The Power of Music
The Power of Music
The Power of Music
University of Uppsala
Department of Archaeology and Ancient History
Master’s Thesis 45 points
Louisa Sakka
Spring 2009
Supervisor: Gullög Nordquist
ii
ABSTRACT
Louisa Sakka, 2009, The power of music. A comparative study of literature and vase
paintings from Classical Athens. Master’s thesis. Department of Archaeology and
Ancient History, University of Uppsala.
This paper deals with ancient Greek music, and in particular the relation of people to
music during the fifth century BC in Athens. Music is believed to exercise great
power over the human character and behavior, and at the same time is a means of
emotional communication. For the first time during the fifth century, the power of
music leaves the realm of the myths and becomes a subject of philosophical
investigation.
Two different types of sources are examined in order to study the relation of
people to music: on the one hand the literary sources of this period, and on the other
the vase paintings. This method reveals various attitudes towards music by using two
different perspectives. Possible explanations are given for the differing information,
the purpose of each source being a decisive factor.
The paper suggests that although the information from the two types of sources
varies and can even be contradictive, the recognition of the power music exercises is
obvious in both cases.
Keywords: music, ethos, power, Plato, vase paintings, art, Athens, Classical,
literature, New Music.
In memory of my father
v
vi
TABLE OF CONTENTS
1. INTRODUCTION ................................................................................................. 1
1.1 Aim ................................................................................................................. 1
1.2 Definition ........................................................................................................ 2
1.3 Sources ............................................................................................................ 2
1.4 Theoretical background ................................................................................... 4
1.5 Method ............................................................................................................ 4
1.6 Account of earlier research .............................................................................. 5
2. BACKGROUND ................................................................................................... 7
2.1 The Athenian society during the fifth century BC ............................................ 7
2.2 Music in ancient Greek life .............................................................................. 8
2.2.1 Music during the sixth century BC ...........................................................11
2.2.2 Changes in music during the fifth century BC ..........................................12
2.3 Plato’s dialogues .............................................................................................13
3. ETHOS IN MUSIC ..............................................................................................15
3.1 Literature ........................................................................................................15
3.1.1 The intellectual debate in fifth century BC Athens ...................................15
3.1.2 Plato on music’s ethos..............................................................................17
3.2 The vase paintings ..........................................................................................23
3.2.1 Music and wine: the cult of Dionysos .......................................................23
3.2.2 The ethos of Orpheus ...............................................................................25
3.2.3 Thamyris and hubris.................................................................................26
3.2.4 Marsyas: the debate between the aulos and the lyra ..................................26
4. MUSIC AND THE CITIZENS .............................................................................28
4.1 Literature ........................................................................................................28
4.1.1 The ideal education ..................................................................................28
4.1.2 The symposion .........................................................................................32
4.1.3 Women and mousike ................................................................................34
4.2 The vase paintings ..........................................................................................35
4.2.1 Musical education ....................................................................................35
4.2.2 The symposion .........................................................................................37
4.2.3 Women and mousike ................................................................................39
5. THE ARTISTS AND THE NEW MUSIC ............................................................44
5.1 Literature ........................................................................................................46
5.1.1 Amateur and professional musicians ........................................................46
Plato’s views on art...........................................................................................46
Plato and Aristotle’s views on professionalism .................................................48
Musical contests ...............................................................................................49
5.1.2 The musical revolution of the late fifth century ........................................50
The New Music ................................................................................................50
Resistance to the New Music ............................................................................53
5.2 The vase paintings ..........................................................................................56
The musical contests .........................................................................................56
6. DISCUSSION ......................................................................................................59
6.1 Reactions to music ..........................................................................................59
6.1.1 The effects of music .................................................................................61
The calming and enchanting effect of music .....................................................61
The exciting effect of music ..............................................................................62
The pedagogical use of music ...........................................................................64
Music in religion and death ...............................................................................66
vii
1. INTRODUCTION
1.1 Aim
The aim of this essay is to study people’s relation to music in Classical Athens. It
concentrates on the role and the importance of music in the lives of the Athenians, the
various uses of music, and the attitudes towards it. Two different types of sources are
used in this study: literary sources and vase paintings. Of the literary sources, Plato’s
dialogues are focused upon: he expresses ideas on the importance of ethos1 and its
relation to music, on the relation of the Athenian citizens to music, as well as on the
status of amateur and professional musicians in the Athenian society. What is of
importance during this period is the emergence of the so-called New Music, which is
studied with the help of, among others, Aristophanes, Pherecrates, Plato, and modern
scholars. The New Music causes many reactions, which are reflected in the written
sources mainly in the form of criticism or satire, and may even be discerned in the
vase paintings of the time.
The main discussion concentrates primarily on the power of music. It is
suggested that the idea of music’s power over the body and soul may be discerned in
most paintings representing music. Parallels of the effects of music visualized in the
paintings are found in the literary sources. The two types of sources are compared and
a possible explanation for similarities and differences in the information they offer is
presented. The intention of this paper is to answer the following questions:
- How is music believed to affect people?
- How is the power of music visualized in the vase paintings? Are there parallels in
the literary sources?
- Do the sources contradict or support each other?
- Is one type of source more reliable than the other?
- Do the sources represent the attitude of the average Athenian citizen towards music?
If not, which type of source represents which class/type of people?
- What sort of information does each type of source offer? What kinds of music do
they mention and what kinds do they not?
1
According to Bundrick: ”The term ethos, a word with a range of nuanced meanings, refers to the
character of a musical instrument or composition, based on such elements as rhythm, mode, tempo, or
pitch. - - - Concepts of musical ethos were tied to perceptions of morality and proper behavior, and to
ideals of sophrosyne (moderation) in the face of hubris (excessive pride in the face of the gods).”
Bundrick 2005, 10f.
2
1.2 Definition
This paper concentrates on music in fifth century BC Athens. The fifth century is a
period of many changes with a lot written about it. It is an interesting time in many
ways: the power is coming into the hands of the people, the economic funds are
increasing, while art, literature, science, and philosophy bloom as never before. Most
of the sources concerning ancient Greek music focus on exactly this period. They are
not only contemporary; the interest in the fifth century is seen long into the Roman
times, as for example in works of pseudo-Plutarch and Athenaeus. It is a recognized
fact between these writers that music plays a very important role in the lives of the
Athenians.
It is easy to comprehend why this essay focuses on Athens. Even though the
most famous and talented musicians come from other places, as Thebes or parts of the
Ionian coast, the sources concerning Athens outnumber those of other cities. It is very
unfortunate not to have as much information about places with important musical
traditions, but one can use the Athenian sources to their utmost, hoping to get a
glimpse of the rest of the Greek world at the same time.
The technicalities of music or the way it is composed and played, are not of the
greatest importance for this essay. What is of interest is the study of the social role
and the psychological effects of music on people in different contexts and situations.
The main sources will be those that assist in this specific study.
1.3 Sources
The studying of music of past societies will always be problematic since it is difficult
to reproduce music in its original form. The problem is even harder to solve in cases
like ancient Greece, the music of which has not left much evidence in the form of
notation. One of the main reasons is that the compositions were transmitted through
listening and memorization.2 There are certain sources however, and M. L. West
divides them into five categories: archaeology and art; references to music and music
making in Greek literature; specialist writing on music; non-literary documents as
inscriptions and papyri; and finally the actual musical scores.3 This chapter offers an
2
Comotti 1989, 7.
3
For more information on the various sources, see West 1992, 4-8.
3
account of the sources of this study, and only a brief description of the difficulties
each source presents. A more detailed criticism of the sources will take place in the
main discussion of this essay.
A study of the literary sources comes first. It would be beyond this essay to
study in depth the theorists of music, detailed descriptions of harmonies and rhythms,
and other technical aspects of playing music. This essay is about the relation of music
to people and to real life, the role and the importance of music, it’s various uses, and
the attitudes towards it. The most appropriate texts are the texts of the philosophers.
One of the first known to theorize about the relation between music, ethos, and the
soul, is Damon of Oa.4 Unfortunately there is very little known about him, and his
ideas have come down to us in fragments cited in later sources, such as Plato and
Athenaeus. It seems like Plato adopts many of Damon’s ideas.
This paper concentrates on Plato’s dialogues. Plato however, is not
contemporary to the society he speaks of: he writes in the fourth century BC about
music of the fifth. Besides, he is creating an ideal city in his dialogues, not aiming at a
detailed description of the musical life of his time. A third obstacle is that Plato is
aristocratic in his ideas, so he does not reflect the views of the average Athenian.
Nevertheless, as mentioned above, Plato describes certain attitudes towards music. He
writes about the dangers and also the benefits of music, about where it is played, and
how people react to it. Although he does not aim in giving an account of the musical
reality of his time, he does criticize it. Indirectly, through these criticisms, he offers
information on what the musical reality was like. Other literary sources examined
briefly are Aristotle, certain of Aristophanes’ plays, pseudo-Plutarch’s De Musica,
Athenaeus’ Deipnosophistae, and others.
In contrast to literary texts, the vase paintings reflect the ideas of a much
broader part of the population. Large amounts of pottery are produced and used by
most of the Athenian population. In addition, many of these vases have survived in a
very good shape until today. Another advantage is that the pottery is contemporary
with the period studied. The vase paintings, however, are art, and art values the
aesthetic result more than the truth, while most representations are not lacking in
idealism either.
4
See p.16 in this essay.
4
1.5 Method
Plato’s dialogues Republic and Laws are examined in order to find the passages
related to music. A summary of his discussions concerning ethos and education and
his views on the role of music in general are presented, while other ancient sources
and modern commentators are also studied.5 The goal is to discern attitudes towards
music and musicians, along with how music and the status of musicians change
during the fifth century BC.
The next step is to examine the vase paintings of this period. Modern scholars
such as Bundrick and Boardman have served as excellent sources, as well as larger
collections of vase paintings, such as LIMC and CVA. Once again the aim is to discern
the attitudes, emotions, and reactions to music as visualized in the vase paintings. The
most important tendencies in vase painting concerning the relevant subjects are
examined in the second part of each chapter.
A comparison of the information from the two types of sources follows. An
account of similarities and differences in the information about music is presented, as
well as how music is perceived, and how it is thought to influence human behavior.
Finally, possible explanations of these differences are offered, taking in account the
purpose and use of each source, by whom and when they are written/created, as well
as what sort of audience/customers/readers they are intended for.
5
For example Anderson 1966; Anderson 1994; Barker 1984; Guthrie 1975; Guthrie 1978.
5
6
For further information see Matthiesen 1974, iii.
7
For further information see Bundrick 2005, 203.
8
West 1992.
9
Comotti 1989.
10
Lippman 1964.
11
Anderson 1994, xi.
12
Barker 1984; Csapo 2004; Nordquist 1992; Nordquist 1994; Nordquist 1995; Nordquist 2008;
Wilson 2004.
13
Stefanis 1988, 7.
14
Murray & Wilson 2004.
15
Guthrie 1975; Guthrie 1978; Barker 1984; Anderson 1966.
6
Vase paintings have received more attention than music. The important
handbooks on Archaic and Classical Black and Red figure painting by John
Boardman, give us a detailed review of painters, their techniques, and their
workshops, while including a large number of illustrations. These are general studies
of the paintings, in which one has the possibility of viewing many scenes representing
music. Martin Robertson has written a general study focusing on the vase painters of
Classical Athens. Francois Lissarrague concentrates on the Greek symposion
(banquet) in the vase paintings, where there are many images depicting the use of
music. Two books that have been of great assistance in the writing of this essay are
Imago Musicae VIII16 and Sheramy Bundrick’s Music and image in classical
Athens.17 Imago Musicae VIII is a selection of articles in which music is treated from
various perspectives, including essays on the power of music as visualized in the vase
paintings,18 representations of musical instruments as the salpinx,19 and domestic
music making.20 What Bundrick contributes with is that she views musical imagery
through the entire fifth century, not individually but in a wider context. She suggests
that the changes in the musical reality of the time, as the debate on music in
education, the importance of a good musical ethos, and the development of
professionalism in music, are reflected in the vase imagery.21
16
Imago Musicae 1995.
17
Bundrick 2005.
18
Seebass 1995.
19
Nordquist 1995.
20
Voutira 1995.
21
Bundrick 2005, 6f.
7
2. BACKGROUND
22
Morris 2006, 274.
23
For more Information on the creation of the Athenian Empire, see Morris 2006, 273-276.
24
Robertson 1992, 235.
25
Plutarch, Pericles 12-13.
26
Morris 2006, 285.
27
Thucydides 2.41.1.
28
Bundrick 2005, 8.
29
Morris 2006, 288.
8
scientific thinking, and not least, questioning of the traditional values and way of living,
create discussions and are mirrored in the works of Plato, Aristotle, and the dramatists.
Ways of acquiring wisdom through discovering the truth of things, and gaining power
through rhetoric, also concern philosophy of the fifth century.30
The atmosphere in Athens during this time, however, becomes all the more
polarized between the rich and the poor. Hostilities are being created as the social
power moves from the elite down to the demos.31 Wallace characterizes the second half
of the fifth century as a time of “political and intellectual uncertainty and
conservatism”.32 This is something that should be held in mind when studying the
musical debate of the second half of the fifth century and beginning of the fourth, since
it could be based on a parallel conflict. This will be discussed in more detail later in this
essay.
In addition, the other Greek cities start to disapprove of Athens’ expansionist
policy. Another league, the Peloponnesian, is created under the rule of Sparta. In the
mean time, many of Athens’ allies revolt and leave the league, given that the fear of the
Persians does not exist any longer. It is not long until the two leagues come into
conflict, leading to the Peloponnesian war (431-404 BC) and defeat of Athens by
Sparta.
30
Morris 2006, 294.
31
Morris 2006, 284.
32
Wallace 2004, 265.
33
Comotti 1989, 3.
34
Murray 2004, 389.
35
Lawler 1964a and 1964b are good examples of studies of ancient Greek dance.
9
Music is a manifestation of happy and peaceful life for the ancient Greeks. It is
always present in celebrations of important religious, public or private events, probably
accompanied by dance. Sorrow, grief, and war are often represented as a “foe to the
dance and lute, parent of tears” 36– without that excluding music even in those moments
(as the lamentations at funerals). In Aeschylus Eumenides Athena says: “And in their
dealings with mankind, visibly, perfectly, they (the Erinyes) work their will, unto some
giving song, unto others a life bedimmed by tears.”37 In religious or private ceremonies,
in public festivals, at symposia or at work, music is a way of expressing feelings,
communicating, and entertaining, just as it is today. One thing worth noting here is that
the strict line drawn nowadays between secular and religious, as between private and
public, was not as obvious in ancient Greece. At religious festivals there was often a
feast after the sacrifice, with eating and drinking. On the other hand, at the symposia,
the men made libations to the gods and sung hymns after the meal and before the
drinking began. The drinking itself was usually in honor of one of the gods.38 It is
therefore not correct to be speaking in today’s terms about phenomena of two and a half
thousand years ago. But to be practical and clear, these terms (religious-secular, public-
private) can be used to characterize the different situations in which music was
performed.
This chapter offers a brief account of the most important situations in which
music elements are found in ancient Greece. Music is almost always played at public
festivals and private ceremonies. The musicians may even compete against each other
in the musical competitions. There is also domestic and personal music making and
music that accompanies an activity of some sort, as children’s play, work, or marching
into a battle.
The public festivals are usually in honor of one or more of the Gods. The most
important ones are the Panathenaic festival and the City Dionysia. There are almost
always processions in which the participating citizens sing, most often accompanied by
an aulos player.39 There are choruses of dancing young women or men, accompanied by
the aulos or the lyra. Finally, an aulos player normally accompanies the sacrifice, which
is the peak of a religious festival. The most well known types of songs related to cults
are the paean, addressed to Apollo, and the dithyramb, addressed to Dionysos. The
36
Aeschylus, Suppliant Maidens 678-83.
37
Aeschylus, Eumenides 952-5.
38
See p. 32f. in this essay
39
In Fig. 11, 40 there are representations of both the aulos and the lyra.
10
latter loses much of its religious essence and becomes part of the City Dionysia, where
groups of men and boys compete in dancing the dithyramb to aulos music. Choruses
and aulos accompaniment are also part of the dramatic contests during the festivals of
the Lenaea and the City Dionysia.40
Even solo musicians and singers perform, and an example is the reciting of
Homer and other epic poems by rapsodoi. Already in the eighth century there are
competitions between these singers or instrumentalists.41 With time, more religious
festivals include musical contests of kitharodoi, aulodoi and auletae; one of these
festivals is the Panathenaea, which is reorganized in the early fifth century BC.
