Indian Philosophy
Indian Philosophy
Indian Philosophy
Indian Philosophy
Also available from Continuum:
Phenomenology, Michael Lewis and Tanja Staehler
The Philosophy of History, Mark Day
The Philosophy of Mind, Dale Jacquette
The Philosophy of the Social Sciences, Robert C. Bishop
Forthcoming:
Classical Chinese Philosophy, Im Manyul
Critical Thinking, Robert Arp and Jamie Carlin Watson
Ethics, Robin Attfield
Metaphysics, Jonathan Tallant
Philosophy of Language, Chris Daly
Philosophy of Law, Jeffrey Brand-Ballard
Philosophy of Science, Emma Tobin
Pragmatism, John Capps
An Introduction
to Indian
Philosophy
Christopher Bartley
Continuum International Publishing Group
The Tower Building 80 Maiden Lane
11 York Road Suite 704
London SE1 7NX New York, NY 10038
www.continuumbooks.com
Christopher Bartley, 2011
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in
any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying,
recording, or any information storage or retrieval system, without prior permission
in writing from the publishers.
British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library.
ISBN: HB: 978-1-8470-6448-6
PB: 978-1-8470-6449-3
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Bartley, C. J.
An introduction to Indian philosophy / Christopher Bartley.
p. cm.
ISBN 978-1-84706-448-6 ISBN 978-1-84706-449-3
1. Philosophy, Indic. I. Title.
B131.B327 2010
181'.4dc22
2010012597
Typeset by Newgen Imaging Systems Pvt Ltd, Chennai, India
Printed and bound in India by Replika Press Pvt Ltd
For my wife Loretta, with love
This page intentionally left blank
Contents
Introduction: Some Types of Indian Religiosity 1
1 Foundations of Brahminism: Vedas and Upanis
.
ads 7
2 Buddhist Origins 13
3 Abhidharma Buddhism 26
4 Sautra ntika Buddhism 35
5 Na ga rjuna and Madhyamaka Buddhism 56
6 Mind-Only: Yoga ca ra Buddhism 68
7 Sa m
.
khya and Yoga 82
8 Nya ya and Vaises
.
ika 90
9 The Mma m
.
sa Vision 117
10 Veda nta 134
11 Advaita-Veda nta 138
12 Visis
.
t
.
a dvaita-Veda nta 168
viii Contents
13 Dvaita-Veda nta and Madhva 184
14 Tantra: Some S
lambana-parks
.
a 42
Extracts from The Examination of Objective Supports of
Awarenesswith the authors own commentary
(A
lambana-parks
.
a -vr
.
tti ) 43
Dharmakrti 45
Metaphysics 46
Perception and thinking 47
The impossibility of permanence 50
Logic 51
The authority of the Buddhas teachings 54
Further reading 54
Questions for discussion and investigation 55
4
Sautra ntika Buddhism
The last chapter saw brief references to the Vibhajyavda tradition. This out-
look became prominent and acquired the name Sautrntika. They maintained
that only the Pli Suttas, not the Abhidharma texts, were the authentic words
of the Buddha. They think that the Vaibhs.ikas have obscured the simplicity of
the Buddhas original teaching and introduced the notion of permanence in
the guise of svabhva. Hence they taught a doctrine of radical momentariness
(ks. an. ika-vda), and simplified the ontology of the Vaibhs.ikas. They reject the
An Introduction to Indian Philosophy 36
latters category of unconditioned phenomena, holding that space is just
the absence of extended objects. They say that nirvn. a is simply the non-
occurrence of suffering and not a reality or state of being. They reject the
category of the citta-viprayukta-dharmas. So there are no avijapti-dharmas,
underpinning karmic causality and no prapti accounting for continuities
within a stream of experiences. Also rejected are the smnya-laks. an. as
(birth, continuation, entropy and impermanence) characterizing the brief
occurrence of dharmas in conditioned complexes.
The Vaibhs.ikas say that the atomic basic realities (dharmas) are permanent
essential natures (svabhva) that may or may not exercise their causative
functions in and as the world. The Sautrntikas retain the notion of dharma
but abandon that of intrinsic nature (svabhva). We saw in the last chapter
that there may be a problem lurking behind the Vaibhs.ikas apparent inter-
pretation of intrinsic nature as causal power. The reason for positing intrinsic
natures for the dharmas is to enable their identification in virtue of their inde-
pendent self-sufficiency and thus to distinguish them from the conditioned,
fluid and transient macroscopic formations that they constitute. But in fact
intrinsic nature is characterized in causal terms as the capacity to interact with
other dharmas. So each dharma is actually characterized in relational terms.
We are not really specifying their internal natures in categorical terms but only
in dispositional ones. Causal powers have to do with external relations. We are
not being told what the possessors of the causal powers are like in themselves.
So the picture is one of a giant causal flux, but with no explanation of the
intrinsic natures of the entities related in the flux. This picture the Sautrntikas
are happy to accept.
So the Sautrntikas retain the notion of basic particulars but reject that of
essence (svabhva). They understand the basic realities as instantaneous
unique particulars that are just moments of causal efficacy. They term the
basic realities svalaks. an. a, which was one of the Vaibhs.ika terms for intrinsic
nature expressed as causal efficacy. Such instants, dharmas minus svabhva,
may perhaps be understood as flashes of energies forming fields of forces.
The Sautrntikas insist that production by the co-operation of causes and
conditions obtains at every level, all the way down, and does not just apply to
macroscopic formations. All things are momentary in the radical sense that
they exist only for the moment at which they are produced. They argue that all
entities are inherently perishable, having no intrinsic tendency to continue in
existence. They reason that: Everything decays. Decay is non-existence. But
non-existence has no causes. So decay needs no external cause. It must be the
Sautra ntika Buddhism 37
intrinsic nature of things to be perishable. Given that perishability is natural,
they cease spontaneously at the moment of their origination. Accordingly,
there is no sense in speaking of real past and future phenomena, as the
Vaibhs.ikas do.
While the Vaibhs.ikas hold that aggregates of atoms are the direct objects of
perception, the Sautrntikas deny that the svalaks. an. as are directly perceptible.
We are acquainted with mental forms when clusters of svalaks. an. as, purely
causal potencies, somehow impart impressions of their forms (kra) to
conscious episodes. This theory is called skra-vda. Clusters of unique
particulars are the material causes and objective supports of perceptions. Our
experience of external reality is mediated by mental representations caused by
the interplay of evanescent particulars. There is some sort of co-ordination
(sarpya) between our mental images and the behaviour of the particulars. We
might consider here the case of rainbows. What we see are bands of colour in
the sky. But this phenomenal representation is caused by light waves refracted
off droplets of water. We do not directly see or feel the unique instants that
are, as it were, the raw materials of the world. Nevertheless they impress
themselves on episodes of awareness and are imperfectly grasped through the
filters of the mental images and concepts that they cause. Our concepts lead us
to reify the given and suppose that the reality basically consists of enduring
subjects confronting a world of objects, properties and structural principles.
The Sautrntikas say that there are instantaneous realities external to
minds and that they are inferable as the causes of the occurrence of mental
representations (jna-kra). If the contents of awareness are just mental
representations, how do we know that there is an external reality? The reply
is that our representations do not occur at random, but are about definite
objects at specific times and places. Moreover, since we have no control over
much of which presents itself in our experiences, it is unlikely that mental
representations have been entirely generated from within a stream of experi-
ences. Surely they have causes other than the immediately preceding moment
(samanantara-pratyaya) in a mental stream. They conclude that the causes of
our mental representations are evanescent realities external to experiences.
Opponents are quick to point out that self-destructing instantaneous particulars
do not last long enough to enter into even short-lived formations that could
cause anything. Indeed the view that existence means spontaneous destruct-
ibility will attract the charge of nihilism. And we shall see that the Sautrntika
representationalism may lead to idealism, which says that there is no need to
posit realities external to minds and that only ideas are real.
An Introduction to Indian Philosophy 38
Ethical consequentiality
The Sautrntikas account for karmic continuity by saying that an intentional
action, albeit instantaneous, is a seed that initiates a transformation in an
experiential series (citta-sam. tna-parin. ma-vies. a). Its fruition is either
reward or punishment. The originating cause need not last until its effect is
realized since it is not a sustaining cause like parents who are necessary for
the origination but not the continued existence of their offspring. They argue
that if an action continued to exist until its fruition, it would have to be eternal.
But if it ceased to exist, it could not produce anything. A seed initiates a series
beginning with germination. The fruit arises as the culmination of the series,
rather than directly from the seed. But it still needs the seed to start the process.
Although the series and the result depend upon the seed as the originating
cause, we do not say that the seed is either annihilated or that it is eternal.
Likewise an intention initiates a series of mental events from which the con-
sequence results. The series requires the initial intention and the consequence
arises from the series. The intention is neither annihilated, nor is it eternal.
Dignaga and Dharmakrti
Dignga (480540 A.D.) was a Buddhist philosopher whose most important
work is the Pramn. a-samuccaya. He also wrote a work called The Examination
of Objective Supports of Cognition (lambana-parks.), extracts from which
are translated below. He belonged to the Sautrntika tradition of thought, which
while admitting a real domain of instantaneous particulars external to minds
claims that what we know are only its reflections mediated by mental images and
discursive concepts. Dharmakrti (600660 A.D.) developed Digngas ideas and
exercised an inestimable influence on subsequent debates. His works include the
Pramn. a-Vrttika, the Pramn. a-Vinicaya and the Nyya-bindu. His treatise
called the Proof of Other Streams of Experiences addresses the problem of other
minds and argues that there is a multiplicity of streams of experience.
Prior to Dignga most thinkers in the Buddhist tradition had accepted that
there are three means of knowing (pramn. a): sensory perception, inference
and reliable testimony (i.e. both human authorities and scriptural reports of the
Buddhas teachings). Dignga denies that testimony is an independent means of
knowing in its own right and subsumes it under inference. The rationale is
Sautra ntika Buddhism 39
that we do not unquestioningly assent to what a person says but accept that
their words are true only when we believe that they are well-informed, reliable
and sincere. But above all what is apparent is a repudiation of the authority of
the Vedic scriptures, which are held to be a pramn. a in their own right by the
orthodox Brahminical traditions.
Dignga divorces sensory perception (pratyaks. a) from thinking (kalpan)
that always involves concepts and words. The former is pure sensation whereas
the latter always involves words, concepts and judgements. Dignga calls it
inference (anumna). Sensory perception never involves general concepts
(smnya-laks. an. a). Perception, always valid because there is no scope for dis-
tortion by the workings of the mind, is direct experience of external reality,
which consists of fluid clusters of unique, momentary particulars (svalaks. an. a).
Because they do not share any common features, particulars are indescribable.
We have here an instance of a reductionist and nominalist outlook: everything
truly real is individual or particular.
The expressions svalaks. an. a and smnya-laks. an. a are inherited from
the Abhidharma. There svalaks. an. a means the characteristic activity of an
individual basic element (dharma) as it is in itself, and smnya-laks. an. a
means the features common to dharmas when their combinations produce
conditioned, macroscopic formations. Such generalities include non-eternity,
unsatisfactoriness and lack of persisting identity. As a Sautrntika, Dignga
accepts that reality consists of clusters of unique instantaneous particulars
(svalaks. an. a) and denies that each atomic factor has an unchanging and eternal
essence. General features are conceptually constructed by perceivers.
Moreover, he believes that the categories of things (padrtha) that the Nyya-
Vaies.ika realists claim to be basic structures discovered in the world are in fact
imposed by the workings of our minds. He says that conceptual construction
(kalpan) is the interpretation of what is given in pure sensation by means of
proper names, words for general features (jti, smnya), words for qualities
(gun. a), words for actions (karman) and words for individual substances (dra-
vya). Our minds group unique particulars together and understand them as
continuing objects bearing types of properties. In other words, the construc-
tive activity of minds constitutes objects out of the flux of sensation. In reality,
there are no universals, no real stability and no entities with determinate
identities.
Dignga thinks that thought and language are inseparable: conceptual thought
is born out of language and language is born out of concepts. Conceptual thought
An Introduction to Indian Philosophy 40
and language deal in generalities (smnya-laks.an. a). But because there are
no objective general features, even simple concepts are at one remove from
reality. They are causally related to the realities and not just arbitrary fictional
inventions. But there is a gap between how our minds work and the way
things are. It is a mistake to suppose that the map is the territory. His view is that
concepts and thinking are interpretations that disguise rather than disclose.
So all inferential procedures are distanced from reality. Logic is not about
reality as rightly articulated in language, but is a set of rules governing the
moves in a conceptual language game. All this convention involving inferen-
tial reason and properties to be established is based on the distinction between
property and property-possessor which is itself imposed by the human mind:
it is not grounded in anything existing outside the mind. But his contribution
to an empiricist theory of inference was very influential, although it must be
borne in mind that it is similar to ideas found in the works of Vasubandhu and
in a text called the Nyyapravea. Dignga proposed that in a valid inference,
we must have observed cases of an inseparable connection (avinbhva-
sam. bandha) between the logical reason (hetu) and what it establishes (sdhya).
We observe wherever the reason occurs, there the sdhya occurs also. We
can be confident that we are reasoning reliably and responsibly (the three
conditions are not claimed to be of an absolute guarantee of truth) when
three conditions (trairpya) obtain:
(i) The logical reason (hetu) must really be a property of the subject (paks
.
a) of the
inference.
(ii) The logical reason must be present in some instance (sapaks
.
a) other than the
subject of the inference, which is similar to that subject in that it too possesses
the property that is to be proved (sadhya).
(iii) Whatever lacks the property to be proved also lacks the proving property or rea-
son. There must be no instances (vipaks
.
a) where the proving property occurs and
the property to be proved does not.
Take the inference that sounds (paks.a) are impermanent (sdhya) because they
are products (hetu). [Invariable association: Whatever is produced is imperman-
ent.] Here the sapaks.a could be something uncontroversially impermanent
such as a pot that also exhibits the property of being a product. It is open to us
to cite an actual instance illustrating the joint absence of the property to be
proved and the logical reason. The atmosphere would be a negative example
because it both lacks impermanence and is not produced by effort.
Sautra ntika Buddhism 41
Apoha: the exclusion theory of
linguistic functioning
The thinkers of the Nyya-Vaies. ika realist tradition think that objective
general features (universal properties, natural kinds, qualities such as colours,
shapes and sizes) are the grounds for the repeated applications of general
terms. On this view we classify some individual animals as cows because they
form a natural kind. The single, real universal property being a cow is itself
an entity common to all cows. But Dignga is an anti-essentialist and a nomi-
nalist who denies that there are any objective generalities structuring and
causally regulating the world, which consists of instantaneous unique and
indescribable particulars. But if there are really neither shared properties nor
even resemblances, how do words and concepts function? They cannot all
behave like proper names because in that case we could not say anything
about things. Digngas answer is that the word-meanings and concepts form-
ing the fabric of inherited and public conventional understanding exclude
each other. The idea is that words (and concepts) do not have meaning in
virtue of their referring to extra-linguistic realities. Rather, they are signs
whose meaning derives from their roles in a framework of significances,
where they stand in relations of opposition and complementarity. (Later
thinkers say that apoha means the mutually exclusive inter-relations of modes
of presentation (pratibimba) and concepts (vikalpa) that determine what we
deem objects and states of affairs.) Words and concepts normally have both
an inclusive and an exclusive role. Dignga emphasizes the exclusive func-
tion. A word is expressive when it excludes other meanings belonging to the
same system. Dignga denies that we need to posit a single real universal
property shared by all individual cows as the basis of the application of the
word/concept cow. It is sufficient that what those clusters of particulars that
we call cows have in common is just their being different from whatever is not
treated as a cow. We apply a meaning such as cow just on the basis of the dif-
ference of cows from everything else. This difference from non-cows is not a
genuine feature. Difference is purely relational. The word cow does not stand
for a property or essence. We sort some particulars because it suits human
interests to do so. Language is a network of mutually exclusive meanings that
we have conventionally constructed in accordance with what matters for us.
To illustrate: We apply the word analgesic to a variety of pills with totally
distinct pharmacological properties because they relieve pain. The concept
An Introduction to Indian Philosophy 42
analgesic is a humanly constructed one because pain relief is a matter of
interest to us. It should be noted that we have here a theory about the func-
tioning of language and not a theory about the acquisition of language or the
acquisition of language and concepts. Were it the latter, it would be impossi-
ble to explain how anyone could learn the meaning of a word in the first
place, because they would have to exclude an infinite range of other things.
As for the former, there is no problem: we are born into a beginninglessly
established linguistic community.
Self-awareness of mental events
All Buddhists deny that there is any constant experiencing subject that is
distinct from the process of awareness. So how do we account for the phenom-
enon of subjectivity? Dignga says that just as feelings are self-aware, each and
every perception and judgement is aware of itself (sva-sam. vitti): it is inherently
self-illuminating. A cognition simultaneously and in virtue of the same act
cognizes its own form as well as that of what it is about. If things were
otherwise minds would be like video-recorders receiving and recording
information and there would be no inner mental life. Reflexive mental events
follow each other so quickly that there is generated the illusion that there is a
persisting subject of experiences that we call a self.
The A
lambana-par ks
.
a
According to the Vaibhs.ika direct realists, the objective ground (lambana-
pratyaya) of a thought is the reality in the world that it is about. According to
this theory, an objective ground is both the extra-mental cause of an idea
and the provider of its representational content. An hallucination is not an
objectively grounded thought in the sense that it has content but it is caused by
some defect in the perceptual system. Dignga agrees that for something to
qualify as the objective ground of an awareness, it must be both the cause and
the representative content of that awareness, but he does not accept that such
causes have to be extra-mental realities.
In his lambana-parks. , Dignga argues against the Vaibhs.ikas that their
realistic atomic theory actually leads to the admission that the direct objects of
perceptual awareness are internal mental forms and not mind-independent
realities. The Vaibhs.ikas hold that we directly perceive structured masses
of real atoms of various kinds and that these cause our perceptions. Like
Sautra ntika Buddhism 43
Vasubandhu, Dignga questions the possibility of atomic aggregation. But
even granting that collections of atoms may cause mental representations, the
atoms do not figure in the subjective content of awareness. A compound of
clay atoms may cause the perception of a pot, but we do not see such a cluster
of atoms. The atoms do not enter into the content of the representation:
what we have is an experience of a solid, coloured extended object. It could
be argued that a conglomerate of atoms does constitute the representative
content. But the problem here is that conglomerates are not real and so fail to
qualify as causes of ideas. Dignga concludes that only an idea (a mental rep-
resentation that appears as if it is about something external) can be the support
of another idea. The cause of a mental representation can be another represen-
tation: thoughts may arise from other thoughts rather than from external
objects. An idea may bring about another idea and be sufficiently like it to mir-
ror its representational content. Although it seems that the conclusion is an
idealist one, Dignga is not an idealist. He believes that the momentary par-
ticulars exist independently of minds, but the direct objects of acquaintance
are their representations in consciousness. He wants to persuade us that our
shared, conventional framework of representations is just that, and that our
thoughts and concepts do not mirror reality as it is in itself. The goal is to
encourage us to realize that our everyday attachments, and our thinking in
terms of ourselves as persisting individual subjects confronting a world of
already established propertied objects awaiting our descriptive understanding,
are really just matters of conventional construction. Once such realization is
achieved we are in a position to detach ourselves from our basically self-
centred concerns and follow the path of insight and compassion leading
towards enlightenment.
Extracts from The Examination of
Objective Supports of Awareness
with the authors own commentary
(A
lambana-par ks
.
a -vr
.
tti)
People who believe that external things are the objective support of sensory
perceptions suppose that either atoms are the support since they cause the
cognition, or that a conglomerate of atoms is the support because such a form is
the representative content of awareness.
An Introduction to Indian Philosophy 44
Even if the atoms are the cause of sensory cognition, since the cognition
does not represent them, the atoms are not the intentional object (vis
.
aya) of the
cognition (just as the sensory faculties are not).
The expression intentional object means the proper form of something as it is
grasped in cognition, since the cognition is manifest as having that form (akara).
Although the atoms are the cause of the manifestation of the thought-form, their
nature is not grasped by cognition (just as the nature of the sense faculties is not).
Thus the atoms are not the objective support of cognition.
As for the conglomerate of atoms, although it is what is represented in
awareness, it is not the objective support because
It is not the cause of the phenomenal representation (abhasa).
It makes sense that when a thing produces a cognition that represents it as it is,
that thing is the objective support. It has been stated that such is the originating
condition. But the conglomerate of atoms does not qualify as such
because it is not a reality like the experience of the moon seeming double.
