View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk
brought to you by
CORE
provided by College of William & Mary: W&M Publish
W&M ScholarWorks
Arts & Sciences Book Chapters
Arts and Sciences
Summer 7-2-2014
Literary Criticism
Charles J. Palermo
College of William and Mary,
[email protected]
Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.wm.edu/asbookchapters
Part of the Arts and Humanities Commons
Recommended Citation
Palermo, C. J. (2014). Literary Criticism. Michael Kelly (Ed.), Encyclopedia of Aesthetics . Oxford and New
York:: Oxford University Press. https://scholarworks.wm.edu/asbookchapters/8
This Book Chapter is brought to you for free and open access by the Arts and Sciences at W&M ScholarWorks. It has
been accepted for inclusion in Arts & Sciences Book Chapters by an authorized administrator of W&M ScholarWorks.
For more information, please contact
[email protected].
Literary Criticism
To define the domain of literary criticism would require some contentious
choices and some contended definitions—about what the “literary” is and
about what kinds of interventions can be included as “criticism.” The aim of
this entry is not to trace the whole history of literary criticism. Nor should it be
assumed that modern literary criticism is naturally or necessarily academic.
The following discussion will address such matters and operate with such
definitions and omissions, always mindful that doing so does not necessarily
settle anything.
M. A. R. Habib locates the origins of literary criticism in Greece around the
end of the ninth century, where it continued to develop down to the Hellenistic
period (Habib, 2005, p. 9). Over the course of these centuries, literary
criticism began to address a set of topics, including mimesis, beauty, truth,
the organic unity of a literary work, and the social functions of literature as
well as rhetoric, the nature of language, audience, figures of speech, the
“canon,” and genres (Habib, 2005, p. 10).
Of course, these topics overlap and depend on each other in complex ways.
Gregory Nagy (1999) explains that a claim to truth underpins the poet’s
authority, and that the claim to truth depends on the poet’s relation to a
tradition. Thus, he notes that “the references made by an archaic poem to its
composer, or “author,” are not so much a personal attempt by the poet to
identify himself but rather a formal reflection of the poetry upon its own
importance: the archaic poem presents itself retrospectively as something
transmitted by the ultimate poet,” who represents and offers access to the
truth of the heroic past (pp. 5–6). This past serves as the object of religious
veneration, the embodiment of moral truth, and the basis of Panhellenic
society (Nagy, 1999, pp. 6–11 and chapter 12).
So it appears that the formation of a canon, the authority of the poet, and the
claim of poetry to truth are mutually determining and fundamentally related to
the social and political order. The relation of these conditions to the themes of
poetry, having evolved in the course of long tradition, becomes so tight that
theme and form (diction, choice of words and phrases) become mutually
determining, too (Nagy, 1999, p. 1). As a result, the authority of the poet
comes to rely on the deployment of forms, the correct use of which
demonstrates the poet’s fidelity to the tradition. Meanwhile, literary effect—the
ability to move or persuade its audience—becomes a fraught issue precisely
because of rhetoric’s power and in relation to the structure of society. This
issue is at work, for instance, in Thersites’s encounter with Odysseus in
the Iliad, as Bruce Lincoln (1994) has explained, in which Odysseus faces off
against an interlocutor of a lower class and divides his address to the
assembly according to its political composition (pp. 14–27). Later, in the
tradition of iambic poetry of the seventh-century poet Archilochos and the
sixth-century poet Hipponax, a fictional speaker inverts the poet’s place in
society (the adoption of a low or despicable persona), which permits a
transgressive speech (such as insult). Such formalized transgressions
continue to embody the values coded in the tradition, but they require the
audience to understand the codes well enough to see them as independent
from the actual circumstances of their utterance, even when they may be, and
sometimes are, read biographically (Nagy, 1999, pp. 247–248). In various
ways, Greek poetry thematizes the difficulty of its correct interpretation and
the contingent and exclusive mode of its address to its audience (Nagy, 1999,
pp. 238–242).