Music is present in private ceremonies, such as weddings or victories in athletic
competitions. Songs are sung accompanied by the aulos or the lyra. At funerals, except
for the women’s songs, professionals seem to be hired to sing laments. The main
instrument on the vases with representations of funeral processions is the aulos. The
extravagance of the funeral processions is limited as early as the beginning of the sixth
century, by laws of Solon.42
The symposion is another event where music is played. It is mainly men from
the elite that gather at someone’s house to eat and drink, discuss and sing to the lyra or
the aulos. This pattern exists already in Homer’s poems, where professional minstrels in
the king’s halls compose and sing their songs, usually to a phorminx.43 In the end of the
sixth and beginning of the fifth century, the symposion is represented in many vase
paintings, showing the guests playing music and drinking. By the end of the fifth
century these customs change; the younger Athenians start to disregard the traditional
music as part of the symposion. Many play new songs that are not according to the
tradition; others prefer instrumental music, without singing; and it becomes more and
more common to hire professional musicians instead of playing music themselves.44
The symposion will be discussed in more detail in the chapter “Music and the citizens”.
Working songs seem to be quite common in ancient Greece. Activities such as
working in the fields or building, are accompanied by music and singing, judging from
the vase paintings and the literary sources.45 One of the uses of music is to keep the
rhythm and motivation. There is a good example of it in Aristophanes’ play Frogs,
40
West 1992, 14-17.
41
West 1992, 18f.
42
West 1992, 21-24.
43
Barker 1984, 18.
44
West 1992, 24-28.
45
For more information on working songs see West 1992, 28-30.
11
where the frogs sing to help the god Dionysos keep the rhythm while rowing.46 Music is
played while men march into battle, to keep their rhythm, but maybe even to inspire
courage and bravery. Women may sing or play music while working at home, weaving
or grinding.47 Children’s games are very often dances and songs. Plato gives an account
of how he believes these first songs should be composed.48 Athletic training is almost
always accompanied by the music of the aulos in the imagery.
There is furthermore a belief that music has a magical or healing ability: this idea
of music as healing physical ills does not exist in the actual Greek medicine, which is
more ‘scientific’. It is, however, used by unqualified doctors and old women, as well as
in cures that are connected to religion, as in shrines of gods that are related to healing.
West names three kinds of healing music: “incantations; paeans and purifying songs;
and music supposed to be efficacious by virtue of its intrinsic properties”.49 The
Pythagoreans prefer the lyre in these cases, but in general the aulos is thought to have
the most power in producing ”strange effects”.50 Music’s healing ability is a theme that
is not seen very often, if at all, in the vase imagery.
46
Aristophanes, Frogs 202-268.
47
West 1992, 27.
48
For more information on Plato’s ideas on children’s songs, see p.28f. in this essay.
49
West 1992, 32.
50
West 1992, 33.
51
Arion is said to be responsible for first composing and naming the dithyramb; Herodotus 1.23.
52
Pausanias says that the aulodoi and auletae contests were new (10.7.4), while contests of kitharodoi
existed before; Pausanias 10.7.2-5.
53
Bundrick 2005, 8.
12
In Athens, the tyrant Peisistratos and his sons engage themselves with upgrading
the musical festivals in Athens. It is said that he reorganizes the Greater Panathenaea in
566 BC, but only in the fifth century does this festival accumulate prestige, with
musicians from all over the Greek world coming to Athens to compete. The vase
imagery follows this evolution, with musical scenes appearing already in the archaic
period, but reaching their peak during the fifth century.54
54
Bundrick 2005, 8.
55
Bundrick 2005, 9.
56
Aristoxenus, Harmonica 1.3; West 1992, 225.
13
musical themes and especially the ones depicting amateur musicians. Professionalism
becomes more widespread now. Lasos of Hermione, Pindar, Damon of Oa,57 Plato, and
Aristotle, theorize on the relation of ethos to human behavior, and even to the welfare of
the whole society. All these changes are even seen in the vase iconography, where there
are more representations of themes associated to ethos.58 This will be discussed in more
detail in the chapter “Ethos in music”.
A Cretan, a Spartan, and “the Athenian stranger” (Plato’s voice) are walking
from the palace of Knossos to the shrine of Zeus on Crete. During the time they discuss
57
For more information on Pindar and Damon see p. 15f in this essay.
58
Bundrick 2005, 10f.
59
Plato, Laws 799e10-11.
60
Guthrie 1978, 382.
14
how the best system could be developed, based mainly on the Athenian, but becoming
stricter with Dorian and Spartan discipline.
It has the same idea as the Republic but this is the second best state, a more real
state. Here Plato allows private properties and private families and the existence of
written laws. He has more tolerance than in the Republic towards the arts. It is divided
in twelve books, and some of them (II, III, VI, VII) speak of education and the arts.
15
3. ETHOS IN MUSIC
3.1 Literature
61
According to Anderson, the idea of musical ethos has its origins in the orient, Anderson 1966, 42.
62
According to Bundrick: “Although ethos signified the good or bad character of any subject, it was
particularly linked with ideals of virtue, most notably sophrosyne, especially in opposition to hubris.
Interest in sophrosyne and hubris inspired the popularity of such subjects as the Centauromachy,
Amazonomachy, and Gigantomachy in wall painting, architectural sculpture, and vase painting. As has
often been noted, these mythical battles could serve as metaphors for the equally epic conflicts between
the Greeks and the Persians, with the sophron Greeks, representatives of civilization, opposing the
bestial, hubristic barbarians who threatened the established order. At the same time, these images
alluded to the struggle for sohprosyne within the individual self”; Bundrick 2005, 104.
63
Bundrick 2005, 103.
64
Anderson 1966, 34f.
65
Pindar, Olympian 2 lines 1-2.
16
mathematics and acquires a more specific musical character.66 For the Pythagoreans,
the whole universe is based on mathematics and they give a mathematical basis to
musical intervals. Certain consonances, as the fourth, the fifth, and the octave, are
seen as representations of the harmony that exists in the ordered structure and
movements of the universe and in the feelings of the human soul, while it is also
connected to ethical value. Damon, Plato, and Aristotle seem to be strongly influenced
by the Pythagorean research in acoustical and musical phenomena.67
The Pythagorean doctrines are very important in the development of a set of
guidelines of musical ethos. Plato’s ideas about the power of music are based mainly
on the Pythagorean theory and on Damon’s ideas of music causing movement in the
soul.68 Damon is known as a theorist of music and as Pericles’ political adviser.
Examples of sources on Damon are Plutarch’s Pericles,69 Aristotle’s The Athenian
Constitution, and Plato’s dialogues, mainly the Republic.70 Damon is known for the
speech he makes in front of the Areopagus, concerning the importance of music in
education. He believes music can infuse virtue, wisdom, and justice to the young and
bases his doctrine on Pythagorean theories.71 One of the fragments saved is the
following:
With good reason Damon of Athens and his school say that songs and
dances are the result of the soul’s being in a kind of motion; those songs
which are noble and beautiful produce noble and beautiful souls, whereas
the contrary kind produce the contrary.72
The second statement is probably the most important principle of all musical
ethics. Damon believes that “musical styles are nowhere altered without (changes in)
the most important laws of the state.”73 This idea is apparent in the Laws and the
Republic. Already before Aeschylus’ time, Pratinas74 complains about the misuse of
rhythms and melodies by virtuoso players on the aulos, which shows that the concern
about the changes in music existed long before Damon and Plato:
66
Lippman 1964, 6.
67
Comotti 1989, 27.
68
Anderson 1966, 38.
69
According to Plutarch ”Damon seems to have been a consummate sophist, but to have taken refuge
behind the name of music in order to conceal from the multitude his real power”; Plutarch, Pericles 4.
70
Wallace 2004, 249f.
71
Comotti 1989, 31.
72
Athenaeus 628c.
73
Plato, Republic 424c5-6.
74
Pratinas was one of the earliest tragic poets of Athens (ca 500 BC) and is said to have introduced the
satyr plays. He was also a writer of dithyrambs and of choral odes called hyporchemata, RE XXII,
1954, 1721-1730, s.v. Pratinas (F. Stoessl).
17
’Tis the song that is queen, stablished by the Pierian Muse; but the flute
must be second in the dance, for is e’en a servant; let him be content in
the revel only, in the fist fights of tipsy youngsters raging at the front
door.75
75
Athenaeus 617b. Csapo is of the opinion that Pratinas might be parodying the critics of New Music,
since he is using the new style himself in this dithyramb. It is likely that the aulos player replies to the
song of the chorus by playing in the new fashion, Csapo 2004, 218.
76
Anderson 1966, 47.
77
Plato, Republic 398c-d.
18
Plato does not allow all the harmonies in his ideal state.78 For example, he
does not allow lamentations; that is why he excludes “the mixed Lydian, and the tense
or higher Lydian” from his State. In addition, drunkenness, softness, and indolence
are unacceptable, and so the Ionian and the Lydian are also excluded.79 That leaves
only the Dorian and the Phrygian:80
“I don’t know the musical modes,” I said, “but leave us that mode
that would fittingly imitate the utterances and the accents of a brave
man… And another for such a man engaged in works of peace…
acting modestly and moderately and acquiescing in the outcome.
Leave us these two modes – the enforced and the voluntary – that
will best imitate the utterances of men failing or succeeding, the
temperate, the brave…”81
Plato even makes rules about which instruments should be played and which
should not: the lyra82 and the kithara,83 the instruments associated with Apollo, are
accepted into his State. The herdsmen are also allowed some type of syrinx, but the
rest of the instruments are driven out.84 The aulos85 is banished, since it is the
instrument of Marsyas.86 According to Anderson, Plato is trying to make the music of
his ideal State totally hieratic, and erase anything that is not originally Greek.87 Apart
from the myth of Marsyas and Athena, there is even a story about the politician and
general Alcibiades:
He refuses to play the flute, holding it to be an ignoble and illiberal
thing…“Flutes then”, said he, “for the sons of Thebes; they know
not to converse. But we Athenians, as our fathers say, have Athene
as foundress and Apollo for patron, one of whom cast the flute
away in disgust, and the other flayed the presumptuous flute-
player”.88
78
For a detailed description of the harmonies see West 1992, 177-179.
79
Plato, Republic 398e.
80
Plato’s choice of keeping the Phrygian mode for enriching civic religious life, and Aristotle’s
indifference for religion and thus banning of the Phrygian mode, are analyzed in Anderson 1966, 107-
109.
81
Plato, Republic 399a-399c.
82
Lyres, harps, and lutes existed in Mesopotamia already before 2000 BC and were also used in west
Asia and the Mediterranean. The Greek variants are surely influenced by them, even though the Greeks
thought of the lyra as autochthonous; Comotti 1989, 70. For more details on the lyra see West 1992,
49-70.
83
The kithara was probably influenced by the kitharae in the Middle East, present already in the
Sumerian age; Comotti 1989, 57.
84
Anderson 1966, 66.
85
According to tradition the aulos came from the East, perhaps Phrygia. The practice of playing pipes
was universal in the Near East, from before 2000 BC, according to West 1992, 81.
86
Plato, Republic 399d-e. For more information on the myth of Marsyas and Athena, see p. 26f. in this
essay.
87
Anderson 1966, 66.
88
Plutarch, Alcibiades 2.5-6.
19
The reason was said to be that he did not like the way it blocked the mouth so
one could not talk, while the lyra brought the notes and the voice in balance. The
moral and aesthetic superiority of the musical performance with a lyra instead of an
aulos is based on an aristocratic ideal, which has body, voice, and instrument perform
in harmony.89
The rhythms of music should follow the same rules, according to Plato,
avoiding any complexities. They should express courage and harmony and be adapted
to the words of the songs that express the same. When Socrates starts speaking about
the rhythms, he seeks the help of Damon in remembering, acting as if he does not
know the various rhythms himself.90 It seems like Plato wants to show that he is not
interested in the techniques of playing music and the technical theory; the author is
more concerned about the effect music has on people, while technical issues interest
professional musicians, which he disdains.91
Plato's main idea is that music should stay simple. The narration that is applied
to music should be plain, imitating only the “good”. It should help educate the young
by giving them examples of just, brave men and good citizens. The narration should
never “imitate” women or slaves, coward men, animals or crashing seas. In
accordance, the rhythm and the melody do not have to undergo changes either, since
they follow the simplicity of the words. All the different types of scales and rhythms
will therefore not be needed, given that there is nothing complicated to be
represented.92 Plato wants gymnastics to be simple and “good”, just like music:
While simplicity in music begets sobriety in the souls, and in
gymnastic training it begets health in the bodies…93
He then changes what he said about music for the soul and gymnastics for the
body, and says that both music and gymnastics aim to improve the soul. Plato
describes how the guardians of the State must train in both in order to become
courageous without being savage from too much gymnastics, and to be gentle and
moderate without being soft and effeminate from too much music.94 So the man that
89
Wilson 2004, 276.
90
Plato, Republic 400a-e. He mentions the dactylic, the iambic, and the trochaic, amongst others.
91
About Plato’s views on the musicians, see p. 46-49 in this essay.
92
Plato, Republic 401a-402a.
93
Plato, Republic 404e.
94
Plato, Republic 410-412. The second part of this statement reminds us of Pericles’ funeral oration, in
which he praises the Athenians by saying: “For we are lovers of beauty yet with no extravagance and
lovers of wisdom yet without weakness”; Thucydides 2.40.1.
20
practices music and gymnastics in a balanced manner will be “the most perfect and
harmonious musician”, according to Plato.95
Music and gymnastics should be preserved in their original form, without any
innovations, which would be dangerous for the State. Plato states that it was originally
Damon who said that when the mousikoi tropoi change, the politikoi nomoi change
with them.96 It is most likely that mousikoi tropoi in this case means musical styles,97
while politikoi nomoi could either be the laws of the city or in general the political
and social rules.98 It is worth noting, however, that nomoi is a term used even for a
type of musical composition and performance.99 From a very young age children
should be taught good order in play, with the help of music. That is how they will
grow up as orderly and good citizens that will not want to change the laws their
predecessors created.100
Plato might possibly think this way but, as pointed out by Anderson, it is
debatable if Damon actually is such a conservative, since he is said to make
innovations himself and is closely associated with the democratic Pericles. According
to Anderson, Plato agrees with and uses many of Damon’s ideas on ethos and
education, but discards many others, and does not consider him to be a suitable citizen
of his ideal State. The basic difference between them is that for Plato, perfection is
necessarily static, though Damon is probably much less conservative.101
As already mentioned, Plato believes there is “good” and “bad” music and
dance. His opinion in the Laws is that the poets should be restricted in what they are
allowed to teach to younger people in order to direct them towards just and correct
lives.102 In the Republic he says that, when poets come to this State, although
respected and praised, they will not always be allowed in to recite their poems; only
those who imitate the style of the virtuous men and thus set good examples for the
95
Plato, Republic 411e-412b:”That he who best blends gymnastics with music and applies them most
suitably to the soul is the man whom we should most rightly pronounce to be the most perfect and
harmonious musician”.
96
Plato, Republic 424c.
97
Wallace 2004, 258; Anderson 1966, 25.
98
Wallace 2004, 258.
99
See the glossary and n. 113 in this essay.
100
Plato, Republic 423d-425a.
101
Anderson 1966, 77f.
102
Plato, Laws 656c.
21
citizens, will be permitted into the State.103 Technical proficiency is less important for
Plato.104
The author admires the laws of Egypt where it is unacceptable to make any
innovations in music, dance or painting; the artists have to strictly follow the
tradition.105 In all other states except Sparta and Crete, according to Plato, there are no
laws forbidding the artists to teach the “bad” music and dancing. He says that if only
true music, the natural melodies, could be found, then there would never be any need
of innovation. This is because the sacred, real music never gets antiquated, and one
does not get tired of it.106 The true and natural melodies could be interpreted as
influenced by the Pythagorean theories about the ratios and numbers in the balanced
universe in relation to music. In Timaeus Plato expresses his belief that the purpose of
harmony and rhythm of music is to help restore the order in the soul, and not to offer
pleasure to the listener:
Music too, in so far as it uses audible sound, was bestowed for the sake
of harmony. And harmony, which has motions akin to the revolutions
of the Soul within us, was given by the Muses to him who makes
intelligent use of the Muses, not as an aid to irrational pleasure as is
now supposed, but as an auxiliary to the inner revolution of the Soul,
when it has lost its harmony, to assist in restoring it to order and
concord with itself. And because of the unmodulated condition,
deficient in grace, which exists in most of us, Rhythm also was
bestowed upon us.107
Plato admits that music and dance should be judged by the pleasure they give,
but not just anyone’s pleasure.108 They should be judged by the pleasure they give to
the best and most educated men, in particular those with virtue and wisdom.109 The
competent judges, says Plato, can only be the older men of the chorus.110 Music and
dancing should not follow the taste of the multitude. Instead, Plato’s ideal artist is
strong enough to present the ”real” music and dance, and better characters than those
of the audience, in order to give the people a higher pleasure from the music, and help
103
Plato, Republic 397-398b.
