however, we were to challenge such
a “metaphysics of presence,” we might argue that in fact the meaning of the
chalk does not coincide with, and is not confinable within, its immediate
existence; that its meaning and purpose actually lie in relations that extend far
beyond its immediate existence; its meaning would depend, for example,
upon the concept of a “blackboard” on which it was designed to write; in
turn, the relationship of chalk and blackboard derives its meaning from
increasingly broader contexts, such as a classroom, an institution of learning,
associated industries and technologies, as well as political and educational
programs. Hence the meaning of “chalk” would extend through a vast
network of relations far beyond the actual isolated existence of that item.
In this sense, the chalk is not self-identical since its identity is dispersed
through its relations with numerous other objects and concepts. Viewed in
this light, “chalk” is not a name for a self-subsistent, self-enclosed entity;
rather it names the provisional focal point of a complex set of relations. It can
be seen, then, that a metaphysics of “presence” refers to the self-presence, the
immediate presence, of meaning, as resting on a complete self-identity that is
sanctioned and preserved by the “presence” of a Logos.
A deconstructive reading of a text, as practiced by Derrida, will be a
multifaceted project: in general, it will attempt to display logocentric operations in the text, by focusing on a close reading of the text’s language, its use of
presuppositions or transcendental signifieds, its reliance on binary oppositions, its self-contradictions, its aporiai or points of conceptual impasse, and
the ways in which it effects closure and resists free play. Derrida’s engagement
Later Marxism, Psychoanalysis, Deconstruction
245
with the history of Western thought is not one of mere critique but also one of
inevitable complicity (where he is obliged to use the very terms he impugns).
This dual gesture must necessarily entail play on words, convolution of
language that accommodates its fluid nature, and divergence from conventional norms of essayistic writing. It might also be argued that the very form of
his texts, not merely their content, is integral to his overall project.
Derrida’s American disciples included the Yale critics Paul de Man, J. Hillis
Miller, and Geoffrey Hartman, as well as Barbara Johnson, who applied and
richly extended deconstructive techniques. Derrida’s own thought is nonetheless open to a number of substantive criticisms. His notion of “difference” –
a concept treated far more articulately by Hegel – effectively abolishes all
historical specificity. It simply abstracts into its own self-identical structure all
the endless variety of true historical relation; it dissolves actual relations into a
principle of abstract relationality. For Derrida, differance is effectively elevated to the status of a transcendental signified. Given that this notion
underlies Derrida’s critiques of philosophical systems which vary widely from
one another, it is evident that he coerces all of these systems into a uniform
assailability: they all suffer from the same defects, the same kinds of aporiai or
impasses. And it is only against a simplistic and positivistic understanding of
truth, meaning, presence, and subjectivity that his notions of trace, difference,
and writing can articulate themselves.
Finally, there has been a tendency to overestimate Derrida’s originality.
The relational and arbitrary nature of language has been perceived by many
thinkers, ranging from Hellenistic philosophers and rhetoricians through
Locke and Hume to Hegel, Marx, the French symbolists, and Saussure. The
notions that “reality” is a construction, that “truth” is an interpretation, that
human subjectivity is not essentially fixed, and that there are no ultimate
transcendent foundations of our thought and practice are as old as the
Sophists of Athens in the fifth century BC. Many of the aporiai “revealed”
by Derrida were encountered as such long ago by the neo-Hegelian philosophers. We can indeed benefit from a detailed reading of Derrida’s texts, one
which situates them in a balanced manner within the history of thought rather
than merely using them as a privileged lens to view that history.
Notes
1. Terry Eagleton, Against the Grain: Essays 1975–1985 (London: New Left Books,
1986), pp. 81–82.
2. Terry Eagleton, Walter Benjamin or Towards a Revolutionary Criticism (London:
New Left Books, 1981), p. 97.
3. Terry Eagleton, Literary Theory: An Introduction (Oxford and Minnesota:
Blackwell/University of Minnesota Press, 1983), p. 211. Hereafter cited as LT.
246
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
4. Terry Eagleton, After Theory (Harmondsworth: Allen Lane and Penguin, 2003),
pp. 221–222.
5. This treatment of Freud’s life is based on his own account, “An Autobiographical
Study” (1925), in The Freud Reader, ed. Peter Gay (New York and London:
W. W. Norton, 1989). Hereafter cited as Freud.
6. Quoted by Peter Gay in Freud, p. 444.
7. C. H. Dodd, The Interpretation of the Fourth Gospel (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1953), pp. 284–285.
Chapter 17
The Era of Poststructuralism (II):
Postmodernism, Modern
Feminism, Gender Studies
The term “postmodernism” resonates in at least three registers: firstly, in the
context of historical development, it appears as “postmodernity,” designating the latest phase in the broad evolution of capitalist economics and culture,
especially since the later part of the twentieth century. This historical
phenomenon has generated two further registers: that of postmodern theory,
which has attempted to account for and explain it; and that of literature
and art, which has variously attempted to express it. In the sphere of literary
and cultural theory, the terms “postmodern” and “postmodernism” have
been applied to the works of numerous writers, such as Jacques Derrida,
Julia Kristeva, and Michel Foucault, who have also been labeled
“poststructuralist.” Postmodernism might be viewed as a broader phenomenon, one of whose manifestations is poststructuralism. Alternatively, the
two terms might be viewed as two perspectives from which to view the history
of modern literary and cultural criticism. The major theorists of postmodernism have included Jean-François Lyotard, Jean Baudrillard, and Georges
Bataille, whose work enjoyed a revival in the 1960s. Left-wing perspectives
on postmodernism have been offered by J€
urgen Habermas, Fredric Jameson,
and Terry Eagleton. Finally, in the register of literature and art,
“postmodernism” has been used by critics such as Ihab Hassan to distinguish
the experimental literature produced after World War II from the high
modernism of the period roughly between 1910 and 1930. We can now
briefly look at each of these three senses of the postmodern.
In the register of historical development, postmodernity designates a
society and culture that has evolved beyond the phases of industrial and
finance capitalism. This society is often called consumer capitalism, a phase
characterized by the global extension of capitalist markets, mass migration of
labor, the predominating role of mass media and images, unprecedented
economic and cultural interaction between various parts of the world, and an
unprecedented pluralism and diversity at all levels of culture. According to
Literary Criticism from Plato to the Present: An Introduction
© 2011 M. A. R. Habib. ISBN: 978-1-405-16034-6
M. A. R. Habib
248
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
many of the theorists of postmodernism, this contemporary social order is no
longer based on, or even attempts to pursue, the Enlightenment ideals of
progress and justice based on universal reason, a notion of human subjectivity
as autonomous, and of the world as knowable (and conquerable) by scientific
and technological advance. Rather, the external world is viewed as an
ideological construction, refracted through an endlessly circulating world
of signs, through media images and the various technologies and institutional
codes (of school, workplace, religious centers) that hold us in their sway. Even
subjectivity itself is regarded as a product of power structures; power is no
longer viewed as an isolable and centralized agency that dominates or coerces
subjects that are already there: rather, it is intimately involved in the very
production of subjectivities which are then conditioned to regulate themselves. Just as the worlds of objective reality and unified autonomous
subjectivity have been dissolved, dissipated through the linguistic and social
structures and semiotic codes that ultimately form and define them, so too the
conventional worlds of morality and culture are viewed as without absolute
foundations and grounded in human desire, material need, a libidinal
economy, and self-projection. Reason itself is viewed as integral to capitalism, as coercive and exclusive, a faculty used to label alternative visions as
mad or irrational; even the category of “experience” as used by the bourgeois
philosophers has become suspect, as well as their understanding of fundamental notions such as space and time. Many radical critics entering the
debates over postmodernism no longer hold the conventional Marxist view of
the economic infrastructure and class struggle as the ultimate determinants of
social development: instead, language, images, and the entire cultural sphere
are all viewed as crucial to the social and political order, with economics
reduced to one of several determinative elements in a complex of causes. In this
scenario, literature and art are given a high role in impugning the existing
orders of capitalism. Culture itself becomes viewed as a site of ideological
struggle. Some Marxists, however, would argue that Marxism itself comprehends the interaction of cultural and economic elements, and that the subsumption of economics into the cultural sphere or superstructure – a kind of
“superstructuralism” which collapses the terms of conventional Marxist
analysis – is itself an ideological strategy of late capitalism.
In general, postmodern and postmodernism denote a contemporary economic and cultural situation, and a series of perspectives, where the major
grand narratives of the recent past – such as the progress of humanity toward
knowledge and freedom – no longer command credibility, and lie in ruins.
The universal has given way to the local, identity has yielded to difference,
depth (the notion of an underlying reality) has given way to a world of
surfaces or mere appearances, and reality is submerged in, and indeed defined
by, a world of signs. What has been called the “crisis of representation” – the
inability of language to represent reality – reverberates through all of these
Postmodernism, Modern Feminism, Gender Studies
249
positions. And all of these positions are shared by postmodernism and
poststructuralism. We might add that this so-called crisis – like most of the
“crises” identified by poststructuralism – is hardly new; it was recognized by
Locke and the bourgeois philosophers, including Hegel and the neo-Hegelian
philosophers such Bradley and Bosanquet. The reaffirmation of such crises
highlights the roots (radices) of these “radical” modes of thought in the liberal
humanist tradition, in the very mode of their reaction against which they
reveal themselves as variants, at once gesturally subversive and substantively
complicit.
The third register of postmodernism, that of literature and the arts, can be
dealt with briefly here. The work of the high modernists, such as Proust,
Joyce, T. S. Eliot, Pound, Virginia Woolf, Kafka, and Brecht, was characterized by a number of underlying assumptions: a recognition of the complex
nature of reality and experience, of the role of time and memory in human
perception, of the self and world as historical constructions, and, underlying
all of these, the problematic nature of language. In terms of style, the
modernists engaged in a breakdown of narrative structures and conventional
poetic forms, the use of allusion, parody, hyperbole, collage, and pastiche.
Postmodernism, as expressed in the writings of Beckett, Robbe-Grillet,
Borges, Marquez, Naguib Mahfouz, and Angela Carter, also rests on the
same assumptions and exhibits the same characteristics.
What, then, is the difference between modernism and postmodernism? We
can perhaps identify three salient features which differentiate them. Firstly,
postmodernism – in both subject matter and style – is marked by a recognition
of ethnic, sexual, and cultural diversity. Whereas modernist texts like Conrad’s Heart of Darkness could only describe the other (in this case, Africans)
from the outside, postmodernist works tend to give the other a voice,
to analyze cultural difference from within (as in the work of Mahfouz).
Secondly, whereas high modernism (with exceptions such as Brecht) prided
itself on its highbrow status and learned allusions, postmodernism – with
equal self-consciousness – deliberately extends into the domain of popular
culture, abrogating distinctions between high and low art, and indeed often
attempting to expose the structures of cultural coercion and domination.
T. S. Eliot’s “The Love Song of J. Alfred Prufrock” may subvert the form and
content of a love song and exhibit the painful, unidealized nature of love in the
modern world; but some later poets from the Indian subcontinent such as
N. M. Rashed and Kishwar Naheed express a colonial condition where the
very possibility of love is withered.
Finally, postmodernist writing unabashedly exhibits difference, diversity,
incoherence, and a world of surfaces, with no attempt to subsume these
under identity, a framework of coherence or depth, or any vision of implied
unity. Heterogeneity is presented as irreducible, recalcitrant to any form of
redintegration. With modernism, difference is still rooted in identity,
250
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
experimentation in tradition, and relativism in the memory of various
absolutes. Even stylistic innovations such as free verse or disruptions of
narrative were haunted by the ghosts of the forms that lurked behind them.
T. S. Eliot’s The Waste Land, supposedly an expression of a fragmented
world marooned from the past, relies heavily on allusions which point to a
retrospective unity in traditional forms of life; Joyce’s Ulysses insinuates
a coherence in its use of the Odyssey as an implied background. But a
postmodernist work such as Beckett’s Waiting for Godot exhibits no structure in its allusions, which are random and repetitive, and where the “action”
of the play defies the very category of action (and of the dramatic unities) and
its location is entirely abstract and unnameable. The only possible modes of
coherence are those that the reader or audience might impose, bringing to
bear their own assumptions and effectively writing or rewriting the play
themselves. Where modernism is nostalgic and retrospective toward vanished
schemes of unity and order, postmodernism insists on the heterogeneity of
the present. We can now look briefly at some of the major theorists of
postmodernism, beginning with a thinker whose opposition to postmodernism inspired much debate.
J€
urgen Habermas (b. 1929)
The work of the German philosopher and sociologist J€
urgen Habermas has
spanned social theory, the genesis of capitalism, and the meanings of
democracy, rationality, and law. He is best known for his account of the
“public sphere” or the elements of the public world not directly under state
control but open to the exchange of private opinion, as in the various levels of
media, religious organizations, and social gatherings. Though he was for
some time associated with the Frankfurt School of Marxist social and cultural
theory, the main impetus of Habermas’ work has been a defense of modern
liberal democracy and its theorization in the Enlightenment ideals of reason,
justice, progress, and freedom. Against poststructuralist opponents who
claim that reason is relative, coercive, and exclusive, he formulates a notion
of “communicative reason,” of a rationality grounded in the very process
of communication, on the basis of which “communicative action” will
be possible.
In a lecture of 1980 entitled “Modernity – An Incomplete Project” (later
published as “Modernity Versus Postmodernity”), Habermas observes that
the Enlightenment philosophers saw the arts and sciences as promoting
understanding of the world, the self, moral progress, and justice.1 But since
the mid-nineteenth century, art has become regarded as increasingly autonomous and devoid of reference to any real world, immersed rather in
self-reference. This tendency reaches new intensity in poststructuralism
Postmodernism, Modern Feminism, Gender Studies
251
(MP, 133). We can remedy this situation, says Habermas, only by redintegrating the aesthetic with the cognitive and the moral-practical (MP, 134).
We should reject the exclusive focus on aesthetic concerns which excludes
consideration of truth and justice, and which tempts us, mistakenly, to
denounce the surviving Enlightenment tradition as rooted in a “terroristic
reason” (MP, 135).
Jean Baudrillard (1929–2007)
The sociologist Jean Baudrillard has sometimes been called the high priest or
prophet of postmodernism. Baudrillard was teaching at the University of
Paris at Nanterre in 1968, and so was at the heart of the student unrest and
revolt of that era, a phenomenon which (largely through its failure) deeply
influenced his outlook. His early work, such as The System of Objects (1968)
and The Consumer Society (1970), was broadly Marxist in orientation. But
a further study, The Mirror of Production (1973), was highly critical of
Marx, viewing his analysis of capital as insufficiently radical and trapped
within the very categories of capitalism (such as “production”). This criticism
was continued in Baudrillard’s own assessment of capitalist economics in
Symbolic Exchange and Death (1976), and subsequent collections such as
Simulations (1983).
The underlying theme running through Baudrillard’s analyses of modern
culture and society is that “reality” has in the late capitalist era been replaced
by codes of signification. What we are witnessing now is a “precession of
simulacra,” a series of images which do not even claim to represent reality but
offer themselves in its place: “Simulation . . . is the generation by models of a
real without origin or reality: a hyperreal.” What we have inherited is the
“desert of the real itself.”2 And with this has also disappeared the entire
subject matter of metaphysics, its quest to define reality (S., 3). There is no
longer a question of imitating or even parodying reality: “it is rather a
question of substituting signs of the real for the real itself” (S., 4). A perfect
model of such simulation is Disneyland, which exists to conceal the fact that it
is the real, infantilized, America which is Disneyland: America itself is “no
longer real, but of the order of the hyperreal and of simulation” (S., 23–25).
The tendencies Baudrillard describes are even more pronounced today: the
infantilism has deepened its grip to all kinds of game shows, cartoon movies
whose audience is just as much adults as children, and, indeed, the
manufacture of entire political and social visions through the news media,
in their coverage of war, other nations, education, and a host of social and
ethical issues.