Thus, Aristotle considered performances of iambic poetry unsuitable for
youths whose education was incomplete and who might therefore be harmed
by such poems (Hedreen, 2014, p. 12). This problem, that poetry is
dangerous precisely because of its claim to truth and the authority it thereby
wins, becomes a theme of later Greek philosophy. Plato’s Republic famously
denounces poetry as harmful to the republic (Books 3 and 10). In
Plato’s Gorgias and Phaedrus, Socrates criticizes the Sophists for teaching
rhetoric because it concerns itself above all with persuading its audience
rather than with discovering the truth. A rhetorician may convince his listener
without believing his own argument (Habib, 2005, pp. 69–71).
Stanley Fish (1970) offers a reading of Phaedrus that complicates the critique
of Socrates. “Rather than a single sustained argument,” Fish claims,
“the Phaedrus is a series of discrete conversations or seminars, each with its
own carefully posed question, ensuing discussion and firmly drawn
conclusion; but so arranged that to enter into the spirit and assumptions of
any one of these self-enclosed units is implicitly to reject the spirit and
assumptions of the unit immediately preceding” (“Literature in the Reader,” p.
136). This means that, section by section, the dialogue “bring[s] the reader to
the point where he is no longer interested in the issues it treats; no longer
interested because he has come to see that the real issues exist at a higher
level of generality. Thus, in a way peculiar to dialectical form and experience,
the space of prose and argument will have been the vehicle of its own
abandonment” (p. 136). In reaching finally its conclusion, “the rejection of
written artifacts,” the reader of the Phaedrus, then, does not find a
contradiction but rather “an exact description of what the reader, in his
repeated abandoning of successive stages in the argument, has been doing”
(p. 138). Ultimately, then, the truth the text proposes to reveal, its meaning, is
not so much stated in the text (in fact, the text would be a series of
contradictory proposals none of which could be called its meaning) as
realized in the reader, in the reader’s experience of the text.
Thus, to sum up: The poet’s authority depends on a claim to truth but that is
importantly different from saying that what the poet writes is true. Criticism
and poetry itself reflects on the conditions under which an audience can
become the true audience for a poem—under which the poem can convey its
truth to its audience. The poet’s authority, therefore, depends on, and derives
from, the authority of a tradition or canon and the values it embodies—even
when, as in the case of Plato’s Republic and his Phaedrus (on Fish’s
reading), the function of the text is to call into question the ontology of the text
and the relationship of the text to truth, the literary tradition, and society.
So, whereas the Greek poet was crucial not only as a poet, but also as
something like a critic or historian of literature in the formation of a canon of
Hellenic literature, literary criticism and history play important roles in defining
modern canons or literatures. As Hans Robert Jauss (1982) explains, the
modern era, in its discomfort with literary history, seeks some principle
according to which to select and organize its literature. Historicist approaches
to literature—recognizing that the critic works not by looking back on a
finished process but by reporting from within history—undermine the security
of the critic’s values and access to works of the past. Writing the history of
closed periods, as if from outside them—or producing a class of literature
that, because of its greatness, transcends history—offered unsatisfactory
solutions once “it was recognized [for instance] that the opposition between
creation and imitation characterizes only the literature of the humanist period
of art, but can no longer grasp modern literature or even, already, medieval
literature” (Jauss, 1982, pp. 7–9). That is to say, not only is the critic unable to
take up an objective position vis-à-vis the literature of his or her own period,
but also the perspective of the critic who inhabits history cannot fully
transcend its own limitations to understand the work of other periods.
Marxist literary criticism sought to meet the challenge of history by
recognizing the inescapable relationship of literature to social praxis. This, in
Jauss’s account, produces accounts of literature as mimetic, that is, as
reflective of social realities—or as “formative of reality” (p. 11; emphasis in
original). The reflectionist kind of account meets difficulties both in explaining
the varieties of literary production under any given set of circumstances and
in explaining the literary work’s survival of “the annihilation of its
socioeconomic basis” (Jauss, p. 12).
