The Handy Philosophy Answer Book
The Handy Philosophy Answer Book
The Handy Philosophy Answer Book
Naomi Zack received her Ph.D. from Columbia University, NY, and has taught at the University at Albany, State University of New York. She is currently Professor of Philosophy at the University of Oregon in Eugene. Her recent publications include: Inclusive Feminism (2005), Thinking about Race (2006), and Ethics for Disaster (2009).
Visit us at www.visibleink.com
THE
THE
Detroit
THE
Copyright 2010 by Visible Ink Press This publication is a creative work fully protected by all applicable copyright laws, as well as by misappropriation, trade secret, unfair competition, and other applicable laws. No part of this book may be reproduced in any form without permission in writing from the publisher, except by a reviewer who wishes to quote brief passages in connection with a review written for inclusion in a magazine, newspaper, or website. All rights to this publication will be vigorously defended. Visible Ink Press 43311 Joy Rd., #414 Canton, MI 48187-2075 Visible Ink Press is a registered trademark of Visible Ink Press LLC. Most Visible Ink Press books are available at special quantity discounts when purchased in bulk by corporations, organizations, or groups. Customized printings, special imprints, messages, and excerpts can be produced to meet your needs. For more information, contact Special Markets Director, Visible Ink Press, www.visibleink.com, or 734-667-3211. Managing Editor: Kevin S. Hile Consulting Editor: Ed DAngelo Art Director: Mary Claire Krzewinski Typesetting: Marco Di Vita ISBN 978-1-57859-226-5 Cover images: iStock Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Zack, Naomi, 1944The handy philosophy answer book / Naomi Zack. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references (pp. 447-466) and index. ISBN 978-1-57859-226-5 1. Philosophy. I. Title. B72.Z33 2010 100dc22 2009042559 Printed in the United States of America 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1
Contents
I NTRODUCTION ix ACKNOWLEDGMENTS xi
vii
Schelling Friedrich Hegel Arthur Schopenhauer Bernard Bosanquet Materialism, Marxism, and Anarchists Ludwig Andreas von Feuerbach Marxism Anarchism Psychology and Social Theory Franz Brentano Alexius Meinong Sigmund Freud Herbert Spencer Sociology and Philosophy
Logical Atomism Bertrand Russell Ludwig Wittgenstein Other Logicians Logical Positivism The Vienna Circle Ordinary Language Philosophy Analytic Ethics Analytic Political Philosophy Epistemology and Metaphysics after Logical Positivism W.V.O. Quine Hilary Putnam Philosophy of Science Philosophy of Mind and Philosophy of Language Noam Chomsky Jerry Fodor
viii
Introduction
What do we really know? What is real? Does life have a meaning? Do you have free will? These are just a few philosophical questions, there are hundreds more. They are called philosophical questions because they cant be answered once and for all and have occupied philosophers for almost three thousand years. You dont have to be a philosopher to ask questions like these, although you may feel like one if you read this book! The Handy Philosophy Answer Book has hundreds of entries about specific philosophers and their ideas. Each entry begins with a question about the philosopher, school of thought or time period, which goes to the heart of his, her, or its importance, followed by an answer, which is also a short overview of the main ideas in the chapter. And each section within an entry also begins with a key question. This answer is followed by further questions, and answers. Each question and answer can be read independently, or as part of its broader context. But you dont have to read the whole book to answer a question about a philosopher or an idea. If you go to the index and look up a name or a subject, you will know what page to find it on. The main part of the book, a Whos Who and Whats What in Philosophy, is divided into ten historical chapters, from ancient philosophy to the present day. The table of contents, index, and glossary, can all be used as guides to the chapters. If you dont know what a philosophical word or idea means, you can find the answer in the glossary, a series of explanations and definitions of key terms, historical periods, schools of thought, and other isms in philosophy. Philosophy is largely a matter of philosophers opinions and they rarely agree, but they do respect each others expert opinions. (This book is written by a professor of philosophy.) The bibliography contains a list of sources for the different philosophers, periods of philosophy, main subjects, and other reference material. You can use this book in different ways. If you want to learn the history of philosophy, you can read through the chapters in order. If you are interested in building a
ix
philosophical vocabulary, you can begin with the Glossary, first. If you are just interested in a particular period or school of thought, you can concentrate on that. If you are interested in all of this material as an introduction to philosophy, or to refresh what you already know, you should read the whole book from cover to cover (at least once) and then track down the material in the bibliography that further interests you. If you are still interested after you have done all that (that is, if the philosophy bug really bites into you), it might be a good idea to take a philosophy course if you are a student, or enroll in one at a local college, if your formal student days are behind you. A good part of philosophy lies in live conversation, so its important to find a context where you can talk to others who share your interests in this subject. If you are not enrolled in a course, there may be a philosophy club that meets regularly where you live, or you could look for such a group on the Internet. Naomi Zack, Ph.D.
Acknowledgments
I thank Ed DAngelo, Ph.D., for his editorial advice, consulting, copyediting, and proofreading for the first draft of this book manuscript. Ed is a Supervising Librarian at a large branch library in Brooklyn, New York, where, since 2003, he has led a philosophy discussion group for the public. He is the author of Barbarians at the Gates of the Public Library: How Postmodern Consumer Capitalism Threatens Democracy, Civil Education and the Public Good (2006). I am immensely grateful to Kevin Hile, Managing Editor at VIP, for all of his work and assistance in revising, copyediting, fact checking, and proofreading the manuscript, as well as seeing it through production. Without Kevins patience, diligence, and professionalism, this book would not have been completed and neither would it have been useful to the reader. Last, but also first, I am indebted to Roger Jnecke, Publisher, for his vision of a Handy Philosophy Answer Book for Visible Ink Press! Given all of the conscientious and expert help I have had with this project, all and any remaining errors and sources of confusion are wholly my own. Naomi Zack, Ph.D. Eugene, Oregon
xi
THE BASICS
What is philosophy?
Philosophy is the activity of seeking wisdom. In Greek, which was the first language of Western philosophy, philosophy means love of wisdom. One loves wisdom by trying to figure out what it is. There are many ways human beings seek wisdom, including art, religion, and lived experience. Philosophy is distinct because it seeks wisdom through the systematic use of reason. Philosophers focus on ideas, the meaning of ideas, and beliefs by analyzing them. They break them down into their parts and then build them back up again and combine them in new ways. In addition to analysis, philosophers reflect on what goes on in the mind and the world; they seek wisdom through intuitions of whole structures of thought or experience.
hilosophy is the only way to come close to answers to important questions that no amount of observation can resolve. For example, philosophy strives to answer questions such as: What is the right thing to do if there are 10 people in a lifeboat that can only hold six safely? What is the meaning of life? Can we prove that God does or does not exist?
Does philosophy only deal with the big questions about life and the universe?
Not all philosophical work is about important questions. Some of it may seem absurd to non-philosophers. For example, how is the mind connected to the body? Most of us know that if we want to raise our right arm and we are not paralyzed, it is the easiest thing in the world to dowe just decide to do it and the arm goes up. But ever since the work of the seventeenth-century philosopher Ren Descartes (15961650),
T HE BA SICS
As children, we often ask lots of questions of our elders about the nature of our world and the universe. Many of us seem to lose that interest as adults, but these are still central questions about the meaning of our lives that philosophers strive to answer (iStock).
philosophers have argued passionately among themselves about the right way to describe the connection between the mind and the body.
hilosophers have viewed God as part of the natural world or the human world, or present in both or neither in the natural world nor the human world.
tant thing in a human life? Do I have free will? Young children naturally ask why questions that drive their parents into philosophical answers, whether they realize it or not.
Metaphysics: the most general questions and answers about the nature of reality, what physical things are, what relations exist between different kinds of things, and the connections between the mind and the world. Philosophy of mind: how the mind works, whether it is dependent on the brain, how it is connected to the body, the nature of memory and personal identity. Aesthetics: the study of art toward an understanding of what beauty is and how artworks are different from natural things and other man-made objects. Ancient philosophy: the birth of Western philosophy from about 800 B.C.E. to 400 C.E.; it is composed mostly of Greek and Roman thought before Christianity. Medieval philosophy: The development of philosophical thought, from about 400 C.E. until the Renaissance in the 1300s in Europe in which Christianity, provided the dominant world view and organizing principle for daily life. Modern philosophy: the foundations of contemporary philosophy from the 1600s through the 1800s. Nineteenth century philosophy: The classical period of modern philosophy, in which Friedrich Hegel, Immanuel Kant, and John Stuart Mill wrote. Analytic philosophy: style of professional philosophy, which is abstract and technical, that developed during the twentieth century. Post-modern philosophy: school of thought that, in the second half of the twentieth century, consisted of reactions against many of the shared assumptions held by philosophers over the centuries.
T HE BA SICS
fter post-modernism, many philosophical subfields split within themselves when interest in continental philosophy (from France and Germany) introduced existentialism, phenomenology, and deconstruction to the field. Academic philosophers became embattled in their own culture wars. Empiricist or mainstream philosophers defended both their traditional methods and established canon against approaches that were more centered on human existence and experience and cultural criticism.
Whats the difference between the practice of philosophy and the subject of philosophy?
Besides being an activity, philosophy is also a field of study, like psychology, history, biology, or literature. When philosophy is studied as a subject, a lot of whats studied is the history of philosophy in the form of writings by past philosophers. At the beginning of the twenty-first century, philosophy is mainly an academic discipline, which branches off into specializations and subfields. As a practice, the activities of academic philosophers consist of college teaching and the writing of scholarly texts, which are contributions and additions to the field of philosophy as a body of knowledge that can be studied.
Did the study of some of the sciences get their start in philosophy?
Yes. Until the end of the seventeenth century, the physical sciences were called Natural Philosophy, and until the nineteenth century there were no social sciences. Social science work was done under the name of philosophy. Many sciences have their roots in philosophical debates. Western science began with the Pre-Socratics in the seventh century B.C.E. The Pre-Socratics were the first Westerners in recorded history to think about the world using reason instead of myth. Much later, Western science got another big boost from Isaac Newton (16431727), who practiced what was then called natural philosophy and persists to this day as physics. Chemistry also got its start through philosophical inquiry by Newtons contemporary Robert Boyle (16271691). In the early twentieth century, the philosopher William James (18421910) founded the science of psychology. And in the middle of
T HE BA SICS
The sciences that we have todayeverything from astronomy and chemistry to physics and psychologyhave their origins in philosophy (iStock).
the twentieth century, Noam Chomsky (1928) combined philosophy with linguistics to get the new field of cognitive science started. There are similar origins in the social sciences: ideals of government and forms of governmenttopics now falling into the category of political sciencewere first theorized by philosophers such as Plato (c. 428c. 348 B.C.E.), Aristotle (384322 B.C.E.), Thomas Aquinas (c. 12251274), Thomas Hobbes (15881679), John Locke (16321704), and John Stuart Mill (18061873). Karl Marx (18181883), who is credited with developing the theoretical foundation of communism and socialism, modified the ideas of philosopher Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (17701831). The first systematic historian was a philosopher, Giovanni Battista (Giambattista) Vico (also Vigo; 16681744), as was the first sociologist, the philosophical positivist Auguste Comte (full name, Isidore Marie Auguste Franois Xavier Comte; 17981857); and the philosopher Immanuel Kant (17241804) is usually credited with having founded anthropology. In the twentieth century, social movements have received valuable inspiration from the work of philosophers: for instance, the womens movement from Simone de Beauvoir (19081986), the civil rights movement from W.E.B. Du Bois (18681963), the animal rights movement from Peter Singer (1946), and the environmental preservation movement from Arne Naess (19122009), who introduced the term deep ecology.
ot at all! Many philosophers were eccentrics, and the history of philosophy is chock-full of bizarre incidents and unusual trivia.
T HE BA SICS
ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY
Why did philosophy start in ancient Greece?
The ancient Greeks had a broad democratic cultural tradition that encouraged individual independence of mind, the questioning of authority, and disagreement among peers. The sea-faring, trading, and warring nature of the ancient Greeks was conducive to the development of intellectual cosmopolitanism among the privileged classes in this slave-owning society. From the Pre-Socratics on, Greek philosophers were not merely thinkers, but also men of action, capable of leadership and civic involvement. Moreover, the Greeks were warlike and valued the virtues of combat, such as courage and honor. When it came to polite interaction, they did not hesitate to voice disagreement, a trait conducive to philosophical debate, as well.
11
G R E E K P R E- S O C R ATI C S
Who were the Pre-Socratics?
The Pre-Socratics (the term simply means those philosophers who came before Socrates) came from outlying Greek city-states located on islands far from Athens, which was the cultural center of ancient Greece. Their ideas circulated widely among Greek intellectuals all over the civilized Western world. In chronological order, the main Pre-Socratics were: Thales (c. 624c. 546 B.C.E.), Anaximander (c. 610c. 546 B.C.E.), Anaximenes of Miletus (580500 B.C.E.), Pythagoras (c. 575495 B.C.E.), Heraclitus (535475 B.C.E.), Anaxagoras (c. 500428 B.C.E.), Parmenides (n.d.), Zeno of Elea (c. 490430 B.C.E.), Empedocles (c. 490430 B.C.E.), Leucippus (n.d.), and Democratus (c. 460c. 370 B.C.E.). They were well-educated men who had enough leisure time to ponder deep questions.
12
The writings of Theophrastus, one of Aristotles students, helped philosophers learn about the Pre-Socratics (iStock).
What did the dialogue between the Pre-Socratics reveal about their philosophy?
The philosophy of the Pre-Socratics can be viewed as one big intellectual conversation. We can see the historical development of their ideas and a kind of progress in their thinking over time if we consider them in (more or less) chronological order. A pattern was thus developed as each generation of students carefully examined and criticized the ideas of their teachers, as well as the rivals of their teachers. Ever since the Pre-Socratics, philosophers have thought about the ideas of their predecessors and tried to perfect or disprove them.
13
Socrates, in Platos Theatetus, tells of the clever witty Thracian handmaid who mocked Thales when he fell into a well when gazing up at the stars. She said that he was so eager to know what was going on in heaven that he could not see what was before his feet. Socrates goes on to say: This is a jest which is equally applicable to all philosophers. For the philosopher is wholly unacquainted with his next-door neighbor; he is ignorant, not only of what he is doing, but he hardly knows whether he is a man or an animal; he is searching into the essence of man.
that way, a primary moving principle (a primary moving principle was a thing that was responsible for the movement of all other things), at the same time that water was held to be the primary stuff of the universe.
14
Anaximander called his primary substance, which cannot be perceivedonly things that are cold and wet or hot and dry can be perceivedapeiron, or that which is eternal and causes other things to change, but does not change itself. Apeiron, in other words, is that thing which cant be perceived itself but which is the origin of all things hot and cold, wet and dry, and for how these things changeit is responsible for everything in the world as we can and do perceive it. According to Anaximander, we see the Sun, Moon, and stars through holes in a cold, wet vapor that encloses Earth. On Earth, wet and dry have formed land and sea, and living things are the result of the Suns effect on moisture. All life started in the sea, according to Anaximander, a theory that actually anticipates the theory of evolution.
Most people think of Pythagoras in terms of his contributions to mathematics, but few realize that his work has also been important to philosophy (iStock).
15
music. Pythagoras went on to explain how number systems correspond to natural phenomena such as the movement of celestial bodies. Pythagoras insight about mathematics is relevant today, because mathematics is the language of modern physics. Pythagoras and his followers also had a great interest in numerology and theories of the mystical significance of numbers. They embraced music as the spiritual side of number and believed that the right practicesin daily habits and diet, as well as playing musical instruments could enable them to hear the music of the stars and planets. They were strict vegetarians, except for a prohibition against eating fava beans.
Heraclitus thought that the essence of life was an inconclusive battle of opposites (Art Archive)
Why did Heraclitus disagree with Pythagoras about the essence of life?
Heraclitus (c. 540480 B.C.E.) thought that the essence of life was an inconclusive battle of opposites. The logos, or rational ruling principle of the cosmos, which takes on the form of fire and is equal to soul or life, is a constant; within the logos, the strife of individual beings brings constant change.
16
any reasons have been given for why the Pythagorians avoided fava beans: a belief that fava beans contain the souls of the dead; the resemblance of the seed in the bean to a human embryo, so that eating them would be like cannibalism; fava beans seem to have the shape of testicles or the gates of hell; they evoke oligarchy or rule by wealth because they were commonly used to draw lots; and they allow part of the soul to escape in causing wind or gas Fava beans were the only beans available in Europe before the discovery of the Americas. Modern research has shown that some Mediterranean populations are deficient in G6PD enzyme, and one-fifth of those with the deficiency suffer kidney damage if they eat fava beans. On the other hand, young fava beans contain Levadopa, which in controlled doses can be an effective treatment for Parkinsons disease.
What exactly was Parmendides reasoning in his claims about the One?
Parmenides first assumed that reality, or what does not change, is One thing only. Given this, anything that is not that one thing is not real. Because something that is not real cannot have an effect on what is real, nothing can divide the One. The One, by definition, cannot move or change. Since the One is the only thing that is real, what we perceive as moving and changing is not real. Parmenides student Zeno of Elea (c 490c. 430 B.C.E.) defended the idea that reality is One and immobile and unchanging by showing how positing its movement and change results in absurdities. He is famous for his paradoxes. Mellisus of Samos (fl. 440 B.C.E.) added that the One is unbounded, or in our terms, infinite, and insisted that there could not be empty space.
What did philosophers after Parmenides assert about the nature of appearance?
Before Plato, there were several attempts by philosophers to rescue the reality of changing, moving components of our ordinary experience from Parmenides claim that the only thing that is real is the One, which does not change. These philosophers who came after Parmenides tried to establish the reality of things that move or change, or in other words, they wanted to reassert common sense against Parmenides mysterious claim that the world we think is real is not real, because it is not the One. Plato returned to Parmenides ideas as a foundation for a more elaborate distinction between appearance and unperceived reality, although for Plato the unperceived One
17
Zenos paradox of Achilles and the tortoise applies a slightly different principle to a race. Suppose that Achilles, in a race with a tortoise, gives the tortoise a head start. Before Achilles can pass the tortoise, he must get to the place where the tortoise has been. But because the tortoise will always have moved on from that place, Achilles will never be able to pass the tortoise!
was in fact many. Aristotle provided the most successful defense of common sense and of the reality of appearance by insisting that the world of appearance was real.
18
T H E S O P H I STS
Who were the Sophists?
In the fifth and early fourth centuries B.C.E. in Greece the Sophists were the solution to increasing litigiousness and education. If you can imagine a professional who is a cross between a lawyer and a self-help coach, that would be a good description of a Sophist. The Sophists put on public exhibitions for pay to teach Greek citizens how to succeed in their public and civic lives. They were constantly on tour, and some became very famous. Intellectually, the Sophists were a cross between pragmatists (in the common sense use of this term, not the philosophical one) and relativists. In our day, a pragmatist is someone practical who is motivated by results, rather than highfalutin principles or abstract theories. And a relativist is someone who believes that
19
there are no absolute truths or universal values, but simply what seems to be the case for individuals, and what they desire.
20
The Sophists insisted that moral beliefs should have rational reasons and be capable of defense in rational argument. In Sophistic treatments of morality, human nature was often opposed to society or convention, and the Sophists were on the side of nature. Finally, it should be noted that the Sophists practiced in an oral tradition, which Socrates was to bring to a level of elegant perfection that no single philosopher or school has equaled in the millennia since his death.
21
Does Gorgias conclusion that whatever is real cannot be thought make sense?
No, there is a gap in his reasoning. Just because thinking about a thing is no guarantee that the thing exists, does not mean that none of our thoughts are thoughts about what exists.
22
Some ancient Sophists believed the world was composed of four elements, and some considered them to be divine in nature (iStock).
rodicus (b. 460B.C.E.), a Sophist, was an ambassador for his home city of Ceos. He traveled widely and became rich from his exhibitions. One of his specialties was distinguishing between synonyms, and Socrates claimed in Platos Protagoras and Meno to have been his student. Prodicus had two versions of his talks: the one-drachma lecture and the 50-drachma lecture. Socrates joked that he would have been more learned about words if hed been able to afford the 50-drachma lecture. The one-drachma lecture had much larger audiences, but, according to Aristotle, Prodicus sometimes gave the larger audiences a bargain by slipping in the 50-drachma lecture for them. If Aristotles story is true, scholarly commentators have overlooked the possibility that the Sophists invented modern sales techniques.
who are ruled by them. In real life, Thrasymachus is believed to have traveled and taught throughout Greece, besides being famous in Athens. In a speech he wrote for a member of the assembly, he advocated for Greek unity and efficiency in government.
S O C R ATE S
Did Socrates really exist?
Socrates of Athens (460399 B.C.E.) was both a real historical person and the main character in Platos dialogues. In both modes, he perfected the methods of the Sophists in rhetoric, argument, and dialogue, but as a character in Platos later dialogues he appears mainly as a mouthpiece for Platos abstract philosophy. While there is some controversy about how much concerning Socrates, the philosopher, was invented by Plato, there is stable agreement about certain facts of his life. All agree that Socrates lived the principles he taught, the most famous being, The unexamined life is not worth living. Socrates father, Sophroniscus, was a stonecutter from Alopeke; and his mother, Phaenarete, was a midwife. Socrates himself was fond of referring to his philosophical manner of discourse as a form of midwifery. In Platos Meno, he uses this role to extract mathematical truths from a slave boy as proof of the presence of innate ideas in the soul, which are first acquired in a divine realm before birth. Sophroniscus was friends with Athenian general and statesman Aristides the Just (530468 B.C.E.), which helped Socrates become connected throughout his life with the leadership class of Athens. He served ably and courageously as a hoplite (infantry-
23
man) in the Peloponnesian War (431404 B.C.E.). When he became absorbed in philosophical activities, however, he became poor. Socrates wife, Xantippe, was depicted as a shrew in later writings about him, but he cared for his young sons, and asked his friends to provide for their (Socratic) education after his death. Socrates was condemned to death for not believing in the gods the state believes in, and introducing different new divine powers; and also for corrupting the young, according to the indictments related in Platos Apology and XenoA statue of Socrates is located at the Academy of Athens phons Apology. He died peacefully by his in Greece (iStock). own hand, drinking a cup of hemlock in preference to the escape arranged by his friends, which would have resulted in a life of exile. He refused exile because it was dishonorable and because he had voluntarily lived in Athens and accepted its laws throughout his life. To desert his city so as to avoid death would be disloyal in his mind. Socrates said he did not fear death, because he knew nothing about it. If there were no afterlife, dying would be like falling asleep, and if there were an afterlife it would enable a higher stage of discourseit would be heaven. Another interpretation is that Socrates did not have much to lose by dyinghe was already an old man.
was no man wiser than Socrates, although Socrates himself always said that he knew nothing. (The fact that he knew he knew nothing is said to have set him apart from everyone else.) Socrates would begin a dialogue by flattering his interlocutors about their intelligence or virtue. If they were willing to converse with him a process of careful questioning followed. From such interrogation it would emerge that the person he was talking to knew very little about the subject in which he was supposed to be an expert. In saying at the outset that he himself knew nothing, Socrates had nothing to lose, whereas his interlocutors would either be personally humiliated or unmasked as hypocrites or charlatans.
What are some key events for which Socrates is often remembered?
Although Plato imports the character of Socrates into almost all of his dialogues, the early dialogues are considered to present a more accurate picture of the historical Socrates, who left no writings of his own. At one time, Socrates studied natural philosophy with Archelaus, who was a pupil of Anaxagoras (c. 500428 B.C.E.). But by the time he took up philosophy in earnest Socrates main interests were in ethics. Unlike many Athenians, he claimed not to understand how ethics derived from religion. In Platos Euthyphro, Socrates encounters the eponymous priest on the way to his own trial and asks him what piety is. Euthyphro responds that piety is what the gods love. Socrates asks him if piety is good because the gods love it, or if the gods love it because it is good. If something is good because the gods love it, then we need to know which gods to follow, because the gods often disagree. But if the gods love something because it is already good, then there must be a standard of goodness, or in this case, piety, which is separate from the gods. That means that the gods are not in themselves the source of morality. Euthyphro, of course, has no answer to this dilemma, and scurries away from Socrates. In the Apology, Socrates taunts and baits the young prosecutor Meletus in a display of dialectic that is exactly what he is on trial for. He relates how he began talking to the experts in the arts and government to seek wisdom, but found that apart from their high birth, wealth, or respected positions, these experts knew less than he. Socrates swears that he has always served Athens, first as a soldier and then as a citizen concerned for the virtue of its youth. He avows his own belief in the approved gods and denies that he ever tried to introduce new gods. The jury of 450 convict him with a majority of 30. Socrates has the right to make an alternative proposal to the death sentence. Voluntary exile would be an appropriate alternative, but instead Socrates suggests that he be given free meals in the Prytaneum for the rest of his life, in place of some charioteer (the charioteers were champion chariot drivers who had high status as popular heroes, as well as athletes.) The charioteers, Socrates says, only make people feel good, while he directly attends to
25
Socrates death is depicted in this 1876 engraving. He was convicted in a trial for not having the correct belief in the gods and for corrupting the young (iStock).
their well-being. He also proposes first a fine of one mina, and then, at the insistence of his friends, 30 minae (still an absurdly small sum against a sentence of death). The court is not moved by Socrates counter proposal and the death sentence stands. In the introduction to Platos Republic, Socrates sets up the purpose of this utopian work, by talking to a group of friends about the nature of justice. Here, Thrasymachus says that justice is whatever serves those in power. Socrates follows with a description of the psychology of a just person, but this does not answer the question of what justice itself is. Socrates then suggests that justice in individuals is difficult to define, but that insofar as the state is the individual writ large, it might be easier to understand what makes a state just and answer the question in that way. The Republic proper is Platos description of a just state.
26
What is Aristophanes comedy The Clouds and how does it relate to Socrates?
Aristophanes comedy The Clouds (423 B.C.E.) is considered a satire of Socrates and other intellectuals of the day. In the story, Strepsiades is an Athenian who has been plunged into debt by his spoiled, extravagant son, Pheidippides. Socrates appears, suspended in air, and asks Strepsiades to remove his clothes before entering his Thinkery. Socrates proceeds to relate his discoveries, which include the distance a flea can jump and determining if a gnat is whistling or farting. He insists that a vortex, and not Zeus, is the cause of rain. The play continues with absurdities such as Socrates stealing from a nearby wrestling school to feed his students, and insults to the audience in the course of a debate about new and old logic. At the end, Stepsiades son, who has been schooled in the Thinkery, tells Stepsiades that it would be morally right for him to beat both his father and his mother. The outraged Stepsiades sets the Thinkery on fire and viciously beats up Socrates and his students. Some believed that The Clouds contributed to the slander against Socrates that led to his trial and death sentence. But Socrates is said to have appeared on stage after the first performance and waved to the audience. And in Platos Symposium, Socrates and Aristophanes are depicted drinking together and conversing in friendship.
P L ATO
What do we know for sure about Platos life?
Although Plato (427347 B.C.E.) is perhaps the most influential and highly revered philosopher in the Western tradition, and thousands of philosophical careers have been based on his ideas, little is known about his life, with certainty. This is partly because there was a convention in Platos time that philosophers writing about their contemporaries not mention them by name. Nevertheless, there is agreement on some broad facts about Platos life. Plato, for instance, was present at Socrates trial and began his own philosophical works about 15 or 20 years later. Plato was the scion of a politically well-placed, rich aristocratic family who were anti-democrats. At first, Plato envisioned a political career for himself, but after the democrats gained power and Socrates was sentenced to death, he prudently avoided politics. Plato served in military campaigns in the war against Sparta and was probably in the cavalry. In the 380s B.C.E., he traveled to Egypt and Syracuse in Sicily. Plato went to Syracuse three times as guest of the tyrant Dionysius the Elder, and then of his son Dionysius the Younger. Both father and son were thought to be interested in Platos ideas about government, but the results of Platos involvement in Sicilian statecraft are usually referred to as disastrous. Plato never married, and when he died at the age of 81 he was relatively poor.
27
A Roman statue of Plato. The Romans admired the Greeks and adapted much Greek culture to their own (iStock).
Platos academy was probably cofounded by Theatetus (417369 B.C.E., after whom Plato named a dialogue) and Eudoxus (c. 408c. 347 B.C.E.), astronomer and mathematician. Lectures were given to seated students who took notes. There were probably never more than 100 students in attendance at a time, and it is not certain that Plato himself lectured there.
28
are the Phaedo, Symposium, Republic, and Phaedrus (believed to have been written in that order), and these were followed by later works of the Sophist, Statesman, and Philebus. Platos Timaeus may fall somewhere either in the middle or late writings. His Letters, numbered I through XIII, were written toward the end of his life. Only Letters III, VII, VIII, and XIII are unquestionably genuine, as is his will. There were no printing presses in Platos day and no book stores or libraries in Athens at the time he wrote. His dialogues probably reached their audiences through oral performances, and it is likely that Plato himself enacted the role of Socrates.
What were Platos main ideas as presented and developed in his early dialogues?
The early dialogues are very argumentative, and they display the Socratic method. Socrates is the main character, who begins by asking a question. Conclusions are not reached so much as questions are raised and clarified. The subject is morality, beginning with shared values such as piety or justice and then demonstrating how little is really known about them. In the Meno, Socrates plies his questions toward the more positive end of showing how knowledge is innate in the soul. Meno is an uneducated slave boy from whom Socrates extracts knowledge of geometry through a series of skillful questions. Socrates concludes that because the soul acquired knowledge before birth, what we know is not learned, but recollected.
29
lato introduces the simile of the cave in the Republic to convey the power of the experience of forms and describe their importance. It is his metaphysics in a poetic nutshell. Imagine a cave where prisoners are chained to the wall and the only objects they can see are shadows of things carried behind a fire in back of them. If a prisoner is freed, he will first encounter the objects in the cave whose shadows he has seen before. If he ascends out of the cave, imagine his amazement when he sees these objects, and the rest of the world, in full sunlight. Imagine also how his fellow prisoners might react if he attempts to relate what he has seen to them. The cave represents normal existence and perception, and the objects in sunlight are the world of the forms.
justice is a kind of division of labor that is mirrored in the tri-part division of the human being, or soul, into body, emotions and spirit, and reason. (For Plato, what we experience as the body belonged to the realm of mere appearance.) Just as human beings are happiest when their reason rules, it is necessary that the ideal city be ruled by those in whom reason is most perfect: namely, philosopher kings and queens. Below the rulers are a guardian class of police and soldiers, who correspond to the spirited part of an individual soul, and at the bottom are the mechanics, servants and farmers, who are like the appetites, or an individuals physical body. To ensure that the rulers love and serve their city above all else, Plato suggests that the family be abolished. In his social structure, men and women do not have to base their lives on their biological reproductive roles. Private property is unnecessary, too, as are monogamous sexual relationships or traditional marriage. The smartest, healthiest, and altogether best boys and girls will be specially trained, beginning with a simple diet, plain living conditions, and exercise in the open air. Because the poets lie and teach impiety, there will be no literature in the new curriculum. In young adulthood, the young rulers will be taught mathematics and philosophy. At the age of 35, they will be sent out into the world for 15 years to serve the community as lower administrators, police, and soldiers. At the age of 50, they will be ready to rule, all the more so because it will be against their desire to devote the rest of their lives to study of the forms. (Plato, like many since him, believed that those who do not wish to rule are the very ones who should rule.)
Now take a line which has been cut into two unequal parts and divide each of them again in the same proportion, and suppose the two main divisions to answer, one to the visible and the other to the intelligible, and then compare the subdivisions in respect of their clearness and want of clearness, and you will find that the first section in the sphere of the visible consists of images. And by images I mean, in the first place, shadows, and in the second place, reflections in water and in solid, smooth and polished bodies and the like: Do you understand? What Socrates hoped his listeners would understand was that what they saw through sight was less clear and further from the truth than what they were able to see in their minds eye or understanding.
31
AR I STOTLE
What was Aristotles main contribution to Western philosophy?
32
Aristotle (384322 B.C.E.) curbed the strain of intellectual mysticism that had been inaugurated by Parmenides (c. 515450 B.C.E.) and he formalized common sense in
ways that checked the speculative excesses of his teacher, Plato (c. 428c. 348 B.C.E.). This enabled a solid foundation for empiricism, or knowledge based on sensory observation and direct experience. Aristotle accomplished his task via encyclopedic accounts of the existing knowledge of his day, assessments of that knowledge, and developments of it into new areas, using new methods of thought. He was a rare combination of a highly well-informed and diligent scholar and an original thinker. Like his nineteenth century successor Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (17701831), Aristotle was capable of thinking the whole world. But unlike Hegel, he thought of the whole world not as an abstract and speculative theorist would but as an ordinary person would, if he or she could do that.
A statue of Aristotle is located at a park named in his honor in Stagira, Halkidiki, Greece (iStock).
33
Scholars now agree that the following works of Aristotle have been lost: dialogues in the same style as Plato; a vast collection of natural observations; popular publications; lectures on the good and Platos forms; as many as 158 constitutions for Greek states, of which only the one for Athens survives. In the first century C.E., Andronicus of Rhodes organized the existing Aristotelian corpus into its present form, but the earliest transcriptions of this are from the ninth century. The first critical edition of Aristotles works was published by the Berlin Academy in 1831. It is estimated to represent as little as a fifth of Aristotles total output, but in amounting to about 1,500 pages of small print in typical translations of Aristotles collected works, it provides a substantial basis for scholarly reference today.
whom he also named his work on ethics. When Alexander, now Alexander the Great, died in 325 B.C.E., Aristotle retired to Chalcis, where he lived for the remainder of his life.
What are some of Aristotles works and what are they about?
Aristotles Organon consists of six early works: Categories, On Interpretation, Prior Analytics, Posterior Analytics, Topics, and Sophistical Refutations. These, together with the Physics and the Metaphysic, address logic, language, the nature of scientific inquiry, and what philosophers have since called ontology, which is the study of things that are real or things that exist. These works demonstrate a systematic philosophic method of analysis and provide the results of that method in general areas of human knowledge. More specific scientific accounts are found in Aristotles On Generation and Corruption, On the Heavens, and Meteorology. On the Soul deals with the general functions of the mind, which in Aristotles Parva Naturalis are applied to specific functions, such as remembering, dreaming, sleeping, and waking. Aristotles works on biology include the History of Animals, Parts of Animals, and On the Generation of Animals. The Nicomachean Ethics and Eudemian Ethics constitute Aristotles theory of moral virtue, whereas his
34
political philosophy is put forth in the Politics. The Rhetoric discusses oratory and persuasion, and the Poetics contains his theory of tragedy as an art form.
What is a syllogism?
According to Aristotle, a classic syllogism has a major premise, a minor premise, and a conclusion. If the major and minor premises are true, then it is not possible for the conclusion to be false; the conclusion must be true. For example, All men are mortal is a major premise. Socrates is a man is a minor premise. And Socrates is mortal is the conclusion.
ristotle rejected Platos claim that only the forms are real and that there is another world of forms outside of the world that we perceive in ordinary life. But he agreed with Plato that knowledge must have certainty. Therefore, his main philosophical task was to describe what made objects real in this world and explain how we can have certain knowledge about them. He also developed a system of logic, or rules of thought, that would guarantee certainty if one began with premises that were certain.
35
36
37
should over-correct for our known faults. Thus, because we tend to be fond of pleasure, we should subject choices that are pleasant to a special scrutiny.
38
H E L L E N I ST I C AN D RO M A N P H I LO S O P HY
How did political events after the decline of Greece change philosophy?
The death of Alexander the Great (356323 B.C.E.) marked the end of the classical period in Greek philosophy. The Greek cities were unable to unify after great losses in the Peloponnesian War (431404 B.C.E.). The next 800 years marked a period of great instability, as the political and cultural center of Western civilization shifted to Europe. As Rome came to dominate Greece, the uncontested brilliance of the Greeks faded into the past. Toward the end of this historical period, Christian thought and practice began to define almost every aspect of civilized life. Some Pre-Socratic thoughtparticularly the ideas and practices of Pythagoras lived on after the decline of Greece; Platos work endured in new forms that were compatible with early Christianity. The Hellenistic or Greek-based forms of the new philosophies of skepticism, stoicism, Epicurianism, and cynicism spread throughout the Mediterranean world. There was little awareness of Aristotles work at the time, although empiricism was easily accepted.
What happened in Athens after both Plato and Aristotle were gone?
Athens remained the center of philosophy until the Romans sacked it in 87 B.C.E. Much of our knowledge of Hellenistic philosophical activity comes from the first century B.C.E. Roman writers Lucretius (9955 B.C.E.) and Cicero (10643 B.C.E.), and secondary medieval sources. Platos Academy became the New Academy, which was devoted to critical work on the thought of other schools. This was the beginning of the skeptics. Aristotles Lyceum, or the Peripatos, was first led by Theophrastus in 322 B.C.E., but after 287 B.C.E., it fell into decline until the middle of the first century B.C.E.
39
Carneades, head of the Academy in the second century B.C.E. The skeptics held that nothing could be known, and they preached epoc, which is the doctrine that all judgments, or conclusions or assessments, should be suspended. These academic skeptics posed problems, or tropes, to show that sensory knowledge is prone to error and reasoning does not necessarily result in certainty. They concluded that because we have no absolute standards for distinguishing between truth and falsehood, the best we can hope for is probable knowledge.
