Creater
Creater
Creater
7-23
The Buddha taught that there is no self. He also accepted a version of the doctrine of
karmic rebirth, according to which good and bad actions accrue merit and demerit and
cause beneficial or harmful events to occur in this life or the next. But how is karmic
rebirth possible if there are no selves? The relevant philosophical issues inspired
centuries of philosophical reflection and debate. This chapter will contextualize and
survey some of the historical and contemporary debates relevant to moral psychology
and Buddhist ethics. They include whether the Buddha's teaching of no-self is
consistent with the possibility of moral responsibility; the role of retributivism in
Buddhist thought; the possibility of a Buddhist account of free will; the scope and
viability of recent attempts to naturalize karma to character virtues and vices; and how
right action is to be understood within a Buddhist framework.
Buddhism centres on the teachings of the Buddha, who lived and taught somewhere
between the sixth and fourth centuries BC. There is some disagreement about what exactly
he taught, how to interpret his views, and what they entail. But most agree that the Buddha’s
early teaching of the Four Noble Truths is central. This teaching analyzes the metaphysical
as a central cause of suffering, but claims that this attachment is rooted in ignorance because
The Buddha also accepted some version of the doctrine of karmic rebirth. Like most
scholars in classical India, the Buddha accepted a cosmology of multiple realms of existence
1 As will become apparent, there is considerable debate about the nature and entailment of this claim.
into which sentient beings are born, die, and are reborn in a continuous cycle.2 The process
of rebirth is known as saṃsāra.3 Where one is reborn is driven by the law of karma, which
functions with respect to moral action; good actions generate karmic merit and bad actions
generate karmic demerit. An agent’s accumulated karmic debt determines the kind of
existence they will have in their next life, and causes some auspicious and inauspicious
events to occur in that life. 4 It also partially explains the nature and fact of the agent’s
present existence as well as some of the auspicious and inauspicious events that occur in
this life.
agents are held to account for their morally evaluable actions, this doctrine offers a
because the laws of karma function across lifetimes and modes of existence.
But how is karmic rebirth possible if there are no selves? If there are no selves, it
would seem that there are no agents that could be held morally responsible for ‘their’
actions. If actions are those happenings in the world performed by agents, it would seem
that there are no actions. And if there are no agents and no actions, then karmic retribution,
and morality more broadly, seem to lose application. Historical opponents argued that the
2 The Buddha accepted a cosmology of six realms: two heavenly realms, a human realm, a realm of animals, a
realm of hungry ghosts, and a realm of hell beings. The Buddha considered each realm to be impermanent
and each mode of being to have its faults and limitations. Those born in the heavenly realms, for example, are
considered to experience progressively subtle states of meditative calm, but these experiences are obscured by
mental defilements, such as pride. The behavioural expression of these defilements accrues karmic demerit
and eventually leads to a lower rebirth. See Harvey (2000: 11–14)
3 The italicised words in this chapter are in Sanskrit. While this chapter will cite concepts discussed in both
Pāli and Sanskrit texts, it will only cite Sanskrit terms for the sake of simplicity.
4 I say ‘some’ because Buddhism recognizes other forms of causation and does not explain all possible
2
Buddha’s teaching of no self was tantamount to moral nihilism. 5 The Buddha, and later
Historical and contemporary explanations of how and why Buddhism does, in fact,
avoid the charge of moral nihilism spans a vast intellectual terrain, engaging issues in
philosophy of mind. These issues also inspired centuries of philosophical reflection and
debate, spanning cultures and continents, and resulted in a complex network of competing
philosophical positions and schools. Any attempt to survey the relevant literature will
provide, at best, a narrow and selective snapshot of available views. However, since many of
these issues are relevant to contemporary discussions of ethics and moral psychology, even
This chapter will contextualize and briefly discuss five historical and contemporary
debates that emerge from the apparent tension between the Buddha’s teaching of no-self
and the possibilities of karmic retribution and morality. These debates concern whether the
Buddha’s teaching of no-self is consistent with the possibility of moral responsibility; the
role of retributivism in Buddhist thought; the possibility of a Buddhist account of free will;
the scope and viability of recent attempts to naturalize karma to character virtues and vices;
and whether and how right action is to be understood within a Buddhist framework. This
‘selective snapshot’ of issues covers much philosophical ground. An objective of this chapter
is to make explicit the ways in which these issues are intimately related in the Buddhist
context.
5Buddhism is accused of nihilism on several grounds. One ground refers to the Buddhist rejection of
Brahmanical conceptions of God (See Patil 2009). Another ground refers to a certain understanding of the
Madhyamaka Buddhist idea of emptiness (śūnyatā, see Huntington 1995). This article focuses on moral
grounds for this charge.
3
The chapter will begin by providing an overview of the Buddha’s teaching of the
Four Noble Truths, since this teaching provides both the context and justificatory grounds
Most contemporary Buddhist philosophers agree that the Buddha’s early teachings of the
Four Noble Truths is central to his thought. 6 The first is the truth or fact of suffering;
suffering (duḥkha) is a pervasive and unwanted feature of sentient life. In the Buddha’s early
teachings, the concept of suffering is discussed in terms that range from bodily physical pain
The second truth diagnoses two main causes of suffering. The first is craving (tṛṣṇā):
craving for pleasure, for continued existence (of oneself and what one loves), and for non-
being (of that to which one is averse). On the Buddha’s analysis, craving conditions
attachment which then causes suffering in the face of change or loss. The second cause of
knowledge but a confluence of false views, the most significant of which are grounded in a
failure to recognize that all things depend on causes and conditions for their existence
Since a change to the causes and conditions changes their effect, it is thought to follow that
all things are impermanent. This extends to oneself and others. The Buddha taught that
there is no permanent and continuing self (ātman) that persists through time. The basic
thought is that if we analyze ourselves into our constituent parts, we will only discover
6For a succinct formulation of this teaching, see the Satipaṭṭhāna Sutta in the Middle Length Discourses of the
Buddha (1995).
