Ethics
Ethics
Ethics
Rosen Educational Services materials copyright 2011 Rosen Educational Services, LLC.
All rights reserved.
First Edition
Thinkers and theories in ethics / edited by Brian Duignan in association with Britannica
Educational Publishing, Rosen Education Services.1st ed.
p. cm.(The Britannica guide to ethics)
In association with Britannica Educational Publishing, Rosen Educational Services.
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN /-.#'#,'+)&#*'+#.[8eea
1. Ethics. I. Duignan, Brian.
BJ71.T45 2011
170dc22
2010018911
Glossary 177
Bibliography 180
Index 183
Introduction
Introduction
ix
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
x
Introduction
xi
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
xii
Introduction
xiii
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
xiv
Introduction
xv
Chapter
Normative Ethics:
11
Eudaemonism and
Consequentialism
EUDAEMONISM
Eudaemonism derives its name from the ancient Greek
word eudaimonia, which literally means the state of
having a good indwelling spirit. The usual English
rendering of this term, happiness, is an inadequate
translation, however, because it incorrectly suggests
that eudaimonia is simply a mood or a state of mind. It
is instead the condition of living a good life, sometimes
called a life of human flourishing. According to eudae-
monistic theories, right or virtuous action is that which
enables, brings about, or is constitutive of happiness in
this sense. The best known forms of eudaemonism are
1
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
those of Plato (c. 428c. 348 BCE), Aristotle (384322 BCE), and
the Stoics.
2
Normative Ethics: Eudaemonism
7 and Consequentialism
7
3
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
4
Normative Ethics: Eudaemonism
7 and Consequentialism
7
5
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
6
Normative Ethics: Eudaemonism
7 and Consequentialism
7
The REPUBLIC
The middle dialogues of Plato have similar agendas.
Although they are primarily concerned with ethical and
other human issues, they also proclaim the importance
of metaphysical inquiry and sketch Platos doctrine of
forms, which Socrates certainly did not hold. According
to this doctrine, corresponding to every property or
feature that a particular thing may have, there is an
unchanging and eternal reality, called a form, in which
the thing participates. Thus, having a property is a
matter of participating in the corresponding form. For
example, Achilles is beautiful by virtue of the fact that
he participates in the form of Beauty, and the racehorse
War Emblem is black by virtue of his participating in the
form of Blackness. Likewise, being courageous, just, or
pious or possessing any of the other human virtues con-
sists of participating in the form of Courage, Justice, or
Piety, and so on. Such forms, according to Plato, are what
Socrates and his interlocutors were searching for in their
struggle to discover the real definitions of the virtues.
However, Plato does not fully specify how the forms are
to be understood until the later dialogues, particularly
the Parmenides.
In one of the greatest dialogues of the middle period,
the Republic, Plato develops a view of happiness and vir-
tue that departs from that of Socrates. According to
Plato, there are three parts of the soulreason, spirit,
and appetiteeach of which has its own natural object
of desire. Thus, reason desires truth and the good of the
individual as a whole, spirit desires the honour and esteem
7
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
8
Normative Ethics: Eudaemonism
7 and Consequentialism
7
9
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
Happiness
Aristotles approach to ethics is teleological. If life is to
be worth living, he argues, it must surely be for the sake
of something that is an end in itself (i.e., desirable for its
own sake). Therefore, the highest human good, which
Aristotle calls happiness, must be desirable for its own
sake, and all other goods must be desirable for the sake of
it. One popular conception of the highest human good is
pleasurethe pleasures of food, drink, and sex, combined
with aesthetic and intellectual pleasures. Other people
prefer a life of virtuous action in the political sphere. A
third possible candidate for the highest human good is
scientific or philosophical contemplation. Aristotle thus
10
Normative Ethics: Eudaemonism
7 and Consequentialism
7
Soul
The soul is the purported immaterial aspect or essence of a human
being, that which confers individuality and humanity. It is often iden-
tified with the mind or the self.
Many cultures have recognized some incorporeal principle cor-
responding to the soul, and many have attributed souls to all living
things. Both the ancient Egyptians and the ancient Chinese conceived
of a dual soul. The Egyptian ka (breath) survived death but remained
near the body, while the spiritual ba proceeded to the region of the
dead. The Chinese distinguished between a lower, sensitive soul,
which disappears with death, and a rational principle, the hun, which
survives the grave and is the object of ancestor worship. The ancient
Hebrews apparently had a concept of the soul but did not separate it
from the body, although later Jewish writers developed the idea of the
soul further.
Ancient Greek concepts of the soul varied considerably. For the
Platonists, the soul was an immaterial and incorporeal substance.
Aristotles conception of the soul was obscure, though he did state that
it was a form inseparable from the body. Socrates and Plato accepted
the immortality of the soul, while Aristotle considered only part of
the soul, the nos, or intellect, to have that quality. The early Christian
philosophers adopted the Greek concept of the souls immortality
and thought of the soul as being created by God and infused into the
body at conception.
Among early-modern philosophers, Ren Descartes believed
that human beings were a union of the body and the soul, each a dis-
tinct substance acting on the other, while Benedict de Spinoza held
that body and soul are but two aspects of a single reality.
In Hinduism the atman (breath, or soul) is the universal, eter-
nal self, of which each individual soul (jiva or jiva-atman) partakes.
The jiva-atman is also eternal but is imprisoned in an earthly body at
birth. At death the jiva-atman passes into a new existence determined
by karma, or the cumulative consequences of actions. Buddhism
asserts that any sense of having an individual eternal soul or of partak-
ing in a persistent universal self is illusory. The Muslim concept, like
the Christian, holds that the soul comes into existence at the same
time as the body. Thereafter, it has a life of its own, its union with the
body being a temporary condition.
11
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
Virtue
Peoples virtues are a subset of their good qualities. They
are not innate, like eyesight, but are acquired by practice
and lost by disuse. They are abiding states, and they thus
differ from momentary passions such as anger and pity.
Virtues are states of character that find expression both
in purpose and in action. Moral virtue is expressed in good
purposethat is to say, in prescriptions for action in accor-
dance with a good plan of life. It is expressed also in actions
that avoid both excess and defect. A temperate person, for
example, will avoid eating or drinking too much, but he
will also avoid eating or drinking too little. Virtue chooses
the mean, or middle ground, between excess and defect.
Besides purpose and action, virtue is also concerned with
12
Normative Ethics: Eudaemonism
7 and Consequentialism
7
13
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
14
Normative Ethics: Eudaemonism
7 and Consequentialism
7
Stoicism
Stoicism was a school of thought that flourished in Greek
and Roman antiquity from about the 3rd century BCE. It
was one of the loftiest and most sublime philosophies
in the record of Western civilization. For the Stoics, the
goal of human beings, the greatest good to which they can
aspire, consists of living according to nature, in agreement
with the world design.
15
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
16
Normative Ethics: Eudaemonism
7 and Consequentialism
7
17
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
18
Normative Ethics: Eudaemonism
7 and Consequentialism
7
19
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
20
Normative Ethics: Eudaemonism
7 and Consequentialism
7
The Middle Stoa, which flourished in the 2nd and early 1st
centuries BCE, was dominated chiefly by Panaetius (c. 180
109 BCE), its founder, and his disciple Poseidonius (c. 135c.
51 BCE), both from the Greek island of Rhodes. Panaetius
organized a Stoic school in Rome before returning to
Athens, and Poseidonius was largely responsible for
an emphasis on the religious features of the doctrine.
