BentPlato BeethovenV16
BentPlato BeethovenV16
BentPlato BeethovenV16
Nineteenth-Century Music?
Ian Bent
2Joseph Kerman's initiative started with his "A Profile for Musicology," Joumal of
the American Musicological Society 18 (1965): 61-69, and continued in many places,
including his Contemplating Music: Challenges to Musicology (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
2 Indiana Theory Review Vol. 16
contributed to that evaluation directly or indirectly include Peter Kivy,
Edward Cone, Fred Maus, and Marion Guck; but a music-hermeneutic
practice has been formulated and put to the test on music only in the
past five years in the work of Lawrence Kramer, and on texts about
music still more recently by Gary Tomlinson. 3
My own treatment of the field, in volume 2 of my Music Analysis
in the Nineteenth Century, gives a historical account of general
hermeneutics and seeks to illustrate how this was put into practice in
writing about music. 4 The present papers goes beyond that, attempting
to demonstrate more tangibly the working of hermeneutics in the early
nineteenth century. My purpose is to isolate the hermeneutics of its
earliest practitioner, Friedrich Schleiermacher, unfiltered by the
subsequent hermeneutics of Dilthey, Heidegger, Gadamer and others,
and to consider its relevance to music by looking at one particular and
celebrated piece of writing about music, namely E. T. A. Hoffmann's
review of Beethoven's Fifth Symphony.6
University Press, 1986). Proceedings of the round table appear in Aui del XlV congresso
della societa internazionale di musicologia ... : vol. 1, Round Tables (Turin: EDT,
1990), 645-90.
4Ian Bent, ed., Music Analysis in the Nineteenth Century (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1994), vol. 1, Fugue, Form and Style; vol. 2, Hermeneutic
Approaches.
8Idem, Uber die Religion: Reden an die Gebildeten unter ihren Veriichtem (Berlin:
Unger, 1799), trans. Richard Crouter as On Religion: Speeches to Its Cultured Despisers
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988).
9Idem, Der christliche Glaube (Berlin: Reimer, 1821-22), trans. Hugh Ross
Mackintosh and James Stuart Stewart as The Christian Faith (Edinburgh: Clark, 1928;
Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1976); Das Leben Jesu: Vorlesungen, ed. K. A. Rtitenik
(Berlin: Reimer, 1864), ed. and with an introduction by Jack C. Verheyden, trans. S.
Maclean Gilmour as The Life of Jesus (Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1975).
4 Indiana Theory Review Vol. 16
each individual dialogue. All of volumes 1 and 2, and part of volume
3, achieved publication before his death. Thereafter, the work remained
incomplete. 10
We can see Schleiermacher's hermeneutics at work by studying his
introductions to Plato's Dialogues, for they have long been held up as
exemplary models of hermeneutic inquiry. For example, the
philosopher Wilhelm Dilthey draws attention to the introduction to The
Republic as follows:
Theaetetus-Sophist-Statesman
What is more, these three are part of a larger sequence of seven that
can be thought of as relating to the trial and death of Socrates:
Theaetetus-Euthyphro-Sophist-Statesman-
Apology-Crito-Phaedo
D_e_fi_ill_·U_·o_n_o_f_sO_P_h_is_t_--' _
L - -_ _ ~i:n:being _1,-__·_._. _S_O_Ph_i_st_ _--'
13This and all other translations from Platons Werke are taken from the 1836 Dobson
edition cited above in n. 10.
Bent, Plato-Beethoven 7
and tame animals; tame animals into man and other animals 14 and so on
until we conclude that sophism is a form of hunting, namely the
hunting of rich and promising youths by flattery!
art
~
productive acquisitive
~ exchange hunting
~
aquatIc land-based
wOe
1\
other man
~
commumty pnvate
We can see from this example the irony with which Plato spotlights
sophism: in the course of his characterization he portrays it first as one
menial occupation then as another-merchandizing, juggling, and so
on.)
l~his step is not fully spelled out by Plato. The argumentation occurs at 221E-223B
of the dialogue.
8 Indiana Theory Review Vol. 16
'----__
D_efi_lil_i_tio_ll_O_f_S_OP_hi_'s_t_---' _ ~~n:being _I L-_ _' __SO_P_hi_st_ _--l
•.
Indeed, the outer layer is not all satire. It contains, for example, one
argument relevant to the larger framework of Socrates' trial and death,
namely that the sort of cross-examination for which Socrates is famous
purges and purifies the mind of inconsistencies and falsehoods, and is,
contrary to the charges against Socrates, non-subversive (249-50).