4
dispositions, etc.). Each of these elements are impermanent; none persists unchanging
across lifetimes and each depends on some other elements for its existence. Importantly,
there is no single constant, unchanging, underlying substance that unifies them as aspects
of ‘me’. The Buddha taught that a thorough understanding of this fact can help remove the
grounds for craving and thus the roots of suffering. It can also motivate psychological
change by removing the false belief that we have fixed characters and so cannot change the
The third truth is the assertion that suffering can end. It is possible to change from a
state of pervasive suffering to one of happiness or overall well-being. Nirvāṇa is the term for
the resulting state or way of life. Why does the Buddha think this is true? Because he thinks
that nothing exists permanently: everything depends for its existence on causes and
conditions. It follows that if one changes the causes and conditions of some effect, one
changes the effect. Psychological change is thus possible if one changes the relevant causes
and conditions.
The fourth truth outlines an eightfold path towards achieving this state of overall
well-being (or eight constituents of an enlightened way of life).7 The elements of this path or
way of life are standardly organized under three headings; wisdom (right view, right
intention), ethical conduct (right action, right speech, right livelihood), and meditation
The Buddha’s teaching of the Four Noble Truths inspired centuries of philosophical
reflection, and led to extensive debates about how best to understand its substantive points.
ethics, and philosophy of mind. They reached their scholarly peak in India between the
fourth and ninth centuries CE, and the major philosophical trends were later classified into
7 This disjunction in thinking of nirvāṇa as a resulting state or way of life informs some contemporary debate
about whether Buddhist thought is best reconstructed (if at all) as a form of consequentialism or virtue ethics.
I will return to this point.
5
distinct Indian Buddhist schools. The most prominent were Abhidharma, Madhyamaka,
and Yogācāra. 8 These debates were also influenced by the emergence of Mahāyāna
Buddhism in the early centuries CE, which attributed additional teachings to the Buddha
that sometimes challenged established Buddhist views and advocated a ‘superior’ path to
awakening. Buddhism also spans various cultures, countries, and historical periods, and so
has been shaped by these different contexts. There is thus no singular ‘Buddhist’ position
on most debated issues by Buddhist philosophers; there are many Buddhist views on many
substantive philosophical issues. This is particularly true of the issue concerning whether
the Buddha’s teaching of no-self is consistent with the possibility of moral responsibility.
Historical opponents argued that the Buddha’s teaching of no-self is tantamount to moral
nihilism. The Buddha identifies these implications as ‘wrong views’ that can and should be
avoided (1995: 618–28). Historical and contemporary Buddhist philosophers offer various
explanations of how Buddhism can avoid this charge of moral nihilism. I will begin by
considering some historical approaches. A standard strategy of response consists of: (1)
elaborating the Buddha’s teaching of no-self in relation to his idea that all existing things
dependently arise (pratītyasamutpāda); (2) reinterpreting the function of karma in terms that
8Although I will use these doxographical distinctions in this chapter, they are in fact not so neatly drawn and
are to be treated as broad heuristics. They are useful because debates amongst proponents of these schools
often turned on broadly accepted points of difference. But, as is often the case in Western philosophy, how to
characterize these differences was a matter of dispute. Distinct philosophical schools also had different points
of emphasis (some metaphysical, some epistemological, some phenomenological) which sometimes led to
misattribution and misclassification. Prominent defenders of some schools were also prominent defenders of
others. And some attempts to clarify the positions of distinct schools led to subclassifications which themselves
were fiercely contested. For a general introduction to the philosophical grounds on which these Buddhist
schools tend to be distinguished, see Siderits (2007), Carpenter (2014), and Westerhoff (2018)
6
fit this explanation; and (3) explaining away talk of agents and their actions in reference to
With respect to (1), most historical Buddhists insist that, in denying a self, the Buddha
is not asserting that no one and nothing exists. Rather, according to at least one prominent
physical and psychological elements. The Buddha proposes several classifications for these
types of token elements; the Five Aggregates or skandhas. They are standardly characterized
as: (1) physical matter (rūpa), (2) feeling (vedanā), (3) recognition or cognition (saṃjñā), (4)
dispositional tendencies (saṃskāra), and (5) consciousness (vijñāna).10 The token elements in
these configurations are causally related events or states, and any particular element is
related, and have synchronic depth insofar as a token element at a given moment can be
or aggregation, itself, is not considered to be a real substance with causal properties. There
is no enduring substantial self that unifies these elements as constituents of ‘me’. It follows
that if there is a law of karma, it must operate over these causally related configurations of
This question relates to strategic move (2); reinterpreting the function of karma in
terms that fit the above elaboration of the Buddha’s teaching of no-self. According to the
9 I introduce this three-part strategy as an organizing device for the sake of clarity rather than to describe an
accepted methodology. Historical Buddhist philosophers did not identify or claim to adhere to this strategy,
but many of their arguments can be analyzed in terms of it.
10 There is scholarly discussion of the precise nature of these token elements. Siderits (1997) and Ganeri (2001)
argue that they are best understood as trope-like property particulars. There is also some contemporary debate
about how these five types of token elements are best rendered in English. See Davis and Thompson (2014)
and Ganeri (2017) for two competing recent accounts.