What was the debate between the Phyrrhonian and academic skeptics?
Pyrrhonian skepticism was founded by Aenesidemus in the early first century B.C.E. Aenesidemus claimed to be merely passing on the thoughts of Phyrro of Elis (c. 315255 B.C.E.). Sextus Empiricus (160210 C.E.) preserved Pyrrhonian skepticism in the second century after Aenesidemus. Pyrrhonian skeptics thought that the academic skeptics went too far in claiming that nothing could be truly known for certain. The Pyrrhonians preferred to suspend judgment on whether anything could be known. They held that suspending judgment led to ataraxia peace of mindin which there was simply no concern for what may or may not
40
lie behind appearances or come after them. Phyrrhonian skeptics were opposed to dogmatism and believed that their chief philosophic opponents were the stoics.
41
The Roman emperor Marcus Aurelius was also a productive philosopher who wrote on stoicism (Art Archive).
Seneca was a playwright, statesman, and one-time tutor to Roman emperor Nero. He was also a contributor to stoic philosophy (Art Archive).
The basic stoic premise is that we are obligated to understand the nature of the things we deal with and be prepared to accept, without fuss, unwanted events that are not under our control. Epictetus is famous for saying that if your favorite clay pot breaks, you should remember that it was always fragile and not yours to begin with. And if your spouse or child dies, that is a reminder that they are mortals, something that we should always remember about the human beings we love.
What is Epicureanism?
Unlike its namesake today, which connotes an enjoyment of good food and fine wine, ancient Epicureanism was an austere doctrine. It was founded by Epicurus (341271 B.C.E.) and his colleagues Metrodorus of Lampsacus (331277 B.C.E.), Hermarchus (dates unknown), and Polyaenus (dates unknown). Epicurus set up communities at Mytilene, Lampsacus, and on the outskirts of Athens, where his school was known as The Garden. Epicurean practice required detachment from political lifealthough not opposition to itand time spent in philosophical discussion with friends. Epicurus wrote letters on physics, astronomy, and ethics, as well as maxims, and a major work, On Nature, little of which has survived. He was an atomist, as Democratus (c. 460371 B.C.E.) had developed the theory, except that he thought atoms themselves contained sets of minima (parts of atoms that cannot be further divided). According to Epicurus, the atoms are in constant motion, with swerves and collisions that have resulted in the formation of bodies as we experience them. There is nothing godlike outside of life and society as we known them, and the gods should just be viewed as ideal models for our own behavior. Death is not to be feared, because we will
42
Today, we often associate Epicurus with the idea of Epicureanism, or enjoyment of food and drink. But Epicureanism actually began as an austere doctrine of serious reflection (Art Archive).
Antisthenes of Athens thought that a virtuous person could always be happier than a non-virtuous one and that the soul was more important than the body (Art Archive).
merely dissolve into our constituent atoms, which are incapable of feeling painor anything else. Epicurean ethics held that pleasure is our only good; it is better even than virtue. Pain is the only evil. Pleasure should be sought in stable ways, which makes a simple life necessary. We should satisfy only our most necessary desires in the company of friends like us. The highest pleasures are katastematic, or those related to satisfaction. The kinetic pleasures that result from stimulation merely increase our insecurity (they are like desires). Our ultimate goal should therefore be the absence of pain via a simple life for the body and the study of physics for the soul. This will result in ataraxia, or freedom from disturbance.
43
Diogenes, depicted in a painting by Flemish artist Pieter Van Mol, was an unusual philosopher given to rude and obscene public gestures that displayed his contempt for social conventions (Art Archive).
was very different from our modern definition of a cynic as someone who is skeptical and tends to believe the worst about people. The cynics derived from Antisthenes of Athens (c. 445360 B.C.E.), who studied with Gorgias (c. 485380 B.C.E.) and was a good friend of Socrates (460399 B.C.E.), even being present at his death. Antisthenes claimed to be proudest of his wealth, because, having no money, he was pleased with what he had. He thought that a virtuous person could always be happier than a non-virtuous one and that the soul was more important than the body. Antisthenes minimalist ideas about what was necessary to live well were carried on by Diogenes of Sinope (400325 B.C.E.), who lived in a wine barrel, claimed that cannibalism and incest were fine practices, and was said to carry a lamp in daylight in search of an honest person. Diogenes successor was Crates of Thebes (fl. 328 B.C.E.), who gave up his wealth to practice cynicism, but also married. He believed that asceticism was necessary for independence and claimed that lentils were better than oysters.
44
one is a friend or an enemy. Whats more, dogs, unlike humans, are honest. Like a dog, Diogenes had no use for family structures, social organizations, politics, private property, or good reputation. He is said to have masturbated in the agora (market place) and replied to those who insulted him by urinating on them. He also gestured at others with his middle finger. Plato described him as a Socrates gone mad. Because of his contempt for convention and knowledge of philosophy, many considered Diogenes a man of wisdom. Alexander the Great once sought Diogenes out, when the philosopher was bathing in his wine barrel, which he did often because of a painful skin condition. When Alexander offered to give him anything in the world he wanted, Diogenes replied, Please get out of my sunlight (or words to that effect).
WO M E N P H I LO S O P H E R S I N AN C I E NT G R E E C E A N D RO M E
Why arent there any women philosophers from ancient Greece and Rome who became well known?
The history of Western philosophy has been dominated by men for several reasons: 1) until the twentieth century, few women were systematically educated in ways that enabled the practice of philosophy; 2) womens family and social roles did not afford them the leisure to practice philosophy; and 3) male philosophers have traditionally seen the field as restricted to men and have sometimes gone to lengths to exclude women. Nevertheless, in every philosophical period some women have been associated with philosophy as practiced by men, and others have been philosophers in their own right. It cannot be known how much of the work of women philosophers has been ignored, forgotten, or never received the attention it deserved because, until the twentieth century, little work by women philosophers was preserved or even mentioned as part of the tradition. The ancient period in Greece and Rome was a foundation for this general, maledominated trend. Upper-class women were sequestered in special quarters in their homes and not educated for public life. Poor women were heavily burdened by motherhood, domestic drudgery, and agricultural work. Women with some leisure might sew, spin, weave, or listen to men converse, but always in their homes, whereas most philosophical interaction occurred in public places. Overall, women in ancient times rarely had the rights accorded to men. Nevertheless, the names and philosophical work of a small number of women philosophers in antiquity have survived.
45
Perictione I, Theano II, Hypatia of Alexandria, Ascepigenia of Athens, and Arete of Cyrene deserve specific mention.
46
When did women philosophers first start to become recognized as part of philosophy?
Beginning in the early Christian era, the scholarly work and educational activities of at least some women philosophers were recognized, and some male philosophers made special efforts to interact with them intellectually.
47
Was Christianity the only religious influence on philosophy after the ancient period?
No. Although, Christianity formed the dominant world view in Europe for over a thousand years, Jewish and Muslim thought also flourished.
N E O P LATO N I S M
What was Neoplatonism?
Neoplatonism was an elaborate system of religious and intellectual belief that was based on ideas about The One as the unseen source of all existence. As a powerful but unseen foundation for everything in existence, the One was similar to Platos forms.
49
dianus IIIs (Marcus Antonius Gordianus Pius; also known as Gordian III; 225244) army against Persia. After Gordianus died, or according to some accounts was murdered, Plotinus fled to Antioch, but then settled in Rome. He founded a school in Rome, became friends with Emperor Gallienus (Publius Licinius Egnatius Gallienus; c. 218268), and began writing down his philosophy. Gallienus intended to give Plotinus land to set up a community in accordance with Platos dialogue, the Laws (c. 360 B.C.E.), but others intervened, and Gallienus was soon assassinated by his own officers in the midst of a competitive military campaign. Plotinus himself died two years later, it is said, from leprosy.
Plotinus was the founder of Neoplatonism during the decline of the Roman civilization (Art Archive).
51
After the One, there is Intelligence, which corresponds to Platos specific forms, taken as a totality. Intelligence has an idea for everything that exists. Intelligence also contains number, which corresponds to souls, and it contains original matter. However, there is not an endless multiplication of ideas because, as the stoics proclaimed, every so often the entire world is destroyed.
Where does the soul fit into Plotinus system of Platonic entities?
All individual souls form one world soul, which comes after Intelligence. Some souls are disembodied, but those that are in bodies have additional accretions. Humans, animals, and plants all have souls that are immortal, substantial (that is, they are substances) and incorporeal (not physical). Because they are incorruptible, individual souls may be reincarnated in different bodies. The soul emanates or effulgurates from Intelligence, just as Intelligence emanates or effulgurates from the One. These emanations from the One and Intelligence neither detract from them nor are they willed. The same is true of the emanation of matter from the soul. Although the processes of emanation from the One, Intelligence, and the Soul are very natural, Plotinus (205270) sometimes speaks of them as selfish descents to lower states. In emanating from Intelligence, the soul is actualizing a desire to rule and it becomes too attached to its body, which can lead to its deterioration. However, even when it is incarnated, the soul also lives in Intelligence.
52
n his biography of Plotinus (205270), Porphyry (233309) wrote the following: An Egyptian priest came to Rome once and made acquaintance with Plotinus through a friend; the priest wanted to test his powers and suggested Plotinus to make the daimon that was born with him visible by conjuring. Plotinus gave a ready assent and conjuration took place in the Temple of Isis, because it was, as it is told, the only pure place the Egyptian could find in Rome. When the daimon was conjured to reveal itself, a god appeared who was not one of the daimons. And the Egyptian is said to have called out: Blessed are you, because a god is by you as your daimon and not some low class daimon! But there was no opportunity to ask anything from the apparition or look at it longer; because a friend who was watching and holding birds in his hands to keep the purity of the place, squeezed them to death, be it out of envy or vague fear.
Scholars have found this passage interesting because it introduces two new elements to ideas about demons in the ancient world: first, that demons could change into benevolent gods or angels; and second, that birds could be used to protect the purity of the soul. Socrates had a daimon who would counsel him in times of stress or alert him to what was important. However, Plotinus interactions with demons more resembles later ideas of magic and sorcery than simply listening to a voice, as Socrates did.
53
in a great multiplication of divine entities, or henads, with which Proclus associated Greek deities. He also developed the triadic ruling principle of remaining-proceeding-returning. That is, the deity remained what it was while its emanations proceeded downward to ordinary existence, and human understanding of this process and communion with the deity constituted returning. Aside from his spiritual work, Proclus wrote on mathematics, astronomy, physics, and literary criticism.
54
What is true of dogs in this sense is true of all natural speciesall of their members seem to share something. Plato would have said that a dogs essence is a copy of
an ideal form of dog, in which all dogs participate. Aristotle would have said that there is an essence of dogness, which can be known to human beings and which is shared by all dogs, but that the dog essence is in each dog and only abstracted by the mind. Strictly speaking, for Aristotle there does not exist a dog essence apart from Rover, Jake, Lacey, Mirabelle, or any other name that designates a unique animal. The problem of universals is the question of whether Plato or Aristotle was correct. Philosophers have agonized over this question and burnt many candles, oil lamps, and computers in the process. Those who think that the essences in individual things are real have been called realists. Those who think that essences are abstractions or creations of the human mind have been called nominalists.
How else has Bothius been influential long after his death?
othius (480c. 525) is best known for his stoic-Neoplatonic text, The Consolation of Philosophy, which he wrote while in prison after having been accused of conspiring with Justinian to overthrow Theodoric. This text was influential throughout the Middle Ages and beyond. It was translated into AngloSaxon, German, and French by 1300, and it inspired the writers Dante, Boccaccio, and Chaucer, as well as many, many others.
In The Consolation of Philosophy Bothius defined God as eternal and the complete and perfect sum total of never-ending life. The created universe had no beginning or end, but existed in time. Bothius resolved the contradiction between the fact that God knows everything and the fact that man has free will by claiming that God has a simultaneous understanding of everything that happens in time, including human freedom.
55
death sentence, but soon after his arrest, Bothius had said, Had there been any hopes of liberty I should have freely indulged them. Had I known of a conspiracy against the King you would not have known of it from me.
56
Hypatia was associated with Alexandrias prefect, who was opposed by Saint Cyril of Alexandria (c. 378444), the militant archbishop. As a result of her involvement in that dispute, Hypatia was hacked to pieces with sharp shells and her body burned by a mob of Christian monks. (The contemporary feminist philosophy journal, Hypatia, is named after her.)
M E D I EVAL P H I LO S O P HY
What was medieval philosophy?
Medieval philosophy was the historical period of thought from the fourth through the fourteenth centuries, which was dominated by religious concerns, the study of ancient Greek philosophy, and a need to reconcile rational inquiry with religious faith. It was mainly, but not completely, limited to the implications of Christian doctrine. Thus, St. Augustine (354430) in the fourth century gave Christianity its first philosophical foundation in politics and ethics; and at the end of the era Nicolas of Oresme (13231382), in working out Aristotelian theories of motion that were approved by the Church, he was able to anticipate infinitesimal calculus and coordinate geometry, before Galileos mechanical theories.
57
Roman states acceptance of Christianity as the official religion. Just before Augustine died, the Vandals were burning and sacking Hippo, where he was bishop. Augustines most influential works are Confessions, On the Trinity, On Genesis According to the Letter, and City of God. They all reflect his own faith after conversion and provide an intellectual structure for much Christian writing that followed. Although Augustines initial education was in rhetoric, his later studies in Neoplatonism deeply influenced his religious understanding. Still, he approached philosophy in terms of how it could serve religion, rather than as a valuable discipline in its own right. This secondary status of philosophy was widely accepted by philosophers throughout the medieval period. Augustine was one of the early Church Fathers and was canonized as a saint, by popular acclaim, as was the custom during the early centuries of the Catholic Church.
A stained glass window at the Cathedral-Basilica of St. Augustine in Florida depicts the churchs namesake (iStock).
58
Augustine believed that Neoplatonism anticipated the basic Christian doctrines about God, the creation, and divine presence. When he returned to his home in North Africa, he
was ordained as a priest and then became bishop of Hippo. He preached, traveled, and corresponded voluminously. In his scholarly and devotional activities, he came to believe that the Christian scriptures, particularly the Gospel account of the life of Jesus, were more important than the writings of philosophers. He concluded that more important than belief, which was an intellectual matter, was understanding, which began with faith: Believe in order that you may understand. Understanding required a vision of God.
What did St. Augustine mean when he said, Please God, make me good.?
St. Augustine (354430) considered himself profligate in his youth, much to the distress of his mother, Monica. In his Confessions, which recounts some of this early history, he is famous for having written what is often repeated as: Please God, make me good, but not just yet. However, some scholars think that a more accurate translation of the Latin is: Oh, Master, make me chaste and celibatebut not yet! They also think that Augustine was not so much talking about his past self as he was ironically criticizing all who lack resolve about developing their virtues and devoting themselves to God. Augustines sins were probably not as great as his oft-quoted remark has led many to believe. As a youth, before his conversion to Christianity, Augustine was fond of drink and women. He had an illegitimate son in 372, but was in a 15-year relationship with the childs mother, which would have been considered perfectly respectable at the time.
How did Augustine support the theology of the Church with philosophy?
St. Augustine (354430) tried to justify the whole of human knowledge, even though he also allowed for error. All knowledge, according to Augustine, resided within the soul as a substance endowed with reason and fitted to rule a body. While the soul can act on the body, the body cannot act on the soul. God is always present to the soul, whether the soul is aware of his light or turns away from it. These views of Augustine established the superiority of religion to philosophy and also embedded God in the same human faculty associated with non-religious understanding to the elevation of religious understanding. Augustines greatest work was The City of God, in which he separated the temporal state (government on Earth) from the religious realm of the afterlife. The temporal state was to have a secondary role in ensuring peace, order, safety, and physical well being for its citizens. The heavenly city, by contrast, requires living according to Gods rules. Although the temporal and heavenly cities may at times overlap, only Gods city is eternal.
Who are some Dark Ages philosophers who came after St. Augustine?
After St. Augustines death in 430, the so-called Dark Ages (roughly 420 to 1000 C.E.) ensued. In 420 the Visigoths living inside of Rome sacked the city. In monasteries in Italy, Spain, and Britain, the Encyclopedists emerged.
59
Johannes Scotus Eriugena (c. 810-877; also known as John Scotus Eriugena) was a Christian rationalist (literally, his name means John the Irishman, the Irishman.) King John the Bold called him to his Palatine School to translate The Pseudo-Dionysius. This document was falsely attributed to St. Dionysius (d. 268), a convert of St. Paul, although it was in fact written by an unknown Neoplatonist. Eriugienas translation was initially a success; building on its main ideas, he constructed his own system, De Divisione Naturae. His basic premise was that logical reasoning ought to be compatible with Christian philosophy. This meant that the teachings of the Church Fathers could be criticized, if necessary. More heretically than that, it left no room for faith in divine creation and salvation. Eriugenas treatise was condemned by Pope Honorius III (11481227) in 1225.
What did Pope Honorius III consider heretical about Johannes Scotus Eriugenas treatise?
In De Divisione Naturae Eriugena presented a Neoplatonic view of the world and cosmos that was also pantheistic. The Catholic Church did not accept pantheism, which held that God was everywhere in the world, because He was supposed to be separate
60
t. Isidore of Sevilles (c. 560636) encyclopediathe Etymologiaewas an ambitious attempt to compile all the knowledge of its day in one source. It contained everything that was known and believed at the time, with little critical editing. For example, under A was an entry on the atomic theory, but there was also an entry on the mythical Antipodes, who were said to populate rocky plains in the south of Africa. Isidore related that their big toes were not on the inside of their feet, but on the outside, which afforded them greater agility in navigating their rocky terrain.
from His creation. According to Eriugena, we cannot ascribe any natural quality from our own experience to God. That view was not a problem for the pope. The problem was that he described the created world as emanating from God in different stages: God created ideas or Platonic forms, and these created perceptible objects. The perceptible objects could not create anything but instead would ultimately be one with God, which meant that God was all in all, part of a circle that ended in himself.
TH E S C H O LASTI C S
Who were the scholastics?
The scholastics were the first heavyweight philosophical school of medieval times. Their eleventh-century founder was St. Anselm of Canterbury (10331109), who was followed by Peter Abelard (10791142) and Peter Lombard (11001160) in the twelfth century. During the same time, Jewish and Islamic philosophers reintroduced Aristotle to the West. This innovation culminated in the work of St. Thomas Aquinas (c. 12251274), followed by John Duns Scotus (12661308).
61
being than the greatest being that can be imagined. Therefore, that imagined being is the greatest being. Now, this greatest being would be everything and have every attribute that it is better to have than not to have: living, wise, powerful, true, just, blessed, unchangeable, non-physical, eternal, beautiful, harmonious, sweet, and so forth. That isand this is the crux of the ontological argumentbecause being is better than non-being, God will have being, which is to say, he will exist. Anselm goes on to claim that God, as the greatest being that can be imagined, is simple. Everything that exists is better insofar as it more resembles the creator of all things: namely, God. All created beings, which are created by God, owe their being and well-being to God. But God is independent and has no obligations to his creations.
62
How did Peter Lombard answer his question of whether God was the cause of evil and sin?
God is of course good and has a good nature. Out of this good nature, God created an angel. This angel became evil after God created him and passed his evil on to man. Evil in man resulted in sin. God was therefore not the first cause of either human evil or sin. (Lombards explanation is similar to how we would explain how a good parent has a bad childat some point the creation or offspring is morally responsible for itself and Lombard located that point originally in an angel.) Lombard (c. 10951160) wrote about this and other issues in his four-volume Book of Sentences (11451151) that soon became a standard text for theological training that was in use until the mid 1200s. Others would begin with his work and then develop their own ideas on its basis.
63
he story of Peter Abelard (10791149) and Eloise chronicles one of the most poignant romantic relationships in the Western tradition. It was referred to in the 1999 movie about a doorway that leads into the head of the actor John Malkovich (Being John Malkovich in which John Cusacks character refers to Peter and Heloise in the salacious dialogue of one of his marionette shows.) Well before this movie, Cole Porter wrote: As Abelard said to Eloise, Dont forget to drop a line to me, Please. In real life, Eloise had written to Abelard: The name of wife may seem more sacred or more worthy but sweeter to me will always be the word lover, or, if you will permit me, that of concubine or whore. Abelard, at the peak of his fame and popularity, assumed the position of tutor to Eloise. They fell in love, and he is said to have seduced her. She became pregnant, and they were secretly married. Eloises uncle discovered the whole affair. Claiming to be incensed by the secrecy of their marriage, he publicly denounced Abelard and then had him castrated. Peter himself recounted these events in his autobiographical work, Historia Calamitatum. Abelard told Eloise to become a nun and he himself became a monk. They carried on a correspondence of passionate love letters. Eloise was more enamored of Abelard than he was of her. Although castration was not an unusual punishment for the kind of betrayal of trust committed by Abelard, he was humiliated by his maiming for the rest of his life, and more or less retreated into his studies. Eloise became the highly successful abbess of a convent. Peter and Eloise were eventually buried together.
speaker who uses the expression. He did not think that words signify the images in the minds of their speakers. Meanings are what true or false sentences say or signify, which lies outside the minds of their speakers. The distinctions in Abelards innovative philosophical theory of reference remain relevant to contemporary philosophers of language.
I S LAMS I N F LU E N C E
How and why did Jewish and Islamic philosophy become part of the scholastic tradition?
64
Arabs, Berbers, and other Muslims invaded Christian Spain in the year 711 as part of their Islamic military campaigns. These military invasions were followed by a kind of
colonization, which supported lasting cultural exchange. The Muslims were inclined to tolerate Judaism as well as Christianity because it was also a monotheistic religion of the book (that is, like both Islam and Christianity, Judaism had its own Bible with one God). As result of the dual tolerance of Jews and Christian by Muslim rulers, the scholastic tradition, which was originally a Christian tradition, came to incorporate both Jewish and Islamic philosophy.
Was military invasion of Europe part of the religious practice of Islam during the medieval period?
Yes, but the Islamic religion was not opposed to Christianity. In fact, as one of three great religions of the book, Islam had much in common with Christianity, as well as Judaism. Its doctrine included a belief in one God, the importance of prayer, the idea of a church or brotherhood for all members of the religion, and the obligation to care for the poor. What was distinctive about Islam, in comparison to Christianity, was its rejection of the idea of the Catholic Trinity, requirements of fasting and other forms of bodily purification on holy days, and the necessity for every Muslim follower to make at least one journey or pilgrimage to Mecca. The
Philosophers owe a debt of gratitude to the Muslims, because it was Islamic scholars who rediscovered the works of the ancient Greeks (iStock)
65
continual importance of God and homage to Old Testament prophets was shared with Judaism, although, unlike Judaism, Islam had a positive conception of Heaven.
66
He was not a complete nominalist about universals, however, because he thought that there were differences and similarities among things of the same kind, which
existed independently of thought. The products of thought were the formal qualities of things. This doctrine, known as intellectus in formis agit universalitatem, neatly corresponded with Aristotles claim that scientific knowledge consisted in truths about forms or essences. However, although Avicennas interpretation of Aristotle seemed to be rather staid and unoriginal, his claim that it could be reconciled with Islam was soon challenged by al-Gazali (10581111); and in the generation after that it was radically revised, along with al-Gazalis objections, by Averros (c. 1126c. 1198).
The Persian philosopher Avicenna was an erudite commentator on the philosophy of Aristotle, among other talents (Art Archive).
What is Sufism?
Sufism is the mystical branch of Islam. Its classical period, or Golden Age, was from 1000 to 1500. Sufism is believed to have branched out from Baghdad to spread through Persia, India, North Africa, and Spain. The movement supported lodges and hospices for students, Sufi adepts, and others visiting on retreat. Sufi practitioners
67
were expected to go through different levels of spirituality. First were the stations, requiring acts of will and actions to suppress individual egos and attachment to and desire for worldly things. This would lead to Gods grace. Once Gods grace was granted it could be experienced individually as love, mystical knowledge, or the loss of ego consciousness. Sufism began as a marginal practice but was accepted by Islamic leaders in the eleventh century, mainly through al-Gazalis (10581111) efforts. Sufism then developed along distinct practical and intellectual directions. The practical paths required training in religious formulas and initiation into orders. It was accompanied by many fraternal and social organizations that continue in the present Islamic world. The intellectual path developed philosophical terminology and absorbed Neoplatonic influences, culminating in Ibn Arabis (d. 1240) system of theosophy. Within that system, God was held to be the only being. Everything else in existence was the result of his self-manifestation. The individual who could identify with all of Gods self-manifestations would have the goal of becoming The Perfect Man, thus far attained only by the Prophet Muhammad. It is perhaps ironic that this intellectual path of Sufism developed when al-Gazali had embraced Sufism as part of a belief that knowledge and reasoning was not a reliable way to experience God.
68
Averros continued the work of Avicenna, commenting on the debate about Aristotlean philosophy and its compatibility with Islam (Art Archive).
both advisor and doctor to the sultan of Marrakesh, who encouraged a series of commentaries on Aristotle. His writings include treatises on medicine and astronomy, but he is best known for his The Incoherence of Incoherence, which was a reply to alGazalis (10581111) The Incoherence of the Philosophers. In his Incoherence of Incoherence, Averros defended natural reason as a means to attain knowledge in all domains. By natural reason Averros, and others after him, meant ordinary thought processes rather than religious intuition or revelation. Averros also wrote a set of commentaries on Aristotle that was influential in Western medieval scholarship. When his interpretations of Aristotle did not square with his own assumptions, he wrote detailed supplements of his own. For example, Aristotles Physics and On the Heavens were composed as two separate works and based on different types of observations. Under Platos influence, Averros assumed that they were united.
MAI MON I DE S
What was the importance of Jewish philosophy in medieval thought?
Moses Maimonides, or Moses son of Maimon (11351204), who is also referred to as Rabbi Moses ben Maimon (RaMBaM), had an extensive influence on subsequent Jewish scholarship, the ideas of Thomas Aquinas (c. 12251274), and many scholars thereafter. Maimonides, like Averros (c. 1126c. 1198), was born in Crdoba, Spain, and, also like Averros, pursued an intense interest in Aristotle. While he intended his writings to be restricted to Jewish readers, his insights about the relationship between monotheistic religious beliefs and classical philosophical insights were studied by both Catholic and Islamic thinkers, as well as Jewish philosophers and theologians.
69
Why is Maimonides Guide of the Perplexed still considered a great philosophical text?
Maimonides (11351204) addresses his Guide to contemporary educated men who were intellectually torn between the claims of Greek science and religion. Maimonides intention in writing seems to be to help his readers understand philosophy, without giving up their religion. To weed out or not upset readers who lacked the mental fire power to follow his reasoning, he said that he deliberately scattered Aristotelian insights throughout the text, instead of putting those together that first occurred together. He often stated both a position and its opposite. In other words, Maimonides first step toward guiding those already confused was to deepen their confusion. But because Maimonides deepened existing confusions so brilliantly, his Guide of the Perplexed has attracted lasting scholarly disputation.
What are some examples of the perplexities Maimonides set out in his Guide of the Perplexed?
70
First, and perhaps foremost, was the question posed in Guide of the Perplexed of what kind of knowledge it is possible for people to have of God. According to the Doctrine of
In the Middle Ages, which was the Great Age of Religion, philosophers were constrained to begin their philosophizing with basic assumptions that God existed and that he was good. But philosophers have always been motivated to push through to the limits of knowledge and seek certainty within those limits. By deploying Aristotle as the personification of philosophy, Maimonides was able to raise necessarily covert questions of whether reason could justify belief in the existence and teachings not only of the Judaic version of God, but also of the Christian (and perhaps Muslim) God. We should remember that such questions, had they not been posed under the cover of the august and unquestionable authority of The Philosopher Himselfnamely, Aristotlewould have resulted in loss of livelihood, excommunication (banishment or ostracism from the community of the devout and faithful) and also death itself. Philosophers were not stupid in the Great Age of Religion, not withstanding their apparent devotion to varied theological regimes and their leaders, whoit just so happened!controlled all aspects of social, political, and economic life in Europe and the Middle East, at the same time that they upheld specific religious doctrines.
Negative Theology, which Maimonides took over from Avicenna (9801037), nothing positive can be known about God, because God has nothing in common with any other being experienced by humans, and humans have no experience of God. All that we can know is what God is not. (Negative theology is the doctrine that God cannot be known by man.) Second, there is a contradiction between the idea of God on which Judaism is founded, and the philosophical, Aristotelian idea of God. The philosophical idea is that God is intellect, whereas the religious idea is that it cannot be known what God is. Maimonides (11351204) sums up this problem with what he calls very disgraceful conclusions in the following passage.
71
Namely it would follow that the Deity, whom everyone who is intelligent recognizes to be perfect in every kind of perfection, could as far as all beings are concerned, produce nothing new in any of them; if he wished to lengthen a flys wing or shorten a worms foot, he would not be able to do so. But Aristotle would say that he would not wish it and that it is impossible to will something different from what is; that it would not add to his perfection, but would perhaps from a certain point of view be a deficiency. Third, Maimonides rejected the Aristotelian doctrine of the eternity of the world. Although he could offer no conclusive rational justification for this rejection, neither did he affirm that this was an issue in which religion was definitively correct.
T H O M A S A Q U I NA S
Who was Thomas Aquinas and what made him known as the greatest medieval philosopher?
St. Thomas Aquinas (12241274) was born in Rocaseca, Italy. He began his religious studies in a Benedictine monastery and studied liberal arts at the University of Naples. He entered the Dominican Order of Preachers when he was only 20. He studied theology in Paris, attaining his doctorate in 1256, and taught there until 1259. Aquinas then lectured on theology and philosophy at Dominican monasteries near Rome, and then returned to the University of Paris. He taught for a year in Naples in 1272. Aquinas died near his place of birth, while traveling to a church council in Lyons. During his teaching career, which spanned from 1252 to 1273, Aquinas wrote extensively. He lucidly solved long-standing problems in the interpretation of Aristotle, made clear distinctions between Christian theology and philosophy, and demonstrated how the two were compatible on many subtle points.
resolution of past philosophy with Christian theology is considered unique. Many of his solutions to standing problems display moderation without intellectual compromise. For instance, his position on universals (whether or not general terms name general things that exist), is even called moderate realism. Aquinas did not believe that universals exist, but he did posit a foundation outside of the human mind for universals and truths about them. That foundation was the fact that individual things of the same kind, which are referred to by the name of that kind (e.g., specific cats that are called cats) have real similarities and resemblances. Whether or not this solution did more than restate the problem remains an open question, but it definitely impressed many as a new way of thinking about the old problem of universals.
Was Aquinas able to solve the conflict between faith and reason?
St. Thomas Aquinas sits between Aristotle and Plato; St. Thomas is still considered one of the most important philosophers to have ever lived (Art Archive).
Thomas Aquinas (12241274) redefined faith as a kind of knowledge, rather than as a specific feeling or attitude of mind. As such, he said that faith fell between opinion and scientific knowledge. Faith was greater than opinion because it involved strong agreement, as an act of will, and it was less than scientific knowledge because it lacked factual evidence that could compel agreement. Aquinas thought that philosophy was reasoning based on existing knowledge or experience, leading to new knowledge, which he called the way of discovery. He held that philosophy was also the use of reason to confirm beliefs by tracing them back to basic principles, which he called the way of reduction. Philosophy becomes theology if the beliefs one begins with are based on faith. There are, in turn, two kinds of theology: truths in Scripture that are learned for their own sake, and metaphysics or explanations based on religious principles. Despite his theological idea of metaphysics, Aquinas did distinguish between philosophy and theology. For instance, in De Aeternitate Mundi, although he held the religious belief that the universe was not eternal, he said that it might be eternal based on philosophical reasoning. In general, apart from religious revelation, Aquinas
73
Aquinas thought that insects sprang to life in filth, owing to the Devils influence. He thought that the development of mice, however, depended on changes in the positions of the stars. As proof of this origin of baby mice, Aquinas had a recipe: Take some old rags and wheat and leave them undisturbed in a drawer for a while (to give the stars enough time to exert their effects) and then take a peek. Again, there is a crude empiricism at work here. If there are mice in a dwelling, its inhabitants rarely see them breed, and rarer still do they observe female mice building nests and giving birth. If this has happened in a neglected drawer, all that may be evident when one suddenly opens it is the litter of pink babies when the last time one looked there was nothing but old rags and wheat. (If you try this at home, the wheat is probably unnecessary, although the mother mouse will doubtless appreciate it.)
believed that we get our knowledge from sense experience and our intellectual understanding of our sense experience.
74
physical body is the matter or material of a human being, and its form or soul is its substantial form. That the soul can understand general truths and exercise free will proves its non-materiality. The reality of the soul is its spirituality. Because the soul cannot be divided, it cannot be corrupted and is therefore immortal. Furthermore, because the soul cannot be divided, it cannot be the result of biological inheritance but is made directly by God, each time a person is born. This divine intervention at birth gives the biological process of human reproduction a dignity and sanctity that elevates the institution of marriage.
O T H E R I M P O RTA N T M E D I E VA L P H I L O S O P H E R S
How was John Duns Scotus work different from Thomas Aquinas?
John Duns Scotus (12661308) was not opposed to Aquinas (12241274), but he brought St. Augustines (354430) thought into philosophical and theological conversations that were largely dominated by interest in Aristotle. Duns Scotus also drew on Avicennas (c. 9801037) notion of unified being in his idea of God as Infinite Being, who had appeared to Moses as I am who am.
75
John Duns Scotus helped broaden philosophical debate after Thomas Aquinas by reminding others of the work of St. Augustine and Avicenna (Art Archive).
Albertus Magnus was a theologian and philosopher who favored Catholic doctrine over the ideas of Aristotle (Art Archive).
Duns Scotus lectured at Oxford, Paris, and Cologne, where he taught that God had created each individual being with a unique nature or haecceity. Duns Scotus thought it was the will and not the intellect that is rational, because the will can will either one thing or its opposite. The will has both an intellectual appetite for happiness and selfactualization and a desire to love things based on their inherent value. These aspects of the will incline us to love God for our own good and also because he is God. Duns Scotus introduced a new idea of intellectual intuition, a kind of awareness that enables us to be certain of our own thoughts, and in the afterlife, be in the direct presence of God.
76
believing, for instance, that when the influence of Jupiter and Saturn increased the result was great fire, whereas when this influence decreased, there would be floods.
77
R E NAI S SAN C E H U M A N I S M
What historical developments helped to start Renaissance humanism?
The historical period of the Renaissance is usually considered to include the years from 1450 to 1600. This time is associated with the transition between the medieval and modern periods. From its beginnings in Italy, the Renaissance was marked by a new interest in literature, poetry, and painting in a shift of attention from the mainly religious preoccupations of life in the Middle Ages to the secular, perceptible world. The Western world changed, along with this transformation of values: the Copernican revolution radically reconfigured the place of human life in the physical cosmos; inquiries leading to the scientific revolution began; seeds for nation states were sown in political thought and action; the great age of exploration and travel by Europeans to Asia, Africa, and the Americas for adventure, science, and wealth began. All of these factors during the Renaissance changed the course of philosophy.
78
Marsilio Ficino was a priest who used the works of Plato to argue for Christianity (Art Archive).
79
resisted taking his side. When Luther criticized him for this, Erasmus responded with On Free Will in which he argued that it was impossible to know, as Luther claimed to know, that man did not have free will. Erasmus was not himself a philosopher, but he made fun of the preoccupations of the scholastics and inaugurated their subsequent reputation as intellectually trivial. Through his influence in Europe on its educational systems, Greek, Latin, and Hebrew became more widely taught. Overall, he was a great supporter of the kind of critical spirit that many scholars believe eventually produced the Enlightenment.
80
Sir Thomas Mores resistance to King Henry VIIIs selfserving policies eventually led to sainthood (iStock).
children from earlier marriages (including Elizabeth, who was to become Queen Elizabeth I) being declared bastards. More refused to swear to the Act of Supremacy, which affirmed the Act of Succession, and so he was committed to the Tower of London, charged with treason, and beheaded. More had always stuck to his own principles while in high office, and his refusal has been generally interpreted as an expression of his belief that Henry VIII had overstepped his royal prerogatives, first in declaring himself Head of the Church of England, so that he could seize Church lands and marry Anne Boleyn, and then in interfering with the royal succession. Mores last words were: The Kings good servant, but Gods First. More was beatified by the Catholic Church in 1886 and canonized as a saint by Pope Pius XI in 1935.
Why was Bernardo Telesio called the first of the moderns by Francis Bacon?
Bernardo Telesio (15091588) studied philosophy, physics, and mathematics at the University of Padua, receiving his doctorate at the age of 26. His subsequent pedagogical activity consisted of conversations with friends under the patronage of the Carafa family in Naples. He was also sought after by Pope Gregory XIII (15021585), who invited him to Rome. Telesios major work was On the Nature of Things According to their Principles. Telesios innovation was to propose that knowledge of nature be based on sensory information about matter and the forces of heat and cold. Because of this emphasis on sensory information, Telesio is credited with laying the groundwork for more rigorous ideas about scientific investigation, which would soon follow in the work of Francis Bacon (15611626) and Galileo Galilei (15641642). However, Telesios own theories about the workings of nature do not greatly depart from Neoplatonic perspectives. According to Telesio, heat, represented by sky, is the source of life and the cause of biological functions. Cold is represented by Earth, and it opposes heat. Heat also emanates spirit, which in animals and humans is located in the brain, for the purpose of anticipating and receiving sensory information. Man also has an anima superaddita, or mind, which is created by God and present in both spirit and body. All beings have a desire or impetus toward self-preservation, which in human beings includes a goal of everlasting life.