Schleiermacher now shifts back to the parts and whole within the
Sophist. He turns to the central layer of the dialogue, showing that its
structure mirrors that of the dialogue as a whole; that is, it comprises
again an outer shell and an inner kernel: 17
The outer part is a discussion of speech and falsehood; the inner part
is a necessary digression that reinforces that discussion, on being and
not-being. What is more, our inner and outer layers are what we might
call "isomorphic" (to use a modern term), for in each case the outer
discussion loses its way, and the inner discussion is interpolated so that
the outer one can find its footing again (see Figure 5).
.c
()
Q)
Q)
0..
CI)
Bent, Plato-Beethoven 11
Schleiermacher calls the inner-inner kernel (which itself divides into
two parts 18) "the most valuable and precious core of the dialogue,"
where "the most inward sanctuary of philosophy is opened in a purely
philosophical manner" (251).
Moreover, the inner' 'layer" of the dialogue refutes several of the
past schools of Greek philosophy, and Schleiermacher teases these out
one by one. 19 From this set of external references, Schleiermacher then
turns to this dialogue's "intimate relation" to two dialogues not
included in our Socratic sequence, namely the Parmenides and the
Timaeus. The Parmenides had, in his view, initiated a discussion of
how "ideas," in their pure form, can be said to exist-a discussion
which later resumes in "a whole series of successive dialogues from
the Theaetetus upwards." In the Sophist, in turn, the "foundation" is
"laid perfectly and dialectically" for the Timaeus (see Figure 6).20 He
then establishes links with several other dialogues on the basis of
contenfl and uses these finally to confirm the closer links within its
own trilogy, Theaetetus-Sophist-Statesman.
19Ibid., 254-59: Parmenides (241Dft), the Ionic philosophers (245Eft), the atomists
(246Eft), the idealists (248Aft).
2'1bid., 259-60. On continuity between the Parmenides and Theaetetus onward, see
ibid., 118, 132 (Parmenides), 198-99 (Theaetetus). In Schleiermacher's chronology (no
longer accepted), the Meno, Euthydemus, and Cratylus arose between the Theaetetus and
the Sophist (ibid., 204, 263), so "successive" implicitly includes these. The proposed
linkage, by its nature, "is intended to be said preliminarily only, " and has remained so,
since Schleiermacher died before reaching the translation of, and commentary on, the
Timaeus.
....
'"
~
M
(go
..c
(""""
0
CIl
t::l... c
Cl
V)
( .S
....
( ·2
<.;::::
LJ /I\.
/I\.
Bent, Plato-Beethoven 13
25 All quotations in this section of the essay are taken from Kimmerle, Hermeneutik,
nach den Handschriften neu herausgegeben . . . , trans. Duke and Forstman as
Hermeneutics: The Handwritten Manuscripts.
16 Indiana Theory Review Vol. 16
There exists a dialectical relation between whole and parts. The
hermeneutic principle, he says,
This "moving back and forth" suggests a shuttle, and indeed the
metaphor of a shuttle is almost as common in Schleiermacher as that of
the circle. For on a loom, a shuttle must be in constant motion, and the
pattern that it weaves emerges, so to speak, perpendicularly to the
plane of the shuttle-not in the path of the shuttle, as would be the case
for many other methods of inquiry.
The circle or shuttle operates just as constantly on the polarity of
whole and part. There is a particularly vivid passage that portrays the
uncertain progress of the interpreter:
27This and all other quotations in this section of the essay are taken from E. T. A.
Hoffmann's Musical Writings, ed. Charlton and Clarke, cited above in n. 6.
20 Indiana Theory Review Vol. 16
everything down just as the feverish workings of his imagination
dictate to him at that moment. (98)
In truth, ... his controlling self [is] detached from the inner
realm of sounds and rul[es] it in absolute authority .... [O]nly
the most penetrating study of Beethoven's instrumental music
can reveal its high level of rational awareness . . . . (98)
Thus, at the end of the first movement he shifts from the individual
moment to the movement as a whole; at the end of the Scherzo he
shifts first from the individual moment to the third movement as a
whole and then to the first and third movements as a related pair.
But shifts between part and whole are only one aspect of this
review. Hoffmann also shifts frequently between what Schleiermacher
called the "grammatical" and the "psychological." For example, of
the first movement:
The shift from purely technical to emotive (to use Peter Kivy's terms)
and back again is palpable; indeed, it probably induces queasiness in
the modern reader. Hoffmann's intention is clear: to attack the passage
concerned from the two ends-from the short hammered phrases,
diminished sevenths, heavy texture, then unison diatonic theme that
constitute the "grammar," and the effect of all this on the listener that
constitutes the "psychology' '-and to fuse the two in the reader!
listener's mind. As we heard Schleiermacher say, "Understanding takes
place only in the coinherence of these two moments."