György (Georg) Lukács would be a prime example. René Wellek (1981)
explains: “ ‘Widerspieglung der Wirklichkeit’ (reflection of reality) is Lukács’s
obsessive central metaphor. In the first volume of Aesthetik the phrase is
repeated (I counted) 1,032 times,” and he continues: “I was too bored to
count it in volume 2” (p. 40). This interest in the objective representation of
real social relations raises the problem of the writer’s relationship to history
and to history’s course, so that “the contemporary writer is asked to depict
reality as it is, objectively, realistically, but with his mind on the future society,
socialistically, propagandistically,” while the “writer in the prerevolutionary past
is asked the same question: Does he have insight into the structure of society
and its movement?” (Wellek, 1981, p. 41). If the task of the contemporary
writer requires a paradoxical mixture of objectivity and advocacy, the
evaluation of the prerevolutionary writer can bracket the explicitly held beliefs
of a Tory Walter Scott or a royalist Honoré Balzac if their representation of
society reveals structures consistent with a socialist analysis. However, the
problem still remains: The claim of the work to truth depends not on
correspondence to real persons and events, but on its conformance to an
account of the workings of history and the structure of society. Thus, the
importance for Lukács of “types,” which are “to quote one of his formal
definitions, ‘the innermost essence of a personality as moved and defined by
such determinations which belong objectively to a significant tendency of the
evolution of society’” (Wellek, 1981, pp. 43–44, citing Lukács, Probleme des
Realismus, Vol. 1, p. 588).
The other, more recent, approach sees the work of art as part of a historical
process, which is understood to include both its production and its effects—
the ways it works—by studying its reception.
An important alternative to Marxist approaches, formalism, faces symmetrical
problems. Rather than assert the dependence of the work of art on praxis,
formalism seeks to study literary phenomena in terms of their devices.
Literature, for the formalist, is distinguished by the stylistic devices by which it
overcomes the automatization that makes practical language familiar,
habitual. Literature’s development—the literary series’ work—is the continual
invention of stylistic devices. At first, it seems, this process is entirely internal
to literature. However, since literature defines itself against practical
language, and since practical language operates as part of history in general,
it seems “possible to place the ‘literary series’ and the ‘nonliterary series’ into
a relation that comprehends the relationship between literature and history
without forcing literature, at the expense of its character as art, into a function
of mere copying or commentary” (Jauss, 1982, p. 18). In the words of Boris
Eichenbaum (1965), a leading Russian formalist, the school adopted a “dual
perspective: the perspective of theoretical study …, which centered on a
given theoretical problem and its applicability to the most diverse materials,
and the perspective of historical studies—studies of literary evolution as such”
(p. 132). This dual perspective evolved in the early phases of the movement,
developing from an early interest in linguistics (which Roman Jakobson
exported to Czechoslovakia in helping to found the “Prague School”) and the
difference between poetic and ordinary language toward a historical account
of the evolving techniques of literature.
According to Eichenbaum, the key theorist of the Russian formalist school
was Viktor Shklovsky. Shklovsky’s single most famous and important
contribution to criticism is probably the concept of ostraneniye (“making
strange” or “defamiliarization”). Defamiliarization counters the encroachment
of “habitualization,” which, as Shklovsky (1965) explains, “devours works,
clothes, furniture, one’s wife, and the fear of war … And art exists,” he goes
on to explain, “that one may recover the sensation of life; it exists to make
one feel things, to make the stone stony” (p. 12). Thus, he affirms: “The
technique of art is to make objects ‘unfamiliar,’ to make forms difficult, to
increase the difficulty and length of perception because the process of
perception is an aesthetic end in itself and must be prolonged” (p. 12). Hence,
the importance of defamiliarization, which, as a psychological effect produced
by literary devices, will operate in real changing, historical circumstances, and
its success will be defined by its reception by real readers.
By now, the experience of an empirical, historically situated reader seems
indispensable to the task of literary criticism. In the 1920s, work such as that
of I. A. Richards focused, via psychological theories of the “impulse” as well
as empirical research into the actual responses of ordinary readers, on the
experience of the text. This led to an interest in the “public” sense of texts—
an account of meaning as the reaction of a competent member of the reading
public. I. A. Richards explores this avenue of thought in his Practical
Criticism (1929), in which puts into practice theories laid out in his Principles
of Literary Criticism (1962, originally published in 1924). Richards (1962)
offers an account of reading that shifts attention from “meaning” toward a
causal account of readers’ reaction: “Thus, the paradoxical fact that so trifling
an irritation as the sight of marks on paper is able to arouse the whole
energies of the mind becomes explicable” (p. 125). And so when words, with
their various senses, “occur in such an intricate whole as a poem … the
responses of competent readers may have a similarity which only its
occurrence in such a whole can secure” (p. 10). This impersonal view of
poetic expression (or communication), which came to be called the New
Criticism, found perhaps its defining expression in a pair of essays by W. K.