7
Buddha, karma functions over intentions, decisions, or will.11 ‘It is volition [cetanā], O monks,
that I call karma; having willed, one acts through body, speech, or mind’ (2012: 963). Many
consider this analysis of karma to be one of the Buddha’s great innovations. It is also broadly
consistent with the Five Aggregate analysis of persons. If one accepts this analysis, what then
should we make of ordinary talk of agents forming intentions, acting intentionally, and the
ubiquitous variety of distinctions between oneself and others? This relates to strategic move
(3); explaining away talk of agents and their actions in reference to the Buddhist distinction
between ‘two truths’. Many Buddhists respond to the above question by appeal to a
On at least one version of this strategic move, ordinary talk of self and other, agents and their
actions, is a matter of social convention and linguistic practice but does not reflect the
The Simile of the Mango in the Milindapañha provides an early example of the first
two strategic moves (Rhys-David (trans.) 1965: 72).12 In the context of a conversation between
King Milinda and the Buddhist monk Nāgasena about the operation of karma, King Milinda
proposes a simile of someone stealing a mango from another person’s tree to argue that that
person could appeal to the Buddha’s doctrine of no-self to justify their behaviour by saying
that the mango they stole was not the same mango as that planted by the other person. But
Nāgasena replies that the person is responsible on the ground that the stolen mango exists
in causal dependence on the one originally planted. It is analogously reasoned that the
person could not justifiably appeal to the Buddha’s teaching of no-self to argue that they are
not responsible for stealing the mango yesterday because they are not the same person
today. This is because there would be a definite causal connection between the elements
11 The interpretative range of the relevant term, cetanā, is broad and more inclusive than the notions of
intention, decision and will (which are, themselves, importantly distinct). I will return to this.
12 The Simile of the Chariot (Rhys-David trans. 1965: 34-38) arguably provides an early example of strategic
move (3).
8
that constitute ‘themselves’ yesterday as those that constituted ‘themselves’ today. Gethin
(1998) takes the point of this simile to be that, properly understood, ‘the principle of the
self and redeem Buddhism from the charge of nihilism’ (p. 144)
While historical Buddhist responses to the charge of moral nihilism tend to exhibit
commitments and entailments of its constituent claims. Many disputes focused on the
metaphysics and semantics of personal identity but had broader implications for the
metaphysics of reality more generally. Competing positions on these issues often function
to differentiate Buddhist schools. Here is a brief sketch of some of the salient philosophical
differences.
systematize the Buddha’s teaching into a unified and comprehensive theory. While the
details were debated, 13 most Abhidharma Buddhists interpreted the Buddha as proposing a
reduction of conscious experience and reality, a project that they respectively attempt to
complete. They consider this project to be motivated by the idea that ‘wholes’ (aggregations,
collections, kinds and types) are merely linguistic conventions for grouping otherwise
discrete entities. While we might conventionally talk about persons and other kinds of
wholes, what ultimately exists, in the Abhidharma view, are simple, causally related,
13 According to tradition, the early Buddhist community subdivided into eighteen distinct Abhidharma schools
and lineages, partly in response to doctrinal disputes about how best to interpret the Buddha’s teaching
(disputes also concerned which rules monks should follow). The most prominent of these Abhidharma schools
were the Theravāda, Sarvāstivāda, Mahāsaṃghika, Pudgalavāda, and Sautrāntika (see Westerhoff 2018). The
contemporary category of ‘Abhidharma Buddhism’ encompasses this variety of viewpoints (and brings with it
all the tensions involved in combining competing viewpoints). See also Ronkin (2005; 2018).
14 The most prominent contemporary defender of (at least some aspects of) this reductive analysis of persons
is Siderits (2003), who compares it favourably with the reductive analysis of persons defended by Parfit (1984).
9
Buddhists reject this analysis of persons and ultimate reality.15 The main point of contention
for Mādhyamikas concerns the status of the individuation criterion for ultimately real
entities, and whether it is consistent with the Buddha’s teachings of dependent arising.
Mādhyamikas argue that it is not. The positive upshot of this refutation, however, is unclear
that there is no ultimate reality, there is no ultimately true reductive base for an analysis of
persons, but that ‘our conventional or customary standards of rational acceptance are the
only game in town’ (Siderits 1989: 238).16 Yogācārins, by contrast, are traditionally read as
identity are analysed as mere reifications of the structural features of (at least some mode
There is a lot more to be said (and that has been said) about these different analyses
of personal identity and reality. If we return to the issue of whether the Buddhist teaching
of no-self is consistent with a morality based in karmic retribution, these different analyses
of personal identity face distinct challenges when it comes to explaining the operation of
karma. An Abhidharma analysis might be able to account for the creation of karmic debt
because it admits intentions in its reductive base. But some Buddhists argue that
Abhidharma cannot explain how this debt accumulates and is discharged (for better or
worse) at some later time. This is because karmic debt would need to persist through time,
15 While this is abundantly clear in the case of Madhyamaka, it is less so in the case of Yogācāra because the
most prominent defenders of Sautrāntika Abhidharma (e.g. Vasubandhu and Dharmakīrti) are also the most
prominent defenders of Yogācāra. This raises complicated issues about how these views are related; whether
their advocates changed their minds, whether the textual evidence combines the views of separate authors,
whether they imply a philosophical progression of insights, or whether these views are compatible or
continuous in some philosophically interesting way.
16 See also Cowherds (2011) for a sustained discussion of the Madhyamaka conception of conventional truth.
17 Some contemporary scholars argue against this traditional reading and insist that Yogācāra is better
understood as some form of phenomenology. This is controversial but influential. See Lusthaus (2002) for its
most prominent defence.
10
physical elements in causal relations. How could karmic debt persist in such an ontology?