Who was St. Teresa and what were her main ideas?
St. Teresa of vila (15151582) entered the Carmelite order when she was 22, and there she sought guidance in how to pray until she was 47. In 1560 she became part of the reform movement among the Spanish Carmelites. Her main works were the Vida (Life), which was her spiritual autobiography, and Way of Perfection and The Interior Castle. Her main project was to help readers surrender to the divine Trinity.
81
Teresa held that mysticism developed in stages. In her Life, she says that the soul is like a garden. First, weeds need to be removed and then water must be carried from a well. The senses must be subdued to minimize distraction during this initial labor of prayer and meditation. The prayer of quiet in the second stage is like irrigation with the help of a water wheel; and in the third stage a condition of contemplation is achieved, which is analogous to having a running brook through ones garden. By this time, the senses no longer function normally and the soul wants to withdraw from the world and unite with God. In the fourth stage, this union is achieved. In The Interior Castle, Teresa uses the analogy of a castle with many rooms to describe a life of contemplation. After six early stages, the soul comes into the direct presence of God.
82
83
How were early modern and modern philosophy related to the scientific revolution?
uch of early modern empiricist philosophy, as developed by John Locke (16321704) and Thomas Hobbes (15881679), was directly inspired by the scientific revolution. Francis Bacon (15611626) had proposed that science could be used for the betterment of mankind and that was also Ren Descartes (15961650) dream. However, both Thomas Hobbes (15881679) and John Locke (16321704) took a practical and strictly empirical approach to knowledge that was closer to the science of their day than either Bacon or Descartes views. The scientifically grounded empiricism of Hobbes and Locke was later refined by David Hume (17111776) and codified by John Stuart Mill (18061873).
M I C H E L D E M O NTA I G N E
Why was Montaigne important?
Michel Eyquem de Montaigne (15331592), the essayist who became mayor of his hometown of Bourdeaux, France, resurrected the ancient Greek skepticism of Sextus Empiricus (160210 C.E.), with some reliance on Cicero. Although Montaigne lived dur-
84
ing the end of the Renaissance, his ideas set the stage for much thought that would follow during the scientific revolution and early modern philosophy. In the history of ideas and philosophy, he is therefore much more than a Renaissance figure.
What is fideism and what does it have to do with what Montaigne demonstrated about skepticism?
Montaigne (15331592) demonstrated how skepticism could be a double-edged sword: it could be used to reject irrational claims, and it could be used to attack the certainty of any body of knowledge, including scientific knowledge based on the senses and the conclusions of logical reasoning. This made skepticism extremely useful for Catholic theologians attacking the claims of Protestants, and vice versa. Today, we think of skeptics as those Michel de Montaigne showed that skepticism could be who require careful scientific evidence for used to effectively argue for either science or religion (Art Archive). claims and judgments. Usually a skeptic is someone who will not take anything on faith. But Montaigne showed that even the best evidence, including sensory information, can be doubted, so that for him, the skeptic is someone who is better off relying on faith. What Montaigne had in mind was not only faith about knowledge that could not be proved to a certainty, but a life of faith in which all attempts at rigorous knowledge were avoided. This is known as fideism.
85
ontaigne had sayings from Sextus Empiricus (160210 C.E.) carved into the beams of the rafters of his study. His favorite, which became his own motto and the motto of the Essays, was Que sais-je? or What do I know? The following aphorisms are excerpts from his Essays. Wise men have more to learn of fools than fools of wise men. From the same sheet of paper on which a judge writes his sentence against an adulterer, he tears off a piece to scribble a love note to his colleagues wife. Dont discuss yourself, for you are bound to lose; if you belittle yourself, you are believed; and if you praise yourself, you are disbelieved. Even on the most exalted throne in the world we are only sitting on our own ass. Fashion is the science of appearances, and it inspires one with the desire to seem rather than to be. He who is not strong in memory should not meddle with lying. I will fight the right side to the fire, but excluding the fire if I can. There are some defeats more triumphant than victories. Age prints more wrinkles in the mind, than it does in the face, and souls are never, or very rarely seen, that in growing old do not smell sour and musty. Books are a languid pleasure. Even in the midst of compassion we feel within I know not what tart sweet titillation of malicious pleasure in seeing others suffer; children have the same feeling. Few men are admired by their servants. The greatest thing in the world is to know how to belong to oneself.
matters that go beyond experience. Along the way to that conclusion, Montaigne discussed many conflicts of opinion that were relevant to disputes current in his day.
The Apology of Raimond Sebond. The essays here were far-ranging, witty, digressive, and all about him; his tastes, opinions, and large and petty problems. He also wrote about his trip to Germany, Switzerland, and Italy in his Journal de voyage en Italie par la Suisse et alAllemagne en 1580 et 1581 (Travel Journal), undertaken after he had presented a copy of his Essays to the French king. Montaigne was diplomatically active in trying to quell religious antagonism and instrumental in securing Henry of Navarres ascension to the throne as King Henry IV. He probably would have become a member of Henrys court had illness not intervened.
When discussing religious belief, which did Montaigne consider to be more important: reason or faith?
In considering reason versus faith as a foundation for religious beliefs, Montaigne (15331592) claimed that faith, simple belief, was the best course, because all reasoning can be shown to be unsound. Philosophical views had been in conflict since the ancients, so only Pyrrhonic skepticism, with its prescribed suspension of judgment, was acceptable. There was no certainty even in the knowledge of the new sciences, since the experts disagreed and scientific knowledge was subject to change.
Was Montaigne the only skeptical philosopher to reason in this Pyrrhonnic way?
No. Montaigne (15331592) derived his views from Sextus Empiricus (160210 C.E.), who held that we could not even know whether we had knowledge in certain cases. By 1590, Sextus Empiricus (150210) Hypotoses had been published in Latin, Greek, and English. Pyrrhonic skepticism died out by the third century C.E. Desiderius Erasmus (14661536) was a closer predecessor to Montaigne, who defended Catholicism based
87
on faith in De Libro Arbitro (1524) on the grounds that theological controversies were inconclusive. Martin Luther (14831546) responded to Erasmus with a dogmatic claim about his subjective certainty about God, based on his own conscience, as well as scripture.
Who were the main defenders of sense knowledge at the beginning of modern science?
Jean Bodin (15301596) and Pierre Le Loyer (15591634) offered defenses of sense knowledge between 1581 and 1605. They held that even though sense knowledge is sometimes unreliable, its errors are corrected by further sensory experience. By the 1620s two priests highly influential in both scientific and intellectual circles, Fathers Marin Mersenne (15881658) and Pierre Gassendi (15921655), used Pyrrhonic antiAristotelian arguments against Rosicrucianism and alchemy.
89
Who were the early seventeenth century free thinkers after Montaigne?
The free thinkers after Montaigne (15331592) combined Pyrrhonic skepticism with anti-Aristotelianism against both religious orthodoxy and traditional authority. The most famous free thinkers, or libertines rudits, were Gabriel Naude (16001653), Guy Patin (16011672), Franois de la Mothe le Vayer (15881672), Pierre Gassendi (15921655), and Isaac la Peyrre (15881672). Naude and Patin were humanists with little interest in scientific claims. But La Mothe Le Vayer took up skepticism to undermine scientific knowledge. Out of this group, only Gassendi had a lasting influence on the course of both natural philosophy (what we would today call science) and philosophy proper.
How did Pierre Gassendis compromises about the nature and limits of knowledge help the development of science?
assendi had shown how the development of science could take place without disturbing core religious beliefs. Like his fellow skeptics, Gassendi believed in God. Science could coexist with religion because science did not have to claim absolute truth, the way religion did.
professor of rhetoric at Digne when he was 21. After he received his doctorate in theology at Avignon and was ordained a priest, he became professor of philosophy at Aix. He also pursued astronomical research. His Exercitationes Paradoxicae Adversus Aristoteleos (1625) set out all that he thought was dubious and mistaken in Aristotles writings. His principle attack on Aristotle was against the possibility of certain knowledge in science. Gassendi argued against Aristotle (384322 B.C.E.) in his claim that certainty was neither possible nor necessary in science. At the same time, he sought to defend atomism against Church doctrine. Gassendi developed what came to be known as a mitigated or moderate skepticism that supported the conclusions of scientific inquiry.
91
what we experience to what has caused our experience, if we have not experienced that cause. Thus, if we have experienced the effect of something, but not the cause itself, we have to admit that we do not know the cause. Nevertheless, we can develop some useful bodies of information about appearances, especially if we augment that knowledge with atomism as a hypothesis. In Syntagma Philosophicum Gassendi asks if there is any certain criterion to tell truth from falsehood. Clearly, some things are obvious, even to skeptics, such as the sun is shining. It is what is concealed from us that causes difficulty: for example, whether the total number of stars is an odd or even number. Things like that can never be known. But, there are other things that are not evident that we can know by signs. Our perception of sweat, for instance, is a sign that we have pores in our skin. There are also naturally non-evident thingssuch as the hidden fire that causes the smoke we seethat we know through indicative signs. While we do not know that the atomic world exists, we can infer it from indicative signs in the world we do perceive. Gassendi thought that it would be needlessly metaphysical to speculate about the property of atoms, such as claiming that they are mathematical. He also insisted that atomic explanations do not apply to the human soul, which he believed was indivisible and immortal, as held by Church doctrine.
How did other philosophers and scientists react to Pierre Gassendis views?
Jean de Silhon (16001667)and Ren Descartes (15961650) tried to develop positive knowledge claims that would avoid Gassendis skepticism. Silhon argued that knowledge was possible because it existed in logic and the sciences. Descartes based his entire philosophy on an attempt to demonstrate the existence of certain scientific knowledge that would not conflict with Church doctrine. In the end, the Jesuits upheld Gassendis view that certainty is impossible and condemned Descartes.
thing that happens can be explained mechanically or mechanistically with the help of mathematics, general principles or natural laws must be supported by observable data, and, perhaps most important, that science itself is an exciting activity that will benefit mankind.
Who were the key players in the theories and practice of them in the scientific revolution?
Some of the key players of the scientific revolution were Nicolaus Copernicus (1473 1543), Ptolemy (90168 C.E., who was not of this period, but highly relevant to it), Galileo Galilei (15641642), Johannes Kepler (15711630), Francis Bacon (1561 1626), Robert Boyle (16271691), and Isaac Newton (16431727).
93
Does everyone now believe the scientific revolution was good for humanity?
ew can deny the value of an objective, factual understanding of the natural world. Modern technology that resulted from this knowledge has prolonged life, added to comfort, and made all human beings more mobile. There is also an understanding that knowledge should be open and that science is subject to revision, which goes back to the early days of the Royal Society. However, in the second half of the twentieth century, the objectivity of early modern science and its values were questioned by historians and cultural critics. Concerning the high value placed on experimentation, for example, it has been discovered that many of the experiments reported by Galileo (15641642) and Boyle (1627 1691) were thought experiments from which they deduced the facts, instead of having directly observed them. And Newton (16431727) himself did not actually base his three laws of motion on experimental data, as much as he logically deduced them from more abstract theoretical commitments. On the cultural side, Francis Bacons (15611626) perspective was based on assumptions that Earth and its creatures were all raw material for the manipulation and use of mankind. There was no sense that nature had value in its own right. In addition, some feminist critics have viewed the scientific revolution as a radical turn away from an ancient and medieval view of Earth as a living, organic whole, or mother to all who lived on it. They claim that this change in perspective privileged aggression and violence as virtues, compared to harmony and nurturance. Many crafts such as tanning, dying, and brewing, but most important, midwifery, became closed to women, as male practitioners took them over, based on more scientific principles, and moved them out of private households.
methods of objectivity were innovative, nevertheless. As the twentieth century historian and philosopher of science Thomas Kuhn (19221996) pointed out, the classical sciences of antiquity were astronomy, statics (bodies at rest or forces in equilibrium) and optics, which were all associated with mathematics and harmonics, so that advances in one led to advances in the others. In the sixteenth century, local motion (as something different from Aristotles idea of motion as qualitative change) was added to the mathematical sciences. In the seventeenth century, the mathematical sciences were revised by the addition of analytic geometry and calculus, new quantitative laws of motion, new theories of vision, refraction, and color, and the extension of statics to pneumatics (studies of air, fluids, and gasses). Still, Kuhn argued that Aristotle and the medievals also understood the importance of observation and experimentation. What was new was not so
94
much the addition of new fields or striking new discoveries, but a change in perspectivenew ways of looking at old things.
Copernicus heliocentric theory challenged the worldview held by the Catholic Church (iStock).
95
planets revolve around Earth. Copernicus became dissatisfied with the Ptolemaic system after his travels in Italy at a time when there was a lively revival of interest in ancient Pythagorian theories about the metaphysical importance of number for all aspects of nature. The Ptolemaic system was not mathematically elegant. But in Copernicus day the Church subscribed to the Ptolemaic theory, because that was the description of the cosmos given in the Bible.
How did Ptolemys view of the solar system become the accepted theory?
Ptolemy of Alexandria (90168 C.E.), using observations and existing written work between 127 and 151 C.E., codified the common sense of his time that the Sun and planets revolved around Earth. His work overthrew the more revolutionary writings of Aristarchus of Samos (c. 310230 B.C.E.), who in On the Sizes and Distances of the Sun and Moon claimed that the Sun is much larger than Earth based on his observations of our Moon. According to Archimedes of Syracuse (287212 B.C.E.), who combined mathematics with observations to found the science of mechanics, Aristarchus said that the fixed stars and the Sun remain unmoved, that the Earth revolves around the Sun on the circumference of a circle, the Sun lying at the center of the orbit. Aristarchus correctly surmised that to explain the apparent immobility of the fixed starsand assuming Earth did movethe distances between the stars would have to be huge compared to the diameter of Earths orbit. Aristarchus theory was defended by Seleucus of Babylonia in the second century but the consensus of educated opinion was that Earth was the center of the universe, either as a floating ball that the heavens revolved around, or a stable solid, which was how it appeared to humanity. Hipparchus of Nicaea (c. 190c. 120 B.C.E.) in Bithynia, around 130 B.C.E., put forth a theory based on the work of Eudoxus of Cnidos (c. 409350 B.C.E.). According to Eudoxus and Hipparchus, the apparent movement of the Sun, Moon and planets was the result of their presence in crystal spheres that were concentric in relation to Earth. It was this view that Ptolemy used as a basis for his mathematical calculations.
B.C.E.,
96
What is an epicycle?
n epicycle is a type of circular motion that is not observed but, rather, theoretically postulated. From the postulation, what could be observed became predictable, which was how it saved the appearances, or was consistent with what was observed. In the Ptolemaic system, the 80 epicycles were necessary to account for the different speeds and directions in the observed movements of the Moon, Sun, and five known planets. They also explained differences in how far the planets appeared to be from Earth at different times. The planets themselves were believed to move in small circles, which themselves moved along deferents, or large circles. Both the epicycles and deferents moved counter-clockwise in planes approximately parallel to the plane on which Earth was situated.
ances, which means that new complicated postulations were necessary to make the theory match observations.
97
opernicus phrase The Thrice Greatest was a reference to Hermes Trismegistus, the Greek name of the Egyptian god Thoth, who was credited with healing arts and secret knowledge by Neoplatonists.
98
Did Galileo contribute more than a defense of Copernicus to science and philosophy?
Yes. Galileo (15641642) is credited with having founded modern mechanics by proving the laws of gravity and acceleration. He also discovered the principle of independent forces and created a theory of parabolic ballistics that accounted for the trajectory of projectiles by positing parabolic arcs for their movement. His innovations in the technology of science included an air thermoscope, a machine for raising water, and a
99
kind of computer for geometrical and ballistic calculations. In pure science he discovered the isochronism of the pendulum (that the oscillation period of pendulums of equal length is constant) and he invented the hydrostatic balance (an accurate device for weighing things in water and in air). With the use of telescopes, he discovered the moons of Jupiter, the existence of mountains on our Moon, and Sun spots; he also described the Milky Way in greater detail. His claim that there were blemishes or what we would call sun spots on celestial bodies was in itself heretical to some Church authorities. Philosophically, Galileo insisted on completely naturalistic causes for the observable world, but he did not object to postulating remote or unobserved causes, according to a retroductive inference. His method of analysis involved taking effects apart and then theoretically putting them together in a new way to fit postulated causes. Insofar as this was a form of hypothetical inference, it is surprising that Galileo was unwilling to appease the Church by calling the Copernican system merely hypothetical. Galileo further angered Church officials, while supporting scientific researchers, with his claim that biblical accounts should not be taken literally by educated people.
J O HAN N E S K E P LE R S I N F LU E N C E
How did Johannes Kepler and Tycho Brahe help complete the Copernican Revolution?
Johannes Kepler (15711630) composed a mathematically precise theory of the Copernican system, and Tycho Brahe (15461601) furnished the measurements that constituted the factual data for the Copernican theory. Keplers theoretical work was what completed the Copernican system. Kepler offered a religious explanation for the spacing of the planets and postulated a driving force centered in the Sun, which diminished with distance, as the cause of planetary movement.
100
Tycho Brahe contributed to the heliocentric model by calculating measurements that helped confirm Copernicus theory (Art Archive).
astronomy and astrology. In 1596 he published the Mysterium Cosmographium, which was the first comprehensive work on astronomy that was based on the Copernican system. At the time, Graz was dominated by Catholics, and Kepler had to flee on religious grounds, because he was a Protestant. He went to Prague, where Tycho Brahe (15461601), the famous observational astronomer, had an observatory. Kepler composed a defense of Brahes observations against Nicolaus Ursus, who had attacked them as mere hypothesis. Kepler also claimed that, in addition to merely selecting the Ptolemaic or Copernican system, independent physical explanations are necessary. Using Tychos observational data, Kepler then began work on the orbit of Mars. After Tycho died, Kepler was given his position as Imperial Mathematician, and also complete access to all of Tychos data. In 1609 Kepler published A New Astronomy Based on Causes or a Physics of the Sky. Kepler then had to leave Prague for the same reasons he had fled Graz. After he went to Linz, his research included music, theology, and philosophy, in addition to mathematics (which included astronomy). In his 1612 Epitome Astronomiae Copericanae he again emphasized the importance of causal explanation, as well as observational predictions, in studies of the movements of the planets. His 1618 Harmonia Mundi was the final expression of this thought. He said of this work: It can wait a century for a reader, as God himself has waited six thousand years for a witness. Kepler was not the last great astronomer to believe he had special information about God. Isaac Newtons (16431727) work was to take the same high tone.
101
ences to human life in practical ways. He believed that human beings needed to master nature and conduct experiments to discover her secretstwentieth century feminists were to take Bacon to task for his assignment of a female gender to nature, compared to the maleness of scientists who were charged to conquer it.
What were the new logic and four types of idols made famous by Francis Bacons Novum Organum?
In his New Atlantis (1627), Francis Bacon (15611626) described a social organization for scientific research. His Novum Organum (1620) presented a new logic of induction, which would take the place of both Aristotelian logic and a simple collection of facts. The aim was to discover real natural laws or reliable generalizations about aspects of nature
Bacons system became famous for the obstacles to acquiring such knowledge, which he described as four kinds of idols. First were idols of the tribe or natural tendencies of thought, such as a search for purposes in nature or reading human desires and needs onto natural things and events. The second were the idols of the cave or the idiosyncrasies and biases of individuals due to their education, social background, association, and the authorities they favored. The third type were idols of the marketplace or meanings of words taken for granted when the words themselves did not stand for anything that existed in reality. And, finally, the idols of the theatre were the influence of theories that had already been widely accepted.
Francis Bacon believed that science could greatly improve the human condition (iStock).
Once the idols are eliminated what did this allow us to do, according to Bacon?
Once the mind was cleared of its idols, it would be able to discover causes through experimentation. Francis Bacon (15611626) thought that all of nature was made up of bodies or material objects that acted according to fixed laws. These laws were the forms of material objects. In seeking causes, first we must look for those things from which certain other things always follow. (For example, heat is followed by a motion of particles.) Next, we look for the cases where the effects do not happen when the cause is absent. (No heat, no movement of particles.) When what we are studying occurs to a
102
greater or lesser degree, we must be able to account for the variation. Whenever possible, we should invent instruments to measure what we are investigating. (In this case, thermometers and barometers.)
103
he British Royal Society grew out of the Invisible College, and the Invisible College was inspired by Francis Bacons New Atlantis.
Masonic friends. The famous poet Ben Jonson attended and said of him, I love the man and do honor his memory above all others. In 1626 Bacon was in London, traveling through the snow with the Kings physician, when he got the idea of using snow to preserve meat. They immediately bought a fowl, had it killed, and Bacon stuffed it with snow. He came down with pneumonia and ate the bird, hoping to regain his strength from it, but died nonetheless.
104
ed, this group and their friends, who had academic posts at Oxford, organized the Philosophical Society of Oxford. Following a lecture on astronomy at Gresham College by Christopher Wren (16321723) in 1660, plans were made to found a college for providing PhysioMathematical learning. Charles II approved their plans within a week. There were 115 original members. One third were scientists and the first president was Lord Brouncker, the leading mathematician of the day. This was The Royal Society of London for the Improvement of Natural Knowledge. It was presented with a silver mace by King Charles II at its inaugural meeting on July 15, 1662. It exists to this day, as an independent academy for scientific knowledge in the United Kingdom.
What ideals for scientists did the early Royal Society promote?
After a rejection of Aristotelian ideals of certainty in scientific knowledge, members of the Royal Society sought what was no more than probably true. Their ideals included open-mindedness, cooperation, and good will toward colleagues. It was as important to know what one did not know as assert what one did. Here is how Thomas Sprat, in his 1667 History of the Royal Society, described the virtues of a virtuoso: The Natural Philosopher is to begin where the Moral ends. It is requiste, that he who goes about such an undertaking, should first know himself, should be well-practisd in all the modest, humble, friendly Vertues; Should be willing to be taught, and to give way to the Judgement of others. And I dare boldly say, that a plain, industrious Man, so prepard, is more likely to make a good Philosopher than all the high, earnest, insulting Wits, who can neither bear partnership, nor opposition. For certainly, such men, whose minds are so soft, so yielding, so complying, so large, are in a far better way, than the bold and haughty Assertors: they will pass by nothing, by which they may learn: they will be always ready to receive, and communicate Observations: they will not contemn the Fruits of others diligence: they will rejoice, to see mankind benefited, whether it be by themselves, or others.
Robert Boylea scientist best remembered for discovering the law named for him about the relationship between volume, pressure, and gaseswas an inventor, theologian, and philosopher who was a member of The Invisible College (Art Archive).
105
106
What were some of the rather humorous experiments carried out by members of the British Royal Society?
he former British comedy troop Monty Python would have had a field day with some of the early investigations conducted by the Royal Society. And King Charles II, who was very interested in experiments in general, loved to make fun of the more preposterous ones. For example, at the Philosophical Society of Oxfordhosted by founding Royal Society secretary John Wilkins (16141672), who had written about the admirable contrivances of natural things in Mathematical Marvelsthere were, among Wilkins own collection, transparent apiaries and a hollow statue that spoke through a concealed pipe. Robert Boyle (16271691) was considered eccentric because he doctored himself and seemed to make a hobby of collecting medical prescriptions. By the time the Royal Society had formed, alchemy had switched from being a science seeking to convert base metals into gold to one with an aim of using new medical discoveries to prolong human life. Nonetheless, in 1689 Boyle worked successfully to get Henry IVs law against multiplying gold repealed. When Margaret Cavendish, Duchess of Newcastle-upon-Tyne (16231673), was granted a visit to the Royal Society in 1667, she was shown experiments involving colors, the mixing of cold liquids, dissolving meat in oil of vitriol, weighing air, the flattening of marbles, magnetism, and a good microscope. The Duchess wrote in her own diary that the new science was useless for solving social and spiritual problems.
107
sensed by us in objects made up of atoms. That is, the world of our perception is made up of secondary qualities, which are formed by interactions between the atoms in objects and the atoms in our sense organs. Secondary qualities are exactly those qualities of sense such as color, sound, texture, and smell that make up our everyday experience. But the real world was made up of atoms!
108
mathematical physics was published in Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica (The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy.)
What were the main elements of Newtons scientific system and what did they have to do with God?
Newton (16421727) used the model of Euclidian geometry to demonstrate the mathematical axioms describing the system of the world. He held that the world consisted of material bodies, or masses made up of solid corpuscles that were either at rest or that moved according to the three laws of motion. Preceding these laws of motion was a scholium, in which Newton stated the conditions of his entire system, which were: absolute time, absolute space, absolute place, and absolute motion. For Newton, the universe itself was like one gigantic box that never moved. (These absolutes were to become very important in contrast to Albert Einsteins theory of relativity.) According to Newton, God played an active role in his system in several ways: he was the first cause of the whole celestial system; he keeps the stars and planets from crashing into one another; he creates absolute space and time; and he corrects for irregularities in the movements of planets and comets, which might otherwise undermine the entire harmony of the cosmos. That is, for Newton, not only did God exist outside of nature as its immaterial and transcendent soul, but God was the real and practical ruler and regulator of the physical universe. He wrote, And thus much concerning God; to discourse of whom from the appearance of things, does certainly belong to Natural Philosophy. (This was religious science in religious times.)
109
ewton (16421727) is famous for three laws of motion and the universal law of gravitation, as follows. 1. Every body continues in rest or uniform motion in a straight line unless an external force compels a change. This is the Law of Inertia. 2. A change in motion is proportional to the force impressed and occurs in the direction of the straight line in which the force is impressed. F = MA, or Force equals Mass multiplied by Acceleration. 3. To every action there is an opposite and equal reaction.
Newtons general law of gravity stated that every particle of matter in the universe attracts every other particle of matter with a force that varies directly as the product of their masses and varies inversely as the square of the distance between the particles.
ers. His main quirk was his secretiveness about his work. He did not even communicate the success of his early research to others until 1669. To this day, it is not clear when he did what or which recorded intuitions correspond to what publications. After he got the position of Lucasian Professor of Mathematics at Cambridge, except for three or four weeks a year, he spent 26 years in Cambridge, lecturing on optics and elementary mathematics. That is, his life was somewhat sheltered. Part of the reason Newton hated to publish was that he did not like the controversy that was always likely to follow. When in 1684 the Royal Society appointed a committee, led by Edmund Halley (16561742), to remind Newton of his commitment to publish Principia Mathematica, Halley had to persuade him to include the third book, which contained the application of his system. Newton at first wanted to suppress that work because he had heard that Robert Hooke (16351703) claimed to have had the same system before him. (Indeed, when Newton had related his discoveries about the decomposition of light, or what the components of light are, to the Royal Society in 1672, Robert Hooke and others disagreed with part of how he explained his findings. Newton refused to discuss the matter or publish his work until after Hooke died.) The Principia manuscript was finally delivered by a Dr. Vincent, husband of Miss Storey, at whose house Newton had lodged in his teens. Apparently she had been the sole romantic interest in his entire life. Biographers relate that Newton had a psychological breakdown from 1692 to 1693, following unsuccessful attempts to get a prestigious and lucrative government position through the efforts of his friend Charles Halifax. Newton wrote to Samuel Pepys (16331703) that he was extremely troubled at the embroilment he was in and that he would have to withdraw from Pepys and his other friends. He then wrote to John Locke (16321704), apologizing for being of the opinion that you endeavored to embroil me with women. Locke was kind and reassuring and Newton apologized further, claiming overwork and lack of sleep. Apparently, there had been no basis in fact for Newtons belief in having been embroiled. Newton did have an embroiled dispute over whether he or Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (16461716) had first invented the theory of fluxions or the differential calculus. Through his office as President of the Royal Society, Newton exerted influence over the investigation of the matter, which was finally resolved to credit him with the discovery, although it misrepresented the time sequence of correspondence on the subject between Newton and Leibniz. Newton did no further scientific work after his position as Warden of the Mint. He referred to natural philosophy as a litigious lady and mentioned another pull at the moon. He was apparently preoccupied with occult readings of biblical prophecy and alchemical theories, although the nature of these endeavors is still unclear because he often wrote in code. Some contemporary scholars now think that these occult studies were Newtons main interest and that the greatness of his scientific achievements was largely the result of hype, after the fact. Newtons reluctance to publish or even con-
111
tinue his studies after he became Warden of the Mint might be less a matter of psychological instability than is often assumed.
M E D I C I N E AN D P H I LO S O P HY
What has medicine got to do with the history of philosophy?
The theory and practice of medicine is not usually associated with philosophers or the history of philosophy. Except for recognition of the ethical aspects of many medical decisions (for example, abortion, end-of-life issues, and cost of care), medical doctors do not seek out philosophical opinions, and philosophers do not view medicine as part of their normal range of subjects. Nevertheless, until at least the eighteenth century, medical ideas and practices concerning the human body were closely connected to philosophy in several ways. Since ancient times, beginning with both Plato and Aristotle, philosophers used the kind of knowledge necessary for the practice of medicine as an important example of the nature of practical knowledge, in general. For instance, doctors may agree on the cause and symptoms of a disease, but deciding that a certain patient has the disease and what the appropriate course of treatment for that person should be requires making judgments that go beyond the evidence. Such judgments depend heavily on what was done in similar cases in past experience, and that says something important about the nature of practical knowledge. (Aristotle said that because of the importance of the role of experience in medicine, which was not an exact science, it would be wiser to choose an older than a younger doctor.) In Aristotles time there was awareness that medicine had been part of philosophy during the pre-Socratic period. Beginning in the medieval period, especially in Islamic culture, many philosophers had practical training as physicians and were employed as doctors to their patrons. That practice was also common through the Renaissance and early modern period in Europe. Another link between medicine and philosophy is that, as educated thinkers, philosophers have always had ideas about the human body and its functions, which in their scientific aspects have come from the medical views of their times. Philosophers have also maintained an interest in human emotions and thought processes, based on theories developed by psychologists and their predecessors before the science of psychology existed.
112
Alcmaeon also investigated the functions of the different senses. Because the process of understanding was similar to the rotations of the stars, he thought that the soul, like the stars, was immortal. He speculated that sense organs relayed information to the brain through passages. When blood moved to the large blood vessels, the result was sleep, whereas when it became redistributed the result was wakefulness. The specific nature of Alcmaeons ideas, and his introduction to medicine of principles unique to that subject, forever changed the practice of medicine and systematic thought about the human body. As Alcmaeons successor, Hippokrates (465370 B.C.E.) was able to build on his thought and establish medicine as a science in its own right.
113
An illustration from The Great Surgery Book (1526) by Paracelsus (Art Archive).
edge of physiology by dissecting pigs and apes, since human dissection was against Roman law. He learned how to treat trauma and wounds while working as a physician in a gladiator school. Galen performed many operations, including brain and eye surgery (the removal of cataracts), which were not attempted again for almost 2,000 years. He eventually became a physician to Marcus Aurelius (121180 C.E.). In the ninth century, Galens writings were translated into Arabic by Hunayn ibn Ishaq (809873). However, the Arabs rarely practiced surgery, and among Christians, the knowledge and practice of surgery had already been abolished. Galen remained so highly regarded that when dissections during the Renaissance appeared to contradict his descriptions, they were considered anomalous. His prescription of bloodletting for almost every illness was followed as late as the nineteenth century.
114
In 1516 Paracelsus became a medical lecturer at the University of Basel, after he cured the famous printer Frobinius. His teachings against Avicenna (9801037) and
Galen (c. 129c. 216 C.E.) were controversial, and he was forced to resume his life of travel in 1528. Paracelsus introduced several lasting medical innovations: chemical urinalysis, a biochemical theory of digestion, wound antisepsis, the use of laudanum for pain, and the use of mercury for syphilis. His books were mainly about human nature and the place of man in the cosmos, but he also wrote important treatises on syphilis.
115
What were some noteworthy advances in medicine during the scientific revolution?
During the scientific revolution, William Harvey (15791657) correctly described and demonstrated the closed circulatory system of blood. Robert Burton (15771640) described (and lived out) the nature of psychological depression. With Harveys achievement, the inside of the human body could be understood as an orderly mechanical (hydraulic) system; with Burtons achievement came the recognition of mental illness as a secular, pedestrian process. Both achievements were practical and gratifying rewards for scientific investigators, as well as their public.
116
In this seventeenth-century painting, William Harvey is shown demonstrating how the blood circulates (Art Archive).
the Motion of the Heart and Blood in Animals) Harvey claimed that the heart pumped blood throughout the body in a closed system. Galen had believed that venous blood came from the liver and arterial blood from the heart, each of which sent blood to the different parts of the body where it was consumed. Harvey recorded his observations during vivisections (dissections of live animals), quantifying the amount of blood that passed through the heart and counting the beats of the heart. He estimated the amount of blood pumped in a day, depending on the size of the heart. He postulated two circulatory loopsone to the lungs and the other to the vital organsand he correctly described the role of the valves of the veins in returning blood to the heart. Harvey was personal physician to both James I and Charles I. That gave him the opportunity to vivisect deer from the royal parks for his experiments and demonstrations. He was also able to observe a pumping human heart in the hole of the chest of a viscounts son, whose wound had been covered with a metal plate. Harvey was not able to observe capillaries and could not account for the transfer of blood from arteries to veins.
117
How did Robert Burton apply scientific methods to his own mind?
obert Burton (15771640) spent most of his life at Oxford University, where he was vicar of St. Thomas Church. He was later appointed rector of Segrave, Leicester. He was a mathematician with interests in astrology and was known to be companionable and cheerful. However, he suffered all his life from a heavy heart and hatchling in my head, a kind of imposthume in my head, which I was very desirous to be unladen of. In the preface to The Anatomy of Melancholy (1621) he explained the work as therapeutic: I write of melancholy, by being busy to avoid melancholy. There is no greater cause of melancholy than idleness, no better cure than business.
a repertory of amusement and information. Indeed, Burtons treatise is full of satire and it constitutes a prodigious display of historical and literary knowledge. However, the genius of Burtons Anatomy lies in its attempt to give a naturalistic account of the mind as both distinct from the body and yet intimately connected with it. Burtons theory of human cognition and consciousness rests on his notion of spirit, through which all of the functions and faculties of mind are physically connected with different parts of the body. While mistaken and overly literal by more modern standards, Burtons general project of investigating mind-body correspondence remains a cornerstone of empirical mind-body and mind-brain scientific research to this day.
118
119
a logical contradiction to deny them, and that they are absolutely certain, or, in current terminology, true in all possible worlds.
S E VE NT E E NT H C E NTU RY R ATI O NA LI S M
FRANC I SCO SUREZ
Who was Francisco Surez?
Francisco Surez (also called Doctor Eximius; 15481617) was a Spanish Jesuit theological philosopher. He taught mainly in Spain and Italy, at Salmanca, Rome, and Coimbra. He wrote On Law (1612), On the Trinity (1606), and On the Soul (1612). His best known work was his 54 arguments, or treatises, known as Metaphysical Disputations (1597), which were believed to have influenced Descartes, Leibniz, and Grotius in the seventeenth century, and Schopenhauer in the nineteenth. Surez treated metaphysics in the first extended systematic way in the European tradition after Aristotle, which was not an Aristotelian commentary.
R E N D E S C A RT E S
Who was Ren Descartes?
Ren Descartes (15961650) inaugurated modern philosophy with a pair of questions that persist to this day: How are mind and matter different? and How is the mind connected to the body? He did not set out to invent these questions, but encountered them himself while on the way toward trying to do something else. He was trying to prove to the Catholic Church that rigorous philosophy was compatible with religion and that science could be both certain and compatible with religion.
Descartes moved to Holland to escape the distractions of Paris, so that he could concentrate on his work. He was secretive about his personal life and moved his household about once a year during a 20-year period. Wherever he was, he conducted experiments, sometimes getting animal organs from local butchers. One account has it that when he studied vision, he literally looked through a calfs eyes. Descartes was greatly interested in special foods and diets, possibly as a way to prolong life or even to achieve immortality. At times he was a vegetarianits clear this was not for moral reasons, given his belief that animals are machinesand other times he thought that the secret lay in eggs. With a servant named Helena Jans, he had an illegitimate daughter. While Descartes daughter, Francine, is usually described as illegitimate by biographers, her baptism was recorded in 1635 in the Reformed Church in Deventer. Francine died at the age of five from scarlet fever, and Descartes expressed great sorrow for this loss. Descartes motto was said to have been: A life well hidden is a life well lived. Another version has it as: I advance masked.
maternal grandmother. At 10 he was sent to the new Jesuit college of La Flche in Anjou, France, and there studied the classics, history, rhetoric, and Aristotelian natural philosophy. Although he considered La Flche an excellent school, he thought that the natural philosophy he learned there was doubtful, mainly because it was based on scholastic abstractions that had been outdated by more recent discoveries and thought. Descartes then took a law degree at Pottiers and set off to complete his education by travel in Europe. He wrote that he had resolved to seek no knowledge other than that which could be found either in myself or the great book of the world. He served briefly in the army and then became friends with Isaac Beeckman (15881637), a Dutch philosopher and scientist who inspired him to study mathematics. Descartes first book, Compendium Musicae, applied mathematics to harmony and dissonance. Descartes also began work on his discovery of analytic geometry that was published in 1637.