In the case of seeing the moon as double owing to a sensory defect, although
the moon appears double in awareness, it is not the direct object of awareness.
Likewise the conglomerate is not the objective support because it cannot be the
cause since it does not exist as a real entity.
Thus what is external is not the direct object of awareness.
The external things called atom and conglomerate of atoms are not the
supports of awareness, because although the atoms cause the awareness they do
not feature in its representative content, and while the conglomerate appears as
the content of awareness, it is not its cause.
Some hold that the aggregated form is the instrumental cause of the cognition.
The form of the atom is not the object of awareness, in the same way that its
solidity is not.
Everything is multifaceted. So it is perceived under some form or description. The
atoms have the nature of being the originating cause of awareness and are repre-
sented as conglomerates. Just as real solidity is not an object of visual perception,
likewise real atomicity is not.
While there are no differences between the atoms that make up objects, it
may be said that the differences between perceived objects emerge from the
different formations of atoms. But this is not the case because (according to
the opponent) the atoms that are the only true realities do not have different
dimensions. The differences between the forms of objects operate on the level of
human conventions. Conventional modes of differentiation do not apply to the
atoms. Everyday objects are posited by the human mentality.
Pots etc exist only as human conventions because if the atoms are taken away
the cognition whose form derives from them is lost. But this does not happen in
Sautra ntika Buddhism 45
the case of what is truly real. Therefore it is intelligible that the direct objects of
sensory perceptions are not realities external to minds.
But the knowable internal form, which appears as if external to the mind, is the
direct object because it has the form of awareness and is its support.
Although there are no external objects, an internal reality, an idea appearing as if
external, is the objective support.
The internal mental form is the objective support of awareness since it both
supplies the manifest image in the cognition of the object, and produces the cog-
nition of the object. (The internal form both supplies the manifest image belong-
ing to the cognition (which the atoms do not) and is the cause (which the
conglomerate qua unreal, cannot be)).
Dharmak rti
Dharmakrti identifies belief in a substantial, permanent and personal self as
a form of ignorance, indeed enchantment. This ignorance is a genuinely
effective occurrence that brings about a complex of a specific mentality and
behavioural dispositions (sam
.
skra). Belief in the self is inherited from mis-
taken constructions of selfhood in previous lives. From mistaken adherence
to belief in the self arise the moral defects (klea) such as desires, infatuations
and antagonisms. The settled condition that is attachment to the self is
expressed in first personal thoughts: The innate belief in a personal reality
is expressed in I-thoughts such as: May I be happy, may I not suffer.
Attachment to self is inextricably associated with the notion of mine and
this inevitably generates desires we want things to go well for ourselves.
It automatically generates hatred and aversions towards whatever is felt to
be inimical to ones own interests often what are imagined to be other selves.
Striving for personal happiness conceals the true nature of the moral defects
so we do not see them for what they are. As long as there is clinging to
self, there is rebirth. But following the Buddhist path, including repeated
meditation on the unreality of the person and the way in which belief in the
self s reality causes suffering and frustration, on the impermanence and
non-substantiality of phenomena, gradually eliminates misunderstanding
and the consequent moral defects. Interiorization of and insight into univer-
sal non-substantiality, seeing the truth, are the proper functions of a purified
mind. Philosophy helps by revealing that nothing real can be permanent. We
are captivated by an inherited and shared web of conceptualization
(kalpan). But the validity of the teaching that dispels our enchantment
(moha) is known by its fruits.
An Introduction to Indian Philosophy 46
Metaphysics
Dharmakrti agreed with Dignga that in the final analysis objective reality
is a flux of momentary particulars (svalaks. an. a) that are inexpressible and
incommunicable as such. By virtue of their configurations in relation to the
cognizing subject, they determine the differences in the representative content
of cognitions. Each svalaks. an. a has its own causal effectiveness (arthakriy).
Dharmakrti develops Digngas view. Instead of saying what is real by
specifying some type of entities (e.g. the svalaks. an. as or the dharmas), he uses
a criterion: only what is causally effective is real. Nothing permanent can be
causally effective either successively or in the present because it cannot engage
in processes of change. Each particular has specific location, time and form. If
something does not perform useful activity, then it is not a real entity, since it
satisfies the criteria for non-existence; but if it does perform useful activity,
then it is not permanent. This criterion of reality rules out the existence
of anything supposedly eternal and unchanging such as God, the soul and
its permanent consciousness, the sounds of the Vedic scriptures, the eternal
relation between Vedic words and their meanings, universals and primal
material nature (prakr. ti) that is inert prior to its plural manifestation as the
cosmos. The question about the reality of otherwise of permanence is central
to the dialectic between Buddhists and Brahmins, some aspects of which we
will be examining in later chapters.
Dharmakrti follows Digngas epistemology: only sensory perception and
inference are means of knowing (pramn. a). Knowledge is reliable cognition in
so far as it contributes to the successful accomplishment of some purpose. It
may also reveal something new: but to Dharmakrtis mind, the instrumental
function is primary and matter of fact truths are revealed in practice. Although
like Dignga he refuses to accept that testimony and language can be epistemic
authorities in their own right they are primarily thinking here of the absolute
authority that the Brahmins ascribe to the uncreated Vedic scriptures in fact,
he says that language may be an instrument of knowing in the derivative sense
that it communicates what are already established to be useful truths about
what is to be sought after and what avoided. The Buddha, and the scriptural
records of his teachings, are sources of knowledge in that they reveal things
that would be otherwise unknown, and tell the truth about what should be
pursued and what eschewed.
As we have seen, according to the Sautrntika outlook there are no permanent
realities. To be real is to be causally effective and that implies the capacity for
Sautra ntika Buddhism 47
change. But they take it for granted that were there anything permanent
it could neither act nor change. Dharmakrti says that there is no such thing
as a permanent means of knowing (nityam. pramn. am) such as the Vedic
scriptures or a divine intelligence because knowledge operates in a world of
changing realities. A means of knowing cannot be unchanging because it is
concerned with impermanent objects. Whatever happens as part of a process
cannot be permanent and unchanging. Something permanent could not be a
means of knowing about what is impermanent because it could not depend
upon assisting factors such as objects, subjects and instruments in the case of
the knowing process. The means of knowing are such because they enable us
to achieve our goals in a world of ever changing realities.
Perception and thinking
It is the particulars that are immediately given in sensory perception.
Dharmakrti outlines his view of knowledge and perception in the first
chapter of his Nyyabindu:
The accomplishment of human goals presupposes right cognition.
Right cognition is twofold: perception and inference.
Perception is free from conceptualisation (kalpana) and is reliable (lit. non-errant)
Conceptualisation is cognition involving a representation that is capable of
beingexpressed in words. (He thus modifies Dignagas view that thought and
language always go together in suggesting that thought is prior to language.)
Cognition that is both free from conceptualisation and from defects is sense-
perception (pratyaks
.
a) [as a means of knowing.]
That has four aspects:
a) Cognition involving the sense-faculties;
b) Understanding (mano-vijanam) produced by the sensory cognition that is its
immediate cause. This process takes the initial sensory cognition of the exter-
nal object as its object.
c) All minds and mental events are reflexively aware of themselves.
(The point here is that they do not require illumination by another conscious
principle such a conscious self). The reflexivity of awareness is used by some
Brahmin thinkers as a way of proving the permanence of the self.
d) Direct Yogic intuition into the atomic composition of reality that does not
require sense-faculties as intermediaries.
The momentary particulars (svalaks
.
an
.
a) are the objects of sensory perception.
They are what is real in the final analysis (paramartha-sat), because reality is that
which has the capacity for causal efficacy.
An Introduction to Indian Philosophy 48
Different from them is what falls under generalising conceptualisation (samanya-
laks
.
an
.
am).
That is the sphere of thinking (anumanasya vis
.
ayah
.
). [This is kalpana]
Perceptual cognition produces knowledge when thought enables us to achieve or
obtain something.
Knowledge is a cognitive state that is in conformity with reality, because success-
ful activity follows when cognitions agree with realities.
Dharmakrtis theory about the relation between perception and the world can
be understood in terms of the triad: sensation image concept. A cluster of
svalaks. an. as has the power to produce the sensation of blue. Blue impressions
produce an awareness having two aspects: a blue mental image (kra) and the
blue mental images being aware of itself. The image copies the impressions.
Constructive mental activity (kalpan), conditioned by traces of prior experi-
ences, interprets the image and produces the thought (vikalpa) that something
is blue. This thought enables us to think, act and communicate. The external
particulars are only the indirect objects of the thoughts that they cause. But
the unique instants behave in such a way that we can organize them under
unifying concepts. While our concepts, involving the association of names
and general properties with the given, do not copy the fluid play of the real
particulars, they represent it indirectly as a map does as territory. We do
not directly know reality as it is in itself because we are primarily aware of
images, some of which are converted into concepts, derived form sensory
impressions. In short, there is a gap between the way our minds work and the
way things work.
Sense perception on its own has no practical application because it does
not discriminate anything. Assuming that the senses are operating normally
and environmental conditions do not obstruct them, it cannot be either true
or false because truth and falsity apply only to conceptual mental states.
Perceptual sensation applies to reality as it is in itself (vastu) before we start to
thinking about it. But it is only when an aspect of reality has been mentally
discriminated in a perceptual judgement (adhyavasya) that we can act in rela-
tion to it. Judgements using concepts enable successful activity (i.e. are reliable)
when they are causally related to the real particulars constituting events.
A vikalpa is a concept that the mind constructs out of the data given in
sensory awareness. Cognitions involving apparently shared features of objects
are conceptual interpretations based on experiences of particulars. Conceptu-
alization involves generalizations but there are no objective generalities.
Sautra ntika Buddhism 49
Objective reality is strictly ineffable, since it includes no general features. Like
Dignga, he wants us to realize that our conventional ways of understanding,
integral to which is the notion of individual subjectivity, in the final analysis
disguise the truth.
But to find our way around successfully, we need to make discriminations
using concepts and words. Some concepts, and elaborated conceptual schemes,
apply more adequately than others to objective reality: i.e. they work better for
us in leading to successful activity. Vikalpas interpret and organize the data of
sensation, making them intelligible and serviceable. The store of human
concepts, built up from impressions derived from a beginningless series of
previous experiences, is transmitted down the generations via shared language.
While some complex concepts ultimately derive from sensory impressions
and mental images formed from them, others, especially the idea that there is
a persisting soul, are just produced by the creative imagination.
A problem arises when people overlook the purely conventional nature of
what are only human ways of thinking and suppose that they correspond
to objective realities. It is a natural mistake to suppose that our concepts
are copies of reality or that our representations mirror reality as it is in itself.
Error occurs when conceptual thought takes its own forms to correspond
directly to reality. Since reality consists of momentary unique particulars,
general concepts cannot represent it as it is in itself. Moreover, stable concepts,
enshrined in language, encourage us to think that there are stable realities.
A much-quoted verse (354) from the Chapter on Perception of the
Pramn. avrttika reads:
Mind is really not diversified but it appears to be differentiated into objects
known or grasped (grahya), perceivers (grahaka) and cognitions because of
mistaken views.
Later thinkers sometimes read this in an idealist sense, but that it not
Dharmakrtis meaning. He means that the oppositions between the perceiv-
ing subject, objects and thoughts are functions of the way our minds work and
not genuine realities. It is we who contrast subjects and objects, thinking them
external to each other. The differentiation of subjects, acts and objects of cog-
nition within the one mind appears because of inherited influences of previous
ideas in a beginningless and uninterrupted stream of experiences. Positing
oneself as an individual thinker facing a world of objects is a kind of selfishness
that Buddhist practice aims to eliminate. Since the polar notions of object and
subject are interdependent, by exposing the falsity of one, we can expose the
An Introduction to Indian Philosophy 50
falsity of the other. Once a person has really understood that the conventional
view of reality as consisting of enduring objects existing independently of the
mind of the individual perceiver is false and that our thoughts are not copies of
reality, they can come to understand that selfhood and its attachments is an
illusory construct.
The impossibility of permanence
We have seen that Dharmakrti takes dynamic causal efficacy as criterial of
reality. It follows that nothing can be permanent and static. Dharmakrtis
opponents recognize different forms of permanence (nityat). By permanent
they mean both eternal and immutable. (Some realists distinguish two
varieties: absolute permanence and permanence compatible with change.)
Nyya and Vaies.ika ascribe permanence to kinds, universals and some
relations. The Mmm. saka ritualists say that both the basic sound units (varn. a)
of the Sanskrit language, the relation between a Sanskrit word and its meaning,
and the Vedic scriptures as a whole are all permanent realities. Others hold
that consciousness is the permanent nature of the soul. The Sm. khyas, for
example, say that the true nature of the soul is permanently static conscious.
(Dignga had challenged this tenet with the consideration that if the self really
changes when a cognition occurs, it is impermanent. But if it does not change
when cognition occurs, it is not a knowing subject.) The consensus among
the various sorts of realists is that permanent realities are revealed and known
by their appropriate manifestations (vyakti) in space and time. Individual
entities are manifestations of universals. A specific usage of a word manifests
a timeless meaning. The evolutes of the material nature (prakr. ti) postulated
as the universal material cause by the Sm. khyas are its manifestations. Realists
argued that such manifestation does not compromise eternity and immutability.
Dharmakrti says that manifestation entails mutability. If there are universals,
they could never be manifest in individuals. Similarly, if the sounds of the Vedas
are permanent, we could never hear their manifestations. If the soul is eternally
of the nature of awareness it would always know everything or nothing.
Dharmakrti examines the notion of manifestation in the context of
the revelation of objects by the cognitive process. On a realist account, some
form of cognitive activity, accompanied by factors such as light, is instru mental
in revealing already existing realities. But according to Dharmakrti, since
everything is momentary there can be no already existing objects. Objects
Sautra ntika Buddhism 51
have to be constituted out of the data of sensation. He insists that whenever
such objects are cognized, this happens as an aspect of a process. Take a stream
of moments that someone may identify as constituting a vase. The stream is
occurring in a dark room. Open the door and switch on the light. You see the
vase. It becomes manifest. Dharmakrtis view is that the presence of the
observer (and the light) has introduced a change into the situation. The stream
of vase moments is not what it was. It is now involved with the light and
the cognitions of the observer. The latter introduce additional factors that
render the pot-stream capable of producing a cognition in the observer. The
manifestation or revelation of the pot is the product of the co-operation of a
variety of causes upon which it depends. Now consider the possibility of the
manifestation of permanent realities whose natures are supposed to be entirely
self-sufficient and independent of co-operating extra factors. If the essential
nature of an entity of that kind is such that it is productive, it will always
produce its characteristic effects. If its essential nature is such that it is not
productive, it will never produce effects. Let us apply this to consciousness:
if the nature of consciousness is to actually illuminate objects, it will always
illuminate everything. And in the case of universals, if being manifest as
individual instances is internal to their nature, they will always be manifesting
all their instances (and we will be aware of them). In the normal case of
cognition (of the vase), manifestation was dependent upon co-operating
causal factors and crucially upon the introduction of an extra-factor into
the situation that rendered the stream of moments capable of producing an
awareness. But this cannot apply in the case of allegedly permanent entities
that are supposed to be in principle knowable. When Dharmakrti concludes
that their revelation is impossible, he is assuming the realist consensus that if
something is real, it is in principle if not in fact knowable.
Logic
As we have seen Dharmakrti thinks that while immediate sensation relates
directly to reality that consists of unique instantaneous particulars, the mental
images (kra) and concepts (vikalpa) that they cause and in terms of
which we interpret what is given do so indirectly. But Dharmakrti does
not think that our concepts are imaginary inventions, although some are.
The instantaneous actualities behave in such a way that we can organize
them under concepts. Although the natural regularity (svabhva-pratibandha)
An Introduction to Indian Philosophy 52
between smoke and fire or that between somethings being an oak and its
being a tree holds primarily between two concepts, it also reflects a real state
of affairs that causes us to make the connection between the concepts.
Dharmakrti says that inference does not grasp the realities directly in that it
operates by determining the object in a mental representation that is not itself
the object. But because the representation of the object is causally related to
the real objects, we can make reliable inferences.
The key feature of a valid logical inference is the invariant association
(vypti) between the logical reason (hetu) and what is to be established
(sdhya). Dharmakrti says that the invariant association of As with Bs (which
he also calls avinbhva sine qua non) must be guaranteed by a natural
regularity (svabhva-pratibandha). The theory of natural regularity attempts
to underpin some forms of inseparable connection in the absence of objective
universals. We know that the connection between the logical reason and the
property to be proved could not be otherwise when the connection is either
that between cause and effect (krya-hetu: e.g. fire and smoke) or a case of
shared nature (tadtmya /svabhva-hetu if something is an oak, then it is a
tree). This necessary relation is the natural regularity. So we may infer from
the fact of somethings being an oak that it is a tree and from the presence of
smoke to the presence of fire. This principle is applied in characteristically
Buddhist arguments like, If something is produced, it is perishable by nature.
While Dignga seems to have been content to allow that the idea of
invariable association is the product of a finite range of observed instances,
as well as the lack of counterexamples (adarana-mtra), Dharmakrti wants
to strengthen the basis of inference because the inductive approach is insuffi-
ciently general and leaves open the possibility of our discovering exceptions in
the future. His teacher varasena thought that our constant association of the
logical reason (hetu) and that which is to be established (sdhya) was based
merely on the fact of our not having observed any exceptions to the rule
(adaranamtra). Dharmakrti thought that this made the basis of inference
too fragile: why should we not discover an exception in the future? Moreover,
we have not surveyed every relevant instance. We do not know that there is no
instance where the hetu occurs and the sdhya does not. We just have not
come across one so far. This is why he argued that the inseparability of hetu
and sdhya had to be grounded in the natural order of things. This means that
the presence of the logical reason guarantees the presence of the property to be
proved. There can be no counterexample.
Sautra ntika Buddhism 53
We saw that causal connection is one of the two forms of natural regularity
between the logical reason and what is to be proved. A causal relation is
understood through positive and negative perceptions. The causal connection
between smoke and fire is known when we find that smoke, which had not
been present, appears when fire is introduced and that when the fire is
extinguished, the smoke disappears.
Dharmakrti applies this in a proof of the existence of streams of experience
other than ones own. He argues that we have inferential knowledge of other
minds. Given that in ones own case there is observation of the phenomena of
language and behaviour immediately after volition or intention, and given that
they are not observed in the absence of volition, one knows from ones own
case that there is a cause-effect relation between volition and the occurrence of
actions. The causal relation is established purely because we are cognizant of
the relations between intention and action and know that where there is no
intention there is no action. Seeing that actions separate from us occur even
when we have not framed any intention, we infer intentions elsewhere to be
the cause of those other actions. Thus other minds are established. Just as I
know from my own case that certain actions are preceded by certain thoughts,
so I may analogously infer that similar patterns of speech and behaviour on the
part of other people show that they are separate streams of experiences.
According to Dharmakrti, the non-apprehension (anupalabdhi) of an
entity that is in principle perceptible (dr. ya) establishes the absence or non-
existence of that entity. This applies to the problem of other minds: from the
fact that we do not perceive them it does not follow that they do not exist
because they do not fall under the category of the in-principle perceptible. But
the case of the Brahminical concept of the Self (tman) is different. Those who
believe that the Self is a basic reality characterize it as something that should
be uncontroversially knowable. Dharmakrti and other Buddhists focus on the
problems of disentangling the soul from the personality and its experiences.
They reason that it is never known, although it is described as the sort of
thing that is knowable. This non-apprehension proves its non-existence. The
same pattern of reasoning is applied to the notion of Prime Matter (prakr. ti),
which is supposed by Sam. khyas and Vedntins to be the ultimate source
and underlying cause of all material products. But the fact that we do not see
supernatural entities, such as ghosts, does not prove that they do not exist
because they are by nature inaccessible to normal perception. This applies to
anything inaccessible to perception by virtue of space, time or its nature.
An Introduction to Indian Philosophy 54
The authority of the Buddhas
teachings
Dignga had subsumed reliable testimony, including scriptural statements
about unverifiable matters, under inference as a means of knowing (pramn. a).
We infer that the Buddhas teachings are valid because we know that he was
reliable and sincere, and above all the teaching works in practice. Dharmakrti
is more radical. He denies that any scripture concerned with the supernatural
and suprasensible matters can really have epistemic authority. Human cogni-
tive possibilities are ordinarily restricted to objects that are actually percepti-
ble, in principle perceptible and hence inferable. We have no access to the
supernatural. But the religious person must be concerned with matters outside
the range of our ordinary cognitive capacities. Where ordinary human author-
ities are lacking, he must have recourse to some scriptural authority if he is to
pursue a way of life that conduces to well-being (purus. rtha). So his situation
is that of one who must choose which of the scriptures and which form of
religious praxis to follow. The best we can do is to follow the Buddhas advice
and adopt what works. We have no means of knowing about the supernatural.