(Schmithausen 1987; Waldron 2003). But some Madhyamaka Buddhists object that this is
While Buddhists historically debated how best to account for the operation of karma,
they did not question its possibility. There are several reasons for this. One reason is that
Buddhist thinkers sought to explain the ‘truth’ of the Buddha’s teachings, and the Buddha
strongly rejected doctrines which denied karmic retribution (1995: 618–28). To doubt its
possibility was said to be a mental defilement because it demotivates moral agency. This
practice is the cessation of suffering. In his early teachings, the Buddha refused to answer
dialogical context. In a conversation with Vacchagotta, for instance, the Buddha refused to
answer questions about the nature of self for the apparent reason that it would cause
Vacchagotta further confusion and thus suffering (2005: 1031–3).18 Later Buddhist scholastics
did attempt to answer substantive philosophical questions, but their dialectical context was
one of defending the Buddha’s teachings against the sophisticated metaphysical and
epistemological systems of their orthodox Hindu rivals. Even in this context, however, the
18Some contest the claim that the Buddha denied the existence of self, arguing that this denial was introduced
by later Buddhist scholastics. Supposed evidence is derived from the fact that the Buddha used the terms ‘self’
(ātman) and action (karma) and remains silent in the Vacchagottasutta when directly asked whether the self
exists. This is a minority view. Most historical and contemporary Buddhist philosophers consider the Buddha’s
analysis of persons to be exhaustive, to render meaningless talk of substantial enduring selves, and that a
proper understanding of the two-truth doctrine adequately explains the Buddha’s use of these terms. Gethin
(1998: 160) also convincingly contextualizes the Buddha’s silence in the Vacchagottasutta as relative to his desire
not to confuse his interlocutor rather than reflecting a general agnosticism.
11
possibility of karma and its transpersonal retributive conception of moral responsibility
remained unchallenged.
Karma naturalized
Buddhist philosophers either (1) ignore it, (2) reject it as inconsistent with a respectably
naturalized Buddhist philosophy that fits with a modern scientific point of view, or (3)
The third strategy is increasingly popular. Many naturalize karma to the fairly
uncontroversial idea that sentient beings can act intentionally and that their intentional
actions have a variety of effects on themselves, others, and their physical and social
environment (Flanagan 2011). And most emphasize the intrapersonal effects of action on
one’s own character or dispositions to feel, act, and experience a meaningful world (Keown
of this idea can be found within the traditional doctrine. Buddhists relate the operation of
karma to intention (cetanā). Contemporary scholars emphasize that the concept of cetanā
has a wide interpretive range that extends beyond volition to include one’s orientation or
intentional attitudes towards the objects of one’s experiences (Heim 2013). This might look
like a conflation of two senses of intentionality; (1) intentions as volitions with objectives that
motivate action, and (2) intentionality understood as the thesis that conscious experiences
12
habituated dispositions inform both what the subject experiences and the ways in which
experienced objects solicit behavioural response (Mackenzie 2013; Ganeri 2017). Intentional
attitudes such as anger, fear, or jealousy might be said to exemplify this idea if understood
as adopted stances which both inform how an object (person or situation) is experienced
and implicate modes of behavioural response (Finnigan 2017a; 2019, 2021). Such a view might
also help explain why the Buddha and later historical Buddhists considered the (otherwise
I think there is a lot to be said for this extended analysis of Buddhist cetanā (pending
more detail and argument). However, several problems arise from attempts to use it to
ground a naturalized account of karma. For one thing, this extended interpretation of cetanā
connects to broader themes in Buddhist moral psychology that make no reference to karma.
Most Buddhist philosophers maintain that the Buddhist analysis of persons, as causally
related psychological and physical elements, provides a rich and deep account of the
psychological causes and conditions of suffering and overall well-being. Most also contend
that this generalizes to a broader analysis of the way our inner worlds shape our behaviour
in ways that do not necessarily involve conscious acts of choice or decision-making. And
many consider this to imply that there are intricate feedback mechanisms between our
behaviour and our dispositional modes of experience and response. However, these insights
are thought to follow from a thorough analysis of the relationship between the Buddhist
doctrines of no-self and dependent arising. It is questionable whether the doctrine of karma
Further problems arise from the fact that naturalized accounts of karma emphasize
the way enacting intentional attitudes, expressing them in bodily action, serves to entrench
and reinforce them as habituated dispositions or aspects of character. It is not clear that this
captures all relevant aspects of the traditional doctrine of karma. One difficulty concerns
13
how it accommodates the retributive aspect of the traditional doctrine and the sense of
agents being held morally responsible by a mechanism of justice that metes out appropriate
rewards and punishments (Reichenbach 1990). Many of the historical examples of karmic
fruit refer to such goods as fortune, longevity, health, physical appearance, and social
influence. While some of these goods might causally relate to character (a conscientious
person might, for instance, be disposed to act in ways that positively contribute to their
health and longevity), many of these goods relate to character only contingently, at best. A
good person is just as susceptible to terminal illness or being severely injured in an accident
as anyone else (Wright 2005). Without the doctrine of rebirth to guarantee the
proportionality of merit and reward or punishment, these retributive goods have no place
This last objection might not seem to be a problem. A defender of naturalized karma
might grant the point but insist that there remains a large and interesting class of
intrapersonal and social goods that can be causally related to character development to a
sufficiently reliable degree, and that these are the only goods it needs to accommodate. But
even so, the retributive aspects of the traditional doctrine and the relevant sense of moral
responsibility remain unexplained. The traditional doctrine of karma assumes some sense
of moral deserts; agents get what they deserve (in this life or the next) and are thereby held
accountable for their actions. But while the behavioural expression of compassion might
generate certain psychological and social goods for the compassionate agent, it seems odd
ensure these outcomes. A defender of naturalized karma might respond that the notions of
retributive justice and moral desert are irretrievably tied to the notions of rebirth and cosmic
justice, or to the notion of self that the Buddha rejected, and so should be jettisoned. But if
naturalized karma jettisons the retributive aspects of cosmic karma, how might it
alternatively ground moral responsibility? Some argue that the notion of moral
14
responsibility should also be abandoned (Goodman 2002). But this is extreme, and
Contemporary Buddhist debates about the possibility of moral responsibility are often
related to the question of whether Buddhism can admit a theory of free will (Repetti 2017a).