Wimsatt and Monroe Beardsley, “The Intentional Fallacy” and “The Affective
Fallacy” (1954). Famously, Wimsatt and Beardsley argued “that the design or
intention of the author is neither available nor desirable as a standard for
judging the success of a work of literary art” (p. 3).
In Europe, a school of criticism that built on the insights of phenomenology
began, albeit from different premises, to address the reader’s experience as
central to interpretation. Phenomenological criticism, on the account offered
by Georges Poulet (1969), sees reading as determined by an awareness of
another consciousness made available by the text, “the consciousness of
another no different from the one I automatically assume in every human
being I encounter, except that in this case the consciousness is open to me,
welcomes me, lets me look deep inside itself, and even allows me, with
unheard-of license, to think what it things and feel what it feels” (p. 54). This
surrender to the world of the text, however, must be accompanied in some
combination by an awareness of the work as a formal arrangement. This does
not mean, however, seeking evidence about the author who arranged the
words that make up the text. (To this extent, the phenomenologist agrees with
the exponent of the New Criticism.) Rather, it means “going back, within the
sphere of the work, from the objective elements systematically arranged, to a
certain power of organization, inherent in the work itself, as if the latter
showed itself to be an intentional consciousness determining its
arrangements and solving its problems” (Poulet, 1969, p. 67). This double
relation to the work—of surrender to the fictional world it narrates and of
formal analysis—requires a complex of dual relations to the text so that the
reader’s experience is both free and wholly his or her own while it is also a
complete surrender to the world opened by the text and so that meaning is at
all times defined by the successive, immediate, imaginative realizations of the
text’s fictional world and also by the text’s total structure (Ray, 1984, p. 21).
Hence, perhaps, Poulet’s paradoxical conclusion: “It seems then that
criticism, in order to accompany the mind in this effort of detachment from
itself, needs to annihilate, or at least momentarily to forget, the objective
elements of the work, and to elevate itself to the apprehension of a
subjectivity without objectivity” (p. 68). The answer to the critic’s dilemmas—
the critic’s dual relations to the text—is to forget the objective embodiment of
the subjectivity that is the critic’s prize, which is to say: to forget the text.
The relation between the objective existence of the text and the contingent
imaginative animation of its narrative in the mind of a reader becomes the
theme of an existentialist theory of reading, such as Jean-Paul Sartre’s, as
well as of later reader-response criticism. While Sartre, in his Qu’est-ce que la
littérature?, sees the work as the author’s way of instigating a limitless
creativity in the reader, whose ongoing and creative exercise of freedom,
which, as it increases, increases the free creativity thereby imputed to the
author (Ray, 1984, p. 13).
On the other hand, William Ray (1984) explains that reader-response theories
can range from those that, like he theory of Roman Ingarden, give the text
and the reader’s imaginative “concretization” of it equal, and in a sense
opposed, reality to those that envision a more dynamic relation between the
text (as a thing given in advance) and the reader’s concretization of it, such
as Wolfgang Iser’s theory (pp. 33–35). In the latter’s view, the progressive
concretizations (the experience and response to “gaps” and “negativities”)
issue in a cumulative, “holistic viewpoint, transcendent of any single
perspective” from which “all other points of view projected by the text can be
contemplated” (Ray, 1984, p. 36). Either way, the problem of reference arises
—which is to say, we are left needing to know whether to verify an
interpretation according to the given text or the reader’s experience, or, put
slightly differently, wanting to know “to whose lived experience the
concretization correlates” (Ray, 1984, p. 49).
