Attending To Reality Iris Murdoch
Attending To Reality Iris Murdoch
Attending To Reality Iris Murdoch
UDK: 224.5:227.87:22.06
Izvorni znanstveni članak
Pripremljen u ožujku 2013.
ATTENDING TO REALITY:
IRIS MURDOCH ON THE MORAL GOOD
Ante Jerončić
Andrews University, Michigan, USA
SUMMARY:
1 Profound thanks go to the friends and colleagues whose feedback made an invaluable contribution to the
thinking in this article: L. Monique Pittman, Karl Bailey, and Vanessa Corredera. I also owe a debt of grati-
tude to my research assistant Mercedes McLean who labored with me in correcting and clarifying the final
draft.
Iris Murdoch, Metaphysics as a Guide to Morals (New York: Penguin, 1993), 14.
101
Ante Jerončić: Attending to reality - Biblijski pogledi, 21 (1-2), 101-114 (2013.)
dingly, result in a double remove of ethics: from the structure of reality on the hand and from
human existence and accounts of human flourishing on the other. In order to interrogate these
issues at a greater length, I will briefly turn to Iris Murdoch’s moral philosophy in order to exa-
mine how her specific form of ethical realism addresses such claims about ethics. Despite some
reservations about the cogency of her approach, I will argue that her basic intuition to connect
morality with the wider realm of meaning and accounts of human flourishing is indispensable
for any theological account of the humanization of life.
Key words: Iris Murdoch; metaphysics; ethical realism; the moral good; human flourishing
102
Ante Jerončić: Attending to reality - Biblijski pogledi, 21 (1-2), 101-114 (2013.)
according to whom he notion of justice is incompatible with the pursuit of self-interest, while
yet others see him as an ethical nihilist whose project is to show that justice does not exist. On
that count, he fills the role of a proto-postmodernist of sorts.
Unfortunately, a detailed assessment of Thrasymachus is beyond the scope of this article.
My goal here, rather, is to posit this enigmatic figure as an archetype for two distinct yet in-
terrelated claims about the nature of ethics: “Morality is dangerous!” and “Morality is a hu-
man construct!” The first pertains to the function of moral claims, of what they do and how
they are being used, while the second addresses their origin and status. Much of the current
disenchantment with morality, both intellectual and practical, pertains to one or the other of
these two aspects—function and status. In respect to function, we see Thrasymachus standing
as a progenitor for a whole array of thinkers, who like him contend that the categories of right
and wrong, at least frequently so, are not so much rooted in reality as surreptitiously wielded
to achieve assorted power interests. What they propose as a counter-move are various forms
of genealogical and archaeological undertakings, that is, procedures for unmasking by which
the real sources of morality, including such matters as moral obligation and conscience, are
purportedly revealed.
Susan Neiman in her Moral Clarity addresses some of these reservations concerning the
unequivocal beneficence of moral discourse, especially when presented in a universalist or
objectivist form.5 In our contemporary culture, most people harbor, justifiably so, deep sus-
picions about any notion of, well, “moral clarity.” One could point to multiple instances from
both the current and previous US administrations, she notes, in order to illustrate that. How
can one forget the chilling dualism of the “axis of evil” and “us vs. them” rhetoric, or the moral
legitimations of extrajudicial killings, or perhaps the way moral self-righteousness about one’s
place in the world exuded a normalizing and ideological effect concerning the most inhuman
of practices—torture. While these are exhibits from our more immediate past, the problem,
of course, is much broader. Anyone knowing anything about 19th and 20th century history, in
other words, anyone knowing anything about colonialism, fascism, and communism, knows
about the capacity of evil to cloak itself in universalist discourse. It is not surprising then given
such and other specimens that we are apprehensive about anyone claiming to know what mo-
rality is and what moral judgments deserve the level of universal normativity. After all, isn’t the
language of moral clarity quite reminiscent of the sort of doublespeak that populates Orwell’s
1984?