Given that the Buddha rejects the existence of a substantial self, it would seem that
Buddhists should deny an analysis of free will in terms of agent causation or agents with sui
generis causal powers. However, the Buddha also explicitly rejected a version of fatalism or
the view that occurrences are inevitably caused (1995: 618–28). This view was thought to be
inconsistent with the Four Noble Truths, which collectively assert that it is possible to
change one’s state or way of life from that of persistent and unwanted suffering to overall
versions of determinism, however, and it is a live question whether they are compatible with
the possibility of moral responsibility. What is the best way to characterize the Buddhist
position on freedom and determinism, and is there a contemporary analysis that it best
approximates?
Contemporary Buddhist philosophers are all over the map on this issue. Buddhism
(Repetti 2017b), and even a form of libertarianism that assumes agent causation (Griffiths
1982). Some argue that Buddhists are illusionists about the possibility of free will (Harris
2012), and others that it is anachronistic to even raise the issue of freedom and determinism
in the Buddhist context (Garfield 2017). Debates on this issue are complicated by the fact that
15
these various positions are often contextualized to distinct Buddhist philosophical
traditions which do not necessarily share the same metaphysical assumptions. And their
contemporary defenders do not necessarily share the same assumptions about what moral
possibility of a free will, then a defender of naturalized karma will need to navigate this
contested terrain. However, the field is still young and various possibilities have yet to be
instrumentalist theories of moral responsibility and/or versions of the social regulation view
of free will, according to which activities of praise, blame, reward, and punishment function
to prospectively regulate behaviour rather than as modes of retribution that track deserts.19
Breyer (2013) defends a version of this approach in the Buddhist context, arguing that the
assignment and acceptance of moral responsibility can be justified in relation to its role in
motivating agents to act in ways that eliminate suffering and achieve liberation. Breyer thus
certain interpretation of the goals of Buddhist practice outlined in the Four Noble Truths.20
While these practices assume conventional distinctions between intentional agents, this is
efficacy rather than grounded in a robustly substantial metaphysical analysis of free will.
19See e.g. Schlick (1939), Dennett (1984), Arneson (2003), McGeer (2013; 2015) andVargas (2013, this volume).
Vargas argues that there are ways to appeal to forward-looking views of assigning and accepting moral
responsibility that allow for some backward-looking retributive judgments. If plausible, this might
accommodate some of the retributive dimensions of karma that would be otherwise lost in a naturalized
karma.
20 Breyer also claims that in order to most effectively enable successful practice, each practitioner should
regard herself as fully responsible for her choices, but others as not responsible. Goodman (2017) suggests a
modification whereby we (ordinary, unenlightened folk) should hold ourselves but not others responsible for
immoral actions, and others but not ourselves responsible for moral actions. Whether this asymmetry
consistently coheres with other socially justified notions of justice is an open question.
16
Breyer’s account seems to exclude the retributive dimension of moral responsibility that is
central to the traditional doctrine of karma. While it could be argued that this is the
inevitable cost of naturalizing karma, it remains an open question whether some alternative
retributive judgments.
Discussions of naturalized karma often occur in the context of debates about how best to
understand Buddhist ethics. This is not surprising. Since karma operates over moral action,
the doctrine of karma must presuppose some view of the moral determinants of action.
to argue that character, as a relevantly extended sense of cetanā, is the morally determining
factor for good or bad actions. While good consequences correspond to good actions in the
doctrine of karma, these consequences presuppose rather than determine the evaluative
worth of the action. From this it has been argued that ‘karma, is not a consequentialist ethic
but a virtue ethic’ (Keown 1996: 346). Others argue, however, that relation to suffering
provides a more fundamental evaluative ground, even of intentions and character, and so
normative ethical terms dominates contemporary Buddhist moral philosophy. Some insist
that Buddhist ethics is best construed in consequentialist terms (Siderits 2003; 2015,
Goodman 2009; 2015). Others that it is a form of virtue ethics (Keown 2001; Cooper and James
2005). Some argue that no version of virtue ethics can provide a viable reconstruction of
Buddhist ethics (Kalupahana 1976; Goodman 2009; 2015; Siderits 2015). Others argue that
Buddhist ethics ‘cannot be utilitarian’ (Keown 2001: 177). Some argue for an integration of
17
these theories into a form of virtue consequentialism (Clayton 2006). Others maintain that
Buddhist moral thought is such a complex and messy affair that it resists systematization
into a singular ethical theory (Hallisey 1996). And yet others argue that attempting to
(Garfield 2010–11).
Most participants in these debates accept the observation that Buddhist moral
thought is a complex and messy affair. If we take Buddhism in its widest possible sense,
find much agreement in moral views but also different points of moral emphasis, distinct
modes of moral reasoning, and disagreements about what the Buddha’s teachings
practically entail.