Both were antagonistic to the ethical doctrines of
Chrysippus, who, they believed, had strayed too far
from the Platonic and Aristotelian roots of Stoicism.
It may have been because of the considerable time that
Panaetius and Poseidonius lived in Rome that the Stoa
there turned so much of its emphasis to the moral and
religious themes within the Stoic doctrine. Panaetius
was highly regarded by Cicero, who used him as a model
for his own work.
Poseidonius, who had been a disciple of Panaetius
in Athens, taught Cicero at his school at Rhodes and
later went to Rome and remained there for a time with
Cicero. If Poseidonius admired Plato and Aristotle, he
was particularly interestedunlike most of his school
in the study of natural and providential phenomena. In
presenting the Stoic system in the second book of De
natura deorum (45 BCE), Cicero most probably followed
Poseidonius. Because his master, Panaetius, was chiefly
concerned with concepts of duty and obligation, it was
his studies that served as a model for the De officiis (44
BCE) of Cicero. Hecaton, another of Panaetiuss students
and an active Stoic philosopher, also stressed similar
ethical themes.
Panaetius and Poseidonius were chiefly responsible
for the widespread popularity of Stoicism in Rome.
21
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
22
Normative Ethics: Eudaemonism
7 and Consequentialism
7
23
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
Logos
24
Normative Ethics: Eudaemonism
7 and Consequentialism
7
as the preexistent logos (1) reveals the Father to humankind and is the
subject of the Hebrew Bible manifestations of God; (2) is the divine
reason in which the whole human race shares; and (3) is the divine will
and word by which the worlds were framed.
25
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
26
Normative Ethics: Eudaemonism
7 and Consequentialism
7
CONSEQUENTIALISM
Consequentialism is a theory of morality that derives
duty or moral obligation from what is good or desirable as
an end to be achieved. Also known as teleological ethics
27
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
28
Normative Ethics: Eudaemonism
7 and Consequentialism
7
Epicureanism
In a strict sense, Epicureanism is the philosophy taught
by Epicurus (341270 BCE). In a broad sense, however, it is
a system of ethics embracing every conception or form of
life that can be traced to the principles of his philosophy.
In ancient polemics, as often since, the term was employed
with an even more generic (and clearly erroneous) mean-
ing as the equivalent of a crude hedonism, according to
which sensual pleasure is the chief good.
29
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
History of Epicureanism
Epicurus is remarkable for his systematic spirit and the
unity that he tried to give to every part of philosophy. In
this respect, he was greatly influenced by the philosophy
and teachings of Aristotletaking over the essentials of
his doctrines and pursuing the problems that he posed.
In the Middle Ages Epicurus was known through
Cicero and the polemics of the Church Fathers. To be an
Epicurean at the time of the Italian poet and philosopher
Dante (12651321) meant to be one who denied Providence
and the immortality of the soul. The first modern defense
30
Normative Ethics: Eudaemonism
7 and Consequentialism
7
31
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
His Works
In accordance with the goal that he assigned to philoso-
phy, Epicuruss teaching had a dogmatic character, in
substance if not in form. He called his treatises dialogismoi,
or conversations. Because the utility of the doctrines
lay in their application, he summarized them in stoicheia,
32
Normative Ethics: Eudaemonism
7 and Consequentialism
7
33
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
34
Normative Ethics: Eudaemonism
7 and Consequentialism
7
35
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
36
Normative Ethics: Eudaemonism
7 and Consequentialism
7
37
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
Utilitarianism
Basic Concepts
The utilitarian understands the consequences of an action
to include all of the good and bad produced, whether
arising after the action has been performed or during
its performance. If the difference in the consequences
of alternative actions is not great, some utilitarians do
not regard the choice between them as a moral issue.
According to John Stuart Mill, actions should be classified
38
Normative Ethics: Eudaemonism
7 and Consequentialism
7
39
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
Methodologies
As a normative system providing a standard by which an
individual ought to act and by which the existing practices
of society, including its moral code, ought to be evalu-
ated and improved, utilitarianism cannot be verified or
confirmed in the way in which a descriptive theory can.
But it is not regarded by its exponents as simply arbi-
trary. Bentham believed that only in terms of a utilitarian
40
Normative Ethics: Eudaemonism
7 and Consequentialism
7
Criticisms
Most opponents of utilitarianism have held that it has
implications contrary to their moral intuitionsthat
considerations of utility, for example, might sometimes
sanction the breaking of a promise. Much of the defense
of utilitarian ethics has consisted in answering these
objections, either by showing that utilitarianism does not
have the implications that they claim it has or by arguing
against the moral intuitions of its opponents. Some utili-
tarians, however, have sought to modify the utilitarian
theory to account for the objections.
One such criticism is that, although the widespread
practice of lying and stealing would have bad conse-
quences, resulting in a loss of trustworthiness and security,
41
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
42
Normative Ethics: Eudaemonism
7 and Consequentialism
7
Historical Survey
The ingredients of utilitarianism are found in the history
of thought long before Bentham. A hedonistic theory of
the value of life is found in the early 5th century BCE in the
ethics of Aristippus of Cyrene (c. 435366 BCE), founder
of the Cyrenaic school, and 100 years later in that of
Epicurus. The seeds of ethical universalism are found in
the doctrines of the rival ethical school of Stoicism and in
Christianity.
43
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
44
Normative ethics: Eudaemonism
7 and consequentialism
7
45
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
46
Normative Ethics: Eudaemonism
7 and Consequentialism
7
47
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
48
Normative Ethics: Eudaemonism
7 and Consequentialism
7
49
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
50
Chapter
Normative Ethics:
21
Contractualism,
Deontology, Feminism,
and Egoism
CONTRACTUALISM
The contractualist approach in normative ethics is
based on the notion of the social contract, which
is conceived as an actual or hypothetical compact
between the ruled and their rulers. The terms of the
supposed contract are used as the basis of a justifica-
tion of the political authority of the rulers, the rights
of the ruled, or both. The original inspiration for the
notion may derive from the biblical covenant between
God and Abraham, but it is most closely associated
51
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
Thomas Hobbes
Thomas Hobbes presented his political philosophy in dif-
ferent forms for different audiences. His work De Cive
(1642) states his theory in what he regarded as its most
scientific form. Unlike The Elements of Law (1650), which
was composed in English for English parliamentarians
and which was written with local political challenges to
King Charles I in mindDe Cive was a Latin work for an
audience of Continental savants who were interested in
the new sciencethat is, the sort of science that did not
appeal to the authority of the ancients but approached
various problems with fresh principles of explanation.