As Hoffmann shifts from objective to subjective, he often
simultaneously moves from orbit to orbit. Take his opening description
of the Scherzo: The slow movement has, at the psychological level,
temporarily replaced the "awful phantom" of the first movement by
"comforting figures." However, at the grammatical level, the constant
modulations, key-juxtapositions, and chromaticisms have not gone
away, and so we sense that the first-movement horrors may return at
any moment. Of the Scherzo he then says:
-grammatical again-
-and psychological.
As Hoffmann intermits the grammatical and psychological, he also
reaches up out of the orbit of the Scherzo into that of the kinship
between Allegro and Scherzo on which he will later capitalize at the
end of the review by speaking of the "relationship which exists
between the subjects of the two Allegros and the [Scherzo]" (251). At
the same time, he also moves to the penultimate orbit, that of Haydn,
Mozart and Beethoven, because his allusion to "the magical
spirit-world" recalls his earlier reference to the "nocturnal spirit-world
[in] a purple shimmer" and the "magical quality" that he finds in
Mozart, and the allusion to "restless yearning" recalls the
"inexpressible yearning" at that same point; and to the outermost orbit,
that of instrumental music as a whole, by recalling his references to
"the realm of the infinite," "an unknown realm," and "that infinite
yearning which is the essence of romanticism" (238).
To summarize, then, the hermeneuticist reading that I have given
Hoffmann's review shows that it begins-after a presumed cursory
reading-at the level of the largest totality by discussing autonomous
24 Indiana Theory Review Vol. 16
Schleiermacher for the first time is known: between June 18 and July
21, 1807. Even the precise time and place of that meeting is recorded. 28
The two men met again on December 12, 1807. 29 Much later in life, in
1820, Hoffmann was to defend Schleiermacher against charges of
corrupting youth, and was admitted as a member of the "Society for
Anarchy," of which Schleiermacher had been a founder-member since
1809. 30
Such evidence allows the possibility of influence, to be sure, but
does not establish it. Any further step will lead me into marshy ground.
One commentator reports that, on moving to Warsaw in 1804,
Hoffmann began a lifelong friendship with Julius Eduard Itzig (an
assistant judge there at the time, and later to become a senior official
of the Supreme Court in Berlin), and that Itzig made it his business to
acquaint Hoffmann with the poetry of Tieck and Brentano, the
philosophy of Fichte, and probably also with the publications of
Schleiermacher. 31
Unsubstantiated as this is, I cannot unfortunately place any reliance
on it. Nonetheless, let me explore its possibilities without giving it
28E. T. A. Hoffmanns Briefwechsel, ed. Hans von Muller and Friedrich Schnapp, 3
vols. (Munich: Winkler-Verlag, 1967-69), 1:214 (to Itzig-see n. 31 below): "Yesterday
I was at Mme Levi's from 7:30 to 8:30, where many people were drinking tea with rum
and making rational conversation; from 9:30 to 11:30 by invitation at Winzer's, where
once again many people were drinking rum with tea- I made the acquaintance of
Bernhardi (has a handsome face), of Schleiermacher, and especially of the composer
Schneider ... " (first half of the letter destroyed, hence no date).
29Ibid., 231 (to Theodor Gottlieb von Hippel): "Fichte and Schleiermacher are again
here, Werner is going back to Berlin" (Zacharias Werner [1768-1823]: childhood friend,
poet, dramatist). On February 9, 1809, he lunched at the house of senior civil servant
Lorenz Fuchs and his wife (in Bamberg?), where Schleiermacher was the topic of
conversation; see E. T. A. Hoffmanns Leben und Werk in Daten und Bildem (Frankfurt
am Main: Insel, 1968), 169 (presumably a diary entry).
30Ibid., 298.
31Ernst von Schenck, E. T. A. Hoffmann: ein Kampf um das BUd des Menschen
(Berlin: Verlag die Runde, 1939), 139. Itzig (1780-1849): born Isaak Elias Itzig, changed
first names in 1799, last name to Hitzig in 1809; later Hoffmann's first biographer.
Schenck offers no evidence for this assertion.
26 Indiana Theory Review Vol. 16
credence. lfHitzig did draw Hoffmann's attention to Schleiermacher's
publications, and if those publications included Plato's Works (two
large assumptions), then between 1804 and 1807 (when Hoffmann
returned to Berlin) Hoffmann could have encountered volume 1,
published in 1804, which included Schleiermacher's introduction to the
Dialogues as a whole and his individual introductions to the Phaedrus,
Lysis, Protagoras, and Laches, as well as their translations; volumes
2 and 3, published in 1805, which contained thirteen more dialogues
with their introductions, including the Parmenides and the Theaetetus;
and volume 4, published in 1807, which included four more, including
the Sophist itself, and the Statesman. In short, any or all of the
introductions to twenty-one dialogues might have come into Hoffmann's
hands between 1804 and 1807. And if all of this were the case, he
might even have encountered volume 5, published in 1809, which
contained the introductions to and translations of a further eight
dialogues, before writing his review of Beethoven's Fifth Symphony in
1810.