The question is the crux, really, of the critical process since what
distinguishes a reader-response theory like Iser’s from others—indeed, what
likewise gives other theories their specificity—is this question of referential
authority. According to what authority are we to regulate our readings—
according to “form, historical period, rhetorical strategy, or authorial intention”
(Ray, 1984, p. 55)? If the imagination’s access to the subjectivity embodied in
the text validates the phenomenologist’s reading, and the dialectical
modification of the reader’s concretization in the successive experience of the
text validates the reader-response critic’s, the codes of the language or the
collective ideas of the discipline serve to validate interpretation for Jonathan
Culler and E. D. Hirsh (Ray, 1984, pp. 99, 111).
The validity of authorial intention as the source of referential authority has
been contested, most especially since the rise of poststructuralism. Many
have argued, and well before poststructuralism, that modern writing has
opened more and more space for the creative activity of a reader. And, while
Wimsatt and Beardsley’s remarks on intention were meant to define the New
Critics’ commitment to the work as an object and to evaluation and
interpretation as public processes, it was clear at the same time that
difficulties of an ontological nature were presenting themselves to criticism—
precisely because one’s account of what kind of thing a work of
literature was (act or object, brute fact or product of interpretation) bore on the
issue of referential authority (De Man, 1983; Fish, 1981). Still, it was not until
the 1960s that a programmatic refusal of the author’s role in determining the
meaning of a text became axiomatic for literary criticism generally. A series of
texts, including Roland Barthes’s “Death of the Author” (1967), Michel
Foucault’s “What Is an Author?” (1969), and Jacques Derrida’s “Signature
Event Context” (1971), from roughly the same moment articulate not a
pragmatic impatience with illegitimate appeals to biography in the explanation
and judgment of literature but principled and closely argued explanations of
the irrelevance of authorial intention to reading per se.
Perhaps the most prominent exponent of deconstructive literary criticism was
Paul de Man. In his work the problem of referential authority gained special
centrality. In his Allegories of Reading (1982), for instance, de Man explains
that “the innumerable writings that dominate our lives are made intelligible by
a preordained agreement as to their referential authority” (p. 204), which is
embodied in the “subject-metaphor” (p. 18) that is the narrator or the “I” of the
text (and not in the historical person of the author). But, since de Man argues
that this grammatical figure for referential authority only occupies the place of
such authority and, being a grammatical figure, cannot exercise it, the “I” of
the text becomes, on his account, an allegory “of the impossibility of reading”
(p. 205).
The popularity of reader-response criticism and of deconstruction almost
completely succeeded in removing the author from discussions of theories of
interpretation when, in 1982 Steven Knapp and Walter Benn Michaels argued
that authorial intention was identical with meaning and, further, that (despite
the victory of “theory”) attempts to describe the two as anything but identical
are incoherent. This is because, at a deep level, Knapp and Michaels (1982)
argue, no other principle than authorial intention can supply an adequate
account of the ontology, and therefore the identity, of texts (pp. 735–736).
“Theory” turns criticism to experience rather than texts and readers rather
than authors. The rise, simultaneous with the ascendancy of “theory,” of
cultural criticism and of various critical practices organized around identity is,
then, not unrelated to developments in theory (e.g., Bérubé, 2004, p. 21;
Michaels, 2004, pp. 129–146). With cultural criticism, we leave literary
criticism to attend instead to culture per se, and so we leave the scope of this
discussion. Certain discourses, of cognitive or affective response, for
instance, have brought techniques of cultural or scientific investigation to bear
on literary texts but, in doing so, set aside the specificity of the literary
(Zunshine, 2010, pp. 5–8).