All we can do is hope that if a body of scriptures is a reliable guide to living well
here, their teaching about what is unverifiable is trustworthy too.
Further reading
Satkari Mookerjee, The Buddhist Philosophy of Universal Flux is about both Dignga and Dharmakrti
and the many disputes between their school and the Naiyyika, Mmm. saka and Sm. khya realists.
M. Hattori, Dignaga, On Perception reconstructs some of the first chapter Pramn. a-samuccaya and
covers much more than perception.
R. Hayes, Dignaga on the Interpretation of Signs, has translations of chapters II and V of the
Pramn. a-samuccaya.
There is a translation and exposition of the lambana-Parks. in Tola and Dragonetti (2004).
For the text of the Pramn. avrttika see Pandeya (1989). For that of the Nyyabindu see Svami
Dvarkadasa Sastri (1994).
Kajiyama (1998) translates a work belonging to the Dignga-Dharmakrti tradition.
John Dunne, Foundations of Dharmakirtis Philosophy contains detailed treatments of ontology,
epistemology, logic and the philosophy of language. There is a valuable Appendix of translations.
Siderits (1991) deals with the philosophy of language, especially the apoha theory, which
has attracted much scholarly attention in recent years. The Nyya response is to be found in
Uddyotakaras commentary on Nyya-Stra 2.2.63. (Jha (1984), p. 1034 ff.)
Sautra ntika Buddhism 55
The articles in Tom Tillemans, Scripture, Logic and Language combine philosophical acuity and
philological expertise.
Vincent Eltschinger, Penser lautorit des critures does much more than that and is a mine of
information about Dharmakrtis intellectual context and religious concerns.
Bimal Matilal, Perception, relates Buddhist representationalism to modern concerns.
Claus Oetke (1994), Trairpya, puts Digngas logic in context, tracing its antecedents and relating it to
Nyya and Vaies.ika parallels.
Questions for discussion and
investigation
1. Does the Sautra ntika account of moral responsibility make more sense than that of
the Vaibha s
.
ikas?
2. Is it possible to reconcile atomistic impersonality and moral responsibility?
3. Is Digna gas theory of language a credible one?
4. Why does Dharmakirti think that truth is the same as successful practice?
Chapter Outline
Verses from Na ga rjunas Ratna val 60
Refutation of Objections 65
Further reading 67
Questions for discussion and investigation 67
5
Na ga rjuna and Madhyamaka
Buddhism
Ngrjuna (c. 150200 A.D.) was a monk trained in the Abhidharma tradition,
which tried to delineate the basic structures of reality as understood from the
ultimate point of view. He repudiated this enterprise that involved categor-
izing mental and material phenomena into types of basically real elements
(dharma) having essential natures (svabhva). Sometimes when Ngrjuna
says that he is not offering a theory of his own, he may have the Abhidharma
taxonomical activity in mind! Ngrjuna holds that supposition that things
have unchanging and enduring natures, either at the fundamental or macro-
scopic level, only encourages us to become attached to them. He thought
that the Sarvstivdins were in effect aspiring to make statements about
reality as a whole from a totally objective point of view. Ngrjuna denies that
any such perspective is attainable by us unenlightened beings. There is no
point in our even attempting to distinguish between ultimate truth and
conventional truth.
His argumentative strategy is to list the possible propositions about some
subject-matter. He then examines them and shows that they are inconsistent
or lead to erroneous or unwanted conclusions. So he denies all of them. Using
this method, he tries to show that our theories and conceptual constructions
Na ga rjuna and Madhyamaka Buddhism 57
cannot capture reality. Since we are not Buddhas, we can attain no grasp of
reality as it is in itself.
His most significant philosophical works include the Madhyamaka-kriks,
the Vigrahavyvartan and the Ratnval. His thought is the subject of a long
exegetical tradition that continues to this day. He is sometimes difficult to
understand. This is because we do not always know the specific questions
to which his statements are the answer. The most important commentator
is Candrakrti (600650 A.D.) who wrote the Prasannapad. ntidevas
(700750) Bodhicryvatara, describing the Bodhisattvas path to final
enlightenment is another influential work.
According to the Abhidharma traditions, the basic elements (dharma)
have intrinsic natures or essences (svabhva). Intrinsic nature was thought
to be timeless, self-sufficient, independent of all else and unchanging. (The
last predicate is crucial.) It is the possession of such permanent identity that
distinguishes the basic elements from the temporary conditioned aggregates
that are the objects of everyday thought and language and grounds the distinc-
tion between ultimate reality and conventional reality. Ngrjuna insists that
neither everyday objects nor the dharmas can have intrinsic natures. If they
had, there would be no change. Reification, the investiture of states of affairs
and objects with persisting identities, comes naturally to us. But in truth,
everything is empty of intrinsic nature (svabhva-nya). Emptiness (nyat)
must always be understood as meaning absence of essence. It does not mean
non-existence. He often says that what we normally consider things, and the
concepts with which we carve up reality, are neither real not unreal. That is to
say, while our discursive conceptual schemes and the entities that they posit do
serve our purposes to an extent, they cannot be the whole truth.
There are no entities with having intrinsic natures that have arisen either from
themselves, or from other things, or from both themselves and others, or from no
causes. [MMK 1.1]
Whether in the cause, or in the conditioning factors, or in a complex of causes
and conditions or in something else, nowhere are there found intrinsic natures of
entities. This is what we mean by saying that all entities are empty. For instance
the sprout is neither in the seed that is its cause, nor in the conditions such as
earth, water and air taken singly or collectively, nor is it a separate reality distinct
from the causes and conditions. Since there is no intrinsic nature there, the sprout
lacks an intrinsic nature. Lacking intrinsic nature means that it is empty. Just as the
sprout lacks an intrinsic nature and is empty, so are all entities empty because they
lack intrinsic nature. [VV 1]
An Introduction to Indian Philosophy 58
The origination of intrinsic nature from causes and conditions is not intelligible.
Intrinsic nature produced by causes and conditions would be created. But
how could intrinsic nature be created? For intrinsic nature is uncreated and not
dependent on anything else. [MMK XV, 12]
Since there is no entity (dharma) that has not arisen dependently on others, there
is no entity that is not empty of intrinsic nature. [MMK XXIV, 19]
Sometimes Ngrjuna says that whatever is interdependently originated
from causes and conditions is devoid of essential nature. That is true. But
he does not mean that lack of essence follows just from the fact of being
interdependently originated. The basic point is that there cannot be any
essences in the first place.
A typical argument against essence is: suppose that seeing is the essence of
the visual faculty, the efficient cause in a visual awareness. The visual faculty
cannot see itself. Seeing, the intrinsic nature of the visual faculty, only operates
in the presence of a visible object and light, and is consequent to another state
of awareness. So the visual facultys characteristic way of being actually depends
upon the co-operation of a variety of conditions. Its nature is not intrinsic to it.
Another argument is that if everything is impermanent, things cannot have
intrinsic natures. If being young is the essence of youth and being old the
essence of the elderly, what undergoes the ageing process? There is also a
difficulty in formulating the relation between essence and that which has
the essence. If essence is a characteristic of its bearer, the bearer must already
exist. But if the bearer already is an entity, the notion of essential nature is
superfluous. And to return to a point made above, the Abhidharma thinkers
appeared to understand essential nature in terms of causal power. But this
leaves open the question of what it is that has the power. He thought that
they were not really identifying essences, but talking about the dispositions of
entities to behave in certain ways.
Ngrjuna insists that the Abhidharma outlook is contrary to authentic
Buddhist teaching about momentariness and non-substantiality according to
which there are no unchanging, self-contained and self-sufficient realities.
Ngrjuna says that the Buddhist theory of causation (prattya-samutpda)
means that everything is interdependent and empty of own-nature. He says that
entities with essential natures would have to be uncaused or self-created, which
is impossible. There cannot be any basic elements with essences or immutable
natures. If reality basically consisted of dharmas possessing essence, the
universe would be static and there would be no changes. If the unsatisfactory
Na ga rjuna and Madhyamaka Buddhism 59
round of existences (sam. sra) had essence or a fixed nature, there would be no
possibility of nirvn. a and if nirvn. a had essence, there would be no sam. sra.
The Abhidharma distinguished between what is genuinely and substantially
real (dravya-sat) and what is treated as real or true by convention (or nominally
existent) (prajapti-sat). The possession of svabhva was criterial for being
genuinely real. Ngrjuna retains the distinction but does not see it as an
ontological one. For him, the distinction is between what we conventionally
take to be true (prajapti-sat) and the absolute standard, the standpoint of
the omniscient Buddhas. There are not two worlds or two dimensions of
reality, one conditioned and the other unconditioned. There is one reality that
can be understood from the point of view of enlightenment or from the point
of view of some conventional pattern of thinking.
Unenlightened people think of the world as a system of interactions between
more or less stable entities that have determinate identities. This is reification
or commodification and it is a basic, inherited and shared mistake. Ngrjuna
often compares our conventional outlooks to dreams, illusions and mirages that
cannot be classified as real or unreal. Ngrjuna believes that he is recovering the
original teaching of the Buddha because the belief that things and selves have
stable, enduring natures only encourages us to become attached to them.
Analysis reveals inconsistencies and shows that the conventional world-view
cannot be true. The realization that everything is empty of essence puts an end
to conceptual construction and reification. We cease to believe that our con-
cepts are capturing an objective reality. Insight into emptiness, the realization
that discursive thought cannot reach the truth, leads to a compassionate
outlook and mental peace, as one is no longer disappointed by the search
for certainties. When we realize that the concept of svabhva is incoherent,
we are on the path to enlightenment.
Not only does the Abhidharma distinction between conventional reality
and ultimate reality (dharmas with essential natures) collapse, but also we
cannot differentiate between sam. sra as the conditioned realm and nirvn. a as
the unconditioned. Ngrjuna insists that there is not the slightest difference
between sam. sra and nirvn. a. But there is a difference between the ways in
which we may understand things.
Ngrjuna recognizes that the Buddhas teaching about interdependent
origination, which is one way of expressing emptiness, was expressed in
conventional terms. Indeed, all the Buddhas teachings were. But it would be
a mistake to think that because the Buddha used the everyday categories of
commonsense, this somehow validates them. The Buddha, in seeking to point
An Introduction to Indian Philosophy 60
us in the right direction by recommending a way of life that he had found led
to enlightenment, had to use some language. He did not say anything positive
about nirvn. a because it is not a state, thing or entity.
Paradoxes and inconsistencies in our ways of thinking show that we cannot
formulate a complete and correct description of reality as it is in itself
independently of any particular perspective. In the Madhyamaka-kriks,
Ngrjuna subjects what realists take to be basic concepts such as those of
causality, motion, time, agency, self and substance to criticism. He shows that
they are cases of reification and conceptual construction. He thinks that it is
pointless to entertain the possibility that our limited conceptual capacities
and schemes can capture the ultimate truth. We cannot step outside the
world, look at it from the outside and make definitively true statements about
it as a whole. We cannot frame an absolute conception of reality and we are
wasting our time and spiritual possibilities in seeking to. We cannot formulate
a correct and comprehensive ontological theory from a totally objective
Olympian point of view, which is what the Abhidharma attempts to do. This
is one meaning of what he calls, the emptiness of emptiness. Emptiness is
not a reality and there is no essence of emptiness.
Verses from Na ga rjunas Ratna val
Chapter I
When we live well following the righteous path, the attainment of the ultimate
good follows. Those who practise the perfect life gradually achieve the ultimate
good. [3]
Living well is happiness, and freedom from rebirth is the ultimate good. Trust in
the Buddhas teaching and insight are the means to that good. If he has trust, a
person may share the path. If he has insight [into emptiness], he knows truly.
Of the two, insight is the most important, but trust comes first. [45]
One who does not transgress the path because he is led by his own desires,
antagonisms, anxiety and delusions is to be considered trusting. [6]
(The wise person reflects upon the moral value of his actions. He avoids
violence and killing, theft and sexual misconduct. He controls his tongue to
avoid lying, cruel words and malicious gossip.)
The unenlightened person is frightened when he hears the teachings I am not,
I shall not be Nothing belongs to me nor ever will. [26]
Na ga rjuna and Madhyamaka Buddhism 61
The Buddha has said that such fears are the result of a mistaken belief in personal
identity and possessiveness. [27]
In reality, it is a mistake to think in terms of I and mine because neither is a
reality when one has understood how things really are. [28]
The interactions of the five components (skandhas) arise from the sense of
personal individuality (aham
.
kara). Personal individuality is not a genuine reality.
If the seed of something is unreal, how can its sprout be real? [29]
When it is seen that the components are unreal, the sense of individuality is given
up. From the giving up of that, the skandhas no longer function. [30]
Just as one sees the reflection of ones face in a mirror, although it is not the real
thing, so one conceives individual personality on the basis of the components,
although it is not a genuine reality like the reflection of ones face in the mirror.
[3132]
Just as there appears no reflection of ones face without a mirror, so without the
five components individual personality does not appear. [33]
While there is grasping at the components, there is the thought I. When there is
belief in personal individuality there is karma and rebirth. [34]
[Just as a mirage looks like water, but is neither water nor really anything, so the
components look like a persisting self but they are not really a self. [54]]
The individual person cannot be produced either by itself, or by another, or by
both itself and another. Nor is it not eternal. When one realises this, personal
individuality vanishes and thence karma and rebirth. [37]
The pattern of thought here is applied in all manner of contexts. Nothing
can bring itself into being. It would have to exist already in order to do so.
If something (in this case, the person) is like that it is a permanent, eternal
reality, neither beginning nor ending. But it makes no sense to say that an
entity is produced by another. This is because a cause is a cause only in relation
to an effect. But if what we are calling the effect does not exist, it is absurd
to speak of the cause. If the cause is non-existent, the effect will be too. The
formulation not by itself and another follows from the first two.
When one understands the relation of cause and effect in this way, one realises
that the world as a whole cannot be considered as an entity that might or might
not exist. [38]
(If the notion of causation belongs to the sphere of our experience in that it is
to be understood in terms of relations between finite things, how can we apply
An Introduction to Indian Philosophy 62
it to the cosmos as a whole and argued that it must come from someone or
something?)
Followers of the Upanis
.
adic tradition do not worry when they say that familiar
worldly life will not exist in the state of liberation. So why are they afraid when we
say that there are no absolutely real entities here either? [40]
In the state of release (moks
.
a) there are neither individual identities nor the five
components. But if such a state is dear to you, why do you resist the elimination
of the self and the components in this life? [41]
It is not the case that nirvan
.
a is non-existent. But what could constitute it as an
entity? Nirvan
.
a is beyond the concepts of being and non-being. [42]
(Nirvn. a is not to be understood as some state or place that is concealed by the
world. It is a mistake to reify nirvn. a and think of it as something that exists as
a sort of parallel universe. We return to the original message of the Buddha:
Nirvn. a is just the extinction of the fires of greed, hatred and delusion.)
In brief, the nihilist theory denies that actions have consequences. This false view
is immoral and leads to hell. [43]
In brief, the true view is that actions have consequences. This correct view brings
merit and rebirth in good states. [44]
When thanks to insight one has ceased to think in terms of what is and what is
not, one no longer thinks in terms of merit and demerit. The good say that this is
freedom (moks
.
a) that is beyond good and bad births. [45]
* * *
If a cause is produced before its effect or simultaneously with it, in reality it is not
a cause. The concept of origination is incoherent, either from the absolute or the
conventional point of view. [47]
(As we said above: since something is identified as a cause only when it
produces an effect, if the relevant factor pre-exists the effect, it cannot be
considered as the cause. It can only be considered as the cause after the time
when the effect has come into existence and in that case its causal function is
superfluous. Ngrjuna is not saying that there are no entities. He is saying
that they are not essentially identifiable as causes and effects.)
Causal relations may be expressed like this: when A is present, B arises. For
instance when we have the idea of long, that of short arises. When something is
Na ga rjuna and Madhyamaka Buddhism 63
produced there is production of something else such as radiance after the
production of a lamp. [48]
If there is no short, there can be no long. There can be no radiance if no lamp is
produced. [49]
When one understands causality like this, it does not lead to nihilism. [50]
This is a classic statement of interdependent origination (prattya-samutpda).
Regularity is just a matter of one thing following another. There is no need to
posit invisible and innate causal powers. The point here is that an attempt to
understand causality in terms of the transformation of essential natures (or
any other metaphysical account such as satkryavda or asatkryavda) is
bound to fail and that disillusionment may lead to nihilism.
We move on to the problem of saying anything sensible about the onto-
logical status of the cosmos or about reality as a whole as it is in itself :
The world does not come into existence. It does not go out of existence. It does
not remain static even for an instant. How can we say that the world as a whole,
to which the categories of past, present and future do not apply, is real? [63]
In truth, since the temporal framework does not apply to either the world or to
nirvan
.
a, how can we specify a real difference between the two? [64]
Given that there is no duration, there is neither origination nor cessation. So how
can the world be produced, endure, and cease. [65]
Just as the concept of production cannot apply to the cosmos taken as a whole,
nor can that of time, and the correlative notions of origination, endurance
and cessation. The cosmos cannot have a starting point in time, if time is a
measure of change and times are relations between things in the cosmos.
Next we see a characteristic example of Ngrjunas arguments against the
Abhidharma:
How can existence be non-temporal if things are always changing? If it is not the
case that things are always changing, how can we account for their variability? [66]
If everything is momentary, how do things get older? But if things are not
momentary, in the sense that they remain the same, how do they get older? [68]
We move on to a critique of the metaphysic of essential temporality the view
that existence can really be reductively analysed into basic moments:
If an instant has an end, it must be supposed to have a beginning and a middle.
Given that the instant consists of three parts, it cannot be a basic reality. [69]
An Introduction to Indian Philosophy 64
Beginnings, middles and ends must be considered like the instant (i.e. similarly
reducible, so there is an infinite regress). The condition of being a beginning, a
middle and an end does not exist from itself or from something else. [70]
No atom is simple since it has many sides. No atom lacks sides (if it did it could
not be connected with others). The ideas of unity and plurality are mutually
dependent, as are those of existence and non-existence. [71]
This anticipates criticisms of the notion of atomic aggregation into larger
entities. The point is that if atoms do not combine, they cannot be simple
or atomic, which is a contradiction. Ngrjuna is saying that analytic reduc-
tionism as practised by the Abhidharmikas fails since we cannot identify
basic units. The later idealist argument will be that we cannot make sense of
physical matter.
Chapter II
As the Kadal tree and all its parts when split down the middle is not anything,
likewise with the person when it is analysed into components. [1]
Hence the enlightened ones have said that all dharmas lack intrinsic natures. They
have ascertained the real nature of the components and seen that they are not
substantial. [2]
It makes no sense to affirm or deny substantial identity. [3]
The Buddha has stated that what is observed and what is stated in scriptures is
neither true nor false. When there is an argument, there is a counter-argument
and neither is absolutely true. [4]
The universe is really beyond the categories of truth and falsity. In truth, we
cannot say it is or it is not. [5]
How could the omniscient Buddha affirm of the universe, about which no true
statement is possible, that it has an end, or that it is infinite, or that it is really
plural or that it is non-differentiated? [6]
People ask how many Buddhas have been, will come and are here now. But the
notion of a limit on the number of beings presupposes the three-fold temporal
framework. [7]
There is no cause of the growth of the world. Decay is relative to the three-fold
temporal framework. [8]
In this consists the depth of the teaching that is a secret from ordinary people:
that the world is like a magical illusion is the essence of the teaching of the
Buddha. [9]
Na ga rjuna and Madhyamaka Buddhism 65
An elephant conjured up by magic may appear and it may seem to have a
beginning and end. But really it has no beginning and end. [10]
Likewise we see apparent beginnings and ends of things in the world. But in
reality there are neither fixed beginnings nor ends. [11]
As a magic elephant comes from nowhere and goes nowhere, being due to a
conjurors pretence, it does not last as a reality. [12]
Likewise the world is like an illusion that comes from nowhere and goes to
nowhere. It does not last as a reality since it is only mental delusion. [13]
What then is the meaning of this world organised by the three times? It cannot
be said to be nor not to be, except from the conventional standpoint. [14]
Therefore the Buddha did not say whether it is finite or infinite, plural or single. [15]
Refutation of Objections
Ngrjuna wrote an important work called The Refutation of Objections
(Vigraha-vyvartan) in response to criticism levelled at his method by
followers of the Nyya school. He envisages an opponent who says that
the proposition that all entities lack intrinsic natures itself lacks one and thus
cannot deny anything. If he admits that the proposition has an intrinsic nature,
he is contradicting himself [VV 12].