In The System of Objects Baudrillard argues that the ideology of competition has shifted from the sphere of production to the sphere of
252
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
consumption.3 The “philosophers of consumption,” such as Dichter and
Martineau, claim that this “new humanism” of consumption offers individuals an opportunity for fulfillment and liberation, and the ability to feel
moral even as they indulge in a hedonistic morality, even as they regress to
childlike and irrational behavior, thereby releasing drives that were blocked
by guilt, superego, or taboo (SO, 185). In industrial society, it is the system
of objects (not human relations or needs) that imposes its own coherence on
and structures an entire society (SO, 188).
Jean-Fran¸cois Lyotard (1924–1998)
Like Baudrillard, Jean-François Lyotard was at the University of Nanterre
during the student revolt of 1968, and he was also an activist against French
imperialism in Algeria. He deeply opposed J€
urgen Habermas’ sanction of the
project of Enlightenment, universal reason, and modernity. Lyotard’s reaction against Marxism in Starting from Marx and Freud (1973) expressed the
misgivings of much poststructuralist thought toward Marxist categories of
analysis. For example, Lyotard saw the function of social class as displaced
by modern technocratic and bureaucratic regimes. He saw capitalism and
totalitarianism as suppressing what he called the “libidinal economy” of
desire, and saw the task of experimental art as revolutionary in releasing
desire. Lyotard is perhaps best known for his work The Postmodern Condition (1979). In the preface to this, he suggests that the term “postmodern”
designates the state of our culture after the transformation of the sciences,
literature, and the arts since the end of the nineteenth century.4 Modern
science, he says, needs to legitimate its own rules by a discourse of legitimation, a metadiscourse which appeals to some “grand narrative,” such as the
emancipation of the human subject in terms of reason or economics, or the
creation of wealth (he sees the two modern grand narratives as liberal
humanism and Marxism). These came out of the Enlightenment narrative
of rationality which Lyotard views as coercive. Indeed, he defines postmodern
as “incredulity toward metanarratives.” Postmodern knowledge, Lyotard
suggests, “is not simply a tool of the authorities; it refines our sensitivity
to differences and reinforces our ability to tolerate the incommensurable”
(PC, xxv). Lyotard suggests that the postmodern artist is like a philosopher,
seeking new foundations. In fact, a work can become modern only by first
being postmodern: it must break the rules and seek a new grounding
(PC, 77–81).
In another article called “Defining the Postmodern,” Lyotard characterizes
modernity in general as a principle of breaking with the past and beginning
“a new way of living and thinking.” He cites three attributes of postmodernity. Firstly, it no longer appeals to “the idea of progress,” and in terms of
Postmodernism, Modern Feminism, Gender Studies
253
style it employs bricolage or collections of quotations from previous styles
and periods.5 A second feature is loss of belief in the idea that the arts,
technology, and liberty can be profitable to mankind as a whole (“DP,” 2).
Finally, it is expressed in literature and art by an investigation of the
foundations and presuppositions of modernity itself (“DP,” 3).
bell hooks (Gloria Jean Watkins; b. 1952)
Another important critique of postmodern theory has issued from AfricanAmerican critics such as Cornel West and bell hooks, who have observed that,
for all its emphasis on difference, postmodern theory has ignored the work of
black writers and intellectuals. hooks (who writes her name in lower case to
direct emphasis to the substance of her books rather than her self) is a feminist
scholar and activist who has produced much work on the intersections of
gender, race, and class. In her essay “Postmodern Blackness,” hooks argues
that postmodernist discourses have been exclusionary and are dominated by
white male voices.6 A radical postmodernist practice should incorporate the
voices of oppressed blacks, and the politics of difference should be integrated
with the politics of racism (RGCP, 25). Postmodernism’s critique of identity
politics comes at a time when black people are just coming to consciousness of
their identity, and are in the process of forming a radical black subjectivity
(RGCP, 28).
hooks stresses that postmodernity is a social and economic condition.
She observes that even in the era of postmodernity the collective AfricanAmerican condition is one of “continued displacement, profound alienation,
and despair” (RGCP, 26). This hopelessness creates a “yearning” which, at
its profoundest, is a “longing for critical voice,” intensified by postmodern
deconstruction of master narratives (RGCP, 27). Hence, postmodernism’s
critique of essentialism can be useful to black studies in a number of ways: by
promoting the notion of multiple black identities and experiences, by resisting
colonial paradigms of a monolithic black identity, and by seeing the connections of race with issues such as class mobility. In general, the critique of
essentialism needs to be harmonized with an emphasis on the “authority of
experience” (RGCP, 29).
Modern Feminism
Like most critical tendencies since the 1960s, modern feminism is distinguished from its precursors by having been forged in the same fire as much
poststructuralist thought, questioning fixed and stable notions of gender,
sexuality, and even the category of “woman.” It has, moreover, moved into
254
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
further areas of inquiry such as the connections of gender with class and race,
power structures, the semiotic codes through which ideology operates, and
the construction of subjectivity itself. The rich flowering of feminist thinking
in America, Britain, and France, each with its specific areas of emphasis, can
be considered in the following sections.
American feminism
Feminist criticism in America received a major stimulus from the civil
rights movement of the 1960s, and has differed somewhat in its concerns
from its counterparts in France and Britain. A seminal work, The Feminine
Mystique (1963), was authored by Betty Friedan, who subsequently
founded the National Organization of Women in 1966. This book expressed the fundamental grievance of middle-class American women, their
entrapment within private, domestic life and their inability to pursue public
careers. A number of other important feminist texts were produced around
this time: Mary Ellman’s Thinking About Women (1968), Kate Millett’s
Sexual Politics (1969), Germaine Greer’s The Female Eunuch (1970), and
Shulamith Firestone’s The Dialectic of Sex (1970), which used gender
rather than class as the prime category of historical analysis. Millett’s
influential book concerned female sexuality and the representation of
women in literature. It argued that patriarchy was a political institution;
it also distinguished between the concept of “sex,” which was rooted in
biology, and that of “gender,” which was culturally acquired. Other critics
examining masculine portrayals of women included Carolyn Heilbrun and
Judith Fetterly.
A number of feminist texts have attempted to identify alternative and
neglected traditions of female writing. These have included Patricia Meyer
Spacks’ The Female Imagination (1975), Ellen Moers’ Literary Women
(1976), and Sandra Gilbert and Susan Gubar’s The Madwoman in the Attic
(1979). The most influential work of this kind was Elaine Showalter’s
A Literature of their Own (1977), which traced three phases of women’s
writing, a “feminine” phase (1840–1880) where women writers imitated
male models, a “feminist” phase (1880–1920) during which women challenged those models and their values, and a “female” phase (from 1920)
which saw women advocating their own perspectives. Recent debates within
American feminism, conducted by figures such as Showalter, Lillian
Robinson, Annette Kolodny, and Jane Marcus, have concerned the relationship of female writers to male theories, the need for feminist theory and a
female language, the relation of feminism to poststructuralist perspectives, as
well as continuing problems of political and educational activism.
A notable recent development has been the attempt to think through
feminism from black and minority perspectives, as in Alice Walker’s
Postmodernism, Modern Feminism, Gender Studies
255
In Search of Our Mothers’ Gardens (1983) and Barbara Smith’s Toward a
Black Feminist Criticism (1977).
British feminism
Much British feminist criticism has had a political orientation, situating both
feminist concerns and literary texts within a material and ideological context.
In her landmark work Women: The Longest Revolution (1966), later
expanded into Women’s Estate (1971), Juliet Mitchell examined patriarchy
in terms of Marxist categories of production and private property as well as
psychoanalytic theories of gender. Her later works, such as Psychoanalysis
and Feminism (1974), continue to refine her attempt to integrate the insights
of Marxism and psychoanalysis. Another seminal text was Michele Barrett’s
Women’s Oppression Today: Problems in Marxist Feminist Analysis (1980),
which attempted to formulate a materialist aesthetics and integrated
Marxist class analysis with feminism in analyzing and influencing gender
representation.7 She focuses on three concepts that have been central to the
Marxist–feminist dialogue: patriarchy, reproduction, and ideology. According to Barrett, the most significant elements of the oppression of women under
capitalism are “the economic organization of households and its accompanying familial ideology, the division of labor and relations of production, the
educational system and the operations of the state,” as well as the processes of
creation and recreation of gendered subjects (WT, 40–41). Other works in
this vein include Judith Newton and Deborah Rosenfelt’s Feminist Criticism
and Social Change (1985), which also argues for feminist analysis that takes
account of social and economic contexts. Other important critics have
included Jacqueline Rose and Rosalind Coward, who has formulated a
materialist feminism, Catherine Belsey, who has assessed Renaissance drama
from a materialist feminist perspective, and Toril Moi, who has engaged in
a critique of the humanism and implicit essentialism of some American
feminists. Finally, a number of critics such as Cora Kaplan, Mary Jacobus,
and Penny Boumelha have comprised the UK Marxist-Feminist Collective,
formed in 1976.
French feminism
The impetus for much modern French feminism was drawn from the revolutionary atmosphere of May 1968 which saw massive unrest on the part of
students and workers. In that atmosphere, an integral component of political
revolution was seen as the transformation of signifying practices and conceptions of subjectivity, based on a radical understanding of the power of
language. Drawing somewhat on the ideas of Jacques Lacan and Jacques
Derrida, feminists such as Annie Leclerc, Marguerite Duras, Julia Kristeva,
256
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
Luce Irigaray, and Helene Cixous variously advanced a notion of l’ecriture
feminine, a feminine writing that would issue from the unconscious, the body,
from a radically reconceived subjectivity, in an endeavor to circumvent what
they held to be phallocentric discourse. For Kristeva, such language came
from a pre-Oedipal state, from the realm of the “semiotic,” prior to the
process of cultural gender formation. Luce Irigaray advocated undermining
patriarchal discourse from within, a strategy she pursues in her readings of
several discourses from Plato through Freud and Marx to Lacan. She indicates
that a feminine language would be more diffuse, like women’s sexuality, and
less rigidly categorizing than male discourse. Helene Cixous also sees a
“solidarity” between logocentrism and phallocentrism (where the phallus
is a signifier, a metaphor of male power and dominance), an alliance that must
be questioned and undermined. Women, she urged, must write their bodies,
to unfold the resources of the unconscious. All of these writers revaluate the
significance of the maternal, viewing this as empowering rather than as
oppressed. Other feminists, however, such as Christine Faure, Catherine
Clement, and Monique Wittig, have challenged this emphasis on the body as
biologically reductive, fetishistic, and politically impotent. Monique Wittig
wishes to do away with the linguistic categories of sex and gender. The
following section will consider briefly the work of two of the more difficult
but influential feminist thinkers, Julia Kristeva and Helene Cixous.
Julia Kristeva (b. 1941) Kristeva’s most influential work is Revolution in
Poetic Language (1974), where she distinguishes between two orders whose
interaction makes up the human subject: the “semiotic,” and the
“symbolic.”8 The “semiotic” consists of the pre-Oedipal drives and immediate surroundings of the body. Kristeva sees this as challenging the “ego of
conventional Western thought (RPL, 30). The “symbolic” encompasses the
emergence of subject and object as well as the constitution of meaning
structured according to social categories (RPL, 86).
Kristeva sees the arts as engaging a jouissance that threatens to disrupt the
symbolic order. She sees this potential especially in poetry and literature. This
“revolutionary” poetic language has a subversive potential inasmuch as it
threatens to reach back into the semiotic realm, to release energies and drives
that have been thwarted by the conventional structure of the symbolic,
disrupting the symbolic from within and reconceiving its notions of subject,
object, and their connections. In the signifying practices of late capitalism,
according to Kristeva, only certain avant-garde literary texts, such as those of
Mallarme and Joyce, have the ability to transgress the boundaries between
semiotic and symbolic; such texts can open up new possibilities of meaning,
new modes of signification. The text, therefore, is instrumental in social and
political change: it is the site where the explosive force of the semiotic realm
expresses itself (RPL, 103). She thus draws attention to the “social function of
Postmodernism, Modern Feminism, Gender Studies
257
texts: the production of a different kind of subject, one capable of bringing
about new social relations, and thus joining in the process of capitalism’s
subversion” (RPL, 105).
Helene Cixous (b. 1937) Helene Cixous’ peculiar contribution to feminism
was to promote ecriture feminine or feminine writing, as expressed in her
powerful manifesto “Le Rire de la Meduse” (“The Laugh of the Medusa”)
(1975). This text might be seen as structured like a poem in its implicit refusal
to engage with conventional rhetorical formats of argumentation and expository prose. While its themes – the need for a female writing, the nature of
such writing, and its momentous implications at both personal and societal
levels – are clear, these themes surface into prominence in Cixous’ text
through an almost poetic refrain, through patterns of recurrence, employing
the materiality of language, wordplay, and the metaphor of the Medusa.
This metaphor is not taken up until the middle of Cixous’ text, where,
addressing women (as she does throughout the text), she charges that men
have “riveted us between two horrifying myths: between the Medusa and the
abyss.”9 The “abyss” refers to Freud’s “myth,” his designation of woman as a
“dark continent,” pregnant with mystery and signifying lack, castration,
negativity, and dependence. And, countering the other myth, that of woman
as Medusa, she affirms: “You only have to look at the Medusa straight on
to see her. And she’s not deadly. She’s beautiful and she’s laughing”
(“LM,” 289). Why beautiful? And why laughing? For Cixous, laughter is
a way of exceeding the very notion of truth as defined by masculine traditions.
Cixous states that a “feminine text” is designed to “smash everything, to
shatter the framework of institutions, to blow up the law, to break up the
truth with laughter” (“LM,” 292).
Cixous exhorts women to bring to birth a female language, which acknowledges its rootedness in the body: “Write your self. Your body must be heard”
(“LM,” 284). The significance of “body” is far-reaching, since it is the body,
especially the female body, that has been repressed historically by male
theology and philosophy, social systems, and even psychoanalysis. Male
visions of the world have achieved the status of “theory” precisely by
abstracting from the data of actual experience, by withdrawing from the
world of the senses and the unconscious into an ideal world, whether of pure
forms, substance, the absolute idea, the transcendental ego, or the soul.
To write with the body implies facilitating a return of the repressed, a
resurrection of that which has been subordinated and treated and secondary,
as dirty, as weighing us down and preventing us from rising to the perception
of higher truths. Cixous suggests that, more “than men who are coaxed
toward social success, toward sublimation, women are body” (“LM,” 290).
Whereas Simone de Beauvoir had viewed the rootedness of woman’s experience in bodily functions as a kind of imprisonment within immanence,
258
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
Cixous regards woman’s greater attunement to bodily needs and drives as
potentially liberating.
Feminism has shown that individuality cannot be wholly abrogated; its
richness and uniqueness cannot be wholly left behind, in the process of
thinking through general concepts. As Cixous insists, “there is . . . no general
woman” and no “female sexuality” that might be “uniform, homogeneous,
classifiable into codes” (“LM,” 280). Hence the implications of a “new,”
feminine, writing will be momentous: “writing is precisely the very possibility
of change, the space that can serve as a springboard for subversive thought,
the precursory movement of a transformation of social and cultural
structures” (“LM,” 283).
Gender Studies
In general, gender studies includes feminist studies of gender, gay and lesbian
criticism, and queer theory. These fields often overlap considerably. Gender
studies is interdisciplinary in both its roots and its methods, having arisen in
literary and cultural theory, sociology, anthropology, and psychoanalysis.
It examines the oppressive history of gays, lesbians, and other erotic groups,
the formation and representation of gender, as well as gender as a category of
analysis of literature and culture, and the intersection of gender with divisions
of race, class, and color.