Recall the Four Noble Truths. The fourth truth outlines an eightfold path or way of
living. One of its constituents is ‘right action’. In response to queries about what this
practically entails, the Buddha provided a set of precepts for his disciples to follow in a
monastic setting. This is known as the vinaya. The earliest schisms amongst Buddhist
communities after the Buddha’s death (or parinirvāṇa) concerned the legitimacy and priority
of these precepts. There are now several bodies of vinaya precepts accepted by distinct
Buddhist communities around the world. 21 The Buddha also did not initially admit the
ordination of women. When he did, he provided a more extensive set of vinaya precepts to
regulate their behaviour than that of monks. There are contemporary debates about the
legitimacy of some of these gender-specific precepts, particularly those that require nuns to
21They include the Vinaya Piṭaka of the Theravāda (followed in Myanmar, Cambodia, Laos, Sri Lanka, and
Thailand), the Dharmaguptaka (followed in China, Korea, Taiwan, and Vietnam), and the Mūlasarvāstivāda
(followed in Tibet, Bhutan, Mongolia, Nepal, and Ladakh). Historically, they also included the Mahāsaṃghika,
Mahīśāsaka, and Sarvāstivāda Piṭakas. See Keown (2004).
18
demean themselves before monks, such as the requirement that nuns sit below or behind
monks regardless of their respective spiritual or hierarchical status (Banks Findley 2000).
Mahāyāna in the early centuries CE. Mahāyāna Buddhism distinctively recognizes certain
additional teachings of the Buddha (or sūtras) that are not accepted by all Buddhists. Some
of these sūtras make claims that contradict or are in tension with those made in the early
teachings. A controversial case concerns vegetarianism. The first precept taught by the
Buddha was that of ahiṃsā or non-violence. Ahiṃsā was a common precept or virtue in
classical India, and is the center-piece of Jainism. Buddhists often explicate it as the
prescription to neither kill nor harm others, where this refers to all sentient beings including
animals. The Jains took ahiṃsā to entail vegetarianism. But the Buddha did not prohibit
eating meat in his early teachings and there is even some evidence that he may himself have
eaten meat.22 This was historically controversial. However, at least three of the Mahāyāna
explicitly arguing that Buddhists should be vegetarian. And while these sūtras explicitly
acknowledge the inconsistency, they explain it away by arguing that the earlier teaching was
a mere provisional step towards complete prohibition. These Mahāyāna sūtras were highly
(Kieschnick 2005; Chuan 2014). This was arguably not the case in India, Tibet, or many South
East Asian Buddhist countries. While all Buddhists agree that one may not intentionally
harm or kill animals, there was (and still is) a lot of disagreement about whether Buddhists
The Mahāyāna sūtras also emphasize and champion the bodhisattva ideal. A
bodhisattva is a person who has committed to remain in the cycle of rebirth to relieve the
22 The Buddha did, however, place some constraints on the practice. See Finnigan (2017c: 8)
19
suffering of all sentient beings. This commitment is called bodhicitta. The motivation for this
commitment is said to be their great compassion (mahakaruṇā) for the sufferings of the
world. And the enactment or expression of this commitment in action is said to be informed
and sympathetic joy (muditā). There is some debate about whether these ideas constitute a
genuine Mahāyāna innovation or just elaborate ideas already contained in the Buddha’s
early teachings. They are nevertheless distinctively central to Mahāyāna Buddhist thought,
and inform distinct modes of moral emphasis and reasoning. In the context of Mahāyāna,
these ideas are bound up with the traditional doctrine of karma in interesting ways. For
instance, the typical method by which bodhisattvas assist others is by performing good
deeds that only indirectly involved others (if at all) and then dedicating the karmic merit to
the benefit of others rather than themselves (Clayton 2009). This practice of ‘dedicating
merit’ is replicated in the Chinese Buddhist ritual of animal release whereby Buddhists
purchase an animal (typically a small fish or turtle) from a temple, release it into a pond or
Given the evident plurality in Buddhist moral concepts and modes of moral
reasoning, there is good reason to be skeptical that all Buddhist moral thought can be easily
unified into a single normative ethical theory. To some extent, defenders of first-order
to some Buddhist text taken to be authoritative by some Buddhist tradition.23 But even so,
they anticipate that these contextualized studies will reveal a single evaluative thread that
comparison. If plausible, this has several potential benefits. It might provide grounds for
23 Good examples are Clayton (2006) and Goodman (2009), who reconstruct the moral thought of Śāntideva.
20
serve as an informative conversational bridge with mainstream ethics that goes beyond
simply asserting, ‘You say this, and Buddhists say this too’, to reveal new justificatory
grounds, new modes of reasoning, and new implications for shared evaluative assumptions.