There is also a subtler attack on the function of morality, one that casts it as an impediment
for human self-realization and authenticity. On this count, “fulfillment is not defined in terms
of obedience to social roles, cultural ideals, or the perfection of a certain set of virtues. It is
defined with respect to enhancing the richness and complexity of a person’s life.”6 Accordingly,
any account of ethics that runs against such aspirations becomes highly problematized. Such
misgivings come in different forms, ranging from the virulent anguish of Nietzsche’s Dionysian
piety, to postcolonial and poststructuralist suspicion of essentialist discourse, to James Joyce’s
5 See Susan Neiman, Moral Clarity: A Guide for Grown-up Idealists (Orlando: Harcourt, 2008).
6 William Schweiker, Responsibility and Christian Ethics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), 12.
103
Ante Jerončić: Attending to reality - Biblijski pogledi, 21 (1-2), 101-114 (2013.)
libidinal celebration of the bodily as found in his poem “The Holy Office.”7 They also inform
current ethical debates in the Adventist faith community, at least occasionally, where anecdotal
narratives, personal experiences, and other forms of affective reasoning are invested with the
weight of a moral arbiter, as if the depth of pathos directly correlates to ethical normativity. The
very idea that empathy might in some instances itself be implicated in structures and acts of
injustice is often lost in the shuffle.
The issue of the function of moral claims, of what they do and what they intend, inevitably
relates to the matter of their origin and status, the second area of concern mentioned above.
For Thrasymachus, we recall, justice is spurious precisely because it is arbitrary and reflective
of subjective interests and preferences. Here too Thrasymachus stands for a venerable stream
of thinking about the nature of moral obligations, one that ties them to constructivist impul-
ses. In view of this, ethical statements are expressions of individual or collective preferences,
feelings, or prejudices stripped of any object-given normativity— “object-given” referring to
the moral realist claim that the good resides outside of us. While there are different varieties of
constructivism, they all have in common the view that “moral reality is constructed from the
states or activities. . . undertaken from a preferred standpoint.”8 You take it away, however that
standpoint might be conceived, and you have taken away morality. Thus a subjectivist, to name
one example of constructivism, will readily claim that individual tastes and opinions are the
things which construct moral reality. In sum, moral constructivism echoes “J. L. Mackie’s con-
tention that ‘values are not objective, are not part of the fabric of the world.’ In other words, we
do not discover moral truths as traditional realism held, by examining human life, the nature
of communities, or reality; we invent them.”9 Instead of being a matter of mimesis, then, ethics
more properly inhabits to the sphere of creative vitality and agon. William Schweiker writes:
The problem we face in ethics is then that the ground of value has shifted from being to
power, or, more precisely put, being itself, the source of value, is conceived in terms of power.
Seeing this shift does not entail jettisoning metaphysical questions from ethics. It is not to
champion will over mind, doing over being. But it is to realize that the metaphysical dimension
of ethics has also shifted. The modern world no longer sees nature as creation or the human
as created in the image of God. We no longer dwell in the classic, mimetic universe wherein
persons and things derived their value from a place in the system of being.10
Christian Smith’s Lost in Transition offers a great study on the preponderance of such su-
bjectivist sentiments in contemporary culture.11 The conclusions of the book are based on a
7 See Martha C. Nussbaum, Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of Emotions (New York: Cambridge Uni-
versity Press, 2001), 683.
8 Russ Shafer-Landau, Moral Realism: A Defence (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005), 14. He also adds:
“Realists believe that. . . the moral standards that fix the moral facts are not made true by virtue of their
ratification from within any given actual or hypothetical perspective. That a person takes a particular attitude
toward a putative moral standard is not what makes the standard correct” (15).
9 Schweiker, Responsibility and Christian Ethics, 107.
10 William Schweiker, “The Sovereignty of God’s Goodness,” in Iris Murdoch and the Search for Human
Goodness, ed. Maria Antonaccio and William Schweiker (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1996),
217-218.