The birth of the gay rights movement in America is often traced to the
“Stonewall Riots” of 1969 in New York City, a prolonged conflict over
several days in which gays, transvestites, and other oppressed groups (of
various color and nationality) offered resistance against police raiding the
Stonewall Inn. Prior to this, especially just after World War II (a time when
young men were experimenting sexually), a number of gay and other erotic
communities had taken root in the margins of big cities such as New York,
San Francisco, and Los Angeles. This led to a series of repressions in the
1950s. But during the 1960s, even before Stonewall, policies toward gays had
relaxed somewhat, and as gays assumed a certain solidarity and political
identity, further liberalization followed during the early 1970s, after which
further backlashes erupted, in terms of both legal enactments and popular
feeling. The effect of such repression was partly to solidify the alternative
erotic communities, who self-consciously struggled in the political sphere to
achieve a voice, and to achieve self-definition in theoretical terms. Even prior
to the Stonewall Riots, gay self-consciousness emerged in many aspects of
culture: in the history of literature, where figures such as Walt Whitman,
Walter Pater, Oscar Wilde, members of the Bloomsbury Group with its ethic
of androgyny, and the 1930s poets W. H. Auden, Christopher Isherwood, and
Stephen Spender had variously articulated their sexuality; in the novels of
Postmodernism, Modern Feminism, Gender Studies
259
James Baldwin and Gore Vidal, which portrayed homosexual relations and
encounters; in leading personalities of pop art such as Andy Warhol and
Jasper Johns; and in pornography.
By the early 1970s, gay studies were beginning to proliferate and to achieve
a theoretical self-consciousness. In 1974 an issue of College English was
devoted to the questions of gay identity and formulating a gay literary
tradition. Just as women’s studies established the importance of gender as
a fundamental category of analysis, so lesbian/gay studies aims to establish
the analytic centrality of sex and sexuality in several fields. The overlap
between gay/lesbian studies and women’s studies is a matter of continuing
debate. Like women’s studies, lesbian/gay studies are informed by the “social
struggle for . . . sexual liberation” and personal freedom, as well as by
resistance to homophobia and heterosexism or the “ideological and institutional practices of heterosexual privilege.”10 Some of the important early gay
and lesbian scholars include: Guy Hocquengham, who analyzed the psychological motivations of homophobia; the gay historian Jeffrey Weeks, who has
analyzed the history of homosexuality in Britain in relation to nineteenthcentury sexual ideologies; the scholar K. J. Dover, who published his
celebrated study Greek Homosexuality in 1978; Lillian Faderman, who
studied lesbianism in the Renaissance; and Terry Castle, who conducted
wide-ranging studies of the lesbian presence in Western literary history.
Gender studies has its roots partly in feminist theory, and, indeed, was until
the 1980s associated with the feminist enterprise, until lesbian critics such as
Bonnie Zimmerman attacked the implicit feminist assumption that there
was some essential female identity underlying differences of race, class, and
sexuality. Some critics, such as those associated with the Radicalesbian
collective, whose manifesto was “The Woman-Identified Woman” (1970),
urged the need for a field of inquiry distinct from mainstream feminism, which
had marginalized lesbianism. They saw lesbianism as the purest feminism
since it asserted female autonomy and refused complicity with all forms of
masculinist exploitation. Jill Johnston’s Lesbian Nation (1973) saw lesbianism as the “solution” for feminism. The lesbian feminist poet and theorist
Adrienne Rich also affirmed lesbianism as a kind of archetypal image of the
broad feminist endeavor, and also urged a dissociation of lesbian from
male gay allegiances. In an influential and controversial essay entitled
“Compulsory heterosexuality and lesbian existence” (1980), she introduced
the idea of a “lesbian continuum” to denote a range of experiences between
women, including mutual practical and political support, bonding against
male tyranny, and sharing a rich inner life. Separatist lesbianism was
also advocated by the Chicana lesbian poet and critic Gloria Anzaldua in
Borderlands – La Frontera: The New Mestiza (1987) and by Monique Wittig
in her essay “The Straight Mind” (1980), as well as by Luce Irigaray’s This
Sex Which Is Not One (1977), which urged the autonomous existence of
260
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
lesbians. During the 1970s the separatist modes of lesbian theory grew,
helped by the development of women’s studies programs. This era saw the
beginnings of an attempt to integrate issues of sexuality, gender, and race. In
her powerful essay “Toward a Black Feminist Criticism” (1977), Barbara
Smith offered a controversial lesbian interpretation of Toni Morrison’s Sula.
Much of this earlier work aimed to deconstruct stereotypes of lesbians as
unnatural or sexless, and to redeem a hitherto neglected tradition of lesbian
thought and writing, as well as reinterpreting “conventional” figures such as
Emily Dickinson and Virginia Woolf. It was underlain by certain assumptions: that there was a definable lesbian identity, and that there was an
analyzable category of lesbian experience.
A more radical kind of approach, known as queer theory (a derisive term
subversively adopted as a positive designation), emerged in the 1990s,
grounded in a Conference on Queer Theory at the University of California,
Santa Cruz. Queer theory was imbued with many of the anti-essentialist
assumptions of poststructuralism, especially the undermining of any fixed
sexual identity, viewing identity as a subject position created by cultural and
ideological codes. It more clearly emphasized sexuality rather than gender in
the formation of identity. Indeed, the lines of allegiance were also shifted
from gender to sexual orientation: lesbian theorists now identified with the
theorizing of gay men rather than with straight women. But much of this
theory, as in work by Diana Fuss, Judith Butler, and Eve Sedgwick, attempts
to deconstruct any absolute distinction between hetero- and homo-sexuality.
Lee Edelman’s Homographesis (1994) deconstructed the notion of gay
identity. Much queer theory, such as Simon Watney’s Policing Desire
(1987) and Donna Haraway’s “The Biopolitics of Postmodern Bodies”
(1989), attempted to analyze the AIDS epidemic in the late 1980s and its
presentation in the media. Other queer theorists such as Michael Moon drew
attention to the “queer” attributes of what presumed to be sexual normality.
The American photographer Robert Mapplethorpe stirred public controversy,
related to government funding for art, with his homoerotic, sadistic, and
masochistic photographs which aimed to exhibit gay sexuality. Later gay and
lesbian theory also attempted to cast attention on writers from other cultural
backgrounds such as Garcia Lorca and Yukio Mishima.11 Gender theory
continues to debate issues of sexuality and its relation to power structures. The
following section will briefly consider the work of three of the pioneers in this
field: Gayle Rubin, Eve Kosofsky Sedgwick, and Judith Butler.
Gayle Rubin (b. 1949)
A feminist anthropologist, Gayle Rubin has produced influential studies of
gender, her work embracing anthropological theory, lesbian literature,
sadomasochism, and feminism. In her early essay “The Traffic in Women”
Postmodernism, Modern Feminism, Gender Studies
261
(1975), she originated the expression “sex/gender system” whereby she saw
sex – spanning gender identity, fantasy, and notions of childhood – as itself a
social product. In a later essay, “Thinking Sex: Notes for a Radical Theory of
the Politics of Sexuality” (1984), she made an influential new distinction
between gender and sexuality. She acknowledged that feminism was a potent
theory of gender oppression. But this must be incorporated into a radical
theory of sex which explains sexual oppression (she points out that lesbians
are persecuted on account not just of their gender but also of their sexual
orientation).12 In general, she argues in this essay that, like gender, sexuality is
political, and that the modern sexual system has been the object of political
struggle. Industrialization and urbanization have led to a reorganization of
family relations and gender roles, enabling the formation of new identities
and new erotic communities such as gays, transsexuals, and transvestites
(LGR, 16, 34).
Rubin urges that a radical theory of sex must explain and denounce erotic
injustice and oppression. Some of the obstacles to its formation include:
sexual essentialism, the idea – fostered by medicine and psychoanalysis – that
sexuality is somehow natural, standing above time, context, and history;
sexual negativity, the idea that sexuality is a dangerous and destructive force;
and the notion of a sexual hierarchy which ranges from acts which are
permissible, through questionable acts to those considered with extreme
contempt. Underlying this hierarchy is the notion of a single, ideal sexuality
(LGR, 35).
Eve Kosofsky Sedgwick (b. 1950)
An American critic and poet, Eve Kosofsky Sedgwick has produced pioneering work in the field of gender studies, especially in queer theory. Her major
works include Between Men: English Literature and Male Homosocial
Desire (1985), Epistemology of the Closet (1990), Tendencies (1993),
A Dialogue on Love (1999), and Touching Feeling (2003). In general,
Sedgwick aims to show that the discourses of gender and sexuality, usually
confined to a narrow ghettoized mode of analysis, are not marginal but
integral to Western culture, and to the operations of power, race, and class.
Indeed, in Between Men, she argues that all human culture is structured by
the “drama of gender difference.”13 She defines the term “homosocial” as
denoting “social bonds between persons of the same sex” (BM, 1).
Sedgwick’s basic purpose is to analyze male homosocial bonds “through
the heterosexual European erotic ethos,” and to reconcile historicist Marxist
approaches, using ideology as an analytic category, with structuralist feminist perspectives in the analysis of sexuality (BM, 16). In general, Sedgwick’s
work shows the sheer fluidity of the distinctions between homosexuality
and heterosexuality, as well as the contextual and indeterminate and
262
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
contingent nature of both gender and sexuality. What counts as “sexual” or
“homosexual” can vary.
Judith Butler (b. 1956)
Judith Butler’s Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion of Identity
(1990) is arguably the most important book in the field of gender studies.
Her central argument is that what we call gender is not an inherent fact or
attribute of human nature but a performance, a cultural performance composed of signifying gestures.14 The effect of Butler’s work, in deconstructing
the category of woman, has been to distinguish lesbian studies from feminism.
She argues that the very concept of woman, the starting point of much
feminism, is not stable but produced by power structures and intersects
intimately with race, class, politics, and culture (GT, 1–3, 128).
In the most brilliant section of her book, Butler argues that the body itself is
shaped by political forces. Both the distinction between sex and gender and
the category of sex itself presuppose that there exists a somehow neutral body
prior to its sexual signification. Indeed the tradition of Christianity saw the
body as a non-entity, as a “profane void,” signifying a fallen state. Equally,
Cartesian dualism (between mind and matter) saw the body as so much inert
matter, attached to the thinking essence of the human. Even the existentialism
of Sartre and de Beauvoir viewed the body as “mute facticity.” Nietzsche and
Foucault, too, saw the body as a surface or blank page on which cultural
values were inscribed. In all these cases, materiality and the body are assumed
to exist prior to signification: not only is the body indifferent to signification,
but signification (as in Descartes’ dualism) is the act of a disembodied
consciousness. The body is simply regarded as external to the signifying
process, which is the province of the thinking mind (GT, 129–130).
It is cultural norms, urges Butler, that maintain the boundaries of the body,
which is not a being but a surface, a signifying practice within a field of gender
hierarchy and compulsory heterosexuality (GT, 139). There is no essence of
gender: it is generated by repeated acts. This performative character of gender
opens up performative possibilities for gender configurations “outside the
restricting frames of masculinist domination and compulsory heterosexuality” (GT, 140–141). Butler’s powerful critique of the notions of
identity and body on which gender is constructed is an important step toward
reconfiguring the performative potential of gender.
Notes
1. This lecture is reprinted in Modernism/Postmodernism, ed. Peter Brooker
(London and New York: Longman, 1992), p. 132. Hereafter cited as MP.
Postmodernism, Modern Feminism, Gender Studies
263
2. Jean Baudrillard, Simulations, trans. Paul Foss, Paul Patton, and Philip Beitchman
(New York: Semiotext[e], 1983), p. 2. Hereafter cited as S.
3. Jean Baudrillard, The System of Objects, trans. James Benedict (London and
New York: Verso, 1996), p. 183. Hereafter cited as SO.
4. Jean-François Lyotard, The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge,
trans. Geoff Bennington and Brian Massumi (Minneapolis: University of
Minnesota Press, 1989), p. xxxiii. Hereafter cited as PC.
5. Jean-François Lyotard, “Defining the Postmodern,” p. 1. This article can easily be
accessed online at: http://qcpages.qc.edu/ENGLISH/Staff/richter/Lyotard.htm.
Hereafter cited as “DP.”
6. This essay is contained in bell hooks, Yearning: race, gender, and cultural politics
(Boston: South End Press, 1990), p. 23. Hereafter cited as RGCP.
7. Michele Barrett, Women’s Oppression Today: The Marxist/Feminist Encounter
(London and New York: Verso, 1980), p. 8. Hereafter cited as WT.
8. Julia Kristeva, Revolution in Poetic Language, trans. Margaret Waller
(New York: Columbia University Press, 1984), p. 24. Hereafter cited as RPL.
9. Helene Cixous, “The Laugh of the Medusa,” trans. Keith Cohen and Paula
Cohen, in The Signs Reader: Women, Gender, and Scholarship, ed. Elizabeth
Abel and Emily K. Abel (Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press,
1983), p. 289. Hereafter cited as “LM.”
10. Henry Abelove, Michele Aina Barale, and David M. Halperin, eds.,
“Introduction,” in The Lesbian and Gay Studies Reader (London and New York:
Routledge, 1993), p. xvi. Hereafter cited as LGR.
11. This account is indebted to an excellent article on “Gay Theory and Criticism” by
Richard Dellamora and Bonnie Zimmerman in The Johns Hopkins Guide to
Theory and Criticism, ed. Michael Groden and Martin Kreiswirth (Baltimore and
London: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1994), pp. 324–331.
12. Gayle Rubin, “Thinking Sex,” in LGR, pp. 32–34. This article was first published
in Pleasure and Danger, ed. Carole Vance (London and New York: Routledge,
1984).
13. Eve Kosofsky Sedgwick, Between Men: English Literature and Male Homosocial
Desire (New York: Columbia University Press, 1985), p. 11. Hereafter cited as
BM.
14. Judith Butler, Gender Trouble (New York and London: Routledge, 1990), p. x.
Hereafter cited as GT.
Chapter 18
The Later Twentieth Century:
New Historicism, ReaderResponse Theory, Postcolonial
Criticism, Cultural Studies
In the 1980s, the political mood in both Europe and America swung to the
right. The increasingly unchallenged predominance of capitalism in the 1980s
and 1990s oversaw the emergence of New Historicism, which called for the
literary text to be situated not, as in Marxist criticism, within the context of an
economic infrastructure, but within a superstructural fabric of political and
cultural discourses, with the economic dimension itself given no priority. One
of the prime influences on New Historicism was Michel Foucault, who saw
knowledge as a form of power and analyzed power as highly diffused and as
not distinctly assignable to a given set of political or ideological agencies.
Another approach that attained prominence during these decades was readerresponse theory, whose roots went back to the reception theories of the
German writers Hans Robert Jauss and Wolfgang Iser, as well as to Wayne
Booth’s The Rhetoric of Fiction (1961). This perspective recognized the
dialogical nature of textual production, redefining the meaning of the “text”
as the product of an interaction between text and an appropriately qualified
community of readers. It could be argued that both the New Historicism and
reader-response theory represented a return of the literary and cultural critic
to political non-commitment in a newer and more fashionable guise – laden
with all the trimmings of poststructuralist terminology – in which liberal
humanist notions of pluralism, tolerance, and claims to political neutrality
could stride once more on the academic stage.
The 1990s saw the concerted growth of two critical tendencies that were
inextricably political. One was postcolonial studies, whose roots can be
traced back through Edward Said’s landmark work Orientalism (1978) to
writers such as Frantz Fanon and Aime Cesaire, who were directly engaged in
struggles against colonialism. The other was ethnic studies, inspired largely
by critics such as Henry Louis Gates. In general, both postcolonial and ethnic
Literary Criticism from Plato to the Present: An Introduction
© 2011 M. A. R. Habib. ISBN: 978-1-405-16034-6
M. A. R. Habib
The Later Twentieth Century
265
studies engage in a broad redefinition of terms – such as identity, gender,
sexuality, and power – that had already undergone a radical critique in the
works of feminist and, more generally, poststructuralist, thinkers. These
studies insisted on examining such terms in the altered contexts of colonial
and racial oppression. For example, it was held that the insights of white,
middle-class feminism did not apply universally over diverse races and
cultures. Each of these approaches can now be considered briefly.