general evaluative thread. What might justify one or other of these competing theories as a
plausible reconstruction of Buddhist moral thought? Finnigan (2017a) engages this question
and identifies three necessary conditions. The first is that the account needs to be consistent
with the Buddha’s teachings of the Four Noble Truths. The second is that the account needs
(which will exclude some options and render the final verdict on those included dependent
base). And the third is that the account needs to plausibly reconstruct the moral thought or
The first condition is the most important, given that the Buddha’s teaching of the
Four Noble Truths is the closest to a central tenet of Buddhism accepted by all Buddhists. If
some version of Buddhist normative ethics is inconsistent with this teaching, then it should
some version of Buddhist consequentialism and some version of Buddhist virtue ethics can
meet this condition. Stated briefly, the Four Noble Truths can justify some version of
Buddhist consequentialism if one emphasizes the first noble truth and accepts a specific
interpretation of the third. On this reading of the Four Noble Truths, the overarching goal
good relative to their role in causing these outcomes. But the Four Noble Truths can also
justify some version of Buddhist virtue ethics if one accepts a different interpretation of the
third noble truth and emphasizes the fourth. On this alternative reading, the eightfold path
21
characterizes the constituents of nirvāṇa, understood as an enlightened way of life. Actions
(intentions, dispositions) are justified as good to the extent that they are mutually dependent
and reinforcing constituents of such a way of life and are collectively inconsistent with
pervasive and unwanted suffering. Both accounts involve consequences of a sort insofar as
they both posit conditional relations between their various constituents. But in one case the
evaluative relation is instrumental and assumes an external relation between the evaluated
item (means) and the basis of evaluation (effect). And in the other, the evaluative relation is
constitutive and assumes an internal regulative relation between the evaluated item and
There is a lot to be said about this distinction. Versions of it are widely employed in
virtue ethics. They do not readily map onto what contemporary Buddhist philosophers
defend in their name, however. The Buddhist consequentialism of Goodman (2009), for
instance, looks an awful lot like the version of Buddhist virtue ethics outlined above. There
is also reason to think that both reconstructions of Buddhist ethics can satisfy the remaining
of Buddhist moral thought. This raises important questions about whether we should
embrace a genuine pluralism about Buddhist ethics. Leaving this question open, there are
several positive and less controversial conclusions one could draw. A potentially positive
outcome is that Buddhist consequentialism and Buddhist virtue ethics provide two distinct
responsibility and the various evaluative components of their proposed mechanism for
constitutive role in reinforcing and regulating an overall good way of living (both
22
individually and socially) that is inconsistent with pervasive suffering. As a result, they
Conclusion
The Buddha’s teachings of the Four Noble Truths contain several distinctive ideas that are
debates concerning whether the Buddha’s teaching of no-self is consistent with the
possibility of a Buddhist account of free will; the scope and viability of recent attempts to
naturalize karma to character virtues and vices; and whether and how right action is to be
understood within a Buddhist framework. The discussion was not exhaustive; Buddhism
contains many more themes that are relevant to moral psychology than discussed here, and
there is more to be said about those that were discussed. This chapter had a more focused
aim: to introduce and explore some of the more distinctive features of Buddhist moral
Acknowledgements
Many thanks to Tom Tillemans for informal discussion of the philological background, and
References
Arneson, R. J. 2003. The smart theory of moral responsibility and desert. In S. Olsaretti (ed.),
Desert and Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Banks Findley, E. 2000. Women’s Buddhism, Buddhism’s Women: Tradition, Revision, Renewal.
London: Wisdom Publications.
23
Breyer, D. 2013. Freedom with a Buddhist face. Sophia 52: 359–79.
Buddha, The. 1995. The Middle Length Discourses of the Buddha: A Translation of the Majjima
Nikaya, trans. Bhikkhu Nanamoli. London: Wisdom Publications.
Buddha. The. 2005. The Connected Discourses of the Buddha: A Translation of the Saṃyutta
Nikaya, trans. Bhikkhu Bodhi. London: Wisdom Publications.
Buddha. The. 2012. The Connected Discourses of the Buddha: A Translation of the Aṅguttara
Nikaya, trans. Bhikkhu Bodhi. London: Wisdom Publications.
Carpenter, A. D. 2014. Indian Buddhist Philosophy. Abingdon: Routledge.
Chuan, C. 2014. Ethical Treatment of Animals in Early Chinese Buddhism. Newcastle upon Tyne:
Cambridge Scholars.
Clayton, B. 2006. Moral Theory in Śāntideva’s Śikṣāsamuccaya: Cultivating the Fruits of Virtue.
Abingdon: Routledge.
Clayton, B. 2009. Śāntideva, virtue, and consequentialism. In J.Powers and C.Prebish (eds),
Destroying Mara Forever: Buddhist Ethics Essays in Honor of Damien Keown. Ithaca, NY:
Snow Lion.
Cooper, D. E., and S. P. James. 2005. Buddhism, Virtue and Environment. Farnham: Ashgate.
Cowherds, The. 2011. Moonshadows: Conventional Truth in Buddhist Philosophy. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Davis, J., and E. Thompson. 2014. From the five aggregates to phenomenal consciousness:
rowards a cross-cultural cognitive science. In S.Emmanuel (ed.), A Companion to
Buddhist Philosophy. Chichester: John Wiley.
Dennett, D. 1984. Elbow Room. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Federman, A. 2010. What kind of free will did the Buddha teach? Philosophy East and West
60: 1–19.
Finnigan, B. 2017a. The nature of a Buddhist path. In J. H.Davis (ed.), A Mirror is for Reflection:
Understanding Buddhist Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Finnigan, B. 2017b. Buddhist idealism. In K. Pearce and T. Goldschmidt (eds), Idealism: New
Essays in Metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Finnigan, B. 2017c. Buddhism and animal ethics. Philosophy Compass 12(7): 1–2.
Finnigan. B. 2018a. Madhyamaka ethics. In D. Cozort and J. Shields (eds), The Oxford
Handbook of Buddhist Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Finnigan, B. 2018b. Is consciousness reflexively self-aware? A Buddhist analysis. Ratio 31:
389–401.
24
Finnigan, B. 2019. Śāntideva and the moral psychology of fear. In D. Duckworth and J.Gold
(eds), Readings of Śāntideva’s Guide to Bodhisattva Practice (Bodhicaryāvatāra). New
York: Columbia University Press.
Finnigan, B. 2021. The Paradox of Fear in Classical Buddhist Philosophy, Journal of Indian
Philosophy, 49: 913-929
Flanagan, O. 2011. The Bodhisattva’s Brain: Buddhism Naturalised. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Ganeri, J. 2001. Philosophy in Classical India: The Proper Work of Reason. Abingdon: Routledge.
Ganeri, J. 2017. Attention: No-Self. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Garfield, J. L. 2010–11. What is it like be a Bodhisattva? Moral phenomenology in Śāntideva’s
Bodhicaryāvatāra. Journal of the International Association of Buddhist Studies 33(1–2):
333–57.