11 Christian Smith et al., Lost in Transition: The Dark Side of Emerging Adulthood (New York: Oxford Univer-
104
Ante Jerončić: Attending to reality - Biblijski pogledi, 21 (1-2), 101-114 (2013.)
series of in-depth interviews that Smith and his team of the researchers have conducted with
a cross-section of American youth. In it we repeatedly encounter images of individuals gro-
ping for a coherent language to express their values in the context of today’s society marked
by consumerist capitalism and rampant individualism. One cannot but squirm observing
the inability of most participants to use any sort of coherent moral language. While most of
them agree that sexual violence and capital murder ought to be condemned, they have a hard
time pinning down why exactly cheating, for example, is unethical. Even more troublesome,
in my view, is the tendency to continually fall back on how one feels about things, as if this
sphere of “common sense” or “innate feelings” was a pristine source of normative authority
somehow untouched by power constellations, ideological claims, and other processes of so-
cialization.
What is so eerie about this study is the extent to which it mirrors my experience of teaching
ethics to Adventist college students. I am often surprised to see how otherwise conservative
individuals who believe in the primacy of Scripture channel such subjectivist sentiments about
the status of moral judgments. Their whole moral understanding usually boils down to quoting
the perennial favorite “Do not judge, and you shall not be judged” in order to support their
contention that any apportioning of moral blame is immoral in itself. Even after weeks of dis-
cussion and lecturing most students still have a hard time to distinguish between condemning
and judging (in the sense of moral deliberation), inevitably conflating the two. And even when
faced with stock examples of human rights violations such as female genital mutilation, or the
fact that the very concept of forgiveness does not make sense in the absence of moral judgment,
the subjectivist reflex hardly recedes.
So far, then, I have briefly attended to two main objections leveled against ethics in con-
temporary society. I have noted how misgivings about the function of ethics, i.e. the way we
use claims of moral obligation, correlate to our understanding of its status and origin. As a
result, morality frequently faces a double remove: first, from the structure of reality; and second,
from human existence and accounts of human flourishing. In order to interrogate these issues
at a greater length, I will briefly turn to Iris Murdoch’s ethical realism. Despite reservations
concerning some of her substantial claims, some of which I will address at the end of this ar-
ticle, I find considerable appreciation for key intuitions marking her philosophical approach.
I think “intuitions” is the right word here, as I have in mind certain generalized affinities that
are congenial to my own biblical and theological sensibilities: her articulation and defense of
metaphysical ethics, her realist and cognitivist moral ontology, and her efforts to present a
“philosophy of life” aiming at moral conversion. Part of such overlapping concerns pertains to
the fact that Platonists and Christians “seek a good which transcends the self but which never-
theless accords or resonates with the self.”12 Thus my interest in exploring Iris Murdoch. Again,
not that I need her to legitimize my commitment to the objectivity of moral value—the Bible
with its theistic framework is quite capable of doing that—but in order to express a gesture of
hospitable rapprochement, one that scours for commonalities and resonances for the purpose
of dialogue and fostering of “alliances.”
105
Ante Jerončić: Attending to reality - Biblijski pogledi, 21 (1-2), 101-114 (2013.)
106
Ante Jerončić: Attending to reality - Biblijski pogledi, 21 (1-2), 101-114 (2013.)
That, in turn, leads to two related assertions. First, Murdoch rejects the proverbial fact/
value distinction according to which statements of value cannot rise to the level of truth cla-
ims. In A. J. Ayer’s famous version of the argument, “the meaning of a statement is determined
by the way in which it can be verified, where it being verified consists in its being tested by
empirical observation. Consequently, statements like those of metaphysics to the truth or fal-
sehood of which no empirical observation could possibly be relevant, are ruled out as factually
meaningless.”22 For Murdoch such a bifurcation of fact and value cannot possibly be correct
as it ignores “the way in which almost all of our concepts and activities involve evaluation.
. . . [In] the majority of cases, a survey of the facts will itself involve moral discrimination.