The New Historicism
Historicism began toward the end of the eighteenth century with German
writers such as Herder, and continued through the nineteenth-century historians Von Ranke and Meinecke to twentieth-century thinkers such as
Wilhelm Dilthey, R. G. Collingwood, Hans Georg Gadamer, Ernst Cassirer,
and Karl Mannheim. Powerful historical modes of analysis were formulated
by Hegel and Marx, who themselves had a profound impact on historicist
thinking; and literary historians such as Sainte-Beuve and Hippolyte Taine
also insisted on viewing literary texts as integrally informed by their historical
milieux. Much of what passes under the rubric of the “New” Historicism is
not new, but represents a return to certain foci of analysis as developed by
previous traditions of historicism.
Historicism has been characterized by a number of features. Most fundamentally, there is an insistence that all systems of thought, all phenomena, all
institutions, all works of art, and all literary texts must be situated within
a historical perspective. They cannot be somehow torn from history and
analyzed in isolation since they are determined in both their form and content
by their specific historical circumstances, their specific situation in time and
place. Hence, we cannot bring to our analyses of Shakespeare the same
assumptions and methods that we bring to Plato. A second feature of
historicism is that history is sometimes held (as by Hegel and Marx) to
operate according to certain identifiable laws, yielding a certain predictability
and explanatory power. A third concern arises from the recognition that
societies and cultures separated in time have differing values and beliefs: how
can the historian “know” the past? The historian operates within the horizon
of her own world view, a certain broad set of assumptions and beliefs; how
can she overcome these to achieve an empathetic understanding of a distant
culture? Thinkers such as Dilthey, Gadamer, and E. D. Hirsch have offered
various answers to this dilemma. Hirsch’s position aspires to be “objectivist,”
effectively denying the historical and context-bound nature of knowledge,
and proposing a distinction between “meaning,” which embraces what
the author meant or intended by his particular use of language, and
“significance,” which comprehends the subjective evaluation of the text
266
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
according to the values and beliefs of the critic. Gadamer proposed a notion
of “horizonfusion” whereby we acknowledge both that the “text” is in fact
a product of a tradition of interpretation (with no “original” meaning) and
that our own perspective is informed by the very past we are seeking to
analyze. Recognizing both of these limitations, we can begin to effect an
empathetic “fusion” of our own cultural horizon with that of the text.
The “New” Historicism, a term coined by Stephen Greenblatt in 1982,
became popular in the 1980s, reacting against both the formalist view of the
literary text as somehow autonomous and Marxist views which ultimately
related texts to the economic infrastructure. It saw the literary text as a kind of
discourse situated within a complex of cultural discourses – religious,
political, economic, aesthetic – which both shaped it, and in their turn, were
shaped by it. Perhaps what was new about this procedure was its insistence,
drawn from Foucault and poststructuralism, that “history” itself is a text, an
interpretation, and that there is no single history. It also rejected any notion of
historical progress or teleology, and broke away from any literary historiography based on the study of genres and figures. In the same way, the
“culture” in which New Historicism situated literary texts was itself regarded
as a textual construct. Hence, New Historicism refused to accord any kind of
unity or homogeneity to history or culture, viewing both as harboring
networks of contradictory, competing, and unreconciled forces and interests.
The language of Marxist economics gave way before Foucault’s terminology
of “power,” viewed as operating in diffuse ways without any definable
agency. The New Historicists tended, then, to view literature as one discourse
among many cultural discourses, insisting on engaging with this entire
complex in a localized manner, refusing to engage in categorical generalizations or to commit to any definite political stance. But some New
Historicists have seen literary texts as crucially participating in conflicts of
power.
In Britain, the New Historicist critics have identified themselves in
Raymond Williams’ terminology as “cultural materialists,” and have often
brought out the subversive potential of literature, especially in relation to the
Renaissance. Greenblatt’s own work has focused on this period, and critics
such as Jonathan Dollimore have produced groundbreaking studies, such as
Radical Tragedy (1984), which have reassessed the work of Shakespeare and
his contemporaries, recognizing the increasingly historical and ideological
functions of drama.1 The book Political Shakespeare, edited by Jonathan
Dollimore and Alan Sinfield, also challenged the liberal-humanist notion of
Shakespeare as a timeless and universal genius, emphasizing instead
Shakespeare’s subversion of authority, sexuality, and colonialism.2 Another
powerful reinterpretation was formulated in Alternative Shakespeares
(1985), in which a range of writers, including Catherine Belsey, Terence
Hawkes, Jacqueline Rose, John Drakakis, and Francis Barker challenged the
The Later Twentieth Century
267
liberal-humanist language of character analysis, artistic coherence, and
harmony. Instead, they drew attention to the manner in which Shakespeare’s
texts produce meaning, construct the human subject, and engage in larger
structural and ideological issues.3 Other critics such as Jerome McGann have
extended New Historical concerns into other historical periods such as
Romanticism. We can now look briefly at the work of Michel Foucault, the
primary influence on this critical tendency.
Michel Foucault (1926–1984)
Along with figures such as Derrida, Foucault has exerted an enormous
influence on many branches of thought in the later twentieth century,
including what is broadly known as “cultural studies.” He had a seminal
impact on queer theory. Born in France, the son of a physician, Foucault
criticized the institutions of medical practice in his first two publications,
Madness and Civilization (1961) and The Birth of the Clinic (1963). Indeed,
the central theme of most of Foucault’s works was the methods by which
modern civilization creates and controls human subjects, through institutions
such as hospitals, prisons, education, and knowledge; corollary to these
investigations was Foucault’s examination of power, its execution and
distribution. Foucault’s next works, The Order of Things (1966) and The
Archaeology of Knowledge (1969), offered a characterization of the growth
of knowledge in the modern Western world, as manifested in the emergence
of disciplines such as linguistics, economics, and biology. He elaborated
a historical scheme of three “epistemes” (outlooks underlying the institutional organization of knowledge) that characterized the Middle Ages, the
Enlightenment, and the modern world. Foucault’s essay “What is an
Author?” (1969) questions and examines the concept of authorship and, in
insights that were taken up by the New Historicism, argued that analysis of
literary texts could not be restricted to these texts themselves or to their
author’s psychology and background; rather, the larger contexts and cultural
conventions in which texts were produced needed to be considered. Subsequently, Foucault offered extended critiques respectively of the institutions of
the prison and of sexuality in Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison
(1975) and The History of Sexuality (1976).
In The History of Sexuality, Foucault’s investigation of the discourse on
sexuality is equally an investigation into the workings of power, which is seen
as more complex and subtle than a procedure of mere repression.4 New
methods of power, Foucault maintains, operate not “by right but by technique, not by law but by normalization, not by punishment but by control”
(HS, 87, 89). Foucault states that power is not “a group of institutions and
mechanisms that ensure the subservience of the citizens of a given state.” Nor
is it a “mode of subjugation” or a “general system of domination exerted by
268
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
one group over another . . . these are only the terminal forms that power
takes” (HS, 92). Nor must power be sought “in the primary existence of
a central point, in a unique source of sovereignty” (HS, 93). Moreover, “there
is no binary and all-encompassing opposition between rulers and ruled at the
root of power relations.” Nor is power something that is “acquired, seized, or
shared” (HS, 94).
What is it, then? According to Foucault, power must be understood as
a “multiplicity of force relations” (HS, 92). Foucault insists that power “is
everywhere; not because it embraces everything, but because it comes from
everywhere.” It is “simply the over-all effect that emerges from all these
mobilities” (HS, 93). A conventional Marxist critique of Foucault would
impugn his apparent removal of political agency from the operations of
power. Yet he characterizes power relations as “both intentional and nonsubjective.” He acknowledges that “there is no power that is exercised without
a series of aims and objectives. But this does not mean that it results from the
choice or decision of an individual subject” (HS, 94–95). He also concedes that
where “there is power, there is resistance, and yet . . . this resistance is never in
a position of exteriority in relation to power.” Foucault stresses that there is
“no single locus of great Refusal, no soul of revolt, source of all rebellions, or
pure law of the revolutionary. Instead there is a plurality of resistances, each of
them a special case” (HS, 95–96). What makes revolution possible, he claims,
is a “strategic codification of these points of resistance” (HS, 96).
Reader-Response and Reception Theory
Another critical approach that has proved widely congenial since the 1980s is
reader-response theory, with roots in earlier thinkers such as Husserl. The
role of the reader or audience of a literary work or performance has been
recognized since classical times. Many classical and medieval writers viewed
literature as a branch of rhetoric, the art of persuasive speaking or writing. As
such, literature had to be highly aware of the composition and expectations of
its audience. Subsequently, several Romantic theories stressed the powerful
emotional impact of poetry on the audience, and various later nineteenthcentury theories such as symbolism and impressionism stressed the reader’s
subjective response to literature and art. Marxism and feminism have long
acknowledged that literature, necessarily operating within social structures
of class and gender, is always orientated toward certain kinds of audiences, in
both aesthetic and economic terms. The hermeneutic theories developed by
Friedrich Schleiermacher, Martin Heidegger, Hans Georg Gadamer, as well
as the phenomenological theories inspired by Edmund Husserl, such as that of
Roman Ingarden, examined the ways in which readers engaged cognitively
and historically with literary texts.
The Later Twentieth Century
269
Hence, reader-response theory was not only a reaction against the
formalism and objectivism of the earlier twentieth century, but also
a renewal of a long tradition that had acknowledged the important role
of the reader or audience in any given literary or rhetorical situation. There
are elements of a reader-response outlook in the theoretical writings of
Virginia Woolf and Louise Rosenblatt. Wayne Booth was the author of an
influential work, The Rhetoric of Fiction (1961). His distinctions between
real author and the “implied author” who tells the story, between actual
reader and the “postulated reader” created by the text itself, and his critical
expressions such as “unreliable narrator,” became standard terms in analyzing fiction. All of these figures recognized that the author of a literary text
uses certain strategies to produce given effects in their readers or to guide
their responses. But it was not until the 1970s that a number of critics at the
University of Constance in Germany (the “Constance School”) began to
formulate a systematic reader-response or “reception” theory. The leading
members of this school were Wolfgang Iser (b. 1926) and Hans Robert
Jauss, whose aesthetics had their roots not only in the hermeneutic and
phenomenological traditions mentioned above but also in the earlier
thought of Alexander Baumgarten, Kant, and Friedrich von Schiller. One
of Jauss’ most important texts was “Literary History as a Challenge to
Literary Theory” (1969, 1970), where he urged that the history of a work’s
reception by readers played an integral role in the work’s aesthetic status and
significance. The American reader-response critic Stanley Fish has argued in
works such as “Is There a Text in this Class?” that what constrains
interpretation is not fixed meanings in a linguistic system but the practices
and assumptions of an institution. The following section will briefly consider
the seminal work of Wolfgang Iser.
Wolfgang Iser (b. 1926)
Iser’s theories of reader response were presented in two major works, The
Implied Reader (1972) and The Act of Reading (1976). In the first of these,
Iser suggests that we might think of the literary work as having two poles: the
“artistic” pole is the text created by the author, and the “aesthetic” pole refers
to “the realization accomplished by the reader.”5 We cannot identify the
literary work with either the text or the realization of the text; it must lie “halfway between the two,” and in fact it comes into being only through the
convergence of text and reader (IR, 275). His point here is that reading is an
active and creative process. It is reading which brings the text to life, which
unfolds “its inherently dynamic character” (IR, 275). It is because the text has
unwritten implications or “gaps” that the reader can be active and creative,
working things out for himself. This does not mean that any reading will be
appropriate. The text uses various strategies and devices to limit its own
270
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
unwritten implications, but the latter are nonetheless worked out by the
reader’s own imagination (IR, 276).
In The Act of Reading, Iser further elaborates his important concept of the
“implied reader.” In analyzing responses to a literary work, he says, “we must
allow for the reader’s presence without in any way predetermining his
character or his historical situation.” It is this reader, who is somehow lifted
above any particular context, whom Iser designates the implied reader.6 The
implied reader is a function not of “an empirical outside reality” but of the
text itself. Iser points out that the concept of the implied reader has “his roots
firmly planted in the structure of the text; he is a construct and in no way to be
identified with any real reader.” What the implied reader designates is “a
network of response-inviting structures,” which prestructure the role of the
reader in the latter’s attempt to grasp the text (AR, 34). In a novel, there
are four main perspectives: those of the narrator, characters, plot, and the
fictitious reader. The meaning of the text is generated by the convergence of
these perspectives, a convergence that is not itself set out in words but occurs
during the reading process (AR, 35). Iser also sees the notion of the “implied
reader” as explaining the tension that occurs within the reader during the
reading process, a tension between the reader’s own subjectivity and the
author’s subjectivity which overtakes the reader’s mentality, a tension between two selves that directs the reader’s ability to make sense of the text.
Postcolonial Criticism
Another, more overtly political, approach to interpretation gathered intensity
in the 1980s, concerned with the economic, cultural, and psychological
effects of imperialism and emancipation from colonial rule. Since postcolonial theory is rooted in the history of imperialism, it is worth briefly looking at
this history. In modern times, there have been at least three major phases
of imperialism. Between 1492 and the mid-eighteenth century, Spain and
Portugal, England, France, and the Netherlands established colonies and
empires in the Americas, the East Indies, and India. Then, between the midnineteenth century and World War I, there was an immense scramble for
imperialistic power between Britain, France, Germany, Italy, and other
nations. By the end of the nineteenth century, more than one-fifth of the
land area of the world and a quarter of its population had been brought under
the British Empire: India, Canada, Australia, New Zealand, South Africa,
Burma, and the Sudan. The next largest colonial power was France, whose
possessions included Algeria, French West Africa, Equatorial Africa, and
Indochina. Germany, Italy, and Japan also entered the race for colonies.
In 1855 Belgium established the Belgian Congo in the heart of Africa,
a colonization whose horrors were expressed in Conrad’s Heart of Darkness
The Later Twentieth Century
271
(1899). Finally, the periods during and after World War II saw a struggle
involving both the countries just mentioned as well as a conflict between
America and the Communist Soviet Union for extended control, power, and
influence. Needless to say, these imperialistic endeavors have survived into
the present day in altered forms and with new antagonists.
The motives behind imperialism have usually been economic. A second and
related motive has been (and still is) the security of the home state. A third
motive is related to various versions of Social Darwinism. Figures such as
Machiavelli, Bacon, Karl Pearson, Hitler, and Mussolini saw imperialism as
part of the natural struggle for survival. The final motive, propounded by
figures such as Rudyard Kipling (in poems such as “The White Man’s
Burden”) and questioned by writers such as Conrad, rests on moral grounds:
imperialism is a means of bringing to a subject people the blessings of a
superior civilization, and liberating them from their benighted ignorance.
Clearly, much of this rationale rests on Western Enlightenment notions of
civilization and progress.
After the end of World War II in 1945 there occurred a large-scale process
of decolonization of the territories subjugated by most of the imperial powers
(Britain, France, Netherlands, Belgium), beginning with the independence of
India in 1947. Colonial struggle is hardly dead: it has continued until very
recently in East Timor, and still persists bitterly in many parts of the world,
including Tibet, Taiwan, Kashmir, and the Middle East.7 Postcolonial
literature and criticism arose both during and after the struggles of many
nations in Africa, Asia, Latin America (now referred to as the “tricontinent”
rather than the “third world”), and elsewhere for independence from colonial
rule. The year 1950 saw the publication of seminal texts of postcolonialism:
Aime Cesaire’s Discours sur le colonialisme, and Frantz Fanon’s Black Skin,
White Masks. And in 1958 Chinua Achebe published his novel Things Fall
Apart. George Lamming’s The Pleasures of Exile appeared in 1960 and
Frantz Fanon’s The Wretched of the Earth followed in 1961. Fanon’s now
classic text analyzed the conditions for effective anti-colonial revolution from
a Marxist perspective, modified somewhat to accommodate conditions
specific to colonized nations. It also articulated the connections between
class and race. Indeed, Fanon pointed out the utter difference in historical
situation between the European bourgeois class, a once revolutionary class
which overturned feudalism, and the African bourgeoisie emerging as successor to colonial rule.