121
122
ticism to deny the findings of the new science that contradicted Church doctrine and scripture. It was Descartes hope that the Jesuits would approve his ideas in the Meditations and even use it as a textbook. Descartes next publication was Principles of Philosophy (1644), which he believed would be a masterpiece that would gain the Churchs approval.
123
escartes wrote Passions of Soul mainly to try to answer her questions about how the mind interacted with the body.
In that book, Descartes discusses how emotions are the minds perceptions of disturbances in our bodies. He thought that the will was part of the soul and immaterial but that there were very delicate fluids in the pineal gland that the will could influence. The result was that parts of the body could be controlled by the mind.
soul, as you have described it, after having had the faculty and habit of reasoning well, can lose all of it on account of some vapors, and that, although it can subsist without the body and has nothing in common with it, is yet so ruled by it. In this passage, the possibility of the materiality of the soul is deftly introduced in a way that illumines Descartes dualism. No one, including Descartes, could satisfactorily explain how an immaterial soul could interact with a material body. One solution to this problem that Elizabeth intuited was to posit the soul as material.
Who was Queen Christina and why was she important in Descartes life?
Ren Descartes second royal correspondent and student, Queen Christina (1626 1689) of Sweden, was a less conventional figure than his other pupil, Princess Elizabeth, although her philosophical skills and subsequent historical legacy were not as great. Christinas father raised her as a prince, and when she assumed the crown she took the title of King Christina. During her reign she greatly expanded the number of noble titles and extravagantly spent down the treasury, most notably for New Sweden, a colonization of America in an area near Willington, Delaware. Christina abdicated in 1664, changing her name to Maria Christina Alexandra. She did this to convert to Catholicism, which was then illegal in Sweden. Maria Christina went first to Rome and then France. She enjoyed great attention as a former queen and was an active patroness of science and the arts. She was remembered for her shocking male dress: a short skirt, stockings, and high heels, which allowed for greater freedom of movement than the long skirts women wore at the time.
124
Greta Garbo portrayed Queen Christina in a 1933 film that was highly acclaimed critically but did not do well at the box office.
125
true mental processes, is in fact constantly deceiving us about the workings of our own minds? So now Descartes has raised doubt to the level of doubting the existence of a good and powerful God, which he himself regards as a very disturbing and distressing predicament.
Descartes assertion that he existed led to other conclusions, such that God exists as does the external world (iStock).
I noticed that while I was trying to think everything false, it must needs be that I, who was thinking this, was something. And observing that this truth, I am thinking, therefore I exist was so solid and secure that the most extravagant suppositions of the skeptics could not overthrow it, I judged that I need not scruple to accept it as the first principle of the philosophy that I was seeking.
What did Descartes do once he was sure of his assertion I am thinking, therefore I exist?
escartes asked himself what kind of thing he was and concluded that he was a thinking thing, that is, a mind-soul, and not the author of his own being, who must be God. God created both Descartes as an immaterial thinking thing, or soul, and the physical universe that included Descartes body. There was a second proof for Gods existence in Descartes ontological argument: God was all powerful and all good, existence was better than nonexistence, therefore God existed.
Because God was good, he could not be a deceiver, and the earlier doubts about the existence of the external world, and the validity of logic and reason, were put to rest. The doubts about sense data could always be corrected by further sense experience. And the distinction between being awake and being asleep could be solved after one was awake and compared the two states. God had made mankind such that our perceptions of the reality of a world that existed could be trusted.
the brain, namely the pineal gland, where it exercises its functions more particularly than elsewhere. That is, the soul directly affects the body through the pineal gland by setting animal spirits in motion, via the will. (Descartes thought that the will was infinite because it was a copy of Gods will, but that human understanding is limited. Because the will often outstrips the understanding, all manner of human evils and misfortunes follow.) Consciousness, or the representation in the mind of the sensation and pains in the body, was unique to human beings, according to Descartes. He thought that animals lacked both a pineal gland and consciousness, and were therefore mere machines.
127
version of occasionalism in his theory of pre-established harmony. On the empiricist side, Thomas Hobbes (15881679) insisted on the nonexistence of anything nonmaterial and John Locke (16321704) directly attacked Descartes idea of substance. Descartes thought that substance was what held matter together and what held mind together, even though substance could not be experienced directly. According to Descartes all physical things were material substance and all mental things immaterial substance.
Why was Ren Descartes idea of substance a problem for the empiricists?
According to Descartes, substance was known to the mind, but not through the senses. The empiricists wanted to build knowledge up from information we get through the senses.
B E N E DICT
DE
S P I N OZ A
128
natural order. Natural science, politics, ethics, education, and even technology were part of what had to be understood to achieve this complete understanding. Before such understanding, Spinoza said that the human mind was like a worm in a bloodstream that thought each drop of blood was an isolated thing, instead of part of a system within an organism. His philosophical task was to describe the whole in which individual humans were parts.
was to discover ones place in nature (iStock). Although Spinozas system had very strong theological elements and he was motivated to construct it for the ethical purpose of determining how to live, he did not base morality on God, but rather on adequate human knowledge. Such knowledge would enable both an ability to control the passions and live peacefully with others. However, indirectly, this knowledge of nature amounted to knowledge of God because, according to Spinoza, God was present throughout nature.
Spinoza wrote philosophy in the form of geometrical proofs and began with axioms from which he proved his conclusions. First, he made the assumption that substance exists. Substance, he continued, has infinite attributes, but humans can perceive only two of these: extension and thought (or matter and mind). Spinozas metaphysics was a monism. Only one thing existed and that was God. God, according to Spinoza, was a being absolutely infinite. Although God had infinite attributes, each one of which expressed His nature without limitation to itself, humans can perceive or understand only two of Gods infinite attributes: thought and material bodies, or extension. Each attribute has both infinite modes and finite modes, although finite modes are infinite in number. A person, for example, is one finite mode of God, existing in God as both a mode of thought and a mode of extension. One way of understanding Spinoza is that mind and matter are different ways of viewing the same thing that exists in God. As everything that exists, God is nature, but nature is also God. Spinoza distinguished between natura naturans, or God in his active role as creating, and natural naturata, or what we humans perceive as nature.
129
serving or altruistic, but the two are united: Nothing is more useful to man than man. He defined good as what we certainly know to be useful to us, and evil as what we certainly know prevents us from being masters of some good. Because God is perfect, He has no needs from which it follows that nothing is good or evil to Him. Gods blessing is not a reward for virtuous behavior, but an inevitable result of living according to reason or having adequate knowledge. Spinoza also held that citizens of a state cannot give up their right to attain their own well being.
130
After Spinoza was excommunicated from his Jewish community, he could receive neither patronage nor any other employment. He therefore made his living by grind-
ing and polishing lenses. The dust from the glass is believed to have fatally injured his lungs and been responsible for his early death.
Did Malebranche have a more extensive philosophy to support his theory of causation?
Yes, Malebranche was highly regarded as a theological metaphysician. In his major book, The Search after Truth (1674), he developed his theory of vision in God. Malebranche agreed with Ren Descartes (15961650) that ideas in the mind are the basic units of perception and knowledge, but he argued that our ideas are actually in God, rather than in us. This vision in God was especially important for abstract knowledge,
131
according to Malebranche, because universals, mathematical truths, and moral understanding were part of the vision in God. As such, they reflected Gods knowledge of what was eternally true about the world He had created. In his Treatise on Nature and Grace (1680), Malebranche provided an explanation of how Gods goodness, omnipotence, and omniscience could allow evil in the world. He claimed that God could have created a more perfect world without the known evils of the present one. This more or mostly perfect world, however, would have been more complicated than the world God did create, and creating that world would have contradicted Gods principle of acting in the simplest possible way, according to general laws. This simplicity and generality could also explain the unequal distribution of grace among human beings.
132
Berkeleys [(16851783)] system, of which he had received some knowledge from a translation just published. But the issue of the debate proved tragic to poor Malebranche. In the heat of the disputation, he raised his voice so high, and gave way so freely to the natural impetuosity of a man of parts and a Frenchman, that he brought on himself a violent increase of his disorder, which carried him off a few days after.
G OT TF R I E D WI LH E LM LE I B N I Z
Who was Leibniz?
Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (16461715) was a German philosopher, scientist, mathematician, and historian famous for his metaphysical idealism as well as his epistemological rationalism. In addition, he made contributions to the fields of astronomy, biology (including embryology), engineering, information technology, law, logic, medicine, paleontology, philology, Sinology, social science, and topology. The calculating machine he invented could add, subtract and calculate square roots; his plans for invading Egypt are said to have been used by Napoleon. Leibniz also kept up a voluminous correspondence throughout his life.
You can thank Leibniz for those calculus problems you did in school (iStock).
133
What was the dispute between Leibniz and Newton about the calculus?
ottfried Leibniz was very sociable intellectually, and welcomed a free and cooperative exchange of ideas. Toward the end of his life, though, he was greatly distressed by the claims of Isaac Newtons (16431727) advocates that he had in effect plagiarized the discovery of the differential calculus from Newton. Leibniz reported that when he was in England in 1637 he was told about Newtons work on the calculus and wrote to him. Newton replied through an intermediary, although he wrote about the binomial theory and included only the following sentence, in Latin, about the calculus (fluxions). The words of the sentence were presented by Newton, in code, as follows: aaaaa cc d ae eeeeeeeeeeeee ff iiiiiii lll nnnnnnnnn oooo qqqq rr ssss ttttttttt vvvvvvvvvvvv x. It meant, Given equation anywhatsoever, flowing quantities involving, fluxions to find, and vice versa. No one has ever been able to make sense of what Newton wrote Leibniz, nor has anyone related it to the differential calculus, although the string of letters are sometimes quoted to illustrate how unreasonable Newton was. Leibniz then invented a differential calculus on his own, showed it to Newtons intermediary, and in 1684 published his method. By 1695, Newtons followers were accusing him of plagiarism. Over the centuries, scholars have exonerated Leibniz of plagiarism. The conclusion has been that they each independently invented the calculus and that Newton did so first, although Leibniz published first.
He was commissioned by Ernst August to write the history of the house of Brunswick in 1685. After traveling to Munich, Vienna, and Italy, he showed, as part of his commissioned writing assignment, how Brunswick was connected with the house of Este. Leibniz had a close correspondence with Ernst Augusts wife, Sophie, and her daughter, Sophie Charlotte, who became Queen of Prussia. He became president of the Berlin Society of Sciences in the same city where Sophie Charlotte lived. After her death, her family was not welcoming to him (perhaps because they had resented his relationship with her while she was alive). Leibniz was continually involved in efforts to promote communication and cooperation in scientific research, both theoretical and practical. He also had hopes that all Christians might unite. He was honored with prestigious government posts in Vienna (17121714), but by the time of his death his royal patrons, and most of the intellectuals who had known him, abandoned him. They did so for several reasons: Isaac Newton was favored in Leibnizs dispute with him; Leibniz no longer had the protection of
134
Sophie Charlotte; and his philosophical work was not popular. Neither the Royal Society nor the Berlin Academy saw fit to honor him after he died. King George I was nearby when his funeral was held but did not deign to attend or send a representative. Leibnizs grave remained unmarked for almost 50 years, until a descendent of Sophie Charlotte took up the cause of rehabilitating his memory. While it is not clear how damaging his dispute with Isaac Newton (16431727) over the discovery of the calculus was to his reputation and standing, it evidently proved more harmful to him than it did to Newton. (Newton had claimed that Leibniz plagiarized his work on the differential calculus.) When Leibniz died, he was engaged in writing a religious work about Chinese philosophy and the Leibniz-Clark Correspondence in which he attacked virtually every aspect of Newtons metaphysical system.
Gottfried Leibniz believed that all human beings were predetermined as homunculi from the beginning of time. In other words, each human being was completely formed before he or she was an embryo in the womb (iStock).
135
Leeuwenhoek reported having seen tiny animals with completely formed features in pond scum and tooth plaque, as well as in the sperm of over 30 animals. He was made a member of the Royal Society, and his descriptions of miniature worlds within worlds were accepted as evidence for preformationism, as well as the original creation of everything in the universe, all at once, by God.
136
Metaphysically necessary principlesLeibniz had a number of these, which included: everything possible demands to exist and it will exist unless pre-
he brilliant French satiric essayist Franois-Marie Arouet de Voltaire (16941778) pilloried Leibnizs philosophical optimism with the character of Dr. Pangloss in his novel Candide. The character Candide is the illegitimate nephew of a baron who starts out life in luxury, with Dr. Pangloss as his teacher. (pan is Greek for all and gloss means tongue, speech, and words, so that Dr. Pangloss translates as Dr. Alltalk.) Dr. Pangloss teaches the metaphysico-theologo-cosmolonigology to Candide. This teaching is a caricature of Leibnizs and the poet Alexander Popes philosophical optimism, which Voltaire found very difficult to reconcile with real human suffering, such as the devastation caused by the 1755 Lisbon earthquake and the oppression of the ancien rgime in pre-revolutionary France. The view of philosophical optimism held that because God is good, everything in the world must be good, as well. It is, in fact, the best world it could be, and everything in it, including what appear as evil to us, is, in the grand scheme of things, inevitable and for the best. Heres a sample of Voltaires satire in which Dr. Pangloss expresses his belief: It is demonstrable, said he, that things cannot be otherwise than as they are; for as all things have been created for some end, they must necessarily be created for the best end. Observe, for instance, the nose is formed for spectacles, therefore we wear spectacles. The legs are visibly designed for stockings, accordingly we wear stockings. Stones were made to be hewn and to construct castles, therefore My Lord has a magnificent castle; for the greatest baron in the province ought to be the best lodged. Swine were intended to be eaten, therefore we eat pork all the year round: and they, who assert that everything is right, do not express themselves correctly; they should say that everything is best.
vented; activity is essential to substance; and states of things remain unless or until there is a reason for them to change. Principles of orderThese consisted of three laws of order: the law of continuity, the law that every action involves a reaction, and the law that cause and effect are equal. Efficient and final causationEfficient causes are what immediately make things happen, whereas final causes are the ends or goals of higher substances. The entire realm of efficient causation is designed to serve the realm of final causation.
137
Principle of the naturalEverything that God allows to exist and happen, he chooses from what is natural; otherwise He would constantly be performing miracles. What is natural is always in between what is essential or necessary and what is accidental.
S E VE NT E E NT H C E NTU RY E M P I R I C I S M
What was or is natural law?
Natural law, or the law of nature, is a set of rules for human actions, usually posited as having a divine source. As a universal moral and political code, natural law was first conceptualized by stoic philosophers, who believed that natural law was part of the fundamental structure of the universe. Some early thinkers believed that natural law applied to animals as well as humans. Christian theorists later took up the idea of natural law as self-evident principles of human behavior that could be known only by rational beings. Thomas Aquinas (c. 12251274) thought that human reason could reveal Gods intentions for how we ought always to conduct ourselves so as to preserve the common good, or the good of
138
the community. Following natural law is an important part of obedience to God. The particular laws of nations and peoples might differ, but the basic principles of natural law are universal.
THOMAS HOB B E S
Who was Thomas Hobbes?
More than any other seventeenth century philosopher, Thomas Hobbes (15881679) directly applied the atomism and materialism of the science of his day to metaphysics. Hobbes believed that everything in existence was caused by matter and motion. He was one of Ren Descartes (15961650) early critics and was considered an atheist by his peers. Hobbes is most famous for his description of the natural condition of mankind as solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short.
139
Thomas Hobbes applied the atomism and materialism of the science of his day to metaphysics (iStock).
Johannes Kepler first published his system of the elliptical shape of planetary orbits and Galileo Galilei was reporting his observations with telescopes. Hobbes met English statesman, scientist, and philosopher Francis Bacon after he returned to England and agreed with him about the need to discard Aristotelian views of science. However, Hobbes did not subscribe to Bacons inductive method. Bacon believed that scientific knowledge could be built up from observation. Hobbes, in contrast, was to develop a system of knowledge beginning from the first principles of matter and motion from which the nature of experience could be deduced.
Hobbes then began reading the classics and translated Thucydides history into English in 1628. By this time, Sir Cavendish had died and his widow dismissed Hobbes to cut expenses. So, Hobbes went back to Europe to work for another noble family as tutor to Sir Clintons son. He became interested in geometry as a method for conveying a philosophical system; his interest in astronomy was piqued when he met the astronomer, priest, and philosopher Pierre Gassendi (15921655), as well as Galileo. From that exchange, he conceived the idea of applying the principles of the science to the human world, specifically to politics and history. He wrote Little Treatise (1637), an explanation of sensation set out in a geometrical form, which was both an attack on Aristotles theory, and his own original thought. He thought that the cause of all sensation was changes in motion of insensible particles. In 1650, Hobbes published his Elements of Law in two parts: the psychological treatise Human Nature and De Corpore Politico, which defended unified government. This began a period when Hobbes life was in danger as politics shifted, because he was suspected of atheism on account of his materialism and was disliked because of his own dislike of Catholics. Overall, his defense of a strong monarchy set Parliament against him. Meanwhile, he was briefly the mathematical tutor to Charles II, before he became king, and he published his magnum opus, Leviathan (1651). Between 1645 and 1663, Hobbes became involved in several protracted and bitter controversies with other thinkers. He disputed the question of free will with John Bramwell, bishop of Derry. Two Oxford dons were angry with him: John Wallis, a professor of geometry, was scathing about Hobbes attempts to square the circle. (This was the problem dating from antiquity of devising a method for constructing a square with an area equal to the area of any given circle.) Seth Ward, professor of astronomy, was opposed to Hobbes entire philosophy.
140
After the plague of 1665 and the Great Fire of London in 1666, people sought reasons for Gods wrath. Parliament passed a bill to suppress atheism, and a committee was constituted to investigate Hobbes Leviathan. There was a report that Hobbes had been burned in effigy, and Hobbes was afraid that his papers would be searched, so he himself burned part of them. The king, who liked Hobbes, intervened, but from then on Hobbes was not permitted to publish his work. Neither the Roman Catholic church nor Oxford University permitted his books to be read, and they occasionally even burned them.
Hobbes played tennis until he was 75, rewrote his autobiography in Latin verse at the age of 84, and at 86 published translations of the Iliad and Odyssey in verse.
How did Hobbes explain sensation, memory, imagination, thought, and emotion?
Hobbes described sensations as effects of movement in the body that are felt through the motions of the heart. Sense always has some memory adhering to it, because sense organs retain the movements of external bodies acting on them. So long as the organs are moved by one object, they cannot be moved by another. Imagination is
141
decaying sense, after the source of sensation is removed, and memory is similar to imagination, except that it also has a feeling of familiarity. Hobbes believed that thought involved literal movements in the head. His idea of unguided thought led to later theories of the association of ideas (that one thought automatically evokes another in the mind). Guided thought is goaldirected. Hobbes thought that while humans and animals both may perform the action that is necessary to reach a goal, only humans have the distinctive trait of prudence. Prudence involves beginning with the action that one can perform and then calculating its consequences as a guide for what to do. Prudence increases with experience. Concerning the passions, or emotions, which he called endeavors, Cover of illustration from Thomas Hobbes book Leviathan Hobbes postulated two types of motion in (Art Archive). the body: vital motions, such as breathing, nutrition, and the circulation of the blood; and animal motion, such as voluntary movement. Pleasure is nothing more than motion around the heart. Appetite is an endeavor toward an object associated with pleasure, and aversion is an endeavor away from it.
142
J O H N LO C K E
Why was John Locke important?
As a philosopher of knowledge, or epistemologist, John Locke (16321704) sidestepped the metaphysical problems raised by Ren Descartes (15961650) and offered a theory
143
of the mind and its capabilities that grounded modern ideas of education, psychology, and philosophy of science. Lockes political views about democratic government and individual rights were foundational not only for the modern British parliamentary system, but also for the basic principles of the U.S. Constitution. His idea of natural law persists in practical political theories to this day.
What happened to Locke during his life and what were some of his important publications?
John Locke was born in Wrington, Somerset, England. His father was an attorney and justice of the peace who fought on the Parliamentary side against Charles I. At Westminster school, which Locke began attending in 1646, he learned the John Lockes political views greatly influenced the classics, Hebrew, and Arabic. From Westdemocratization of the British government and the minster, he went to Oxford University, fundamental ideals of the U.S. Constitution (iStock). where he disagreed with the scholastic philosophy that was taught. After he achieved his masters degree, he lectured in Latin and Greek, and in 1664 he was given the position of Censor of Moral Philosophy. When his father died in 1661, Locke inherited enough money to be financially independent. He soon met such famed scientists as Robert Boyle, Isaac Newton, and renowned physician Thomas Sydenham, who inspired Locke to train as a medical doctor. Locke never practiced medicine but was considered knowledgeable in this area all his life. In 1666, Locke met Lord Ashley, Earl of Shaftesbury. Shaftesbury suffered from an infected cyst on his liver, and Locke oversaw his surgery, including the insertion of a silver tube to drain the wound. The Earls gratitude after recovery resulted in a longterm patronage. Shaftesbury supported Lockes philosophical endeavors and his nomination to the Royal Society in 1668. Conversations with colleagues Locke met through that connection resulted in the early drafts of his An Essay Concerning Human Understanding (1689)
144
Locke also served Shaftesbury in practical political ways that resulted in some of his most important contributions. He drafted a constitution for British colonial Car-
olina and was secretary to the Council of Trade and Plantations. Shaftesbury was tried for treason due to his leadership of the Parliamentary opposition to the Stuarts. He was acquitted, but left England for Holland. Locke also left, and while he was in Holland, his position at Oxford was taken away by the king; then James II denounced him as a traitor after the Duke of Monmouths failed rebellion. Locke continued to write, working on An Essay Concerning Human Understanding (1689) and his First Letter Concerning Toleration (1689). He also became involved with the plan to put the Protestants William and Mary on the English throne. Locke advised William, and after the Glorious Rebellion of 1688, he escorted Mary, Princess of Orange, on her ship back to England. In 1689 and 1690, Lockes two major works An Essay Concerning Human Understanding and Two Treatises of Civil Government were completed. Always suffering from poor health, Locke then retired from his active involvements in politics. Still, he went on to write Some Thoughts Concerning Education (1693) and The Reasonableness of Christianity, (1695), followed by A Vindication of the Reasonableness of Christianity (1695). This last work sparked a controversy between Locke and Edward Stillingfleet, bishop of Worcester. Lockes denial of evidence for substance was taken by Stillingfleet to be a denial of the Anglican Churchs doctrine of the Trinity, as well as a barrier to life after death through the immortality of the soul.
How and why was Lockes idea of the social contract different from Hobbes?
Locke held that the social contract was an agreement between citizens or their representatives and the government or king. Because basic amenities of human life and its fundamental social institutions were present before the social contract, government was not as essential in Lockes view, as it had been in Hobbes. Human society existed and functioned well before government, and if government dissolved or if the governed brought it down for just reasons, society would still exist. However, if something destroyed society, that would also destroy the government.
145
What did John Locke mean by saying the mind was a tabula rasa?
nlike the rationalists, who thought that we were born with certain ideas about the world, Locke thought that our minds are like a blank slate (tabula rasa) at birth. All of our ideas are the result of two different processes that happen after we are born. The first is sensory experience, and the second is our reflection on our sensory experience and on the workings of our own minds. One of his main arguments against innate ideas was that people do not all have the same ideas, but their ideas differ as their experience has differed.
comes to own. (Locke used the term mixes labor with for labor, in cases where we today would say works on.) Locke went on to claim that, in the state of nature, there were two provisos against accumulation through labor: that there be as much and as good left over; and that there be no waste. The first proviso assumed that natural resources would never run out. The second allowed for the store of unused items in precious objects that could be used as money, thereby allowing surplus production to be stored as wealth without the original producer being wasteful. In Lockes state of nature there was industry, cooperation, and trade. Human beings were basically peaceful, except for a few criminals. To assure justice in punishment, government was necessary, but it was merely a convenience added to a generally functional and satisfying situation.
146
Lockes refusal to posit a form or substance for the soul seemed to contradict the Trinitarian doctrine of three attributes or natures present in one God. Some of his
critics, such as British theologian Edward Stillingfleet, accused Locke of denying the possibility of resurrection in the absence of an incorruptible, immaterial soul substance. Lockes reply to Stillingfleet was to reaffirm his belief in the immortality of the soul, as a matter of faith, rather than a fact that could be proved by reason. Stillingfleet believed that some substantial form of a persons body was necessary for there to be a Resurrection of that person. Lockes response was to make fun of Stillingfleet by interpreting him to claim that the same body literally had to arise from the grave. Locke wrote, And I think your lordship will not say, that the particles that were separate from the body by perspiration before the point of death were laid up in the grave.
How were Lockes ideas about substance related to his theory of knowledge?
Locke confined knowledge to sensory information and the workings of the mind, and he had a moderate skepticism about claims beyond those two sources of information. Locke introduced his Essay Concerning Human Understanding (1689) as the result of conversations among friends which led to the question of what it was possible for them to know, given the limitations of human faculties: It was necessary to examine our own abilities, and see what objects our understandings were or were not fitted to deal with. Lockes method was not to rely on tradition or what other philosophers had claimed, but to look to the things themselves. Knowledge, according to Locke, was direct awareness of some fact. The only facts we can know are those that consist of relationships among our ideas. A fact is something true about the world. Locke did not think that we had direct experience of the world. Things in the world acted on our sense organs to produce ideas. Therefore, the truths we know (facts) are about the relationships between ideas. Ideas are mental objects for Locke, some of which are representations of things in the world. In Book I of the Essay, Locke attacks the rationalist doctrine of innate ideas and innate knowledge. His argument is that we have innate capacities, but nothing like knowledge until there is experiencethis is Lockes famous description of the mind as a tabula rasa, or blank slate. In Book II, he explains our different types of ideas by tracing them to sensation and reflection on sensation. Reflection consists of combination, division, generalization, and abstraction. For Locke, our ideas are like impressions from experience. When we consider our ideas in our minds, we can combine different ideas, divide an idea into more ideas, generalize about what ideas in a group share, or abstract some property shared by a group of ideas. In Book III, Locke explains how words can mislead us about facts or the things themselves. Book IV is a discussion of how we are obligated to conduct our minds in forming beliefs, so as not to stray too far from what we know.
147
This arrangement, however, was not without its detractors. John Edwards, who believed that Lockes Reasonableness of Christianity was a subversive and even atheistic work, referred to Locke as the governor of the seraglio [brothel] at Oates.
interest in this subject among a new group of property owners who had representation in their government and were neither poor nor idly rich. Lockes letters to Clarke were first published anonymously in 1693, and then became Some Thoughts Concerning Education, which went through 24 editions by 1800, five of which Locke supervised before he died. Locke advised that the temperament of the child should be observed so that having once established your authority and the ascendant over him, the next thing must be to bend the crooks the other way if he have any in him. But he counseled a light touch concerning physical discipline, which was an innovation, and he suggested that shame was a better tool than corporeal punishment. Lockes system for bringing up male children to become men of property and affairs involved an austere diet, trained bowels, hard beds, early rising, and plenty of exercise outdoors with bare heads and wet feet in all kinds of weather. The fondness of mothers and superstitions of servants were to be minimized. Locke assumed that selfdiscipline in childhood would result in strong adults. Locke thought children should be educated at home, by sober tutors, with an emphasis on learning languages. He had no use for poetry or abstract, speculative learning, but advised that astronomy, geography, anatomy, history, and geometry be part of the home curriculum. He also advised that a gentlemans son acquire skill in at least one manual trade, such as painting, woodworking, gardening, or metalworking.
148
149
The basic tenet of Cambridge Platonism was the obscure religious belief, first stated by the Giovanni Pico della Mirandola (14631494), that both Pythagoras and Plato based their philosophy on teachings by Moses that were expressed in the cabala and other facets of the Jewish mystical tradition. Their other beliefs affirmed Gods existence, the souls immortality, and the animation of the natural world by, or with, spirit. They were convinced both that man had free will and that reason was of primary importance in religious matters. However, they were not empiricists, because they believed in innate ideas and innate principles of morality and religion, which were recognizable through intuition. And furthermore, it needs to be kept in mind that not all of those known as Cambridge Neoplatonists, shared the same views.
150
Henry More asserted that animals, not just people, had souls (iStock).
He differed with Descartes, however, in insisting that animals have souls. He attacked Thomas Hobbes (15881679) and Benedict de Spinoza (16321677) for their presumed atheism. He was a tutor to Cambridge Platonist Anne Conway (16301679) and deplored her enthusiastic conversion to Quakerism. He is said to have coined the terms Cartesianism and materialist. Henry Mores writings included a history of the English Jesuits, translations, and his Life and Doctrines of our Saviour Jesus Christ (1660).
What did Anne Conways physical pain have to do with her philosophy and religion?
Anne was born December 14, 1630, a week after her father, Sir Heneage Finch, who was speaker of the House of Commons, died. Having learned Latin, Greek, and Hebrew at home, she began a correspondence with Henry More (16141687), who had been her brothers tutor at Christ College. More held her in very high intellectual esteem, and their correspondence continued after she married Edward Conway, at the age of 20. More wrote of her that he had scarce ever met with any Person, Man or Woman, of better Natural parts than Lady Conway. One of her motivations for studying philosophy and possibly converting to Quakerism was her need to reconcile the existence of a good, all-powerful God with pain and suffering in the world. Anne herself was afflicted with extraordinarily severe headaches all her life. At one point, she had her jugular arteries bled in search of relief.
G E N D E R AN D EA R LY M O D E R N WO M E N P H I LO S O P H E R S
Why is gender an important topic in studies of early modern philosophy?
Social and family life, generally, and ideas about the sexes were so different in the seventeenth century compared to our own that they should not be overlooked as an
151
Why were the great seventeenth century philosophers and scientists bachelors?
hey were either relatively poor (Descartes, Spinoza, Locke), or prohibited from marrying because they were priests (Fathers Marin Mersenne [15881648] and Pierre Gassendi [15921655]), or it was a tradition for men of learning not to have their own families. For example, Oxford dons were not allowed to marry at that time and the seven fellows of Gresham College (founded in 1558) were all bachelors. Another reason might have been the prevailing beliefs about the nature of women. Women were not allowed to be scholars, and wives and family life was not only considered a distraction for men of learning, but sexual relations were believed to be intellectually weakening for scholars.
important background to the beginnings of modern philosophy. Interestingly, all the well-known seventeenth century philosophersDescartes, Spinoza, Leibniz, Hobbes, and Lockewere bachelors their entire lives, as were the great majority of their colleagues in philosophy and the sciences.
Why was the single status of early modern men of science and philosophy important?
Inevitably, bachelorhood would have had the negative effect of not having long-term intimate relationships or much experience with children and family life in adulthood. A bachelors style of life would have then supported a view of the world from the perspective of a lone individual, and an assumption that the philosophical mind would always have the same gender as oneself.
Would marriage have changed the emotional lives of seventeenth century philosophers?
The answer is not clear. In the seventeenth century, primogeniture, or leaving the entire inheritance of a father to his oldest son, was the norm. About one-quarter of younger sons in the middle classes did not marry because they could not afford to set up households or find brides with substantial dowries. Child mortality was between 30 and 50 percent of all live births, and after 20 years of marriage it was highly unlikely that both spouses would still be alive. These statistics rendered family relationships more dependent on roles than on individual emotional attachments based on distinct personalities. (During the early modern period, people did not marry for what we consider to be romantic reasons.)
152
None of this is to say that there were not strong lifelong friendships between men and women. Philosophers such as Ren Descartes, John Locke, and Gottfried Leibniz had long-term female correspondents, but it is doubtful that they knew what we would call love.
What were the general ideas about women that were held by people in the seventeenth century?
The old Aristotelian idea that females were imperfect males was still assumed to be true in seventeenth-century Europe. The modern science of biology, which established two distinct sexes, was still in the future. Although eighteenth and nineteenth century sexual distinctions based on biology supported the idea that the capabilities of women were inherently limited and inferior to those of men, they at least focused on the distinctness of male and female identities. The Aristotelian view has been called the one sex theory. Many serious and wellregarded theorists of the human body solemnly insisted that the female reproductive system was no more than an inverted form of the male one. Like Aristotle, they believed that women were naturally colder and damper than men, besides being in every respect weaker. Moreover, women were considered to be the sex-desiring, aggressive gender, whereas men were often viewed as helpless and vulnerable in sexual matters. Medical opinion concurred that blood, semen, and spinal fluid were all the same basic vital substance or fluid, albeit in different forms. Sexual intercourse was not only often viewed as a weakening form of physical dissipation, but male ejaculation was believed to draw brain tissue down the spine and out the penisa very strong reason for a male philosopher to remain celibate. Moreover, women were viewed as the source of venereal disease, unwanted children, and burdensome financial obligations. So great was their negative sexual power held to be that they were at the same time also presumed responsible for male impotence.
Did women object to this negative view of them in the seventeenth century?
It is difficult to see how they had much opportunity to object. Before and after Oliver Cromwells rise to power in England, pubic entertainment and behavior were often bawdy. By the time King William III ascended the throne in 1688, Puritanism dominated public morals, especially among the middle class. For some women, such as the successful playwright Alphra Behn, this was not good news. She wrote: Though I the wondrous change deplore / That makes me useful and forlorn. But even during the wild times of the Tory Restoration, when sexuality was freely discussed and written about, and sexual relationships and desires were acknowledged as natural and tolerated in respectable society, Behns explicit poetry and plays had rarely gone beyond the conventional wisdom that women were the dangerous sex.
153
Did any of the early modern male philosophers consider the position of women in their writing?
es. Ren Descartes (15961650) deliberately wrote his Discourse on Method (1637) in French, in part so that women, who were not usually taught Latin, would be able to read it. Hobbes considered women to be just as strong and free as men in the original state of nature and talked about their consent being necessary to enter into marriage. He also referred to the power of women when he called them Lord Mothers, to whom their children were obligated if they had nurtured and raised them, instead of abandoning them to fortune. John Locke (16321704) thought that the doctrine of the divine right of kings, which was based on heredity from Adam, simply left out the existence of female parents. He described marriage as a partnership for the sake of procreation and raising children and suggested that once children were grown the husband and wife could go their separate ways if they chose. In his Thoughts Concerning Education (1693), written in response to his cousins questions about how young men should be raised, Locke wrote that girls should receive basically the same education as boys.
In her poem The Disappointment she relates Lysanders impotence when he is in the presence of the extremely desirable Cloris. Cloris flees, blushing with distain and shame, and Lysander curses, The sheppardess charms / Whose soft betwitching influence / Had damned him to the hell of impotence.
154
155
157
3. An overall secularity and downplaying of traditional Christian transcendence. 4. A new aesthetic and ethics based on the goodness of nature. 5. Perhaps most important, a great faith in progress or the belief that the present is better than the past and that the future will be better than the present. Nevertheless, none of the paramount Enlightenment thinkers simply played out these themes in direct ways. They almost all used reason or rational thoughttogether with a fair amount of witto propound and develop their ideas. The ideas themselves, though, sometimes had unforeseen consequences. That is, often the Enlightenment geniuses went too far, or were not able to fully think things through. As a result, skepticism, pessimism, and romantic madness took over when the ideas of progress and the ideals of human reason ran out.
158
Enlightenment, who did not subscribe to the belief in progress characteristic of the age. For example, in philosophy, Giambattista Vico, Edmund Burke, and JosephMarie de Maistre; and in letters, William Cowper, Choderlos de Laxlos, the Marquis de Sade, and Jonathan Swift.
159
for it to become a reality. The British Parliament awarded him 20,000 pounds, but that money never came through. Berkeley married in 1728 and he and his wife, Anne, went to Rhode Island to set up farms to grow food for the prospective college. They remained there for three years, and then returned to live in London. He defended Christianity in The Minute Philosopher in 1732, and claimed that mathematics was more mysterious than religion in The Analyst in 1734. That same year, he became Bishop of Cloyne, which led him to move back to Ireland, where he remained until he died in 1753, while visiting his son at Oxford University.
Dysart Castle in Thomasttown, County Kilkenny, Ireland, was the home of George Berkeley. (Art Archive).
How did George Berkeleys theory of vision relate to the concept of matter and physical existence?
Berkeley is well known for his theory of vision that contributed so much to modern psychology of perception. However, in that theory he completely repudiated the primary bastion of empiricism: namely, matter. Berkeley departed from both common sense and science in elaborately insisting that matterthe entire physical world based on our best evidence, simply did not exist in the way that the other empiri-
160
erkeley is an aberration insofar as his ideas defy common sense to the point of being dismissible as simple absurdities. He is an obstacle insofar as he founded a powerful and enduring school of thought that dominated some areas of philosophy in the nineteenth century and evolved into very perplexing progressive movements in the twentieth and, it now seems, twenty-first centuries.
cistsHobbes, Locke and Hume, and later on, John Stuart Mill and Bertrand Russellassumed that it did. For any serious student of the history of philosophy, Berkeley is either a delightful aberration or an intractable obstacle because of this position.