Innumerable forms of evaluation haunt our simplest decisions.”23 Correlatively, valuing is not
a specialized activity of the will consigned to isolated acts of ethical or aesthetic valuation, but
rather presents the transcendental condition of knowledge. It is not so much that we think
about morality, but thinking itself, to the extent that it is an evaluative activity, is morality. That
is why ethics “is and ought to be connected with the whole of our being.”24
Second, the recognition of the ubiquity of values alerts us to the importance of metaphysics
whose task it is to probe the “unconditional element” (Paul Tillich) in reality as such.25 Akin
to artists who “try to capture fleeting moments in a unified whole, so too the quest for me-
taphysics is a way to do justice to reality, to the intimations of transcendence or the moral Good
in even our most ordinary experiences and endeavors.”26 In that sense, metaphysics “is a deep
emotional motive to philosophy, to art, to thinking itself.”27 Namely, we intuitively respond to
predications of being such as unified, balanced, integrated, dynamic, powerful, vivid, delicate,
moving, graceful, elegant, and so on.28 That is why metaphysics, as I understand Murdoch to be
claiming, is a form of aesthetic cognition par excellence. Like Plato’s concept of synoptikos, de-
noting the ability of a person to see things “in a unified manner,”29 so too Murdoch affirms the
22 A. J. Ayer, “The Vienna Circle,” in The Revolution in Philosophy (London: Macmillan, 1957), 74. For this
reference to Ayer I am indebted to Maria Antonaccio, Picturing the Human: The Moral Thought of Iris Mur-
doch (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), 29.
23 Murdoch, Metaphysics, 25-26. For Murdoch’s discussion of the naturalistic fallacy and its component parts
see her “Vision and Choice in Morality,” in Existentialists and Mystics: Writings on Philosophy and Litera-
ture, ed. Peter J. Conradi (London: Chatto & Windus, 1997).
24 Murdoch, Metaphysics, 495.
25 For an excellent overview of the rise and demise of modern metaphysics see A. W. Moore, The Evolution of
Modern Metaphysics: Making Sense of ThingsThe Evolution of Modern Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2012).
26 Murdoch doesn’t mean to suggest, I think, that every single form of artistic expression concerns such a
search for unity in an intentional way; much of contemporary art, after all, favors the fragmentary and the
nonrepresentational, and with it the brokenness bodies, the “ugly,” the pressing air of dystopian disintegra-
tion.
27 Murdoch, Metaphysics, 1.
28 On this point see Frank Sibley’s seminal essay “Aesthetic Concepts,” in Approach to Aesthetics: Collected Pa-
pers on Philosophical Aesthetics, ed. John Benson, Betty Redfern, and Jeremy Roxbee Cox (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2006).
29 Alister E. McGrath, The Intellectual World of C. S. Lewis (Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 2013), 91.
107
Ante Jerončić: Attending to reality - Biblijski pogledi, 21 (1-2), 101-114 (2013.)
108
Ante Jerončić: Attending to reality - Biblijski pogledi, 21 (1-2), 101-114 (2013.)
metaphysics as much as she argues for its indispensability. The fleeting and kaleidoscopic natu-
re of existence, she argues, cannot be captured in systems that for the sake of unity and compre-
hensiveness purge that which really matters in life—the nuances, the gradations, the subtleties
of difference. “What makes metaphysical (‘totalizing’) coherence theories unacceptable,” writes
Murdoch echoing Kierkegaardian sentiments, “is the way in which they in effect ‘disappear’
what is individual and contingent by equating reality with integration in system, and degrees
of reality with degrees of integration, and by implying that ‘ultimately’ or ‘really’ there is only
one system.”35
However, the real polemical thrust of Murdoch’s defense of metaphysics, I believe, con-
cerns both the nature of the self and the function of language in identity-construction. She ma-
kes that particularly evident in her rigorous defense of “consciousness,” i.e. the actuality of the
self and inner space of freedom vis-à-vis anti-humanist impulses in poststructuralist thought.
In the latter, the self is often perceived as transitive, conflicted, derivative, and illusionary;
“an opaque product of variable roles and performances which have been imposed upon it
by the constraints of society and by its own inner drives or conflicts.”36 In these theoretical
models, the self is decomposed into a totalizing assemblage of disharmonious parts—“an
interplay of different layers of signs and symbols,”37 a semiotic chimera of sorts. What is left
in the wake of such an apokalypsis or “uncovering” is a portrayal of the human self in terms
of a heterogeneous, intermittent cacophony; a cornucopia of différance, a continual sliding
off from one signifier to another.