For literary criticism committed to the internal relation of ascriptive categories
(identities) to meaning, on the other hand, Edward Said (1975) affirms that
“texts are a system of forces institutionalized at some expense by the reigning
culture” (pp. 21–22). Thus, we return to notions with which we began, such as
“the critic’s role in writing as dialectically creating the values by which art
might be judged and understood” (Said, 1975, p. 21). But this activity is not
like that of the ancient poet, whose self-reflexive engagement with literature
derived its authority from its privileged relation to the truth, namely, the
tradition transmitted to its people. Rather, according to the postcolonial critic
Said, modern textual criticism, which replaces “God as author-authority,”
“enables the appearance of European ethnocentrism” (pp. 15–16). Sandra
Gilbert and Susan Gubar, writing at roughly the same time, explain that the
connection between the figure of the author and authority is deeply implicated
in the construction of the author as a patriarchal/male figure, which reaffirms
its maleness by constructing woman as inferior and unable to create. And that
means that even women’s literature comes to be shaped by the metaphors
and types defined by the dominant male literature, and the representation of
women by men becomes a matter internal to the possibility of women’s
writing: “the creative ‘I AM’ cannot be uttered if the ‘I’ knows not what it is”
(Gilbert and Gubar, 1979, p. 17). Thus literary criticism’s task comes to entail
(once again, as it did for the ancient Greeks) considering the relation of the
poet’s place in society to the forms his or her words can take.
Likewise, in Said’s words, the literary critic plays a “role in creating the
processes of the present, as process and inauguration, the actual conditions
by means of which art and writing bear significance” (p. 21). Said calls on the
critic to use this function for “the articulation of those voices dominated,
displaced, or silenced by the textuality of texts” (p. 21). Yet, he notes,
following Lukács and taking Socrates as his example, that the literary critic’s
form par excellence, the essay, guarantees him “an ironic destiny with regard
to the great questions of life” (p. 20). Said affirms that, like Socrates, whose
“death perfectly symbolizes in its arbitrariness and irrelevance to those
questions he debates,” the critic’s essay “is patently insufficient in its
intellectuality with regard to living experience” (p. 20).
Perhaps Said and Fish, in their recourse to the figure of Socrates, correctly
signal a crisis in modern literary criticism that echoes the crisis that closes its
development in classical Greece—a crisis in the authority of both poet and
critic, a crisis of meaning. Fish offers another reading, of a sentence from the
“Conclusion” of Walter Pater’s The Renaissance. The sentence, Fish (1970)
explains, “does not, at first sight, afford much scope for the critic’s analytical
skill”: “That clear perpetual outline of face and limb is but an image of ours”
(“Literature in the Reader,” p. 129). In the end, however, after taking the
sentence word by word, it shows itself to be an act of conjuring and vanishing.
Fish affirms: “Now you see it (that), now you don’t” (p. 130).
Lately, some literary critics have written more optimistically. Ellis Hanson
(2012) offers his own reading of Pater, describing (in a way not unlike Fish’s)
the experience of the prose’s unfolding in the reader’s time (p. 558ff). The
result, however, is not the self-consuming “Now you see it (that), now you
don’t” that Fish narrates. Rather, Hanson’s experience of Pater’s prose is of a
prose that defers its object, a “languorousness” that “surrenders a certain
objectivity, a certain activity and will-to-possess, in favor of a wistfully
amorous expansion of subjective effects of impression, contemplation, and
imagination, under the pressing influence of the beloved object, of experience
itself, in its continual departure” (p. 562). To this “new aesthetic criticism,”
Michael Clune opposes another possibility: that an antitheatrical impulse,
following Samuel Beckett in texts such as Malloy (1951) and along the lines
described by Michael Fried in a series of critical and art-historical texts
beginning with “Art and Objecthood” (1967), has pressed toward a
nonrelational mode of writing, which denies both the politics of recognition
and the claims of the “new aesthetic criticism.” The value addressed in this
criticism is a refusal of the reader, of the claims of social relations, of truth and
value as arising from such relations, and a reorganization of the enterprise of
writing around the “satisfaction” of the writer, and (pace de Man and
Archilochos) the radical recommitment of the “I” to a relationship of identity
with the person of the writer (Clune).
Bibliography
Bérubé, Michael. “There Is Nothing Inside the Text, or, Why No One’s Heard of
Wolfgang Iser.” In Postmodern Sophistry: Stanley Fish and the Critical Enterprise,
edited by Gary A. Olson and Lynn Worsham, pp. 11–26. Albany: State University of
New York Press, 2004.
Find this resource:
Clune, Michael W. “Bernhard’s Way,” 29 March
2013. http://nonsite.org/feature/bernhards-way/.