161
What is occasionalism?
ccasionalism is the theory that nothing in real life ever caused anything else. God determined everything that each thing would do when he created the world. So, when one pool ball hits another and the second moves, the first pool ball does not cause the second to move because the second ball was already programmed to move that way on its own. Occasionalism holds that everything that seems to interact is like two clocks side by side with one a fraction of a second set ahead of the other. When the faster clocks handles move, it only looks like its causing the slower clocks handles to move.
which are in our minds. (This is one reason why ideas are so important.) We tend to assume that if we have a word for something then we have an idea of it. But sometimes we fool ourselves, and our words are just empty with no ideas behind them. Therefore, we need to make sure that we actually have the ideas we think we have. Just because we are accustomed to using language in certain ways, does not mean that all words that are intelligible to us refer to ideas. If we reflect on abstract, general words, such as man, whiteness, animal, or matter, it becomes evident that there is nothing in the mind to which these words refer. All of our ideas are about particulars or combinations of particulars. We lack the capacity to create new ideasonly God can do thatalthough we are able to combine existing ideas in new ways and create copies of existing ideas.
162
trine and Berkeleys embellishment of it, God does all the real work, from which we, because we have been created by Him along with the rest of His creation, benefit. Berkeley thus extended the presence of God in human cognition as something like a force constituting reality itself. Nonetheless, he endures as an empiricist due to his emphasis on sense data as a component of knowledgenever mind that for Berkeley, sense data were not signs or indications of what philosophers and the vast majority of non-philosophers call an external world, or reality. For Berkeley, sense data were neither real objects in themselves, nor signs of an external world, but ideas, created by God and placed in us. Period.
What did George Berkeley think of matter, extension, and other mainstays secured by Ren Descartes and refined by John Locke?
According to Berkeley, matter and extension (the main property of matter that was supposed to be its occupation of space) were abstract, general ideas, which is to say that the words naming or describing them did not refer to real ideas. Since only ideas, minds, and God exist, matter and extension did not exist for Berkeleythere was nothing real corresponding to them. Berkeley applied the same criticism to our presumptive ideas of causation and the distinction between primary and secondary qualities. He looked for the ideas of sense or imagination to back them up, and found none. In the case of causation, Berkeley was basically an occasionalist.
What did George Berkeley think of the distinction between primary and secondary qualities?
Seventeenth century empirical philosophers believed that secondary qualities are what we perceivenamely colors, sounds, textures, and smells. They thought that primary qualities like mass and number were the qualities of atoms that made up objects. We cant perceive primary qualities, but the seventeenth century empiricists held that it is the interaction between the primary qualities of atoms that cause our perception of secondary qualities. For example, the atoms in red paint interact with our eyes, through light, to cause the experience of red. But Berkeley denied that there was a distinction between primary and secondary qualities because it is impossible to have an idea of a primary quality such as mass, extension, size, or number without also having an idea of its color, texture, or other secondary qualities.
163
Bishop Berkeley having received benefit from the use of Tar-Water, when ill of the colic, published a work On the Virtues of Tar-Water; and a few months before his death, a sequel, entitled Further Thoughts on Tar-Water; and when accused of fancying he had discovered a nostrum in Tar-Water, he replied, that, to speak out, he freely owns he suspects Tar-Water is a panacea. Sir Hugh Seymour Walpole preserved the following epigram on Berkeleys remedy: Who dare deride what pious Cloyne has done? The Church shall rise and vindicate her son; She tells us all her bishops shepherds are, and shepherds heal their rotten sheep with tar.
What was Berkeleys answer to whether a tree falling in the forest makes a sound?
Berkeley said that objects we sense only exist insofar as we have ideas of their sensory qualities. When we do not perceive those qualities, such as the sound of a tree falling in a forest, then they do not exist as our ideas. However, this would not entitle us to conclude that such a tree makes no sound. Our ideas of sensory qualities come to us from God, who has created them. If a tree falls in the forest and God creates the sound of its crashing down, then that idea in Gods mind would guarantee the occurrence of the sound, even though human beings could not perceive it. The same reasoning was applied by Berkeley to the continued existence of a room when no people are inside it. It would still exist as a series of ideas in Gods mind.
164
DAVI D H U M E
Who was David Hume?
David Hume (17111776) was the first philosopher in the Western tradition to construct a system of thought that had no intellectual reliance on God. His atheism was not merely a matter of personal belief, but was based on an application of skepticism to claims that the existence of God could be known by reason. Hume extended that skepticism to the nature of knowledge about the world, as well, and showed how limited our knowledge of both cause and effect, and the future, really is. He was the first, thoroughly modern, naturalistic philosopher.
David Hume, depicted in this 1854 engraving, sought to create a science of the mind (iStock).
165
to secure the position of chair of philosophy at the universities of Edinburgh and Glasgow. He was appointed secretary to General St. Clair for three years in 1746, which led him to Brittany and Turin; and he was in charge of the Advocates Library in Edinburgh for five years, beginning in 1752. He was then private secretary to the British ambassador in Paris and undersecretary of state.
How did Hume proceed philosophically to create his science of the mind?
Hume formulated and applied, over a large range of subjects, two main principles. First, all of our knowledge is the result of either sense impressions or reflections on the workings of our own mind. Second, no matter of fact can be proved a priori, or before experience. As Hume put it: All the perceptions of the human mind resolve themselves into two distinct kinds, which I shall call impressions and ideas. He held that the sciences of the natural world and beliefs about human society are the result of empirical investigation. The truths of mathematics and logic are known without investigating the world. For this reason, they are not about the world, but about the workings of human minds. Our sensory information, which gives us immediate factual knowledge, is more compelling than our ideas. As Hume stated: The most lively thought is still inferior to the dullest sensation. Hume had no use for past philosophical projects that contained a priori speculation about the workings of this world or the next. Here is how he summed up this doctrine: If we take into our hand any volume; of divinity or school metaphysics, for instance; let us ask, Does it contain any abstract reasoning concerning quantity or number? No. Does it contain any experimental reasoning concerning matter of fact and existence? No. Consign it then to the flames: For it can contain nothing but sophistry and illusion.
166
ume famously denied any evidence for the existence of a self as a substance or soul. He wrote: For my part, when I enter most intimately into what I call myself, I always stumble on some particular perception or other, of heat or cold, light or shade, love or hatred, pain or pleasure. I never can catch myself at any time without a perception, and never can observe any thing but the perception. He went on to explain that what a person calls his or her self is no more than a bundle or bundles of perceptions, no one of which is a direct idea of a self-thing.
produces an association of the ideas of causes and effects with each other. For example, the idea of bread is associated with the idea of nourishment.
What is the big problem with Humes reduction of the self to perceptions?
Overall, Hume saw the mind as a kind of theater stage, across which ideas pass, with each idea a separate existence of sense or logical relation. He did not address the implied question of whom the audience is that has access to this theater. What he was looking for and failed to find was an object of reflection that could in a unitary, distinct way, justify the term self. He was not looking for the reflecter, or the I in search of its self. He simply assumed that this reflecter was not the self he was looking for
167
when one enters most intimately into what I call myself. Another way of putting this is that Humes analysis of the self cannot account for that process of analysis (of reflecting on ones own ideas). Hume did not take into account the fact that he was reflecting, and that the thing he was that was reflecting is what is meant by the word self.
168
169
J E AN-JA C Q U E S RO U S S EA U
Who was Rousseau?
Jean-Jacques Rousseau (17121778) was an original political philosopher who may have contributed more than any other single person to the motivations for the French Revolution. He was, in addition, a highly creative novelist capable of gathering a reading public into a community that lived vicariously through his characters, some locking themselves up for days to sentimentally enjoy his latest novel. For these reasons, Rousseau may have been the first modern celebrity-philosopher.
170
Political Right), and mile; or, On Education (1762). All of these writings were critical of established religion and therefore banned in both France and the canton or city-state of Geneva. Rousseau fled arrest in 1762 (brought on by the uproar about his political ideas), and after some disorganized travels, finally, in 1765, prevailed on the hospitality of the very English David Hume (17111776). The latter situation did not work out, however. Rousseau reentered France in 1770 under the assumed name Renou, and went to Paris. He had begun work on the Confessions, in England, but the completed edition was not published until after his death. He wrote Considerations on the Government of Poland after an invitation to make recommendations for a constitution for the Polish-Lithuanian Jean-Jacques Rousseau argued for the natural goodness Commonwealth. This was followed by his of mankind (iStock). Dialouges: Rousseau (1776, published in 1782), Confessions of Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1782), and Reveries of the Solitary Walker (1782). He then wrote an analysis of Glucks opera Alceste, before dying suddenly in 1778.
171
Rousseau himself is said to have had five children by Thrse Levasseur, and each one was brought to an orphanage at birth. Those individuals who already hated Rousseau, such as Voltaire (16941778), pointed out that most children in orphanages at that time perished. Rousseaus only defense was that he did not think he would have been a good father. When a friend of Rousseaus noted that the course of education described in mile was not practical, Rousseau wrote back: You say quite correctly that it is impossible to produce an mile. But I cannot believe that you take the book that carries this name for a true treatise on education. It is rather a philosophical work on this principle advanced by the author in other writings that man is naturally good. If Rousseau did not take himself seriously as an educational theorist, then his own behavior as a parent would not have meant that he was a hypocrite on that score. The question, however, remains whether this behavior qualifies him as naturally good, so the question of hypocrisy does not go away that easily.
Rousseau postulated that individual rights are given up to the community in the founding contract. In return, the individual becomes a citizen whose rights are protected. But this is an active model of citizenship because the individual is required to agree to the general will at the same time that he or she acts in self-interest.
172
what is good for the community, is enacted by legislators into laws. This general will, or communal good, may at times be opposed to what is simply good for the majority. Rousseaus proposal for the ideal society was thus focused on the end or goal of that society. He thought that direct democracy was usually the best means for achieving that end in small societies, but in larger societies representative democracy, or even monarchy, would be more appropriate. Rousseau also advocated some form of state religion that would be binding on all citizens and require their participation for the sake of social coherence and stability.
T H O MAS R E I D AN D J E R E M Y B E NTHA M
Why was Thomas Reid important?
Thomas Reid (17101796) was the founder of Scottish Common Sense Philosophy, which was prominent in English thought during the first half of the nineteenth century, and was revived by G.E. Moore (18731958) in his attack on idealism in the twentieth century. Reids basic contribution was a criticism of the doctrine of ideas in philosophy, which in his own time was famously deployed by David Hume (17111776), although it had strong predecessors in John Locke (16321704) and George Berkeley (16851783). Reid believed that it is impossible that what we know are sensations or ideas in the mind because this cant account for the immediacy of our experience of objects present to the senses, motion, or our experience of our own selves. Reid thought that we directly know real objects in the world, just like we assume in common sense. For example, when you look at a computer screen as you type, you do not perceive the idea of the screen, but rather the screen itself. His common sense was to insist on the location of the knower directly in the world, with no mediation in the mind by ideas, sensations, or impressions.
Did Thomas Reid have his own ideas, in addition to saying why the empiricists were wrong?
Yes, and Reid was highly influential for a while, although he is often overlooked as an Enlightenment philosopher. He lectured at Kings College, Aberdeen, and held the chair of moral philosophy at Glasgow. His main publications were An Inquiry into the Human Mind on the Principles of Common Sense (1764), Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man (1785), and Essays on the Active Powers of Man (1788). After rejecting the empiricist representative theory of knowledge, Reid developed an intuitionist theory of knowledge in terms of mental faculties: Reid thought that we have innate powers of conception and conviction. There are first principles that we can identify by their early appearance, universality, and irresistibility. We could not
173
What can now be said about the dispute between Thomas Reid and the empiricists?
n terms of the process of knowledge, as a matter of physiological psychology concerning what goes on in the brain, there may well be ideas or representations in the brain, as the empiricists maintained. However, in the mind, our direct experience seems not to be of our ideas or sensations but of the objects we sense themselves, as Reid pointed out.
deny an irresistible principle. For instance, sensations are operations of the mind that, together with impressions made on our sense organs, cause our conceptions of primary and secondary qualities. A sensation of smell thus suggests that there is a quality in the object causing the sensation. In analyzing vision, Reid reasoned that the data are received on the round surface of the eye, but processed within it. He concluded that visual space must have a non-Euclidian geometry of curved space (he was about a century ahead of his time in postulating non-Euclidian geometry). In addition to faculties of perception and memory, Reid posited a moral faculty resulting in conceptions of justice or injustice that may differ, depending on different peoples conceptions of the same action. He also posited active powers, leading to action, according to principles of action. When Reid spoke of powers in this way, he seemed to mean capabilities in the mind. The principles of action were animal principles (such as appetites and physical desires) and rational principles that include understanding and will.
174
175
eremy Bentham founded University College in London and bequeathed to it something called the Auto-icon, which contains his own embalmed body. After his death in 1832, the philosopher had his remains preserved and put on display in this large cabinet. It is said that the College Council depends on Bentham to resolve tied votes, a rumor the Council denies utterly. The head on display in the Auto-icon is bogus, however, as the original head was stored more securely elsewhere after it was damaged by student pranksters.
nic calculus consisted of literally quantifying pleasures and pains according to these factors: how near or far, how long-lasting, how intense, how likely to cause pleasure or pain of the same kind, and how many are affected.
I M M AN U E L K A NT
Was Immanuel Kant an important figure of the Enlightenment?
Yes, Immanuel Kant (17241804) was more intellectually influential in the nineteenth century and beyond than any other Enlightenment philosopher because he constructed a system of reason from which empiricism and the sciences could be derived. Kant thereby, theoretically, ended any residual tensions between rationalism and empiricism because his rationalism allowed for empiricism. In that sense, he was the epitome of the Age of Reason. Of course, for those who ignored Kant, the business of philosophy remained empiricism, idealism, or rationalism, as usual.
176
vatdozent (Private docent, or P.D.) to teach physics, mathematics, anthropology, geography, and some philosophy. (In his courses on anthropology and geology, he taught the prevailing view of European racial supremacy over Asians and Africans.) He was poor until 1770, when he secured the position of chair of logic and metaphysics at Knigsberg. Other European intellectuals, such as Jean-Jacques Rousseau (17121778), whom Kant greatly admired, constantly moved and traveled to secure their fame and livings, with amorous and political adventure, as a kind of byproduct of their intellectual careers. But that was not for Kant. He never left the area of East Prussia, and remained a bachelor in Knigsberg (now Kaliningrad) all his life. When the Prussian king asked him not to publish further about religion in 1794, he duly complied. Kants health was fragile, Immanuel Kant constructed a system of reason from which empiricism and the sciences could be derived (iStock). but he took care of himself, living until he was 80. He relied on travelers and published works for information about the outside world and was content to dine with friends and fulfill his professorial duties, including a term as rector of the university. Kants early works were about natural science, the most notable being his General History of Nature and Theory of the Heavens (1755). His magnum opus was The Critique of Pure Reason, but when it finally appeared in 1781 few could understand it. He tried to make his ideas more accessible in his Prolegomena to Every Future Metaphysics (1783). This was followed by his 1790 Critique of Practical Reason and the Critique of Judgment. In 1793 and 1797, he published Religion within the Bounds of Mere Reason and the Metaphysic of Morals. Kant was by then famous, but younger thinkers undertook to explain his system better than he had. He was working on his response to them in his Opus Postumum when he died.
177
Was Immanuel Kant only interested in the foundations for knowledge of the physical world?
o. In addition to what Kant held to be mans universal awe for the starry heavens above, he addressed the moral law within as a subject of practical reason. He also had lasting things to say about the self and belief in God.
be the case in order to account for what is known. And his metaphysics is transcendental in that what ultimately exists exceeds and eludes both our direct knowledge and full understanding, even though we are justified in postulating it according to certain principles of reason.
178
Kants solution was to apply a transcendental deduction to such principles and show that without them experience would not be possible. For example, concerning
causation, he argued that consciousness itself requires orderly experience based on necessary connections in reality. This was Kants answer to David Humes (17111776) reduction of causation to constant conjunction. He rejected Humes skepticism that constant conjunction is all that there is by claiming that the world could only make sense to us if we assumed that that there were real causal connections in it. In his Prolegomena to Every Future Metaphysics (1783), Kant famously said that Hume had awakened him from his dogmatic slumbers.
179
es. He lived a very precise and orderly life, and his neighbors claimed to be able to set their clocks by his daily walks. During the 1770s, he retreated into what biographers call his silent decade. He set himself the task of figuring out how perception and intellect are connected. Never a bon vivant, he withdrew from even minimal social contact. But he was very forthright about what was going on in his life and did not make the usual social excuses. When a former student tried to coax him out, he responded in this manner: Any change makes me apprehensive, even if it offers the greatest promise of improving my condition, and I am persuaded by this natural instinct of mine that I must take heed if I wish that the threads which the Fates spin so thin and weak in my case to be spun to any length. My great thanks, to my well-wishers and friends, who think so kindly of me as to undertake my welfare, but at the same time a most humble request to protect me in my current condition from any disturbance.
scendental ego is the necessary origin of those fundamental structures of thought and intuition that are necessary for experience. The transcendental ego is known only as an object of thought, and not as an object of direct experience.
181
182
183
arate houses. Their daughter, Mary, became Mary Shelley, the author of Frankenstein. Fanny committed suicide at the age of 22.
T H E P H I LO S O P H E S
Who were the philosophes?
The term philosophe can and has been applied to virtually all intellectuals who advocated change in the world order during the decades leading up to the American and French revolutions. In that sense, David Hume, Jeremy Bentham, and Benjamin Franklin were all philosophes. However, to tell a manageable history of philosophy it is useful to narrow the term down to the French encyclopedists and Adam Smith, Edward Gibbon, Gotthold Lessing, and Cesare Beccaria.
184
What was individually noteworthy about Diderot, dAlembert, Holbach, and Montesquieu?
Denis Diderot (17131784) was the general editor of the Encyclopedia. His The Skeptics Walk (1747) was a robust attack on Christianity. His claim that the universe was wholly material and evolving, as asserted in Letter on the Blind (1749), resulted in a brief imprisonment. Diderots comedies were considered secondrate, but his literary analyses created the new genre of literary criticism. Jean le Rond dAlembert (1717 1783) was the chief philosopher in the encylopedists project. In his Discours prliminaire he divided a philosophy of man into pneumatolDenis Diderot is credited with creating the field of literary criticism (Art Archive). ogy (or the human soul), logic, and ethics. He held that the substance of the universe cannot be known, and in Essay on the Elements of Philosophy (1759) defined the field as a comparison of phenomena (that is, appearances). Baron Paul-Henri-Dietrich dHolbach (17231789) was a major contributor to the encyclopedia. He was a solicitor at the Paris Parlement and hosted philosophical dinners. He systematized Diderots naturalism and published anonymous, irreligious treatises applying philosophy against the Catholic Church. He argued that everything in existence was based on matter and motion in a completely determined universe. Holbach thought that Christian virtues were unnatural, that piety was fanaticism, and that church officials were immoral. He was also a utilitarian. Baron de La Brde et de Montesquieu (Charles-Louis de Secondat; 16891755) was the chief political encyclopedist. His most famous work is The Spirit of the Laws (17401748) in which he argued that governments can be divided into republics, monarchies, or despotisms, which are respectively motivated by political virtue, honor, and fear. Types of government depend on the character, history, and geography of a people. A constitutional government with a separation of executive, legislative, and judicial powers is the only form that can protect liberty. This idea influenced the framers of the U.S. Constitution.
185
186
187
A witty playwright, poet, and essayist, Voltaire was a widely read French popularizer of Isaac Newton and John Locke (iStock).
Voltaires Letter on Mr. Locke in his Philosophical Dictionary took up a possibility raised by Locke of matter being able to think. However, later in life, he retreated to a skeptical position on such materialism after it was taken up by the philosophes in defense of atheism.
188
Founding Fathers of the United States such as Benjamin Franklin (left) and Thomas Jefferson were energized by the Age of Enlightenment and the flourishing ideals of liberty and democracy (iStock).
Its still better to bet that he is, because if he isnt, we lose nothing. Whereas, if we bet that he isnt and he isnt, we are merely confirmed in our misery, but if he turns out to exist, we go to hell when we die. Voltaire would have none of this. Voltaire believed that the design evident in nature was proof of Gods existence, as First Cause, Prime Mover, and Supreme Intelligence. However, he thought that God was indifferent to human concerns, and tried to resolve the problem of evil: How can a benevolent and omnipotent God permit evil to exist? Votaire was very distressed by the Lisbon earthquake and tidal wave that struck on All Saints Day in 1755, killing thousands. In his Pome sur le dsastre de Lisbonne (1755) he rejected both Leibnizian optimism and the doctrine of original sin. He concluded that all humans can do is accept such evil and continue to worship. In Zadig and Other Writings his sense of religious awe was further stressed; he maintained an attitude of tolerance for the rest of his life, with ongoing interests in the teachings of Confucius and the Quakers. In his final years, Voltaire overtly attacked the Catholic Church for its intolerance. He proclaimed, Those who can make you believe absurdities, can make you commit atrocities.
189
These optimistic ideas were inspirational in the writings of Thomas Paine, Benjamin Franklin, Thomas Jefferson, and others. The American separation of church from state, as an article of individual libertyagainst oppressive government religion, and for free thought and speechcame directly from Enlightenment ideas, as did the division of the powers of government and the distrust of government. It should be noted, however, that libertinism and outright atheism were to remain European phenomena for a very long time. Under the inspiration of Jonathan Edwards (17031758), American Protestant religious philosophy flourished in the late eighteenth century in a New England Born-Again movement known as the Great Awakening.
York City, and became a leader of the Great Awakening in 1729 in Massachusetts. His theology was a Puritan form of Calvinism. Edwards interest in philosophy included Nicolas Malebranche (16381715), the Cambridge Platonists, and John Locke (16321704). He was himself an idealist, similar to George Berkeley (16851783), who held that human minds are made up of thoughts and sensations, God being the only true substance.
190
If you cry to God to pity you, he will be so far from pitying you in your doleful case, or showing you the least regard or favour, that instead of that, he will only tread you under foot. And though he will know that you cannot bear the weight of omnipotence treading upon you, yet he will not regard that, but he will crush you under his feet without mercy; he will crush out your blood, and make it fly, and it shall be sprinkled on his garments, so as to stain all his raiment. He will not only hate you, but he will have you in the utmost contempt: no place shall be thought fit for you, but under his feet to be trodden down as the mire of the streets. And, insofar as the virtuous strive to emulate God, Edwards felt it is fitting that they enjoy the suffering of such sinners in Hell. In 1758, in his Why Saints in Glory Will Rejoice to See the Torments of the Damned, Edwards wrote: When they shall see how miserable others of their fellow-creatures are, who were naturally in the same circumstances with themselves; when they shall see the smoke of their torment, and the raging of the flames of their burning, and hear their dolorous shrieks and cries, and consider that they in the meantime are in the most blissful state, and shall surely be in it to all eternity; how will they rejoice!
C O U NT E R-E N LI G HTE N M E NT F I G U R E S
Which Counter-Enlightenment figures had lasting effects on philosophy?
Giovanni Battista (Giambattista) Vico, or Vigo (16681744), has in recent years been rediscovered, or discovered, as an important philosopher. Edmund Burke (17291797) was the most explicit conservative of modern times, although Joseph-Marie de Maistre (17531821) held similar views. Also, Jonathan Swift (16671745) deserves mention as a mordant critic of the establishment in general, and the Marquis de Sade (17401814) represents a kind of extreme marginality in his depravity, which marginality was later taken up by nineteenth and twentieth century progressiveshe also remains genuinely outrageous!
191
Did Vico interact with other Enlightenment thinkers over his lifetime?
No. Giambattista Vicos circumstances did not afford him the leisure of an intellectual vocation. Outside of Italy, only the German intellectuals, such as Johann Georg Hamann and Johann Gottfried von Herder, knew of his work. Italy was not united during his lifetime. Naples endured constant upheavals as Spain, Austria, and France took it over. Additional political stress resulted from the strength of the Jesuits within the city. Vicos father was a bookseller in Naples. After fracturing his skull as a child, Vico could not attend school for three years, so he read on his own. When he did enroll in university, he proved to be an undisciplined student. He concentrated on logic and medieval scholasticism before settling on law. But, after assisting his own father in a lawsuit in his teens, he never practiced law again. For 10 years after 1685, Vico worked as a tutor, reading on his own in philosophy, history, ethics, jurisprudence, and poetry. He did not like mathematics, nor was he particularly interested in science. By the time Vico became professor of rhetoric at the University of Naples in 1695, it was a Cartesian center dedicated to the study of Ren Descartes philosophy. And Vico was opposed to many aspects of Cartesianism, especially his rationalism. From 16991708, Vico delivered the beginning lecture for the University every year. Of the essays that developed from those lectures, On the Study Methods of Our Time (1709), was well received for its advocacy of liberal education. This was quickly followed by his 1709 lecture, On the Most Ancient Knowledge of the Italians. In 1722 his three volume Universal Law was complete, and in 1725 both his autobiography and The New Science, which was to be revised in 1730 and 1744, were released. Vico failed to be promoted to chair of civil law and had to write poems and vanity pieces for hire to make a living. He grew bitter and his lifelong melancholy worsened. His death in 1744 followed an agonizing illness.
192
Signor Giambattista Vico, he was born in Naples in the year 1670 of upright parents, who left behind them a very good reputation. The father was of cheerful humor, the mother of a quite melancholy temper; and both came together in the fair disposition of this little son of theirs. As a boy he was very lively and restless; but at the age of seven he fell headfirst from high on a ladder to the floor, and remained a good five hours motionless and senseless, fracturing the right side of the cranium without breaking the skin, hence from the fracture arose a shapeless tumor, and from the many deep lancings of it the child lost a great deal of blood; such that the surgeon, having observed the broken cranium and considering the long state of unconsciousness, made the prediction that he would either die of it or he would survive stolid. However, neither of the two parts of this judgment, by the grace of God, came true; but as a result of this illness and recovery he grew up, from then on, with a melancholy and acrid nature which necessarily belongs to ingenious and profound men, who through ingenuity flash like lightning in acuity, through reflection take no pleasure in witticism and falsity.
seeking the same kind of certain knowledge in science that mathematics yielded. In his first book, On the Ancient Italian Knowledge, (1710) Vico argued that Descartes was wrong in holding awareness of his own existence as a first philosophical principle, and in trying to prove Gods existence through reason alone. Vicos own view was that the mind does not make itself and for that reason cannot know how it has knowledge of itself. Concerning mathematical and even scientific certainty, Vico did not think we can arrive at it through clear and distinct ideas, as Descartes claimed. He claimed that mathematical knowledge is certainly true because the human mind has created the very standard for mathematical truth, or because we have made mathematics. However, God has made the physical universe, and only He can have certain knowledge about that. Vico did concede that when we do make things in nature, or through scientific experiment, we can gain knowledge from the confirmation of our hypotheses.
193
194
reestablish proven rights or customs. For example, while he was opposed to the French Revolution for its ideals of liberty, equality, fraternity, he was in favor of the Irish movement for independence and the American Revolution.
195
Joseph-Marie de Maistre believed that the Catholic Church would eventually triumph over the objective, scientific ideas of the Enlightenment (Art Archive).
Jonathan Swift, known for his satires such as Gullivers Travels, did not believe that humans were particularly rational creatures (iStock).
Aquinas [c. 12251274]). He viewed the French Revolution as satanic, in his 1796 Considerations on France. However, de Maistre went beyond Burke in his belief that the Catholic Church would triumph over Enlightenment philosophy. In his 1810 Essay on the Generating Principle of Political Constitutions, he described a fundamental human and God-ordained desire for order and discipline.
196
At the same time, Swift also wrote another strange poem, A Beautiful Young Nymph Going to Bed, which is about a woman who repulsively removes all the parts of herself, including prostheses, that made her seem attractive. Swift apparently had an obsession about the falseness of women. Although he was a priest in the Anglican Church, he had a 17-year love affair with Esther Vanhomrigh, a former tutee, whom he rejected for the younger Esther Johnson, known in his writings as Stella. Esther Vanhomrigh, or Vanessa to Swift, was the friend who left money to George Berkeley (16851783). She died soon after Swift finally rejected her. Esther Johnson also died young. In 1742, Swift was pronounced of unsound mind and memory, incapable of looking after himself or his affairs. When Swift died in 1745, he left his estate to found an insane asylum, but he was apparently not insane from psychological causes. Rather, he had labyrinthine vertigo, known as Mnires Disease, a physiological ailment that was not well understood in his day. His final words were, I am a fool. Swifts Latin epitaph reads in English: When savage indignation can no longer torture the heart, proceed, traveler, and, if you can, imitate the strenuous avenger of noble liberty.
He sent up the established respectability of his age through forays into fiction, as well as the rhetoric of a pamphleteer. Thus, when it became clear that he would not get support for the plight of the poor in Ireland, he and his friends founded the Scribelous Club for the sake of engaging in activity against the dunces. Swift is most famous for his 1726 satire, Gullivers Travels. His 1729 A Modest Proposal for Preventing the Children of Poor People from Being a Burthen to Their Parents or Country, and for Making Them Beneficial to the Public was a shocking criticism of the treatment of the Irish poor in which he suggested that their babies be substituted for the traditional goose that graced the tables of absentee English landlords.
197
Virtue), Juliette (Vice Richly Rewarded), 120 Days of Sodom (The School of Licentiousness), Incest, and The Crimes of Love. In an age that was not strongly focused on vice and sin, he managed to spend over 30 years of his life incarceratedin an insane asylum, as well as in prisonmostly on account of his writing. The term sadism is based on his name.
When prostitutes in Paris complained of de Sades abuse, he was exiled to his castle. Then he had an affair with his sister-in-law, for which his mother-in-law secured an arrest warrant from the king. A series of arrests and escapes in which his wife was his accomplice ensued. He was confined to an insane asylum at Charenton after being imprisoned in the Bastille. In the asylum, the Abb allowed him to produce plays. When he was released in 1790, his wife divorced him.
198
Dworkin (19462005) analyzed de Sade to illustrate the inherently violent misogynistic nature of all heterosexual pornography.
199
N I N E T E E NT H C E NTU RY E M P I R I C I S M
What happened that affected empiricism in the nineteenth century?
Empiricism became systematized as an overall philosophical methodology with applications for science, ethics, and political science. This was largely the work of two men who did not agree with each other, William Whewell (17941866) and John Stuart Mill
201
(18061873), and a third, Auguste Comte (17981857), who founded the new school of thought called positivism. Comte was also important in founding sociology, but can be considered here as an empiricist for his methodology. Whewell was primarily focused on science and its popularization. Mill was able to bring a coherent explanation of empirical science into philosophy because his empiricism was more easily accepted by empiricist philosophers than was Whewells. Mill also extended empiricism to ethics, political philosophy, and rights for women. Comte was the most extreme empiricist to date, and in the twentieth century positivism was revisited as a method for doing philosophy in general.
WI LLIAM WH EWE LL
Who was William Whewell?
William Whewell (17941866) was a polymath who contributed work to mechanics, mineralogy, geology, astronomy, political economy, theology, education, law, architecture, ethics, the philosophy of science, and what he named tideology. He was a founder and president of the British Association for the Advancement of Science, and a fellow of the Royal Society. Whewell invented the term scientist analogously with artist. He was the most influential figure in British education in the nineteenth century.
202
at scientific knowledge. However, he did not go as far as Kant in locating the possibility for scientific knowledge wholly within the mind. That is, unlike Kant, Whewell thought that the world as it is known to human beings exists independently of human minds. Neither did Whewell go as far as the empiricists, who emphasized induction and observation, in what he called the sensationalistic school.
203
he purpose of the British Association of Science is to promote sustainability and make science and technology accessible to the public. However, on the organizations website they credit David Brewster, who invented the Kaleidoscope in 1815, as its principal founder, not William Whewell. The Association now has about 3,000 members, is mainly concerned with the popularization of science, and sponsors a Young Scientist program that has about 12,000 members. Each year since 1932, the British Association of Science has held a Festival of Science, featuring hundreds of speakers. You can learn more about their current activities at http://www.the-ba.net/the-ba/.
to construct phenomenal laws or generalizations, and causal laws, or explanations. This is where he described colligation as a renovation of Francis Bacons (1561 1626) principles. In colligation, the mind superinduces upon facts some conception that can be used to generalize. For example, Whewell described astronomer Johannes Kepler as having colligated the points of the Martian orbit. Whewell argued that discovery occurs not as the result of new facts, but in applying the right conception to existing facts. Thus, according to Whewell, Kepler applied his ellipse conception to the facts of Mars orbit that were already collected by the Danish astronomer Tycho Brahe. Whewell believed that choosing the right conception to colligate facts cannot be done by simple observation or guesswork, but requires a special process in the mind in which we infer more than we see. Once theories are created, theories can be extended to what cannot be observed, such as light waves, orbit shapes, and gravity. In other words, Whewell thought that we always approach experience with something in mind that helps us interpret experience and go beyond it.
How did William Whewell think consilience, coherence, and predictions should be applied to test theories?
Scientific theories must withstand the tests of consilience, coherence, and prediction. Consilience refers to new kinds of cases confirming the theory. A theorys coherence is its ability to explain new kinds of facts. The theorys coherence ought to increase over time. Predictions should turn out to be accurate. Once they have withstood such tests, theories and basic scientific principles become necessaryit is a contradiction to deny them, given an understanding of their meaning.
204
J O H N S T UA RT M I L L
Why was John Stuart Mill important?
John Stuart Mill (18061873) is to this day studied most for his work on ethics, which codified utilitarianism, one of the three major philosophical moral systems, along with virtue ethics and deontology. However, he had important political influence, too, as a British progressive, and also codified the empirical philosophy of science. His contributions to both democratic progress and the philosophy of science were so influential that they are often taken for granted politically and in definitions of science, without a perceived need to trace their authorship.
205
human values, such as the preservation of the environment and limited population. He argued that the ideal economy would be made up of worker-owned cooperatives. Mills On Liberty (1859) was his most contested work because it was an attack on the leveling effects of social opinion. Mill thought that democratic societies imposed conventions on their members that did not allow for much individual experimentation in life styles. His more conservative contemporaries objected to the freedoms of opinion he championed, as well as his idea that if what others consider a vice does not harm them, they have no right to interfere with an individual who practices it. His Utilitarianism (1861) argued for the greatest good for the greatest number of people, in which the greatest good is defined as happiness. His On the Subjection of Women (1869) has endured as a classic feminist work. His last major work, Three Essays on Religion (1874), was a rational perspective on religion, but was neither agnostic nor atheistic. Mill reasoned that there probably was a God, but that the amount of human suffering in the world made it unlikely that God was very benevolent toward human beings.
What did John Stuart Mill think about Jeremy Benthams pleasure principle?
Jeremy Bentham (17481832) had introduced the idea that the only thing good in itself was pleasure. By the time Mill wrote his ethics, this was widely known as Benthams Pleasure Principle. Mill recognized the value of pleasure, but was more interested in happiness.
How did John Stuart Mill define the difference between higher and lower pleasures?
Mill did not think that a simple quantitative calculus could be used to make moral decisions. He argued that there were lower pleasures that were mainly connected with immediate physical gratification and delight, and higher pleasures that involved delayed gratification or prior diligence. The higher pleasures, such as those found in the cultivation and enjoyment of art, literature, poetry, and friendship, were better than the lower pleasures. Mills proof that they were better was the testimony of those who had experienced both the lower and higher pleasures.
206
Did John Stuart Mill have much chance to indulge in the pleasure principle as he grew up?
he pleasure principle was certainly not applied to Mills young life in the same sense as Jeremy Benthams (17481832) formulation, although it possibly was in Mills more nuanced version of utilitarianism, which distinguished between higher and lower pleasures. Mills father, James, with help from his friend Bentham, educated the young Mill at home. Young John knew Greek at three, Latin at five, logic by 12, and economics by 16. He was also deeply schooled in a social mission to increase the good for the greatest number through progressive political programs. Mill had a nervous breakdown at 20. Biographers believe that his highly structured and rigorous childhood education was the cause of an emotional imbalance. The humanities had been neglected in his education, and his social interactions with peers were limited by the demands of his studies. Mill then began a course of study in literature to develop his more humanistic sensibilities. He read romantic poetry and Johann Wolfgang von Goethe, and he began to rethink Benthams simple hedonic calculus. The result was Mills famous distinction between higher and lower pleasures and a scathing assessment of Benthams character as oblivious and uncultured: Bentham, an essay first published in the London and Westminster Review in 1838, and revised in 1859 for his own Dissertations and Discussion, Volume 1.
poverty. He believed in democratic government, provided that citizens were wellinformed and it was not a simple majority rule based on emotions.
207
What are John Stuart Mills progressive ideas in The Subjection of Women?