What does it mean to say that a statement lacks an intrinsic nature? When
a statement is true, it is an example of language operating as an instrument of
knowledge (pramn. a). Ngrjuna is supposing that the opponent holds that
the essence of a pramn. a consists in its power (akti) to be an instrumental
cause that establishes the truth about things. So the point is that if a pramn. a
lacks intrinsic nature, it also lacks that capacity.
Ngrjuna replies that the opponent has not understood the meaning
of emptiness. Entities that are interdependently originated are empty of
intrinsic natures because they are dependent upon causes and conditions. His
proposition is indeed empty in this sense. But everyday objects, albeit empty,
perform their functions successfully. The same applies to his proposition.
Essence is not a precondition of functioning in an ever-changing world. The
statement has a therapeutic value for people who take it for granted that things
have essences.
There is also the objection from the Nyya school that Ngrjuna cannot
show that all things are empty, since such a demonstration requires that
there are valid means of knowing (pramn. as: i.e. perception, inference and
An Introduction to Indian Philosophy 66
testimony). The objects of the pramn. as must exist too, because one cannot
negate what does not exist. The opponent says:
You deny the reality of things after you have apprehended them by perception,
but you also say that the perception by which entities are cognised is not a
reality. [VV 5]
Ngrjuna replies:
If I apprehended an object by perception or inference or testimony, I could
then affirm or deny things about it. But I dont do that so the objection is not
sound. [VV 30]
If you hold that objects are established by means of knowing (praman
.
a), tell me
how you establish those means of knowing. [VV 31]
If the praman
.
as are established by other praman
.
as, there is an infinite regress.
There is neither beginning, nor middle nor end. [VV 32]
If you think that praman
.
as are established without praman
.
as, you have
abandoned your own doctrine. [VV 33]
A praman
.
a cannot establish itself, because something cannot exercise its
characteristic activity upon itself. [VV 3439]
If the means of knowing are self-established, they are established independently
of the objects known. Self-establishment does not require anything else. [VV 40]
If you think that the means of knowing are established independently of the
objects known, then those means of knowing are not means of knowing about
anything. [VV 41]
If the praman
.
as are established only in relation to the objects known, the objects
known are not established by the praman
.
as. [VV 43]
If the objects known are established independently of the means of knowing,
what is the point in seeking to establish the praman
.
as? [VV 44]
If you hold that the objects of knowing are established by the means of knowing
and that the means of knowing are established by the objects of knowing, you
cannot establish either. [VV 46]
If the praman
.
as are established by the objects known, and if those objects have to
be established by praman
.
as, then, because the praman
.
as have not been estab-
lished, the objects have not been established either. So how will the objects known
establish the means of knowing? [VV 48]
Na ga rjuna and Madhyamaka Buddhism 67
Further reading
David Burtons Emptiness Appraised is the best starting point. Chapter III of Paul Williamss Mahyna
Buddhism is helpful. His Altruism and Reality is mostly about the Bodhicaryvatra. See especially
Chapter V.
The Bodhicaryvatra is lucidly translated in Crosby and Skilton (1996).
Bhattacharya (1998) translates the Vigrahavyvartan. Lindtner (1982) contains much helpful
explanatory material, as well as texts and some translations. The most readable translations of the
Madhyamakakriks are those by Jay Garfield (1995) and Frederick Streng (1967). Chapters VIIX
of Mark Siderits, Personal Identity (2003), sees emptiness as a global form of anti-realism and offers
much food for thought.
Hahn (1982) has the text of the Ratnval.
For engagement with Nyya over the question of the pramn. as see especially Uddyotakaras
commentary on Nyya-Stra 2.1.819. This is translated in Jha (1984), p. 606ff.
Bimal Matilals Logical Illumination of Indian Mysticism (Matilal, 2002) is stimulating.
Questions for discussion and
investigation
1. Why does Nagarjuna think that the Abhidharma distinction between the absolute
and conventional dimensions of reality collapses?
2. Is Nagarjuna entitled to make any truth-claims?
Chapter Outline
Extracts from Vasubandhus Twenty Verses Proving that only
Mental Phenomena are Real (Vijapti-ma trata -siddhi) 72
Thirty verses on consciousness 74
Vasubandhu and Sthiramati on The Construction of Phenomena 76
Illustrative extracts from Sthiramatis Madhya ntavibha gat
.
ka 76
Further reading 81
Questions for discussion and investigation 81
6
Mind-Only: Yoga ca ra
Buddhism
Some Buddhists espouse an idealist form of philosophy in that they deny that
there are any material or physical realities existing independently of minds.
There are neither selves nor an external world but only constructs of selfhood,
agency and objectivity arising from the flux of momentary self-aware thoughts
and feelings. We must bear in mind here that the philosophers were also
monks, practising profound meditation every day. The point is reflected in the
designation of this tradition as Yogcra, which means, the practice of yoga.
(Other names include Citta-mtra, which means mind-only and Vijna-
vda or consciousness theory.) Meditation often involves experiencing what
are purely thought-forms as if about external realities. It is not surprising
that such people should be especially open to the possibility that what we
ordinarily take to be external realities are but projections of consciousness.
The Buddhist idealists have a strong sense that the ways in which we experi-
ence what we unenlightened beings call the external world is conditioned by
personal and subjective factors. Our mind-set or world-view determines how we
see the world. What makes one persons perception of a state of affairs different
Mind-Only Yoga ca ra Buddhism 69
from that of another is the moods, emotions and memories that one brings to
bear in the circumstances. This is illustrated by the point that when hungry
ghosts see a body of water, they see a mass of pus. Humans see it as a crystal
stream and drink from it. Such observations about the subjective constitution of
experience do not in themselves license any conclusions about the ontological
status of the physical world. But we shall see that these Buddhists present argu-
ments against the intelligibility of the concept of material substance.
The central figure here is Vasubandhu who lived during the period c. 350
400 A.D. Trained in Sarvstivda methods of analysis and meditation, he
wrote a work called the Abhidharmakoabhs. ya which is a critical survey from
a Sautrntika point of view of Buddhist realist schools. Another work is the
Karmasiddhiprakaran
.
a, which is a Sautrntika critique of realist notions
of how karma operates, and an attempt to reconcile atomistic impersonality
with moral responsibility and consequentiality. It appears that he moved
from a representationalist to an idealist philosophical position and wrote the
Madhyntavibhgastra, the Trisvabhvanirdea, the Vim. atik and the Trim. ik
from that point of view. His commentator Sthiramati lived around 550 A.D.
The Sautrntika representationalists think that it makes sense to suppose
that most of our perceptions have external causes. Mental contents are
representations (kra) caused by a world outside the mind to which they
bear some relation. That relation is not one of mirroring or picturing since
they hold that the external world really consists of a flux of unique momentary
particulars (svalaks. an. a) and does not feature as such in the content of
awareness. They posit an external world on the basis of the inference that
there has to be something that causes those experiences over whose occur-
rence we have no control (bhyrtha-anumeya), not as a result of direct
acquaintance (bhyrtha-pratyaks.a). We can see how easily this may encourage
an idealist outlook. The gulf between what is supposedly given in experience
and its interpretation in concepts, thinking and judging (an interpretation that
conceals rather than discloses) is just too wide. If we are not directly acquainted
with objects in the world, and if conceptual and descriptive thinking does
not reach out to the world, and if the existence of that world can only be
certified by inference (itself a mental activity), why suppose that there is an
extra-mental physical dimension to reality? If the manifest content of experi-
ence is determined by our thoughts rather than by objects in the world, we
might wonder what sense can be given to the notion of a mind-independent
reality. Surely it is falling out of the picture. If experience of a hypothetical
given the amorphous flux of ineffable particulars does not express that
An Introduction to Indian Philosophy 70
given as such but is posited as something that has a purely instrumental causal
role in the genesis of discursive thinking, actually concealing the true nature of
things, it is not obvious that experiences of such a given need be postulated at
all. Considerations like these (whose influence is apparent in Digngas
lambana-Parks. ) seem to be the impetus behind Vasubandhus move
towards idealism or the view that only the mental factors of existence
(vijaptis) are real. Vasubandhu came to reject the Sautrntika view that we
can validly infer that there is an extra-mental reality as the cause of our percep-
tual sensations. We do not need to posit a material dimension of reality in
order to explain the character of experiences, whose occurrence can be
explainedby the revival of traces of prior experiences (vsan or sam. skra)
within a stream. There is an argument from economy: it is always better to
assume one thing than to assume many. It is better to postulate potent mental
traces of experiences than to posit external objects. (Perhaps he thought that
the maxim that when something is seen, there is no need to postulate the
unseen begs the question.) He argued against the very coherence of the notion
of material substance. He rejected the Vaibhs.hika view that we are directly
aware of objects made up of real physical atoms. Atoms are partless and indi-
visible. As such they cannot join together. But if we insist that atoms come
together, they must have parts. If they coalesce, there will be no increase in
extent: if they have no dimension, they cannot combine to form larger objects.
If they have dimension, they will be divisible and this undermines atomism. If
there are no atoms there cannot be any wholes distinct from their parts. The
Vaibhs. ika realists hold that all mental acts have existent objects external to
the mind. They say that to be is to cause an awareness: anything that is the
referent of an awareness exists. Vasubandhu argues that dreams and hallucina-
tions show that this is not true. Perceptions do not necessarily depend upon
mind-independent realities.
We might suppose that as well as objects outside the mind, there is also spatio-
temporal determination. Vasubandhu replies that experience of such determina-
tion also occurs in dreams. In response to the argument that it appears that
there are many minds experiencing the same objective environment, Vasub-
andhu appeals to the Buddhist notions of hells, which are shared hallucinations.
Vasubandhu thinks that individual events in a mental series are aware
of themselves. An awareness is simultaneously and in virtue of the same act
self-cognized, just as a lamp illuminates itself while illuminating an object.
This tenet of the reflexivity of mental events is central to the idealist outlook:
It shows that an idea can be the object of another idea and that there is no need
to posit physical objects as the causes of our thoughts. Moreover, the reflexivity
Mind-Only Yoga ca ra Buddhism 71
of each individual mental event dispenses with the need for an independent
consciousness, an observer-principle with a perspective on mental states.
Like all Buddhists, Vasubandhu believes that it is the intentional actions
of sentient beings that are responsible for the diversity and organization of
the cosmos, which exists to be the environment in which the consequences
of actions are to be experienced. The Abhidharma thinkers understand this
realm to be basically constituted by the material and mental elements of
existence. The idealists reject the category of material elements and hold
that think that the elements of existence are only the mental ones. Lives are
streams of ideas (vijapti) ever emerging from a mental storehouse of vestiges
(laya-vijna) impressed by previous actions. These self-conscious ideas may
mistakenly conceive themselves as individual subjectivities, viewing ideas as
other than themselves and as constituting other streams.
Vasubandhus view is that unenlightened people lead an enchanted life con-
taminated by selfish attachments, aversions and delusions. Enlightened people
who are detached from the objects of sense realize that what we call the world is
a fabric of appearances. They are free from desires, aversions and delusions; in
particular the delusion that one is fundamentally an enduring, substantial soul,
a further fact over and above the stream of ones psycho-physical continuity.
Awareness of a mind-independent physical world is the product of habitual con-
struction by ideas projecting themselves as if external. People are individualized
not through relations to external circumstances but by a mind-set consisting of
their inherited traits, attitudes, moods, emotions and memories. Deconstruction
of such factors encourages detachment from everyday experience.
Our everyday environment and ways of life are considered a mirage conceal-
ing authentic reality. That reality is consciousness from which arises phenomenal
reality, the environments experienced by sentient beings. For the first moment
of consciousness he adopts the traditions expression the construction of phe-
nomena (abhta-parikalpa), which means the dichotomization of conscious-
ness into subjects and objects of awareness (grhya-grhaka-vikalpa).
The unenlightened mind is veiled by moral, emotional and intellectual
defects (klea), foremost among which are cravings, antagonisms and failures
in understanding. Defects spring from seeds embedded in streams of con-
sciousness. They suppress the pure factors that are conducive to salvation
and whose cultivation promotes a transformation of mind and conduct. The
Buddhist path, understanding, meditation and morality, is intended to
counteract the impure factors. The aspirant to enlightenment must focus
attention upon eliminating impurities. Internalization of the teaching that the
elements lack fixed and enduring identities (dharma-nairtmya) produces
An Introduction to Indian Philosophy 72
a non-discursive, direct intuition into the nature of unconditioned reality in
which subject-object dichotomy disappears. Intensification of this intuition
destroys all the defects, together with their seeds, in a stream of experience.
We have seen the basic tenet that what are ordinarily considered to be mate-
rial objects do not exist independently of awareness. The denial of the subject-
object-relation repudiates the outlook that we are individual subjects receiving
sensory impressions from a realm of material objects that are entities in their
own right independently of constructive consciousness. He thinks that no sense
can be made of the realist view that the perceiving mind confronts an inde-
pendently existing domain of physical objects. This is not just because thinking
about physical reality may be contrary to genuine spirituality but because
atomism as an account of a purportedly material domain external to minds is
incoherent. Like all Buddhist thinkers, he aims to provide a rationale for why
we should not be self-centred. A structural feature of the self-centred mentality
is that it thinks in terms of discrete subjects and objects. There is an internal
relation between this mentality and supposing that people and things have
timeless essences, permanent identities or unchanging natures. It does not mat-
ter whether what are considered objects are mental or physical. The real point
of perceptions-only (vijapti-mtra) is to help us to internalize and act upon
the truth that there are no individual subjects of awareness confronting things,
and each other as objects. The notion of the apprehending subject is relative to
that of there being mind-independent entities. Once it is realised that what we
think of as objects are not stable external entities, our everyday understanding
of cognition is transformed. Since subject and object are interdependent, the
subjective element is also eliminated. In short, he wants to undermine thinking
in terms of the pervasive subject-object polarity (grhya-grhaka-bhva, liter-
ally grasped-grasper relation) which conditions our outlook on life.
Extracts from Vasubandhus Twenty
Verses Proving that only Mental
Phenomena are Real (Vijapti-
ma trata -siddhi )
According to Maha yana, it is established that the three realms are only mental
(vijapti-matra). The words cittam (mind), manas, vijana and vijapti are syn-
onyms. Cittam includes all mental events (caitta). Only excludes material forms.
Mind-Only Yoga ca ra Buddhism 73
If awareness of objects required causation by external objects, dreams and delu-
sions would not be possible. Consciousness appears in the guise of external per-
ceptible objects. Ideas of objects are sufficient. They arise from a sub-conscious
store of mental seeds and traces of prior experiences. The Abhidharmikas says
that all cognitions have real objects. The first verse responds to this by saying that
some thoughts have unreal objects. The point is that reference to an extra-mental
feature is not a necessary feature of awareness. If some thoughts can have signifi-
cance in the absence of any external object, the question arises whether we are
right to assume that there are really any extra-mental items.
1. All this is just awareness, because there is manifestation of non-existent objects
as when a visually impaired person sees non-existent cobwebs etc.
Here the realist opponent says:
2. If ideas are not caused by external objects, they would not be determined by
time and place, there would be no shared experiences, and they would not
have effects.
If there could be awareness of colour and shape in the absence of an external
object with colour and shape, it has not been caused by an external object.
So why is it produced at a specific place and not anywhere? And why does it arise
at that place at a specific time and not always?
And why is it produced in the streams of experience of all who are present
at that time and place and not just in one, just as the illusory appearances
occur in the stream of the visually impaired and not in others?
And why are the hairs and bees seen by the visually impaired are not causally effect-
ive? Things seen in dreams do not perform the functions of their counterparts in the
waking state. Fictional cities dont do anything because they do not exist.
Hence, in the absence of external objects, spatio-temporal determination,
sharing of experiences and causally efficacy are unintelligible.
3. Spatio-temporal determination is established in dreams; evil spirits (pretas) in
immaterial hells share experiences for they all see rivers of pus.
In dreams, things are seen at specific places and times. So spatio-temporal deter-
mination is established without external objects. Beings in hell, who are there
because of similar maturation of karma, all see a river of pus. Thus is there shared
experience although the objects of awareness are not externally existing.
4. [The real is the causally effective] and there is production of effects as in
wet dreams. Again in the case of hell, all see the hell-guards and are punished
by them.
In erotic dreams there is emission of semen without intercourse. All the denizens
of hell suffer, although the guards be unreal, as a consequence of the maturation
of parallel karma.
An Introduction to Indian Philosophy 74
6. If you allow that the experiences of individuals in hell are the products of
purely mental karmic traces, why not admit that this applies to all
experiences?
10. The truth is that persons lack permanent identity. Put another way, the teach-
ing that everything is ideas leads to internalization of the truth that there are
no dharmas with permanent identities.
Material substance is impossible because:
11. The object in awareness is a not a single whole. It is not a multiple composed
of many atoms. Nor is it a conglomeration of atoms. This is because the
atoms do not exist.
12. Given its simultaneous connection with six other atoms, the atom would
have six parts. If the six occupy the same place, they would have the same
mass as one.
1315 develop the refutation of the conglomeration theory.
Thirty verses on consciousness
Vasubandhu also wrote a short treatise, called the Trim. ik or Thirty Verses,
which is a reflection upon the structure of consciousness and the phenom-
enology of experience. He begins by saying that the words identity (tman)
and element of existence (dharma) are variously applied to what are modi-
fications of consciousness (vijna-parin. ma). There are three types of such
modification and they constitute an unenlightened mode of living.
The first is the fruition (vipaka) of seeds of experiences, deposited in the store-
consciousness or receptive mind (alaya-vijanam) by previous actions occurring in
a stream. This is called the store-consciousness. It contains experiences in the form of
implicit ideas. The receptive mind is always associated with mental phenomena
(caitta) including sensations, perceptions, attentiveness, feelings, and intentions.
Enlightenment is a transformation of the receptive mind. [35a]
The second is thinking about or in terms of ideas (mano-vijanam) belonging
to the inherited repository of ideas. This is always polluted and corrupted by
four defects: belief that there is a permanent self (atma-dr
.
s
.
t
.
i), delusions about
oneself (atma-moha), an exaggerated sense of ones importance (atma-mana),
and self-love (atma-sneha). This egocentric mental mode is a function of the
mental phenomena. It is transcended in enlightened being. [5b7]
The third modality is perceptual cognitions of objects (vijapti-vis
.
aya). These
perceptions are conditioned by a range of mental phenomena: sensation, desire,
memory, and reflection. They may be affected by either virtuous factors such as
Mind-Only Yoga ca ra Buddhism 75
faith, shame, lack of greed, hostility and delusions, energy and non-violence or by
harmful ones. [814]
The transformations of consciousness are mental creations (vikalpa). What is
thus constructed does not really exist independently. Everything is really just
ideas. [17] The emergent transformations of consciousness influence one
another and generate a conceptual scheme or worldview. Thanks to the
ongoing revival of vestiges of prior actions, there is a constant supply of new
experiences. [1819]
What commonsense regards as entities or objects (vastu) are in fact constructed
by the mind. Such constructed natures (parikalpita-svabhava) do not exist in their
own right. [20]
Mental construction is produced by causes and conditions and hence its nature is
dependent or conditioned (paratantra). But in its original, pristine self-sufficient
state, mind is not conditioned by causes. This unconditioned mode is called its
perfection (nis
.
panna). [21]
It is rationally undecidable whether the unconditioned mind is the same as or
different from the conditioned mind. This is because the conditioned mind, the
process of mental construction, is just a feature, qua activity, of the unconditioned
mind. Furthermore, as long as the conditioned state is not understood as such, we
can have no conception of their being an unconditioned state. Immersed in the
unenlightened mode of awareness, there is no possibility of the conditioned
minds realising its limited nature out of its own resources. It simply lacks the
ability to attain an external, neutral perspective upon itself. [22]
What are called the three natures are not intrinsically determined. [23]
It is a mistake to attribute a self-sufficient intrinsic identity (svabhava) to either the
products of mental creation, to the process of mental creation or to the uncondi-
tioned mind. [24]
The permanent and true nature of the elements is purely mental. [25]
As long as one does not realize that only the mental elements of existence are
real, the subject-object mentality persists. [26]
Just confronting an object and thinking this is merely an idea is not to experience
the mind-only state. [27]
When thought does not apprehend any objective support (alambana), then it is
established in the mind-only state. In the absence of objects of thought, there is
no grasping. [28]
This is supernatural direct intuition, beyond the mind (citta), beyond thinking.