De Cives break from the ancient authority par
excellenceAristotlecould not have been more loudly
advertised. After only a few paragraphs, Hobbes rejects
one of the most famous theses of Aristotles politics,
namely that human beings are naturally suited to life in a
polis (city-state) and do not fully realize their natures until
they exercise the role of citizen. Hobbes turns Aristotles
claim on its head: human beings, he insists, are by nature
unsuited to political life. They naturally denigrate and
compete with each other, are too easily swayed by the
rhetoric of ambitious men, and think much more highly of
themselves than of other people. In short, their passions
magnify the value they place on their own interests, espe-
cially their near-term interests. At the same time, most
people, in pursuing their own interests, do not have the
52
Normative Ethics: Contractualism,
7 Deontology, Feminism, and Egoism
7
53
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
54
Normative Ethics: Contractualism,
7 Deontology, Feminism, and Egoism
7
55
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
John Locke
John Lockes importance as a political philosopher lies
in the argument of the second of his Two Treatises of
Government (1690). He begins by defining political power
as a
56
Normative Ethics: Contractualism,
7 Deontology, Feminism, and Egoism
7
57
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
58
Normative Ethics: Contractualism,
7 Deontology, Feminism, and Egoism
7
Property
59
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
Organization of Government
Locke returns to political society in Chapter VIII of the
second treatise. In the community created by the social
contract, the will of the majority should prevail, subject to
the law of nature. The legislative body is central, but it can-
not create laws that violate the law of nature, because the
enforcement of the natural law regarding life, liberty, and
property is the rationale of the whole system. Laws must
apply equitably to all citizens and not favour particular
sectional interests, and there should be a division of legis-
lative, executive, and judicial powers. The legislature may,
with the agreement of the majority, impose such taxes as
are required to fulfill the ends of the stateincluding, of
course, its defense. If the executive power fails to provide
the conditions under which the people can enjoy their
rights under natural law, the people are entitled to remove
him, by force if necessary. Thus, revolution, in extremis, is
permissibleas Locke obviously thought it was in 1688
89, during the Glorious Revolution against King James II
of England.
The significance of Lockes vision of political society
can scarcely be exaggerated. His integration of individu-
alism within the framework of the law of nature and his
account of the origins and limits of legitimate government
authority inspired the U.S. Declaration of Independence
(1776) and the broad outlines of the system of government
adopted in the U.S. Constitution. George Washington,
the first president of the United States, once described
Locke as the greatest man who had ever lived. In France
too, Lockean principles found clear expression in the
Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen and
other justifications of the French Revolution of 1789.
60
Normative Ethics: Contractualism,
7 Deontology, Feminism, and Egoism
7
Jean-Jacques Rousseau
61
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
62
Normative Ethics: Contractualism,
7 Deontology, Feminism, and Egoism
7
rich. Even so, the rich are no happier in civil society than
are the poor because the social individual is never satisfied.
Society leads people to hate one another to the extent that
their interests conflict, and the best they are able to do
is to hide their hostility behind a mask of courtesy. Thus
Rousseau regards the inequality not as a separate problem
but as one of the features of the long process by which
people become alienated from nature and from innocence.
In the dedication Rousseau wrote for the Discourse,
to present it to the republic of Geneva, he nevertheless
praises that city-state for having achieved the ideal bal-
ance between the equality which nature established
among men and the inequality which they have instituted
among themselves. The arrangement he discerned in
Geneva was one in which the best persons were chosen
by the citizens and put in the highest positions of author-
ity. Like Plato (c. 428c. 348 BCE), Rousseau always believed
that a just society was one in which everyone was in his
right place. And having written the Discourse to explain
how human liberty had been lost in the past, he went on
to write another book, Du Contrat social (1762; The Social
Contract), to suggest how it might be recovered in the
future. Again Geneva was the model: not Geneva as it had
become in 1754, when Rousseau returned there to recover
his rights as a citizen, but Geneva as it had once been (i.e.,
Geneva as the Protestant Reformer John Calvin [150964]
had designed it).
The Social Contract begins with the sensational open-
ing sentence, Man is born free, and everywhere he is in
chains. Rousseau proceeds to argue that these chains
need not exist. If a civil society, or state, could be based
on a genuine social contract, as opposed to the fraudu-
lent social contract depicted in the Discourse on the Origin
of Inequality, people would receive in exchange for their
independence a better kind of freedomnamely, true
63
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
64
Normative Ethics: Contractualism,
7 Deontology, Feminism, and Egoism
7
65
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
John Rawls
The publication of A Theory of Justice (1971), by the
American philosopher John Rawls, spurred a revival of
interest in the philosophical foundations of liberalisma
political doctrine, originating with Locke, that empha-
sizes the rights and freedoms of the individual. According
to classical liberals, the central challenge of politics is to
devise a system that gives government the power neces-
sary to protect individual liberty but also prevents those
who govern from abusing that power. Modern liberals,
in contrast, see a greater challenge in removing obstacles
that prevent individuals from living freely or from fully
realizing their potential. Such obstacles, as they conceive
them, include poverty, disease, discrimination, and igno-
rance. Because of Rawlss work, the viability of liberalism
has been a major theme of political philosophy in English-
speaking countries.
In A Theory of Justice, Rawls observed that a necessary
condition of justice in any society is that each individual
should be the equal bearer of certain rights that cannot
be disregarded under any circumstances, even if doing so
would advance the general welfare or satisfy the demands of
a majority. This condition cannot be met by utilitarianism,
66
Normative Ethics: Contractualism,
7 Deontology, Feminism, and Egoism
7
67
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
68
Normative Ethics: Contractualism,
7 Deontology, Feminism, and Egoism
7
DEONTOLOGY
Deontological ethical theories place special emphasis on
moral rules and on the related concept of duty. In deon-
tological ethics an action is considered morally good
because it conforms to a moral law, principle, or rule, not
because the product of the action is good. Deontological
69
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
70
Normative Ethics: Contractualism,
7 Deontology, Feminism, and Egoism
7
71
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
72
Normative Ethics: Contractualism,
7 Deontology, Feminism, and Egoism
7
Natural-Rights Theory
Another important variety of deontological ethics is
natural-rights theory. Although the social-contract theo-
ries of Hobbes and Locke both presupposed and justified
the existence of some natural rights, some later political
philosophers took the notion of natural rights as absolute
and defined the scope and limits of government power on
the basis of this assumption. The leading 20th-century
representative of this line of thinking, the American phi-
losopher Robert Nozick (19382002), held that the state
should have no more than minimal powersessentially
the powers to protect citizens rights to life and property
because only a state with those powers could have come
about without violating anyones natural rights.
73
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
74
Normative Ethics: Contractualism,
7 Deontology, Feminism, and Egoism
7
75
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
76
Normative Ethics: Contractualism,
7 Deontology, Feminism, and Egoism
7
77
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
the late 18th and early 19th centuries. Together with the
Glorious Revolution in England and the resulting English
Bill of Rights, it provided the rationale for the wave of
revolutionary agitation that swept the West, most nota-
bly in North America and France. Thomas Jefferson
(17431826), who had studied Locke and Montesquieu,
gave poetic eloquence to the plain prose of the 17th cen-
tury in the Declaration of Independence, proclaimed by
the 13 American colonies on July 4, 1776: We hold these
truths to be self-evident, that all men are created equal,
that they are endowed by their Creator with certain
unalienable Rights, that among these are Life, Liberty
and the Pursuit of Happiness. Similarly, the marquis
de Lafayette (17571834), who won the close friendship
of George Washington (173299) and who shared the
hardships of the American Revolution, imitated the pro-
nouncements of the English and American revolutions in
the Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen
of Aug. 26, 1789, proclaiming that men are born and
remain free and equal in rights and that the aim of every
political association is the preservation of the natural and
imprescriptible rights of man.