According to Robert Young, the “founding moment” of postcolonial
theory was the journal the Tricontinental, launched by the Havan Tricontinental of 1966, which “initiated the first global alliance of the peoples of the
three continents against imperialism” (Young, 5). Edward Said’s Orientalism
appeared in 1978. More recent work includes The Empire Writes Back
(1989) by Ashcroft, Griffiths, and Tiffin, Gayatri Spivak’s The Post-Colonial
272
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
Critic (1990), as well as work by Abdul JanMohamed, Homi Bhabha,
Benita Parry, and Kwame Anthony Appiah. Robert Young sees postcolonialism as continuing to derive its inspiration from the anti-colonial struggles of
the colonial era, both having certain common characteristics such as
“diaspora, transnational migration and internationalism” (Young, 2). Bill
Ashcroft, Gareth Griffiths, and Helen Tiffin also use the term postcolonial in
a comprehensive sense, “to cover all the culture affected by the imperial
process from the moment of colonization to the present day,” on account of
the “continuity of preoccupations” between the colonial and postcolonial
periods.8
Postcolonial criticism has embraced a number of aims: most fundamentally, to reexamine the history of colonialism from the perspective of the
colonized; to determine the economic, political, and cultural impact of
colonialism on both the colonized peoples and the colonizing powers; to
analyze the process of decolonization; and, above all, to participate in the
goals of political liberation, which includes equal access to material resources, the contestation of forms of domination and the articulation of
political and cultural identities (Young, 11). Early voices of anti-imperialism
stressed the need to develop or return to indigenous literary traditions so as to
exorcize their cultural heritage of the specters of imperial domination. Other
voices advocated an adaptation of Western ideals toward their own political
and cultural ends. The fundamental framework of postcolonial thought has
been furnished by the Marxist critique of colonialism and imperialism, which
has been adapted to their localized contexts by thinkers from Frantz Fanon to
Gayatri Spivak.
This struggle of postcolonial discourse extends over the domains of gender,
race, ethnicity, and class. Class divisions and gender oppression operate both
in the West and in colonized nations. Many commentators have observed that
exploitation of workers occurred as much in Western countries as in the areas
that they subjugated. Hence, postcolonial discourse potentially embraces,
and is intimately linked with, a broad range of dialogues within the colonizing
powers, addressing various forms of “internal colonization” as treated by
minority studies of various kinds, such as African-American, Native
American, Latin American, and women’s studies. All of these discourses
have challenged the main streams of Western philosophy, literature and
ideology. In this sense, the work of African-American critics, such as Henry
Louis Gates Jr., of African-American female novelists and poets, of commentators on Islam such as Fatima Mernissi and Aziz al-Azmeh, and even of
theorists such as Fredric Jameson, is vitally linked to the multifarious projects
of postcolonialism.
One of these projects was “multiculturalism.” Many critics held that
oppressive ideas were embodied and reproduced in the conventional canons
of literature and philosophy which we offer to our students: the literary
The Later Twentieth Century
273
tradition from Homer to T. S. Eliot and the philosophical spectrum from
Plato to logical positivism. In these canons, the voices of minorities, women,
and the working classes were suppressed. The growth of English literature
was from the beginning imbued with ideological motives. Arnold and
subsequent professors at Oxford saw poetry as the sole salvation for
a mechanical civilization. The “timeless truths” of literature were intended
to “promote sympathy and fellow feeling among all classes,” to educate
citizens as to their duties, to inculcate national pride and moral values.
And English was a pivotal part of the imperialist effort. In 1834 Macaulay
argued the merits of English as the medium of instruction in India, stating: “I
have never found one . . . who could deny that a single shelf of a good
European library was worth the whole native literature of India and
Arabia.” We can refrain from commenting on this except to add Macaulay’s
own subsequent statement that “I have no knowledge of either Sanscrit or
Arabic.” Such statements reveal the depth to which constructions of
Europe’s self-image, resting on the Enlightenment project of rationality,
progress, civilization, and moral agency, were premised on the positing of
various forms of alterity or “otherness,” founded on polarized images
such as superstitiousness, backwardness, barbarism, moral incapacity, and
intellectual impoverishment.
It is in profound recognition of this integral relationship between the
literary canon and cultural values that writers such as the Kenyan Ngugi
Wa Thiong’o have written essays with such titles as “On the Abolition of the
English Department” (1968), and important texts such as Decolonizing the
Mind (1986). Indian-born Gayatri Spivak’s work focuses on the structures of
colonialism, the postcolonial subject, and the possibility of postcolonial
discourse. In her essay “Can the Subaltern Speak?” (1983), later expanded
in her book Critique of Postcolonial Reason (1999), she addresses the issue
of whether peoples in subordinate, colonized positions are able to achieve
a voice. Like Spivak, Homi Bhabha extends certain tenets of poststructuralism into discourses about colonialism, nationality, and culture. The notion
of “hybridity” – a state of “in betweenness” with respect to two cultures – is
central to Bhabha’s work in challenging notions of identity, culture, and
nation as coherent and unified entities. Many writers, notably Chinua
Achebe, have struggled with the dilemma of expressing themselves in their
own dialect, to achieve an authentic rendering of their cultural situation and
experience, or in English, to reach a far wider audience. It should be noted also
that what conventionally passes as “English” is Southern Standard English,
spoken by the middle classes around London and the south of England. This
model of English has effectively peripheralized the English spoken not only in
other parts of England but also in other areas of the world. Today, there are
innumerable varieties of English spoken in many countries, and only recently
has their expression in literature been institutionally acknowledged. These
274
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
various debates can now be considered briefly in some of the major figures
who have made contributions to postcolonial criticism and theory.
Edward Said (1935–2004)
Known as a literary and cultural theorist, Edward Said was a Palestinian who
taught at various institutions in the United States. His thinking has embraced
three broad imperatives: (1) to articulate the cultural position and task of the
intellectual and literary critic; (2) to examine the historical production and
motivations of Western discourses about the Orient in general and Islam in
particular; (3) to attempt to bring to light and clarify the Palestinian struggle
to regain a homeland.
In Orientalism (1978) Said examines the vast tradition of Western
“constructions” of the Orient. This tradition of Orientalism has been
a “corporate institution” for coming to terms with the Orient, for authorizing
views about it and ruling over it. Central to Said’s analysis is that the Orient
is actually a production of Western discourse, a means of self-definition of
Western culture as well as of justifying imperial domination of oriental
peoples.9 Said’s aim is not to show that this politically motivated edifice of
language somehow distorts a “real” Orient, but rather to show that it is
indeed a language, with an internal consistency, motivation, and capacity for
representation resting on a relationship of power and hegemony over the
Orient.
The book is also an attempt to display Orientalism as but one complex
example of the politically and ideologically rooted nature of all discourse.
Thus, “liberal cultural heroes” such as Mill, Arnold, and Carlyle all had
views, usually overlooked, on race and imperialism (Orientalism, 14). Using a
vast range of examples, from Aeschylus’ play The Persians through
Macaulay, Renan, and Marx, to Gustave von Grunbaum and the Cambridge
History of Islam, Said attempts to examine the stereotypes and distortions
through which Islam and the East have been consumed. These stereotypes
include: Islam as a heretical imitation of Christianity (Orientalism, 65–66),
the exotic sexuality of the Oriental woman (Orientalism, 187), and Islam as a
culture incapable of innovation (Orientalism, 296–298). Said suggests that
the electronic postmodern world reinforces dehumanized portrayals of the
Arabs, a tendency aggravated by the Arab–Israeli conflict and intensely felt by
Said himself as a Palestinian.
Henry Louis Gates Jr. (b. 1950)
The most prominent contemporary scholar of African-American literature,
Henry Louis Gates Jr., has sought to map out an African-American heritage of
both literature and criticism. Central to this project has been his endeavor to
The Later Twentieth Century
275
integrate approaches from modern literary theory with modes of interpretation derived from African literary traditions. Gates has edited a number of
pioneering anthologies such as Black Literature and Literary Theory (1984),
“Race,” Writing, and Difference (1986), and The Norton Anthology of
African American Literature (1997), as well as helping to found AfricanAmerican journals. The important works authored by Gates include Figures
in Black: Words, Signs, and the “Racial” Self (1987) and The Signifying
Monkey: A Theory of African-American Literary Criticism (1988). One of
his goals in these texts is to redefine the notions of race and blackness in the
terms of poststructuralist theory, as effects of networks of signification and
cultural difference rather than as essences. Gates’ work has influenced,
and displays analogies with, the output of critics such as Houston A. Baker
Jr. and Wahneema Lubiano.
In the introduction to his Figures in Black, which is perhaps the most
succinct statement of his overall endeavor as a black critic, Gates suggests that
the connection between the development of African-American criticism and
contemporary literary theory can be charted in four stages, corresponding
broadly to his own development: the first was the phase of the “Black
Aesthetic”; the second was a phase of “Repetition and Imitation”; the third,
“Repetition and Difference”; and, finally, “Synthesis.”10 The Black Aesthetic
theorists of the first stage attempted both to resurrect “lost” black texts and to
formulate a “genuinely black” aesthetic, and were persistently concerned
with the “nature and function of black literature vis-a-vis the larger political
struggle for Black Power”(FB, xxvi). Gates identifies his own radical innovation as lying in the emphasis he accorded to the “language of the text,”
a hitherto repressed concern in African-American criticism. His engagement
with formalism and structuralism led to the second phase of his development,
that of “Repetition and Imitation.” Realizing that a more critical approach to
theory was called for, Gates’ work moved into the stage of “Repetition and
Difference,” using theory to read black texts but thereby also implicitly
offering a critique of the theory itself. The final stage of Gates’ work, that of
“Synthesis,” involved a “sustained interest in the black vernacular tradition
as a source field in which to ground a theory of Afro-American criticism,
a theory at once self-contained and related by analogy to other contemporary
theories” (FB, xxix). Drawing on poststructuralist theories, Gates argues
that, charged with lack of intellectual capacity and correlative lack of
humanity, black authors have literally attempted to write themselves into
existence, to achieve an identity through the narratives of their own lives, an
identity that subsists primarily in language: the very language in which they
had been designated as absences was itself appropriated as the sign of
presence (FB, xxxi). Gates valuably articulates the problems surrounding
any black critical use of so-called “theory.” And his own project is indeed
informed by recourse to native African idioms and traditions.
276
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
Cultural Studies
It is worth making brief mention of another, related, field which developed
rapidly over the last decades of the twentieth century: cultural studies. In the
nineteenth century, Coleridge, Burke, Arnold, Carlyle, Ruskin, and William
Morris all wrote extensively on the larger cultural issues surrounding the
study of literature. Earlier twentieth-century writers on the subject have
included D. H. Lawrence, Virginia Woolf, T. S. Eliot, many Marxist thinkers,
F. R. Leavis, and Raymond Williams. As it is practiced now, cultural studies
has a wide designation, encompassing sociology, anthropology, history,
literature, and the arts. As applied to the study of literature, cultural criticism
is marked foremost by its broad definition of “literature”: this includes not
only the conventional genres of poetry, drama, and fiction but also popular
fiction such as thrillers and romances, television and mass media, cinema,
magazines, and music. Indeed, the conventionally entitled “Department
of English” might nowadays more accurately be termed a “Department of
Cultural Studies,” since it sees literature as situated within a larger fabric
of cultural discourses.
Cultural criticism grounds literature in a larger framework which can
include the economic institutions of literary production, ideology, and broad
political issues of class, race, gender, and power. Hence cultural analysis tends
to stress what is specific or unique – in terms of time, place, and ideology – to
a given cultural and literary moment. Typically, cultural studies has extended
its methodology beyond conventional reading and research to encompass
field study, empirical observation, interviewing, and interdisciplinary
collaboration.
Marxist thinking has given the term “culture” a political valency, viewing it
as a part of the ideological process. The Frankfurt School saw modern mass
culture as reduced to a bland commercialism. Leading figures of the school
included Max Horkheimer, Theodor Adorno, Herbert Marcuse, and Walter
Benjamin, who all produced analyses of modern culture, drawing on Marxist
and sometimes on Freudian theory. In collaboration, Adorno and Horkheimer produced an incisive critique of modern culture that was to prove seminal
for cultural studies: Dialectic of Enlightenment (1944). They argued that
culture under the monopoly of capitalism imposes a sterile uniformity on
everything: “Films, radio and magazines make up a system which is uniform
as a whole and in every part.”11 In general, the culture industry serves to
control people’s consciousness, impressing upon them their own powerlessness, stubbornly refusing to engage their ability to think independently,
equating pleasure with complete capitulation to the system of power, reducing individuals to mere expendable copies of the identities manufactured by
the media and film, presenting the world as essentially meaningless and
The Later Twentieth Century
277
governed by blind chance (rather than on such virtues as merit and hard work)
(DE, 147). In this system, even art is a commodity, its value defined by market
forces (DE, 158).
In contrast with the Frankfurt School, Marxists such as Antonio Gramsci
have seen culture – as in the development of a working-class counterculture –
as an instrument of possible resistance to the prevailing ideologies. The view
of culture as oppositional or potentially subversive was developed in England
by figures such as Raymond Williams, one of the founders of the New Left
movement, the historian E. P. Thompson, and the socialist Richard Hoggart
who in 1964 founded the Centre for Contemporary Cultural Studies at
Birmingham University. Leading figures in the Centre included Stuart Hall,
author of an important essay, “Cultural Studies and its Theoretical Legacies,”
and Dick Hebdige, known for his book Subculture: The Meaning of Style. As
well as analyzing the subversive nature of youth cultures, critics at the Centre
examined the ideological function of the media and issues in education. In
America, the Marxist critic Fredric Jameson saw modern mass culture as
essentially postmodernistic in its form; Janice Radway wrote on the popular
form of the romance novel in her widely selling Reading the Romance (1984),
and examined the institutional workings of middle-brow fiction in her
subsequent A Feeling for Books (1997). Whereas Radway locates in the
reading of popular fiction a space of resistance to patriarchal norms, other
critics such as Susan Bordo, in her Unbearable weight: Feminism, Western
Culture, and the Body (1993), emphasize the profound and imposing impact
of popular culture on women’s self-image and cosmetic practices, showing
how much of their alleged freedom to form themselves is illusory.
Many cultural critics have drawn on semiotics to analyze popular culture.
In his Television Culture (1987) John Fiske argues that the techniques and
codes employed by television mold our perceptions but he rejects the idea that
audiences are wholly passive consumers of ideological meanings, arguing
instead that a text “is the site of struggles for meaning that reproduce the
conflicts of interest between the producers and consumers of the cultural
commodity. A program is produced by the industry, a text by its readers.”12
The French sociologist Pierre Bourdieu saw his work as politically motivated,
opposing globalization and cultural forms of oppression. His work in general
attempted to understand how the human subject was positioned in larger
social structures, and he saw aesthetic judgment as integrally located within
such structures.
In summary, cultural studies might be characterized by its broad definition
of literature as including all aspects of popular culture, its situation of
literature as a set of semiotic codes among broader social codes, its view
of culture as an instrument of subordination or subversion, as a site of
ideological struggle, its commitment to broadly left-wing political aims, and
its generally empirical, interdisciplinary, and collaborative methodology.
278
The Twentieth Century: A Brief Introduction
Notes
1. Jonathan Dollimore, Radical Tragedy: Religion, Ideology and Power in the
Drama of Shakespeare and his Contemporaries (New York and London:
Harvester Wheatsheaf, 1984), pp. 8, 18, 54, 59, 63, 78.
2. Jonathan Dollimore and Alan Sinfield, Political Shakespeare: New Essays in
Cultural Materialism (New York and London: Cornell University Press, 1985).
3. John Drakakis, ed. Alternative Shakespeares (New York and London: Routledge,
1985).
4. Michel Foucault, The History of Sexuality: An Introduction, trans. Robert Hurley
(Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1978), p. 69. Hereafter cited as HS.
5. Wolfgang Iser, The Implied Reader: Patterns of Communication in Prose from
Bunyan to Beckett (Baltimore and London: Johns Hopkins University Press,
1974), p. 274. Hereafter cited as IR.