Murdoch rejects the deterministic cast of these approaches and contends, perhaps unchari-
tably so, that they channel “a deep human wish: to give up, to get rid of freedom, responsibility,
remorse, all sorts of personal individual unease, and surrender to fate and the relief of ‘it could
not be otherwise’.”38 Now, that might or might not be true. What is important to the argument
is her underlying concern that without something like a self, without some notion of agency
that carries the possibility of “distancing,” the very concept of morality becomes problematic if
not unintelligible. Thus even someone like Foucault who does not envision the possibility of a
space unencumbered by relations of power, i.e. a way of conceptualizing the self apart from the
capillary forces of normalization, is at least able to say that something like that comprises our
condition. Foucault, the agent, sees, analyzes, names, and critiques and thus is in the position
to assume a position of otherness from that which he criticizes; he is not just a facsimile of dis-
course. It is such a possibility of critical distance that Murdoch has in mind when she claims,
alongside thinkers such as Charles Taylor and Seyla Benhabib, that human consciousness is not
just a gluey, tempestuous Petri dish concocted by fatalistic forces, be they societal, psychologi-
cal, or linguistic. “The person we wish to defend here, endorsed by common sense,” she writes,
“is not easily magicked away. Our present moment, our experiences, our flow of consciousness,
109
Ante Jerončić: Attending to reality - Biblijski pogledi, 21 (1-2), 101-114 (2013.)
our indelible moral sense, are not all these essentially linked together and do they not imply the
individual?”39 Even Kierkegaard, who is loath to admit any easy correlation between consciou-
sness and certainty, would consent to as much.
While I am aware that such a truncated treatment of Murdoch’s thought falls glaringly
short of doing justice to the subtlety of her approach, it suffices to illustrate how some of
her central commitments such as the omnipresence of value, the function and importance
of metaphysics, and the reality of a self-determining consciousness figure in her account of
moral realism. Before turning to some critical comments about Murdoch’s approach, a few
observations about her conception of the Good in relation the human transformation and
self-realization are in order.
110
Ante Jerončić: Attending to reality - Biblijski pogledi, 21 (1-2), 101-114 (2013.)
from the Republic—trapped in darkness and illusion about our true condition. Our psyche is
“as an egocentric system of quasi-mechanical energy, largely determined by its own individual
history, whose natural attachments are. . . ambiguous, and hard for the subject to understand or
control . . . . Objectivity and unselfishness are not natural to human beings.”43 Put bluntly, our
“fat relentless ego” is a great enemy of morality.44 Such a thoroughly pessimistic view of human
nature, by Murdoch’s own admission, is at the foundation of all of her writings, including her
novels where the protagonists “always seem to love the wrong person or get caught in nets of
illusion. That they, and we, are so caught reflects our condition, a condition . . . equivalent
to the doctrine of original sin.”45 In fact, “it would be difficult to name a contemporary no-
velist… who takes Freud more seriously in his unyielding portrait of the self-deception of
the ego, especially as the ego searches for the good.”46
It is in this context that we find the dynamic interplay of two key concepts in Murdoch’s
moral vision: attention or vision and detachment. Like the tradition of Russian personalism
that understands ethics as being “about truth and falsehood, . . . about living in recognition of
reality,”47 so too Murdoch sees misperception as the great enemy of morality. On her Platonic
terms, “it is perfectly obvious that goodness is connected with knowledge; . . . with a refined
and honest perception of what is really the case, a patient and just discernment and exploration
of what confronts one, which is the result not simply of opening one’s eyes but of a certainly
perfectly familiar kind of moral discipline.”48 That is, we stand in need of an ocular conversion;
morality is always a struggle to see rightly. Or as she puts it elsewhere: “I can only choose wit-
hin the world I can see, in the moral sense of see which implies that clear vision is a result of
moral imagination and moral effort.”49
The term “moral effort” is a crucial one here in that it connects perception to the idea
of character.50 What we “see” is determined by who we are—a frequent echo in C. S. Lewis’s
Chronicles of Narnia—and who we are cannot be accounted for without some recourse to mo-
Literature, ed. Peter J. Conradi [London: Chatto & Windus], 1997), 341.
43 Murdoch, The Sovereignty of Good, 50.
44 Ibid., 51.
45 Stanley Hauerwas, “Murodchian Muddles,” in Iris Murdoch and the Search for Human Goodness, ed. Maria
Antonaccio and William Schweiker (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1996), 198.