In sum, the idea of natural rights, though now known
by another name, played a key role in late 18th- and early
19th-century struggles against political absolutism. It
was, indeed, the failure of rulers to respect the principles
of freedom and equality that was responsible for this
development.
78
Normative Ethics: Contractualism,
7 Deontology, Feminism, and Egoism
7
79
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
80
Normative Ethics: Contractualism,
7 Deontology, Feminism, and Egoism
7
When Nazi laws and decrees sanctioned the regimes atrocious crimes, many
were persuaded that some actions are unconditionally wrong, regardless of the
circumstances. FPG/Archive Photos/Getty Images
81
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
Robert Nozick
In the 20th century the most influential philosophical
defender of natural rights was Robert Nozick. The politi-
cal philosophy he adhered to, libertarianism, is essentially
a classical form of liberalism that holds that any govern-
ment power beyond the minimum necessary to protect
life and property is unjustified. Ironically, given his subse-
quent political philosophy, Nozick was a member of the
student New Left and an enthusiastic socialist during his
high school and college years. At Columbia University
in New York City he helped to found a campus branch
of the League for Industrial Democracy, a precursor of
the leftist Students for a Democratic Society. While in
graduate school, however, he read works by libertarian
economists such as F.A. Hayek and Ludwig von Mises,
and his political views began to change. His conversion
to libertarianism culminated in 1974 with the publica-
tion of Anarchy, State, and Utopia, a closely argued and
highly original defense of the libertarian minimal state
and a critique of the social-democratic liberalism of his
Harvard colleague John Rawls. Immediately hailed by
82
Normative Ethics: Contractualism,
7 Deontology, Feminism, and Egoism
7
83
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
Libertarianism
Libertarianism is a political philosophy that takes individual liberty
to be the primary political value. It may be understood as a form
of liberalism, the political philosophy associated with the English
philosophers John Locke and John Stuart Mill, the Scottish econo-
mist Adam Smith, and the American statesman Thomas Jefferson.
Liberalism seeks to define and justify the legitimate powers of gov-
ernment in terms of certain natural or God-given individual rights.
These rights include the rights to life, liberty, private property, free-
dom of speech and association, freedom of worship, government
by consent, equality under the law, and moral autonomy (the pur-
suit of ones own conception of happiness, or the good life). The
purpose of government, according to liberals, is to protect these
and other individual rights, and in general liberals have contended
that government power should be limited to that which is neces-
sary to accomplish this task. Libertarians are classical liberals who
strongly emphasize the individual right to liberty. They contend that
the scope and powers of government should be constrained so as
to allow each individual as much freedom of action as is consistent
with a like freedom for everyone else. Thus, they believe that indi-
viduals should be free to behave and to dispose of their property as
they see fit, provided that their actions do not infringe on the equal
freedom of others.
84
Normative Ethics: Contractualism,
7 Deontology, Feminism, and Egoism
7
85
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
86
Normative Ethics: Contractualism,
7 Deontology, Feminism, and Egoism
7
87
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
88
Normative Ethics: Contractualism,
7 Deontology, Feminism, and Egoism
7
FEMINISM
Feminist ethics is one aspect of a much broader move-
ment known as philosophical feminism. Feminism in this
sense is a loosely related set of approaches in various fields
of philosophy that emphasizes the role of gender (ones
identity as male or female) in the formation of tra-
ditional philosophical problems and concepts. Feminist
philosophers analyze the ways in which traditional phi-
losophy reflects and perpetuates bias against women, and
89
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
90
Normative Ethics: Contractualism,
7 Deontology, Feminism, and Egoism
7
91
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
Feminist Ethics
92
Normative Ethics: Contractualism,
7 Deontology, Feminism, and Egoism
7
93
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
Moral Psychology
Moral psychology is the study of the development of the moral sense
(i.e., the capacity for forming judgments about what is morally right
or wrong, good or bad). The U.S. psychologist Lawrence Kohlberg
hypothesized that peoples development of moral standards passes
through several levels. At the early level, that of preconventional
moral reasoning, the child uses external and physical events (such as
pleasure or pain) as the source for moral decisions. His standards are
based strictly on what will avoid punishment or bring pleasure. At the
intermediate level, that of conventional moral reasoning, the child or
adolescent views moral standards as a way of maintaining the approval
of authority figures, chiefly his parents, and acts in accordance with
their precepts. At the third level, that of postconventional moral
reasoning, the adult bases his moral standards on principles that he
himself has evaluated and accepts as inherently valid, regardless of soci-
etys opinion. Beginning in the 1970s, Kohlbergs work was criticized
by psychologists and philosophers influenced by feminism. According
to Carol Gilligan, Kohlbergs stages are inherently sexist, because they
equate moral maturity with an orientation toward moral problems
that is socially instilled in males but not in females. Whereas the male
ethic of rights and justice treats morality in terms of abstract prin-
ciples and conceives of moral agents as essentially autonomous, acting
independently of their social situations according to general rules, the
female ethic of care treats morality in terms of concrete bonds to
particular individuals based on feelings of care and responsibility and
conceives of moral agents as connected and interdependent through
their feelings of care and responsibility for each other.
94
Normative Ethics: Contractualism,
7 Deontology, Feminism, and Egoism
7
95
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
96
Normative Ethics: Contractualism,
7 Deontology, Feminism, and Egoism
7
97
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
ETHICAL EGOISM
Ethical egoism, whose name is derived from the Latin ego,
meaning I, is an ethical theory holding that an action
is right if and only if it promotes ones self-interest. (The
word is sometimes misused for egotism, the overstressing
of ones own worth.)
Egoist Doctrines
Egoist doctrines are less concerned with the philosophi-
cal problem of what is the self than with the common
notions of a person and his concerns. They emphasize
self-perfection sought through the furthering of ones own
welfare and profitallowing, however, that sometimes
one may not know where these lie and must be brought to
recognize them.
Many ethical theories have an egoist bias. Ancient
Greek ethics bid each person to seek his own happi-
ness (though it should be emphasized that happiness as
the Greeks conceived it entailed an appropriate con-
cern for the interests of others). In the 17th century,
Thomas Hobbes (15881679) and Benedict de Spinoza
(163277) held in different ways that self-preservation
is the good. Those who stress the tending of ones own
conscience and moral growth are likewise egoists in this
sense. In contrast with such views is an ethics that is gov-
erned more by humanitys social aspects, which stresses
98
Normative Ethics: Contractualism,
7 Deontology, Feminism, and Egoism
7
Ayn Rand
Although few contemporary philosophers are strict ethical
egoists, some economists and political thinkers have been
attracted to the position. In the 20th century the fore-
most advocate of egoism was the Russian-born American
writer Ayn Rand. In a series of commercially successful
novels, Rand presented her philosophy of objectivism,
which essentially reversed the traditional altruistic ethics
of Judaism and Christianity.
Rand graduated from the University of Petrograd in
1924 and two years later immigrated to the United States.