Mill begins The Subjection of Women (1869) by saying that it is more difficult to argue against a position that is held on irrational grounds than one based on reasoning. (Ren Descartes [15961650] made a similar claim at the beginning of his Meditations.) Those who hold irrational views will not be persuaded to change them by rational argument but will just look for a more profound basis of their opinion, even to the point of claiming it is the result of instinct. This set the stage for Mills claim that the condition of women at the time he wrote was the result of a long historical tradition of might makes right, combined with the power enjoyed by all men simply by being born male. He compared this condition to slavery on a number of counts: women were completely dependent on men for their livelihood, being deprived of education and means for productive employment; women did not have control over their own bodies or children in marriage; women lacked civil rights, such as the right to vote or own property; and women were subject to violence and rape within marriage, without legal recourse. Mill also claimed that women were trained to display the traits of mind and character (or lack thereof) that would make them desirable subordinates to men: stupidity, preoccupation with appearance, and adoration of and submission to men. Men assumed that all women wanted to be wives and mothers, which made their exclusion of them from education and the professions ironic, to say the least. But although marriage appeared to be a contractual relationship, women did not have any real freedom to withhold their consent because they could not earn a living on their own.
208
Against existing arguments that women were not the equals of men, Mill claimed that insofar as women had been so suppressed by their circumstances in marriage
and lack of education, men knew very little about what their true capabilities were. He claimed that the highest masculine and the highest feminine characters were clearly equal.
What was John Stuart Mills view of logic and scientific methodology?
Foremost, Mill argued that deductive logic does not depend on intuition for its proof, but rather on internal consistency. The foundational assumptions or axioms of all sciences are based on experience. Even the shared scientific axiom that nature is uniform or law-like is proved through simple enumeration of confirming examples, that is, through induction. More specific causal explanations do no more than summarize necessary and sufficient conditions: A necessary condition is always present when the effect occurs; the effect is always present when a sufficient condition is present. For example,
209
arriet Taylor (18071858) was John Stuart Mills wife. He met her when he was 25, while still recovering from his nervous breakdown. She had been married since the age of 18 to John Taylor, with whom she had three sons. Mill and Harriet Taylor had what they described as a platonic relationship, until the death of her husband after 20 years of marriage. At one point, the Taylors separated, with Harriet taking her daughter to live with her, while John raised their sons. Some feminist writers believe that Harriet was actually the author of Mills The Subjection of Women, (1869) as well as other writings, such as On Liberty (1859), for which Mill gave her great credit. Taylors contemporary detractors referred to her as that stupid woman, and said she only appeared to have been Mills collaborator because she was adept at repeating what he had already said or written. Taylor published very little in her own name. She was a founding member of the Kensington Society, which circulated the first petition for the rights of women, and she contributed articles to the Unitarian journal, Monthly Repository. Mill was without question extremely devoted to her, and after her death he wrote: Were I but capable of interpreting to the world one half the great thoughts and noble feelings which are buried in her grave, I should be the medium of a greater benefit to it, than is ever likely to arise from anything that I can write, unprompted and unassisted by her all but unrivalled wisdom.
a bullet to the brain is sufficient to cause death in most cases, but it is not necessary because people die from other causes. Or, oxygen is necessary to cause fire, but it is not sufficient because fire requires friction and combustible material, as well as oxygen. Mill also thought that the basic principles of arithmetic and geometry could be proved by induction. He agreed with Isidore Marie Auguste Franois Xavier Comte (17981857) about a unified view of the social sciences, whereby the laws for more general sciences could be derived from what is known about more specific sciences. For example, observations of individual human behavior could result in a science of psychology, and observations of individual psychology could result in a science of society or sociology. It should be noted that much subsequent theoretical work in mathematics and social science did not find Mills ideas useful.
210
AU G U STE C O MTE
Who was Auguste Comte?
Isidore Marie Auguste Franois Xavier Comte (17981857) was famous and influential in his day as a sociologist, and even coined the word sociologie. He was the first Western sociologist. Comte has also endured as the founder of positivism. Comte taught mathematics for a while at lcole Polytechnique in Paris, where he himself was educated. Although mental illnessto the extent of psychotic episodes that required hospitalizationinterfered with his work, his condition stabilized enough for him to complete his major work during a marriage that ended in divorce. After the woman he loved in a subsequent platonic relationship died, he formulated his mission to create a new religion of humanity. Comte published Cours de philosophie positive (Course in Positive Philosophy) in six volumes from 1830 to 1832.
211
The theological phase contains religious restrictions and belief in the supernatural. The metaphysical phase involves the justification of political rights above authority. In the scientific phase, solutions to social problems can be found. By combining these laws of phases, Comte developed an Encyclopedic Law, according to which all of the sciences could be ordered into a hierarchy in which sociology was the greatest and included all of the others. Comte wrote: If it is true that every theory must be based upon observed facts, it is equally true that facts can not be observed without the guidance of some theories. He thus posited an interconnection between facts and theories, which holds to this day.
I NTU ITI O N I S M
What was nineteenth century intuitionism?
To some extent all philosophical systems have a place for intuition: direct knowledge that is non-inferential or cannot be proved by prior argument and for which there is no way to resolve doubts. Mill thought that William Whewells (17941866) philosophy of science was intuitive, although it was in places quite inferential. However, Whewell did have an explicitly intuitionist moral theory. Other noteworthy nineteenth century intuitionists were William Hamilton, F.H. Bradley, Henry Sidgwick, James Martineau, and, toward the end of the century and into the next, Henri Bergson.
How did John Stuart Mill criticize William Whewells view of moral intuitionism?
ills criticism of Whewells moral intuitionism was that it implied that morality could not progress because necessary truths are always true. Mill further claimed that Whewells necessary moral truths would preserve the status quo, and he charged Whewell with conservatively supporting slavery, marriage without womens consent, and cruelty to animals. What Mill missed, however, was that, as with Fundamental Ideas in science, Whewell held that we may not know all of the relevant rules of morality. Thus, discovering these rules allowed for moral progress.
losophy. He agreed with Immanuel Kant (17241804) that we cannot know things in themselves, but also with Thomas Reid (17101796) about naturalism. Reids idea that we know things in the world directly and Kants idea that we do not know things in themselves are contradictory. Hamilton believed that they could be mysteriously combined through intuition. John Stuart Mill (18061873), in An Examination of Sir William Hamiltons Philosophy (1865), vigorously attacked Hamiltons notion that scientific principles are intuitively valid, rather than valid on account of their ability to provide causal explanations, as Mill thought.
213
believe that morality is an intrinsic value, which, depending on their social status, they self-realize in their actions. Good selves could be actualized only if bad selves were suppressed. Therefore, the good self requires the bad self and morality can never be completely actualized unless oneself dies through surrender to Christianity.
214
radley was made a fellow at Merton College, Oxford, in 1870. This was a lifetime position with no teaching duties, which only marriage could terminate. Bradley never married, and he lived on campus until he died. A kidney inflammation in 1871 left him careful of his health, and although he participated in the governance of the college, he avoided other social occasions. For instance, he turned down an opportunity to be a founder of the British Academy. Bradley detested cats and shot them on the college grounds, during the night. R.G. Collingwood, his neighbor for 16 years, later wrote: Although I lived within a few hundred yards of him I never to my knowledge set eyes on him.
cipal of Newnham in 1892. The Sidgwicks collaborated on many reform and intellectual projects, including investigations into parapsychology. Sidgwicks principal works are The Methods of Ethics (1874) and Outlines of the History of Ethics (1886).
215
an extent that he is often counted as a utilitarian himself. But second, it is his comparative assessment of egoism, utilitarianism, and intuitionism that remains most instructive. (Egoism is the moral system according to which we should always act in our own self-interest.) Sidgwick examined both common sense moral principles and the main claims of all three systems and concluded that none is self-evident or certain according to intuition. He thought that utilitarianism could be useful when we do not know what to do and seek guidance, but that the basic principles of utilitarianism depend on intuition for their acceptance. But egoism also seems self-evident, and it often conflicts with utilitarianism. Sidgwick admitted that he could not resolve this contradiction.
216
Henri Bergson is most famous for arguing that objective measurable time is not the same as real time (Library of Congress).
What did Henri Bergson have to say about laughter and the human sense of humor?
ergson wrote a 1900 analysis of laughter, which shows he was pretty interested in the concept of humor. He thought that the comical is a part of life that cannot be fully understood by reason alone. Laughter requires a state of indifference, according to Bergson, for laughter has no greater foe than emotion. He went on to say that the comic demands something like a momentary anesthesia of the heart. [I]ts appeal is to intelligence pure and simple.
To be comical, something must be rigid, like a facial grimace or a mechanical walk. Our perception of this rigidity is broken up by our laughter. Ordinary language bears Bergson out on this because we talk about being cracked up, or broken up when something is funny. Anything that switches our attention from the soul or moral realm to the body can be comical, said Bergson: for example, a speaker sneezing at a dramatic moment in his presentation. Bergson saw the overall purpose of comedy as a reassertion of life in an age of machines.
measurable time, which can be divided into equal segments, is not the same as real time, which we experience directly. In Matter and Memory (1896) he offered a mindbody theory consistent with his later work on evolution in which he argued that a creative urge, rather than Darwinian natural selection, is what causes evolution. In An Introduction to Metaphysics (1903) he provided further support for his theory of time. In Creative Evolution (1907) he claimed that a life force is necessary to explain evolution, and in Two Sources of Morality and Religion (1935) he claimed that there are two kinds of society: one free and allowing for reform and creativity, the other stagnant, conservative, and repressive.
217
P H I LO S O P HY O F MAT H E M ATI C S A N D LO G I C
Why did philosophers become interested in mathematics, geometry, and logic, during the nineteenth century?
Philosophers have always been interested in these subjects, but in the nineteenth century there were even more innovations in science and technology than before. Changes in the world had an invigorating effect on higher learning, and philosophers took an interest in new research in the sciences and mathematics. Logic had been a philosophical subject since Aristotle, so new forms of logic were of interest to many philosophers who were not logicians.
What advances were made during the nineteenth century concerning the philosophy of mathematics and logic?
During the nineteenth century, a logical theory of probability was propounded, nonEuclidian geometry was discovered, the objectivity and necessary truth of scientific first principles were questioned, a new system of logical notation was devised, and the possibility that mathematics could be reduced to logic was introduced.
218
Mathematican and astronomer Pierre-Simon Laplace was famous for his theory of probability (Art Archive).
probability was that if there is no reason to believe that one of a number of events, n, will occur, then the probability of each happening is 1/n. For example, the probability that any day of the week chosen at random will be either a Tuesday or a Thursday is 2/7.
219
auss (17771855) was meticulous, conservative, and did not much enjoy teaching or other disruptions of his work. He did not collaborate or help younger mathematicians. Neither did he appreciate interruptions. It is said that he was once concentrating on a problem when told that his wife was dying. He responded, Tell her to wait a moment till Im done.
220
Beltramis model of n-dimensional hyperbolic geometry in which points are represented by the points in the interior of the n-dimensional unit ball (or unit disk, in two dimensions, in this schematic) and lines are represented by the chords or straight line segments with endpoints on the boundary sphere (here, it is the circumference of the two-dimensional disk.)
A Venn diagram of sets A, B, and C. Where one or more sets overlap, it means that they have members in common. It can be seen by the overlapping in this diagram that some things are A, B, and C, some things are A and B, some things are B and C, and some things are A and C.
221
How can this be? Freges explanation was that there is a difference between sense and reference. Reference is the actual planet Venus, in this case. But sense is how the planet is referred to by the term Morning Star (i.e., a bright object in the eastern sky before sunrise). Thus, The Morning Star does not stand for Venus itself, but for the sense of how Venus is presented. This is why the two sentences that appear to be equivalent really are different. It explains why it is not informative to say that Venus is Venus or that The Morning Star is the Morning Star, but it is informative to say that Venus is the Morning Star.
222
G E R M AN I D EA LI S M
What is German idealism?
It was the philosophical perspective developed in the nineteenth century that reality is not physical but psychic, or mental. Its main author was Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (17701831). There were also British and American versions of Hegelian thought.
How were nineteenth century German idealists different from Plato or George Berkeley?
Before the nineteenth century, idealism tended to be a train of thought in individual writers who posited the existence of unseen entities and claimed greater reality for them than the things in the world that could be sensed. Except for Plotinus (205270) and other Neo-Platonists, idealism before the nineteenth century was limited to positing entities or structures that existed in a separate realm, independently of perceived reality, as humans perceive reality. The nineteenth century idealists, in contrast, posited ideal entities and structures and also described their functions in ways that directly influenced the perceived world and events within it. A medical analogy is that before the nineteenth century, idealists were like philosophical anatomists, whereas in the nineteenth century, idealists also worked as philosophical physiologists. This last is especially true of Friedrich Hegel (17701831), although he could not have constructed his system without Immanuel Kants (17241804) work before him, and the directions in which Johann Gottlieb Fichte (17621814) and Friedrich Schelling (17751854) tried to take Kants work.
223
What are some important facts about Johann Gottlieb Fichtes career?
Fichte was appointed professor of philosophy at the University of Jena in 1794, where he extended his Kantian idea of duty to criticize the drunkenness, lewdness, and brawling of the students. In 1795 he became an editor of the Philosophiches Journal, and in the preface to an article he was going to publish that had been written by a friend of his, he wrote that God was the moral order of the universe. There were complaints that this was an atheistic view, and so the governments of Saxony and other German states suppressed the Philosophiches Journal and demanded that Fichte be kicked out of Jena. Fichte defended himself in writing and then threatened to resign his university position. The Jena University authorities interpreted his threat as an offer, which they immediately accepted, so he lost his position there. Much later, in 1810, he became the first professor of philosophy at the University of Berlin. Fichtes independent philosophy was first stated in Foundation of the Science of Knowledge (1794) and popularized in The Vocation of Man (1800). In 1796 he wrote Foundations of Natural Right, which was his treatment of natural law. In 1808 he gave a series of Speeches to the German Nation in French-occupied Berlin (published as Addresses to the German Nation in 1922). In those talks, Fichte supported resistance against French dictator Napoleon Bonaparte, arguing for the common good.
What were the main original ideas that were important to Johann Gottlieb Fichtes philosophy?
224
Fichte was opposed to what he called dogmatism, or the idea that there was an external world that was independent of human beings and what they valued. He thought
that atheism, materialism, and determinism were the results of such beliefs in objective reality, and this was to the detriment of morality. Even Immanuel Kants (17241804) system had a dogmatic strain in his positing of things-in-themselves, which could not be known. Fichtes solution to these problems of dogmatism was idealism: mind creates everything.
225
Schelling resurrected a type of alchemical thought whereby magnetism, which is the general form of particular existence, either becomes evident in light or maleness, or else becomes evident in heavy inertia, or femaleness. In ordinary language (although there was nothing ordinary about this belief) the alchemists believed that things that exist are all made up of a magnetic something that can manifest itself in either lightweight and airy (or male) beings, or else in heavy and dense (or female) beings. He believed that existent reality became separated from the Absolute in a spontaneous act of freedom, which created time itself, along with the world as we know it. That is, there occurred in the Absolute a spontaneous burst of freedom that resulted in the separation of what we perceive as reality from the Absolute. Another consequence was the appearance of time. This is to say that the Absolute exists outside of time. Schelling had a following among Romantics in the sciences, as well as in the arts because Romantics in the nineteenth century, as today, loved quasi-mystical explanations of the world. Lorenz Oken (17741851), for example, postulated that all of life in Schellings sense in which nature is unconscious mind, originated in primeval slime. The connection between Okens idea and Schellings thought is not at all clear, except to indicate how one wild set of ideas is capable of inspiring others.
FRIEDRICH HEGEL
Who was Friedrich Hegel?
For sheer intellectual fire-power, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (17701831) was probably the most brilliant thinker of the nineteenth century. He was a philosopher who could think about the entire world with an Aristotelian comprehensiveness, if not an Aristotelian lucidity. He is best known for his idealist positing of an Absolute, a kind of non-religious, Neo-Platonic, post-Enlightenment One, which was observed only through its workings in the ordinary reality experienced by mere mortals, but deduced (divined?) through the logic of Hegel himself.
226
What is the story behind Friedrich Schellings scandalous romantic affair with August Wilhelm von Schlegels wife?
hen he was teaching in Jena, Schelling was close friends with German poet August Wilhelm von Schlegel, who was highly esteemed by other German Romantics, and with Karoline, who would later be the poets wife. There was discussion of marriage between Schelling and the Schlegels daughter, Auguste. But Auguste died from dysentery in 1800, after Schelling had supervised her treatment. At first, Schelling was blamed, but later biographers exonerated him because her death was probably medically inevitable at that time.
Schelling and Karoline then recognized their love for each other, and August moved out, leaving Jena for Berlin. Later, Johann Wolfgang von Goethe, another famous literary figure, helped secure a divorce, and Schelling and Karoline married, after they had left Jena to avoid the predictable scandal.
lin and the philosopher Friedrich Schelling (17751854), who would be his colleague and intellectual opponent. (They disputed the importance of Reason, with Hegel proudly affirming it and Schelling expressing a lack of enthusiasm for it.) When he graduated, Hegel first worked as a tutor for a Bern family, and then he moved to Frankfurt. His fathers death provided him with sufficient income to concentrate on his own scholarly work in hopes of getting a university position. His early interests were in reconciling fluid notions of reason with non-institutionalized Christianity. In 1805, Schelling assisted Hegel in moving to Jena, where he lectured for several years and became a professor at the University of Jena. By this time, as expressed in his early essays, Hegel was having doubts about the freedom promised by the Enlightenment. He loved the thought and ways of life of ancient Greece and believed that Enlightenment rights would result in new forms of repression. One motivation for this concern might have been his experience of the French Revolution. On a deeper philosophical level, he thought that what was most noble in human beings required society and government for its development. This view conflicted with the individual rights doctrine, which assumed that government was the enemy of natural human rights. At Jena, he co-edited the Critical Journal of Philosophy with Schelling, which was dedicated to exploring the consequences of Immanuel Kants (17241804) transcendental idealism, in light of Johann Gottlieb Fichte (17621814) and Schellings own work. Hegel left Jena when the University closed after Napoleon Bonapartes victory in October 1806. He then edited a pro-Napoleon newspaper in Bavaria, and became headmaster of a Nuremberg high school in 1808.
227
In 1807 Hegels important Phenomenology of Spirit was published, and then his Science of Logic (1812) resulted in a professorship at Heidelberg. In 1818 he assumed his last post, which was as a professor at Berlin, lecturing widely on philosophy of history, history of philosophy, aesthetics, and philosophy of religion, much of which was unpublished until it was posthumously compiled from his notes and those of students. Hegels Foundations of the Philosophy of Right: Natural Right and Political Science in Outline was published in 1821.
228
resents different forms of consciousness that have progressed toward absolute knowledge or philosophical science. The progression of consciousness occurs because different forms of consciousness are contradictory and their inner dialectic resolves the contradictions via the emergence of new forms. This dialectic is not a dialogue between consciousnesses, but the inner development of what consciousness is conscious of. Hegel is able to chronicle this development of consciousness toward absolute knowledge, because it is presumed to be attained through his philosophical work.
229
Hegels roommates were the poet Christian Friedrich Hlderlin and the philosopher Friedrich Schelling (17751854). From Hlderlin he learned to love the ancient Greeks even more. They all protested against the political and ecclesiastical stasis of Tbingen. On July 14, 1792, Hegel, Hlderlin, and Schelling were said to have planted a liberty tree on a meadow near the Tbingen Seminary, although not all biographers think this in fact happened. Hegel was hardly a Romantic philosopher, but there was some romantic drama in his life. As he was finishing The Phenomenology of Spirit (1807), Christina Burkhard informed him that she was pregnant with their child. Ludwig, his illegitimate son, was born in February 1807. He completed the manuscript on the same day Napoleon Bonaparte captured Jena: October 18, 1807. In 18ll, at the age of 41, he married Marie von Tucher, who was 20. Maries aristocratic family was not enthusiastic about the match, though, and a government official friend had to intervene to negotiate it. During their courtship, Hegel wrote her a romantic poem (which most describe as hackneyed); he referred to his hope of marrying her as an ascension into eternal bliss.
What did Friedrich Hegel think was the highest form of spirit?
The modern state of Hegels own time is considered by him to be the epitome of Absolute spirit. This state is a unity that molds its members and also allows them individual freedom.
230
ian state represented the final union of philosophy and Christianity, and the Left Hegelians, including Ludwig Andreas von Feuerbach (18041872) and Karl Marx (18181883), who interpreted a politically revolutionary future for the dialectic propounded by Hegel.
A RT H U R S C H O P E N H A U E R
Who was Arthur Schopenhauer?
Arthur Schopenhauer (17881860) was influenced by the other German idealists, whom he despised as optimistic fools. Unlike Friedrich Hegel (17701831) and both the Right or the Left Hegelians, his view of the Idea that formed and worked the world was pessimistic.
231
ics or numbers are projections of the mind that enable us to experience phenomena, Schopenhauer felt that the noumenal world has no numberit is one. This claim would have no consequences in experience if it were true, since it is an effort to describe what underlies experience.
How did Arthur Schopenhauer think we could best become aware of noumenal will?
Through aesthetic experience, especially of nature and music, we can become aware of the noumenal world. Schopenhauers theory of nature appreciation is a modification of Immanuel Kants (1724 1804) notion of the sublime. Schopenhauer thought that there is tranquility in the experience of the beautiful, but that the experience of the sublime, such as in watching a storm, requires an active participation. Thus, the observer tears himself away from his own will in contemplating the sublime object by a free exaltation. Music is a pure expression of the absolute noumenal will. In listening to music, which expresses the universal will, we directly become universal subjects, bypassing our own individual wills.
Arthur Schopenhauer was known for having a more pessimistic view of the world than German idealists like Friedrich Hegel (iStock).
232
Fichte, Schelling and Hegel are in my opinion not philosophers, for they lack the first requirement of a philosopher, namely a seriousness and honesty of enquiry. They are merely sophists who wanted to appear to be, rather than to be, something. They sought not truth but their own interest and advancement in the world. So much for men, in Schopenhauers opinion. In his twenties, Schopenhauer experienced unrequited love for the mistress of the Duke of Weimar. He and his mother, a successful novelist, quarreled over his treatment of her guests and he never saw her again after age 26. Women, in general, he said: are directly fitted for acting as the nurses and teachers of our early childhood by the fact that they are themselves childish, frivolous and short-sighted; in a word, they are big children all their life long an undersized, narrow-shouldered, broad-hipped and short legged race. [T]hey have no proper knowledge of anything; and they have no genius. Schopenhauer was also said to have abused at least one female servant. In his old age, he lived alone, except for a poodle.
B E R NA R D B O S A N Q U E T
Who was Bernard Bosanquet?
Bernard Bosanquet (18481923) was an English Hegelian who taught at University College (from 1870 to 1881) and at St. Andrews (from 1903 to 1908), Oxford. His name was inherited from French Huguenot forebears. He left Oxford when an inheritance enabled him to pursue social activist causes in London. His major works appear as the published editions of the Gifford Lectures that he gave in 1911 and 1912: The
233
In 1895 he married Helen Dendy, who was a social activist and reformer. She served on the Royal Commission on the Poor Laws from 1905 to 1909. Both Bosanquets believed that the best way to secure social reform was through education that developed individual character. This viewpoint often brought them into conflict with leading socialists of the time.
Principle of Individuality and Value (1912) and The Value and Destiny of the Individual (1913). Bosanquet explained the existence of the Absolute with his own system of logical doctrines; he advocated for community values as opposed to individualism, and he was the leading British philosopher of aesthetics in his day and beyond.
where once there were conflicting desires. On a community level, this is the general will. Being ruled by the general will results in liberty. The general will is the foundation of the modern state that has as its aim the actualization of what is best for all of its citizens.
What is materialism?
In a general philosophical sense, materialism is the doctrine that only physical, material things are real. In a political Marxist sense, materialism is the doctrine that economic conditions and transactions determine the course of history.
What is Marxism?
Marxism is the doctrine attributed to Karl Marx (18181883) that human society is divided into social classes and that the material or economic struggles among classes are the most important events on the big stage of history.
Karl Marx viewed human history in terms of a continuing struggle between economic classes (iStock).
235
What is anarchism?
Anarchism is the political doctrine that human happiness and well being are best served without powerful political structures. Anarchists seek the decentralization of power, into small units, controlled by the people.
LU D WI G AN D R EAS
VO N
F E U E R BAC H
n his Principles of the Philosophy of the Future (1843) Feuerbach wrote the rallying cry for many vegetarians: Der Mensch ist, was er isst, or Man is what he eats. However, his full thought on this was not merely dietary. The preceding sentences, written in 1850, read: The doctrine of foods is of great ethical and political significance. Food becomes blood, blood becomes heart and brain, thoughts and mindstuff. Human fare is the foundation of human culture and thought. Would you improve a nation? Give it, instead of declamations against sin, better food. Feuerbach struggled with how human fare became human thought. His solution was to convert the essence of religion into the essence of man, but Marx criticized him for his location of abstractions in the individual, preferring to understand the individual as a collection or intersection of social and economic relations.
how religion should be studied made possible sociologies, histories, and other nonreligious studies of religion.
MARXI S M
Who was Karl Marx?
Karl Marx (18181883) was the German revolutionary and philosopher of modern society and economics who is most often credited with having founded communism and socialism as political movements and systems of thought. He is also credited with the impetus behind the modern labor union movement. Marxs early works are considered utopian and were not published in his lifetime. His magnum opus is Das Kapital (Capital, released in 1867, 1885, and 1894), although the The Communist Manifesto (1848) that he wrote with Friedrich Engels (18201895) is less hypothetical and more accessible to the reader. At the time Marx and Engels wrote, the following did not exist for workers in industrialized nations: minimum wage laws, health care insurance, pension plans, workplace safety regulations, laws against child labor, or specified hours for shifts or work weeks. Neither was there widespread and compulsory public education for the children of workers. While some of these goods do not universally exist at this time in industrialized nations and may not exist at all in parts of Asia, Africa, and South America, they are now generally taken for granted as fundamental human entitlements.
237
Along with Karl Marx, Friedrich Engels established the ideals of communism (Art Archive).
Engels greatest contribution was a presentation of Marxs ideas in more accessible and popular formats and terms. Engels father was a textile manufacturer, and the young Engels worked at his mill in Manchester, eventually owning it. Engels helped Marx financially throughout his life and also supported his children after Marx died. He edited Marxs Das Kapital after Marxs death.
In a nutshell, what did Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels write in their philosophy?
Human beings must work to live. History, noted Marx and Engels, is a Hegelian dialectical process in which different divisions of labor have developed, resulting in the nineteenth century in a bourgeois owning class that controls the government and an exploited proletariat, or working class, that furnishes the labor for capitalists. Capitalism is an economic system in which owners seek profits through everexpanding production and markets. Their profit is the result of subtracting the costs of material and equipment, or capital, plus wages paid to workers, from the money they take in. Within the producing system, labor, or the work of the working class, results in a surplus value, because workers are exploited by employers. The worker is paid just enough to go home and eat, sleep, and engage in familial acts of reproduction, which altogether reproduce his labor so that he can continue to function as a worker. That is, every aspect of the workers life is squeezed by their employers so that they can maximize their profits. The result is that workers, especially those who made up the vast pool of labor in nineteenth century industrial society, were poor.
238
The Marxes fifth child, Franziska, was born at their Soho flat, but she only lived for a year. Eleanor was born in 1855, but later that year Edgar became the Marxes third child to die. The family owned very little, and some days Marx could not leave the house because Jenny had to pawn his trousers to buy food. But on some Sundays, they all went to Hampstead Heath for picnics. After Marx began earning money from his articles for the New York Daily Tribune, and Jennys mother left her a small inheritance, they were able to move to Kentish Town. In 1856, Jenny had a baby that was still-born, and after that she caught smallpox. Although she survived this illness, it left her deaf and badly scarred. Marx also grew ill, and he wrote to Engels that such a lousy life is not worth living. But when he had an outbreak of boils in 1863, he was consoled that it was a truly proletarian disease.
Both the working class and the owning class have their own ideologies, which unreconstructed are the ideology of the owning class. That is, the owning class sees the world in a way that justifies their position: for example, in believing that all who have great wealth have earned it by hard work. The politically dominant class in a society is the class that economically controls the main means of production. In general, the ideology of any social class is the result of where that class is located in terms of the dominant means of production in its society. Workers and others need to realize that workers are human beings who become alienated from their own labor when it is merely treated as a commodity on which their employers make a profit. The short-term solution to this situation is for workers to unite and demand better pay and working conditions. The long-term solution is a historical process through which capitalism will destroy itself through its own internal contradictions. The erstwhile workers will then become socialist owners who are able to pursue self-fulfilling activities, instead of merely laboring to survive from one day to the next.
239
A NA R C H I S M
What is anarchism?
Anarchism is a theory and political movement that is based on ideals of freedom and equality. All forms of domination, authority, and subordination are considered unjust and backed up by force. The state and all of its supporting institutions, as well as the institutions supported by the state, are deemed unacceptable. Society should be reorganized into small, self-governing communities in which members cooperate toward the same ends and produce their livelihood together. English journalist and political philosopher William Godwin (17561836) initiated modern anarchism in the eighteenth century, and in the nineteenth, Pierre-Joseph Proudhon (18091865), Mikhail Alexandrovich Bakunin (18141876), and Pyotr Alexeyevich Kropotkin (18421921) were leading figures.
240
A 1948 French cartoon lampoons Pierre-Joseph Proudhouns ideas about the poor. Proudhon asks a servant why he left the door open, and the servant responds that since there is no such thing as property, why does it matter? (Art Archive).
akunin and Marx were bitter enemies. Marx campaigned to expel Bakunin from the International Working Mens Association. The tempestuous relationship between Marx and Bakunin is a well known part of the history of Western socialism. As a co-member of the International Working Mens Association, Marx referred to Bakunin as a man devoid of all theoretical knowledge. Bakunin said that Marx was from head to foot an authoritarian. [T]he instinct of liberty is lacking in him. Although Marx said that Bakunin was in his element as an intriguer, it was Marx who in 1848 published an untrue rumor, begun by the Russian ambassador, that Bakunin was a Russian agent responsible for the arrest of Poles.
neglected after World War I, some of Proudhons social ideas remain influential in contemporary economic organization. Examples of this include the representation in management of workers in large industries, as well as cooperative housing units and food growing and buying projects.
241
Siberia. His views are held to be contradictory because he believed both that the instinct for freedom in the masses would lead to revolution and that revolution would need to be the result of a plan by educated elite. In his first period, Bakunin criticized liberal projects to reconcile the demands of workers with the establishment, and he was particularly excoriating about both the Church and the state. In his second period, he attacked scientism, or the dominance of technical approaches to public policy, calling for a revolt of life against science. Overall, Bakunin and his followers were opposed to the development of Marxism.
Peter Kropotkin was a Russian prince whose views on communism were mitigated by science and the ideas of evolutionary theory (Art Archive).
242
He read Pierre-Joseph Proudhons (18091865) writings, which led him to resign his commission in protest of an execution of Polish prisoners, who had attempted to
escape. After exploring the eskers of Finland, he was offered the position of secretary of the Russian Geological Society in 1872, but instead went to Switzerland to meet exiled radicals. Kropotkin decided he was an anarchist after moving interactions with Bakunins followers among the watchmakers of Jura. (The watchmakers were conscientious craftsmen who were not part of the wider industrial revolution, and their cooperation in a close-knit community inspired Kropotkin.) When he returned to Russia, he joined the underground, and in 1874 was imprisoned in the Peter and Paul Fortress. He escaped to Europe, where he founded the journal Le Rvolt in 1879 and participated in the London International Anarchist Congress in 1881. In Lyons, France, in 1882, he was sentenced to five years imprisonment for being a member of the International Workingmens Association, but public outcry led to an early release. After that, he went to England and remained there, returning to Russia after the Russian Revolution of 1917. When Kropotkin lived in England, he worked mainly as a scholar. Leading scientific journals and publishers printed his work. His most important publications were Memoirs of a Revolutionist (1899), Mutual Aid: A Factor in Evolution (1902), and Modern Science and Anarchism (1912). His last work, Ethics, was published in 1924 after he died in Russia. Kropotkins final years were disappointing to him because the aftermath of the Russian Revolution defied his anarchist ideals. He denounced the Bolshevik reign of terror after the October Revolution.
243
understood, of course, in its wide Darwinian sensenot as a struggle for the sheer means of existence, but as a struggle against all natural conditions unfavourable to the species. The animal species, in which individual struggle has been reduced to its narrowest limits, and the practice of mutual aid has attained the greatest development, are invariably the most numerous, the most prosperous, and the most open to further progress. The mutual protection which is obtained in this case, the possibility of attaining old age and of accumulating experience, the higher intellectual development, and the further growth of sociable habits, secure the maintenance of the species, its extension, and its further progressive evolution. The unsociable species, on the contrary, are doomed to decay. However, Kropotkin did hold that revolution is part of human evolution and that anarchism was a return to a condition that had been distorted by modern repressive institutions. Because human beings are naturally social, government is unnecessary.
P SYC H O LO GY AN D S O C I A L TH E O RY
What was philosophically significant about nineteenth-century psychology and social theory?
In the nineteenth century, the foundations were laid for psychology and sociology to develop as distinct fields separate from philosophy. The reasons for their separation are differences in subject matter as well as methodology. Concerning the latter, Wilhelm Dilthey (18331911) put the case of his age best in claiming that human sciences such as history, psychology, philology, and philosophy were characterized by a need to understand, whereas the physical sciences sought causes. However, in the twentieth century, quantitative methodology and experiments in search of causes were to characterize important parts of both psychology and sociology. Quantification and causal explanation were also to characterize economics, which did not become distinctly independent from political philosophy, sociology, and philosophy until the twentieth century. But in the nineteenth century, the establishment of psychology and sociology as separate from epistemology, ethics, and political philosophy, as well as revolutionary critique, was a major achievement.
F R A N Z B R E N TA N O
Who was Franz Brentano?
244
Franz Brentano (18371917) taught in Wrzburg and at the University of Vienna, influencing Austrian philosopher Alexius Meinong (18531920); Edmund Husserl
rentano thought that judgments can be correct or incorrect and that the same held for loving and hating. If a thing is good, then it is impossible to love it incorrectly. Correctness in loving and hating is objective, as is incorrectness. Brentano was an intuitionist concerning such correctness. He thought that we could be immediately and directly aware of the fit between the emotion and the object.
(18591938), the founder of phenomenology, and Sigmund Freud (18561939), the father of psychoanalysis. He was ordained as a Roman Catholic priest in 1864, but renounced his vows after engaging in a dispute about papal infallibility. He resigned his professorship at the University of Vienna, so that he could marry, and was not able to regain that position. Later years left him blind, but he continued to write in virtually every subfield of philosophy until he died. Brentanos principal writings are Psychology from an Empirical Point of View (1874) and Our Knowledge of the Origin of Right and Wrong (1889).
245
ALEXI US M E I NONG
Who was Alexius Meinong?
Alexius Meinong (18531920) was born in Lemberg, Austria, and studied philosophy with Franz Brentano (18371917), who set him the task of reading David Hume (17111776). This resulted in two early books on Hume, the first on abstraction and the second on relation, which appeared as Hume-Studien in 1877 and 1882, respectively. Like Brentano, Meinong is considered an analytical phenomenologist. Unlike those phenomenologists in the so-called continental tradition, he applied the rigors of logic to introspection. He established the Institute of Psychology in Graz, Austria, where he was a professor. Meinong is best known for his theory of objects and values, and his principle publication is On Assumptions (1902).
246
SIGMUND FREUD
How are psychology and philosophy related?
Up until the nineteenth century, no clear distinction was made between philosophy of mind and psychology. The science of psychology did not yet exist in its own right until the early twentieth century. Early historical figures in the science of psychology, such as Sigmund Freud (18561939), are of interest to philosophers because their theories of the human mind changed ideas about human nature in ways that philosophers had to take into account.
Sigmund Freud was the father of psychoanalysis and clinical practice (Art Archive).
247
Freuds principle works are The Interpretation of Dreams (1900), Three Essays on the Theory of Sexuality (1905), and Civilization and Its Discontents (1930). Also of particular interest in his application of his theories to healthy people in ordinary life is Psychopathology of Everyday Life (1901).
What are some details of Sigmund Freuds life that led him to his work?
Freud was born in Freiberg, Germany, but raised in Vienna, Austria. He studied medicine at the University of Vienna, specializing in neurology. In 1886, Freud married Martha Bernays. They had six children, and the youngest, Anna, herself became a noted psychoanalyst. Freuds youngest son, Ernst, was the father of Lucien Freud, the celebrated twentieth century portrait painter. Biographers of Freud assess his family life as happy and stable, providing much needed support for the controversy that swirled around his startling and original psychological theories. Freuds mentors J.M. Charcot and Josef Breuer investigated hysteria, and Freud became interested in the psychological aspects of this disorder because hysterical patients have physical symptoms without underlying disease. Freud and Charcot published their clinical findings of how talk can change patients ideas, as a treatment for hysteria, in their Studies in Hysteria (1895). As Freud developed a sexual interpretation of the causes of hysteria, Breuer distanced himself from him.
248
Freud named the childs attraction for its mother after the fictional character Oedipus, who is the tragic figure from the Sophocles play who accidentally falls in love with his mother (Art Archive).