104
Plato, Laws 654b8-d7.
105
Plato, Laws 656d-657b.
106
Plato, Laws 657b-c.
107
Plato, Timaeus 47c7-e2.
108
At 667e, in the Laws, Plato presents his interpretation of the word “pleasure”: “it is the pleasure we
feel of some work of art, which does not do harm nor good in any degree worth speaking of. This is
why the quality of music should not be judged by the amusement and the pleasure we get from it,
because that does not do us any good; art should be judged by the standard of truth.”
109
Plato, Laws 657d-659a.
110
Plato, Laws 670b-671a.
22
them learn from it. Cleinias, the Cretan man, replies that both in Crete and in Sparta
there are strict laws on what the poets should present in their work; they should
promote justice and convince the people that only a just and good man is fortunate
and happy, while the harmony and rhythm should be suitable to the good character of
the words.111
Plato is quite concerned with the new way of making music to impress and
entertain, with the mixing of different types of rhythm and melody. He considers all
art dangerous because it consists of imitation, but music is what requires most care: if
one makes a mistake in music it can have very bad consequences. The poets, he says,
are much inferior to the Muses and can make mistakes as, for example, wrong
combinations of melodies and rhythms, use of solo kithara or aulos without words, or
imitation of women, slaves, and even animals. This is wrong for Plato for the
following reasons: first, because the imitations mousike represents should be easily
understood and therefore based on the words of a song; secondly, music should
imitate only the “good” and form the youths’ characters in the best way so that they
become just and temperate men with courage, something that cannot be achieved
when imitating women, slaves, and animals.112
In the old days, the author recounts, there was such good order in the theatres,
that everybody kept quiet until the whole performance was finished. Thus, the
audience was not allowed to give its opinion on the music; this was up to the
competent authority to judge. As time past, however, poets took more and more
freedom in making innovations in music, mixing the different styles113 and ignoring
the rules of the “just and lawful in music”.114 They now inspire the audience to
believe that they themselves can also judge if music is good or bad, according to the
pleasure it gives them. This, according to Plato, is how music lost its quality. But the
worst is that this freedom in music leads further to a freedom in people’s everyday
lives, with disobedience of their elders and their rulers. In the end it will even lead to
disregarding the gods.115 According to these concerns of Plato and his recount of the
situation in the past, it appears that some proper forms and established styles of
111
Plato, Laws 659a-660c.
112
Plato, Laws 668a-670a.
113
Plato gives a brief account of the different “kinds and manners” of music that existed from very
early in time according to him. He mentions hymns, paeans, lamentations, dithyrambs, and nomoi.
These different styles, Plato continues, one should not mix with one another; Plato, Laws 700b.
114
Plato, Laws 700a-d.
115
Plato, Laws 700d-701b.
23
playing music in ancient Greece might have existed, but are now being ignored. These
forms might be related to the Pythagorean system of harmonics and consonance.
The Greeks know of music’s ability to calm or excite, and Dionysus and his followers
are connected with the second effect. Good examples of music’s exciting effect are
seen in the symposion, the komos, and the Dionysian thiasos, where wine is drunk and
music is played. The wine drinking is however limited: it has to be properly mixed
with water, so that it’s positive effect will not turn into drunkenness.
In the vase paintings, the positive and negative effects of both music and wine
are visualized. One of the themes on the vases is mania, the madness that possesses
the god or his followers, the satyrs and the maenads. The most frequently seen
instruments in this case are the aulos and a stringed instrument, the barbitos (Fig. 1,
116
Sophorsyne is a complex philosophical term, which includes the ideals of excellence of character,
moral sanity, moderation, and soundness of mind. For further information on sophrosyne and hubris
see nn. 1 and 62, as well as the glossary of this essay.
117
Aristotle, Poetics 1450a24; “An excellent painter of character”, translation by Bundrick 2005, 104.
118
Bundrick 2005, 104-106.
119
Bundrick 2005, 106.
24
2).120 There are also percussion instruments, as the tympanon, krotala, and kymbala,
probably liked for the noise they make (Fig. 2, 3).121 The aulos is said to create the
strangest effects on people and to “excite the emotions”. Aristotle says
characteristically:
The flute is not a moralizing (ethikon) but rather an exciting influence
(orgiastikon), so that it ought to be used for occasions of the kind at
which attendance has the effect of purification rather than
instruction.122
120
The phorminx and the kithara are also depicted in some of the paintings related to the cult of
Dionysos, but not frequently. The fact that the kithara is seen with Dionysos, however, shows that it
was not strictly Apollonian. Nymphs never play the kithara. It is only played by the satyrs, since in
reality only men ever played it. For more details see Bundrick 2005, 106-108.
121
For example see LIMC s.v Dionysos 295, 296, 314, 329, 333.
122
Aristotle, Politics 1341a.
123
Bundrick 2005, 107.
124
Bundrick 2005, 109. For example see LIMC s.v. Dionysos 153.
125
Modern scholars have mentioned opium, ivy- or toadstool-eating, Godwin 1981, 132.
126
Plato, Laws 790e-791a; Lippman 1964, 46.
127
For example see LIMC s.v. Dionysos 350, 356, 465, 801.
25
128
For more information on symposion scenes, see p. 37-39 in this essay.
129
Bundrick 2005, 116.
130
For example see LIMC s.v. Orpheus 28, 36, 44.
131
For example see LIMC s.v. Orpheus 8, 9.
132
Seebass 1995, 20.
133
Berlin Antikenmuseum, 3172, ca.440; Imago Musicae 1995, fig.5; Bundrick 2005, fig.74.
134
For a more detailed description of this vase painting see p. 61 in this essay.
26
There are mythological scenes for example, such as Apollo, Musaios and the Muses
(Fig. 27, 28, 29), and domestic scenes where women play music (Fig. 30, 31).135
3.2.4 Marsyas: the debate between the aulos and the lyra
Another mythological contest is that between Apollo and Marsyas, who finds the aulos
Athena has thrown away, since it disfigures her face. Marsyas is defeated by the lyra-
playing Apollo and punished (Fig. 9).140 In the vase paintings there is most often the
representation of the contest (Fig. 8).141
According to Voutira, this myth reflects the debate that is going on at the time,
concerning the ethical superiority of the lyra in comparison to the aulos. The lyra has
only been attested in art from the late eighth century onwards, but right from the
beginning it is associated with aristocratic education, indicating social status.142 The
135
For scenes with women playing music see p. 39-43 in this essay.
136
Bundrick 2005, 127.
137
For example see LIMC s.v. Thamyris 10.
138
Bundrick 2005, 129.
139
Voutira 1995, 75.
140
Apollodorus 1.4.2.
141
For example see LIMC s.v. Mousai 103.
142
Bundrick 2005, 14.
27
stringed instruments as the lyra, the kithara, and the barbitos, are slowly replacing the
traditional aulos playing. The advantage of the stringed instruments is that one can
sing at the same time. Plato, who discards any solo instrumental music, since it can be
misinterpreted, has also stressed this. The lyra in particular, is considered the perfect
instrument for amateur musicians since it is simple to play and does not need much
technical practice. It is worth noting a change in the iconography of the myth in the
last three decades of the fifth century: Marsyas is now pictured playing the lyra
instead of the aulos (Fig. 10),143 something which might mirror the ongoing debate
between the two instruments. This debate may even be reflected in a scene with a
woman preferring the lyra than the aulos handed to her (Fig. 11).144
143
Voutira 1995, 83. For example see LIMC s.v Mousai 107.
144
There are scenes in which both the aulos and the lyra are pictured, but they never seem to be played
simultaneously. There are mythical scenes where Apollo holds a lyra and a Muse the aulos, see Fig. 27,
28.
28
4.1 Literature
The above statement makes clear the important role Plato believes musical education
to have. Education in general is one of the first things that the rulers of his ideal State
should take care of and it should start at a very young age. In the Republic Plato states
that the narrations that are told to children should be censured;146 they should not
speak of the “world below” in a terrifying way for example, nor should they show a
man weeping or lamenting for a friend’s death. They should speak only of the brave
and fearless, the just and temperate man, and Plato even allows falsehood in order to
preserve the social and moral values.147 It is most likely that the narrations he speaks
of are meant to be sung, as most Greek poetry and narrations were; they can thus be
compared to modern nursery rhymes and songs. In general, taking care of education in
Plato’s state includes bringing more simplicity in music and gymnastics, a manlier
character of poetry, and greater harmony between the individual and the State.
The educated man, according to Plato, is the one that is “fully choir-
trained”.148 Choreia is an essential term in Plato. It has many meanings,149 but here it
is basically the choir training of the citizens which includes instruction in dance and
song.150 It aims mainly at preparing them for the ritual dancing and singing in honor
of one or more of the gods. Choreia for Plato is the equivalent of the entire
educational system of the Athenian citizens.
Plato divides education into gymnastics for the body and music for the soul.151
However, there is confusion in his ideas concerning the division of education and the
145
Plato, Republic 401d5-8.
146
In general Plato recognizes two different styles of narration: in the one, the narrator uses more
imitation then narration, but in the other, that Plato prefers since it is a more precise copy of reality, as
he says, the narrator uses more narration than imitation, Plato, Republic 377a-c.
147
Plato, Republic 377a.
148
Plato, Laws 654a-b.
149
For other meanings see Michaelides 1978 s.v. choreia.
150
Plato, Laws 654b.
151
Plato, Laws 795d6-e1.
29
aim of each part of it. In the Laws Plato has the same opinion as in the Republic,152
that education has two branches: gymnastics for the care of the body, and music for
the care of the soul. In its turn gymnastics also has two branches: dancing, which
imitates musical recitation, and aims at preserving dignity and freedom, and wrestling,
which aims at health, agility, and beauty.153 The above statement comes in
contradiction with another part of the Republic where he states that both music and
gymnastics aim at the improvement of the soul, the first giving the moderation one
needs and the second the courage, without being too savage or too soft.154 It is
apparent that Plato is not very consistent in the division of music, dancing, and
gymnastics, neither on what their aims are.
The author then presents a detailed educational program, starting from birth
until the age of sixteen. Babies should be treated in a way that does not make them too
comfortable but neither hateful by being exposed to sorrows too early. Children
should be allowed to play games, but from the age of six they should start schooling.
Education should be compulsory for all and the teachers are to be foreigners who will
be paid. He insists that the rules concern women as much as men, even the type of
gymnastics and war training.155 The legislator should not leave the female to live a
soft life without order and wasting money, while only taking care of the male half of
the city.156 All should be trained from very young to find pleasure in the severe and
orderly music and not in the sweet and vulgar music, in order to become better people.
Plato is afraid that the children who are brought up allowed to make changes
in their games will grow up to be people who want a different sort of life, and this will
end up in them wanting to change the laws of the state, one of the biggest evils,
according to the author. Since music is an imitation of good and bad characters, the
young should be prevented from seeing imitations of the bad; this can be achieved if
music is censured and not innovated. He praises the example of Egypt where art has
stayed the same in centuries and has not changed to the better or the worse; this is
152
Plato, Republic 404e; 376e: “Gymnastics for the body and for the soul music”. See also discussion
on music and gymnastics, p.19f in this essay.
153
Plato, Laws 795d6-e. For an analysis of the contradiction in Plato’s ideas about gymnastics caring
for the body at one point, the soul at another, see Anderson 1966, 94f.
154
Plato, Republic 410a-412b.
155
Plato, Laws 804d-e.
156
Plato, Laws 804e-806c.
30
accomplished by consecrating all dancing and music, and having special songs and
dances for all the ordained religious festivals.157
From the age of ten and for three years the child can learn the “letters” and
from the age of thirteen and for three years exactly, it can learn to play the lyra.158
Plato then moves on to the regulations concerning the teachers of the lyra. The teacher
should keep the music simple so that it is easier for the student to learn all he has to
learn in three years. No heterophonia, and no mixed rhythms; there should be
homophonia between the melody of the voice and the instrument.
So, to attain this object, both the lyre-master and his pupil must use
the notes of the lyre, because of the distinctness of its strings,
assigning to the notes of the song notes in tune with them; but as to
divergence of sound and variety in the notes of the harp, when the
strings sound one tune and the composer of the melody another, or
when there results a combination of low and high notes, of slow and
quick time, of sharp and grave, and all sorts of rhythmical variations
are adapted to the notes of the lyre, - no such complications should
be employed in dealing with pupils who have to absorb quickly,
within three years, the useful elements of music.159
This section is one of the very few in which Plato describes the playing of
music in such detail. Indirectly, it depicts and criticizes the new ways of playing
music that appear in the second half of the fifth century. It also shows that it is very
likely there are teachers and students wanting to practice this “difficult” music, which
is the reason Plato feels he has to set these rules. The New Music that the virtuosi
professionals bring with them, is more complicated but probably also more
impressive, especially for the younger generations, and seems to be making its way
into every aspect of the Athenians’ lives, whether Plato and other traditionalists like it
or not.
Plato limits the time of learning to play the lyre to three years, and wants to
keep the knowledge simple. This will be enough for the child to gain the ethical
values that music contributes with, since virtue is represented by simplicity in music,
according to Plato.160 The child should not for any reason continue and specialize in
playing music since this will take precious time from other knowledge that has to be
gained, as the “letters” mentioned above, arithmetic, “measuring length and surface
157
Plato, Laws 798b-799b.
158
Plato, Laws 809e-810a.
159
Plato, Laws 812d-e.
160
About the simplicity in music see p. 19 in this essay.
31
and solid”, and astronomy.161 Musical training seems to be a preparation of the citizen
who will then continue with philosophical studies. Becoming a virtuoso will make one
effeminate and soft instead of virtuous.162
Finally, Plato speaks of the regulations that should be applied on dancing and
gymnastics, the other half of education. The boys will have dancing masters and the
girls dancing mistresses. Supervising and responsible for both music and gymnastics
is the “Director of the Children”, who will be old, but able to choose the assistants he
wants to help him, women and men.163 As in learning to read, write, and play music,
there will be public instructors paid by the state to teach the military art to the young
people. Women should be taught just as much, in order to be able to protect the young
in case of war, when the men go into battle.164
Plato divides the movements of the body called dancing, into two categories:
“the one representing the solemn movement of the beautiful bodies, the other the
ignoble movement of ugly bodies”. Of the first kind there is a dance of war, of a noble
and manly person, and a dance of peace, which shows a temperate character, enjoying
prosperity and modest pleasure.165 Here Plato divides dancing into the same
categories he did earlier with the Dorian and Phrygian harmonies in music, where the
first was a harmony of war, the second of peace.166
The dance of war is called Pyrrhiche and the dance of peace Emmeleia, or
dance of order. The Pyrrhiche is a passage rite for boys becoming men, and part of the
Panathenaic games, where men and boys compete. It is usually accompanied by an
auletes (Fig. 17).167 Of the bad kind of dancing, which should not exist in Plato’s
State, there is a kind of Bacchic dance, according to the author, by drunken men
imitating Pans, Silenoi, and Satyrs, associated with purifications or initiation into
mysteries.168 The ignoble type of dancing should be shown to the youths in the way of
comedy, says Plato. It should be something to be laughed it, so that they know what to
avoid doing and learning. Slaves and strangers should be hired in these cases, and no
serious attention should ever be paid to these dances.169 The guardians should make
161
Plato, Laws 817e.
162
Plato, Republic 410c-d. See also p. 19 and n. 94 in this essay.
163
Plato, Laws 813b-d.
164
Plato, Laws 813e-814b.
165
Plato, Laws 814e.
166
Plato, Republic 399a-399c. See p. 18 in this essay.
167
Bundrick 2005, 78.
168
Plato, Laws 815b-d.
169
Plato, Laws 816d-e.
32
sure no changes are made once the correct dances are recognized, so that the city and
the citizens should continue living in the same way, as much as possible alike each
other; that is how they will live their lives happy and well, according to Plato.170
There is a passage in Protagoras where the thought of Plato’s contemporaries
may be presented. If Plato is really letting Protagoras speak for himself in this
passage, it is possible to discern how he, and possibly other sophists, view ethical
education.171 If this is so, the belief that training in rhythms and modes from a young
age is very important and long lasting, is even held by others besides Plato in the
Athenian society of the time172
The Laws and the Republic are in agreement about the importance of music in
education and in forming people’s characters. In the Laws there are new ideas as well,
since Plato now includes in his educational program public festivals, all classes of
society, and all ages, even babies and embryos, while even the symposion is seen as a
place of education. One of the most interesting new ideas that Plato has in the Laws is
the importance of games, consisting in singing and dancing from a very young age.