She initially worked as a screenwriter in Hollywood and in
1931 became a naturalized U.S. citizen. Her first novel, We,
the Living, was published in 1936. The Fountainhead (1943),
her first best-selling novel, depicted a highly romanticized
architect-hero, a superior individual whose egoism and
genius prevail over timid traditionalism and social con-
formism. The allegorical Atlas Shrugged (1957), another
best-seller, combined science fiction and political mes-
sage in telling of an anticollectivist strike called by the
management of U.S. big industry, a company of attractive,
self-made men.
The political philosophy of objectivism shaped Rands
work. A deeply conservative doctrine, it posited indi-
vidual effort and ability as the sole source of all genuine
achievement, thereby elevating the pursuit of self-interest
to the role of first principle and scorning such notions
99
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
In her successful novels, Ayn Rand promoted radical egoism and laissez-faire
capitalism. New York Times Co./Archive Photos/Getty Images
100
Normative Ethics: Contractualism,
7 Deontology, Feminism, and Egoism
7
101
Chapter
Metaethics
3
M etaethics is the subdiscipline of ethics concerned
with determining the nature of moral concepts
and judgments. Metaethics identifies a fundamental
task of the moral philosopher, the logical analysis of
(1) moral concepts such as right and wrong, obligatory
and forbidden, and good and evil; (2) the nature and
function of moral judgments or statements; and (3)
the nature of moral reasoning. Metaethics is thus to
be contrasted with normative ethics, which explores
questions such as: What actions are right and what
are wrong?; How should one live and what things
should one value?; and Is life worth living?
Many philosophers hold that the fundamental
questions in ethical theory are metaethical. Some even
assert that they are the only questions appropriate for
a moral philosopher and that normative questions can
be dealt with by all people in their capacity as moral-
ists. The position of the moral philosopher is thus
analogous to that of the philosopher of science, who
considers only the elements of scientific reasoning and
remains neutral on the question of which scientific
statements are true and which false.
Major metaethical theories include naturalism,
nonnaturalism (or intuitionism), emotivism, and
prescriptivism. Naturalists, such as Ralph Barton
Perry (18761957), W.T. Stace (18861967), Richard
B. Brandt, and Geoffrey James Warnock (192396),
102
7 Metaethics 7
103
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
104
7 Metaethics 7
Moral realists believe that judgments about what is right or wrong and
what is virtuous or vicious are objectively true or false, depending on what
the moral facts are. Jean-Claude Winkler/Photographers Choice/
Getty Images
105
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
ETHICAL RELATIVISM
Ethical relativism is the doctrine that there are no absolute
truths in ethics and that what is morally right or wrong
varies from person to person or from society to society.
106
7 Metaethics 7
107
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
Cultural Anthropology
Cultural anthropology is the branch of anthropology that deals with
the study of culture. The discipline uses the methods, concepts, and
data of archaeology, ethnography, folklore, linguistics, and related
fields in its descriptions and analyses of the diverse peoples of the
world. Called social anthropology in Britain, its field of research
was until the mid-20th century largely restricted to the small-scale
(or primitive), non-Western societies that first began to be identi-
fied during the age of discovery. Today the field extends to all forms
of human association, from village communities to corporate cul-
tures to urban gangs. Two key perspectives used are those of holism
(understanding society as a complex, interactive whole) and cultural
relativism (the appreciation of cultural phenomena within their own
context). Areas of study traditionally include social structure, law,
politics, religion, magic, art, and technology.
108
7 Metaethics 7
David Hume, oil painting by Allan Ramsay, 1766; in the Scottish National
Portrait Gallery, Edinburgh. Courtesy of the Scottish National Portrait
Gallery
109
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
110
7 Metaethics 7
111
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
112
7 Metaethics 7
113
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
114
7 Metaethics 7
Choosing what fruit to buy seems to be an act of free will, given that in ordi-
nary cases nothing forces a person to buy one kind of fruit rather than another.
Keren Su/The Image Bank/Getty Images
115
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
Determinism
Determinism is the view that, given the state of the uni-
verse (the complete physical properties of all its parts)
at a certain time and the laws of nature operative in the
universe at that time, the state of the universe at any sub-
sequent time is completely determined. No subsequent
state of the universe can be other than what it is. Because
human actions, at an appropriate level of description,
are part of the universe, it follows that humans cannot
act otherwise than they do. Free will is impossible. (It is
important to distinguish determinism from mere causa-
tion. Determinism is not the thesis that every event has a
cause, since causes do not always necessitate their effects.
It is, rather, the thesis that every event is causally inevi-
table. If an event has occurred, then it is impossible that
it could not have occurred, given the previous state of the
universe and the laws of nature.)
Philosophers and scientists who believe that the
universe is deterministic and that determinism is
incompatible with free will are called hard determin-
ists. Because moral responsibility seems to require free
will, hard determinism implies that no one is morally
116
7 Metaethics 7
Libertarianism
Philosophers and scientists who believe that the universe
is indeterministic and that humans possess free will are
known as libertarians (libertarianism in this sense is not
to be confused with the school of political philosophy
called libertarianism). Although it is possible to hold that
the universe is indeterministic and that human actions are
nevertheless determined, few contemporary philosophers
defend this view.
Libertarianism is vulnerable to what is called the
intelligibility objection. This objection points out that
a person can have no more control over a purely random
action than he has over an action that is deterministically
inevitable; in neither case does free will enter the picture.
117
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
118
7 Metaethics 7
119
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
Compatibilism
Compatibilism, as the name suggests, is the view that
the existence of free will and moral responsibility is com-
patible with the truth of determinism. In most cases
compatibilists (also called soft determinists) attempt to
achieve this reconciliation by subtly revising or weakening
the commonsense notion of free will.
120
7 Metaethics 7
If there is a device in Johns brain that will force him to vote for candidate
B if he is inclined to vote for candidate A, but he votes for candidate B on
his own, has he acted freely? Dan Kitwood/Getty Images
121
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
Modern Compatibilism
Following the rediscovery of Classical learning during the
Renaissance, philosophers sympathetic to compatibilism
122
7 Metaethics 7
123
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
Contemporary Compatibilism
Notwithstanding Bradleys argument, compatibilism
remained popular among 20th-century thinkers. G.E.
Moore attempted to reconcile determinism and free will
through a conditional analysis of freedom. When one
says that a person acted freely, according to Moore, one
simply means that, if he had chosen to do otherwise, he
would have done otherwise. The fact that the person may
not have been in a position to choose otherwise does not
undermine his free agency. But what does it mean to say
that one could have done otherwise? In Freedom and
Necessity (1946), A.J. Ayer maintained that to say that
I could have acted otherwise is to say that I should have
acted otherwise if I had so chosen. The ability to do oth-
erwise means only that, if the past had been different,
124
7 Metaethics 7
125
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
126
7 Metaethics 7
127
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
EVOLUTIONARY ETHICS
The best known traditional form of evolutionary eth-
ics is social Darwinism, though this view owes far more
to Herbert Spencer (18201903) than it does to Charles
Darwin (180982), the English naturalist who formulated
the theory of evolution through natural selection. It begins
with the assumption that in the natural world the struggle
for existence is good, because it leads to the evolution of
animals that are better adapted to their environments.