The Oedipus complex results from a situation in which the child desires the mother as a result of prolonged human dependency on one caregiver. Male children fear that their fathers will punish them through castration. Female children transfer their original oedipal yearnings for their mothers to their fathers in an Electra complex, which is also accompanied by penis envy. This all occurs unconsciously in terms of active and passive principles that later come to be expressed and identified as male and female, respectively. Because the primary process of the psyche tends toward a cathartic discharge of repressed energy, the pleasure principle is Freuds main explanatory tool. He applied this principle to the way in which the emergence of unconscious material can account for humor and also everyday failures in function and memory. In psychoanalysis, both dreams and free association could be used to access unconscious conflicts and particularly oedipal fantasies.
249
He was also just as willing to analyze literary characters and authorship; thus, he famously wrote about Shakespeares Hamlet: Fleetingly the thought passed through my head that the same thing might be at the bottom of Hamlet as well. I am not thinking of Shakespeares conscious intention, but believe, rather, that a real event stimulated the poet to his representation, in that his unconscious understood the unconscious of his hero. Freud also collected his own memory lapses, slips of the tongue, and dreams for analysis. In the 1936 article A Disturbance of Memory on the Acropolis, he explained why he felt doubtful and uneasy when he visited the Acropolis in Greece in 1904: It must be that a sense of guilt was attached to the satisfaction in having gone such a long way: there was something about it that was wrong, that from earliest times had been forbidden. It was something to do with a childs criticism of his father, with the undervaluation which took the place of the overvaluation of earlier childhood. It seems as though the essence of success was to have got further than ones father, and as though to excel ones father was still something forbidden. Freuds father had been too poor to make such a trip, and not educated enough to have been interested in the Acropolis.
H E R B E RT S P E N C E R
Who was Herbert Spencer?
Herbert Spencer (18201903) was a philosopher and social reformer who was assistant editor-in-chief of The Economist. He also wrote for the Westminster Review, while George Eliot was its editor. Spencer was an atheist, without any training in the humanities, and he believed that only science could yield useful knowledge. In his ethics, he combined Jeremy Benthams (17481832) version of utilitarianism with John Stuart Mills (18061873) view that happiness is the true end. Spencer thought that pleasure and pain were evidence of happiness or unhappiness. Spencer is best known for his evolutionary views that predated Charles Darwins publication of On the Origin of the Species by Means of Natural Selection (1859). Spencers main publications were works he published in his major project
250
Herbert Spencer was an atheist who believed science was the only way to uncover true knowledge (Art Archive).
Mary Ann Evans, the novelist better known by her pen name, George Eliot, had a warm friendship with Spencer. Although he did not enjoy public places and entertainment, he took her to restaurants and the opera. Biographers believe that Eliot would have married Spencer, if hed asked her, but he never did. She said that the life of this philosopher, like that of the great [Immanuel] Kant, offers little material for the narrator. After First Principles of a New System of Philosophy (1880) was published, Spencer developed an illness that led to insomnia and self-medication with opium. He became very reclusive and would sometimes wear ear plugs so that he did not have to listen to what others said. Although he advocated for public causes such as the metric system, and against the Boer War, he spent his last years with very little human interaction.
System of Synthetic Philosophy, beginning in the 1850s, and 1884s The Man versus the State.
251
S O C I O LO GY
AN D
P H I LO S O P HY
including ethics, philosophy of history, education, religion, art, and money. His writing style was digressive rather than tightly analytic, as was expected in German philosophy at that time. Overall, as a Lebensphilosphe, or philosopher of life, Simmel saw life as more than itselfin other words, more than the human biological organism and its processes because it was productive, particularly in cultural creativity. Perhaps Simmels most distinctive work was his Philosophy of Money (1900), a subject that few philosophers have directly addressed, then or since. He also wrote about fashion.
Max Weber interestingly combined ideas of economics with religion (Art Archive).
253
his career as an academic. His main project was to understand the dominant features of modern life in its Western development. His most famous work was The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism (1904).
254
CONTINENTAL PHILOSOPHY
What is continental philosophy?
Existentialism, phenomenology, critical theory, and structuralism all represent what is now called continental philosophy. Existentialism is a philosophical perspective on the world, which begins from the standpoint of one individual in ways that apply to all individuals. Phenomenology is a more abstract and systematic development of the processes of individual knowing and understanding. (Existentialists have tended to be more literary than phenomenologists.) Critical theory is a twentieth-century development of the theoretical methodology of Marxism. Structuralism is an application of a number of continental traditions to social criticism, resulting in analyses of social structures. One thing they all have in common is that their original foundational ideas came from European thinkers. But more than geography is at stake with this name. Continental philosophy is often contrasted with Anglo-American analytic philosophy, which has dominated in twentieth-century philosophy departments in American colleges and universities, since philosophy became a profession in higher education during the 1930s. It should be noted that what is true of American academic philosophy departments has not been true of English, French, and German departments in the United States, which over the twentieth century welcomed continental philosophy into their curricula. Moreover, continental philosophy is not alone in its stepchild status among American professional philosophers, because the same thing happened to American philosophy, also known as pragmatism, after the 1950s.
255
E X I STE NTI A LI S M
What is existentialism?
Existentialism is a kind of philosophy that begins from the concrete reality of the human individuals existence in the world. What is shared by all humans in their day to day life becomes a foundation for knowledge and the nature of reality. Existentialism is focused on human experience from the first person, some me or I.
S R E N K I E R K E GA AR D
Who was Sren Kierkegaard?
Sren Aaybe Kierkegaard (18131855) was a Danish Christian existentialist who extolled religious faith as an individual and emotional leap from all that was reasonable and rational. He wrote from his heart and the emotional circumstances of his own life.
256
Danish Christian existentialist Sren Kierkegaard based his philosophy on his religious faith (Art Archive).
cursing God during severe weather as a 10-year-old shepherd. He later became well off as a wool merchant. Kierkegaard was sickly as a boy, but he could reduce larger boys to tears with his sarcasm and mockery. At the University of Copenhagen, he did not find Hegelianism congenial because it did not address a truth, which is true for me, to find the idea for which I can live and die. The religion of Lutheranism did not speak to him, either, and for a while he indulged in expensive food and drink and wore fashionable clothes because he believed that immediate pleasure was the most important thing. But his fathers despair haunted him and became his own. Kierkegaard was intending to become a pastor when he became engaged to Rigene Olsen in 1841. He had met her when she was 14, three years earlier, and they were deeply in love. But Kierkegaard broke off the engagement, and she subsequently married her tutor, Frederick Schlegel (who became governor of the Danish West Indies). An original lifes path was taking shape for Kierkegaard, and when he decided not to marry he also decided not to become a Lutheran pastor. Kierkegaard believed that philosophy was neither about system-building nor analysis, but rather the expression of individual existence. He had no respect for professors because he did not think there was any way they could comprehend his subjectivity. Kierkegaards most important works were all written in the 1840s: Either/Or: A Fragment of Life (1843), Fear and Trembling (1843), The Concept of Dread (1844), Philosophical Fragments (1844), Concluding Unscientific Postscript (1846), and The Sickness unto Death (1849). His autobiographical writings and journals shed considerable light on his personal thoughts and feelings. Nonetheless, it was not his intention to disclose everything. He wrote: After my death no one will find among my papers a single explanation as to what really filled my life (that is my consolation); no one will find the words which explain everything and which often made what the world would call a trifle into an event of tremendous importance to me, and what I look upon as something insignificant when I take away the secret gloss which explains it all. When Kierkegaard was near death he refused a pastors sacrament, remarking: Pastors are royal officials; royal officials have nothing to do with Christianity. His epitaph read, as he had requested: That individual.
257
Why did Sren Kierkegaard believe Friedrich Hegel did not write to him?
irst of all, Kierkegaard did not take seriously Friedrich Hegels (17701831) claim to have written the system of everything. Kierkegaard thought that everything could be viewed as a system by God, but that no human thinker, who is himself incomplete, could have such a perspective. He also rejected the tradition on which Hegel built that posits intellectual doubt as the beginning of philosophy. Kierkegaard thought that the beginning of philosophy was wonder. Also, he didnt think that real doubt could be solved intellectually, but that it required an act of will. Finally, Kierkegaard did not think that God or the Absolute could be imminent in the world, because God is instead the ultimate Other, defying rational understanding. Kierkegaards biggest complaint about Hegel was that he was like a man who had built a palace but lived outside it in a miserable hovel. He meant by this that in constructing his grand and elaborate system, Hegel had neglected his own immediate existence as a concrete individual.
258
With a paper like The Corsair, which hitherto has been read by many and all kinds of people and essentially has enjoyed the recognition of being ignored, despised, and never answered, the only thing to be done in writing in order to express the literary, moral order of things reflected in the inversion that this paper with meager competence and extreme effort has sought to bring aboutwas for someone immortalized and praised in this paper to make application to be abused by the same paper. May I ask to be abusedthe personal injury of being immortalized by The Corsair is just too much. And abused he was, in a campaign so bitingly satiric and mocking of all his personal weaknesses and defectshe was short and frail, and had been born with a hump on his backthat he described himself as apprehensive of everyone with whom he came into contact, even the butcher boy. This was not selfindulgent paranoia because Kierkegaard experienced the modern phenomenon of a celebrity degraded by the gutter press everywhere he walked in Copenhagen. It was a catastrophe for him because walking and talking to people in all stations of life had been his principal diversion.
Was there only one kind of religious life for Sren Kierkegaard?
No, Kierkegaard distinguished between two. In the first, the individual relates to God, using his idea of God to deal with guilt. In the second, there is a teleological suspension of the ethical, as in the story of Abraham and Isaac. The implication of this transcendence of the ethical is that real religion is higher and more important than what is accepted as goodness in society.
F YO D O R D O STOYEVS KY
Why have existentialist philosophers claimed Dostoyevsky as one of their own?
The great Russian novelist Fyodor Mikhailovich Dostoyevsky (18211881) is considered an inspiration to the modern philosophical tradition of existentialism because of the depth of his appreciation for the difficulty of the human condition and the univer-
259
sal problems he and his fictional characters agonized over. Friedrich Nietsche (18441900) said that Dostoyevsky was the only psychologist from whom I have something to learn. He praised Dostoyevskys Notes from the Underground (1864) for having cried truth from the blood. Indeed, in Notes from the Underground Dostoyevsky introduces a self-deprecating narrator, who became an iconic anti-hero for subsequent existentialist writers. The narrators first words are, I am a sick man, and his ensuing reflections, rantings, and ruminations make it clear that the sickness at issue is primarily a malaise of the soul. Not the least of this sickness is a disgust with reason. Although Dostoyevsky is well known for valorizing simplicity in religious faith, he did not arrive at that viewpoint easily, either in works of fiction such as Crime and Punishment (1866), or in his own life. In his masterpiece, The Brothers Karamazov (1881), Ivan is an atheist, while his brother, Alyosha, is studying to become a monk. In the famous Grand Inquisitor dialogue within this novel, Ivan presses Alyosha on his faith, going to the heart of the matter in asking how a good God can permit the suffering of innocent children. Ivan recounts the story of a peasants child whom the lord allows his dogs to tear apart, because the child threw a stone at one of them. The character of Alyosha is said to be modeled on Dostoyevskys close friend, the Russian philosopher Vladimir Sergeyevich Solovyov (18531900), who longed to reunite the Roman Catholic and Russian Orthodox churches.
What aspects of Dostoevskys life influenced his deep interest in human difficulty?
Dostoyevskys father was a violent and abusive alcoholic. He was also the doctor of the Mariinsky Hospital for the Poor in Moscow. Dostoyevsky himself suffered from epilepsy from the age of nine. As a child, he used to disobey his parents and explore Mariinsky Hospital, absorbed by the misery of the patients and the stories about their lives that they told him. His first book, Poor Folk (1846), brought out the individual humanity of the poor, who were otherwise be ignored and dismissed by the educated reading public of the time.
260
Russian Fyodor Dostoyevsky expressed his belief in the extreme difficulty of the human condition through such novels as The Brothers Karamazov and Crime and Punishment (iStock).
In 1849 Dostoyevsky was arrested for his participation in the liberal group of intellectuals called the Petrashevsky Circle. He was sentenced to death, although Czar Nicholas II did not really intend for the execution to be carried out. Nevertheless, the experience of standing for hours in the freezing cold in anticipation of a firing squad was believed to have scared Dostoyevsky for life. He was then exiled to Siberia for four years of hard labor. He wrote of this period: In summer, intolerable closeness; in winter, unendurable cold. All the floors were rotten. Filth on the floors an inch thick; one could slip and fall. We were packed like herrings in a barrel. Fleas, lice, and black beetles by the bushel. When Dostoyevskys brother and wife died in the same year, he fell into a deep depression and became a gambler. During that period he wrote Crime and Punishment (1866), in a frenzied haste, because he was out of money. His life evened out after 1867, when he married his 20-year-old stenographer to whom he had dictated The Gambler (1867). While this book is about an elderly woman who gambles selfdestructively, some think that Dostoyevsky was describing his own compulsion. Dostoyevsky lived at the Russian resort Staraya for years before his death from emphysema and an epileptic seizure that brought on a lung hemorrhage. Forty thousand people went to his funeral.
F R I E D R I C H N I ETZ S C H E
Who was Friedrich Nietzsche?
Friedrich Nietzsche (18441900) was a brilliant philosophical iconoclast whose devastatingly direct critical writing style might in itself have qualified him as an existentialist. More substantively, though, was how he developed critiques of bourgeois culture, Christianity, empirical reason, and altruistic morality from the standpoint of a protesting individual who was grander, smarter, more creative, and in odd ways for a much later readership, hipper than those who championed accepted values of the time. While Dostoyevsky and others had criticized modernity in the hope of a return to more conservative religious values, Nietzsche looked ahead to coming generations, who would use science as an art to transcend the dreariness of Western history.
261
When Nietzsche was six, his younger brother died, and he, his mother, and his sister moved to Naumburg. Nietzsche grew up in a household consisting of his mother and sister, his paternal grandmother, and two unmarried aunts. Biographers have remarked that this allfemale environment was detrimental to his psychological health as an adult. They have referred to this environment in trying to make sense of the hostility Nietzsche displayed toward women in some of his writings, such as this from Thus Spoke Zarathustra (18831885): When thou goest to woman, take thy whip. At boarding school, Nietzsche suffered from migraines. He was inspired by the poetry of Johann Hlderlin, who had gone insane, so this was not considered a healthy subject by Nietzsches teachers. Nietzsche studied theology and classical philology at the University of Bonn, but only philology at the University of Leipzig. He served briefly in the army from 1867 to 1868, and was discharged after a chest injury, which was incurred when he landed on the pommel of his saddle while mounting. When he was only 24, his teachers considered him so promising that he was appointed associate professor of classical philology at Basel. Nietzsche moved to Basel, became a Swiss subject, and, in 1869, a full professor.
Friedrich Nietzsche was more forward thinking than many of his contemporaries, rejecting many of the values of his time (BigStock Photos).
In 1870 he received leave to serve as a medical orderly in the Franco-Prussian War, returning to Basel with both dysentery and diphtheria. He received his doctorate in 1873 and resigned from his academic position in 1879 for health reasons. After that, he continued to write and to travel for nine years.
262
Nietzsches health was poor throughout his life. His eyesight was weak and he had gastro-intestinal pains that he treated himself by walking and by taking a plethora of pills. In January 1889, Nietzsche broke down in a street in Turin, his arms around a horse that had been beaten. Over the next few days, he wrote demented letters to his friends, claiming to have been crucified by German doctors in a very drawn-out manner, and ordering the Emperor of Germany to report to Rome so that he could be shot. His friends brought him back from Italy, and his mother put him in a clinic in Jena. The treatment was unsuccessful, though, and his mother brought him home. In 1893, his sister, Elisabeth, returned from Paraguay, where her husband had committed suicide. She took charge of the editing and publication of Nietzsches manuscripts and isolated him from his friends. When their mother died in 1897, Elisabeth brought Nietzsche to Weimar, where she allowed people to see him. Nietzsche was not communicative, but she had him dressed up anyway, so that she could display him. He was by then very famous.
which he dedicated to Voltaire and in which Nietzsche included his own endearing essay about his own works, Why I Write Such Good Books (1888).
263
the chorus in the tragic play. In The Birth of Tragedy (1872), which was his doctoral dissertation, Nietzsche quoted the great tragic playwright, Sophocles: There is an ancient story that King Midas hunted in the forest a long time for the wise Silenus, the companion of Dionysus, without capturing him. When Silenus at last fell into his hands, the king asked what was the best and most desirable of all things for man. Fixed and immovable, the demigod said not a word, til at last, urged by the king, he gave a shrill laugh and broke out into these words: Oh, wretched ephemeral race, children of chance and misery, why do you compel me to tell you what it would be most expedient for you not to hear? What is best of all is utterly beyond your reach: not to be born, not to be, to be nothing. But the second best for you isto die soon.
the Overman would not be meek or ashamed of his strength. He would love life on earth completely, with no need to believe in heaven.
265
ome people have, indeed, interpreted Nietzsche in this way because he does celebrate the strong overcoming the weak. When the Nazis came to power in Germany, Nietzsches sister tried to benefit by presenting her brothers works to them as an appropriate philosophy for the Third Reich. This tarnished Nietzsches reputation until Walter Kaufmann, in his own translations and edited editions of Nietzsches works in the 1960s, reinterpreted him as a philosopher of individual freedom. Most current philosophers who like Nietzsche believe that he meant every individual has the freedom to become strong and detach himself from the herd.
entities, but by constantly increasing their own power. The will to live was for him identical to the will to power because existence is a continual struggle. The transmogrification of values by the Overman would represent a future stage of this will to power in the form of new, successful life.
J E A N - P A U L S A RT R E
Who was Jean-Paul Sartre?
Jean-Paul Charles Aymard Sartre (19051980) was the icon of twentieth century existentialism. Popular versions of his ideas gave existentialism its dark glamour of atheistic, nihilistic, cigarette-smoking, absinth-drinking, caf-frequenting, French intellectuals, arguing about ideas, and practicing free love. Sartre himself smoked a pipe, was short, stocky, near-sighted, and wall-eyed. He was well known by his contemporaries for his work in the French resistance against the Nazis, and later on, for his Marxism and opposition to the Vietnam conflict. Sartre refused to accept the Nobel Prize for Literature in 1964 on the grounds of his political objections to the bourgeois militaristic culture that made such a prize possible. Sartres main existentialist works consisted of numerous plays and essays; the novel Nausea (1938); and the philosophical works The Imagination (1936), The Transcendence of the Ego (1937), and Being and Nothingness (1943). His Marxism was developed in the uncompleted, three-volume work The Critique of Dialectical Reason (19581959).
of the very idea of nature: man makes himself. This ability to make oneself is accompanied by a responsibility for what one makes and it leads to considerable anguish because one must choose what to be on ones own. The living human being is always in a situation of varying degrees of difficulty from which there is no escape. Others are also present in ones life, of course, and they have the same kind of freedoms you do, which renders cooperative and lastingly loving human relationships extremely difficult. One can never Jean-Paul Sartre was the icon of twentieth century fully see the other as he or she is to himexistentialism (Art Archive). self or herself. Because others are in the same situation, the net effect is that hell is other people. Sartres view of intimate relationships was bleak because the person desired always eludes being the object desired. The desired person can never fully become an object because he or she has their own freedom. To accept ones freedom and ones situation, or facticity, are both necessary in order to be in good faith. The person who lives in bad faith either denies his own freedom and responsibility or denies the reality of his situation. Everything is chosen, even emotions that carry one to extremes, or insanity. Even the most difficult situation, which one has not chosen, does not negate ones freedom. It is the individual who gives the situation the meaning it has for him or her as a difficult situation. With a gun to ones head, for instance, one still has the choice of whether or not to live.
267
his question is deeply imbedded in the disputes among Sartres closest followers that followed his death. Their disputes were not so much matters of philosophy as they were a competition for who would inherit Sartes legacy and be able to speak for him after his death. According to Bnny Levy, a former Maoist who had been Sartres secretary for several years and transcribed 40 hours of taped conversations in Hope Now: The 1980 Interviews (1996), Sartre expressed hope for the coming of the Messiah.
disciplined work impossible. People are responsible for allowing their own background, weaknesses, or strengths to be motives for action in the immediate present.
268
Beauvoir also quarreled fiercely with Arlette Elkaim, the young Jewish Algerian student who had contacted Sartre when she was 18. Sartre enjoyed discussing his phi-
losophy with Elkaim, and he preferred to write in her apartment, instead of following his lifetime habit of writing in cafs. Then he adopted her and bought her a house in the south of France, which became their summer vacation home. Beauvoir had an adopted daughter of her own, Sylvie Le Bon de Beauvoir, with whom she had had an erotic relationship, although Sylvie later described it as platonic. Sylvie wrote Tte--Tte (2005) about de Beauvoir and Sartre. In 2005, Sylvie and Sartres daughter were not on speaking terms. Each in her sixties, they continued to bitterly contest their respective rights to Sartre and de Beauvoirs literary properties. Since Sartre and de Beauvoir are inextricably linked through letters in which they discussed each other, the complexity of the dispute between their literary heiresses can only be imagined. By 2005, Sylvie was a retired philosophy teacher and Arlette was described as extremely reclusive. Geographically, these women had lived close to each other in the same Parisian arrondisement, for some years. Beauvoir had a high tolerance for alcohol all her life (she liked its taste) but drank more heavily in her later years. She was also hooked on amphetamines. When she died in 1986, she was buried in Sartres grave, thereby sealing their link for posterity.
Simone de Beauvoir is credited with beginning the Second Wave of feminism (AP).
269
270
(18131855) and Buber. He also approached philosophy as a Bergsonian intuitionist by relying on his immediate insights for his views, rather than arriving at them through argument. His main works include Mystery of Being (1951) and Man against Mass Society (1955). His William James Lectures at Harvard University (1961, 1962) were published as The Existential Background of Human Dignity. Simone Weil (19091943) was born into a Jewish Parisian family but converted first to leftist syndicalism, which was a Marxist political movement with the goal of putting labor unions in control of both industry and government. Her subsequent religious thought was a combination of Neo-Platonism, Christianity, and Jewish mysticism. She was an activist on behalf of the democratically elected government during the Spanish Civil War, and for the French resistance during World War II. She criticized the way in which Marxism had become a religion to some and objected to the dehumanizing effects of capitalism. Her solution was meaningful work as a fundamental human need. Her main writings, published posthumously, are Gravity and Grace (1947) and Oppression and Liberty (1955).
271
was a friend of Jean-Paul Sartre (1905 1980), but they became alienated from each other as a result of Camus critique of communist tyranny in his essay im favor of revolutionary struggle, The Rebel (1951). His novel The Plague (1947) dramatized the ever-presence of death in human life. In his nonfiction essay The Myth of Sisyphus (1942) Camus claims that meaning can be found by affirming the absurd and then rebelling against it, as in imagine Sisyphus happy. Sisyphus punishment by Zeus consists of eternally rolling a large boulder up a mountain, only to begin again after he has reached Albert Camus, the brilliant author of novels like The Rebel, struggled to understand the meaning of human life the top and the boulder has rolled down in a godless world (Art Archive). again. His crimes were first to put Death in chains and then escape death himself. Camus was awarded the Nobel Prize for Literature in 1957; his own death in a car crash raised the question of his suicide. Paul Ricoeur (19132005) wrote on a variety of subjects, including existentialism, phenomenology, ethics, psychology, and theory of language. All of his work was distinguished by a deep engagement with key figures in the history of philosophy. His Freedom and Nature (1950) was received as a rejection of Sartres theory of freedom. Ricoeur argued that willing always has an involuntary component, which works as a kind of built-in resistance. What is voluntary consists of motive, decision, and consent, each of which has its own involuntary moment. The involuntary moments include birth, death, character already developed, the body, and the unconscious. (First, its not clear that Sartre equated freedom with acts of will, because freedom is present in all consciousness. Second, Sartre would have said that what we accept or recognize as involuntary requires a free choice of bestowing that particular meaning.)
P H E N O M E N O LO GY
EDMUND HUSSERL
Who was Edmund Husserl?
272
Edmund Husserl (18591938) is recognized as the founder of phenomenology as a systematic method of philosophy. He also created an important and new perspective
on logic and mathematics, which distinguished them from empirically discovered psychological rules of thought. Husserls major works are Logical Investigations (1900), The Idea of Phenomenology (1907), and Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Investigation (1913).
What are some key facts about Edmund Husserls life and career?
Husserl was born in Prossnitz, Moravia, which became part of Czechoslovakia after World War I and is now in the Czech Republic. His family was Jewish. Husserl studied mathematics in Leipzig and Berlin, and then got his Ph.D. in Vienna in 1883, writing Contributions to the Calculus of Variations that year. For the next two years, he studied psychology and philosophy with Franz Brentano (18371917) and then went to the University of Halle for his habilitation (preparation for university teaching) under a student of Brentano. He wrote On the Concept of Number, which he revised four years later, in 1891, as Philosophy of Arithmetic. In 1886 Husserl converted to Christianity, taking the name Edmund Gustav Albrecht Husserl. The next year, he married Malvine Steinschneider, who was to prove a valuable source of information about his work and intentions to academic colleagues. They had a daughter and two sons. In 1901, the Husserls moved to the University of Gttingen. He was promoted to ordenlichen professor in 1906, and the next year he traveled to Italy to see Brentano. Husserl was at this time in correspondence with Wilhelm Dilthey and leading mathematicians, as well as philosophers, about their work and his. German psychologist and philosopher Karl Jaspers (18831969) visited him in 1913, the same year Ideen was published. While visiting his son Wolfgang, who was injured in World War I, Husserl experienced nicotine poisoning. In 1916 Husserl was appointed to a professorship in Freiburg. Wolfgang was killed in action that year. For the next two years, Edith Stein was his assistant, as was philosopher Martin Heidegger (18891976), for whom he obtained a lectureship and helped get an assistant professorship in 1919. The next year, his son Gerhard was wounded, although he recovered. Over the following decade, Husserl and Heidegger were in contact, exchanging ideas and manuscripts. Because of his Jewish birth, in 1933 the German government barred Husserl from using the library at Freiburg University, or any other German academic institution, although after an immediate public outcry, he was reinstated a week later by a decree. Husserl resigned from the Deutsche Akademie several months after that. His leaving was not only a matter of what had happened at Freiburg but of the growing danger to all Jews in Germany at that time. He was then appointed to the School of Philosophy at the University of Southern California, but declined because his assistant, Eugen Fink, was not permitted to accompany him. Husserl was not allowed to participate in the Paris Congress of Philosophers in 1937. At his cremation the next year, Eugen
273
Fink eulogized him. Fink had been Husserls dedicated and collaborative research assistant for 10 years. In his own work, Fink was to eventually turn from Husserls philosophical perspective to that of Heidegger. Husserl had only published six books during his lifetime, but he had a huge collection of papers and manuscripts. Fearing that the Nazis would destroy them, the Belgian philosopher Herman Leo Van Breda (19111974) took them out of Germany, where they became part of the Husserl Archives in Louvain after World War II.
274
Edith Stein, a student of Edmund Husserl, was canonized after performing a miracle to save a child who overdosed on acetaminophen (AP).
How did Edmund Husserl separate mathematics and logic from psychology?
irst, Husserl distinguished between numbers that are the result of counting actual objects before us and numbers as symbols. Clearly, most of mathematics deals with numbers as symbols. Husserl claimed that symbolic numbers, as well as propositions and universals, cannot be reduced to mental states, as psychologism claimed. As intentional objects of consciousness, in Franz Brentanos (18371917) sense of intentionality, these logical and mathematical entities are objective.
who had overdosed on acetaminophen in response to a prayer from relativesis disputed by some Jewish groups who claim it is not clear whether she is a genuine martyr. Her legacy includes numerous writings, some of which were translated into English in the 1980s and 1990s: Life in a Jewish Family: Her Unfinished Autobiographical Account (1986), On the Problem of Empathy (1989), Essays on Women (1996), and The Hidden Life, (1993). Stein also wrote Knowledge and Faith, Finite and Eternal Being: An Attempt to an Ascent to the Meaning of Being, Philosophy of Psychology and the Humanities, Self-Portrait in Letters, which have not yet been translated into English or published.
275
How did Edmund Husserl distinguish between two types of the self?
First, Husserl explained that there is the psychological ego or the self that owns or makes the intentional acts of consciousness. The psychological ego exists in the world, because one can be aware of it as a self. But there is also the transcendental ego for which there is a world and which is concerned about truththe transcendental ego intends the world. The transcendental ego makes it possible for the psychological ego to exist and it determines how it will function.
M A RT I N H E I D E G G E R
Who was Martin Heidegger?
Martin Heidegger (18891976) was the phenomenological ontologist who first united existentialism with phenomenology, but later revealed that his true concern was ontology. He is considered one of the titans of Western philosophy and had more
276
direct enduring influence over twentieth century continental philosophy than any other thinker. Heidegger wrote extensively on the history of philosophy, developing his own phenomenological analyses. His main books include his doctoral dissertation The Doctrine of Judgement in Psychologism (1914), his habilitation (in Europe, Ph.D.s write two dissertations, one to get a degree as a scholar and the second to qualify them to teach on a university level) The Doctrine of Categories and Signification in Duns Scotus (1914), his most famous Being and Time (1927), and then Introduction to Metaphysics (1953), What Is Called Thinking (1954), What Is Philosophy? (1956), On the Way to Language (1959), Nietzsche I and II Martin Heidegger was a phenomenological ontologist who united existentialism with phenomenology (AP). (1961), and Phenomenology and Theology (1970). Transcripts of Heideggers lectures were partly published in 1975 (the complete works would constitute over 100 volumes). Heidegger is also known for articles on art and poetry, as well as his essay The Question Concerning Technology.
277
Heidegger paid dues as a member of the NSDAP, or Nazi Party, from 1933 to 1945. In his inaugural address in May 1933 as rector of Freiburg University, three months after Hitler came to power, he called for the students and faculty to serve the new regime, referring to the march our people has begun into its future history and to the power to preserve, in the deepest way, the strengths which are rooted in soil and blood. In June 1933, he told the Heidelberg Student Association that the university must be integrated into the Volksgemeinshaft (peoples community) and be joined together with the state. In August 1933, he established the rule that the rector would no longer be elected by the faculty but appointed by the Nazi minister of education, a position to which he was himself appointed in October 1933. In November 1933, he applied the Nazi laws on racial cleansing to the students at Freiberg, awarding financial aid to Aryan students, but not to Jews or Marxists. Heidegger also secretly denounced to the Nazi government a number of Jewish or politically suspect professors at Freiburg, such as Hermann Staudinger, who won the Nobel prize in chemistry in 1953, and Eduard Baumgarten, the pragmatist philosopher who was teaching at Gttingen. Max Mller, the Catholic intellectual, was fired by Heidegger as student leader and prevented from getting a lectureship. Edmund Husserl (18591938), Heideggers former teacher, was denied use of the University Library at Freiburg because he was a Jew even though he had converted to Lutheranism. (Heidegger and Husserls intellectual relationship is examined in the film The Ister, directed by David Barrison and Daniel Ross in 2004.) Although Heidegger resigned as rector in 1934, the next year he referred to the inner truth and greatness of National Socialism. At least until 1960, Heidegger maintained a friendly acquaintance with Eugen Fisher, the head of the Institute of Racial Hygiene in Berlin that employed the infamous Dr. Joseph Mengele as a researcher. Heidegger never repudiated Nazism after World War II. In his lecture on technology in 1949, he referred to the mechanism of agriculture, saying: Agriculture is now a motorized food-industryin essence, the same as the manufacturing of corpses in the gas chambers and the extermination camps, the same as the blockade and starvation of the countryside, the same as the production of the hydrogen bombs.
278
Many were offended by this comparison by Heidegger of murdered Jews to agricultural products. In a last interview before his death, Heidegger described the main task of thought as achieving a satisfactory relationship to technology. He said that National Socialism had that goal but that those people were far too limited in their thinking to acquire an explicit relationship to what is really happening today and has been underway for three centuries. In other words, his greatest disappointment with the Nazis was their failure in addressing the problem of technology!
279
What is Dasein?
Dasein is Martin Heideggers term for a human being. Its literal meaning is being there. Heidegger intended by this term to convey that human beings are not simple, self-contained biological beings but that they are always concerned with things beyond their physical selves, with things in the world, other people, and the future.
280
Why did Martin Heidegger claim that existentialism was not a type of humanism?
In going back to Presocratic thought, Heidegger concluded that the original concern of man, or Dasein (in a cultural line that linked contemporary Germans to ancient Greeks), was Being. Heidegger believed that the Presocratics had only started to formulate the primary questions concerning Being, when the Socratics introduced a subject-object kind of metaphysics that already foreclosed one kind of answer to the original question of Being. Heidegger makes it clear to the reader that he does not know what this original question concerning Being was. Indeed, he devoted his philosophical work to trying to reconstruct the question, thereby inviting readers to ponder the same problem he did, with no conclusive answer. In this sense, Heidegger provides an exercise in meditation to those of his readers who take the time to understand him. Heidegger wrote much about what that question might be, relying on a phenomenological intuition that language is the house of Being. He did not mean by this the language of the they, or even the discourse of French existentialists, such as JeanPaul Sartre (19051980), with its insufficiently general concerns. Until the question of
281
Why did Martin Heidegger refuse having his works translated from the German language?
eidegger had a strong bias in favor of German as the language of thought. He did not think that his philosophy could be understood by those who did not speak German, and would not permit his work to be translated into Spanish.
Being could be formulated, the kind of humanism that existentialism could be could not even be properly imagined, according to Heidegger.
M A U R I C E M E R L E A U -P O N T Y
Who was Maurice Merleau-Ponty?
Maurice Merleau-Ponty (19081961) was an anti-empiricist who sought to reconstruct the world based on a phenomenology of human perception. He was influenced by Edmund Husserl (18591938), was friends with Jean-Paul Sartre (19051980) for a while, and continues to be of great interest to phenomenological philosophers of
282
erleau-Ponty died suddenly of a stroke while preparing to give a lecture on Ren Descartes (15961650). He repeatedly returned to Descartes split between the mind and the body in composing his own philosophy. He did not accept the Cartesean split, but sought to address the mind and body as a united whole. Merleau-Ponty thought that a persons own body, le corps propre, should be, in its personal, individual, lived reality, a scientific subject. It is ones own body that makes consciousness corporeal. He wrote: Insofar as I have hands, feet, a body, I sustain around me intentions which are not dependent on my decisions and which affect my surroundings in a way that I do not choose. Clearly, Merleau-Pontys stroke proves this point because it was not something he chose, but definitely something that conclusively affected not only his surroundings but the possibility of his even having those surroundings. Whats ironic is that he made his point by having a stroke, which is very different from making a philosophical argument.
mind. His principal works are The Phenomenology of Perception (1945), numerous essays, and his unfinished The Visible and the Invisible.
What are some facts about Maurice Merleau-Pontys life and career?
Merleau-Pontys father was killed in World War I. He completed his philosophical studies at the cole Normale Superieure in 1930 and then taught in high schools throughout France. He wrote two dissertations for his doctorate and was given the chair of child psychology at the Sorbonne in 1949; next, he was made chair of philosophy at the College de France in 1952. With Jean-Paul Sartre (19051980) he founded the journal Les Temps Moderne. But he resigned from the publication as editor, partly in objection to Sartres subject-object dichotomy. Merleau-Ponty wrote about their dispute in Adventures of the Dialectic (1955). Overall, Merleau-Ponty opposed dualisms and he also criticized self-versus-world ideas. He thought that the self was as much a body as a mind and that our bodies are always in the world.
283
was thus on the human body as a perceiving, living part of world, a position theretofore much neglected in philosophical inquiry. According to Merleau-Ponty, perception is neither abstract nor scientific. Rather, all perception is lived; it is the experience of human beings in the world. Consciousness is, to use a later term, embodied and always engaged in perceiving the world. What is phenomenological about human experience is that what is perceived cannot be separated from how it is perceived or from how it is described. In conversation with Ferdinand de Saussure (18571913), Merleau-Ponty composed The Prose of the World (1969), claiming that meaning is not determined by history but by the subjects actual experience in the world. Language is itself continually changing as a result of this experience. In The Visible and the Invisible Merleau-Ponty had intended to show how communication and thought can go beyond perception, but he died before completing that project.
The president of Italy visits Antonio Gramsci museum. Gramsci (whose photo is seen in the background on the right) came up with the idea that a societys dominant class defines the ideology of all classes within that society (AP).
gift from Felix Weil (18981975) in 1923, following the First Marxist Week, which was very well-received by intellectuals. The Institute was, in addition, funded by Frankfurt University and, during the Nazi period (19331944), Max Horkmeier (18951973) and Theodore Adorno (19031969) secured the support of Columbia University to set up its exiled version as The International Institute of Social Research in New York City. The Institute in Frankfurt was reinstated after World War II ended in 1945. Walter Benjamin (18921940), Herbert Marcuse (18981979) and Erich Fromm (1900 1980), were also among its first generation of members. Jrgen Habermas (1923) remains its most famous contemporary member. Hannah Arendt (19061975) had political interests that implied she had more in common with the Frankfurt School than any other movement, despite striking out on her own as an American philosopher after leaving Germany. Although not part of the Frankfurt School because he was imprisoned by the Italian fascist government in 1926, the Marxist theorist Antonio Gramsci (18911937) deserves mention in this context.