This is the transformation of the receptive mind, immune from afflictions and
obscurations. [29]
An Introduction to Indian Philosophy 76
Vasubandhu and Sthiramati on The
Construction of Phenomena
What we see here is the view that the world of our experience is nothing more
than the interplay of ideas projecting themselves as if referring to external
things. But there are no realities other than ideas and really no subjects of
experience to which those ideas belong. A line of idealist thought, traced back
to a revelation by the Bodhisattva Maitreya to Vasubandhus brother Asanga,
says that the conditioned realm of our experience manifests the mental con-
struction of the unreal (abhta-parikalpa). The word bhta means reality
or a reality. The negative prefix a is probably being used in the sense of
mistaken for. So abhta actually has a more subtle meaning than unreal or
non-existent. What it means is what is mistaken for reality. On this reading,
the mental creation of what is mistaken for reality means the same as
bhva-kalpan or the imaginative construction of entities where entity
means a stable object (or subject) with intrinsic properties whose identity
is determined independently of its relations to others. So abhta-parikalpa
means that what we ordinarily understand and treat as objects and subjects are
abstractions from a matrix of relations. Also constructed and not authentically
real is the dichotomy of subject and the subject (grhya-grhaka-vikalpa). The
notion of emptiness (nyat) is taken to mean falsity of the subject-object
polarity that structures our unenlightened understanding. Sthiramati appears
to move towards a kind of absolute idealism, according to which everything is
a manifestation of an unconditioned (nyat) fundamental reality that is the
ultimate substrate of the process called the Construction of Phenomena
(abhta-parikalpa). The unconditioned reality is the precondition of the
experiences of subjectivity and objectivity, of minds and things. As such,
it transcends them and is neither mental nor physical while manifesting
itself as both.
Illustrative extracts from Sthiramatis
Madhya ntavibha gat
.
ka
The construction of phenomena (abhuta-parikalpa) exists. Duality is not found
there. The Unconditioned (sunyata) is real, and the construction of phenomena
depends upon it. [1.verse 2, page 9]
Mind-Only Yoga ca ra Buddhism 77
Vasubandhu says that abhuta-parikalpa means the distinction between
cognising subject and objects grasped.
Sthiramati begins by saying that the stanza is directed against the view of the
Madhyamikas that none of the elements of existence (dharma) are realities.
In order to repudiate this universal denial it is said that the construction of
phenomena exists.
But does not this contradict the Buddhist scriptures to the effect that all the
elements of existence are empty?
There is no contradiction because it says that duality is not found there. This
means that the construction of phenomena is empty of the distinction between
knowing subjects and objects known. It does not mean that the Absolute is void
of intrinsic nature.
But if duality is never real, like the hares horn, the constructor of phenomena
will be the only true reality. This entails that the Unconditioned is not a reality.
No, because the scripture says Emptiness is real. Emptiness here means
the absence of the opposition between subject and object in the constructor of
phenomena, not the non-existence of the Unconditioned Reality. [page 10]
Sthiramati now turns his attention to the Sarva stiva din view that in addition to
minds and mental acts, material objects are also objective realities. The statement
that the construction of phenomena really exists is intended to refute this. There
is no matter that is independent of this process. This is why the text says, there is
no duality there meaning that the construction of phenomena is neither the
apprehender of anything, nor is it apprehended by anyone. Moreover, it is simple
reality, void of subjects and objects.
Material objects are not grasped independently of awareness. As in dreams and
hallucinations, consciousness represents material objects. If A is the cause of B,
it is illogical that B occurs in the absence of A. [If material objects are required as
the causes of ideas, in the absence of the former the latter would not occur. But
they do.] Hence consciousness does not require external objective supports
[to represent objects]. Consciousness represents objects as if external when
subconscious seeds [in the storehouse of ideas] come to fruition.
If there are no objects, there are no subjects. There are no objects subsisting
independently of the construction of phenomena.
But if there is nothing to be grasped, there can be no liberation because there
would be no transcendental reality.
This is why the text says, the Unconditioned exists. The Unconditioned is the
transcendental reality. It is free from the subject-object duality. It is the foundation
of the construction of phenomena. So liberation is possible.
An Introduction to Indian Philosophy 78
But if the Absolute is the basis of the construction of phenomena, why it is not
apprehended?
It is not apprehended because it is concealed by the construction of phenomena,
not because it does not exist.
The assertion that the construction of phenomena exists can be taken as meaning
that the elements of existence are modifications of consciousness.
The denial of duality can be directed against the Sarvastivadin view that objects
both appear and exist in their own right independently of the construction of
phenomena. [page 11]
Some think that the denial of duality is just nonsense. Others think that the empti-
ness of the elements means just that there is no controlling inner soul.
To counter the denial that there is an ultimate reality, the scripture states that the
Unconditioned exists.
But if the Unconditioned is the foundation of the construction of phenomena,
there is the entailment that liberation would happen for everyone without effort.
No because the Unconditioned is concealed by the process of the construction
of phenomena. Liberation is not possible until the Unconditioned is disclosed
through the great effort involved in purification of the mind.
But if the subject-object duality is unreal, why does the deluded world think that
it exists?
The duality is like a mass hallucination produced by the construction of phenom-
ena. The Unconditioned reality is defined as that which is free from subject and
object.
But what is the construction of phenomena?
In general terms, it is mind and the whole range of mental acts in the three
spheres of existence, past, present and future, the complex of causes and effects
constituting beginningless sam
.
sara and lasting until nirvan
.
a [page 12]. Specifically,
it is the subject-object polarity (grahya-grahaka-vikalpa). The object-pole is con-
sciousness representing things and people. The subject-pole is representations in
consciousness of a self and its perceptions. An example of an object apprehended
would be something with colour, shape and size. An example of a subject would
be a visual perception. The subject-object polarity is not intrinsic to the construc-
tion of phenomena. Unenlightened people do not understand the nature of the
Unconditioned Reality because it is concealed from us. But the enlightened being
(Bodhisattva) correctly discerns that the construction of phenomena is empty of
Mind-Only Yoga ca ra Buddhism 79
the subject-object polarity. After the experience of duality has been superseded,
the unconditioned reality and the construction of phenomena remain. The
Bodhisattva intuits them as they are without any mistaken superimposition.
Hence everything is taught as neither empty nor as non-empty. Because of exist-
ence, non-existence and existence, this is the Middle Path. (1.verse 3 page 13)
Vasubandhu: The Unconditioned and the Construction of phenomena are not
empty but the duality of subject and object is. Everything conditioned is called
the construction of phenomena: the Unconditioned is called Emptiness. The
construction of phenomena is real. The subject-object duality is not real.
The Unconditioned is the substrate of the construction of phenomena and
the construction of phenomena depends upon it.
Sthiramati: The construction of phenomena is conditioned when it is externally
related to causes and conditions. Emptiness is unconditioned because it never
related to causes and conditions.
Consciousness (vijnana) generates projections (pratibhasa)of objects, living beings,
selves and perceptions. Because the objects of these ideas are unreal, the ideas are
not real either. (1. verse 4. page 14)
Vasubandhu: The projection of objects means colours and shapes etc. The projec-
tion of living beings means the sense faculties in ones own and other experi-
ential streams. The projection of self means the corrupt mind that posits a
permanent self. The projection of perceptions means the six modes of sense-
based awareness. The unreality of objects means that they do not exist inde-
pendently of consciousness. In this sense the ideas of them are false.
Sthiramati: It has been taught that the construction of phenomena that is empty
of subject and object is real. The verse explains how the sense-faculties, objects
and perceptions are related to it.
[page 15] By statements that the construction exists, we learn that it is a reality
but nothing about its nature. We do not understand the reason for our instinctive
adherence to the subject-object polarity despite the unreality of duality. That is
why the verse indicates that the intrinsic nature of the construction of phenomena
is consciousness. The basis of our instinctive adherence to the subject-object men-
tality is the projection of objects and living beings etc. Ideas of inanimate objects,
living beings, polluted minds and sense-based perceptions are maturations of
seeds, vestiges of prior intentional actions, in the storehouse consciousness (alaya-
vijana). These specific transformations of karmic potencies create the different
modes of phenomenal existence.
But why does mind represent things as if they were external to it? We would
never mistake a post for a man if there were no men.
An Introduction to Indian Philosophy 80
When the mind forms representations of objects, unenlightened people habitually
assume that the objects exist independently of consciousness. It is like people with
cataracts seeing cobwebs. In order to free people from that instinctive attachment
to objectivity, it is said that the representations of objects are only subjective per-
ceptions and lack reality as do the cobwebs. Thus it has been said that the various
manifestations regarded as constituting an objective domain depend upon the
construction of phenomena.
Coloured things with size and shape, sounds, smells, flavours and textures are
really just internal to the mind. Likewise with our ideas of sentient beings and the
thinking self.
[page 16] Perceptions appear to grasp external objects but the truth is that there
are no external objects corresponding to them.
But common sense says that the objects of perception and the sense faculties
are mind-independent realities. Why should we reject this in favour of idealism?
There are many cases of awareness in the absence of real external objects, for
example, dreams, hallucinations, projections in meditation. If the production of
awareness were causally dependent upon external objects, ideas could not occur
in the absence of the latter and their content could not be different from the
things that have produced them [so we would see water-atoms and light waves,
not rainbows].
Hence, we say that every perception representing things and living beings arises
without any external objects. If there are no real objects, the ideas of the self and
its perceptions are not genuine either, since the two are co-dependent. Although
the subject-object polarity is unreal, the consciousness that posits it is real.
* * *
The construction of phenomena can be understood under three descriptions:
It is called the Constructed nature when there are objects, the Dependent nature
because of the construction of phenomena, and the Perfected nature when there
is no duality. (1. Verse 6. Page 18)
Vasubandhu: The nature that is conceptually constructed (parikalpita-svabhava) is
the world of objects. The dependent nature (paratantra-svabhava) is the con-
struction of phenomena. The perfected nature (parinis
.
panna-svabhava) means
the unreality of the subject-object polarity.
Sthiramati: It is meant here that the construction of phenomena is in itself devoid
of the subject-object polarity. Mentally constructed means that subject
and object are treated as if truly existing, although unreal because they lack
intrinsic natures as such. Dependent means what is produced from causes and
Mind-Only Yoga ca ra Buddhism 81
conditions. The perfected nature is empty of duality produced by the mind. It
is unconditioned and changeless.
The subject-object polarity does not really belong to the construction of phenomena,
which is called the dependent nature when it is subject to causes and conditions. It
is called constructed when it appears under the form of subject and object which
do not really exist there. It is perfected when those conditions do not obtain. In
this way, three natures are attributed to the construction of phenomena.
[pages 2021] Idealist objections to the Sautrantika representationalists:
They say that the objective support (alambana-pratyaya) of awareness is some
instantaneous reality. It effects a representation of its form in awareness. They say
that the objective realities that we perceive are either particular atoms or clusters
of atoms. But this is unsatisfactory because there are no such atoms. But in any
case, what we perceive are macroscopic objects and not atoms or clusters of
atoms. There surely cannot be such a mismatch between the contents of our
mental representations and their objective supports.
Moreover, they themselves say that compounds or wholes are purely nominal
or conceptual existents (prajapti-sat). How then can they be the causes of
perceptions if they are themselves constructs out of experiences of the given?
Further reading
Text and translation of the Twenty Verses in Tola and Dragonetti (2004) and Wood (1991). For the
Thirty Verses see Wood. For Sthiramatis Madhyntavibhgat. k, I have used Pandeya (1989). The
first book is interpreted with informative notes in Stcherbatsky (1970).
Chapter IV of Paul Williams, Mahyna Buddhism (1989) is enlightening.
Questions for discussion and
investigation
1. Why do the idealists deny the reality of matter? Is it just because they want to
encourage us to be detached from things?
2. Has Vasubandhu succeeded in showing that there is no physical reality?
Chapter Outline
The Sa m
.
khya vision 82
Causal processes 84
The human condition: bondage to natural causality 86
The Yoga vision 87
Further reading 89
Questions for discussion and investigation 89
Sa m
.
khya and Yoga
7
The Sa m
.
khya vision
Sm. khya is one of the six orthodox Brahminical Hindu systems of salvation
or visions (darana), and it is closely associated with the Yoga system of
spiritual development. Although this tradition is ancient, its basic text is
the Sm. khya-Kriks of varakr. s. n. a (c. 400500 A.D.) upon which there are
commentaries including the Yuktidpik (c. 650 A.D.) and the Tattvakaumudi
by Vcaspati Mira (c. 841 or 976 A.D.). Sm. khya is basically a non-theistic,
world-renunciatory and gnostic outlook, rather than a religion for the person
immersed in daily life and ritual religion. Its goal is the elimination of
suffering by the eradication of its ultimate cause. Religious practices, such
as rituals and austerities, can only afford a temporary relief from suffering.
What is required is discriminative understanding of the difference between
the conscious subject, and material nature and its manifestations. In other
words, we need to understand that the active embodied person is alienated
from its true identity, which is but reflexive static conscious subjectivity. The
goal is isolation or freedom from determination by natural causal processes.
Sa m
.
khya and Yoga 83
Sm. khya posits a dualism of souls and matter. There is an infinity of souls
(purus. a), which are self-contained and inactive self-aware conscious monads
whose true mode of existence is beyond space, time and matter. Souls are
merely disinterested observers, and most definitely not active participants
in the sphere of becoming. Somehow, some of these souls have become
entangled in the material environment, including individual personality and
the body. Sm. khya and Yoga aim to free the soul from this imprisonment
by matter and rebirth.
Souls have become confused with limited and basically material forms.
When there is an association between what is merely a static conscious monad
and the material mind (buddhi), the latter is illuminated, irradiated by the
light of consciousness and becomes as-if conscious [SK 20]. The confusion is
compounded when the activity of the buddhi is mistakenly attributed to the
inactive soul. Thus we have the origins of the individual person and the series
of births marked by suffering. But the souls are really always purely passive
spectators of human experiences, abiding in splendid isolation, each illumi-
nated only by its own consciousness. It is, however, a basic tenet of Sm. khya
that the experiences deriving from involvement with matter which bind the
soul also operates for the sake of its release (SK 21).
The other pole of the dualism is Primal Matter (pradhna or mla prakr. ti).
It is beginningless and ever-changing. The latter spontaneously transforms
itself (parin. ma) into the real cosmos of material and psychological phenom-
ena. The best we can say is that this just happens. There is no divinity initiating
or superintending the process.
Prime Matter is said to consist of three strands (gun. a): sattva (goodness and
light), rajas (dynamic energy) and tamas (heavy and dark). (The Yuktidpik
interprets the triad as standing for happiness, distress and delusion.) Before
the manifestation of the cosmos, they are in a state of equilibrium, cancelling
out one anothers properties. Their mere existence is said to prompt the
transformation of material nature. Matter (prakr. ti) transforms for the sake of
the human souls so that they have experiences that lead them to realize the
difference between soul and matter. Opponents ask how an unconscious
cause can act for the sake of anything, let alone produce specific and organized
realities. The Sm. khya position, however, is that the existence of the cosmos
call for explanation. The world consists of active and complex realities made
of parts. Each has its own purpose and we should assume a purpose for the
totality. They espouse a principle that composite entities exist for the sake of
something else (parrtha) that is different in nature from them. So it is
An Introduction to Indian Philosophy 84
concluded that physical entities exist for the sake of conscious souls.
Just as the unconscious milk functions for the nourishment of the calf, so matter
functions for the sake of the liberation of the soul (purus
.
a). [SK 57]
No purus
.
a is really bound or liberated or reborn. Only matter in her various
transformations is bound etc. [SK 62]
Through repeated meditation on the nature of the manifest world, there arises
the intuitive insight that the purus
.
a is not the individual personality and whatever
it identifies with. [SK 64]
Primal Matter evolves to produce the basic material and psychological realities
tattva i.e. buddhi (mind/intellect); aham. kara (ones sense of personality;
manas (the co-ordinator of the separate sense-faculties and their deliverances);
the five sense-faculties (indriya); physical organs; the essences of sounds,
touch, colours, tastes and smells; and the gross elements space, air, fire, water
and earth which make up physical objects). These products contain the gun. as
in differing proportions and compose the world we inhabit.
Individual objects are collections of qualities (gun. a-sam. drava) such as
colours, shapes, textures, tastes and smells. The Sm. khyas reject the Nyya
view that there is a separate property-possessor (dharmin) that is distinct from
the conglomeration of properties. They think that once we have listed, as it
were, all the properties of an entity, there is no extra factor called the substrate.
Such would be what is sometimes called a bare particular or an entity without
properties, and that makes no sense. It has indeed been observed that the notion
that the ultimate subject of predication should be something without properties
is an idea so absurd that only philosophers could have come up with it.
All that is required for the substantial unity of entities over time is that
they be integrated in a suitable way. As the Yuktidpik puts it, When an entity
without departing from its nature loses an earlier property and receives a
new one, that is called modification (parin. ma) (YD pp. 111 and 163]. This
is true to experience. People and things change all the time and still remain
identifiably the same. There can only be change, rather than replacement, if
something stays the same.
Causal processes
Sam. khya propounds a theory of causation termed satkrya-vda which
says that future products pre-exist in a potential state in their underlying,
Sa m
.
khya and Yoga 85
substrative causes (updna-kran. a) prior to their actualization or manifesta-
tion (abhivyakti) as entities identifiable by their specific names and forms.
Milk transforms into yoghurt. Milk is the underlying cause or substrate and
yoghurt emerges as a product (krya) from it. Pots are transformations of
the clay that is their substrative cause and which their individual forms
have implicitly pre-existed. Here the causal process involves a modification
(parin. ma) of a stable underlying reality and not the generation of a totally
novel product. Hence there is a strong ontological link between the emergent
effect and its causal substrate. We shall see the importance of this emanative
model of cosmic causality for those forms of Vednta that see the cosmos of
souls and matter as real transformations of the divine being.
The Sm. khya theory of causation develops in opposition to that of the
Nyya-Vaies.ikas. That position is called asatkrya-vda or the production of
something new. This says that prior to origination, the effect did not exist in
its underlying cause but is a totally new product, different from the already
existent basic elements out of which it is made. They reject the category of
potentiality, holding that only what is actual and concrete is real and can cause
something else. Causation is not the actualization of what was potential but
the generation, through re-arrangement, of new entities out of already existent
factors. A cause is defined as a necessary prior condition of an effect. There are
three factors in a causal complex such as the manufacture of a cloth by a weaver
out of threads: the substrative or underlying cause (samavyi-kran. a) which is
always a type of substance (dravya) e.g. the threads comprising the cloth
(the new whole avayavin); the non-inherent cause (asamavyin) which is
always a quality (gun. a) or activity (karma) e.g. the weaving and colour of
the threads; the efficient or instrumental cause (nimitta) e.g. the shuttle
and other instruments. The weaver is the agent cause. The products of causal
processes are integrated wholes (avayavin). The whole is a new creation with
its own identity, over and above the sum of the parts in which it inheres. The
whole entity cannot exist without the parts, but the parts can exist without the
whole. It is distinct from the parts since it manifests a single specific universal.
An individual object must be the substrate of a universal; such as cowness
or potness a collection of different parts will not suffice. That the whole is
not reducible to its parts is crucial to the Nyya-Vaies.ika resistance to
the Buddhist reduction of objects to constituents and phases because they
explain endurance through space and time in terms of integrated natures
that are held together by the relation of inherence (samavya). The Nyya-
Vaies.ikas adduce a number of reasons for their view that prior to origination,
An Introduction to Indian Philosophy 86
the effect does not exist in its underlying cause. Some of them are:
(a) The effect was not perceived in the causal substrate.
(b) If the pre-existent effect lacks specifiable properties, it is not identifiable and thus
its existence does not fall within the province of inference.
(c) The agents efforts would be superfluous if the effect already existed.
(d) A pile of threads is not called cloth and vice versa.
(e) Difference in function of causes and effects: a lump of clay wont carry water.
(f) Difference in form or shape of causes and effects.
(g) Number: threads are many, the cloth one.