From this premise it concludes that in the social world a
similar struggle for existence should take place, for simi-
lar reasons. Some social Darwinists have thought that the
social struggle also should be physicaltaking the form
of warfare, for example. More commonly, however, they
assumed that the struggle should be economic, involving
competition between individuals and private businesses
in a legal environment of laissez faire. This was Spencers
own position.
As might be expected, not all evolutionary theorists
have agreed that natural selection implies the justice of
laissez-faire capitalism. Alfred Russel Wallace (18231913),
who advocated a group-selection analysis, believed in the
justice of actions that promote the welfare of the state,
even at the expense of the individual, especially in cases
in which the individual is already well-favoured. The
Russian theorist of anarchism Peter Kropotkin (1842
1921) argued that selection proceeds through cooperation
within groups (mutual aid) rather than through struggle
128
7 Metaethics 7
Social Darwinism
Social Darwinism is the theory that persons, groups, and races are
subject to the same laws of natural selection as Charles Darwin had
perceived in plants and animals in nature. According to the theory,
which was popular in the late 19th and early 20th centuries, the weak
were diminished and their cultures delimited, while the strong grew in
power and in cultural influence over the weak. Social Darwinists held
that the life of humans in society is a struggle for existence ruled by
survival of the fittest, a phrase proposed by Herbert Spencer.
The social Darwinistsnotably Spencer and Walter Bagehot
in England and William Graham Sumner in the United States
believed that the process of natural selection acting on variations in
the population would result in the survival of the best competitors
and in continuing improvement in the population. Societies, like
individuals, were viewed as organisms that evolve in this manner.
The theory was used to support laissez-faire capitalism and polit-
ical conservatism. Class stratification was justified on the basis of
natural inequalities among individuals, for the control of property
was said to be a correlate of superior and inherent moral attributes
such as industriousness, temperance, and frugality. Attempts to
reform society through state intervention or other means would,
therefore, interfere with natural processes. Unrestricted competition
and defense of the status quo were in accord with biological selec-
tion. The poor were the unfit and should not be aided, whereas in
the struggle for existence, wealth was a sign of success. At the societal
level, social Darwinism was used as a philosophical rationalization for
imperialist, colonialist, and racist policies, sustaining belief in Anglo-
Saxon or Aryan cultural and biological superiority.
Social Darwinism declined during the 20th century as an expanded
knowledge of biological, social, and cultural phenomena undermined,
rather than supported, its basic tenets.
129
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
130
7 Metaethics 7
131
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
132
7 Metaethics 7
133
Chapter
Applied Ethics
4
A pplied ethics, as the name implies, is the branch
of ethics consisting of the application of norma-
tive ethical theories to practical problems. Some of
the most compelling issues in contemporary applied
ethics have arisen in the fields of medicine and the life
sciences, where continual technological advances have
created new ethical dilemmas for doctors, patients,
and researchers. Another set of problems has been
raised by the concern among growing numbers of
people in the West about the morality of traditional
ways in which humans use animals (e.g., for food,
clothing, entertainment, and scientific research). The
environmental movement since the 1970s, especially
the emergence of global environmental issues such as
ozone depletion and climate change in the late 20th
century, has led to renewed speculation among philos-
ophers about whether nonsentient living things, or the
natural environment as a whole, have moral value, and
if so whether inherently or by virtue of their close rela-
tion to other morally valuable things (such as future
generations of humans). Finally, traditional questions
regarding the morality of war and the value of peace
have been especially prominent in general political dis-
course since the 1960s, when the morality and legality
of the Vietnam War were questioned by a new genera-
tion of college students, activists, and intellectuals.
134
7 Applied Ethics 7
BIOETHICS
Bioethics is the branch of applied ethics that studies the
philosophical, social, and legal issues arising in medicine
and the life sciences. It is chiefly concerned with human
life and well-being, though it sometimes also treats
ethical questions relating to the nonhuman biological
environment. (Such questions are studied primarily in
the independent fields of environmental ethics and ani-
mal rights.)
135
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
Costly and difficult procedures like organ transplantation raise the question
of who should and should not receive lifesaving treatment. Christopher
Furlong/Getty Images
136
7 Applied Ethics 7
Issues in Bioethics
The issues studied in bioethics can be grouped into sev-
eral categories.
137
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
138
7 Applied Ethics 7
139
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
140
7 Applied Ethics 7
141
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
142
7 Applied Ethics 7
Approaches
Bioethics is a branch of applied ethics. To say that it is
applied, however, does not imply that it presupposes
any particular ethical theory. Contemporary bioethicists
make use of a variety of different views, including primar-
ily utilitarianism and Kantianism but also more recently
developed perspectives such as virtue theory and perspec-
tives drawn from philosophical feminism, particularly the
school of thought known as the ethics of care.
143
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
144
7 Applied Ethics 7
145
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
146
7 Applied Ethics 7
Policy Making
Global Bioethics
The field of bioethics has grown most rapidly in North
America, Australia and New Zealand, and Europe. Cross-
cultural discussion also has expanded and in 1992 led to
the establishment of the International Association of
Bioethics. A significant discussion under way since the
start of the 21st century has concerned the possibility of a
global bioethics that would be capable of encompassing
147
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
ANIMAL RIGHTS
Animal rights are moral or legal entitlements that are
attributed to some nonhuman animals, usually because of
the complexity of their cognitive, emotional, and social
lives or their capacity to experience physical or emotional
pain and pleasure. Historically, different views of the
scope of animal rights have reflected philosophical and
legal developments, scientific conceptions of animal and
human nature, and religious and ethical conceptions of the
proper relationship between animals and human beings.
148
7 Applied Ethics 7
Ancient Origins
Deliberate avoidance of flesh eating probably first
appeared sporadically in ritual connections, either as a
temporary purification or as qualification for a priestly
function. Advocacy of a regular fleshless diet began about
the middle of the 1st millennium BCE in India and the east-
ern Mediterranean as part of the philosophical awakening
of the time. In the Mediterranean, avoidance of flesh
eating is first recorded as a teaching of the philosopher
Pythagoras of Samos (c. 580c. 500 BCE), who alleged the
kinship of all animals as one basis for human benevolence
149
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
150
7 Applied Ethics 7
Modern Developments
By the early 20th century vegetarianism in the West was
contributing substantially to the drive to vary and lighten
the nonvegetarian diet. In some places a fleshless diet was
regarded as a regimen for specific disorders. Elsewhere,
notably in Germany, it was considered as one element
in a wider conception of vegetarianism, which involved
151
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
152
7 Applied Ethics 7
Philosophical Background
The proper treatment of animals is a very old question in
the West. Ancient Greek and Roman philosophers debated
the place of animals in human morality. As noted earlier,
the Pythagoreans and the Neoplatonists urged respect
for animals interests, primarily because they believed in
the transmigration of souls between human and animal
bodies. In his biological writings, Aristotle (384322 BCE)
repeatedly suggested that animals lived for their own sake,
but his claim in the Politics that nature made all animals for
the sake of humans was unfortunately destined to become
his most influential statement on the subject.