De Man, Paul. Allegories of Reading: Figural Language in Rousseau, Nietzsche,
Rilke, and Proust. New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1982.
Find this resource:
De Man, Paul. “Form and Intent in the American New Criticism.” In Blindness and
Insight: Essays in the Rhetoric of Contemporary Criticism, 2d ed., pp. 79–101.
Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1983.
Find this resource:
Eichenbaum, Boris. “The Theory of the ‘Formal Method.’” In Russian Formalist
Criticism: Four Essays, edited by Lee T. Lemon and Marion J. Reis, pp. 99–139.
Regents Critics Series. Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1965.
Find this resource:
Fish, Stanley. “Literature in the Reader: Affective Stylistics.” New Literary History 2,
no.1 (Autumn 1970): 123–162.
Find this resource:
Fish, Stanley. “Why No One’s Afraid of Wolfgang Iser.” Diacritics 11, no.1 (March
1981): 2–13.
Find this resource:
Gilbert, Sandra M., and Susan Gubar. The Madwoman in the Attic: The Woman
Writer and the Nineteenth-Century Literary Imagination. New Haven, Conn.: Yale
University Press, 1979.
Find this resource:
Habib, M. A. R. A History of Literary Criticism: From Plato to the Present. Oxford:
Blackwell, 2005.
Find this resource:
Hanson, Ellis. “The Languorous Critic.” New Literary History 43, no. 3 (Summer
2012): 547–564.
Find this resource:
Hedreen, Guy. “Smikros: Iambic Portrait of an Artist as a Symposiast by
Euphronios.” In The Cup of Song, edited by Vanessa Cazzato, Dirk Obbink, and
Enrico Prodi. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014.
Find this resource:
Jauss, Hans Robert. Toward an Aesthetic of Reception. Translated by Timothy Bahti
and introduced by Paul de Man. Theory and History of Literature 2. Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press, 1982.
Find this resource:
Knapp, Steven, and Walter Benn Michaels. “Against Theory.” Critical Inquiry 8, no. 4
(Summer 1982): 723–742.
Find this resource:
Lincoln, Bruce. Authority: Construction and Corrosion. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1994.
Find this resource:
Lukács, Georg. Probleme des Realismus. 3 vols. In Werke, edited by György
Márkus and Frank Benseler. Neuwied, Germany: Luchterhand, 1962–1986.
Find this resource:
Michaels, Walter Benn. The Shape of the Signifier: 1967 to the End of History.
Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 2004.
Find this resource:
Nagy, Gregory. The Best of the Achaeans: Concepts of the Hero in Archaic Greek
Poetry. Rev. ed. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1999.
Find this resource:
Poulet, Georges. “Phenomenology of Reading.” New Literary History 1, no.1
(October 1969): 53–68.
Find this resource:
Ray, William. Literary Meaning: From Phenomenology to Deconstruction. Oxford and
New York: Blackwell, 1984.
Find this resource:
Richards, I. A. Principles of Literary Criticism. New York: Harvest, 1962.
Find this resource:
Said, Edward. “The Text, the World, the Critic.” Bulletin of the Midwest Modern
Language Association 8, no. 2 (Autumn 1975): 1–23.
Find this resource:
Shklovsky, Viktor. “Art as Technique.” In Russian Formalist Criticism: Four Essays,
edited by Lee T. Lemon and Marion J. Reis, pp. 3–24. Regents Critics Series.
Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1965.
Find this resource:
Wellek, René. Four Critics: Croce, Valéry, Lukács, and Ingarden. Seattle: University
of Washington Press, 1981.
Find this resource:
Wimsatt, William K., and Monroe Beardsley. “The Intentional Fallacy.” In The Verbal
Icon: Studies in the Meaning of Poetry, by William K. Wimsatt and Monroe
Beardsley, pp. 3–20. Lexington: University of Kentucky Press, 1954.
Find this resource:
Zunshine, Lisa. “What Is Cognitive Cultural Studies?” In Introduction to Cognitive
Cultural Studies, edited by Lisa Zunshine, pp. 1–33. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins
University Press, 2010.
Find this resource:
C
P