The human condition: bondage to
natural causality
We said above that some souls have become entangled in and misidentify
themselves with aspects of the material environment, in particular psycholo-
gical faculties and events, and the body. The process occurs when the mind
(the buddhi), a material product, captures the reflection of the light of some
consciousness. The conscious spirit is then confused with some organic material
configuration. We only function as individual conscious agents and experiences
when conjoined with a body and psychological apparatus. We engage with the
world through the operations of the physical buddhi. Immersed in daily life,
where our natural drives and the acquisitive mentality encourages us always to
be moving on, satisfying our interests and achieving our own purposes, we
generate karma that necessitates further births in the here and now.
The Sm. khya distinction consciousness as the transcendental presupposition
of experience and consciousness as a stream of psychological events cognitions,
thoughts, feelings and desires will become influential. Consciousness is
constitutive of sentient beings, but sensory activity, perceptual cognitions and
consequent conceptual thoughts that come and go are psychological functions
that properly belong to the material mind and sense-faculties. Sm. khya-krik
5 says that perception is a judgement (adhyavasya) about each of the sensory
faculties specific objects. Sm. khya-krik 23 says that judgement is a function
of the physical buddhi. The Yuktidpik commentary elaborates: definite
awareness is a conceptual apprehension involving a propositional belief
such as, This is a cow or this is a man. Primary experience is a function of
the sense-faculties that assume the form of external objects. A thought such
as, This white cow is running is a judgement based on sensory deliverances.
Sa m
.
khya and Yoga 87
Primary experience, mere observation or just seeing something, is restricted
to the present time, but perceptually based thoughts and judgements can
range over past, present and future. Sense-based primary experience is
not conceptual. Concepts belong to the buddhi, which is able to discover
generalities, and is unrestricted where its objects are concerned. But although
the mind apprehends the forms of objects once they have been grasped by
the senses, being physical it requires illumination by the consciousness that
it has borrowed if psychological events are to mean anything. Hence we need
to posit the conscious principle as the ultimate source of experiencing.
But that principle is merely an observer rather than an active participant
in experience. Such is the vision of the world-renouncer. This is of course
problematic because if the process by which the souls become enmeshed
in physical conditions is a purely mechanical and automatic one, and since
prakr. ti and its works are eternally active, it is hard to see why it should not
afflict the released soul again.
Liberation (kaivalya wholeness, isolation) from the cycle of becoming
and rebirth (sam. sra) results from the discriminating insight, presupposing
the discipline of yoga, that the purely conscious and inactive soul is distinct
from both the physical and psychological spheres that are the evolutions
of material nature. Prakr. ti then ceases to function in relation to the enlight-
ened centre of consciousness. Liberation occurs when the three gun. as are
reabsorbed into prakr. ti, whose functions cease. The spectator-soul recovers
its true form, detached from mental modifications and other features of
embodiment. Knowledge is enough to effect the souls disengagement from
the environments of experience.
The Yoga vision
Yoga accepts the Sm. khya metaphysic, but the Yoga tradition has its own
identity. The foundational text is the Yoga-Stra of Patajali, variously dated
from the second century B.C. to fourth century A.D. The commentary by
Vysa is probably a work of the sixth century. Vcaspati Mira (9501000)
wrote a commentary called the Tattvavaiaradi. The Yogastrabhs. yavivaran. a
is probably much later.
In Indian culture, any discipline of physical and mental self-cultivation and
self-transformation whose aim is that of freeing us from rebirth is called yoga.
The Yoga-Sutra defines its subject as the restraint and suppression of all mental
An Introduction to Indian Philosophy 88
modifications that is to say, all forms of thought and feeling, whose forms
the soul has assumed. The goal is a disengagement from the life of action in
which the soul recovers its true nature. This is achieved by constant contem-
plative practice and detachment, presupposing mental and moral cultivation.
Detachment is said to be self-mastery on the part of one who no longer
thirsts for perceptible objects or any of the transitory goals promised by the
Scriptures. Active yoga consists in austerities, the recitation of mantras and
the study of scriptures bearing on freedom from rebirth, and the direction
of the mind to vara an exemplary soul (purus. a) who has transcended the
mutually dependent factors of karma and what are collectively termed the
afflictions. The latter are ignorance (a failure to discriminate what matters
from what does not, the morally valuable from the corrupt, and what is ones
true identity from ones personality and everyday identifications), selfishness,
desires, animosity and attachments. The discriminating person has realized
that everything is unsatisfactory because pleasures turn into frustrations,
because of the weight of dispositions inherited from previous lives over which
we have no control, and because our minds are always restless and at war
within themselves.
The soul in its pure form is mere non-intentional awareness. When
implicated in the conditions of space and time, it has an observers perspective
on of the thoughts and feelings that are functions of the embodied mind with
which it is associated.
The eight stages of the physical, moral and mental discipline of classical
Yoga are:
Self-restraint; non-violence, honesty in thought, word and deed, sexual restraint and
lack of greed.
Discipline: interiorization, tranquillity, asceticism, mantra recitation, the study of texts
on liberation and attention to God.
Physical postures; exercising control over the psychosomatic complex.
Breath-control: regulation and reduction of the processes of inhalation and exhalation
that increase psychophysical control.
Withdrawal of the senses from their objects and direction of attention to the inner
self.
Attention: focusing the mind on a single point (i.e. an object of meditation).
Meditation: the uninterrupted continuity of awareness of the object of meditation.
Profound contemplative introversion in which there is no self-awareness.
Mental purification coincides with purification of the soul. The state of
liberation from rebirth is one of wholeness and isolation (kaivalya) where
Sa m
.
khya and Yoga 89
consciousness experiences only itself. It occurs when the constituents of
material nature no longer operate in relation to the individual centre of
consciousness. The soul recovers its true form, disjoined from mental and
physical modifications.
Further reading
For the Sm. khya-krikas see Larson (1979).
Larson and Bhattacharya (1987) has a useful introduction and summaries of works, including the
important Yuktidpik, which is edited in Wezler and Motegi (1998).
For the Yoga-Stras and commentaries see Woods (1927) and Whicher (1998).
Chapter 11 of Halbfass (1992) is valuable for Sm. khya.
Questions for discussion and
investigation
1. Can we make sense of there basically being more than one centre of pure
consciousness?
2. Does it make sense to hold that material nature operates for the sake of the
purus
.
as?
3. Can the purus
.
as be finally released from rebirth?
8
Nya ya and Vais es
.
ika
Chapter Outline
Nya ya 92
Vais es
.
ika 92
Metaphysics: the system of categories (pada rtha) 93
Substances: the category dravya 93
The category Gun
.
a (quality) 98
The category Karman (motion) 100
The category general property (Sa ma nya) 100
The category Vis es
.
a (ultimate particularity) 103
Samava ya (the inherence relation) 104
The category Abha va (absences) 105
Epistemology: the Prama n
.
as 105
Knowledge by perception (pratyaks
.
a) 109
Anuma na: knowledge by reasoning or inference 111
S
am
.
kara 140
Authentic Being 144
The inexpressibility of the Brahman 149
Bhagavad G ta -Bha s
.
ya 13.12b 149
The path of active religious practices is insufcient for
enlightenment 150
S
am
.
kara and the Buddhists 156
Man
.
d
.
ana Misra 162
The development of the tradition 166
Further reading 166
Questions for discussion and investigation 167
Discursive thought carries the mind here and there. Attention, extroverted or
introverted, is restless. Feelings and moods come and go. Most of life is
pervaded by the dualities of means-end rationality, the seeker and the goal,
actions and their results. But the meditator absorbed in profound contempla-
tion has neither thoughts nor feelings, nor experience of a world external to
consciousness. There is just motionless undifferentiated awareness that does
not seek to accomplish any purposes. This state is what Advaita calls pure
consciousness. Tranquil consciousness knows no fluctuations. It is not directed
towards nor about objects. It is not about anything. It has no specific content.
It is said to be blissful, for it nothing lacks. There is no sense of selfhood or
individuality. There is merely: being conscious.
Advaita-Veda nta 139
The Advaita tradition is inspired by certain Upanis.adic passages suggestive
of the identity of the soul and the Absolute Reality such as:
You are That. (Changogya Upanis
.
ad 6.8.7: tat tvam asi)
In the beginning, all this was just Being, one only without a second. (Changogya
Upanis
.
ad 6.2.1)
But many of the scriptures have a dualistic sense, some clearly suggesting a
difference between the Brahman and the individual souls and the cosmos,
others talking in terms of distinct agents, instruments and goals that are
aspects of external religious practices, and others obviously supposing that
the Supreme Principle is a being with glorious characteristics. Advaita-Vednta
draws a distinction between the ultimate authority of texts teaching non-
difference and those that cannot possibly be construed in a non-dualistic
fashion. While this may appear controversial, it is not unprecedented for as
we saw above, the Mmm. sakas had already distinguished between those texts
that prescribe actions (vidhi) and those that merely describe how and why to
do things (arthavda).
Advaitins say that the essential teaching of the Upanis. ads is that what we
experience as the differentiated world of interrelated conscious and non-
conscious individual entities is really a complex, proliferated misunderstand-
ing superimposed upon the undifferentiated and inactive Brahman or Pure
Being. That foundational reality is nothing other than the coincidence of Being
and static consciousness. Liberation is just the cessation of the ignorance
or misconception (avidy) that is responsible for our experiencing reality as
fragmented and our misunderstanding ourselves as individual experiencers
and agents. While religious activities, ritual and meditative may point one in
the right direction by purifying the mind and distracting us from immediate
selfish pursuits, they cannot produce enlightenment of liberation from rebirth
directly.
This is the tradition of those who deny that extroverted religious activity
can of itself deliver liberation from rebirth. Enlightenment arises from intuitive
insight unmediated by thoughts and words, into the identity of the inner self
(pratyag-tman) and the Brahman. This is the mystical realization of the
equation of Being and Consciousness. It is the manifestation of what one
always and already is. While insight obliterates all experience of differentiation
and individuality, vestiges of such experience persist in the life of the enlightened
one, who is liberated while alive until his release at death. A possible response
An Introduction to Indian Philosophy 140
on the part of the one who has seen the light is the renunciation of all ritual
acts as well as all everyday responsibilities and obligations. am. karas radical
vision is that of the world renouncer (sam. nysin). Man. d. ana Mira is more
concerned with integrating liberating gnosis into the everyday life of the
householder. He recognizes that renouncing social ties and the shared religion
is not an easy option. He says that the Vedic rituals purify the mind and prepare
the way for realization of ones true identity as the Brahman. Understanding of
that identity, conveyed by scripture, is intensified by ritual and contemplation
that counteract the still forceful traces of the pluralistic mentality. He recom-
mended the repetitive type of meditation called prasam. khyna as a means of
removing moral defects and hindrances (klea) and as a way of internalizing
the Upanis.adic statements conveying non-duality. We shall see am. kara
rejecting this version of the view that liberation is the fruit of a combination
of works and gnosis.
S
am
.
kara
am. kara, one of the founders of the tradition holding that differences are
unreal, probably lived around 700 A.D. His major work is a commentary on
the Brahma-Stras. He also wrote commentaries on the Bhagavad Gt and on
individual Upanis. ads. Among the many other works attributed to him by
the Advaita tradition, the Thousand Teachings or Upadea-Shasr stands
out. His vision is that of the radical renouncer, which ultimately calls into
question the values of mainstream orthodoxy by denying that there are any
real individual thinkers, agents and acts.
There is no question that am. kara was an original genius, but it should
be mentioned that the Advaitic tradition traces itself back to Gaud. apda
who probably lived around 450500 A.D. and wrote the gama-stra about
the Mn. dkya Upanis. ad. He likened the phenomenology of normal experi-
ence to that of dreaming and claimed that in both cases it is only the fact of
consciousness that remains constant. Individual entities (bhva) are mental
constructs (kalpan). The one supreme soul, the waveless absolute, imagines
itself as conscious individuals.
Gaud. apdas contemporary, the grammarian Bhartr. hari taught the non-
dualism of meaning (abda-advaita). The idea is that the diversified phenom-
enal cosmos (the proliferation of names and forms) is the emanation from a
unitary sonic Absolute not of things but of meanings. It is the appearance
of the transcendent meaning-reality (abda-tattva), otherwise known as the
Advaita-Veda nta 141
Brahman. The Absolute appears to transform itself through its innate powers
into meanings, words and sentences. Words and what they mean are identical.
The differentiated world of our experience is a product of diversification by
language. Reality is a matrix of differentiated meanings rather than things or
objects. Ignorance (avidy), our default position as it were, is a function of
linguistic proliferation into individual words and propositions. It consists
in understanding the world in term of the individual entities that are the
referents of words and resting content at that level. Bhartr. haris linguistic
idealism exercised a considerable influence on Man. d. ana Mira as well as on
the monistic aiva traditions.
In common with many classical Indian philosophers, am. karas soterio-
logical goal is the freedom of the authentic self (tman) from rebirth. The
tman cannot be captured by concepts and words. It will only reveal itself, and
that is something over which we have no control and upon which our activities
have no effect. tman here means something like true nature or fundamental
identity. It is different from embodied individual personality, from caste-based
social ro
am
.
kara responds that the unconditioned reality cannot intrinsically possess
two natures because it is illogical that one and the same reality should both
intrinsically have and lack characteristics such as colour and shape. Relation to
superimposed properties (upadhi) does not involve a change in the real nature
of an entity. A brilliant crystal does not become dim by being related to a
projected red feature. And the superimposed properties in relation to the
Brahman are projected by avidya. We must understand that of the two sorts
of characteristics, the one of the Brahman as void of every differentia and
beyond discursive thought is the true one.
Brahma-Su tra-Bha s
.
ya 3.2.1415
The Brahman has no forms (akara) such as colour and shape. As scripture says,
The Brahman is without before and after. There is nothing inside or outside
of it. The Brahman is the identity that experiences everything (Br
.
hadaran
.
yaka
Upanis
.
ad 2.5.19.) These passages refer to the transcendent (nis
.
prapaca) nature
of pure being, so it must be understood that it is formless.
Other scriptural passages that refer to the Brahman as having form are not primar-
ily about the Brahman, but are instructions to contemplate the supreme reality in
certain ways.
There is no problem about the fact that some texts teach meditation on the Brah-
man as having some specific forms. This sort of attribution of characteristics does
not compromise our view that the Brahman does not have a twofold nature
although properties are superimposed upon it. When something is due to a
superimposed property (upadhi), it cannot be a genuine property of an entity. And
the superimposed properties are fabricated due to ignorance. We have already
explained that primal ignorance is the precondition of all religious and secular
dealings.
Brahma-Su tra-Bha s
.
ya 3.2.18
Because the nature of unconditioned pure being is consciousness, void of
differentia, beyond mind and language and conveyed by the negation of all
finite characteristics, the scriptures teaching freedom from rebirth use the simile
of the sun reflected in water, meaning that the Brahmans having different
features is not the real truth because those features are properties that have
been superimposed.
Advaita-Veda nta 149
Brahma-Su tra-Bha s
.
ya 3.2.21
Being and consciousness coincide in the Brahman. They are not distinct properties.
The supposition that the Brahman has a mode of being that excludes conscious-
ness and another mode that has the form of consciousness that is other than
being implies that it is internally complex. Being is just consciousness and
consciousness is just being. They are not mutually exclusive, so conceptual analysis
(vikalpa) about whether the Brahman is either Being or consciousness or both is
groundless. Scriptural texts that speak of the Brahman under certain forms have
their own positive purpose: they do not merely have the significance of denying
that finite features of the cosmos pertain to the Brahman. When features of the
cosmos are mentioned in passages enjoining meditation such as, It is made of
mind: the vital breaths are its body; its appearance is light the text does not have
the purpose of suppressing plurality but that of enjoining meditation.
The inexpressibility of the Brahman
We have seen that ones true identity as the Brahman, and the unreality of all
differences and individuality are revealed by some of the scriptures. But
the nature of the Absolute state cannot really be expressed by concepts and
words. am. kara understands Br. hadran. yaka Upanis. ad 2.3.6 as referring to the
Brahman and reads the passage as, Now there is the teaching, It is not this.
It is not that. There is no better expression than, not this. This is the designa-
tion of the truth about reality. The formula is meaningful by eliminating all
limiting conditions.
It expresses something that has no distinguishing features (name form, actions,
differences, class-property or qualities) that are the reasons for the application
of words. Brahman has no distinguishing features. Therefore it is not possible
to describe it as such and such. Brahman may be described by means of names,
forms and actions that are superimposed upon it. But when we want to express
its proper form that is devoid of every specific limiting condition, then it is not
possible to describe it in any way. There is only one way left namely, the designa-
tion, Not this, not this i.e. by the negation of all possible descriptions.
Bhagavad Gta -Bha s
.
ya 13.12b
Unconditioned Absolute is beginningless. It is not said to be Being or non-Being.
This text is tremendously influential in the Advaitin tradition. Among other
things, it was taken as stating that there can be no continuity of being
An Introduction to Indian Philosophy 150
(analogia entis) between the Brahman and anything belonging to the cosmos.
The formula Inexpressible as being or non-being was also applied to avidy
and its works. What am. kara actually says here is that it means that the
Absolute is not the sort of empirical thing that either could or could not exist.
It is not knowable by conventional means adapted to our world, but only by
Scripture. He also says:
It stands to reason that the unconditioned reality (Brahman) cannot be directly
expressed by words such as being and non-being for words are ordinarily
used to reveal some object, and when they are heard they convey a conventional
meaning, by expressing the kind to which an object belongs, or some action,
quality or relation. Thus cow and horse express kinds, he cooks and he reads
express actions, white and black express qualities, and having wealth and
possessing cows express relations. But Brahman does not belong to a kind, so
it cannot be expressed by words such as being or non-being. Because it is
without characteristics, it has no qualities such that it might be expressed by
words for them. Because it is unchanging it cannot be expressed by action-words.
Because it is non-relational, unique, non-objectifiable and the Inner Self of all, it
cannot be expressed by any word.
What about those Scriptures that speak of the Absolute in anthropomorphic
terms? The answer is:
That which is totally other than the cosmos is explained by the provisional attribu-
tion of features to it followed by a demonstration that they are inappropriate.
The path of active religious practices
is insufficient for enlightenment
All Vedntins hold that the scriptures, meaning the Vedas and the Upanis.ads,
are the only means of knowing (pramn. a) the Brahman, the unconditioned
absolute reality, the Being of beings. am. kara thinks that some scriptural
passages generate an unmediated intuition into the identity of the true self
and the Brahman. Knowledge is enough: it is the necessary and sufficient con-
dition of liberation. This soteriology is resisted by those who think that the
scriptures are primarily about religious practices, rituals and types of medita-
tion, as the way to liberation. The scriptures tell us what do and how to do it.
They command us to bring about states of affairs. They do not provide infor-
mation or state facts about already established realities, except when such
Advaita-Veda nta 151
information contributes to the accomplishment of religious activities. State-
ments of fact are meaningful only as supplementary to action-commands. The
scriptures do not teach about already established realities, since those are
within the province of pramn. as like perception and inference. Some Vedantins,
such as Man. d. ana Mira, understood the function of scripture in this frame-
work. They thought that the scriptures bear upon the Brahman by treating it
as the object of meditation. That is, the scriptural statements primarily enjoin
the activity of meditation. The Brahman is the focus of meditation. So the
scriptures treat of Brahman only indirectly as something that is to be realized
by religious activity. am. kara rejects this outlook. Actions are always oriented
towards results. They presuppose duality and individuality. The framework of
means and ends and the associated instrumentalist mentality are part and
parcel of the perpetuation of sam. sra. Liberation is simply the manifestation
of the souls true identity. It is not something to be produced or obtained and
thus is not connected with the performance of acts, be they ritual perform-
ances or meditations. The importance of this topic is reflected in the extent of
his commentary on Brahma-Stra-Bhs. ya 1.1.4.:
The Brahman, the omniscient and omnipotent foundational cause of the
origination, stasis and dissolutions of the universe, is understood from the
Upanis
.
ads because all their statements agree in conveying that reality as their
meaning. For instance there are:
In the beginning, this cosmos was being alone, one without anything else and
In the beginning, this cosmos was the one atman. Once it has been understood
that the words in such passages cohere with each other in bearing upon the real
nature of the Brahman, it would be mistaken to assume another meaning, for
that would involve imagining what is not scriptural teaching and abandoning the
scriptural teaching. It is not the case that such fact-asserting passages are to be
understood as expounding the natures of agents [involved in ritual performances]
because there are scriptural texts that repudiate the fruits of ritual activities, such
as Whom might one see and by what means?
The Brahman, although it is a fully accomplished reality, does not fall within the
province of means of knowing such as perception and inference, because the
identity of the Brahman as ones true self can only be known from the scripture,
That thou art.