He believes that music in this case should be pleasant for the children so it will
become attractive to them. Aristotle supports the idea of early habituation to good
music, so that the children will at a young age be able to appreciate it and feel
pleasure listening to it173 and also be able to judge correctly without being carried
away by pleasure.174
170
Plato, Laws 816c-d.
171
Plato, Protagoras 325d7-e1.
172
Anderson 1966, 95.
173
Aristotle, Nicomacheian Ethics 1103b23-5.
174
Aristotle, Nicomacheian Ethics 1113a25-1113b2.
175
See “Background” in this essay.
176
It is worth noting that these religious songs were accompanied by the aulos, something that proves
the serious and ritualistic side of the instrument; Bundrick 2005, 81.
33
ideals of Plato and other writers, such as Xenophon, and they do not always represent
the real symposia. There are vase paintings for example, which show that a drinking
party can get out of control, including very drunk men and even sexual orgies (Fig.
25).177 Even Plato suggests there to be “banqueting laws” about speaking, drinking,
and playing music, as well as “officers of Dionysos”, who will make sure that the
drinking stays under control. These commanders will be of the elder men, some of
which will stay sober.178 The above measures indirectly show the author’s concern
about the situation at the symposia at the time.
In the Laws, Plato speaks of the “choir of Dionysos”, which will consist of old
men, to the surprise of the speaker’s companions.179 He explains that these old men
will be encouraged to sing with the help of wine. There should be rules concerning
who can drink wine, according to Plato: young children should not drink it at all until
the age of eighteen, since they already have a lively spirit. Men up to the age of forty
should only drink very limited amounts, while the older one gets, the more one is
allowed to drink. Plato’s explanation is that older people not only want to wash away
their sorrows and lighten up their lives with the wine, but they will also have more
courage to get up to sing and dance; that is the best way of teaching the younger
people all they have learnt through their long lives. They are, according to Plato, the
most wise and appropriate to influence the youth and speak/sing of virtue and
justice.180 So the author gives an educational aspect to the symposion as well as the
religious and the social.
The symposion is a place of performance of poetry and also one of its themes;
the poets speak of the rules and the pleasures of it. What can also be seen as a theme
in this poetry is the banquet of the gods on Olympus.181 Aristophanes is one of the
poets who takes up the symposion theme: in his Wasps182 (422 BC) there is a
description of an imaginary symposion, where after dinner the guests wash, pour
libations, and sing the skolia.183
177
See also Lissarrague 1987, fig. 9: a red-figure cup from c. 480, NY 20-246, ARV 467/118, in which
there is more drinking and erotic play than discussion.
178
Plato, Laws 671c-e.
179
Plato, Laws 665a-b.
180
Plato, Laws 666a-b.
181
Schmitt 1990, 20-22.
182
Aristophanes, Wasps 1208-50.
183
A short drinking-song, which the next guest tries to complete with his own; Barker 1984, 103.
34
Symposia still exist in the second half of the fifth century but professionals are
now responsible for the entertainment. Plato shows his dislike of the new ways of
entertainment at “the wine parties of the common market-folk” through Socrates in
Protagoras.184 Aristophanes in his Clouds also complains about the young people’s
disregard of traditional songs and sympotic customs.185
Both Plato and Xenophon have written a Symposium. In the first case the
guests decide that the evening should be dedicated to philosophical discussion, so they
send away the professional auletria to entertain the women in the women’s quarters
instead.186 Music is presented as pure entertainment, just as in Xenophon’s
Symposium. Here there is a lively description of the acrobatics, singing, dancing, and
music, that the hired professionals, two girls and a boy, amuse the guests with.187
184
Plato, Protagoras 347c-d.
185
Aristophanes, Clouds 1353-79.
186
Plato, Symposium 176e.
187
Xenophon, Symposium 2.1-3, 2.7-8, 2.11-23, 9.2-7.
188
Plato, Republic 451c.
189
Plato, Republic 451e.
35
In Laws, Plato insists that education should be compulsory for all and that his
rules are to be applied on both women and men.190 Concerning music itself though, he
makes a division into feminine and masculine:
And while it is necessary for him (the lawgiver) to assign both words
and music for both types of song as defined by the natural difference of
the two sexes, he must also clearly declare wherein the feminine type
consists. Now we may affirm that what is noble and of a manly
tendency is masculine, while that which inclines rather to decorum and
sedateness is to be regarded rather as feminine both in law and in
discourse.191
The ideal man in the author’s opinion is noble and manly, while the ideal
woman is solemn, respectable, and modest. The music, says Plato, should follow these
principles. This model of the moderate woman is also seen in Pericles’ funeral
oration, where a respectable woman in ancient Athens should be heard and seen as
little as possible, “whether in praise or in blame”.192
190
Plato, Laws 804d-806c.
191
Plato, Laws 802e.
192
Thucydides 2.45.2.
193
As for example in Plato, Laws 812d-e, see p. 30 in this essay.
36
However, music is still included, and not knowing how to play the lyra is considered
equal to not have had a good education.194 The number of literate Athenians increases
during this century and education is not a privilege of the elite anymore. In the
iconography there is a remarkable increase of the musical theme in the fifth
century.195
From the end of the sixth century BC there are many scenes of schoolrooms
where boys are learning by their music teachers to play music and recite poems,
usually in the presence of a paidagogos with a stick (Fig. 14).196 They are seen mostly
on vases connected to the symposion, such as cups, craters, and amphorae. The fact
that education is still limited to the elite has an influence on the character of the
representations. For instance, there is often a combination of schooling- and
symposion-scenes, or at least an indirect alluding to the certain purpose of education,
with small symposion scenes on the sides of the vase or just craters in the background
of the schoolroom. One of the most famous vases is by the Douris Painter, with
lessons in music, reciting, and singing (Fig. 12, 13).197 The paidagogos shows that
these students are from the upper classes. In the background there are two drinking
cups, referring to the symposion. There is teaching of the aulos on one side of the cup.
In the tondo of the cup there is a scene referring to gymnastics. Thus, as a whole the
cup is a visualization of Plato’s ideal of a balanced and harmonious combination of
gymnastics and music, for the well being of the body and the soul.198
The musical instruments in the vase paintings often refer to the good education
one has received and can be seen for example in mythological themes (Fig. 15), and
scenes associated to the dead, on white-ground lekythoi (oil-flasks) (Fig. 32, 33). In
these cases the instruments are mainly chelys lyres (Fig. 15, 40)199 and in some cases
kitharae (Fig. 32, 33). In the second half of the fifth century these scenes of deceased
playing the lyra or with images of lyres around their tomb become more frequent.200
194
Bundrick 2005, 49.
195
”These scenes advertise training in mousike for the good of the city and democracy, no matter how
grounded they essentially are in aristocratic ideals. It is understood by the viewer that mousike affords
the types of virtues most beneficial to oneself and the polis, including sophrosyne and harmonia.”
Bundrick 2005, 51.
196
Paidagogos was usually a slave that would follow the young boys to school; Bundrick 2005, 60.
197
For more details on the Douris painter see Robertson 1992, 84-93; Boardman 1975, 137-139.
198
Bundrick 2005, 60-62.
199
Bundrick 2005, 64-66.
200
For representations of women on white-ground lykethoi, see p.40f. in this essay; Bundrick 2005, 68.
37
There are many scenes where an auletes plays during athletic practice,
especially in red-figure vases (Fig. 16).201 The pyrrhike is also a famous theme on
vases from the late sixth until the mid fifth century (Fig. 17). It seems like the pyrrhic
dance loses its importance around mid fifth century, something that is seen in the
decrease of these scenes on vases and in Aristophanes’ complaints in Clouds about
how boys in his days do not dance the pyrrhike correctly anymore.202 As Bundrick
observes, many of the above scenes referring to education, as athletic training and
music schools, seem to almost disappear from the vase paintings more or less at the
same time, after the middle of the fifth century.203
201
See Boardman 1975 fig. 286, vase painting by Douris with athletic training accompanied by aulos
music; Basel, Antikenmuseum Käppeli 425, ARV 430, 31.
202
Aristophanes, Clouds 988-9.
203
Bundrick 2005, 80.
204
Bundrick 2005, 81f.
205
For example see Lissarrague 1990 fig. 96, red figure amphora from c. 510 BC, in Berlin, inv.
1966.19; See also Lissarrague 1990 fig.97, black figure epinitron from c. 500 BC, in Eleusis, 907.
206
For example see Lissarrague 1990 fig. 98, black figure skyphos by Pistias class, from c. 515 BC, in
Elvehjeim Museum of Art, Madison, 1979.122.
207
Plato, Symposium 176a.
38
if coming out of the mouth of one of the reclining men.208 In another, a symposiast is
holding castanets while singing o paidon kalliste (“O most beautiful boy”) (Fig. 19).
There is an example of a man playing the lyra and singing, with the words coming out
of his mouth and over his head on the one side, while on the other words come out of
the lyra in the opposite direction (Fig. 21). He is singing a love song about a beautiful
youth, as is so usual at the symposia.209
The context of the banquet scene is often balanced by representations of
collective activities, such as battles and parades. This way the meal is treated as one
civic practice amongst others. Sometimes there are symbols of the banqueters’
occupations besides the general context, such as arms, musical instruments, and
drinking vessels.210 Schmitt finds that the emphasis has been placed on three main
elements: “the equal distribution of food and wine; the exchange of conversation, of
singing, and of different forms of pleasure; the insertion of commensality in a whole
framework of civic activities”.211
Examining the iconography through time, it is obvious that during the sixth
century there is a focus on aristocratic occupations, such as the symposion and the
komos. Apart from the hetaerae, women are not depicted playing music so often. With
the establishment of a more democratic system in the end of the sixth century, and
during the beginning of the fifth, there is an increase of musical interest which is also
reflected in the vase paintings: school scenes (Fig. 12, 13, 14), more symposion
scenes with amateur musicians (Fig. 21, 22, 25, 26), athletic (Fig. 16, 17) and
courtship scenes with musical accompaniment, Eros as a musician, Apollo and the
Muses (Fig. 27, 28, 29).212
Sympotic and komos scenes can be seen on vases from 530 until about 400
B.C., but the most vibrant ones are from the period 530-460 BC. During this period
the so-called Anakreontic scenes appear, with men dressed in exotic costumes,
dancing, singing, and playing music.213 One theory is that they are dressed as women,
and a second, more convincing, is that these costumes and customs are Ionian, but
208
For example see Lissarrague 1990 fig. 100, red figure cup by the Brygos Painter from c. 480, in
Paris, Cabinet des médailles 546, ARV 372/26.
209
Lissarrague 1990, 132f.
210
Schmitt 1990, 17.
211
Schmitt 1990, 19.
212
Bundrick 2005, 197f.
213
For example see Bundrick 2005 fig. 53, column krater by the Pig Painter with Anakreontic komastes
from c. 470-460 BC, in the Cleveland Museum of Art, The A. W. Ellenberger Sr. Endowment Fund
(1926.549).
39
seen as effeminate by the Athenians.214 There is evidence that the symposion and the
komos can get out of control, as seen in a representation of drunken symposiasts (Fig.
25).
However, these scenes of elite entertainment and leisure, as many other scenes
examined hitherto, decrease from the mid-fifth century BC. At the same time there is
more focus on the professional musicians in the symposion scenes, instead of the
symposiasts playing music themselves. During the second half of the fifth century
there are many representations of female professional musicians and pyrrhiche
dancers, replacing the images of the male pyrrhic dancers (Fig. 23, 24, 26). Bundrick
notes that the shift of focus from the aristocratic symposia scenes to professional
entertainers in the second half of the fifth century may reflect changing attitudes not
only towards musical education, but also towards the way of life of the elite in
general.215
214
Bundrick 2005, 84-86.
215
Bundrick 2005, 87-90.
216
The first line, both in the Odyssey and the Iliad is a calling to the Muse or the Goddess for
inspiration; Homer, The Odyssey 1.1, The Iliad 1.1.
217
For example see LIMC s.v. Mousai 12, 19, 36b, 44b.
218
Plato, Symposium 176e; Aristophanes, Wasps 1335-81; Aristotle, Athenian Constitution 50.
219
Nordquist 2008, 124f.
220
Bundrick mentions hydriai, lekythoi, pelikai, oinochoai, pyxides, bell and calyx craters, lebetes
gamikoi, amphorae, and stamnoi, all associated with women and household work; Bundrick 2005, 94.
40
221
Boardman 1989, 219.
222
Nordquist 2008, 125-127.
223
Pausanias 9.20.
224
See Fig. 20 for a vase painting representing Sappho and Alcaeus.
225
Bundrick 2005, 93-96.
226
Some scholars support the idea that they represent Muses, because of the similarity of the scenes
with the ones depicting the goddesses. Bundrick mentions Maas & Snyder 1989, 120, 140f.
227
Some scholars have suggested they are hetaerae, since it is the only type of mortal musicians the
literary sources mention and because most other scenes with female musicians are picturing hetaerae.
Bundrick mentions Williams 1983, 99f.; Neils 2000, 224f.
228
Voutira believes the book roll is supposed to be showing both text and musical notation; Voutira
1995, 75f.
41
or three women with a lyra or a barbiton, and one holds the aulos.229 The aulos is
hardly ever seen played simultaneously with the stringed instruments, so it is likely
they are played alternately.230
Bundrick is of the opinion that these women are mortal and not hetaerae. The
paintings show the women respectably dressed and reading papyri, something that the
hetaerae are not seen doing. The author mentions two theories of the status of
Athenian women. The “pessimistic” one is that they are not allowed to be educated
and are limited to the house and housework; the “optimistic” one is that men are
aware of the importance of women in managing the household, and they are not
totally excluded or oppressed, even if there is a separation of duties for men and
women.231 As Aristotle points out, women do take part in the public life of Athens,
especially in the religious cults.232 After Pericles’ law in 451/0 that both mother and
father should be Athenians in order to be an Athenian citizen, Athenian women
probably become more important. Bundrick believes that this supports her opinion
that the vase scenes represent leisure moments of educated, privileged Athenian
women, playing music.233
There is a group of white-ground funerary lekythoi with women playing
instruments on them, and “the funerary nature of these vases suggests it was desirable
and acceptable to memorialize a woman as educated for all eternity”.234 On these
vases there is usually one person playing music and another listening, and the music
serves as an expression of grief (Fig. 32, 33).235
It is most probable that these women are mortals and respectable Athenian
citizens, for the following reasons: their clothing indicates that they are not hetaerae
but respectable women; besides, they are not pictured in a context similar to that of
the symposion scenes, and the atmosphere is much calmer. There are no inscriptions
with names of the Muses; they are inside an oikos, represented by the columns for
door and walls, while Muses are out in the nature, usually sitting on a rock. Finally,
229
For example see Voutira 1995 fig. 18, red figure calyx krater from c. 440-430, in Würzburg von
Wagner Museum, 521.
230
Voutira 1995, 90.
231
Bundrick 2005, 96-98.
232
Aristotle, Rhetoric 1361a; Aristotle, Politics 1259a38-1259b10.
233
Bundrick 2005, 98.
234
Bundrick 2005, 99.
235
Seebass 1995, 32.
42
there are always just women depicted, no men, indicating that the scene might be
taking place in the gynaikon, the private space of the women.
236
See Nordquist 1990 and ”Background” in this essay.
237
Nordquist 2008, 126f.
238
Bundrick 2005, 157f.
43
are probably the ones used in reality in these rituals.239 This ecstasy, reached with
music and dancing, seems to be the purpose of mysteries in general; the mystae
(initiates) want to get away from civilization and the earthly, while coming closer to
identification with the divinity. It is reasonable that this is especially appealing to the
women and lower classes of society, which are all accepted as participants in the
rituals, and for a while free themselves from everyday troubles.
Private ceremonies
Women are seen playing music in private ceremonies, as, for instance, at weddings.
During the sixth century it is mainly Apollo Kitharoidos that is portrayed in wedding
scenes as the musician, but in the fifth it is mostly mortals playing the music, even the
brides themselves in some cases.240 There are vase paintings depicting the dances of
women at weddings, accompanied by male or female musicians (aulos or lyra players
or both).241 In some paintings there is one woman playing the harp, probably the bride
(Fig. 36). In another the bride is playing the chelys lyra,242 while once the bride is
seen holding an aulos up to her face.243 These musical instruments may allude to the
bride’s education and social status.244
239
Bundrick 2005, 158-160.
240
Bundirck 2005, 179.
241
Bundrick 2005, 181.
242
For example see lebes gamikos by the Painter of Athens 1454, in Athens, National Museum 1171,
from Peristeri; ARV 1179,4.
243
For example see Bundrick 2005 fig. 20, lebes gamikos by the Washing Painter with bride and
companions, c. 430-420, in Athens, National Archaeological Museum (14791).