Aristotle, and later the Stoics, believed the world was
populated by an infinity of beings arranged hierarchically
according to their complexity and perfection, from the
barely living to the merely sentient, the rational, and the
wholly spiritual. In this Great Chain of Being, as it came
to be known, all forms of life were represented as existing
for the sake of those forms higher in the chain. Among
corporeal beings, humans, by dint of their rationality,
occupied the highest position. The Great Chain of Being
became one of the most persistent and powerful, if utterly
erroneous, ways of conceiving the universe, dominating
scientific, philosophical, and religious thinking until the
middle of the 19th century.
The Stoics, insisting on the irrationality of all non-
human animals, regarded them as slaves and accordingly
treated them as contemptible and beneath notice.
Aggressively advocated by St. Augustine (354430), these
153
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
154
7 Applied Ethics 7
155
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
156
7 Applied Ethics 7
157
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
158
7 Applied Ethics 7
159
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
Speciesism
Speciesism is a term that some advocates of animal rights have
applied to the practice of favouring the interests of humans over the
similar interests of other species. It is also used to refer to the belief
that this practice is justified. The inventor of the notion, the English
philosopher Richard Ryder, and others, notably Peter Singer, have
claimed that speciesism is exactly analogous to racism, sexism, and all
other forms of discrimination and prejudice.
An influential argument against the legitimacy of speciesism,
due to Singer, rests on the principle of equal consideration of inter-
ests (PEC). This is the claim that one should give equal weight in ones
moral decision making to the similar interests of all those affected
by ones actions. According to Singer, the PEC expresses what most
people since the 20th century would understand (upon reflection) by
the idea of human equality. The PEC implies, among other things,
that one should not give greater weight to the interests of whites or
160
7 Applied Ethics 7
males than one does to the similar interests of blacks or females. Race
and sex, in other words, are morally irrelevant characteristics when it
comes to evaluating the similar interests of different persons.
According to Singer, anyone who accepts the PEC must agree
that a broader version of the principle applies to animals as well as to
humans. If the PEC were restricted to humans, species would count
as a morally relevant characteristic on the basis of which one could
treat the interests of one kind of being as more important than the
similar interests of another. But it is unclear why species should have
this special status. There is no good reason to suppose that it is any
more relevant than race or sex. If this is correct, speciesism is just as
immoral as racism and sexism, and for the same reasons.
Most philosophers who reject this line of thinking have tried
to show that species is a morally relevant characteristic because it is
uniquely associated with one or more capabilities (e.g., rationality) that
are themselves morally relevant. Because, according to speciesists, all
humans and no animals have these capabilities, the PEC applies only
to humans, and speciesism is not equivalent to racism and sexism.
One difficulty with this response is that it is not obvious why ratio-
nality or any other proposed capability should be considered morally
relevant (i.e., why it should count as a reason for favouring the inter-
ests of any being). The main objection, however, is that for each of the
proposed capabilities there are counterexamples based on so-called
marginal cases. It is clear, for example, that some humansincluding
infants and the profoundly mentally retardedare not rational. It is
also clear that some animals are rational, if by rationality one under-
stands the ability to adapt means to ends in novel ways. The defender of
speciesism thus faces a dilemma: either the interests of humans are no
more important than the similar interests of animals, or the interests of
some animals are just as important as the similar interests of humans.
Speciesists have replied to marginal-case objections in various ways,
none of which has won general acceptance.
ENVIRONMENTAL ETHICS
Environmental ethics is the field of applied ethics that
considers questions concerning human moral obligations
to the natural environment. Two schools of thought, cor-
responding to two broad intellectual camps within the
161
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
162
7 Applied Ethics 7
163
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
164
7 Applied Ethics 7
165
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
166
7 Applied Ethics 7
PACIFISM
Pacifism is the opposition to war and violence as a means
of settling disputes. It may entail the belief that the waging
167
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
Norwegian philosopher Arne Nss was a key architect of deep ecology, a radi-
cal doctrine that develops preservationist ideas from the early environmental
movement. Erlend Aas/AFP/Getty Images
168
7 Applied Ethics 7
169
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
Political Influences
Since the Renaissance, concepts of pacifism have been
developed with varying degrees of political influence. A
170
7 Applied Ethics 7
171
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
172
7 Applied Ethics 7
Types of Pacifism
Personal pacifism is a relatively common phenomenon
compared with national pacifism. Members of several small
Christian sects who try to literally follow the precepts of
Jesus Christ have refused to participate in military service
in many nations and have been willing to suffer the crimi-
nal or civil penalties that followed. Not all of these and
other conscientious objectors are pacifists, but the great
majority of conscientious objectors base their refusal to
serve on their pacifist convictions. There are, moreover,
wide differences of opinion among pacifists themselves
about their attitude toward a community at war, ranging
from the very small minority who would refuse to do any-
thing that could help the national effort to those prepared
to offer any kind of service short of actual fighting.
173
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
Conscientious Objector
A conscientious objector is one who opposes bearing arms or who
objects to any type of military training and service. Some conscien-
tious objectors refuse to submit to any of the procedures of compulsory
conscription. Although all objectors take their position on the basis of
conscience, they may have varying religious, philosophical, or political
reasons for their beliefs.
Conscientious objection to military service has existed in some
form since the beginning of the Common Era and has, for the most
part, been associated with religious scruples against military activi-
ties. It developed as a doctrine of the Mennonites in various parts of
Europe in the 16th century, of the Society of Friends in England in the
17th century, and of the Church of the Brethren and of the Dukhobors
in Russia in the 18th century.
Throughout history, governments have been generally unsym-
pathetic toward individual conscientious objectors; their refusal to
undertake military service has been treated like any other breach of
law. There have, however, been times when certain pacifistic religious
sects have been exempted.
The relatively liberal policy of the United States began in colonial
Pennsylvania, whose government was controlled until 1756 by Quaker
pacifists.
Under the conscript laws of 1940, conscientious objector status,
including some form of service unrelated to and not controlled by the
military, was granted, but solely on the basis of membership in a rec-
ognized pacifistic religious sect.
In Great Britain a noncombatant corps was established during
World War I, but many conscientious objectors refused to belong to
it. During World War II, three types of exemption could be granted:
(1) unconditional; (2) conditional on the undertaking of specified civil
work; (3) exemption only from combatant duties. Conscription in
Great Britain ended in 1960, and in 1968 recruits were allowed dis-
charge as conscientious objectors within six months from the date of
their entry into the military.
Scandinavian countries recognize all types of objectors and
provide both noncombatant and civilian service. In Norway and
Sweden civil defense is compulsory, with no legal recognition
174
7 Applied Ethics 7
CONCLUSION
As this volume attests, the history of ethical theorizing
in the West is both enormously varied and deeply con-
tinuous. Although the eudaemonism of Aristotle and
the evolutionary ethics of E.O. Wilson are conceptually
as well as temporally very remote, both identify what is
morally good for human beings with the unimpeded oper-
ation of certain natural (or naturally selected) capacities.
Epicuruss noble ethics of refined pleasure and friendship
has distinct affinities with G.E. Moores ideal utilitari-
anism, which aims at friendship and beauty as well as
pleasure. The political liberalism of John Rawls is a far cry
from that of John Locke (in fact, Lockes view is better
described as libertarianism), but they are defended with
strikingly similar conceptual constructs and methods of
argument. In the area of metaethics, the sophisticated
contemporary debates regarding the truth and objectiv-
ity of moral judgments can be dizzying in their technical
sophistication, but they are essentially just elaborations
of ancient positions. And while the practical problems
addressed by contemporary applied ethics are in some
cases completely new, almost all of the ethical perspec-
tives from which they are examined would seem familiar
to philosophers of the Enlightenment, if not also to those
of ancient Greece.