46 David Tracy, “The Many Faces of Platonism,” in Iris Murdoch and the Search for Human Goodness, ed.
Maria Antonaccio and William Schweiker (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1996, 60.
47 Rowan Williams, Prospect Magazine, http://www.prospectmagazine.co.uk/magazine/rowan-williams-dosto-
evsky-russian-literature-personalism-interview/#.Ubsb2-ec824 (last accessed February 20, 2015).
48 Murdoch, The Sovereignty of Good, 37.
49 Ibid., 35-36.
50 Murdoch writes: “Truthfulness, the search for truth, for a closer connection between thought and reality,
demands and effects an exercise of virtues and a purification of desires. The ability, for instance, to think
justly about what is evil, or to love another person unselfishly, involves a discipline of intellect and emotion.
Thought, goodness and reality are thus seen to be connected” (Murdoch, Metaphysics, 399). Hauerwas
echoes this perspective when he notes that “Christian ethics is not first of all concerned with ‘Thou shalt’ or
‘Thou shalt not.’ Its first task is to help us rightly envision the world. . . . We can only act within the world
we envision, and we can envision the world rightly only as we are trained to see” (Stanley Hauerwas, The
Peaceable Kingdom: A Primer in Christian Ethics [Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1983], 29).
111
Ante Jerončić: Attending to reality - Biblijski pogledi, 21 (1-2), 101-114 (2013.)
ral categories such as character and virtue, in other words, the moral good. That is why in order
to properly attend to reality we need to be changed, and we are changed, in turn, buy pursuing,
in the words of Simone Weil, “morally disciplined attention”51—a concerted reflection in the
form of prayer and meditation, of that which is morally good, not unlike the meditation of the
righteous person in Psalm 1.
Assessing Murdoch
Let me briefly retrace the steps of our discussion so far. I began with the observation that con-
temporary ethics faces challenges both in regards to the status and function of moral claims.
As we have noted, such misgivings often take the form of subjectivist proposals that deny the
stance-independent or objectivist status of moral norms as well as their beneficence for human
self-actualization. I then turned to Murdoch’s moral philosophy in order to address such a
double remove of morality in order to argue for a moral realist perspective that situates ethics
as the ground of Dasein or being-in-the-world. The Good, as Murdoch repeatedly stresses,
underwrites our basic acts of cognition and reminds us that the pursuit of truth and virtue are
essential to subjective well-being. On all of these issues I find myself in basic agreement with
Murdoch.
And yet some lingering questions remain. First, since the Murdochian Good is not a Being
or an extrinsic reality outside of me, how can I ever be sure that what I consider as a given
is not simply an expression of my historical consciousness? While I have reservations about
Nietzsche’s genealogical method, for example, not least of which is its continual slide into in-
stances of genetic fallacy, I do wonder how Murdoch’s account could properly defend itself
against the onslaught of such a hermeneutics of suspicion. In order to respond such a challenge
she could argue, in principle, that our innate sense of the Good is epiphenomenal to evoluti-
onary codings, and in so doing provide a naturalistic account of moral intuitionism. But that
line of disputation, as we will see, is closed to her the moment she rejects empirical verifications
of the Good.
Second, I believe that there is a quantum leap from an ontology of cognition that argues for
the transcendentally of value to the idea of moral obligation. That is, one can grant Murdoch
the claim about the ubiquity of value and yet remain unconvinced that gradations of perfection
have any moral claim upon one’s life. And besides, isn’t Murdoch’s argument itself a curious
instance of the “naturalistic fallacy”—that just because I encounter moral and non-moral value
in my daily existence that that in itself obliges my assent? In approaching such a dilemma, I
side with the position that, ontologically speaking, the moral ought can properly function only
within a framework of the divine command theory. Stated plainly, God—understood in the
broadest theistic sense as a divine lawgiver—is the lone basis of moral obligation. Correlatively,
and I am following Stephen C. Evans here, what justification for the law-like character of mo-
dern moral theories can we provide in the absence of a transcendental cause?52 One can read,
112
Ante Jerončić: Attending to reality - Biblijski pogledi, 21 (1-2), 101-114 (2013.)