Garfield, J. L. 2017. Just another word for ‘nothing left to lose’: freedom, agency, and ethics
for Madhyamaka. In R. Repetti (ed.), Buddhist Perspectives on Free Will. Abingdon:
Routledge.
Gethin, R. 1998. The Foundations of Buddhism. Trowbridge: Opus.
Goodman, C. 2002. Resentment and reality: Buddhism on moral responsibility. Philosophical
Quarterly 39: 359–72.
Goodman, C. 2009. Consequences of Compassion: An Interpretation and Defense of Buddhist
Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Goodman, C. 2015. From Madhyamaka to consequentialism: a road map. In The Cowherds,
Moonpaths: Ethics and Emptiness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Goodman, C. 2017. Uses of the illusion of agency: why some Buddhists should believe in free
will. In R. Repetti (ed.), Buddhist Perspectives on Free Will. Abingdon: Routledge.
Griffiths, P. J. 1982. Notes towards a Buddhist critique of karma theory. Religious Studies 18:
277–91.
Hallisey, C. 1996. Ethical particularism in Theravada Buddhism. Journal of Buddhist Ethics 3:
32–43.
Harris, S. 2012. Free Will. New York: Free Press.
Harvey, P. 2000. An Introduction to Buddhist Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Heim, M. 2013. The Forerunner of All Things: Buddhaghosa on Mind, Intention, and Agency.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Huntington, C. W., Jr. 1995. The Emptiness of Emptiness: An Introduction to Early Indian
Madhyamaka. Honolulu: University of Hawai’i Press.
Kalupahana, D. 1976. Buddhist Philosophy: A Historical Analysis. Honolulu: University of
25
Hawai’i Press.
Keown, D. 1996. Karma, character, and consequentialism. Journal of Religious Ethics 24(2):
329–50.
Keown, D. 2001. The Nature of Buddhist Ethics. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
Keown, D. 2004. Vinaya Piṭaka. In D. Keown (ed.), Dictionary of Buddhism. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Kieschnick, J. 2005. Buddhist vegetarianism in China. In R.Sterckx (ed.), Of Tripod and Palate:
Food, Politics, and Religion in Traditional China. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
Lusthaus, D. 2002. Buddhist Phenomenology: A Philosophical Investigation of Yogācāra Philosophy
and the Ch’eng Wei-shih lun. Abingdon: Routledge Curzon.
Mackenzie, M. 2013. Enacting selves, enacting worlds: on the Buddhist theory of karma.
Philosophy East and West 63(2): 194–212.
McGeer, V. 2013. Civilizing blame. In J. D. Coates and N. A. Tognazzini (eds), Blame: Its Nature
and Norms. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
McGeer, V. 2015. Building a better theory of responsibility. Philosophical Studies 172(10): 2635–
49.
Rhys Davids, T. W. (trans.) 1965. The Questions of King Milinda. Delhi: Motilal Barnasidass.
Parfit, D. 1984. Reasons and Persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Patil, P. 2009. Against a Hindu God: Buddhist Philosophy of Religion in India. New York:
Columbia University Press.
Reichenbach, B. R. 1990. The Law of Karma: A Philosophical Study. London: Macmillan.
Repetti, R. (ed.) 2017a. Buddhist Perspectives on Free Will. Abingdon: Routledge.
Repetti, R. 2017b. Why there should be a Buddhist theory of free will. In R.Repetti (ed.),
Buddhist Perspectives on Free Will. Abingdon: Routledge.
Ronkin, N. 2005. Early Buddhist Metaphysics: The Making of a Philosophical Tradition
Abingdon: Routledge Curzon.
Ronkin, N. 2018. Abhidharma. In E. N. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy:
https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2018/entries/abhidharma/
Schlick, M. 1939. When is a man responsible? In The Problems of Ethics, trans. D. Rynin.
Hoboken, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Schmithausen, L. 1987. Ālayavijñāna: On the Origin and the Early Development of a Central
Concept of Yogācāra Philosophy. Tokyo: International Institute for Buddhist Studies.
26
Siderits, M. 1989. Thinking on empty: Madhyamaka anti-realism and canons of rationality.
In S.Biderman and B.A.Scharfstein (eds), Rationality in Question: On Eastern and
Western Views of Rationality. Leiden: Brill.
Siderits, M. 1997. Buddhist reductionism. Philosophy East and West 47(4): 455–78.
Siderits, M. 2003. Empty Persons: Personal Identity and Buddhist Philosophy. Farnham: Ashgate.
Siderits. M. 2007. Buddhism as Philosophy. Farnham: Ashgate.
Siderits, M. 2008. Paleo-compatibilism and Buddhist reductionism. Sophia 47: 29–42.
Siderits, M. 2015. Does Buddhist ethics exist? In The Cowherds, Moonpaths: Ethics and
Emptiness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Tillemans, T. 2016. How Do Mādhyamikas Think? London: Wisdom Publications.
Vargas, M. 2013. Building Better Beings: A Theory of Moral Responsibility. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Vargas, M. (this volume). ‘Instrumentalist Theories of Moral Responsibility’ in M.Vargas &
J.Doris (eds.) Oxford Handbook of Moral Psychology, Oxford: Oxford University Press
Waldron, W. 2003. The Buddhist Unconscious: The ālaya-vijñāna in the Context of Indian
Buddhist Thought. Abingdon: Routledge Curzon.
Westerhoff, J. 2018. The Golden Age of Indian Buddhist Philosophy, Oxford: Oxford University
Press
Wright, D. 2005. Critical questions towards a naturalized concept of karma in Buddhism.
Journal of Buddhist Ethics 12: 78–93.
27