6. Wolfgang Iser, The Act of Reading: A Theory of Aesthetic Response (Baltimore
and London: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1978), p. 34. Hereafter cited as AR.
7. Several points in this account are taken from the excellent chapter “Colonialism
and the Politics of Postcolonial Critique,” in Robert Young’s Postcolonialism: An
Historical Introduction (Oxford: Blackwell, 2001). Hereafter cited as Young.
8. Bill Ashcroft, Gareth Griffiths, and Helen Tiffin, The Empire Writes Back: Theory
and Practice in Post-Colonial Literatures (London and New York: Routledge,
1989), p. 2. Hereafter cited as EWB.
9. Edward Said, Orientalism (New York: Vintage, 1978), p. 3. Hereafter cited as
Orientalism.
10. Henry Louis Gates, Jr., Figures in Black: Words, Signs, and the “Racial” Self
(New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987), p. xxv. Hereafter cited
as FB.
11. Max Horkheimer and Theodor W. Adorno, Dialectic of Enlightenment, trans.
John Cumming (New York: Continuum, 2001), pp. 120, 147. Hereafter cited as
DE.
12. John Fiske, Television Culture (London: Methuen, 1987), p. 14.
Epilogue
New Directions: Looking Back,
Looking Forward
New Directions: The New Liberalism, Aestheticism,
and Revolutionism
Our own era has witnessed a decline of “theory” in the sense of a grand
narrative of historical development, or a series of archetypes with claims
to universal explanatory power. By the early twenty-first century, even
deconstruction and New Historicism were viewed as excessively comprehensive. Critiques of “metaphysics” or generalizations about “history” or
indeed “theory” were seen in many quarters as impossibly general. These
larger visions gave way to more empirical modes of inquiry, based on
more narrowly defined fields and interests. Cases in point are ecocriticism,
which examines the manifold significance of nature and the environment
in literature; and narratology, or the study of narrative, which engages
in detailed, factual study of specific historical periods, localities, and authors.
Recent political events – the attacks of September 11, 2001, the consequent
wars in Afghanistan and Iraq, and the “war on terror” – have somewhat
shifted the parameters of literary and cultural thinking. Some critics have
attempted to restore what they see as the neglected ethical dimension
of literature, and its potential to impinge upon larger debates concerning
morality, classical questions regarding the good life, and more pressing
political and even economic issues. Others have reaffirmed a commitment
zek,
to the aesthetic. Among the most prominent recent critics are: Slavoj Zi
who has reformulated, in Lacanian categories, some Marxist imperatives
in the light of present political dilemmas, such as the Palestinian–Israeli
conflict; Antonio Negri and Michael Hardt, who have formulated a new
conception of “Empire”; Marxists such as Terry Eagleton and poststructuralists such as Jean Baudrillard, who have analyzed the meanings of “terror”;
Literary Criticism from Plato to the Present: An Introduction
© 2011 M. A. R. Habib. ISBN: 978-1-405-16034-6
M. A. R. Habib
280
Epilogue: New Directions: Looking Back, Looking Forward
the newer liberal humanists, including Elaine Scarry, Martha Nussbaum, and
John Carey, who have analyzed the public status of the arts, the notions of
beauty and justice, as well as the meanings of democracy and good citizenship; the new formalistic critics, who include figures such as Michael Berube
and Geoffrey Harpham, who wish to reserve a space for the aesthetic, for the
study of literature as literature. With the exception of formalism, most of
these approaches effect a broadening of “literary” study into the public
sphere, into the cultural and political “texts” that commonly surround us. We
can now briefly look at these contemporary developments.
A New Liberalism
Martha Nussbaum (b. 1947)
The very public range of Martha Nussbaum’s concerns is indicated by the
titles of some of her major works: The Fragility of Goodness (1986),
Cultivating Humanity: A Classical Defense of Reform in Liberal Education
(1997), Sex and Social Justice (1998), and Frontiers of Justice (2005).
Nussbaum’s thought can be characterized as universalist and focused on
ethical and political concerns, in particular on issues of social justice,
especially regarding women and other disadvantaged groups. Perhaps her
work could be viewed as united by a central humanistic endeavor to ask the
Aristotelian questions “What is the good life?” and “How should one live?”
Her objective is to contribute to, and articulate the ideals of, universal peace,
tolerance, and justice, enlisting the ethical and cognitive power of emotions
in their complex connection with reason. In this endeavor, she stresses the
importance of a genuinely liberal education and in particular of the potential
of literature and philosophy to help us understand and overcome many of the
ethical and political dilemmas we commonly face.
Elaine Scarry (b. 1946)
Elaine Scarry first achieved prominence through her book The Body in Pain:
The Making and Unmaking of the World (1985). She exemplifies well the
recent venturing by academics into public discussion, engaging a wide spectrum of issues, ranging from the attacks of September 11, war, torture,
citizenship, and the Patriot Act, through beauty and the body to law and the
social contract. Her books include Literature and the Body (1988), On Beauty
and Being Just (1999), and Who Defended the Country? (2003). As Scarry has
said in an interview: “There is nothing about being an English professor that
exempts you from the normal obligations of citizenship . . . In fact, you have an
increased obligation, because you know how to do research.”1 Accordingly,
Epilogue: New Directions: Looking Back, Looking Forward
281
Scarry has controversially discussed the defense of America after 9/11, she has
argued that the Patriot Act actually represents an abuse of the notion of
patriotism, and has suggested that what comprises the gravest threat of terror
is the American government itself which has undermined the American
constitution and fundamental principles of democracy. She has also urged in
various articles that nuclear war and current military arrangements are (like
torture), in their refusal to be based on consent, profoundly undemocratic.
John Carey (b. 1934)
Former Merton Professor of English at Oxford, John Carey is known for his
anti-elitism and sometimes unorthodox views on literature and the arts, as
expressed in his acerbic wit and his Orwellian commitment to plain language.
As such, he has been one of the few to broaden the function of scholar to
public intellectual, combining academic duties with decades of discussion in
newspapers, on the radio, and on television, and serving as member, then
chair, of the Booker Prize committee. Carey co-edited with Alastair Fowler
the complete poetry of John Milton (1968), still regarded as the most
scholarly single-volume edition of Milton’s complete poems. His monographs include a study of Dickens, The Violent Effigy (1973), the highly
praised Thackeray: Prodigal Genius (1977), and John Donne: Life, Mind,
and Art (1981), a historical and psychological analysis which, through its
investigation of the traumatic influence of Catholicism on Donne’s literary
imagination, has effectively transformed critical perception of Donne as both
poet and preacher. In a recent book, What Good Are the Arts? (2006), Carey
attempts to dethrone extravagant claims about the spiritual or moral benefits
of the arts.2 He suggests that art should not be the province of a privileged
elite, and that there is no absolute standard or value of art (WG, 167). But,
drawing on research which exhibits the redemptive potential of art and
literature, Carey argues that literature is superior to the other arts on two
accounts: it is uniquely critical, and self-critical; and it can moralize, often in
diverse and contradictory ways. Literature is the only art capable of reasoning
(WG, 159–166, 173–181).
The New Aestheticism
Something is wrong, terribly wrong, in the department of English. Full professors and graduate students alike are failing – in some cases refusing – to read
literature as literature. The integrity of the discipline of literary study, perhaps
the integrity of literature itself, is being undermined by the very people who are
supposed to guard the flame of literacy and watch over our cultural treasures.
Ideologues swarm the halls.3
282
Epilogue: New Directions: Looking Back, Looking Forward
This is how Michael Berube (accurately) characterizes the perspective
of conservatives such as Lynne Cheney (head of the NEH in the Reagan
era), Roger Kimball, author of Tenured Radicals (1990), and Jonathan
Yardley, an art critic for the Washington Post. Critic Geoffrey Galt
Harpham talks of “the project of theory” (my emphasis) which, by
proclaiming the death of the author, killed the interest of literature, and
bequeathed a climate of “professional occultation” in which literature lost
its “aesthetic specificity” and “became enfolded within a generalized
textuality.”4 Harpham himself appears to revert to Aristotelian notions
of subjectivity, character (as expressed in criticism), and criticism “as a
mimetic practice whose primary purpose is to produce an accurate
representation of its object,” whereby the critic realizes “his own true
and essential nature” (CC, 9, 11). This gesture is symptomatic of a common desire – perhaps a desperation – among certain critics to repress the
entire history of critical interpretation and return to a primordial condition or time when literature was viewed simply as literature. There is,
however, nothing in Aristotle’s philosophy or literary criticism or rhetoric
which sanctions such a narrow aestheticism or such a narrow vision of
literary-critical practice. And there is a danger that, if we isolate the
“purely” literary, leaving out all of the human interest – psychological,
social, moral, political – we will end up with little more than a series of
empty techniques and exercises.
In fairness to Harpham, it could be argued that his project is one
of reaffirmation of the aesthetic rather than origination of ideas of critical practice. This project has also been advanced by scholars such as
Helen Vendler, who urge that our love of literature – rooted in a response to it which suspends scholarship, criticism, and theory – should
focus on its unique uses of language. But the call for such a return has
also surfaced in the work of more culturally minded critics such as
George Levine. Like Arnold, Levine urges an endeavor to reclaim the
aesthetic, as a province relatively free of the infringements of ideology
and politics, as one of the few remaining spaces of free play. He notes
that over the last decade the real subject of literary study has become
ideology, and its purpose is political transformation. Instead, the aesthetic should be a realm which enables the exercise of disinterest and
impersonality, allowing a sympathy for, and understanding of, people
and events, furnishing us with a “vital sense of the other.” Finally, as
against much theory which sees literature as co-opted into the exercise of
state power, Levine suggests that much literature is genuinely subversive.
Indeed, the aesthetic has a function in the exercise of academic freedom.5
While there may be some merit to Levine’s project, its vision of the
aesthetic somewhat rehearses what was already articulated long ago by
Kant, Arnold, and many others.
Epilogue: New Directions: Looking Back, Looking Forward
283
The New Theorists of Revolution
zek (b. 1949)
Slavoj Zi
zek has been called “the most vital interdisciplinary thinker to
Slavoj Zi
emerge in recent years.” He contends essentially that Lacan is heir of the
Enlightenment but he radicalizes the quest of European metaphysics from
Plato to Kant and Hegel to understand “the nature of being.” Born in
zek worked with other Lacanians at the Institute of
former Yugoslavia, Zi
Philosophy in Ljubljana. The interests of this group included European
zek’s major
philosophy, popular culture, and the operations of ideology. Zi
works include The Sublime Object of Ideology (1989), Tarrying with the
Negative (1993), and the Ticklish Subject (1999). He published a selfinterview entitled The Metastases of Enjoyment in 1994. According to
zek’s primary projects is an anti-totalitarian critique
Sarah Kay, one of Zi
of ideology, and an “impassioned attack on capitalism,” as well as a plea for
a return to universality.6
zek’s arguments concerning ideology are expressed in
Some of Zi
The Sublime Object of Ideology. His use of Lacanian categories is directed
toward the ideological and political spheres, and has a broadly Hegelian
zek points out that traditional Marxism sees a basic social
disposition. Zi
antagonism – premised on economics and class – which underlies other
antagonisms of race, gender, and political systems; and that a revolution in
the economic sphere would resolve all of these antagonisms.7 The basic
feature of so-called post-Marxism, he says, is a break with this logic:
for example, feminists argue that gender is more fundamental than class and
that inequalities in this sphere must be addressed first. But it is Lacanian
zek, that advances decisively beyond the usual
psychoanalysis, insists Zi
post-Marxist anti-essentialism in “affirming the irreducible particularity
zek sees the first post-Marxist in this
of particular struggles” (SOI, 4). Zi
respect as none other than Hegel, whose dialectic comprehends the inherent
contradictions of capitalism, such as the fact that a radical or pure democracy
zek, Hegelian dialectics embody an acknowledgment of
is impossible. For Zi
antagonism: far from being a “story of its progressive overcoming,” Hegel’s
dialectic expresses the failure of all radical attempts at revolution, and his
notion of absolute knowledge accepts contradiction “as an internal condition
of every identity” (SOI, 5–6).
zek’s aim in this book is threefold: to introduce the basic concepts of
Zi
Lacan free of the distortions that interpret him as a post-structuralist. Indeed,
Lacanian theory is “perhaps the most radical contemporary version of the
Enlightenment” (SOI, 7). The second aim is to effect a return to Hegel, by
reading Hegelian dialectics on the basis of Lacanian psychoanalysis: what we
find in Hegel is “the strongest affirmation yet of difference and contingency.”
284
Epilogue: New Directions: Looking Back, Looking Forward
zek wishes to contribute to the theory of ideology via a new reading
Finally, Zi
of classical motifs such as commodity fetishism and of Lacanian concepts
such as sublime object. This Hegelian heritage, as “salvaged” by Lacan, will
allow a new approach to ideology, one that resists post-modernist traps such
zek rejects
as the illusion that we live in a “post-ideological” age (SOI, 7). Zi
the conventional Marxist notion of ideology as a false consciousness or
illusory representation of reality. Rather, reality itself is already conceived of
in ideological terms: ideology “is a social reality whose very existence implies
the non-knowledge of its participants as to its essence” (SOI, 21). Clearly,
Lacan’s salvaging powers – encompassing not only Freud, but Hegel and
Marx – have hitherto been overlooked.
Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri: the Concept of Empire
In the year 2000, the left-wing American philosopher Michael Hardt and
the Italian Marxist dissident and philosopher Antonio Negri published their
zek as a new communist
collaborative book Empire. This was hailed by Zi
manifesto for our age, though others derided it as fashionable, vague, and
speculative. Hardt and Negri argued that, following the collapse of various
colonial regimes throughout the world, and then of communism with its
barriers to the expansion of capitalism, a new phenomenon – which they call
“Empire” – is materializing in our postmodern world. Along with the
globalization of economic and cultural markets, there “has emerged a global
order, a new logic and structure of rule – in short, a new form of sovereignty.
Empire is the political subject that effectively regulates these global exchanges, the sovereign power that governs the world.” The power of the
nation-state, they observe, while still effective, has progressively declined,
having less and less power to regulate the flow of money, technology, people,
and goods across national boundaries.8 Sovereignty, in fact, has taken a new
form, composed “of a series of national and supranational organisms united
under a single logic of rule.” Empire is the name for this new global form
of sovereignty.
Empire, however, is distinct from imperialism, which was “an extension of
the sovereignty of the European nation-states beyond their own boundaries.”
These states policed the purity of their own identities and excluded all that
was other. In contrast, Empire has no center of power and does not rely on
fixed boundaries: it is a decentered and deterritorializing “apparatus of rule
that progressively incorporates the entire global realm . . . The distinct
national colors of the imperialist map of the world have merged and blended
in the imperial global rainbow” (E., xii–xiii). The old divisions of the globe
into first world (the capitalist West), second world (Communism), and third
world have dissolved into a “smooth” world. The dominant productive
processes have been transformed: industrial factory labor has largely given
Epilogue: New Directions: Looking Back, Looking Forward
285
way to communicative, cooperative, and affective labor. In this postmodern
global economy, the creation of wealth comprehends “biopolitical” production, the production of the entire realm of social life, in which the economic,
political, and cultural spheres increasingly overlap (E., xiii).
Looking Back, Looking Forward
Looking back over the history of literary criticism (or at least one version of
that history), we can see that, since Plato, there has been a series of complex
tendencies moving toward totalizing and unifying schemes, reaching a climax
in the intellectual hierarchies of the Middle Ages in which theology stood at
the apex of knowledge, where all dimensions of humanity – bodily, emotional, intellectual, and spiritual – had their appointed place, and where
humanity itself had a defined location both within the universe and within the
historical scheme of providence. Since the Renaissance or early modern
period, there has been a dissolution of these coherent and totalizing visions,
spurred by economic and political development, the Protestant Reformation,
the Enlightenment, the French Revolution, the Industrial Revolutions, and
the rise to hegemony of the middle classes throughout Europe. This movement from general to particular has been underlain by a deepening vision of
the intellect as rooted in sense-perception, of rationality as tied to our physical
and emotional apparatus of survival, and of an increasing awareness that the
world is not an objective datum but a human historical and social construct.