244
Bundrick 2005, 189-191.
44
245
West 1992, 34f.
246
Barker 1984, 18.
247
West 1992, 34.
248
Lissarrague 1990, 124.
45
Greek world. They bring with them their talents and innovations that cause the debate
discussed in this essay.249
On the other hand there are professionals who provide official routine services
without needing any special talent, and usually have a lower status than the talented
performers. In Athens there are the auletes of the archons and the auletes of the boule,
as well as salpingtae with civil duties. They are most likely Athenian citizens.250
There are also mourners and auletae that can be hired for various public or private
events, as weddings and funerals. At the symposia, by the end of the fifth century
“young men scandalized their elders by reciting speeches from decadent modern
dramas instead of drawing on the traditional repertoire, or they rejected altogether the
doing of a party piece” .251 Professionals seem to be hired all the more often to
entertain the guests. They are women or men, slaves or hirelings, often of foreign
origin. They entertain the guests with music, dancing, and acrobatics, taking the place
of the amateur music making that was more common in the beginning of the fifth.252
Other symposiasts satisfy themselves with philosophical conversations and no music
at all.253
In Greek cult an auletes always participates in the sacrifice; it is either a man or
a woman, who receives a share of the meat of the sacrificed animal. The musician is
either an amateur aristocratic citizen or a professional of high or low status, and
sometimes even a slave. He or she is temporary employed for a certain event or
festival or paid by the year, having steady duties with civil or sacral authorities. It
seems, however, that the money is not enough to support them a whole year, so these
musicians probably play at other occasions as well, when they get the chance. In the
texts the professional musicians are not appreciated as much as the star performers,
who are employed by kings and other wealthy men. But in general in the literary
sources, any form of professionalism is seen negatively.254
249
See p. 50f. in this essay.
250
Nordquist 1991, 84f.
251
West 1992, 26.
252
West 1992, 35. As in Xenophon, Symposium, see p. 34 in this essay.
253
As for example in Plato, Symposium 176e.
254
Nordquist 1991, 93.
46
5.1 Literature
A brief account of the ideas of Plato and Aristotle concerning art and the artists, as
well as musical contests, will follow. Next, this chapter will concentrate on New
Music and the reactions it caused.
255
Plato, Republic 601a7-b2.
256
According to Guthrie this approach appears sometime during the sixth century BC; Guthrie 1975,
208.
47
This is an example of poetic ecstasy. Plato means that the poet can create only
when he is in a “divine frenzy” with the gods giving the power to him, since he is not
himself competent enough. Socrates proves it here by saying that in any other case Ion
would have knowledge on all the themes in Homer, which Ion does not. However,
Socrates only asks about practical knowledge, not aesthetic, which shows that Plato
sees art as didactic, giving moral and political advice.259 The Muses provide their help
in giving the facts of the poem not creating its form.260
Plato believes that the poets do have a poetic ability, but that they are not
always capable of telling between good and bad and have no perception of what is just
and lawful in music.261 The composition of prayers to the gods in addition, is a
responsibility of the poets, and Plato finds it very important to have the correct
prayers composed, so that nothing bad is requested of the gods.262 That is why the
poets will never compose alone, but always with the guidance of men over the age of
fifty and the inspection of the Law-wardens, who will judge the compositions before
letting them be performed for the citizens.263 He requires strict rules in the ideal state;
257
For a more detailed analysis, see Guthrie 1975, 204-211.
258
Plato, Ion 542a-b.
259
Guthrie 1975, 205.
260
Guthrie 1975, 206f.
261
Plato, Laws 802b-c.
262
Plato, Laws 801a-b.
263
Plato, Laws 801c-d.
48
the poets will not be allowed to teach anything that goes against the traditional ethical
standards, otherwise they will be banned.264
In general Plato is not so concerned about the artists’ technical abilities or their
special skills in composition. His main concern is that they are men of virtue,
regardless of musical or poetic talent. His focus is basically on the practical issues in
securing the educational ethos in music and he imposes many rules on how the artists
should compose their works in order for this to be achieved.
264
Plato, Laws 656c1-7.
265
Nordquist 1991, 95.
266
Aristotle, Politics 1341b9-14.
267
Plato, Laws 804d-e.
268
For example in Plato, Laws 653a-c and 659a.
49
what is believed to form a better character. Since most citizens from the lower classes
need to work though, all this can only concern the elite and it agrees with the rest of
the author’s aristocratic ideas. Plutarch narrates that even
Philip (of Macedon) once said to his son (Alexander) who, as the
wine went round, plucked the strings charmingly and skillfully, “Are
you not ashamed to pluck the strings so well?”269
As Plato says, the gods created the religious festivals for the people to rest
from their work; there they can engage in dance and song in the company of the
Muses, Apollo, and Dionysos, and that way “set right again their modes of
discipline”.270 That can be compared to Aristotle’s opinion on why music has become
an essential part of education: it provides dignified enjoyment in leisure time. He
believes that moderate playing and listening to music is good for both the body and
the mind, assists in the development of a morally correct character, and leads to
wisdom.271 Even Pericles’ idea can be paralleled to the philosophers’:
Moreover, we have provided for the spirit many relaxations from toil:
we have games and sacrifices regularly throughout the year…272
Musical contests
Mousikoi agones are musical competitions where solo kitharodoi, kitharistae, aulodoi
and auletae perform, the most famous events being the Pythia at Delphoi and the
Karneia at Sparta, both in honor of Apollo.275 With time, mousikoi agones are
introduced into the Panathenaic festival, which becomes Panhellenic.276 In Plato’s
opinion there should be musical and gymnastic contests between the citizens:
269
Plutarch, Pericles 1.5.
270
Plato, Laws 653d.
271
Aristotle, Politics 1339b10ff (or 1337b29-34).
272
Thucydides 2.38.1.
273
Ford 2004, 334.
274
Ford 2004, 336.
275
Wilson 2004, 281.
276
Bundrick 2005, 160.
50
277
Plato, Laws 764d-e.
278
Plato, Laws 657e-659b.
279
Plato, Laws 700a-701d; Aristotle, Politics 1342a18: theatriki mousike; Pseudo-Plutarch, De Musica
1140d-f: theatriki mousa.
280
Csapo 2004, 207.
281
Barker 1984, 93.
51
The most important musical forms the above sources speak of, apart from the
music used in drama, are the dithyramb and the kitharodic nomos, which follow a
similar evolution. The dithyramb undergoes many changes, not least when tyrant
Peisistratus sets up the City Dionysia, where competitions in dithyramb, tragedy, and
comedy take place. Comotti suggests that this competitive atmosphere is what pushes
the composers to make innovations. The dithyramb loses its religious character with
time and the composers feel free to use myths about other gods, and even to make
changes in the melody and rhythm.282 According to Csapo, it is the Athenian
democracy that finally turns the dithyramb into a show for the Athenian mass.283 The
kitharodic nomos follows the changes of the dithyramb. Although innovations take
place all through the fifth century, they concern mainly the dithyramb; only during the
last decades of the century do they spread to other genres.284
The most famous composers of this period are Melanippides, Phrynis,
Philoxenus, Timotheus, Cinesias, and Telestes. There is a comedy called Cheiron
written by a certain Pherecrates, quoted in pseudo-Plutarch’s treatise De Musica.285 In
this play, personified Music herself makes a speech complaining about the way
musicians have been treating her lately. The fragment is criticizing the innovations
made in music at the time. Pherecrates wins his first prize in 438 BC, so he is
contemporary to the poets he mentions.286 It is one of the most important documents
concerning New Music.
The various innovations of these musicians are too many to be mentioned in
this essay.287 Besides, one can come upon difficulties understanding their exact
meaning. Some examples can be given here, as Melanippides who is accused of being
the one to have started the degeneration of music.288 He is active around 480-430
BC289 and is in fact admired by Xenophon.290 Aristotle mentions of his innovations in
the structure of the traditional dithyramb.291 Philoxenus is another example,
282
Comotti 1989, 23f.
283
Csapo 2004, 209.
284
Comotti 1989, 30.
285
Pseudo- Plutarch, De Musica 1141d-1142a.
286
Anderson 1966, 50.
287
For an extensive description of the innovations see Barker 1984, 93-98; West 1992, 356-368;
Comotti 1989, 35-40.
288
Pseudo- Plutarch, De Musica 1141d-1142a.
289
Barker 1984, 93.
290
Xenophon, Memorabilia 1.4.3: ”In epic poetry Homer comes first...in Dithyramb, Melanippides.”
291
Aristotle, Rhetoric 1409b: ”Instead of antistrophes composed dithyrambic preludes.”
52
With these innovations, Timotheus’ music becomes difficult to sing for the
amateur Athenian citizens who form the chorus in these times. It is also harder for a
large group to sing this music, than for a single individual. Only well-trained
professionals can meet the demands of the New Music, and this is one of the main
reasons that the Hellenic dithyrambic chorus slowly dies out.298 This concern is seen
clearly in the Problems, attributed to Aristotle, in which the author describes how the
amateur chorus cannot keep up with the innovations in musical performances.299
Plato’s distress over the New Music becomes more comprehensible now, since, for
him, the chorus of the citizens personifies the civic paideia; it is through the chorus
that the citizens get their best and most important education.300 However, even though
Timotheus is strongly criticized in Pherecrates, Aristophanes, and the philosophers, he
becomes the leading composer of his time. In fact, his nomoi and those of Philoxenus
become classics in the education of children two centuries later.301
292
Athenaeus 643d: “Far superior to all poets is Philoxenus.”
293
Aristophanes, Birds 1377ff.; Lysistrata 838ff.; Frogs 153, 1435-7; Ecclesiazousae.330.
294
Plato, Gorgias 501e.
295
Pseudo- Plutarch, De Musica 1141d-1142a; Aristophanes, Clouds 970-1.
296
Anderson 1966, 50.
297
Pseudo- Plutarch, De Musica 1142a.
298
Anderson 1966, 51.
299
Pseudo- Aristotle, Problems 918b15-39.
300
Plato, Laws 654a-b.
301
Polybius 4.20.8-9.
53
West calls these new virtuosi “star performers”. They perform in a time when
personality and individual virtuoso skills are becoming all the more important for the
public. In general this period is characterized by more complexity in music (in
rhythms, melodies, and poetic diction) and a mixing between musical styles. New
Music is closely associated with emotional expression and decorative elaboration, so
specialist performers on the aulos become very important, since it is an instrument
one can apply these innovations on easily. The status of the leading auletes is now
higher than ever.302
Many of the well-known auletae are Theban, as Pronomus,303 who is well
known for having been the first to play all the harmoniae on one pair of auloi.304
Another one mentioned is Antigeneidas from Thebes,305 who does not like the name
“auletes” being applied to every simple musician that plays at a funeral. There are
quite a few details in the information about him and other auletae, something that
shows the growing interest in them.306
The most celebrated kitharistes of these times is Stratonicus of Athens (active
between 410 –360 BC).307 He is said to have adopted the kithara with up to eleven
strings. The kitharodoi are the musicians who arouse the most popular interest, and
they are the ones who get the biggest prizes at the Panathenaic competitions in the end
of the fifth and beginning of fourth centuries.308
302
West 1992, 366.
303
Stefanis 1988, 2149.
304
Barker 1984, 97.
305
Stefanis 1988, 196.
306
In the inscriptions, the auletes never used to be named, whereas in the fourth century they started
being named after the choregos and the chorus-master and later even before the chorus-master; West
1992, 367.
307
Stefanis 1988, 2310.
308
West 1992, 368.
309
Some of the conservatists named are Tyrtaeus of Mantinea, Andreas of Corinth, and Thrasylus of
Phlius; Pseudo- Plutarch, De Musica 1137f-1138a. Dorion is another, who plays for Philip of Macedon;
West 1992, 369.
54
Athenian citizens and characterize them as morally harmful.310 Plato forbids any
imitations of women, animals, cowards, and whatever creates a lot of noise, since all
that demands the use of different and complex scales, rhythms, and changes from one
to another.311
Plato does not directly criticize the musicians as much as Pherecrates and
Aristophanes do. He criticizes the changes that have taken place in musical
performance. In Laws Plato describes with distaste how the situation has changed in
the theatre, in the following passage:
Among us, at that time, music was divided into various classes and
styles…312 So these and other kinds being classified and fixed, it
was forbidden to set one kind of words to another class of tune. The
authoriry… was a rule made by those in control of education that
they themselves should listen throughought in silence, while the
children and their ushers were kept in order by the discipline of the
rod… But later on, with the progress of time, there arose as leaders
of unmusical illegality poets who, though by nature poetical, were
ignorant of what was just and lawful in music; and they, being
frenzied and unduly possessed by a spirit of pleasure, mixed dirges
with hymns and paeans with dithyrambs, and imitated flute-tunes
with harp-tunes, and blended every kind of music with every other;
and thus through their folly, they unwittingly bore false witness
against music, as a thing without any standard of correctness, of
which the best criterion is the pleasure of the auditor, be he a good
man or a bad. By compositions of such a character, set to similar
words, they bred in the populace a spirit of lawlessness in regard to
music… Hence the theatregoers became noisy instead of silent, as
though they knew the difference between good music and bad
music, and in place of an aristocracy in music there sprang up a kind
of base theatrocracy.313
Thus, as Plato recounts, in the “old days” there was order, but now the will of
the audience has taken over, and the poets compose in order to please the crowd
instead of educating them, which is the original purpose of music.
Aristoxenus is another one who believes music has degenerated in favor of the
crowd’s pleasure.314 In his opinion earlier music aimed to educate and honor the gods,
but in his times musicians compose only for the concert-hall. He criticizes Crexus,
310
Plato, Republic 395d-400a.
311
Plato, Laws 669c-670a, 700a-701a.
312
Plato mentions the hymns, the dirges, the paeans, the dithyramb, and the (kitharodikos) nomos;
Plato, Laws 700b.
313
Plato, Laws 700a-701b.
314
Pseudo- Plutarch, De Musica 1140d-f, 1137b.
55
Timotheus, and Philoxenus, who have all discarded the enharmonic genus, trying to
make music sweeter.315
It is a common practice during this period to criticize other composers’ work in
one’s own. This is seen especially in comedies, where the criticism is expressed with
humor, often satire and abuse. The best sources are Aristophanes and the Pherecrates-
fragment mentioned above. These plays offer not only contemporaries’ views towards
the changes in music, but also information about musical techniques, musicians, and
the actual changes that are taking place.
Aristophanes works from about 430 until 390 BC. He is a traditionalist who
sees the changes in music as corruption of the arts. He is a supporter of simple and
manly music, as represented in the compositions of Aeschylus.316 A detailed account
of all he says about music is beyond this essay, but a few examples can be named. In
Clouds, Aristophanes criticizes the new dithyramb-composers and makes the
character Socrates call them “quacks of every degree…and fools who their staves of
dithyrambs proudly rehearse”,317 while the dithyrambic poet Cinesias is satirized by
Aristophanes in his play Birds.318
Frogs is one of the latest of Aristophanes’ plays, written in 405 BC. In this
play Dionysos decides to travel to Hades to bring back Euripides, because no good
poets are left in Athens anymore. When he gets there though, he discovers that
Euripides has taken Aeschylus’ honored place on the poetic throne of Hades. A long
contest begins between the two poets, Euripides and Aeschylus, with Dionysos as a
judge. The styles of their compositions are evaluated and compared with each other,
both from a musical and a poetic perspective.319 An interesting passage is where
Aeschylus makes fun of Euripides:
But he from all things rotten draws his lays, from Carian flutings,
catches of Meletus, dance-music, dirges. You shall hear directly.
Bring me the lyre. Yet, wherefore need a lyre for songs like these?
Where's she that bangs and jangles her castanets (ostraka)?
Euripides's Muse, present yourself: fit goddess for fit verse.320
315
Pseudo- Plutarch, De Musica 1145a-d.
316
Barker 1984, 100.
317
Aristophanes, Clouds 331-333.
318
Aristophanes, Birds 1373-1409.
319
Barker 1984, 111f.
320
Aristophanes, Frogs 1300-1305. The ostraka are an instrument like a castanet, associated with
whores and mystery cults, mainly women’s rites; Barker 1984, 115.