for instance, Derek Parfit’s brilliant discussion about “decisive reasons… to act in some way”
in On What Matters and after plodding through a thousand pages or so still fail to become
convinced as to why exactly such reasons demand one’s submission.53 And so with Murdoch’s
ethics as well. We have already noted how her notion of transcendence is entirely immanentist
in character; there is no supernatural beyond. Simply retaining the formal structure of divine
command theory while getting rid of its substance, i.e. the belief in a God who has the right to
demand our allegiance, might not do the trick in the end. Granted, this is a hypercharged issue
whose complexity I have not even begun to address here, but I do contend that this presents
a lacuna in Murdoch’s thought and that her proposal, consequently, stands in need of a more
cogent phenomenology of moral obligation to account for the ought demanded by the Good.
Third, Murdoch insists that we should not identify the Good “with pleasure, or a will to
live, or what the government says. The possession of a moral sense is uniquely human; morality
is, something unique,. . . sui generis, ‘as if it came to us from elsewhere.’”54 While I understand
Murdoch’s motive in doing so, a refusal to provide an account of natural goodness prevents
her from specifying different forms human goods, such as pre-moral (material well-being), re-
flexive (personal well-being), and social (communal well-being).55 After all, it is quite difficult
to delineate such goods and their normativity function without the ability to give an account
of states and activities that are proper to humans and on which their flourishing depends.56
With that in mind, one wonders whether, in the end, Murdoch’s ethics is more an invitation to
“spiritual” transformation—certainly one essential aspect of human flourishing—rather than a
synthetic vision of how to morally orient human existence in pluralistic societies.
The failure of such a position becomes even more glaring as we consider exponential incre-
ases of power in our world in varied cultural and technological domains—biotechnological de-
velopments, transhumanism, “states of exceptions” (Carl Schmitt), the panopticizing of society,
child labor, exploitation of women, and so on. Such dehumanizations of life call for, I believe,
continued humanist efforts, both religious and nonreligious, to articulate transcultural goods,
norms, and judgments that are, in Hans Jonas’s words, “compatible with the permanence of
genuine human life.”57 I am not sure how Murdoch’s ethics could ever provide such normative
resources given her self-imposed constraints.
Such reservations aside, I am grateful to Murdoch for articulating a broader vision of the
moral landscape, one that moves beyond questions “of what we ought to do” to broader ones
“about what it is good to be or what it is good to love.”58 She prods us to revisit long neglec-
ted paths that strive to connect morality with the wider realm of meaning and reminds us
Anscombe, ed. Mary Geach and Luke Gormally (Exeter: Imprint Academic, 2005).
53 Derek Parfit, On What Matters, vol. 1 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011), 33.
54 Murdoch, Metaphysics, 26.
55 Schweiker, Responsibility and Christian Ethics, 120-121. For a good discussion of this issue see R. Kendall
Soulen and Linda Woodhead, eds., God and Human Dignity (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans,2006).
56 See for example Philippa Foot, Natural Goodness (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001).
57 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: The
University of Chicago Press, 1984), 11.
58 Charles Taylor, “Iris Murdoch and Moral Philosophy,” in Iris Murdoch and the Search for Human Goodness,
ed. Maria Antonaccio and William Schweiker (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996), 3.
113
Ante Jerončić: Attending to reality - Biblijski pogledi, 21 (1-2), 101-114 (2013.)
that ethics is essential to how we envision and protect human flourishing. Like some of her
theological counterparts—Augustine, von Balthasar, and C. S. Lewis come readily to mind
here—Murdoch maintains that experiences of beauty and goodness, fleeting as they might be,
evoke a yearning “for the infinite, a hunger for more than matter can provide.”59 So while I do
not consider myself a Murdochian, that would be quite impossible, really, given my theological
convictions, I do see her as someone who valiantly attempts to clear long neglected paths by
focusing not just on the good life but on the good beyond life.
SAŽETAK:
Ključne riječi: Iris Murdoch; metafizika; etički realizam; moralno dobro; ljudski procvat
59 Thomas Dubay, The Evidential Power of Beauty: Science and Theology Meet (San Francisco: Ignatius, 1999),
56.
114