Certain totalizing philosophies such as that of Hegel attempted to reconfigure
a unified vision of the fragmented modern world, situating it as the latest
phase of historical development. But Hegel’s system collapsed, leaving in its
aftermath various more localized approaches (many of which reacted against
it) including Marxism, positivism, Anglo-American idealism, and existentialism. Hence, the preoccupation with the particular and the local which we
now witness, in literary theory and criticism as well as in mass culture – in
realism, in the veneration of science, in our empirical, piecemeal, “common
sense” approach to life – is not new (though it has reached new intensities),
but is the product of a long historical development.
Notwithstanding this historical movement from the general to the particular, much of the literary theory covered in this book has shown us that
literature and criticism cannot be insulated from their political, social, and
economic frameworks. The acts of reading, writing, and interpretation are
not somehow value-free and do not subsist in some atemporal, academic
vacuum; they are informed by a much broader cultural and political fabric. As
such, literary criticism furnishes the tools for analyzing not only Shakespeare
and Milton, Toni Morrison, and Naguib Mahfouz, but also the “texts” of a
soccer game, television programs, advertisements, political speeches, press
286
Epilogue: New Directions: Looking Back, Looking Forward
conferences, rock concerts, and news presentations. We can draw on the
insights furnished by a host of thinkers – ranging from Plato and Aristotle
through Emerson and Whitman to Alexis de Tocqueville and contemporary
politicians – to analyze the nature of democracy in an array of uniquely
modern contexts. We can probe the various readings of the connection
between “literal” and figurative language – from Augustine through Aquinas
and Ibn Rushd to Locke, Schleiermacher and Derrida – to facilitate analyses
of the Qur’an and the various texts of Islam, as well as the texts of democracy
and liberalism on all its levels. These are among the most urgent tasks
confronting the twenty-first century.
In the context of the history of literary criticism, we can see more clearly the
deficiencies of some of the literary theory of the last half century: it has
claimed an excessive originality, it has often been infected with a tiresome and
pretentious jargon; its departures from the ideal of clarity are not sufficiently
controlled or informed; it has insulated itself in discussions of issues which are
of little interest to the larger society, and, correspondingly, it has ignored
some of the crucial issues which pulse at the heart of the contemporary world:
morality, religion, fundamentalism, family, the nature of the state, and the
public and educational roles of both literature and criticism. But the best
theoretical work has indeed addressed these issues in a dazzling variety of
contexts, deepening and enriching the study of both literature and culture.
Looking forward, we can struggle to ensure that the skills fostered by our
diverse and rich critical heritage are not insulated within academia: by showing
the continuity between our critical languages and the languages of the public
sphere, by practicing in an exemplary fashion the skills of close and critical
reading, by articulating the political implications of our work, by confronting
the crucial moral and religious dimensions of our lives, by extending our
inquiries over the fields of popular culture, by refashioning our departments in
the humanities to accommodate prevailing cultural concerns, and by supporting the participation of our institutions in the larger community. We can draw
on the richness of our literary, philosophical, and literary-critical heritage in
realizing the potential of the humanities to help shape the political, educational,
and economic discourses that will determine our future, and to foster an
increased understanding of our world, ourselves, and others.
Notes
1. Interview with Emily Eakin, New York Times Magazine, November 19, 2000,
online version: http://partners.nytimes.com/library/magazine/home/20001119mag
-scarry.html.
2. John Carey, What Good are the Arts? (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006),
pp. ix–xii. Hereafter cited as WG.
Epilogue: New Directions: Looking Back, Looking Forward
287
3. Michael Berube, “Aesthetics and the Literal Imagination,” in David Richter, ed.,
Falling into Theory (Boston and New York: Bedford/St. Martin’s, 2000), p. 391.
4. Geoffrey Galt Harpham, The Character of Criticism (London and New York:
Routledge, 2006), pp. 5–6. Hereafter cited as CC.
5. George Levine, “Reclaiming the Aesthetic,” in Richter, ed., Falling into Theory,
pp. 378, 386–389.
zek: A Critical Introduction (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2003), pp. 1,
6. Sarah Kay, Zi
3–6, 7–14.
zek, The Sublime Object of Ideology (London and New York: Verso,
7. Slavoj Zi
1989), p. 3. Hereafter cited as SOI.
8. Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri, Empire (Cambridge, MA and London:
Harvard University Press, 2000), p. xi. Hereafter cited as E.
Index
Academie Française (French Academy),
100
Achebe, Chinua: and language
choice, 273
Addison, Joseph, 121–2
Adorno, Theodor: Dialectic of
Enlightenment, 276–7
aestheticism, 174, 175, 176;
new, 281–2
d’Alembert, Jean, 117
allegory, 27; Christian, 39, 53,
55–6, 61–2, 69, 70–1; Coleridge
on, 157
Alternative Shakespeares, 266–7
Althusser, Louis, 231
“ancients” vs. “moderns” debate, 87,
99
Anzaldua, Gloria, 259
Aquinas, see Thomas Aquinas, St.
Ariosto, Ludovico: Orlando
Furioso, 81, 87
Aristophanes: Clouds, 25; Frogs, 10
Aristotle, 15–22; legacy of, 21–2; and
logic, 16–17; in Middle Ages, 58,
59–60, 64, 65, 66, 67; Nicomachean
Ethics, 18; Poetics, 18–21, 31, 63,
85, 86; and poetry, 17–19, 21;
Rhetoric, 25–6; and tragedy, 19–21
Arnold, Matthew, 185–8; on
criticism, 186; Culture and
Anarchy, 187; “Dover Beach,”
reading of, 2–5; and humanist
tradition, 193; “The Study of
Poetry,” 187–8
“art for art’s sake,” 129, 152,
176, 177
associationism, 119
Auden, W. H., 208
Augustine of Hippo, St., 53–6; and
classical heritage, 53, 54;
Confessions, 53, 54; De doctrina
christiana, 30; on drama, 52; on
signs, 54–5
Averro€es, see Ibn Rushd
Avicenna, see Ibn Sina
Bacon, Sir Francis, 82, 115
Bakhtin, Mikhail, 199–201; on
dialogism, 199, 200; “Discourse on
the Novel,” 199–200; on
language, 199, 200–1; on the
novel, 199–200, 201
Barrett, Michele, 255
Barthes, Roland, 226–8; “death of the
author,” 219, 227; and
poststructuralism, 227, 228
Bataille, Georges, 223–4; influence
of 223; and phenomenology,
219
Baudelaire, Charles, 175, 176–7; Les
Fleurs du Mal, 176; and Poe, 177;
and symbolism, 176
Baudrillard, Jean, 251–2, 279; on
consumption, 252; System of
Objects, 251–2
Beardsley, Monroe C., 204; “Affective
Fallacy,” 204–5; “Intentional
Fallacy,” 204
Literary Criticism from Plato to the Present: An Introduction
© 2011 M. A. R. Habib. ISBN: 978-1-405-16034-6
M. A. R. Habib
290
Index
de Beauvoir, Simone, 217–18, 257;
Second Sex, 214, 217–18
Beckett, Samuel: Waiting for Godot, as
postmodernist text, 250
Behn, Aphra, 109–11, 213
Benjamin, Walter, 207
Bergson, Henri, 185; influence of, on
literary critics, 195
Berube, Michael, 280, 282
Bhabha, Homi, 273
Blake, William, 153
Blanchot, Maurice, 219
Bloom, Harold, 235
Bloomsbury Group, 195, 215
Boccaccio, Giovanni, 71–2; Genealogia
Deorum Gentilium, defense of poetry
in, 72; and vernacular literary
forms, 81
Boethius, 44, 52; Consolation of
Philosophy, 44
Boileau, Nicolas: Art of Poetry, 101–2
Bonaparte, Marie, 235
Booth, Wayne, 32; Rhetoric of
Fiction, 264, 269
Bordo, Susan: Unbearable Weight, 277
Bourdieu, Pierre, 277
Bradley, A. C.: Shakespearean
Tragedy, 193
Bradstreet, Anne, 213
Brecht, Bertolt, 212
Breton, Andre: on Bataille, 223
Burke, Edmund, 123–4; Reflections on
the Revolution in France, 123–4; on
the sublime, 124
Burke, Kenneth, 32
Butler, Judith: Gender Trouble, 262
Calverton, V. F., 207
Calvinism, 84
Capella, Martianus, 51
Carey, John, 281
Casiodorus, 51
Castelvetro, Lodovico, 87–8
Castiglione, Baldassare: Courtier, 81
Castle, Terry, 259
Caudwell, Christopher, 208
Champfleury see Husson, JulesFrançois-Felix
Chaucer, Geoffrey: Canterbury
Tales, 82; Wife of Bath, 213
Christianity: and classical heritage, 51,
52–4; doctrinal rifts in, 49–50; see
also Church
Church (Roman Catholic): in Middle
Ages, 49, 50, 51–2, 83–4
Cicero: De inventione, 27, 28; De
oratore, 28; in Renaissance, 85;
rhetoric defended by, against
Plato, 28; rhetorical theory of, 28;
and teaching of rhetoric, 51
Cixous, Helene, 256, 257–8; and the
body, 257–8
classical period (in ancient Greece), 9;
rhetoric in, 23–6
Coleridge, Samuel Taylor, 153, 156–60;
conservatism of, 157; and
imagination, 157–60; on poets and
poetry, 159, 160
College English: gay issue, 259
communism: detached from
Marxism, 209–10
Conrad, Joseph: Heart of Darkness as
modernist text, 249
Constance School: and reception
theory, 269
Contemporary Cultural Studies, Centre
for (Birmingham), 277
Corax, 24
Corneille, Pierre: Three Discourses,
101
Counter-Reformation, see Reformation,
Catholic
“crisis of representation,” 248–9
Croce, Benedetto, 219
cultural studies, 276–7; scope
of, 276
Dante Alighieri, 70–1; on
allegory, 70–1; Il Convivio, 70;
“Letter to Can Grande,” 70, 71;
Divine Comedy, world view of, 83;
De Vulgari Eloquentia, 61, 70
Index
Day Lewis, Cecil, 208
“decadence,” 175
decolonization, 271
deconstruction, 240–4, 279; and
logocentrism, 241–2
defamiliarization, 198
deism, 116
Derrida, Jacques, 240–5; American
disciples of, 245; and
language, 242–3; originality of, 245;
on speech and writing, 243–4
Des Roches, Catherine, 213
Descartes, Rene, 115–16
Diderot, Denis, 117
Diomedes, 51
Dollimore, Jonathan: Political
Shakespeare, 266; Radical
Tragedy, 266
Donatus, Aelius: Ars minor and Ars
maior, 51
Dover, J. K.: Greek Homosexuality, 259
drama: English Renaissance, 82; and
performance, 101, 103, 109
Dryden, John, 103; Essay of Dramatic
Poesy, 103
Du Bellay, Joachim: Defence and
Illustration of the French
Language, 90
Duranty, Edmond, 170
Eagleton, Terry, 232–3, 279; After
Theory, 233
Eco, Umberto: on Aquinas, 68, 70
ecocriticism, 279
Eichenbaum, Boris, 198–9; “Theory of
the Formal Method,” 198–9
Eliot, George, 171–2; and
realism, 171–2
Eliot, T. S., 32; and modernism, 196–7;
“Prufrock,” 249; and tradition, 197;
Waste Land as modernist text, 250
Emerson, Ralph Waldo, 161, 162–4; on
language, 162–3; on nature, 162
Empson, William: Seven Types of
Ambiguity, 202
Engels, Friedrich, 209, 210
291
English: as academic subject, 193; and
colonialism, 273; varieties of, 273
Enlightenment: characterized, 114;
legacy of, 118; main figures of, in
France, 117; main figures of, in
Germany, 117; philosophy of,
characterized, 118, 119; political
theory in, 117; precursors
of, 115–16; and reason, 115; and
Romanticism, 145; and science, 114,
168;
epic: supremacy of, 89, 99; “national,”
90
Erasmus, Desiderius, 81–2; and
Pope, 109; Praise of Folly, 82
ethnic studies, 264–5
existentialism, 219, 220–3
Fabian Society, 207
Faderman, Lillian, 259
Fanon, Franz, 271; Wretched of the
Earth, 271
al-Farabi, 64
feminism: in ancient Greece, 213; black
and minority perspectives on, 254–5;
early modern, 213; and l’ecriture
feminine, 256, 257;
Enlightenment, 125–6;
international, 214; and
literature, 213; medieval, 73–5, 213;
modern, 213, 230–1, 253–8; see also
feminist criticism
feminist criticism, 212–18; in
America, 254–5; in Britain, 255; in
France, 255–258; and
language, 213–14, 216, 255–6; and
lesbianism, 259; and
psychoanalysis, 235; see also gender
studies
Fichte, Johann Gottlieb, 148, 149
Fish, Stanley: and reader-response
theory, 269
Fiske, John: Television Culture, 277
formalism, 197; new, 280; and
rhetoric, 32
Formalism, Russian, 197–201
292
Index
Foucault, Michel, 267–8; and New
Historicism, 264, 267; History of
Sexuality, 267; on power, 267–8
Frankfurt School, 207, 235, 276
Freud, Sigmund, 233, 234, 235–8; as
cultural critic, 236–8; and
dreams, 236; Oedipus complex,
236
Friedan, Betty: The Feminine
Mystique, 254
Frye, Northrop, 224; Anatomy of
Criticism, 32, 224
Fugitives, 203
Fuller, Margaret, 161; Woman in the
Nineteenth Century, 161–2
Gadamer, Hans Georg, 266
Garland, Hamlin: Crumbling Idols, 171
Gascoigne, George: “Certayne Notes of
Instruction,” 94–5
Gates, Henry Louis, Jr., 274–5; Figures
in Black, 275
Gautier, Theophile, 175
gay studies, 259
gender: as performance, 262; and
sexuality, 261; study of, 258,
259–62; see also feminist criticism
Geneva School, 220
Giraldi, Giambattista, 87;
Discourse, 87
Goldmann, Lucien, 231
Gorgias, 24
Gosson, Stephen: School of Abuse, 91
Gourmont, Remy de: criticizes
symbolism, 175–6
grammar (grammatica): medieval
treatises on, 60–1; poetry as part
of, 60, 62
Gramsci, Antonio, 212, 277
Greece, ancient, see classical period;
Hellenistic period
Greenblatt, Stephen, 266
Greimas, A. J.: and structuralism, 219
Gregory the Great (pope), 52
Gregory, John: A Father’s Legacy to his
Daughters, 126
Guicciardini, Francesco: History of
Italy, 81
Habermas, J€
urgen, 250–1; and
“communicative reason,” 250
Hall, Stuart: “Cultural; Studies and its
Theoretical Legacies,” 277
Hardt, Michael, 279; Empire, 284–5
Harpham, Geoffrey Galt, 280, 282
Hawthorne, Nathaniel, 162