However, all of this is idle speculation. None of the external
evidence has elicited demonstrable influence. To turn now to internal
evidence is to lead to somewhat firmer ground. There is in fact one
allusion to Plato's Dialogues in Hoffmann's writings. It occurs in
Kreisleriana, in a letter from Baron Wallborn to Kapellmeister
Kreisler:
32Kreisleriana, pt. 2, item 1, ed. Charlton and Clarke, 125, where the allusion is
identified as to the Symposium, 215A-216D.
Bent, Plato-Beethoven 27
Look at him! Isn't he just like a statue of Silenus? You know the
kind of statue I mean; you'll find them in any shop in town.
It's a Silenus sitting, his flute or his pipes in his hands, and it's
hollow. It's split right down the middle, and inside it's full of
tiny statues of the gods. 33
33Plato: Symposium, trans. Alexander Nehamas and Paul Woodruff (Indianapolis and
Cambridge: Hackett, 1989),65. Woodruff footnotes that "flute" translates aulos, which
is really a reed instrument.
35Dobson, 27-28.
28 Indiana Theory Review Vol. 16
37The verb besinnen is "to reflect (on)," "to ponder," "to consider"; its past
participle besonnen is ' 'prudent, ' , , 'circumspect, ' , , 'sober, " "discreet, " but also
(perhaps by influence from Besinnung, "reason," "considerateness," etc.) "sensible,"
"considerate. "
Bent, Plato-Beethoven 29
mit defer Besonnenheit ausgejahrt,38 where these two quintessentially
nineteenth-century terms 39 are shadowed by an equally quintessentially
eighteenth-century pair, Erfindung and Ausjahrung. If genius presides
over the process of "invention," then it is rational awareness that
presides over' 'articulation" of that genius. Genius is here the lower
order of art, rational awareness the superordinate art. Just as, in
Charmides, Besonnenheit was the "science of self" (and it is this
meaning that Schleiermacher picks out in his introduction, emphasizing
"the complete difference between knowledge and perception with
reference to its power of making itself its own object' '40), so too in
Hoffmann's review it governs Beethoven's symphony: "He is
nevertheless fully the equal of Haydn and Mozart in rational awareness,
his controlling self detached from the inner realm of sounds and ruling
it in absolute authority [Er trennt sein Ich von dem innern Reich der
Tone und gebietet daraber als unumschrankter Herr]. ,,41 Besonnenheit
and Genialitat are ultimately fused in a single notion, "rational genius
[die besonnene Genialitat].' ,42
For a definitive statement of the Socratic position on rationality with
respect to art, it is to, of all places, the Apology-the dialogue in which
Socrates defends himself at his trial, is found guilty, and is sentenced
to death-that we must turn. In search of greater wisdom than his own,
Socrates goes first to the politicians, then to the poets
38Charlton and Clarke, 251; original in AmZ 12 (1809/10): col. 658 (see n. 6 above
for full citations).
39Jacob and Wilhelm Grimm (Deutsches Worterbuch [Leipzig: Hirtzel]) cites only
Goethe and Fichte for Besonnenheit; Klinger, Schiller, and Goethe for besonnen in this
sense (vol. 1 [1805]); and Goethe, Schiller (1795, 1797), Tieck, and von Humboldt for
Genialittlt (vol. 4, pt. 1 [1897]).
4°Dobson, 107.
43Apology, 22B-C, quoted from The Dialogues o/Plato, vol. 1, Euthyphro, Apology,
Crito, Meno, Gorgias, Menexenus, trans. R. E. Allen (New Haven and London: Yale
University Press, 1984), 84.
[The poet] must simultaneously cast flames upon the least detail
and apply a thermometer to the flames; he must in the battle
heat of all his faculties maintain the subtle balance of single
syllables and must ... lead the stream of his perceptions to the
debouchement of a rhyme. Inspiration produces only the whole;
calmness produces the parts. 46
46Vorschule der Aesthetik, trans. Margaret R. Hale as Horn of Oberon: Jean Paul
Richter's "School for Aesthetics" (Detroit: Wayne State University Press, 1973), 37.
32 Indiana Theory Review Vol. 16
Vernunft von Verstand, eben die Eltern von beiden. 47
47Schnaus, 81.
48 Horn of Oberon: Jean Paul Richter's "School for Aesthetics, " trans. Hale, 36.
51Ibid., 286.