As for the view that the Veda ntic teaching is meaningless in that it is not
concerned with matters to be actively pursued or avoided this is not a problem
for us who say that the ultimate good is achieved, after the destruction of all
afflictions, merely by knowledge of ones identity as the Brahman, which is
not something to be pursued or avoided. It is true that there are subordinate
An Introduction to Indian Philosophy 152
references to divinities and individuals in scriptural passages primarily enjoining
the practice of meditation, but this does not contradict our position. The Brahman
cannot be subordinate to injunctions to meditate because once one has realised
that ones true identity is the Brahman, there is an end to thinking in dualistic
terms about rites and constituents of events and there is nothing to be pursued or
avoided. Once the dualistic mentality, which thinks of the Brahman as supplement-
ary to injunctions to meditate, has been eradicated by understanding identity [of
the Brahman and the self], it cannot arise again.
While some Vedic passages have authority by being injunctive, one cannot impugn
the authority of those scriptures that have knowledge of the self as their result.
The epistemic authority of scripture cannot be known by inference, because there
are no analogous instances that could be cited as part of the argument. Thus it is
settled that scripture is the means of knowing the Brahman.
* * *
An opposing view, from someone like Man
.
d
.
ana Misra who thinks that liberation
is the fruit of meditation, rather than just knowledge:
The purport of scripture is not mere understanding but religious activity, in this
case meditation or contemplation.
Reply: Although scripture is the means of knowing about the Brahman, still
scripture teaches that the Brahman is something that should be meditated upon
(pratipatti-vidhi-vis
.
ayata), in the way in which certain factors (e.g. the sacrificial
post) are taught as subordinate aspects of ritual activities. This is because scripture
is concerned with ritual actions and abstentions. Scripture is meaningful by
moving people to action or by restraining them. Anything else is relevant in so
far as it is supplementary to action-injunctions.
In the same way, the Upanis
.
adic statements are meaningful. Given that scripture
is injunctive, just rituals such as the Agnihotra are enjoined for the person who is
intent on paradise, so knowledge of the Brahman is enjoined as an activity for the
one intent upon immortality.
Preliminary reply: There is a radical distinction between two kinds of inquiry: in the
ritual portions of scripture, the ritual duty that one wants to know is something
that is to be brought into being, but our quest is for the Brahman that is always
and already fully accomplished. The fruit of knowledge of the Brahman must be
distinct from the fruit of the knowledge of ritual duty that depends upon
performances.
Response from the opponent: No, there is no difference because the Brahman is
taught as connected with injunctions to perform actions by texts such as the Self
is to be visualised and Everyone should meditate upon the Self. The injunctions
stimulate the desire to know the natures the Self and the Brahman and the
Advaita-Veda nta 153
Upanis
.
ads apply by teaching its proper form as eternally omniscient, all-pervasive,
pure knowledge, liberated, consciousness and bliss. By meditating on that proper
form there arises freedom from rebirth, unknown by ordinary means but known
from scripture. If the Upanis
.
ads taught established facts without reference to
injunctions to perform ritual actions, they would be meaningless because not
connected with things to be pursued or avoided.
A query: But a fact-assertive statement such as, this is a rope, not a snake is seen
to be meaningful by removing fear produced by a misperception. Likewise, the
Upanis
.
ads are meaningful by removing the misconception about transmigration
when they teach the reality of the non-transmigrating Self.
Reply: this would be the case if the misconception about transmigration were
removed merely by hearing about the proper form of the Brahman, just as the
mistake about the snake is removed just by hearing about the rope. But it does
not cease. Although the Brahman has been heard about, features of transmigrat-
ory life are seen to continue as before. This is why there are injunctions that one
should meditate, after hearing about the Brahman.
Hence, it must be understood that scripture is a means of knowing the Brahman
in that it is the object to injunctions to meditate.
S
am
.
kara now replies: The above view is mistaken because of the radical difference
between the results of the knowledge of the Brahman and knowledge about rit-
ual actions. Actions called duty (dharma) are known from the scriptures. This is the
province of the Mmam
.
sa Sutras, which also tell us what to do and what not. The
consequences of right and wrong acts, success and failure, produced by contact
with the objects of the senses, are perceptible pleasures and pains experienced
physically and are known to apply to all creatures from the creator deity Brahma
down to inanimate things. Scripture teaches that there is a hierarchy of pleasures
amongst living beings and from these a hierarchy of dharmas is inferred. From the
hierarchy of dharmas there is a hierarchy of qualified practitioners. The latter
accords with what people aim at and their ability to pay. Those who perform sac-
rifices for the public good follow the higher path because of their special know-
ledge. The southern path is followed by those who perform rituals for themselves.
That there are gradations (taratmya) in enjoyments in those superior realms is
known from the scripture, dwelling there until merit is used up. Likewise we
know that degrees of enjoyments amongst terrestrial beings (and below) are con-
sequences of dharmas indicated by Vedic mandates. The gradation in embodied
pleasures and pains, occasioned by the hierarchy of dharma and adharma, on the
part of those subject to defects such as ignorance is known from scripture and
reasoning to be the nature of transmigratory existence. There is no end to pleas-
ure and pain for the embodied one refers to the nature of transmigration as just
portrayed. Pleasure and pain do not touch the disembodied teaches that the
disembodied state called liberation (moks
.
a) is not the product of the right actions
specified by Vedic mandates. Liberation cannot be the product of the performance
An Introduction to Indian Philosophy 154
of ritual duty, since liberation is the natural state of the soul. Scripture teaches that
the eternally disembodied state called liberation is utterly different from the fruits
of prescribed actions.
Some permanent things, such as earth and the qualities posited by the Sa m
.
khyas,
may change and still retain their identity. But the permanence we are talking
about is absolute, all pervading like the atmosphere, free from every sort of
modification, self-sufficient, impartite and self-illuminating. Where merit, demerit,
their results and the passage of time do not apply, that is the disembodied reality
called liberation. It is the same as the Brahman. Were that being taught as
something subordinate to the performance of actions, and if liberation were to
be accomplished by prescribed actions, it would be impermanent. In fact, it would
be at the top of the hierarchy of impermanent states that are the fruits of action.
But everyone agrees that liberation is permanent. Thus it is illogical that the
Brahman is taught as subordinate to prescribed actions.
Many scriptures such as He who knows the Brahman becomes that Brahman
teach that liberation is the immediate consequence of knowledge of the Brahman
and rule out any action intervening. No prescribed action intervenes between
the vision of the Brahman and the realisation of pure consciousness as the nature
of everything. Other passages reveal that the sole result of knowledge of the
selfs identity with the Brahman is just the removal of obstacles to liberation. The
Nyaya-Sutras say the same: release occurs immediately after the destruction of
misconceptions. . . . There is removal of misconception as a result of knowledge
of the identity of the self and the Brahman. . . . Knowledge of the Brahman does
not depend upon human activity. Rather, it depends upon reality, like knowledge
of mind-independent entities that are objects of praman
.
as such as perception.
[knowledge of an entity as it is in itself does not depend upon human ideas
but only on the reality itself . . . knowledge of established entities depends upon
reality. Brahma-Sutra-Bhas
.
ya.1.1.2]. We cannot rationally suppose that such an
Unconditioned Reality, or knowledge of it, has any connection with things to be
brought about. The Brahman cannot be something to be brought about as if it
were the object of the action of knowing. Scriptures declare that the Brahman is
not within the scope of knowing or contemplation.
But if the Brahman is not an object, how can scripture be the source of knowledge
about it?
We reply that scripture has the force of removing differences fabricated by
ignorance. Scripture does not intend to teach that the Brahman is a specific object
(belonging to a kind of things). Rather, scripture leads the mind away from
differentiation, such as that between objects, subjects and acts of knowledge,
that has been fabricated by ignorance, teaching that the Brahman is never an
object because it is ones own inner reality. . . . Because scripture teaches the
proper form of the eternally released self by dispelling the belief, fabricated by
ignorance, that transmigration is a reality, we cannot be accused of holding that
Advaita-Veda nta 155
liberation is a transitory state. It is logical for someone who holds that liberation is
something to be produced, or that it is a transformation of the self, to say that
is depends upon mental, verbal or physical effort. In either case the non-
permanence of freedom from rebirth is the certain conclusion.
Freedom from rebirth does not depend upon action as if it were something to be
accomplished. It is not something to be accomplished because it is the already and
always real nature of ones identity. Even if the Brahman were different from ones
true identity, it would not be something to be attained because it is all pervading
and always present to everyone.
Release is not the product of ritual purification, which would make it depend upon
human activity. Such purification comes about by the removal of defects or the
acquisition of virtues. The latter cannot pertain to liberation since it is the nature of
the Brahman to which no perfection need be supplied, and there are no defects to
be removed. If you say that release is a hidden feature of ones self that is mani-
fested when the self purifies itself by action, we deny this since the self cannot be
the substrate of actions. Actions do not exist without modifying their substrates. If
the self were changed by action inhering in it, impermanence of the self would
result. Hence actions cannot inhere in the true self. The inner self cannot be puri-
fied by an action belonging to something external, because it is never an object.
The embodied self may be purified by actions but that which is purified is a self
that has been possessed by ignorance and confused with the body. It is this
personality that considers itself purified by ritual acts. All actions are performed by
the personality that understands itself as an individual centre of consciousness and
which enjoys the fruits of actions.
Release is not the product of ritual purification because it is just being the
Brahman. It has no connection with actions and is the fruit of knowledge alone.
But is not knowing a mental action?
There is an important difference. When an action such as contemplating is man-
dated, it is independent of facts and dependent upon human mental effort.
Although meditation and reflection are mental, whether they are performed or not
is a matter of human choice. But knowledge is produced by the valid instruments
of knowing. The instruments relate to entities as they are in themselves. Thus it is
not possible to create, not create, or change knowledge since it depends only upon
already established reality, and not upon Vedic mandates or human minds. To illus-
trate: when the Veda tells us to contemplate man or woman as fire, that is an
action since it is generated by an injunction, and it depends upon some human
choice. But the concept of fire depends neither upon Vedic mandate nor human
choice. It is a matter of knowledge not action because it depends upon an entity
that is the object of perception. The same is to be understood with respect to all
the entities that are objects of the valid means of knowing. This being the case, the
knowledge of the Brahman as it is does not depend upon Vedic mandates.
An Introduction to Indian Philosophy 156
But what is the meaning of passages that look like mandates, such as, The Self is
to be seen, to be heard about?
We reply that they have the force of diverting attention from natural everyday
activities. A person preoccupied with externals, pursuing the objects of desires,
does not achieve the ultimate human good. Passages such as the self is to be
seen actuate a person who seeks the ultimate good to direct his mind towards
the inner self, distracting his attention from mundane activities.
S
am
.
kara and the Buddhists
am. kara is accused by some opponents of being a closet Buddhist. Buddhists
and Advaitins agree that the notion of selfhood is illusory because constructed
out of the interactions between our modes of consciousness and the world.
Moreover, like the Buddhists am. kara envisages the evaporation of personal
individuality once enlightenment dawns, and blames suffering on ignorance.
But the accusation is far from the truth. am. karas metaphysic is totally differ-
ent from the Buddhist temporalism that rejects the very notion of enduring
identities in favour of successions of phases. am. kara believes that behind the
array of changing phenomena there is a single unconditioned reality: the static
co-incidence of pure being and consciousness. Relative to Unconditioned
Being, the world that we experience is less than fully real, not the genuine art-
icle, but there is an ultimate reality enjoyed by depersonalized consciousness.
In other words, the cosmos has a real cause (sat-kran. a-vda), even if we must
be agnostic about the ontological status of entities that cannot be determined
as either real or unreal. This is because every phenomenon is ultimately unreal
when considered as individual, but real in so far as it participates in the general
reality or the Brahman.
Let us see what he says about various Buddhist schools:
Brahma-Su tra-Bha s
.
ya 2.2.18
There are three traditions of Buddhist thought:
Those who say that both material and mental phenomena are real.
Those who say that only mental phenomena are real.
Those who say that there are no intrinsic natures.
To begin with, we refute those who admit the reality of all mental and physical
factors. By physical they mean both the four elements and the sense faculties and
their respective objects. They say that earth, water, air and fire are combinations of
Advaita-Veda nta 157
four different kinds of atoms. The five constituents (skandha) that make up human
lives (body, perceptions, feelings, conceptual thoughts and inherited dispositions)
are internal and in combination form the basis of all interpersonal dealings.
Here we object that there are two different kinds of combinations: but the
reality of these sorts of combinations is unintelligible. This is because the atomic
components of the material combinations are non-conscious and the emergence
of sentience depends upon the prior existence of some compound. They do not
accept any other persisting conscious subject or director who could combine the
basic factors. It cannot be the case that the atoms and skandhas function sponta-
neously because that would entail that they would never cease from activity.
We see here the basis of one of the most significant objections to the Buddhist
reductionist analysis. It may appear economical, plausible and attractive but it
is hard to see how after completing the reduction of entities into their elements
there is any way back. It is easy to smash a glass, but impossible to put the
pieces back together again. It is not clear that Buddhism can account for the
emergence of entities, including the person, from the elements.
Brahma-Su tra-Bha s
.
ya 2.2.19
The Buddhist says that although there is no persisting subject of experience
or director who combines the basic factors, the world process is sustained by
the interactive causality of dependently originating factors such as ignorance
etc. Ignorance, habits, perceptions, name and form, the six types of sensation,
touch, feeling, grasping, birth, old age and death, sadness, pain, frustration and
discontent form a self-perpetuating circle of causes and effects. The reality of
those facts of life is accepted by everyone. The cycle of factors, each conditioning
the other as effect and cause, presupposes that there are real combinations [such
as bodies and minds].
S
am
.
kara replies:
You are only talking about the originating causes of the elements in the series
and overlooking the sort of organisational causality that would account for the
formation of combinations. The latter is impossible if there are only momentary
atoms and no subjects of experience. Perhaps the factors beginning with ignor-
ance are the causes of the formation of aggregates. But how can they cause that
which is the necessary condition of their existence?
Moreover, you do not think that the combinations are formed in the interests of
enduring conscious subjects so that they might experience the fruits of their
karma (bhogartham). Hence, experience is just for the sake of experience and is
not sought by anything or anyone else. So freedom from rebirth (moks
.
a) is just
for the sake of itself and there is no one by whom it is sought. A being with an
An Introduction to Indian Philosophy 158
interest in both experiencing the fruits of action and gaining freedom from rebirth
would have to exist contemporaneously with those processes and such persist-
ence would conflict with your belief in the instantaneity of beings (ks
.
an
.
ikatva).
So while there may be a relation of originative causality between the members
of the series, this does not suffice to explain their organized combinations.
am. kara continues to establish the stronger claim that the Buddhist position
cannot even make sense of originative causality between members of the
series. He begins by arguing that a strictly instantaneous reality does not last
for long enough to bring about the existence of anything else.
Brahma-Su tra-Bha s
.
ya 2.2.20
The theory that realities are instantaneous implies that when the later moment
originates, the earlier one no longer exists. So it is not possible to establish the
relation of cause and effect between the two occasions. The claim that once
the prior moment is fully actualised it becomes the cause of the later one is
not intelligible because the hypothesis that a fully actualised entity has a causal
function (vyapara) means that it is connected to another moment [so it is not
strictly an instantaneous occurrence but an extended one].
Nor does it make sense to say that the causal function simply is the existence of the
prior entity. This is because origin of an effect that is not tinged by the own-nature
(svabhava) of its cause is impossible. If one accepts that the effect is tinged by the
own-nature of its cause, the nature of the cause continues in the effect and that
entails the abandonment of the hypothesis of instantaneity. Nor can it be argued
that there could be a cause-effect relation without the nature of the cause affect-
ing the effect because if that were applied in all cases there would be chaos.
Moreover, what you understand as simultaneous origin and cessation would be
either the same as the proper form of an entity, or two phases of its existence, or
something else. If they are the same as the proper form, the words origin and
cessation and entity would be synonymous. If the terms origin and cessation
mean two phases that are the beginning and end of an entity whose existence is
what occurs between them, the acceptance of instantaneity of the entity would
be overthrown because it would be connected with three phases beginning,
middle and end.
If origin and cessation are quite other than the entity, it would follow that the
entity is everlasting.
The theory of the essential temporality of beings (ks. an. ikatva) extends to
human personality which the Buddhists understand as just a series of causally
related experiential phases. There is no persisting principle of identity or
Advaita-Veda nta 159
soul that is a further fact over and above the stream. am. kara challenges the
intelligibility of this proposal:
Brahma-Su tra-Bha s
.
ya 2.2.25
Moreover the nihilist (Vaina sika literally the believer in the spontaneous
destructibility of all entities) accepting the instantaneity of everything must
apply instantaneity to the subject of experiences. But that is not possible because
of the phenomenon first personal memory [of the form, I remember that I
did that]. Such memory is produced by the reoccurrence of an experiential
awareness and it is only possible if the one who remembers is the same as
the original subject. One man does not remember the awareness of another.
How could there be the experience of the awareness, I saw that and am seeing it
now if there were no single subject seeing the earlier and the later? We all know
that the experience of recognition occurs only when there is a single subject of
both seeing and remembering. . . . The nihilist knows himself to be the one
subject of seeing and remembering whenever he thinks, I saw that. He does not
deny that the past perception belongs to him any more than he denies that fire is
hot and light.
Since one and the same agent is connected with the two moments of seeing
and remembering, the nihilist must give up his acceptance of the essential
temporality of beings.
If he recognises that all his past and future experiences belong to one and the
same subject, and accepts that there is sometimes synthetic awareness of both
successive and simultaneous cognitions, how can the nihilist who asserts universal
instantaneity maintain his position?
The Buddhist may say that recognition and synthetic awareness derive from the
similarity of the momentary cognitions [and this generates the misapprehension
that there are persisting object and the illusion that there is an enduring self]. But
similarity is a relation between two different things. Someone who says that
although there is no single perceiver of two similar things, synthetic awareness is
based on similarity is talking nonsense. If he admits that there is a single perceiver
of the similarity between the earlier and later moments, he thereby grants that
there is one thing enduring through two moments and this contradicts the
hypothesis of instantaneity.
When a universally accepted reality is denied by philosophers, whatever they may
say in support of their own view or in finding fault in that of others, they convince
neither themselves nor others. When it is know that something is such and such,
it must be expressed accordingly. Their thesis about similarity fails to accord with
the facts of experience. The act of recognition is an understanding about one and
the same thing and not of something that is similar to something else. It may be
that sometimes there is a doubt about whether an external object is the same one
An Introduction to Indian Philosophy 160
or something similar to it. But there is no room for doubt about whether the
perceiving subject is identical to itself or just something similar.
am. kara now turns his critical attention to the Buddhist consciousness-only
theory that reductively identifies what are usually taken to be extra-mental
realities with elements of awareness. Of the various ingredients of the cosmic
process posited by the Buddhist schools, they say that only the mental ones
are real.
Brahma-Su tra-Bha s
.
ya 2.2.28:
The Buddhist purva-paks
.
in: the Enlightened One taught the theory that the
external world really exists in consideration of those followers who were convinced
about the reality of things external to minds. But this was not his own belief,
which was that amongst the five constituents of personal existence (skandhas),
only perceptions were real. According to the vijana-vada, we can make sense
of everything to do with means of, objects and results of knowing if they are
purely internal to minds. Even if there were external objects, the process of know-
ing would not get under way without mind. But how is it known that this entire
process is internal and that there are no objects independent of perceptions?
Because there cannot be external objects. If external objects are accepted, they
would be atoms or combinations of atoms, such as pillars. But atoms are not
discerned in our awareness of pillars etc because they cannot be represented in
consciousness. External objects cannot be combinations of atoms because we
cannot determine whether they are the same as or different from the atoms.
Moreover, although cognitions share the same nature in that they are just con-
sciousness, they may express different objects. This would not happen unless the
differentia were internal to awareness, so it must be accepted that a cognition has
the same form as its object (vis
.
aya-sarupya). Once this is granted, given that the
representation of the object is determined by cognition (and not the other way
round), the postulation of external objects is superfluous. Moreover, given that
the object and the awareness of it always occur simultaneously (sahopalambha-
niyamad), it follows that there is no difference between a cognition and its object.
It is not that the case that where the cognition and its object are concerned, there
is apprehension of the one when there is non-apprehension of the other. This
would not make sense if the two were different in nature in which case there
would be nothing to stop the one occurring without the other. Hence there are no
objects external to the mind.