56
After a long competition, Dionysos decides that the one who proves best
advisor on political and moral matters for Athens will be the one who follows him
back.321 However, Dionysos just takes “the one that his soul desires”,322 which is
Aeschylus, while Sophocles is left with the throne in Hades.323
although he is still represented with kitharoidoi.329 Although aulos players have not
disappeared from the iconography, the kitharodoi seem to have the highest status
among professional musicians, even in the paintings. On a vase by the Pan Painter the
word kalos330 is written on the bema, which a very concentrated kithara player is just
mounting (Fig. 37). Both aulos and kithara players wear beautifully decorated
costumes, contrasting with the standard ones of the sixth and the fifth century images
of Apollo (who wears a chiton and a himation). These costumes are derived from East
Greek precedents and show the Athenians’ interest in “Eastern exotica”, but also the
fact that many of these professional musicians are actually non-Athenians.331
Some figures in the fifth century paintings are interpreted as judges of the
musical contests,332 something that might allude to the democratic system of Athens,
from the way they were selected.333 The aulodic contest becomes more important
again in the second half of the fifth century. Musical contests are now represented on
a larger variety of vases, which shows that this event is accessible to a wider
audience. The representations of events such as contests, theatrical plays, and
sacrifices, where the entire citizen body participates, are strongly related to the
democratic system, in contrast to the symposion and komos scenes, which are related
to the aristocracy.334
Well-known musicians are now included in the vase iconography. There is a
vase painting by the so-called Pronomos painter, which represents the auletes
Pronomos in a theatrical scene (Fig. 38). It has a very rich iconography and the
auletes is sitting in a central position with the inscription ‘Pronomos’ over him. The
play-writer is sitting by his side. Dithyrambs seem to be a vase-painting theme as
well. Even depictions of theatrical choruses may be recognized, as with a scene of a
richly dressed auletes amongst two men clad as birds, dancing (Fig. 41). It has been
329
Wilson 2004, 284.
330
According to Bundrick the word kalos ”proclaims his fame and talent, almost transforming him into
a statue”; Bundrick 2005, 165.
331
Bundrick 2005, 166.
332
For example see Bundrick 2005 fig. 99, calyx krater in the manner of the Peleus Painter with
victorious kithara player, c. 430-420 BC, in London, The British Museum (E 460).
333
It is not totally clear how the judges of the musical contests were selected, but it seems to have been
done democratically, by lot; Bundrick 2005, 168f.
334
Bundrick 2005, 170.
58
335
Bundrick 2005, 176.
336
Bundrick 2005, 178.
337
See Bundrick 2005 fig.17, bell krater by Polion from c. 420 BC, in New York, The Metropolitan
Museum of Art; Fletcher Fund, 1925 (25.78.96).
338
Bundrick 2005, 174.
339
Bundrick 2005, 201.
59
6. DISCUSSION
340
Dowden 1992, 158.
341
Aristotle, Politics 1341a.
60
how the Bacchants are calmed from their frenzy.342 It is usually wind and percussion
instruments that have this effect on people.343
Seebass is of the opinion that, although there are many scenes representing
music in general, very few of them actually visualize the power of music. He points
out that the power of music is celebrated in myths but not seen as much in the
images.344 In this essay it is suggested that among the vase paintings representing
music, there are very few in which the effects of music and how people respond to it
are not obvious.
Music is hardly ever a neutral element in the paintings. The presence of
musical instruments, especially when being played, indicates a charged atmosphere,
where everyone present is influenced by the sound of them: music can soothe and
calm, it can entertain, excite, purify, heal, and much more, and all these effects are
visualized in the vase paintings. Seebass searches for representations of the myths that
directly speak of how music affects the soul. This chapter demonstrates how most
scenes representing music display the relation of music to ethos and the soul, directly
or indirectly.
Even though the debate concerning the influence of music is held mainly
among the philosophers and musical theoreticians, the vase painters create scenes in
which the effects of music are apparent. Whether they and their customers are
conscious of the effects of music in the same way as the philosophers, cannot be
known for sure, since there are no written sources by them. The vase painters are not
even necessarily Athenians; they are often non-Greeks or slaves.345 It is possible that
the Athenian citizens at least, are a lot more interested and informed about the
philosophical and musical debates than most people are nowadays. First of all, music
seems to play a more important role in the Athenians’ lives than it does in the life of
the average person today, in which it aims mainly at entertainment. Secondly, these
debates take place openly in the agora, and are presented in the theatre, where all
citizens are present. As Pericles says about the Athenian citizens:
You will find united in the same persons an interest at once in private
and in public affairs, and in others of us who give attention chiefly to
business, you will find no lack of insight into political matters.346
342
Plato, Laws 790e-791a.
343
Lippman 1964, 45f.
344
Seebass 1995, 18.
345
Price 1999, 12.
346
Thucydides 2.40.1.
61
The difference between the people and the philosophers must be the fact that a
large part of the population is open for the new ideas in music, while the philosophers
are more critical and afraid of the dangers that will follow this lawlessness in music.
347
For example see LIMC s.v Mousai 12, 19.
62
on the music, as is the one playing it. One gets a feeling of piety and respect for the
musician, and the concepts of harmonia and sophrosyne describe the scene well.
Seebass expresses it as following: ”The serious, positive mood that strikes the
onlooker is the result of a visualization of musical eukosmia and eunomia through
gracefulness, order, and a balanced sophisticated distribution of pictorial elements”.348
Plato prefers the music of Apollo than that of Dionysos or Marsyas.349 Already
in Pindar Apollo’s lawful and correct music is praised:
'Tis Apollo that allotteth to men and to women remedies for sore
diseases. 'Twas he that gave the cithern, and bestoweth the Muse on
whomsoever he will, bringing into the heart the love of law
(eunomian) that hateth strife.350
348
Seebass 1995, 30.
349
Plato, Republic 399e.
350
Pindar, Pythian 5.60-7.
351
See p. 40f. in this essay.
352
See Seebass fig. 20, Athens, National Archaeological Museum, 1260, ARV 1060.145.
353
Plato, Symposium 176e.
63
and percussion instruments. The aulos is known for its strange effects on people’s
behavior, with its ability of imitating sounds and the high pitch it can reach. In
addition, the loudness and especially the rhythmic steady beat that percussion
instruments can produce are important elements in building up an ecstatic ambience.
The women in these scenes seem influenced by the music, and are dancing so vividly
that the moves of their bodies appear uncontrolled. The wide-open arms to the side
and the head tipped back are indicative gestures of ecstatic mood. Music in these
scenes is a way of coming closer to god and to nature, away from society and
civilization, while it frees the women from everyday burdens. There are parallels of
this frenzied dancing with flinging of the head even today, for example in African
tribes and in South America, especially in cases where the people are struck by
poverty or diseases. Modern psychologists often interpret it as a need to try and free
the spirit from the body and unite it with the deity, liberating it from everyday
sufferings.354 This type of music with a steady repetitive beat can even be compared to
modern rave parties, where people dance intensely to rhythmic music, bringing
themselves into an ecstatic mood.
Plato believes that the frenzied bacchic women can be healed with ecstatic
music and dancing, as a sort of catharsis, in the same way that babies can be soothed
and calmed with singing and rocking. Here Plato is referring to the healing and
calming power of music.355 He explains it in the following way: both the Bacchants
and the children have an emotion of fear, caused by a poor condition of the soul. So
when one applies external agitation (music and movement in this case), it
overshadows the fear, bringing calmness and peace to the soul. It helps the children
sleep, and brings the Bacchants to a stable state of mind, by dancing to the aulos, and
with the help of the gods they are worshipping.356 Lippman points out that these
orgiastic rituals are similar to ”the epileptic fits of the shaman, the dancing epidemics
of the Middle Ages, the seventeenth century outbreaks of tarantism, or the
uncontrollable jerking of American revivalist meeting”. He notes the importance of
religion in every case of orgiastic rites.357
In the symposion scenes a variety of reactions may be discerned. When the
men are seen playing music themselves, they are often singing about their love for
354
Lawler 1964b, 96.
355
Plato, Laws 790d-e.
356
Plato, Laws 790e-791b.
357
Lippman 1964, 46.
64
some other man or boy (Fig. 18, 19, 21). Their pose is indicative of immense pleasure
or even ecstasy, with the head tipped back and/or the hand lifted towards it. The
listeners are sometimes oblivious of their surroundings, enchanted by and focusing
only on the music. But it is not only the symposiasts that are depicted; they are often
accompanied by the professional female musicians and dancing girls (Fig. 4, 23, 26).
The atmosphere becomes erotic and this is represented with indicative poses too.
Dancing is often shown in komos scenes,358 indicating the enthusiastic rhythm of the
music and the happiness or drunkenness of the participators (Fig. 23). Music is
sometimes seen as an erotic symbol: an interesting metaphor of this is Fig. 26, where
a hetaera places an aulos in front of a symposiast’s erected penis.
The symposion is for Plato a place where the younger are to be educated by the
elders with discussion and song. He allows moderate drinking of wine by the ones that
are older, so that they can have the courage to dance and sing in order to pass on their
important knowledge and wisdom from life-experience to the younger.359 He offers a
very idealized picture of the symposion, without the drunkenness, sexual orgies, and
indecent behavior that probably are quite frequent (Fig. 25). He does mention at some
point that if there is a leader at the symposion they might avoid becoming as drunk as
usual and stay away from fights.360
The reason why Plato presents an idealized picture of the symposion has to do
with the fact that he is not describing reality; he is giving an account of how things
should be ideally, according to him. Even when he says he is describing how things
are in his times, he exaggerates and idealizes the past. In the vase paintings there is
drunkenness, erotic games, dancing girls, as well as male and female professional
musicians, all of which are indirectly criticized by Plato and Aristotle.
358
For example see Bundrick 2005 fig. 11, exterior of a cup by the Foundry Painter from c. 480 BC, at
the Toledo Museum of Art, purchased with funds from the Libbey Endowment, Gift of Edward
Drummond Libbey (1964.126).
359
Plato, Laws 666a-d.
360
Plato, Laws 671a-e.
65
education is intended to form citizens with a good ethos, and that in its turn will
contribute to the wellbeing of the polis. On the Douris cup the students are paying
attention to their teachers and to their own music playing. A boy playing the lyra
seems absorbed by the music, for his eyes are just staring into space (Fig. 12, 13). In
another painting, a paidagogos is leaning on his stick to listen carefully (Fig. 14).
These school scenes may be said to visualize the idea of music’s power in the
education of the young, and thus its contribution to the welfare of the city.
From the early fifth century there are scenes of musical performances on the
bema, with aristocrats playing the lyra or kithara: the instrument is a symbol of their
high status, while their pose and garments inspire respect (Fig. 37). Some have their
heads tipped back while playing, a posture that possibly shows how the musician is
affected by the music. One can compare these scenes with Plato’s ideal of musical
contests between the citizens, where the winner will be the one with the best ethical
teachings in his song.
Music is connected with athletic competitions and military marches as well. In
the vase paintings these activities are often accompanied by the aulos or the salpinx.
In the athletic scenes an auletes playing music is very frequent (Fig. 16, 17), in
contrast to Plato’s view of the aulos as a less manly instrument producing strange
effects on people. Maybe it is exactly this stimulating effect of the instrument that is
meant in these paintings. The music helps the athlete to keep the rhythm, encourages
and motivates him. Herodotos talks of the “marching to the sound of pipes and harps
and flutes bass and treble”.361 The importance of good rhythm in battle, especially in
the formation of the hoplites, is infused into the citizens already with the practicing of
war dances, as the pyrrhic.362 Even Plato points out that
We should live out our lives playing at certain pastimes –
sacrificing, singing and dancing – so as to be able to win Heaven’s
favour and to repel our foes and vanquish them in fight.363
Victory songs, such as Pindar’s epinicia, are also part of the athletic
competitions: they praise the winner and inspire others to similar deeds. These songs
become very important and prestigious, since music’s goal is changing; from it being
the inspiration of bravery on the battlefield, music now ”aimed at cultivation for a
361
Herodotos 1.17.
362
Wallace 2004, 262.
363
Plato, Laws 803e.
66
leisured way of life compound of sport and intellectual pleasures, with political
activity as the typical serious pursuit”.364
Dr. Costas Karageorghis, a reader in sport psychology, has studied how
listening to music while exercising can improve one’s training results. Music works as
a motivator, as well as a distraction from negative feelings, as fatigue. The results of
this study show that if one listens to music one enjoys, with a moderate to fast tempo,
depending on the type of exercise, and encouraging lyrics, exercise endurance
increases by up to 20%.365 It can be assumed that in the ancient world music is used
during athletics and in battle for the same reason.
364
Lippman 1964, 62.
365
Kurutz 2008; Science Daily, 2008/10/02: “Jog To The Beat: Music Increases Exercise Endurance
By 15%”.
366
Herodotos 1.132.
367
Seebass 1995, 31.
368
Aeschylus, Suppliant Maidens 678-83.
67
369
Aeschylus, Eumenides 952-5.
370
Danfulani 1996, 36f.
371
For example see LIMC s.v. Mousai 44b, s.v Apollo 696b. There is even a scene in which Apollo is
pictured with a kithara, and the four Muses are holding krotala, in LIMC s.v Mousai 36b.
372
See p. 18 in this essay.
373
Aristotle, Politics 1341a.
374
See p. 18 in this essay.
68
Plato is concerned about the orgiastic and hypnotic power of music. The
passage where he speaks of the calming music of the aulos in the case of the
Bacchants was mentioned above.375 In the Republic he bans the aulos from his ideal
city. He says that one should prefer Apollo and his instruments to Marsyas and his
instruments.376
In the Symposion however, an admiration as well as fear of the aulos and its
effects can actually be discerned: Socrates’ way of enchanting people with words is
compared to the enchanting music of the aulos-player Marsyas.377 Plato speaks of
Marsyas in quite a different tone, admiring his talent:
So that if anyone, whether a fine flute-player or paltry flute-girl,
can but flute his (Marsyas’) tunes, they have no equal for exciting
a ravishment, and will indicate by the divinity that it is in them
who are apt recipients of the deities and their sanctifications.378
It must be emphasized that the aulos plays a very important role in cult rituals
and religious festivals, especially in dramatic contests. In vase scenes with sacrificial
processions and sacrifices the aulos is almost always present (Fig. 42),379 as is the
auletes during a theatrical play (Fig. 38, 41). Even at the symposion, the spondeion
and the paean are sung to the accompaniment of the aulos, something that proves that
the instrument has a serious and ritualistic side to it as well.380
375
See p. 63 in this essay.
376
Plato, Republic 399e.
377
Plato, Symposium 215b-216b.
378
Plato, Symposium 215c.
379
Nordquist 1990, 145f.
380
Bundrick 2005, 81.
381
Price 1999, 12.
69
The written sources on the other hand, although of great importance when
studying the past, offer a one-sided story. They reveal the opinions of their (male)
authors only: Plato comes from the aristocratic class and has aristocratic ideas. He
shows his dislike of the new ways of entertainment at “the wine parties of the
common market-folk” through Socrates in Protagoras.382 Aristophanes complains
about the young people’s disregard of old-fashioned songs and sympotic customs in
his Clouds.383 Unfortunately the written sources from the fifth century concerning
music and its use are limited. The philosophers who are not even contemporary,
present only their own opinions and criticisms. They strive to find the best for society,
and only indirectly, through their criticisms, do they provide information on the real
situation. Aristophanes, though a comedian, probably offers more direct information,
since his comedies include open criticisms of or satires on his contemporaries and the
musical reality of the time. Besides, theatrical plays are directed to a more general
public than the philosophical treatises.
However, the vase paintings cannot be viewed as representations of reality
either. Painting is art, and that means it includes artistic elements controlling the
degree of truth in the representations; the aesthetic pleasure is usually prioritized
before a realistic representation, while it is not rare to encounter idealism, symbolism,
and anachronisms. Thus, the information about what the musical instruments look like
or when, where, and by whom music is played is not always accurate.
On the other hand, the pottery from this period is plentiful and varied. Besides,
all kinds of art are products of the society in which they are created, and are
undoubtedly influenced by and often a representation of it in one way or another. The
vase paintings provide quite a broad picture, including men, women, and children,
higher and lower classes, mythological and historical figures, gods and mortals. By
studying the vases as a whole, through time and in thematic groups, there is a lot to
learn from them; they offer a more complete and varied story than the literary sources.
One can discern broader tendencies, repetitions, similarities, changes, and how themes
become more or less popular through time in the imagery; all this may in fact offer
some of the desirable information.
In addition, the vases are contemporary to the period they represent. The
literary sources on the other hand, are in their majority from a later period. Even in the
382
Plato, Protagoras 347c-d.
383
Aristophanes, Clouds 1353-79.
70
case of Plato and Aristotle, their works are written decades after the time they
describe. Both are subjective and idealistic. Plato and Aristotle, as well as most others
that criticize the New Music, have created an idealized and timeless musical past, in
which music is seen as manly, dignified, and autochthonous, while the New
Musicians are seen as effeminate, vulgar, and bringing influences that are not Greek,
thus degrading music and the Athenian society as a whole.