In this respect the history of ethics is perhaps no dif-
ferent from most other branches of philosophy: progress
175
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
176
Glossary
anarchism Political theory holding all forms of gov-
ernment authority to be unnecessary and
undesirable and advocating a society based on vol-
untary cooperation and free association of
individuals and groups.
bioethics Study of the philosophical, social, and legal
issues arising in medicine and the life sciences; chiefly
concerned with human life and well-being.
chauvinism Undue partiality or attachment to a group
or place to which one belongs or has belonged.
compatibilism Thesis that free will, in the sense
required for moral responsibility, is consistent with
universal causal determinism.
conscientious objector One who opposes participation
in military service, on the basis of religious, philo-
sophical, or political belief.
corporeal Taking bodily form; tangible.
determinism In philosophy, the doctrine that all events,
including human decisions, are completely deter-
mined by previously existing causes.
egoism In ethics, the principle that each person should
act so as to promote his or her own interests.
Enlightenment European intellectual movement of the
17th and 18th centuries that emphasized the use of
reason and science to combat injustice and oppres-
sion and to promote the material and moral progress
of human society.
eudaemonism In ethics, the view that virtuous activity
is a means toward and partly constitutive of human
happiness, or flourishing.
euthanasia Act of painlessly killing or allowing to die
persons with diseases, disorders, or injuries that will
inevitably result in death.
177
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
178
7 Glossary 7
179
Bibliography
Eudaemonism and Consequentialism
180
7 Bibliography 7
Metaethics
Stephen Darwall, Allan Gibbard, and Peter Railton,
Moral Discourse and Practice: Some Philosophical
Approaches (1997), is an anthology that contains several
important contributions to the modern debate over
moral realism.
A philosophical defense of ethical relativism is
Gilbert Harman, Explaining Value and Other Esssays in
Moral Philosophy (2000). Thomas Nagel, The Last Word
(1997), is a philosophical critique of relativism of all
kinds, including ethical relativism.
Treatments of evolutionary ethics include Edward
O. Wilson, On Human Nature (1978, reissued with a new
preface, 2004); and Michael Bradie, The Secret Chain:
Evolution and Ethics (1994).
Applied Ethics
Helga Kuhse and Peter Singer (eds.), A Companion to
Bioethics (1998), features reviews of key topics in the field.
181
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
182
Index
A Aristippus, 43
Aristotle, 2, 4, 10, 1115, 21, 30,
abortion, 96, 136, 138139, 140, 52, 75, 120, 121, 153, 175
142, 144 artificial inequalities, 61
Academy, the, 18 Ashoka, 169
actual law, 65 Atlas Shrugged, 99, 101
act utilitarianism, 38, 47 Augustine, St., 122, 153154, 170
aesthetic pleasures, 14 Austin, John, 46, 80
afterlife, 10, 31, 35 autonomy, 84, 137, 143, 144, 145,
agent-causation, 118, 120 146, 148
akrasia, 4, 7 autonomy principle, 145, 146, 148
Alexander the Great, 17 Ayer, Sir A.J., 103, 124125
Alternate Possibilities and Ayn Rand Letter, The, 101
Moral Responsibility, 125
Amafinius, 37
B
Ambrose, St., 26
American New Right, 83 Bacon, Francis, 77
American Revolution, 76, 78 Bagehot, Walter, 129
anarchism, 53, 8283, 8486 Baier, Annette, 93
Anarchy, State and Utopia, beauty, 18, 42, 4647, 175
8283, 8486 Beauvoir, Simone de, 91
animal law, 154156, 158159 Behemoth; or, The Long
Animal Law, 158 Parliament, 56
Animal Legal Defense Fund, 158 beliefs, moral, 107108, 111
Animal Liberation, 157 beneficence principle, 145
animal rights, 148161 Bentham, Jeremy, 28, 32, 40,
Animal Welfare Act, 156 4041, 42, 43, 44, 46, 48,
animals, legal status of, 154156, 49, 79, 151, 157
158, 160 Bible, 24, 25, 76, 150, 170
anthropocentrism, 162, 163165 biocentrism, 162, 163,
Antigone, 7374 165166, 167
antirealism, 105106 bioethics, 135148
Apollodorus, 36 biomedical ethics, 135
Apology, 45 Blackburn, Simon, 104
Aquinas, St. Thomas, 75, 122, 136 Blueprint for Survival, 164
arete, 2 body-soul relationship, 10, 15,
Ariosto, Ludovico, 31 27, 3334, 35
183
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
184
7 Index 7
185
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
186
7 Index 7
187
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
188
7 Index 7
Mill, John Stuart, 28, 32, 3840, natural selection, 128, 129, 131
41, 42, 46, 47, 48, 7980, 84, Nature of Rationality, The, 89
90, 91, 123124 Nazism, 8081, 173
minimal state, 82, 8486, 89 Neoplatonism, 150, 153
Minucius Felix, Marcus, 26 New Left, 82
Mises, Ludwig von, 82 Nicomachean Ethics, 11, 14, 15, 120
monarchical absolutism, 7576 Nietzsche, Friedrich, 28, 110
Montaigne, Michel de, 31 nonmaleficence principle, 145
Montesquieu, 77, 78 nonnaturalism, 102
Moore, G.E., 29, 46, 103, 105, normative ethics, definition of, 1
124, 130, 175 Nowell-Smith, Patrick, 47
moral action, 46, 6970, 104 Nozick, Robert, 73, 8289
moral beliefs, 107108, 111
moral intuition, 41, 105, 124
O
moralists, 31, 102
morality of scientific inquiries, objective truth, 110, 112
141142 objectivism, 99101
moral language, 103104, 106 Objectivist, The, 101
moral laws, 69, 70 Okin, Susan Moller, 95
moral philosopy, 1, 11, 23, 72 Origen, 27
moral psychology, 94
moral realism, 104105
P
moral reasoning, 47, 94, 102, 103
moral responsibility, 71, pacifism, 167, 169175
114128 pain, 30, 33, 34, 36, 40, 41,
moral rights, 157 4243, 44, 148, 149, 157
moral virtues, 1215, 153 Palladas, 37
moral worth, 16, 163 Panaetius, 2122
motivation, 41 Parmenides (philosopher), 18
Parmenides (Socratic dialogue), 7
patient rights, 137138
N
Patro, 36
Narayan, Uma, 97 Paul, St., 26, 27
natural inequalities, 61 Pax Romana, 169170
naturalism, 102103 peace, 31, 33, 54, 169170, 171
naturalistic fallacy, 130 PEC (principle of equal
natural laws, 17, 47, 60, 61, 63, consideration of interests),
73, 7480 157, 160161
natural rights, 47, 64, 7382, 76, Perry, Ralph Barton, 2829,
85, 86 102103
189
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
190
7 Index 7
191
7 Thinkers and Theories in Ethics 7
192