Hebdige, Dick: Subculture, 277
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm
Friedrich, 134–41, 285; aesthetics
of, 137–41; and dialectic, 136–7; and
historicism, 136; Lectures on the
History of Philosophy, 137; legacy
of, 135, 140–1, 219; Philosophy of
Right, 136; and the Romantics, 147,
zek and, 283–4
149; Zi
Heidegger, Martin, 219, 220–3; Being
and Time, 220, 221; Introduction to
Metaphysics, 221; on
language, 221–3
Hellenistic period, 9, 26; rhetoric
in, 26–7
Hermagoras of Temnos, 27
heterological tradition, 181–8,
223–4
Hicks, Granville, 207
Higher Criticism, 169
Hippias of Elis, 58
Hirsch, E. D., 265
historicism: tradition of, 265; see also
New Historicism
historiography: Renaissance, 81
Hobbes, Thomas, 118
Hobsbawm, Eric, 189, 190, 191
Hocquengham, Guy: on
homophobia, 259
Hoggart, Richard, 277
Holland, Norman, 235
homosexuality: and
heterosexuality, 260; in history of
literature, 258–9
hooks, bell, 253
Horace: Ars poetica, 35–6, 64, 85, 86
Index
Horkheimer, Max: Dialectic of
Enlightenment, 276–7
Howells, William Dean, 171, 173;
Criticism and Fiction, 173
Hugh of St. Victor: Didascalion, 61–2
humanism: and classical languages, 81;
medieval, 71–2; and
Protestantism, 84;
Renaissance, 79–80, 81–2; and
twentieth-century criticism, 194; and
twenty-first-century criticism, 280;
and vernacular prose, 81
Hume, David, 116–17, 123, 129; on
artistic taste, 123
Husserl, Edmund, 220
Husson, Jules-François-Felix
(Champfleury), 170
Ibn Rushd (Averro€es), 58, 64, 65, 67;
Commentary on the Poetics of
Aristotle, 64, 65–6; on Qu’ran as
literary exemplar, 66
Ibn Sina (Avicenna), 64
imagination: in Romantic world
view, 146–7, 154–5,
157–60; Baudelaire on, 177
imperialism: history of, 270–1; motives
behind, 271
impressionism, 175
infantilism, 251
“intertextuality” (Barthes), 228
Irigaray, Luce, 256
irony: in Romantic world view,
147–8
Irvine, Martin, 61
Iser, Wolfgang, 220, 264, 269–70
Isidore of Seville, 51
Isocrates, 24, 58, 259
Jakobson, Roman, 201–2; on
language, 201; “Linguistics and
Poetics,” 201
James, Henry, 174; on novelistic
realism, 174
Jameson, Fredric, 169, 232, 277
Jauss, Hans Robert, 220, 264, 269
293
Jerome, St., 50
John of Salisbury, 62;
Metalogicon, 62–3
Johnson, Samuel, 111–13;
Dictionary, 100; on Dryden, 103;
Lives of the English Poets, 113; and
Shakespeare, 111, 112
Johnston, Jill: Lesbian Nation, 259
Jones, Ernest, 234
Joyce, James: Ulysses as modernist
text, 250
Kant, Immanuel, 129–34; Critique of
Judgment, 129, 130; Critique of
Practical Reason, 130; Critique of
Pure Reason, 129, 133; legacy
of, 134; and the Romantics, 147,
148; on the sublime, 133–4; on taste
judgments, 130–2
Keats, John, 153
Kennedy, George, 52–3
Klein, Melanie, 235
Kristeva, Julia, 256; Revolution in
Poetic Language, 256–7
Labriola, Antonio, 211
zek
Lacan, Jacques, 238–40; Zi
and, 283–4
language: Emerson on, 162–3; and
feminist criticism, 213, 255–6; Locke
on, 32, 33, 100, 119, 120–1;
twentieth-century theories of, 195;
Wordsworth on, 146, 154
Law and Literature movement, 33
Lawrence, D. H., 194
Leavis, F. R., 206
Leconte de Lisle, Charles-Marie-Rene,
175
Left Review, The, 208
Leibniz, Gottfried: lampooned by
Voltaire, 117
Lenin, Vladimir Ilyich, 211; “Party
Organization and Party Literature,”
211
lesbianism, 259–260;
separatist, 259–60
294
Index
Lesser, Simon O., 235
Lessing, Gotthold, 117
Levine, George, 282
Levi-Strauss, Claude: and
structuralism, 219
Lewis, C. S.: Allegory of Love, 194
liberal arts, 58–9
liberal humanists, 280–1
literary criticism: and American national
identity, 193; in antiquity, 9–10; and
Enlightenment philosophy, 118–19;
as explication du texte, 193, 195;
medieval, 60–1, see also Middle Ages;
nature of, 1; Pope on practice
of, 105–6; in Renaissance, 85–6; and
rhetoric, 23; scope of, 1–4; theory
of, 5; tradition of, 2, 6; and
twentieth-century
background, 189–91; twentiethcentury movements in, 194–5;
twenty-first century directions
in, 279–86
Locke, John, 120–1; empirical
philosophy of, 116, 117, 119, 120,
129; language theory of, 32, 33, 100,
119, 120–1; political theory of, 118
logic: poetry as part of, 60, 64–5, 66
logocentrism, 241–2; and
phallocentrism, 256
Longinus: On the Sublime, 30, 37–9;
and Romanticism, 39
orgy, 212
Lukacs, Gy€
Luther, Martin, 84
Lyotard, Jean-François, 231,
252–3; Postmodern Condition, 252
Macaulay, Thomas Babington, Lord: on
superiority of English, 273
Macherey, Pierre: Theory of Literary
Production, 231
Machiavelli, Niccolò: Prince, 81
MacLeish, Archibald, 204
Macrobius, 39, 42–3; Commentary on
the Dream of Scipio, 43
Mallarme, Stephane, 175;
Divagations, 175
Marvell, Andrew: “Horatian Ode” as
propaganda, 85
Marx, Karl Heinrich, 208
Marxism: and aesthetics, 210–11, 212;
and literary criticism, 207–8, 210–12,
230, 231–3; and
poststructuralism, 230; principles
of, 208–10
Marxist-Feminist Collective (UK), 255
Mazzoni, Giacopo, 88–9; On the
Defense of the Comedy of
Dante, 88–9
McGann, Jerome, 267
Mendelssohn, Moses, 117
metaphor, 27; and metonymy in
Jakobson, 202
metonymy, 27; and metaphor in
Jakobson, 202
Middle Ages: culture and society
in, 49–50, 57–8, 285; idealization
of, 146; poetry studies in, 60; reading
of literature in, 61; university
education in, 58–9; urbanization
in, 58
Millett, Kate: Sexual Politics, 254
Milton, John, 80
Mitchell, Juliet, 255
modernism: and Bloomsbury
Group, 195; characterized, 194–5,
196; exponents of, 249; and
language, 196; in literature, 249;
poetics of, 196–7; and
postmodernism, 249–50; and
reality, 196
monasticism, 50, 52
Montaigne, Michel de, 82
Montesquieu, Charles Louis de
Secondat, Baron de, 118
More, Sir Thomas: Utopia, 82
Moreas, Jean: symbolist manifesto,
175
Morris, William, 207
Moscow Linguistic Circle, 198, 201
multiculturalism, 272
Mussato, Albertino, 81
Myth Criticism, 224
Index
narratology, 279
naturalism, 169–70
“negative dialectics,” 207
Negri, Antonio, 279; Empire,
284–5
neoclassicism, literary, 98–100; in
England, 102–13; and the
Enlightenment, 99–100; in
France, 100–2; and imitation, 99;
and nature, 99; and science, 99
Neo-Platonism, 37, 39–44; in
Renaissance, 82
neo-Romanticism, 194
New Criticism, the, 32, 194, 195,
202–5; influence of, in academia, 203
New Historicism, 264, 265–7, 279
New Humanists, 193
New Left Review, 230
Nietzsche, Friedrich, 182–4; influence
of 182–3; on tragedy, 183–4
Norbrook, David: on Renaissance
poets, 85; on term “Renaissance,” 79
Nussbaum, Martha, 280
Origen: On First Principles, 52
Orwell, George, 208
Parnassian poets (French), 175
Pater, Walter, 177–8
Petrarca, Francesco (Petrarch), 81
phenomenology, 219, 220
philosophy: poetry as part of, 60;
systems of, in later nineteenth
century, 168
Pisan, Christine de, 71, 72–4, 213; Book
of the City of Ladies, feminism
of, 73–5
Plato, 10–15; Gorgias, 25; Ion, 12;
legacy of, 15; and poetry, 12–15;
Republic, 12–15; and the
Sophists, 25; theory of
Forms, 10–11, 15
Platonism, Renaissance, 82
Plekhanov, George: Art and Social
Life, 211
Plotinus, 40–2
295
Poe, Edgar Allen, 164–6; poetic theory
of, 164–5, 175
poetry: as part of grammar, 60, 62;
Renaissance defenses of, 91–3
Pope, Alexander, 104–5; classical ideals
of, 107–8; Essay on Criticism, 104,
105–9
positivism, 168–9; and Hegel, 169
postcolonial studies, 264–5, 270,
271–2; scope of, 272
postcolonialism: literature of, 271
postmodernism, 247–53; and black
studies, 253; exponents of, 249; in
literature, 249–50; and
Marxism, 248; and
modernism, 249–50; theorists
of, 247
postmodernity, 247; and consumer
capitalism, 247–8;
poststructuralism, 230–45, 247; and
Marxism, 230
Poulet, Georges: and
phenomenology, 219
Pound, Ezra, 196
Prague Linguistic Circle, 201
Pre-Raphaelite Brotherhood, 175
Priscian: Institutio grammatica, 51
prose: vernacular, 81
Protagoras, 24
psychoanalysis, 233–40
psychoanalytic criticism, 233–5; and
feminist critics, 235
Puttenham, George: Arte of English
Poesy, 95–6
queer theory, 260
Quintilian, 28–30; Institutio
oratoria, 29, 31; in Renaissance, 85;
rhetorical theory of, 29–30
Rabelais, François: Gargantua and
Pantagruel, 82
Radicalesbian collective, 259
Radway, Janice: Reading the
Romance, 277
Rank, Otto, 234–5
296
Index
Ransom, John Crowe, 203–4; World’s
Body, 203–4
reader-response theory, 264,
268–70
realism, 169, 170–4; exponents
of, 169, 170, 171
Realisme, 170
reception theory, 32, 264, 269
Reformation, Catholic, 83, 84
Reformation, Protestant, 83, 84
Renaissance: and classical
heritage, 80–1, 85, 86, see also under
humanism; culture and society
in, 79–80; literary criticism in, 85–6;
new genres in, 86; scientific trends
in, 82–3; as term, 79; vernacular
literatures in, 82
rhetoric: in antiquity, 23–30;
Christian, 56; literature and, 268; in
Middle Ages, 30; in modern literary
theory, 31–3; origins of, 23; poetry
as branch of, 60, 63–4, 88–9, 94; and
philosophy in Western thought, 33; in
Renaissance, 31–2; and
Romanticism, 31
Rhetorica ad Alexandrum, 26
Rhetorica ad Herennium, 27
rhyme: controversy over, 94; Dryden
on, 104
Rich, Adrienne, 259
Richard, Jean-Pierre: and
phenomenology, 219
Richards, I. A.: Philosophy of
Rhetoric, 32; influence of, on literary
criticism, 195, 202; Principles of
Literary Criticism, 202
Rimbaud, Arthur, 175
romance (genre), 87
Romanticism: characterized, 145–6;
and Enlightenment, 145, 147; in
America, 160–6; in
England, 153–60; in France, 151–3;
in Germany, 148–51; and
imagination, 146–7; and
irony, 147–8, 149; and
literature, 145; and nature, 146
and rhetoric, 31; and
subjectivity, 146
Rosenblatt, Louise: and reader-response
theory, 269
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, 118, 151–2;
Confessions, 146; Social
Contract, 152
Rubin, Gayle, 260
Said, Edward, 274: Orientalism, 274
Sartre, Jean-Paul, 217, 219
Saussure, Ferdinand de, 224, 225–6
Scarry, Elaine, 280–1
Schelling, Friedrich, 148, 149; System of
Transcendental Idealism, 148–9
Schiller, Friedrich von, 149–50; On the
Aesthetic Education of Man, 149–50;
and Romanticism, 150
Schlegel, Friedrich von: Fragments, 147;
on irony, 149
Schleiermacher, Friedrich, 150–1;
Hermeneutics and Criticism, 150–1
scholasticism, 58, 59; and Aristotle
64–5; and poetry, 60
Schopenhauer, Arthur, 181–2
science, 114, 115, 168–6; ascendancy
of, 168
scripture, Christian: allegorical readings
of, 52, 53, 61–2
Second Sophistic period, 30, 37
Sedgwick, Eve Kosofsky, 261
Servius, 51
Sharpe, Ella Freeman, 235
Shaw, George Bernard, 208
Shelley, Percy Bysshe: Defence of
Poetry, 153; on the imagination, 147
Shklovsky, Victor: “Art as Technique,”
198
Showalter, Elaine: A Literature of their
Own, 254
Sidney, Sir Philip, 91–3; Apologie for
Poetrie, 91–3
signs: St. Augustine on, 54–5; Saussure
on, 225–6
Sinfield, Alan: Political
Shakespeare, 266
Index
socialist realism, 211–12
Society for the Study of Poetic Language
(Russian), 198, 201
Socrates, 11, 25
Sophists, 24–5
Southern Agrarians, 203
Spectator, The, 122
Spender, Stephen, 208
Spinoza, Baruch, 116
Spivak, Gayatri, 273
Sta€el, Germaine de, 152–3
Steele, Richard, 121–2
Stonewall Riots, 258
Sturm und Drang, 148
style: levels of, 27
structuralism, 219, 224–6
sublime, the, 37–9
Swift, Jonathan: Battle of the
Books, 99
symbol: Coleridge on, 157
symbolism, 174, 175; French, 175–6,
196; influence of, 175
Symons, Arthur: Symbolist
Movement in Literature,
176, 196
synecdoche, 27
Taine, Hippolyte: and naturalism,
170; History of English
Literature, 170
Tasso: Discorsi del Poema Eroica, 89
Tel Quel, 230
Tertullian, 52
Theater of the Absurd, 219
Theophrastus, 24, 26–7
Thomas Aquinas, St., 67–70; on
allegory, 69; on poetry, 70; Summa
contra Gentiles, 67; Summa
Theologica, 67–8, 69
Thompson, E. P., 277
Thoreau, Henry David, 161
Tillyard, E. M., 194
Tocqueville, Alexis de, 115
tragedy: Aristotle on, 19–21
transcendentalism, 162, 164
Tricontinental (journal), 271
297
Trotsky, Leon: Literature and
Revolution, 211; Towards a Free
Revolutionary Art, 211
unconscious, the, 233–4
unities, doctrine of the, 20–1, 86,
87–8, 101, 112
universities: growth of, 59; medieval
curriculum in, 58–9, 60
Valery, Paul, 195
Valla, Lorenzo, 82; and textual
criticism, 81
Vendler, Helen, 282
Vergil, 51
veritism, 171
Verlaine, Paul, 175
vernacular languages, 81; used by
Renaissance writers, 89–90
Vico, Giambattista, 122–3
Vinsauf, Geoffrey de, 63; Poetria
Nova, 63–4
Voltaire, 117, 118
Wa Thiong’o, Ngugi, 273
Weber, Max: on Calvinist world
view, 84
Weeks, Jeffrey, 259
Whitehead, A. N., 10
Whitman, Walt, 161; Song of
Myself, 161
Wilde, Oscar, 178–9; on criticism,
179
Williams, Raymond, 231–2, 277
Wilson, Edmund: Axel’s Castle, 207
Wilson Knight, G.: Wheel of Fire,
194
Wimsatt, William K., Jr., 204–5;
“Affective Fallacy,” 204–5;
“Intentional Fallacy,” 204
wit: in literature, 104, 105, 106–7
Wittig, Monique, 256, 259
Wollstonecraft, Mary, 124–7; on
education of women, 126–7, 213;
and feminist literary criticism,
125–6
298
Index
Woolf, Virginia, 215–17; and
language, 216; as
modernist, 215–16; and readerresponse theory, 269; A Room of
One’s Own, 214, 215, 216
Wordsworth, Dorothy, 153
Wordsworth, William, 153, 154–6; and
classical views on poetry, 155, 156;
and imagination, 154–5; and
language, 146, 154; Preface (Lyrical
Ballads), 154, 155
Yeats, W. B., 196
Young Germans: members of, 170
Young, Robert, 271, 272
Zhdanov, A. A.: defines socialist realism
aesthetic, 211–12
Zimmerman, Bonnie, 259
zek, Slavoj, 279, 283–4: Sublime
Zi
Object of Ideology, 283–4
Zola, Émile, 172–3; and
naturalism, 170, 172