One of the advantages of literary sources is certainly the fact that they can
express abstract ideas, ideals, and values, such as ‘democracy’, ‘hubris’, and ‘ethos’
for example, with the help of words. This cannot be done in the visual arts; in this
case the artists use symbols, personifications, and myths in order to express and
visualize these, which today can create difficulties in the interpretation.
In general, the two types of sources basically confirm each other, although
there are some contradictions. They are two different types of sources with entirely
different purposes, and the information from them depends precisely on their purpose.
In the case of Plato, a philosopher attempts to create an ideal State, seeking the best
way of ruling it: education of the citizens and strict censorship of anything that harms
their characters is prioritized. His criticism of the actual situation in the Athenian
society can be distinguished and offer indirect information. In the case of the vase
paintings, the aesthetic pleasure decides over the representation. The themes that are
depicted are in one way or another connected to reality, and thus provide information
on the musical life of the time. The way the sources are interpreted is crucial in both
cases, since there is hardly any direct information in either of them. Nevertheless, the
combination of two different types of sources has the advantage of allowing the
information to be crosschecked and offering a more complete picture of reality.
384
As quoted in Frith 2004, 23; quoted from Martin & Seagrove 1988, 53.
385
Washburne & Derno 2004, 5f.
386
Plato, Republic 424c.
387
Plato, Laws 657b-c.
388
Plato, Laws 657d-659a.
389
Plato, Laws 700a-701a.
72
state, which will be disastrous according to Plato.390 However, it appears more likely
that music and the society are in constant interaction. Musical education becomes
accessible to a larger part of the population when democracy is established, while the
musical competitions become panhellenic, and virtuosi musicians come to Athens
from all over the Greek world with their innovations. It seems like the society and the
changes in it influence music more than music could ever influence society.
It is apparent that the transformations in music during the second half of the
fifth century are unlike any earlier, both in the speed that they occur and in their
range. Changes are made on musical instruments, as the adding of strings, allowing
music to become more complex with innovations in melodies and rhythms, at the
same time as professionalism increases. The competitive ambience triggers the
musicians to try out new ways of playing to impress the public, and many become
virtuosi. It is possible that there is less order in public gatherings, given that with the
democratic system they become open to a much larger crowd, something that worries
the aristocratic class.
The critics of New Music seem to connect it to anything that is not good in
democracy during the fifth century. The elite can no longer claim their superiority in
musical knowledge (one of their status symbols being good musical education) since
they are compared to the virtuosi professionals. This specialization and
professionalism is not only discerned in music. Already in the sixth century vase
painters, and later on sculptors, start signing their work.391 From the fifth century
onwards the names of musicians from musical, dramatic, or dithyrambic competitions,
appear in texts, vase paintings, and inscriptions.392 Some examples are the auletes
Antioxos from the beginning of the fifth century, pictured on a vase;393 the famous
auletes Pronomos from the fifth century, who is named in many sources and depicted
on a vase painting;394 the kitharodos Herakleitos Tarantinos who participated in the
wedding celebrations of Alexander the Great in Sousa;395 and the
kitharistes/kitharodos Stratonikos Athenaios, from the first half of the fourth century,
390
Plato, Laws 700d-701b.
391
For more information on signatures and inscriptions on the vases, see Robertson 1992, 3-5, 45f, 186;
Morris 2006, 188.
392
See n. 305 in this essay.
393
Stefanis 1988, 211a.
394
Stefanis 1988, 2149.
395
Stefanis 1988, 1093.
73
396
Stefanis 1988, 2310.
397
Csapo 2004, 236-238.
398
Csapo 2004, 246.
399
About Sparta’s marching song, the embaterion, see Csapo 2004, 241f.
74
400
As for example the transcriptions from Euripides’ plays Orestes and Iphigeneia in Aulis; West 1992,
284-286. For other examples of musical notation see Anderson 1994, 210-227; West 1992, 283-326.
401
See description of Bacchic scenes p. 62f. in this essay.
402
See p. 28f. in this essay.
75
Artemis at Braurona is one of them, in which the girls dress up as bears and
participate in a procession, a race, and a dance.403
Working songs are another kind of music largely neglected by the sources.
They are mentioned in Aristophanes’ Frogs, where the chorus sings to help Dionysos
keep the rhythm while rowing the boat.404 These songs are probably sung during
many types of activities where synchronizing and a good tempo are needed.
Unfortunately only speculations can be made on the nature and use of this music.
Plato’s Symposium shows that women can entertain themselves with music,
when Socrates sends away the professional auletria into the women’s quarters.405
There are even representations of women playing music in domestic settings in the
vase paintings. Nevertheless, it is still uncertain if female Athenian citizens play
music themselves, and if they do, what this music sounds like.
Most likely there is music to all kinds of merry-making and dancing, simple
songs for private celebrations in everyday life, which are not mentioned at all. It is
apparent that certain areas receive less attention from research than others. One of
them is the role of music in private life and the family; another is music in the lower
classes of the society. The reason seems to be the limited information in the ancient
sources, which do not consider these types of music worth noting. The role of music
in lower class families may be very different than in the higher classes. An example is
that, since the poorer families can probably not afford nurses, it is the mother’s duty to
sing the lullabies to the baby and teach the child it’s first songs, so music might play
an important role in forming a tighter bond between them. In addition, in these
families the members have to work harder, so they probably engage more often in the
so-called working songs, which are basically neglected both by the ancient sources
and the modern scholars. Finally, the study of the relation of children to music, in
their games or at school, is also worth deeper research.
It is interesting to make a comparison with what is written by scholars about
music in modern times, even though there is always a risk of applying one’s own
ideas and values anachronistically to a society that existed under totally different
circumstances. Today there is a large amount of studies of classical or liturgical music
403
Price 1999, 90.
404
Aristophanes, Frogs 202-268.
405
Plato, Symposium 177.
76
for instance, while not much is written about popular music.406 It is perhaps a similar
situation in ancient Athens, where more attention is given to the ’higher quality’
music in the philosophical discussions, than to what the people actually listen to and
play themselves. Luckily there are some examples of everyday music from the
comedies, and we can get hints of it from the vase paintings. However, it is doubtful
that the full picture of the world of music in ancient Athens will be revealed, since so
much information is lost or has never been put down on paper.
Carl Dahlhaus’ essays on what he calls “trivial music”, aim at finding the best
way of judging this music aesthetically; he tries to find a balance between the
aesthetic and other powers that are included in the formation of music, as history,
politics, religion, or society. According to Dahlhaus, “low music” exists in all times.
Until the eighteenth century there were three main reasons of contempt against it:
musically, the performers did not follow the rules; morally, they were indecent; and
socially, they came from the lower classes.407 He notes that the criticism of trivial
music “is often based on the idea of a universal, undivided music”.408 The above ideas
bring to mind the contempt that emerges in the aristocratic class against the
professional musicians of the second half of the fifth century in Athens.
However, this musical debate between “high” and “low” quality music
concerns only a very little group of people, while the rest of the society probably finds
it irrelevant. This picture is seen in Classical Athens of the fifth and fourth centuries,
where the musical debate is going on besides the actual musical reality of the time and
the preferences of the people, while the musicians continue making innovations, in
spite of the criticism they receive.
406
Lately there has been an increased interest in the study of popular art forms. Some examples are
Stahl 2004; Rodel 2004; Ganetz 2008.
407
Dalhaus 2004, 336.
408
Dalhaus 2004, 350.
77
In Old Norse literature there is a belief that music has magical power, and
according to the mode the musician plays he can induce any emotion he wishes to the
listener.412 There is even a certain war song, its purpose being “to incite men’s
fighting spirits before a battle”.413
Many scholars have been interested in studying contemporary uses of music in,
amongst others, African and Australian tribes or Brazilian communities. There are
certain tribes in Nigeria for example, where music and dance play an important role in
the religious life of the people. During special festivals, it is through music they
believe they come into contact with their dead ancestors.414
In the Afro-Brazilian Macumba community in Salvador, Brazil, the members
have been able to communicate and keep their traditions alive through their religious
and social rituals and their “deep symbols of music and dance”, regardless of the
inhuman treatment they received as slaves of the white. The Portuguese colonists
perceived their music and dancing as pure entertainment, while in reality it was a way
of communicating and giving energy.415 Ritual trance is also used in these
communities, in order to come in contact with the gods for advice on problems or
needs of the members. The mediums, which are priests or priestesses, manage to
409
Sarjala 2001, 11.
410
Sarjala 2001, 15.
411
Sarjala 2001, 5.
412
Näsström 1996, 232.
413
Näsström 1996, 233.
414
Danfulani 1996, 36f.
415
Demarinis 1996, 62.
78
come into a state of trance with the help of special rhythms, movements and drum-
beating patterns.416
The AMUSE (Appraisal in Music and Emotion) project, organized by Uppsala
University, aims at creating a model of psychological mechanisms that will be able to
explain and predict people’s responses to music. The results can even be used in the
application of music therapy. Patrik Juslin is a member of the above research team
and in his thesis concludes that the music performers are able to communicate
emotions to listeners with the use of certain cues, as tempo, sound level, articulation,
and spectrum, by both the performers and the listeners, as a sort of nonverbal code.
This process of communicating emotions can even be improved, according to Juslin,
who suggests possible ways for the performers to become better in this procedure.417
What Juslin notes, however, is that his studies can be criticized with the argument
that, even though the listeners are probably not used to making precise judgments of
emotional expressions in music, they are often exposed to it in daily life418 and, of
course, are already familiar to Western music.
The most recent study on how music communicates emotions is published in
March 2009 and chooses another approach. A team led by cognitive scientist Thomas
Fritz of the Max Planck Institute for Human Cognitive and Brain Sciences in Leipzig,
Germany, studies how the Mafa farmer’s in Cameroon, Africa, interpret various types
of music. Two things are noteworthy before giving the results of this experiment: first,
the Mafa do not have a separate word for music; music is seen as an important
ingredient in their rituals, but never independently. Second, the music of this people
only ever expresses joy and happiness. What is important for Fritz is to find a group
of people that have never come in contact with Western music before, and the Mafa
have not. He tests one group of Mafa people and one group of Germans, giving them
various melodies to listen to, and then guess what kind of emotions they express. The
results of the study are that music seems to have a universal way of expressing
emotions, such as happiness, sadness, and fear. A second result is that melodies that
are consonant are more pleasurable to listen to for both groups, while the digital
modifications of these melodies into dissonant are not perceived as pleasurable at all.
416
Demarinis 1996, 71.
417
Juslin 1998, 44.
418
Juslin 1998, 45.
79
This finding provides thus, the first solid evidence for a universal human ability to
distinguish basic emotions in music.419
Just as in the scenes of Orpheus, Apollo, and mortals, where the music is
enchanting its listeners, and similarly to the literary sources of Classical Athens,
modern studies also engage in the understanding of the power of music over the soul
and the body. The ritual trance and the ecstatic condition that the Bacchants reach
with music and dance is observed in other cultures as well, not only in Africa and
South America, but even in the Western world, in the form of rave parties for
instance. As mentioned earlier, even the presence of music during athletics and
battles, both in the imagery and the literary sources, could be paralleled with modern
studies of the usefulness of listening to music while exercising. The intention with
mentioning the above studies is to point out that what the philosophers in Classical
Athens are concerned about is not something unique. Music has certain universal
characteristics that exist in many different cultures. Music is one of the most common
ways of communicating emotions, ideas, and values, and the power of music over
one’s behavior and feelings is something that will arouse excitement, wonder, and
curiosity long into the future, given that after 2500 years it is still a subject of modern
research.
419
Bower 2009.
80
7. CONCLUSIONS
As demonstrated in the previous chapters, although the vase paintings may in certain
cases contradict the literature, most of the times they confirm and even go beyond the
information in the literary sources, giving a more complete picture of the world of
music. Nevertheless, both types of sources must be approached critically, since
neither of them aim at a realistic description of music and its use in Classical Athens.
Different types of sources have different purposes. Plato is creating an ideal
State; Aristophanes and the other comedians criticize society in a humoristic way; and
the vase painters are at the service of a large group of people, decorating vases for
religious or everyday use, and aiming at an aesthetically pleasant result. The purpose
of each source should always be taken into account. A combination of sources, and
especially of different types of sources, has the advantage of allowing crosschecking
of the information and of offering a broader picture of the past. No single source
presents the entire picture of musical life in Athens, but they give evidence of the
attitudes and feelings towards music, both its intellectual and emotional side. All
sources suggest that music plays an important role in the ancient Greeks’ lives and
causes an intense debate.
The extensive reaction towards the New Music during the fifth century BC in
Athens is an example of the constant struggle between the conservative and the
progressive groups of a society. It is not the first time innovations are made in music:
music certainly undergoes changes before the fifth century and continues to do so
after it; the New Music is probably not as extreme and dangerous as presented in the
sources. Nonetheless, the changes of this specific period are most likely greater than
any time before. They are a consequence of the vast changes in the Athenian society
of the fifth and fourth centuries, with the establishment of democracy, and the
accessibility of music to a much broader audience. New Music becomes associated
with a modernity many do not approve of. Music in general is part of the political and
social life of Athens and is included in a broader political debate between the extreme
democrats and the traditional oligarchs. Plato seems to be trying in his dialogues to
bring stability back into the changing society of his time, by reorganizing the musical
education of the citizens and censuring the arts.
It seems very likely that, even though the criticisms of New Music gain an
important place in theory, they hardly influence the actual practitioners of it.
Innovations continue to take place in the world of music, as in every other aspect of
81
420
Polybius 4.20.8-9.
82
The concerns of the philosophers and musical theorists of Classical Athens are
not unique. Music has certain universal characteristics seen in many different cultures.
It is one of the most celebrated forms of art, for its ability to communicate emotions,
ideas, and values. The power of music has been concerning people in all times and
modern research continues to study music’s effects on one’s behavior and feelings.
The musical debate that takes place in Classical Athens is not unique either. Even if
the circumstances are very different, there is an ongoing debate concerning the quality
of music still today. Since the categorizing of art into “good” and “bad” is subjective,
a culturally conscious society with freedom of speech will always be prone to debates.
It is these debates and the continuous discussion and questioning that keep the cultural
life vibrant.
83
GLOSSARY
Aoidos: epic singer; very often poet-composer-singer421.
Auletes: aulos player.
Auletris and auletria: female aulos-player; often a professional engaged to play at
banquets.
Aulodos: performer on the aulos who is accompanied by a singer422.
Aulos: wind instrument of which the main body was a pipe of reed with a number of
fingerholes.
Barbitos or barbiton: stringed instrument, a narrower and longer variety of the lyra.
Chelys: tortoise. The earlier type of lyra was called a chelys-lyra called because its
sound-box was a tortoise-shell.
Chiton: tunic worn next to the skin423.
Choreia: (in Plato) choir-training.
Chorus: dance; choir; the chorus of the ancient drama.
Cymbala: percussion instrument consisting of two hollow hemispheric metal plates.
Demos: the people, the inhabitants; the common people424.
Dithyrambos: a lyric song of an enthusiastic character in honor of Dionysus.
Emmeleia: the dance of the chorus in ancient tragedy, distinguished by its lofty,
dignified and restrained character.
Epinikion melos: a song praising a victory in war or in a musical or athletic contest.
Eunomia: good order or good custom425.
Eukosmia: orderly behavior, good conduct, decency426.
Harmonia: in music it indicates the octave, and the different disposition of the notes in
a system with its parts adjusted so as to form a perfect ensemble.
Heterophonia: diversity of note427.
Himation: an outer garment worn above the chiton428.
Homophonia: the unison of note.
Hubris: arrogance and excessive pride, especially in the face of the gods429.
Hymenaeos: a nuptial or bridal song, sung by the bride’s friends on her way from her
parents' house to that of the bridegroom.
Hyporchema: song and dance in honor of Apollo.
421
All explanations of the Greek terms are found in Michaelides 1978, if not noted otherwise.
422
Bundrick 2005, 239.
423
Liddell-Scott 1996 s.v. chiton.
424
Liddell-Scott 1996 s.v. demos.
425
Bundrick 2005, 239.
426
Liddell-Scott 1996 s.v. eukosmia.
427
Liddell-Scott 1996 s.v. heterophonia.
428
Liddell-Scott 1996 s.v. himation.
429
Bundrick 2005, 239.
84
430
Liddell-Scott 1996 s.v. sophrosyne.
431
Bundrick 2005, 240.
85
LIST OF ILLUSTRATIONS
Fig. 1: Exterior side of a cup by the Brygos Painter with followers of Dionysos; c.
490-480 BC. Paris, Bibliotèque Nationale, Cabinet des Médailles (576). Photo:
Bibliotèque Nationale de France. After Bundrick 2005 fig. 63.