Perception of objects is comparable to dreams. Just as ideas in dreams manifest
the form of the apprehender and the apprehended although there are no external
objects, so in the waking state one must understand that representations of solid
objects occur without external objects. This is because from the point of view of
felt experience, there is no difference between the forms of awareness.
Advaita-Veda nta 161
Now if there are no objects external to minds, how is the variety of repres entations
(pratyaya-vaicitrya) explained? It is explained by the variety of residual impressions
(vasana-vaicitrya) left by previous ideas. In the beginningless series of births, an
impression causes a perception which in turn leaves an impression and so on. This
explains the variety of representations. Moreover, we understand by reasoning from
positive and negative concomitance that the variety of cognitions is just caused by
residual impressions. We both admit that in dreams and hallu cinations, the variety
of cognitions is caused by residual impressions in the absence of external objects.
But we do not accept that there can ever be any variety of cognitions without
residual impressions. Hence there are no objects external to awareness.
S
am
.
kara now replies:
It is impossible to make sense of the non-existence of external objects because
they are perceived. External objects, corresponding to representations (prati-
pratyayam), are perceived. It cannot be the case that what is being perceived does
not exist.
The Buddhist may claim, I do not say that I am not aware of objects. What I do
say is that I am not aware of any object apart from perception. But objects
independent of perception must be accepted simply because of the nature
of perception itself. No one perceiving a pillar or a wall is just conscious of his
perception. But everyone perceives pillars and walls precisely in so far as they are
the objects of perceptions. Even those who deny the reality of external things
implicitly grant their existence when they say that representations internal to
consciousness (antar-jeya-rupam) appear as if external. If we accept that reality
is as it is given in direct experience, it is logical to accept that it is precisely the
external that is manifested in consciousness, but not what is like the external.
The Buddhist argues that the external-like is what is manifest because of the
impossibility of external objects. This cant be right because what is possible and
what is impossible is ascertained by the means of knowing (prama n
.
a) and the means
of knowing do not depend upon independently arrived at ideas of what we might
imagine to be possible and impossible. What is possible and what not is understood
by the use of some means of knowing. External objects are apprehended as they are
in themselves by all the means of knowing. How can it be said that they are not
possible on the basis of specious argumentation, given that they are perceived. And
it is not the case that there are no external objects because of the conformity
between cognitions and objects. If there were no objects, conformity between
the representation of the object in awareness and the external object would be
impossible. And the object is represented as external. That is why the co-occurrence
of thought and object (sahopalambha-niyama) is due to the fact that a relation of
mode of presentation and object presented obtains between thought and object.
It does not derive from the identity of thoughts and objects.
Moreover, consciousness remains the same although conditioned by different
objects, such as a pot and a cloth. This is parallel to seeing a black cow and a
An Introduction to Indian Philosophy 162
white cow. The individuals differ in respect of their colours but the generic prop-
erty cowness is constant and immutable. The distinct identity of the one constant
factor is established in comparison with the two and the distinct identities of the
two are established in comparison with the single factor. Hence, thought and
objects are distinct.
Moreover, two successive but discrete thoughts with a thinker, self-contained and
confined to their own instantaneous occurrences, cannot be related as the appre-
hending factor and the apprehended. It follows that all the Buddhist teachings are
lost because they involve inter-related ideas.
Man
.
d
.
ana Misra
am. karas contemporary Man. d. ana Mira is the other founding father of the
monistic Vedanta vision. His Brahma-Siddhi was as influential as am. karas
commentaries. Vacaspati Mira attempted to reconcile the outlooks of the two
thinkers in his Bhamat commentary on am. karas Brahma-Stra-Bhs. ya.
Man. d. ana differs from am. kara in seeing positive value in religious
practices. He thinks that Vedic rituals are purificatory and predispose one
to the realization of ones true identity. He has no quarrel with the path of
world-renunciation (sam. nysa) but observes that it is difficult. He thinks
that the enlightenment received from scriptural statements about the truth
of non-duality must be intensified by ritual and contemplation in order to
counteract still forceful residual traces of ignorance.
am. karas inspiration is selfless contemplative experience, which shows that
tranquil consciousness is the self-revealing and self-establishing true nature of
reality. For am. kara, the fact that awareness occurs as the same in all cognitions
shows that it is the basic reality. In pure consciousness there is neither differ-
entiation nor individuality. This is called the Brahman, where consciousness
and Being coincide. Experience of differences between knowers, thoughts
and objectivity are fabricated through misunderstanding. Man. d. anas position
is somewhat different. It is what Paul Hacker called a radical ontologism. Put
simply, Man. d. ana does not put so much weight on considerations about the
nature of consciousness as am. kara. If we say that am. karas vision arose from
looking within, then we may say that Man. d. anas began from looking outside.
There is something there, whatever it may be. The foundational scriptural text
here is the Chndogya Upanis.ads In the beginning this world was just being,
one without a second (Ch.Up.6.2.1). Being (satt) presents itself universally.
Being is present everywhere. Not being something, just being. Being is not dif-
ferentiated. Primary awareness, non-discursive and pre-reflective, reveals this
Advaita-Veda nta 163
non-predicative being. Being is apprehended prior to the identification
of objects in respect of their general and specific features. Being is the core
identity of entities when we abstract away their properties and relations.
Everything is experienced as sharing the undifferentiated form of Being that
is always the same everywhere. Hence we have a monism of Being, rather than
one of consciousness. The Brahman is already known in immediate experience,
even though we inhabit the sphere of avidy (misunderstanding), having lost
sight of the true nature of Reality.
It is difficult to capture exactly what Being means other than to say that
it is the foundational reality of beings. It is that which is the unconditioned
condition of there being anything at all. Man. d. ana also says what it is not.
For example, it is more than actual and concrete entities that exercise causal
efficacy, which Dharmakrti treats as the criterion of reality. Moreover, it is not
the susceptibility for being connected with some means of knowing or mode
of evidence (pramn. a). Such an epistemic account of being would restrict what
is to what can in principle be known or identified. Man. d. anas view is that Being
transcends knowability. The conception is richer than that expressed by the
existential is that we use to assert that some entity is numbered among the
objects that furnish our world (There is a table here). It is certainly stronger
than Freges suggestion that affirmations of existence are just denials that the
number zero applies to some concept. It is also more than is captured by the is
of predication, which we use to say that something is such and such (The table
is black). Finally, Being is not an entity because it does not belong to a kind.
The Being of beings is the Brahman, that which is unconditioned by
particular features. It is known as such from the advaita-rutis, which also
teach the unreality of diversity. But if scripture is a means of knowing a
non-dual reality, it is in conflict with everyday perception that apprehends
differentiated entities. Man. d. ana denies that there is a conflict: perception
apprehends pure being. The rationale for the denial that difference and
individuality are basic realities and for the claim that perception does not
grasp difference is extensively elaborated in arguments that will be developed
by later Advaitins, especially Vimukttman [fl. 950 A.D.] and r Hars.a
[fl.1150 A.D.]. We shall briefly mention a few points here.
Perception identifies the proper form of an entity: it refers to the thing
just as it is in itself. Separating it from other things comes next. We cannot
differentiate unless we have identified something in the first place. If differen-
tiation or exclusion (apoha) were the nature and function of perception when
we discern a particular entity, we would perceive the difference of the object
An Introduction to Indian Philosophy 164
from everything else whether or not present in space and time. This is
manifestly impossible and contrary to experience. Difference from other
things cannot be the very nature (svabhva) of an entity. Difference is
relational. If it is constitutive of the nature of an entity, it follows that the
entity is the same as that from which it differs. But if difference is not of
the nature of entities, they are not essentially different.
Another consideration is that if difference is the very nature of entities,
given that it is a form of mutual absence or non-existence (anyonya-abhva
one things not being another a reciprocal absence of natures), it follows that
entities do not exist.
It is objected that Man. d. ana is treating difference as a real feature of entities,
when it is a best a boundary. Difference is not a thing in its own right; it is not
a mode of being of an entity but is only falsely presented by constructive
cognitions (vikalpa). There is no property being different that belongs to
entities because difference does not really exist an imagined nature does not
really belong to an entity. Man. d. ana responds that this is exactly what he is
saying: difference does not really exist but is projected by beginningless avidy.
He also considers the alternative that difference means the interdependence
of entities and not their natures. A proper form is unitary but entities differ
with respect to each other. Man. d. ana denies that interdependence is a genuine
property of entities (i.e. a property whose loss or gain means a real change in a
thing) by which they are constituted. It is illogical to hold that the continuing
existence of entities depends on other entities when their natures are consti-
tuted by their own specific causes. Interdependence is a human concept and
not something that belongs to things as they are in themselves.
After Dignga, it became a standard view among Brahminical philosophers
that there are two varieties of perception: non-conceptual and conceptual. The
former is reception of whatever is given: the latter is the explicit identification
of features, both general and specific. As Kumrila put it:
In the first place here is cognition (jana) that is just seeing (alocana) and it is
free from concepts (nirvikalpaka). It is produced from the pure entity and is like
the cognitions of infants and the mute. Neither general (samanya) nor specific
features (vises
.
a) figure explicitly in the content of awareness, but the individual
that is their substrate is grasped . . . A subsequent cognition by which an entity
is grasped in terms of its properties such as its universal and its qualities is also
considered a form of perception.
Advaita-Veda nta 165
Man. d. ana denies that there can be two varieties of perception. Perception is a
means of knowing that just refers to Being. Every perception reveals the
general form of being that is the Brahman.
His position is:
Initially there is non-conceptual perception whose sphere is just Being (vastu-
matra). It is the ensuing conceptual cognitions that comprehend particularities.
What Man. d. ana means is simply that in the first instance we just register the
presence of something really there. (If reality is basically simple, features of
entities such as universal property, qualities and the relations between them
are just products of conceptual superimposition.) Judgements that involve
conceptual or constructive cognition come next. But that is not perception as
a means of knowing. Indeed it is not knowing at all.
The rationale is: perception is a means of knowing. What are called
non-conceptual and conceptual perception are different functions with com-
pletely different kinds of objects. The one refers to undifferentiated pure
being, the other to particularities. He has shown that differentiation is not
genuinely real, so cognitions of particularities must be false. They are cases
of avidy. Avidy here means error or misconception (vibhrama). Error must
be about something. There can be no apprehension of the non-existent. So
constructive cognitions must be misunderstandings about pure Being.
Avidy is not genuinely real if it were it could never be eliminated but it
is not totally unreal in that it is a familiar phenomenon. That is why it is
called illusion.
We beings are alienated from Being. This is avidy. Avidy is responsible for
all plurality of individual selves, cognitions and objects, and the concomitant
process of rebirth. It is also connected with sorrow, delusion and passions.
It conceals ones true nature; instead creating the illusion that one is an indi-
vidual agent subject to ritual and social duties and transmigration. While later
Advaitins will distinguish between subjective avidy that affects individuals
and avidy as a positive cosmic force that projects diversity and conceals the
true nature of the Brahman, Man. d. ana, like am. kara makes more modest
claims. He says that avidy belongs to individual selves. This is one of the
reasons why the subsequent tradition will posit a causative avidy. Something
has to constitute the individual as an individual in the first place if it is to be
the substrate of avidy.
An Introduction to Indian Philosophy 166
The development of the tradition
The early Advaitins attribute the illusion of multiplicity to beginningless
avidy. The epithet beginningless means that we cannot explain its occur-
rence. But it also encouraged the thought that avidy is some sort of effectual
reality in its own right. Arguments about avidy led to the development
establishment of two schools of thought. One is called the Bhmat school
after Vcaspati Miras commentary of the Brahma-Stra Bhs. ya. They say
that the individual soul is the locus of avidy. It distinguishes a fundamental
causal avidy from everyday mistakes and ignorance. Avidy has two powers:
it conceals the truth and it projects the illusion of diversity. What is called the
Vivaran. a school follows Praktmans commentary on Padmapdas
Pacapdik. Padmapda (700750 A.D.) said that avidy is the cause of all
misconception (and superimposition), while am. kara tends to treat them as
the same. He described avidya as a material (jad. a) force that is the underlying
cause of the world-appearance. Avidy veils the pristine nature of the Brahman
and in association with the workings of karma and memory traces of previous
cognitions produces the illusion of limited selfhood that is the substrate of
individual experience and agency. He thought that the limited self is a finite
reflection (pratibimba) of Brahman. This school says that the Brahman is both
substrate and the object of beginningless avidy, which is the substrative cause
of plurality. Avidy is an actual entity (bhva-rpa) that is the opposite to
rather than just the absence of knowledge.
Further reading
am. karas Brahma-Stra-Bhs. ya is translated in Thibaut (1904). Mayeda (1979) translates the
Upadea-Shasr and has a useful introduction.
Suthren Hirst (2005) is highly recommended for am. kara.
Potter (1981) has an introduction and summaries of works by am. kara, as well as Man. d. anas
Brahma-Siddhi by Allen Thrasher. The latters Advaita of Vednta of Brahma-Siddhi is stimulating,
as are Ram-Prasad (2001 and 2002).
Halbfass (1995) collects important articles by Paul Hacker.
Suryanarayana Sastri (1971) translates a classic of Advaita epistemology and metaphysics. It is a pity
that he repeatedly translates vr. tti (mental function) as psychosis.
Some aspects of the debates between the Advaitins and theists about scriptural exegesis are described
in Bartley, Theology of Rmnuja (2002).
The Summary of the Text in Acharya (2006) is useful for later Advaita.
Advaita-Veda nta 167
See Granoff (1978) for r Hars.a.
For Bhartr. hari, see John Broughs classic essays on Theories of General Linguistics in the Sanskrit
Grammarians and Some Indian Theories of Meaning in Hara and Wright (1996). Also Matilal
(1991).
For Gaud. apda, there is a text and translation in Karmarkar (1953). See King (1995), for connections
with Buddhism.
Questions for discussion and
investigation
1. In what senses is Advaita subversive of mainstream orthodoxy? Does it represent
the implicit rejection of Hindu dharma?
2. Is a notion of a static absolute principle compatible with our experience?
12
Visis
.
t
.
a dvaita-Veda nta
Chapter Outline
The religious context 168
Knowing God only from Scripture 172
Opposition to Advaita 173
The individual self 175
The soul-body model 178
Further reading 183
Questions for discussion and investigation 183
The religious context
After about 700 A.D. we see the rise to predominance within Hinduism of
the sort of personalist theism found in the Bhagavad Gt and the Purn. as,
accompanied by a decline in the religion in which the Vedic rituals are central.
This is not to say that ritual practices disappear. Rather, they are assimilated to
modes of practice that are more concerned with worship of a deity conceived
personally whose grace or favour is accessible to those human beings who love
to respond to him in love (bhakti). God is thought to be concerned with the
destinies of finite beings. From this perspective, the cosmos is understood as
creation for the sake of sentient beings rather than as a hierarchy of spheres of
existence (tattva), through which souls may or may not progress as a natural
process in accordance with karma, understood as an automatic mechanism.
There develops theological concept of the soul and a notion of human beings
Visis
.
t
.
a dvaita-Veda nta 169
as essentially lovers, enjoyers and knowers of God. According to this mentality
the individual is constituted by God and the meaning and fulfilment of its life
is to be found in relationship to God.
Viis. t. dvaita Vednta is the doctrinal articulation of the theistic r
Vais. n. ava religious tradition that still flourishes in Tamil Ndu. It is a pluralist
ontology and epistemological direct realism about a complex universe whose
basic constituents are kinds of property-bearing enduring substances. The
term Viis. t. dvaita, frequently mistranslated as qualified non-dualism, is held
by the tradition to mean the integral unity of complex reality. Vednta is the
systematic hermeneutic of the Upanis. ads, the brief summaries of the teachings
of the latter in the Brahma-Stras, and the Bhagavad Gt.
The r Vais. n. ava tradition developed in interaction with the enthusiastic
devotion (bhakti) towards a personally conceived deity found in the hymns
of the Tamil lvrs, the temple and domestic rituals and theology of the
Tantric (i.e. non-Vedic) Pcartra gamas, and a reflective Vais.n. ava smrta
orthodoxy. The latter found expression in the philosophical theologies of
Nthamuni (9801050 A.D.), Ymuna (c. 10501125 A.D.) and Rmnuja
(c. 11001170 A.D.). The latter was a creative genius who, adopting ideas
from Ymuna and an earlier commentator on the Brahma-stras called
Bodhyana, synthesized ideas current in the tradition into a realistic and
pluralistic philosophical and theological system.
Influential Viis. t. dvaitins and their works include:
Na thamuni (9801050): Nyayatattva (known only from quotations).
Ya muna (10501125): atmasiddhi, I
svarasiddhi, Sam
.
vitsiddhi; agamapraman
.
yam
(on the validity of the Pacara tra cult and its scriptures).
Ra ma nuja (11001170): S
r Bhas
.
ya (commentary on the Brahma-su tras),
Vedarthasam
.
graha (prcis of the former); Bhagavadgta-bha s
.
ya.
Parasara Bhat
.
t
.
a (11701240): Tattvaratnakara (quotations from Veda nta Desika).
Vedavya sa (Sudarsanasuri) (11201300): srutaprakasika (commentary on sr
Bhas
.
ya), Tatparydpika (commentary on Vedarthasam
.
graha).
Veda nta Desika (Ven kat
.
ana tha) (12701350): Tattvamuktakalapa, Sarvarthasiddhi,
Nyayaparisuddhi, Nyayasiddhajana, Tatparyacandrika (commentary on Ra ma nujas
Gtabhas
.
ya), Tattvat
.
ka (commentary on sr Bhas
.
ya), Pacaratraraks
.
a.
S
aiva
Philosophies of Kashmir
14
Chapter Outline
S
a kta S
a kta S
aiva traditions
As well as the aiva Siddhnta dualists there were many worshippers of
forms of iva and the Goddess who subscribed to a non-dualistic (advaita) or
monistic metaphysic. While believing that it is knowledge and not ritual that
is essential for liberation, adherents of these cults enjoyed a rich liturgical life.
An Introduction to Indian Philosophy 210
Some rituals confer specific benefits and powers. But ritual practice may also
help to consolidate belief, deepen commitment and keep alive an original
inspirational insight by preserving a sense of enlightened deliverance from
the frustrations, changes and chances of daily life. Enlightenment is under-
stood as recovery of ones true identity as the deity. Salvific realization may be
achieved by ritual informed by gnosis, or by gnosis alone, or it may simply
happen unexpectedly thanks to a purely fortuitous descent of divine grace.
While enlightenment and liberation, understood as the salvific expansion of
consciousness bestowed in initiation, are possible in the course of ones life
(jvan-mukti), most initiates have to wait for death, which is coterminous with
the exhaustion of the residual karma appropriate to this life, to experience it
fully. The life of ritual practice confirms and intensifies the original liberating
experience, purifying it of conceptual elements. Thus enlightened, one sees the
world in a new light.
Utpaladeva and Abhinavagupta
Utpaladeva (925975 A.D.) follows Somnanda (900950 A.D.), who was the
original theorist of the Pratyabhij school. Somnandas ivadr. s.t.i expounds a
form of absolute idealism, the philosophical outlook that denies that physical
or material things have any reality independent of universal consciousness.
An aspect of the argument is that if there were a real difference in nature
between consciousness and material objects, knowledge of the world would
be impossible. Material things, whether atoms or concrete wholes, on the
one hand and consciousness on the other are utterly different categories
and cannot be connected. Relation is possible only when categories have
something in common. So a relation between thinking minds and objects
is possible if consciousness is the common factor present in everything. To
be is to be a manifestation of consciousness. All conscious subjects are
essentially the same. The universal consciousness is identified as the supreme
godhead named as iva, who is present everywhere. Everything is a manifes-
tation of the single divine consciousness and ultimately there are no real
individual identities.
Human problems start when we just think of ourselves as isolated individuals
with caste-based social identities confronting a separate material environment.
The point of religious practice is the recovery of ones true identity as Shiva
through the expansion of ones conscious energy.
S
ivas tranquil state is the highest form of self-awareness. But there is an even
higher state that is ever so slightly distinct, and that is the abode of the Goddess.
The whole of reality comes from the creative light of consciousness (praka sa), itself
deriving from the sheer delight that lacks nothing and which itself finds its rest
in the uncreated light wherein there are no traces of awareness of differences. The
Goddess is the unsurpassable tranquil state that has consumed the traces of
awareness of existences that had remained in the uncreated light. S
ivas nature
is the tranquil state that devours time. The Goddess is the perfection of that
tranquillity. (Maha nayapraka sa 3.10411. Text cited in Sanderson (2007), p. 309)
Reinterpretation of S