Fig. 2: Interior side of a cup by the Brygos Painter with Dionysos and satyrs; c. 490-
480 BC. Paris, Bibliotèque Nationale, Cabinet des Médailles (576). Photo:
Bibliotèque Nationale de France. After Bundrick 2005 fig. 62.
Fig. 3: Attic red-figure krater by the Retorted Painter, with Dionysos and his
entourage. Toronto, Royal Ontario Museum, 919 V 13.21. – Photo: Museum. ARV
1490/13. After Nordquist 1995 fig. 4.
Fig. 4: Stamnos by Smikros with symposion; c. 510-500 BC. Brussels, Royal
Museums of Art and History (A 717). Photo: Museum. After Bundrick 2005 fig. 68.
Fig. 5: Cup by the Painter of Louvre G 265 with death of Orpheus; c. 480-470 BC.
Cincinnati Art Museum, John J. Emery, William W. Taylor, Robert S. Dechant, and
Israel and Caroline Wilson Endowments (1979.1). Photo: Museum. After Bundrick
2005 71.
Fig. 6: Orpheus playing the lyra while Thracian men listen. Berlin, Antikenmuseum,
3172, front side. – Photo after Fyrtwängler 1890: pl. II. After Seebass 1995 fig.5.
Fig. 7: Apulian hydria with the myth of Thamyris. Palermo, Banco di Sicilia, 385.
Photo after Immerwahr, Henry R. “More book rolls on Attic vases.” Antike Kunst 16,
1973: pl. 33,2. After Voutira 1995 fig. 4.
Fig. 8: Red figure bell-krater with Marsyas playing the aulos; Paris, Louvre, G 490. –
Photo: Museum. ARV 1190,21. After Voutira 1995 fig. 10.
Fig. 9: Apulian pelike with Apollo playing the lyra and Marsyas holding the aulos; c.
420 BC. Naples, Museo Archeologico Nazionale, 3231. – Photo: Museum. After
Voutira 1995 fig. 8.
Fig. 10: Red figure bell-krater with Marsyas playing the lyra. Heidelberg, Ruprecht-
Karls-Universität, Archäologishces Institut, 208. Photo: Museum. ARV 1189,19. After
Voutira 1995 fig. 11.
Fig. 11: Red figure cup with a woman choosing the lyra rather than the aulos.
Bologna, Museo Civico Archeologico, PU 271. – Photo after CVA, Bologna, Museo
Civico, III I pl. 118. After Voutira 1995 fig. 12.
Fig. 12, 13: Cup by Douris with school scene, c. 490-480 BC. Antikensammlung,
Staatliche Museen zu Berlin, Preussischer Kulturbesitz (F 2285). Photo: Bildarchiv
Preussischer Kulturbesitz/Art Resource, NY. After Bundrick 2005 fig. 1, 2.
Fig. 14: Hydria by Phintias with instruction in lyra playing; c. 510-500 BC. Munich,
Staatliche Antikensammlungen und Glyptothek (2421). Photo: Museum. After
Bundrick 2005 fig. 35.
Fig. 15: Hydria by the Painter of the Yale Oinochoe with the judgment of Paris.
London The British Museum E 178. ARV 503,20. After Boardman 1989 fig. 34.
Fig. 16: Unattributed hydria with diskos thrower, athlete with javelin, trainer, and
aulos player; c. 510-500 BC. London, The British Museum (E 164). Photo: The
British Museum. After Bundrick 2005 fig. 47.
86
Fig. 17: Unattributed hydria with pyrrhic dance, including aulos player; c. 500 BC.
New York, The Metropolitan Museum of Art, Rogers Fund, 1921 (21.88.2). Photo:
The Metropolitan Museum of Art. After Bundrick 2005 fig. 48.
Fig. 18: Red figure cup by the Brygos Painter with young symposiast singing a
skolion and holding a bough of myrtle; c. 480. Florence, 3949; ARV 376/90. After
Lissarrague 1990 fig. 99.
Fig. 19: Red figure cup with symposiast singing; c. 490. Athens, MN1357. After
Lissarrague 1990 fig. 102.
Fig. 20: Red figure kalathos by the Brygos Painter with Alkaios and Sappho; c. 470
BC. Munich, 2416; ARV 385/228. After Lissarrague 1990 fig. 95.
Fig. 21: Red figure amphora with lyre player singing; c. 520 BC. Paris, Louvre G 30;
ARV 15/9. After Lissarrague 1990 fig. 103.
Fig. 22: Red figure cup with symposion scene, where the symposiasts are playing a
game with the cups; c. 490 BC. Private collection; M. Vickers, Greek Symposia
(London, n.d.), fig. 17, p. 15. After Lissarrague 1990 fig. 68.
Fig. 23: Stamnos by the Chicago Painter with man dancing and woman with krotala.
Cape Town, South African Museum H 4810. J. Boardman and M. Pope, Greek Vases
in Cape Town (1961) no. 14. After Boardman 1989 fig. 27.
Fig. 24: Hydria by Polygnotos with acrobats, musicians, and dancers. Naples, Museo
Archeologico Nazionale, 3232, from Nola. ARV 1032,61. After Boardman 1989 fig.
138.
Fig. 25: Black figure oenochoe by Kleisophos with revelers in a komos; c. 530 BC.
Athens National Museum, 1045. ABV 186. After Lissarrague 1990 fig. 77.
Fig. 26: Amphora by the Kleophrades Painter with revelers, including woman with
aulos; c. 500-490 BC. Martin-von-Wagner Museum der Universität Würzburg (L
507). Photo: Museum (K. Oehrlein). After Bundrick 2005 fig.70.
Fig. 27: Bell krater by the Danae Painter with Apollo and Muses; c. 440-430 BC
Vienna, Kunsthistorisches Museum (IV 697). Photo: Museum. After Bundrick 2005
fig. 25.
Fig. 28: Neck amphora by the Peleus Painter with Mousaios and the Muses Melousa
and Terpsichore. London, The British Museum E 271, from Vulci. ARV 1039,13.
After Boardman 1989 fig. 144.
Fig. 29: Lykethos by the Achilles Painter with Muses on Helicon. Munich, Schoen 80,
from Greece. ARV 997,155. After Boardman 1989 fig. 262.
Fig. 30: Bell krater by the Danae Painter with women playing barbitos and listeners;
c. 440-430 BC. New York , The Metropolitan Museum of Art, Rogers Fund, 1923
(23.160.80). Photo: The metropolitan Museum of Art. After Bundrick 2005 fig. 59.
Fig. 31: Red figure hydria with women in domestic setting; c. 450 BC. Switzerland,
private collection. – Photo: D. Widmer, Basel. After Voutira 1995 fig. 5.
Fig. 32: White-ground lekythos by the Achilles Painter with woman, playing
phorminx, and companion; c. 460-450 BC. Stockholm, National Museum (G 2107).
Photo: Deutsches Archäologisches Institut, Athens (neg. Athen Varia 699). After
Bundrick 2005 fig.60.
87
Fig. 33: White-ground lekythos from Gela by the Achilles Painter: one woman sitting
with a kithara, the other standing with the lyra. Oxford, Ashmoelan Museum,
1889.1016. – Photo: Museum. Beazley ARV: 1000.195. After Seebass 1995 fig. 24.
Fig. 34: Stamnos by the Chicago Painter with women celebrating a ritual before an
image of Dionysos, a so-called Lenaia-scene; c. 450 BC. San Antonio Museum of Art,
Gift of Gilbert M. Denman, Jr. (86.134.64). Photo: Courtesy of San Antonio Museum
of Art. After Bundrick 2005 fig.93.
Fig. 35: Volute krater attributed to the Group of Polygnotos with cult procession
before two seated divinities; c. 440-430 BC. Ferrara, Museo Archeologico Nazionale
di Spina (2897/T 128). Photo: Scala/Art Resource, NY. After Bundrick 2005 fig.94.
Fig. 36: Lebes gamikos by the Washing Painter with women preparing for a wedding,
the bride playing the harp, and Eros, c. 430-420. New York, The Metropolitan
Museum of Art, Rogers Fund, 1916, 16.73. ARV 1126,6. After Boardman 1989 fig.
207; Bundrick 2005 fig. 19. Photo: The Metropolitan Museum of Art.
Fig. 37: Pelike by the Pan Painter with kithara player mounting a bema; c. 480-470
BC. New York, Solow Art and Architecture Foundation. Photo: Foundation. After
Bundrick 2005 fig. 98.
Fig. 38: Drawing of volute krater by the Pronomos Painter with theatrical scene and
the auletes Pronomos in the centre; c. 400 BC. Naples, Museo Archeologico
Nazionale (81673/H3240). Photo: Deutsches Archäologisches Institut, Rome (neg.
69.176). After Bundrick 2005 fig. 102.
Fig. 39: Bell krater by the Villa Giulia Painter with Apollo, Artemis, and Leto; c. 460-
450 BC. New York, The Metropolitan Museum of Art, Fletcher Fund, 1924
(24.97.96). Photo: The metropolitan Museum of Art. After Bundrick 2005 fig. 85.
Fig. 40: Stamnos by the Villa Giulia Painter with Apollo and the Muses. Oxford,
Ashmolean Museum, 524. ARV 620,30. After Boardman 1989 fig. 23.
Fig. 41: Unattributed calyx krater with comic scene; c. 415-410 BC. Malibu, CA, The
J. Paul Getty Museum (82.AE.83). Photo: Copyright The J. Paul Getty Museum. After
Bundrick 2005 fig. 101.
Fig. 42: Stamnos by Polygnotos with roasting of sacrificial meat; c. 440 BC. London,
The British Museum (E 455). Photo: Copyright The British Museum. After Bundrick
2005 fig. 90.
88
89
ILLUSTRATIONS
Fig. 1. Exterior side of a cup by the Brygos Painter with followers of Dionysos.
Fig. 2. Interior side of a cup by the Brygos Painter with Dionysos and satyrs.
90
Fig. 3. Attic red-figure krater by the Retorted Painter, with Dionysos and his entourage.
91
Fig. 9. Apulian pelike with Apollo playing the lyra and Marsyas holding the aulos.
94
Fig. 10. Red figure bell-krater with Marsyas playing the lyra.
Fig. 11. Red figure cup with a woman choosing the lyra rather than the aulos.
95
Fig. 15. Hydria by the Painter of the Yale Oinochoe with the judgment of Paris.
97
Fig. 16. Unattributed hydria with diskos thrower, athlete with javelin, trainer, and aulos player.
Fig. 17. Unattributed hydria with pyrrhic dance, including aulos player.
98
Fig. 18. Red figure cup by the Brygos Painter with young symposiast singing a skolion and holding a
bough of myrtle.
Fig. 20. Red figure kalathos by the Brygos Painter with Alkaios and Sappho.
Fig. 22. Red figure cup with symposion scene, where the symposiasts are playing a game with the cups.
Fig. 23. Stamnos by the Chicago Painter with man dancing and woman with krotala.
101
Fig. 26. Amphora by the Kleophrades Painter with revelers, including woman with aulos.
103
Fig. 27. Bell krater by the Danae Painter with Apollo and Muses.
Fig. 28. Neck amphora by the Peleus Painter with Mousaios and the Muses Melousa and Terpsichore.
104
Fig. 30. Bell krater by the Danae Painter with women playing barbitos and listeners.
105
Fig. 32. White-ground lekythos by the Achilles Painter with woman, playing phorminx, and
companion.
107
Fig. 33. White-ground lekythos from Gela by the Achilles Painter: one woman sitting with a kithara,
the other standing with the lyra.
108
Fig. 34. Stamnos by the Chicago Painter with women celebrating a ritual before an image of Dionysos,
a so-called Lenaia-scene.
109
Fig. 35. Volute krater attributed to the Group of Polygnotos with cult procession before two seated
divinities.
Fig. 36. Lebes gamikos by the Washing Painter with women preparing for a wedding, the bride playing
the harp, and Eros.
110
Fig. 37. Pelike by the Pan Painter with kithara player mounting a bema.
Fig. 38. Drawing of volute krater by the Pronomos Painter with theatrical scene and the auletes
Pronomos in the centre.
111
Fig. 39. Bell krater by the Villa Giulia Painter with Apollo, Artemis, and Leto.
Fig. 40. Stamnos by the Villa Giulia Painter with Apollo and the Muses.
112
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Ancient sources
Aeschylus, Eumenides Aeschylus, Eumenides, Loeb, transl. Herbert
Weir Smyth, London (1926) 1971.
Aeschylus, Suppliant Maidens Aeschylus, Suppliant Maidens, Loeb, transl.
Hebert Weir Smyth, London (1922) 1952.
Apollodorus Apollodorus, The Library, Loeb, transl. Sir
James George Frazer, London 1921.
Aristophanes, Birds Aristophanes, The Birds, Loeb, transl. B.B.
Rogers, London (1924) 1968.
Aristophanes, Clouds Aristophanes, The Clouds, Loeb, transl. B.B.
Rogers, London (1924) 1967.
Aristophanes, Frogs Aristophanes, The Frogs, Loeb, transl. B.B.
Rogers, London (1924) 1968.
Aristophanes, Wasps Aristophanes, The Wasps, Loeb, transl. B.B.
Rogers, London (1924) 1967.
Aristophanes, Lysistrata Aristophanes, The Lysistrata, Loeb, transl.
B.B. Rogers, London (1924) 1972.
Aristophanes, Ecclesiazusae Aristophanes, The Ecclesiazusae, Loeb,
transl. B.B. Rogers, London (1924) 1972.
Aristotle, Athenian Constitution Aristotle, The Athenian Constitution, Loeb,
transl. H. Rackham, London (1952) 1971.
Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics Aristotle, The Nicomachean Ethics, Loeb,
transl. H. Rackham, London (1947) 1968.
Aristotle, Politics Aristotle, Politics, Loeb, transl. H. Rackham,
London (1932) 1972.
Aristotle, Poetics Aristotle, The Poetics, Loeb, transl. W.
Hamilton Fyfe, London (1932) 1982.
Aristotle, Rhetoric Aristotle, The ”Art” of Rhetoric, Loeb,
transl. John Henry Freese, London (1926)
1967.
(Pseudo-) Aristotle, Problems (Pseudo-) Aristotle, Problems, Loeb, transl.
W. S. Hett, London (1936) 1961.
Athenaeus Athenaeus, The Deipnosophists, Loeb,
transl. Charles Burton Gulick, London
(1927) 1959.
Herodotos Herodotos, The Histories, Loeb, transl. A. D.
Godley, London (1920) 1981.
114
Modern sources
Anderson 1966 D. Warren Anderson, Ethos and education
in Greek music, Harvard, Mass., 1966.
Anderson 1994 D. Warren Anderson, Music and musicians
in ancient Greece, New York 1994.
ARV J. D. Beazley, Attic Red-Figure Vase-
paintings, 1956.
ABV J. D. Beazley, Attic Black-Figure Vase-
paintings (second edition) 1963.
Barker 1984 Andrew Barker, Greek musical writings. The
musician and his art, Cambridge 1984.
Boardman 1975 John Boardman, Athenian red figure vases.
The archaic period, London 1975.
Boardman 1989 John Boardman, Athenian red figure vases.
The classical period, London 1989.
Bundrick 2005 Sheramy D. Bundrick, Music and image in
classical Athens, Cambridge 2005.
Comotti 1989 Giovanni Comotti, Music in Greek and
Roman culture, London 1979 (English
transl. 1989).
Csapo 2004 Eric Csapo, ‘The politics of the New Music’,
in Music and the Muses. The culture of
Mousike in the Classical Athenian city, ed.
Penelope Murray & Peter Wilson, Oxford
2004, 207-248.
CVA Corpus Vasorum Antiquorum
Dahlhaus 2004 Carl Dahlhaus, ‘Trivial Music
(Trivialmusik). ‘Preface’ and ‘Trivial Music
and aesthetic judgement’’, in Bad music. The
music we love to hate, ed. Washburne, J.
Christopher & Derno Maiken, New York
2004, 333-362.
Danfulani 1996 Umar H. D. Danfulani, ‘Rituals as dance and
dance as rituals’, in Dance, music, art, and
religion, ed. Ahlbäck Tore, Åbo 1996, 27-
57.
Demarinis 1996 Valerie Demarinis, ‘With dance and drum’,
in Dance, music, art, and religion, ed.
Ahlbäck Tore, Åbo 1996, 59-74.
Dowden 1992 Ken Dowden, The uses of Greek mythology,
London 1992.
Frith 2004 Simon Frith, ‘What is Bad Music?’ in Bad
music. The music we love to hate, ed.
116
Internet sources
Science Daily (Oct. 2, 2008) “Jog To The Beat: Music Increases Exercise Endurance
By 15%”, at: http://www.sciencedaily.com/releases/2008/10/081001093753.htm
(24/04/09)