285
communists. According to Togliatti, education and persuasion were the paths to reform toward a classless society, rather than Bolshevism or direct political revolution. Gramscis most influential idea has been what Togliatti called Gramscis theory of hegemony, whereby the dominant class in society creates not only its own ideology, but also that of the classes dominated by itall classes share the ideology of the dominant class. Hence, education and persuasion are important to change the social mass mind, so that political change can evolve. In this sense, it could be said that Gramsci was not only a member in spirit of the Frankfurt School, he was also a structuralist.
286
German-American social and political philosopher Hannah Arendt was an ardent critic of all forms of totalitarianism (AP).
287
herself an existentialist because she thought we are is a more important starting point for philosophy than I am. Her positive model of society was active citizen participation in ways that leave social and private interests out of civic identities. Arendts analysis of the trial of the Nazi Adolf Eichmann, in which she introduced the concept of the banality of evil, was very controversial for her criticism of how Eichmanns trial was conducted in Israel, and how Jewish leaders had behaved under German dictator Adolf Hitler. Arendts last work was an examination of practical judgment in political contexts in which she used the figure of Socrates (460399 B.C.E.) to posit inner dialogues. Conscience, she said, had the role of supporting friendship with ones self.
288
African American social critic and political activist Angela Davis has remained relevant since the 1970s by continuing to write on race and gender issues (AP).
name. She was for a while on the FBIs most wanted list after she fled arrest. In the end, Davis was acquitted of criminal charges and was rehired at the university. Davis claimed that she never completed her dissertation because it was lost in papers confiscated by the FBI. She has since developed a distinguished career in critical writings about race and gender as well as the prison industrial complex in contemporary American culture. Davis principal works include If They Come in the Morning: Voices of Resistance (1971), Frame Up: The Opening Defense Statement Made (1972), Angela Davis: An Autobiography (1974), Women, Race and Class (1981), Violence against Women and the Ongoing Challenge to Racism (1985), Women, Culture and Politics (1989), Blues Legacies and Black Feminism: Gertrude Ma Rainey, Bessie Smith, and Billie Holiday (1999), Are Prisons Obsolete? (2003), and Abolition Democracy: Beyond Prisons, Torture, and Empire (2005).
289
ing about language, symbols, and how people and events were represented in popular culture, as well as academic disciplines. Language became the new main subject across disciplines.
290
Claude Lvi-Strauss applied theories of language systems to the ways people relate to each other (AP).
forces, as Marx had claimed. Althusser killed his wife in 1980 and was committed to a psychiatric facility, thereby ending his academic career.
What was Michel Foucaults method for forming his cultural criticism?
Foucault studied institutions and ideas by understanding their histories. In the course of that anthropological archeology, he often pinpointed the emergence of new forms of human discourse and personal identity. In the case of sexuality, for example, Foucault argued that new forms of power create new forms of sexuality, as do new practices of observation and medical diagnosis. One of Foucaults most enduring contributions was to demonstrate how many human traits and practices that are believed to be natural are in fact the effects of social and political institutions that exert unexamined power on individuals. At the same time, the individuals are complicit in remaking themselves to conform to institutional expectations. A primary example would be ideas of gender such as athletic ability in women. Before the second half of the twentieth century, women were believed to be unable to participate or excel in sports due to natural limitations. Foucault is famous for having claimed to invert Plato (c. 428c. 348 B.C.E.), who had said that the soul is imprisoned in the body, meaning that our natural physical needs and desires oppress our higher spiritual selves. Foucault thought that the soul is the prison of the body, meaning that our ideas shape our physical existence.
291
icos Poulantzas (19361979) developed a nuanced Marxist analysis of social class in late capitalist systems. Building on Antonio Gramsci (18911937), he argued that elements of the ruling class have made strategic alliances with oppressed classes and successfully secured their ongoing consent, such as with the American New Deal instituted by President Franklin Roosevelt. Poulantzas major works include Political Power and Social Classes (1968), Classes in Contemporary Capitalism (1973), and State, Power, Socialism (1978).
that medical practice in general required a certain kind of seeing before specific pathologies could be detected. In The Order of Things (1966), he argued that part of the development of economics, science, and linguistics in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries entailed the invention of the idea of man as a universal subject. (Man, the universal subject, was supposed to be always the same and always rational.) In The Archaeology of Knowledge (1969), Foucault showed how the sciences themselves are constituted by discourses, or background ways of forming and transmitting knowledge. Without prior standards that make scientific knowledge acceptable as knowledge, scientific discoveries would have no importance. For example, if we hear that scientists have discovered a gene that predisposes people to a certain kind of cancer, we accept this as true, because we accept the authority of science. Discipline and Punish: The Origin of the Prison (1975) marks the beginning of Foucaults investigation of power. He argued that institutions such as the prison, the army, the factory, and the school wield power through specific techniques in which oppression can coexist with representative democratic political structures.
292
Iran, published in the Italian newspaper Corriere della Sera, provoked controversy when they were translated into French and English in 1994 and 2005, respectively. Foucault was in a committed 25-year relationship with Daniel Defert, a former student. He described it as having lived in a state of passion, adding that at some moments this passion has taken the form of love. Much has been said and written about Foucaults exploration of homosexual bars and sex clubs in the Castro district of San Francisco. Foucault died of an AIDS-related infection, although this was not admitted at first, when his death was announced in Le Monde. Before he died, Foucault destroyed massive amounts of his unpublished writings and directed that other manuscripts be destroyed also.
293
AMERICAN PHILOSOPHY
What is American philosophy?
The term American philosophy most often refers to the school of pragmatism, which began in the late-nineteenth century. Pragmatism is internationally recognized to be a distinct form of philosophy, not only created by philosophers from the United States, but also reflective of American culture. There were, of course, intellectuals in the United States before the pragmatists, and some of their work was highly original, linked to distinct cultures: seventeenth, eighteenth, and nineteenth century political theorists, abolitionists, suffragists, evolutionists, Native American thinkers, American Hegelians, and New England transcendentalists. Many American philosophers after the pragmatists have worked within analytic, empirical, continental, and postmodern traditions, as well as later forms of pragmatism. American philosophy, broadly understood as an intellectual aspect of culture, would include all of these fields. However, American philosophy, as systematic philosophy, traditionally understood, narrows the subject down.
E AR LY AM E R I CA N P H I LO S O P H I CA L STR A I N S
Which early American philosophical strains were most influential?
The thought of several Native American orators, the St. Louis Hegelians, the transcendentalists of New England, and writers on evolution all influenced pragmatist philosophy, either directly or by their emphasis of what were to become enduring American themes to be taken up by pragmatists and others.
295
However, the speeches of eighteenth and nineteenth century Native American leaders who sought to resist removal to reservations and preserve the lives, cultures, and lands of their peoples endure as unreconstituted early American philosophy. Noteworthy in this regard is Teedyuscung, who, when he spoke at treaty councils in Pennsylvania, began: I desire all that I have said may be taken down aright. Teedyuscung, Tenskwatawa, and Sagoewatha spoke like Americans.
For Native American tribes it has been a struggle to preserve their rich artistic and spiritual values. Native American philosophy has become a subject of interest at universities in recent years (iStock).
296
It is true I am a Shawnee. My forefathers were warriors. Their son is a warrior. From them I take only my existence; from my tribe I take nothing. I am the
maker of my own fortune; and oh! that I could make of my own fortune; and oh! that I could make that of my red people, and of my country, as great as the conceptions of my mind, when I think of the Spirit that rules the universe. I would not then come to Governor Harrison to ask him to tear the treaty and to obliterate the landmark; but I would say to him: Sir, you have liberty to return to your own country.
A M ERICA N PH IL OSOPH Y
What was the most striking Native American contribution to American philosophy?
There is growing recognition of the influence of Native American thought on eighteenth and nineteenth century Euro-American ideas, as well as later on in history. Contemporary pragmatist scholars have traced contemporary concerns with community well-being in a pluralistic society to early Native American attempts to negotiate with Euro-Americans. Others have identified deeper mainstream American cultural debts to indigenous peoples. Robert Pirsig, the author of Zen and the Art of Motorcycle Maintenance (1974), in his second book, Lila (1991), draws a fascinating and neglected comparison between what was to become the distinctly direct and plain American style of speech (if not always writing) and speeches in English made by Native American Great Plains leaders. Pirsig quotes Ten Bears, speaking in 1867 to other Native Americans and representatives from Washington: I was born on the prairie, where the wind blew free, and there was nothing to break the light of the sun. I was born where there were no enclosures, and where everything drew a free breath. I want to die there and not within walls. I lived like my father before me, and like them I lived happily. While pragmatists such as John Dewey (18591952) were often prolix, their writing was nevertheless direct and innocent of the high style of European abstraction and unnecessary embellishment. Their ideas were not unnecessarily complicated. The same can be said of much New England transcendentalist writing, although maybe not of the St. Louis Hegelians, of the more idealist pragmatists such as Charles Sanders Peirce (18391914) and Josiah Royce (18551916), or the process philosophers Alfred North Whitehead (18611947) and his follower Charles Hartshorne (18972000).
297
S T. L O U I S H E G E L I A N S
Who were the St. Louis Hegelians?
They were a group of philosophers and teachers who founded The Saint Louis Philosophical Society in 1866 and began to publish The Journal of Speculative Philosophy in 1867. The founding members were Henry C. Brokmeyer (18261906), William T. Harris (18351909), and Denton Jacques Snider (18411925). Brokmeyer was a Prussian immigrant who had come to the United States in 1844, attended Brown University, plied several trades, and lived in a hut (like Henry David Thoreau [18171862]). Harris was a Yale dropout who came to St. Louis to teach Pittman shorthand. Brokmeyer and Harris undertook the project of translating Hegels Science of Logic (1812) into English. Snider, who had graduated from Oberlin College, came to St. Louis in 1865 to teach at Christian Brothers College.
Did the Eastern philosophers interact much with the St. Louis Hegelians?
Although they were not academic philosophers, the St. Louis philosophers were in conversation with the Eastern transcendental thinkers, such as those of the Concord School of Philosophy, which had been organized by William Harris (18351909) and
298
A M ERICA N PH IL OSOPH Y
Was there other philosophical activity in St. Louis besides the St. Louis Hegelians?
ontemporary with the St. Louis Philosophical Society, and also located in St. Louis, were a Kant Club, an Aristotle Club, and a Plato Club that later became known as Akademe.
transcendentalist Amos Bronson Alcott (17991888). The Concord School held conferences during the summer from 1879 to 1887, and when Alcott first visited Harris in St. Louis, he was abused by Henry C. Brokmeyer (18261906) in what the Hegelian observers called the first bout between East and West. The result was celebrated as a victory for the West. Another famed Eastern philosopher, Ralph Waldo Emerson (18031882), also visited the St. Louis Philosophical Society.
299
Thomas Davidson (18401900), who was another early member of the St. Louis Society, founded the Breadwinners College in New York City and a summer school in Glenmore, New York, where he later lived.
N E W E N G L A N D T R A N S C E N D E N TA L I S T S
Who were the New England Transcendentalists?
They are considered to be the American counterparts to European Romantics, who valued emotion as much or more than reason and stressed the importance of individual and private yearnings. The distinctively American form of Romanticism, as seen in the novels of Herman Melville (18191891), the prose of Ralph Waldo Emerson (18031882), the poetry of Walt Whitman (18191892), and the essays of Henry David Thoreau (18171862), emphasized the condition of the solitary and courageous private person in nature. As well, there were distinctly philosophical transcendentalists, such as Amos Bronson Alcott (17991888).
300
publications include New Connecticut, Tablets (1868), Concord Days (1872), and Sonnets and Canzonets (1882). Most of his other work is still unpublished, except for his vague Orphic Sayings that appeared in The Dial, and which is representative of transcendental thought.
A M ERICA N PH IL OSOPH Y
301
After Thoreau left his hut to stay at Ralph Waldo Emersons (18031882) house, it was moved around Brooks Clark Farm as a structure for storing corn. It was finally placed in the northwest pasture of the farm to memorialize Thoreau and left there until 1867, although the windows were gone by then. In 1868, the roof was taken off to cover a pig yard, and in 1885 the floor and some other wood from the hut were used to make a shed off the barn. The remainder of the hut was then taken apart to replace planks in the barn. Others say that these boards were used to remodel the farm house.
to build a broad community and support democratic social interactions through writing and public speaking. But both Thoreaus privileged love of nature and the pragmatists more common touch represent a cultural sea change from much of the thought discussed in the salons, drawing rooms, and formal church-like architectural settings of Europe.
302
about his travels; The Conduct of Life (1860); the poetry collection May-Day and Other Pieces (1867); and Society and Solitude (1870). Emersons last series of essays were lectures given at Harvard University in 1871 and posthumously published as Natural History of Intellect (1904). There is also the Correspondence of Thomas Carlyle and R.W. Emerson (1883).
A M ERICA N PH IL OSOPH Y
Ralph Waldo Emerson was the leading American transcendentalist of the nineteenth century (Art Archive).
303
Stuart Mill (18061873). In 1835 Emerson bought a house in Concord, Massachusetts, and married Lydia Jackson, with whom he had four children. He was reasonably well off financially (partly due to a lawsuit securing his inheritance from his first wife) and he used part of the money to help Amos Bronson Alcott (17991888), his neighbor. Many considered Emerson the greatest orator of his day.
304
A M ERICA N PH IL OSOPH Y
Atlantic magazinewhich also published essays by the African American intellectual Frederick Douglassprinted these words by Emerson, referring to the slave-owning and free American states, in 1862: We have attempted to hold together two states of civilization: a higher state, where labor and the tenure of land and the right of suffrage are democratical; and a lower state, in which the old military tenure of prisoners or slaves, and of power and land in a few hands, makes an oligarchy. But the rude and early state of society does not work well with the later, nay, works badly, and has poisoned politics, public morals, and social intercourse in the Republic, now for many years.
305
306
The famous abolitionist, suffragist, orator, and statesman Frederick Douglass is considered by many to have been the first liberatory African American intellectual (Art Archive).
which had as the motto Right is of no SexTruth is of no ColorGod is the Father of us all, and we are all brethren. In the 1850s, Douglass spoke for school desegregation in New York. During the U.S. Civil War, he promoted the rights of blacks to fight for the Union. When the Emancipation Proclamation was issued in 1862, he said: We were waiting and listening as for a bolt from the sky we were watching by the dim light of the stars for the dawn of a new day we were longing for the answer to the agonizing prayers of centuries. In 1884, after his first wife had died, Douglass married Helen Pitts, a white suffragist from New York. Pitts had worked on Alpha, the nineteenth-century radical womens publication, while living in Washington, D.C. Douglass main writings are A Narrative of the Life of Frederick Douglass, an American Slave (1845), The Heroic Slave: Autographs for Freedom (1853), My Bondage and My Freedom (1855), and Life and Times of Frederick Douglass (1881; revised, 1892); he edited The North Star from 1847 to 1851, after which it became the Frederick Douglass Paper.
A M ERICA N PH IL OSOPH Y
S O C IAL DARWI N I S M
What was evolutionary thought like in America during the nineteenth century?
Within educated communities, Charles Darwins theory of evolution was broadly accepted as an accurate history of living beings. Since Deism, or the idea that God was suffused throughout nature, was a widespread perspective at the time, there was not an obvious conflict between religious accounts of creation and evolution. Discussion more commonly centered on whether social forms of evolution were ruthlessly competitive or cooperative. As in nineteenth century European thought, there were two perspectives: life in society, as in nature, was red in tooth and claw and a matter of survival of the fittest; or, life in society, as in nature, evolved through cooperation. It is not surprising that the transcendentalists favored the cooperative view.
307
sion on general readers. They shared a belief that competition was valuable in itself and that those who failed in lifes contests failed a deeper test of evolutionary survival. Instead of social reform, their ideals were to encourage the traits that enabled success at competition by means of selective human breeding, as well as moral approval of the winners.
308
A M ERICA N PH IL OSOPH Y
Toward the end of the nineteenth century and the beginning of the twentieth, Social Darwinism and its associated eugenics merged with white American racialist beliefs that would later be considered racist or discriminatory. For example, in 1916 amateur anthropologist and lawyer Madison Grant published The Passing of the Great Race; or, The Racial Basis of European History. Grant propounded a theory of Nordic Superiority and argued for a public eugenic program to save the Nordics from being overrun by non-white racial groups. Grants book sold 1,600,000 copies by 1937. It was widely influential in individual beliefs and public policy that restricted immigration from Asia and discriminated harshly against African Americans.
The idea of progress through technological innovation was certainly the faith held by such prominent thinkers as inventor Thomas Edison (AP).
309
Review in 1831 that machines free ordinary people from burdensome labor and promote democracy.
P R A G MATI S M A N D P RO C E S S P H I LO S O P HY
What is pragmatism?
Pragmatism is a distinctively American philosophy that originated in community discussion groups and came to define the philosophy department at Harvard University during the late nineteenth century. While not as scientific in perspective as some philosophy in Europe during the same time, it represented an effort to think in a practical way.
C HAR LE S SAN D E R S P E I RC E
Who was Charles Sanders Peirce?
Charles Sanders Peirce (18391914) is recognized as the founder and originator of pragmatism, although his intellectual expertise extended to logic, mathematics, economics, social science, the physical sciences, and geodesic work. Peirces published writings date from 1857 until his death and constitute 12,000 printed pages. There are, in addition, 80,000 pages of his unpublished hand-written work. His principal works, published posthumously, are edited volumes, such as The New Elements of Mathematics (four volumes, 1976), The Essential Peirce (two volumes, 1992 and 1998), and Writings of Charles S. Peirce: A Chronological Edition (five volumes, 18821993).
What are some key facts about Charles Peirces career and life?
Charles Sanders Peirce (18391914) was born in Cambridge, Massachusetts. His father, Benjamin, was professor of mathematics at Harvard University and a founder of the U.S. Coast and Geodetic Survey and the Smithsonian Institution. (Benjamin Peirce is also said to have built the Harvard department of mathematics.) At the age of 12, young Charles discovered logic, and at 16, he began his independent study of philosophy. In 1859 he graduated from Harvard, unsure of what I would do in life. His primary interest was in logic, for which there were no career opportunities. He practiced geodesy for several years and returned to Harvard to study natural history and philosophy in 1861. He got a Ph.D. in chemistry in 1863, graduating summa cum laude. Peirce continued his studies of logic on his own and has been considered to be one of the greatest logicians of all times. Although he disagreed with Immanuel Kants (17241804) insistence that space was Euclidean and later moved to Friedrich Hegels
310
A M ERICA N PH IL OSOPH Y
The first edition of Peirces Collected Papers was put together by Charles Hartshorne, Paul Weiss, and Arthur Burks during the 1930s. Critics have deemed this collection arbitrary and not truly representative of Peirces thought because it makes Peirce seem unnecessarily obscure and does not clarify the progression of his ideas. A Chronological Edition (1989) of Pierces work, edited by the Peirce Edition Project of the Indiana University at Indianapolis, has produced more coherent results, covering the period from 18571886. Two other well-regarded efforts are Peirces Cambridge Conferences Lectures of 1898 (1992) and Peirces Harvard Lectures on Pragmatism of 1903 (1997).
(17701831) objective idealism, Kant remained a dominating influence over his philosophical ideas. Peirces philosophy was a distinct form of pragmatism, which he called Pragmaticism.
311
thingand that these signs are all meaningful. The meaning of each sign is part of a system that also contains the object and the interpretant. The object is what the sign is a sign of. The interpretant is the feature or activity of mind that experiences the sign. And, the interpretant is also a signbecause everything is a signso it also has an object and a second interpretant. This structure of signobjectinterpretant, interpretant-as-sign object new interpretant goes on infinitely. But the reality of the object consists of a limiting form that is approached as cognitions approach infinity. That is, if an object is real, our process of inquiry and experience can go on almost forever. Reality for Peirce was a convergence of inquiry, and since what we know is always general or a universal, the object is made up of universals. This makes reality mental, hence Peirces philosophical idealism. However, Peirce ran into difficulties with the logic of these relations, and after discovering an original (and still not widely understood, except by logicians) logic of relations, he constructed his third system (18701884), which more closely resembled what is now considered pragmatism and is based on the operating principles that most now associate with Peirce, although he called his system pragmaticism to distinguish it from the ideas of other pragmatists, who were less concerned with science.
312
A M ERICA N PH IL OSOPH Y
ierce did have a job as lecturer in logic at Johns Hopkins University, in Baltimore, from 1879 to 1891. But in 1883 he divorced Harriet Melusina Fay, to whom he had been married since 1862, and married Juliette Froissy. Froissy was thought to be a gypsy, and Peirce was said to have lived with her before their marriage. A scandal ensued, and Peirce left his academic position. Peirces only subsequent employment was for the U.S. Coast and Geodetic Survey, which ended in 1901 due to congressional curtailment of funding. Peirce then did odd jobs and was employed as a consultant in chemical engineering. Sometimes, William James (18421910) and other friends assisted him financially.
of idealism that posited the entire universe as a living, feeling organism, with habits that are mirrored in our general laws of nature (descriptions of regularities).
W I L L I A M JA M E S
Who was William James?
William James (18421910) built on Charles Peirces (18391914) pragmaticist ideas to create a more humanistic form of pragmatism. James was also the founder of modern psychology as a science independent of subjective introspection. His principal works include The Principles of Psychology (1890), The Will to Believe and Other Essays in Popular Philosophy (1897), The Varieties of Religious Experience (1901 1902), and Pragmatism (1907).
313
was awarded his M.D. in 1869. It was his only academic degree, although he never practiced medicine. He married Alice Gibbens in 1878 and spent the remainder of his life teaching at Harvard, in both psychology and, after the early 1880s, philosophy. James students included such luminaries as President Theodore Roosevelt, author and philosopher George Santayana, civil rights activist W.E.B. Du Bois, philosopher Ralph Barton Perry, author Gertrude Stein, philosopher and legal scholar Morris Raphael Cohen, Alain Locke (sometimes called the Father of the Harlem Renaissance), logician and pragmatist C.I. Lewis, and psychologist and philosopher Mary Calkins.
314
Intellectually, James pragmatism grew out of the limitations of psychology to provide answers to the moral questions that interested him: How can religion be justified intellectually? Is there free will? What is the nature of truth?
A M ERICA N PH IL OSOPH Y
What were William James theories concerning religion and free will?
James thought that whether or not to believe in God, or to believe that we have free will and that there are objective values, cannot be decided neutrally by an appeal to facts. The facts in such matters are inconclusive, and a neutral intellectual position does not address the importance to us of whether or not God exists, or if we have free will, or whether there are objective values. Because our beliefs in such matters will make a difference in our lives and those of others, we must will to believe that God exists, that we have free will, and that there are objective values. In the case of free will, to motivate ourselves toward actions that are unpleasant, we should think about their positive consequences. James offered an example of this: when one is reluctant to arise from bed on a cold morning, if one thinks about what one will do that day the necessary physical motion becomes almost automatic.
315
ome biographers have speculated that James interest in spiritualism was the result of his fathers deep interest in Swedenborg. Emmanuel Swedenborg (16881772) had inspired the formation of the New Jerusalem church in London in 1788. Swedenborg had combined the scientific thought of Ren Descartes (15961650) and John Locke (16321704) into a form of mechanism that was in harmony with the biblical universe as known through revelation. It is not a wide stretch to see similarities in this view and James project of applying scientific methods to the supernatural.
J O S IAH ROYC E
Who was Josiah Royce?
Josiah Royce (18551916) is known as an absolute pragmatist. He sought to combine German and British absolute idealism with American pragmatism. Royce was born in Grass Valley, California, which, at the time following the gold rush, was a mining town. His family moved to San Francisco when he was 11 and he graduated from the University of California in 1875; he then received a Ph.D. from Johns Hopkins University in 1878. Royce also studied at universities in Leipzig and Gttingen, after which he taught English at the University of California for four years.
316
In 1882, he was invited to join Harvards philosophy department, where he eventually became a professor and led a highly acclaimed and distinguished career. Royces major publications are The World and the Individual (1899), Sources of Religious Insight (1912), The Problem of Christianity (1913), War and Insurance (1914), The Hope of the Great Community (1916), and Lectures on Modern Idealism (1919). Also available is Royces Logical Essays: Collected Logical Essays of Josiah Royce (1951).
A M ERICA N PH IL OSOPH Y
JOH N DEWEY
Who was John Dewey?
John Dewey (18591952) was the most famous philosopher in the United States during the early twentieth century. He was a public intellectual during the decades when ordinary people, as well as intellectuals, filled halls to hear intellectually stimulating and edifying speeches. His interactive, pragmatic approach to ordinary life, education, and art appreciation has shaped American experience in fundamental ways that do not always refer to him by name. Although, or because, Dewey was shy, he wrote 37 books and more than 700 articles. His main publications include Psychology (1887), Human Nature and Conduct
317
(1922), Experience and Nature (1925), The Public and Its Problems (1927), The Quest for Certainty (1929), Philosophy and Civilization (1932), A Common Faith (1934), Art as Experience (1934), Liberalism and Social Action (1935), Logic: The Theory of Inquiry (1938), Freedom and Culture (1939), and Problems of Men (1946).
What are some key facts about John Deweys life and career?
Dewey was born in 1859 in Burlington, Vermont, where his father was a grocer. He attended the University of Vermont and then taught classics, science, and algebra at a high school in Oil City, Pennsylvania, and then in Burlington, Vermont. Unsure of his future direction, but encouraged by former teachers, he applied to the new graduate program in philosophy at Johns Hopkins University but was turned down for a fellowship twice. Dewey finally borrowed $500 from an aunt to attend. He thereby became part of the first generation able to obtain Ph.D.s in philosophy in the United States. Deweys teachers at Johns Hopkins were philosophers George Sylvester Morris (18401889) and Charles Sanders Peirce (18391914), and psychologist G. Stanley Hall (18441924). At first, Dewey was very interested in Hegelian ideas of organism, that the living being interacts with its environment, and that society is an organic whole that can be viewed as an organism. After writing a dissertation on Immanuel Kant (1724 1804), he taught at the University of Michigan from 1884 to 1894. At this time he became interested in public education and progressive politics, as well as psychology. In 1894 Dewey became chair of the department of philosophy, psychology, and education at the University of Chicago. At Chicago, working with colleagues, he began to develop activist social theories. This resulted in the 1903 Studies in Logical Theory, which was dedicated to William James (18421910). Dewey had a national reputation when he left Chicago for Columbia University. The Journal of Philosophy, published by the Columbia Philosophy Department, became an outlet for his ideas and a forum for discussion of them over the decades. Dewey lectured in Tokyo, Peking, and Nanking, and studied education in Turkey, Mexico, and Russia.
318
John Dewey was the most famous philosopher in the United States during the early twentieth century (AP).
In retirement, Dewey chaired the 1937 Mexican commission investigating charges against Russian revolutionary Leon Trotsky, which produced a report, Not Guilty. He also defended Bertrand Russell in 1941, when Russell was denied a teaching opportunity at City College, New York, because of his political ideas.
A M ERICA N PH IL OSOPH Y
319
When Dewey began to consider education, school children were expected to sit quietly and absorb information passively. While Dewey did not believe in a completely child-centered method of instruction, he emphasized the activity of learning, with an understanding that children are already curious and energetic participants in common, ordinary life outside the classroom. Dewey thought that children should be taught skills to solve problems, including moral problems. When he became chair of the department of philosophy, psychology, and education at the University of Chicago, he founded The Laboratory School. It was based on his theory of education, the motto of which was Learn by Doing! However, he acknowledged practical advice from Ella Flagg Young, the first woman president of the National Education Association, who was able to translate his ideas into actual practices and exercises in the classroom. He was also in contact with Jane Addams, who had cofounded the educational mission at Hull House. Dewey spent considerable time there himself, talking to working people about their problems and aspirations. His 1899 The School and Society was a best seller. Deweys subsequent works on education were The Child and the Curriculum (1902), How We Think (1910), and Democracy and Education (1916).
Dewey called the aesthetic qualities of experience tertiary qualities. Because experience is a kind of transaction, the aesthetic quality of an experience can change and become more meaningful toward a consummation. A consummation is the reconstruction of an experience by intelligence: for example, solving a problem. What is not aesthetic according to Dewey is what is slack or overly rigid. There is nothing in either scientific inquiry or practical action that precludes the presence of aesthetic qualities.
JA N E A D DA M S
Who was Jane Addams?
320
Jane Addams (18601935) was the first woman public intellectual in the United States. She was a close colleague of both John Dewey (18591952) and George Herbert Mead
(18631931). In 1931 Addams was awarded the Nobel Peace Prize for her progressive public activities in beginning the settlement house movement. The settlement movement involved locating places for assisting members of impoverished immigrant communities, directly in their neighborhoods. Addams began the services of Hull House with art appreciation classes and quickly developed a program of education for youth, child care, instruction in domestic skills, and adult education. She was only recovered as a philosopher and feminist in the latetwentieth century. Her main works Famous for founding Hull House in Chicago, Jane Addams won a Nobel Peace Prize for her work helping the include Democracy and Social Ethics impoverished (Art Archive). (1902), Newer Ideals of Peace (1906), Twenty Years at Hull House (1910) and Second Twenty Years at Hull House (1930), The Long Road of Womans Memory (1916), and Peace and Bread in Time of War (1922).
A M ERICA N PH IL OSOPH Y
What are some highlights of Jane Addams life that led her to found Hull House?
Addams father was a mill owner and politician in Cedarville, Illinois. Her mother died when she was two, while giving birth to her ninth child. Addams attended Rockford Seminary (a womens college), failed in medical school, and became depressed for a decade, during which she traveled throughout Europe. Along the way she visited Londons Toynbee Hall, which was a young mens community that helped poor Jewish and Irish immigrants in East London by working within these peoples neighborhoods. Addams resolved to duplicate this plan, and in 1889 she founded Hull House in the Near West Side community of Chicago. Hull House was run and operated by women. Addams had long-term relationships with her cofounder and college friend, Ellen Gates Starr, and, later on, with her colleague Mary Rozet Smith. Addams work at Hull House, and other settlement houses based on it, made her well known; she became a very popular public speaker. She was involved in the founding of other progressive organizations, such as the National Association for the Advancement of Colored People, the American Civil Liberties Union, and the Womens International League for Peace and Freedom. Former President Theodore Roosevelt asked her to second his nomination for the presidency by the Bull Moose Progressive Party in 1912. (Roosevelt had served three years as U.S. president after 1901, and a full term after 1904.) The Progressive Party strongly supported womens rights and suffrage.
321
However, Addams became a target for intense public criticism when she expressed both pacifist and feminist views before World War I. Toward the end of her life, she dedicated herself to world peace and African American civil rights.
G E O R G E H E R B E RT M E A D
Who was George Herbert Mead?
George Herbert Mead (18631931) was a philosopher, social theorist, and reformer whom John Dewey (18591952) described as a seminal mind of the first order. (Dewey brought him to the University of Chicago when he accepted his position there.) Mead had been raised in a New England Puritan community, but in his mature thought he became an empiricist. Meads most important contribution to both pragmatic theories of education and sociology was his idea of symbolic interaction. He offered an explanation of the development of the human mind and self, through the development of language and role playing. Although something of a behaviorist in his insistence on the social nature of individual mental development, Mead also believed that there were different developmental stages of adjustment to the external environment. Mead worked with Dewey in the Chicago Laboratory School and was a friend of Jane Addams (18601935) and a close observer of her work at Hull House.
322
A M ERICA N PH IL OSOPH Y
ead was a philosopher of emergence, in his studies of Darwinian evolution. He proposed that new forms of life change the nature of the past, because after a new form exists, what preceded and led to it needs to be reinterpreted. Mead did not publish while he lived, although his works were prepared by his students to appear posthumously as Mind, Self, and Society (1934).
Santayana retired from Harvard in 1912 and spent the remainder of his life writing and traveling in Europe. His main publications are The Sense of Beauty (1896), Interpretations of Poetry and Religion (1900), The Life of Reason (five volumes, 19051906), Skepticism and Animal Faith (1923), The Realms of Being (four volumes, 19271940), Persons and Places (1944), The Middle Span (1945), and My Host the World (1953). In addition to numerous other books and essays, Santayanas published correspondence to over 350 respondents runs to eight volumes.
323
R A L P H B A RT O N P E R RY
Who was Ralph Barton Perry?
Ralph Barton Perry (18761957) is best known for his theory of value and his realist views. But he received a 1936 Pulitzer Prize for his biography of his mentor and colleague, The Thought and Character of William James (1935). Perry received his Ph.D. from Harvard in 1899 and taught there from 1902 to 1946. His main publications include a 1925 revision of Alfred Webers History of Philosophy, The New Realism (1912), General Theory of Value (1926), Puritanism and Democracy (1944), The Realms of Value (1954), and The Humanity of Man (1956).
324
A M ERICA N PH IL OSOPH Y
C .I . L E W I S
Who was C.I. Lewis?
C.I. Lewis (18831964) was the most Kantian of all the pragmatists, although he did not become a pragmatist until he read Charles Sanders Peirces (18391914) papers, when he was given an office in the library room where they were stored at Harvard. Lewis was born in Stoneharn, Massachusetts. His father was a shoe maker who became barred from employment due to union activism. Lewis attended Harvard as an undergraduate and returned to get his Ph.D. there after teaching in Colorado. He then went through the tenure process at the University of California and became well known for his work in symbolic logic. But he gave up his position as associate professor there to be an assistant professor in the Harvard department of philosophy in 1920, where he remained until 1953, serving twice as chair. Lewis was the most famous philosopher of his generation during the 1940s, but he had become obscure by the 1960s, largely due to the success of his student W.V.O. Quine (19082000). Quines success was largely based on the widespread acceptance of his refutation of the analytic/synthetic distinction, which was the cornerstone of Lewis entire philosophical edifice. Lewis main works are A Survey of Symbolic Logic (1918); Symbolic Logic (1932), which was written with C.H. Lanford; Mind and the World Order (1929); An Analysis of Knowledge and Valuation (1946); and The Ground and Nature of the Right (1965).
What was the analytic/synthetic distinction and why did C.I. Lewis need it?
Analytic truths are true by definition and tell us nothing about the world. Synthetic truths are about the world, but they can turn out to be false. Along with this distinction is the a priori/a posteriori distinction: a priori knowledge is known without, or before, experience, whereas a posteriori knowledge can only be known after, or as a result of, experience. Empiricist philosophers traditionally hold that there are no a priori synthetic truths, and they have tended to assume that what is analytic is also a priori, and what is synthetic is a posteriori.
325
Lewis main philosophical tool, in accounting for both ordinary experience and scientific knowledge, was to distinguish between the a priori and what he called the given. Quite simply, he thought that our knowledge and experience was the result of the interplay between the a priori and the given. There is something brute in our experience that we have no control over, but we make sense of it by projecting a priori principles and categories onto it.
326
A M ERICA N PH IL OSOPH Y
Although Americans are taught that their country is a wonderful melting pot of races, race relations and cultural pluralism prove to be complex issues. Alain Locke was well known for studying their dynamics (iStock).
How did Alain Locke apply pragmatism to issues of race and culture?
Locke was interested in values and valuation, cultural pluralism, and race relations. He argued that each cultural group has a distinct identity, which should not conflict with the citizenship of its members in a wider whole. Thus, African Americans could have the cultural identity(ies) supported by the Harlem Renaissance and remain Americans. This model of identity was the intellectual foundation of Lockes efforts in promoting black culture. But some now view it as an applied pragmatic strategy. Locke believed that black identity was largely the result of economic and political forces and not biology. However, his pragmatic strategy was not to argue this belief directly, but to promote an understanding of race as culturewithin a broader society that emphasized false biological notions of racetoward the goal of eventual racial equality.
P RO C E S S P H I LO S O P HY
What is process philosophy?
Process philosophy was an early twentieth century system of thought that was strongly influenced by Albert Einsteins theory of relativity and other scientific ideas, such as the wave theory of light and sub-atomic physics. The fundamental metaphysical
327
premise of process philosophy is that the basic unit of existence is not a stable thing, such as an atom, but events, or change over time. The two most prominent process philosophers were Alfred North Whitehead (18611947) and Charles Hartshorne (18972000).
328
A M ERICA N PH IL OSOPH Y
What did Alfred North Whitehead think the world was composed of in reality?
According to Whitehead, the most primitive real unit is an actual occasion, which is not any thing or substance that persists in time, but a process, a process of becoming. This process of becoming is related to every other process of becoming, or as Whiteheads commentators have explained, the basic unit of reality is a Leibnizian monad that has windows on every conceivable surface. The entire world is organic and nature is a structure of evolving processes. Reality is process. Moreover, Whitehead believed that his ontology, unlike the scientific ontology of inert objects, allowed for the existence of an evolving God.
329
ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY
What is analytic philosophy?
Analysis is a mental process that breaks down ideas, beliefs, arguments or trains of thought, and systems of thought into their simpler components. Insofar as philosophy is about mental products in its own field and others, all philosophy is analytic. However, in American philosophy departments, and internationally, the term analytic philosophy has come to designate twentieth century mainstream philosophical thinking, as opposed to continental philosophy, pragmatism, and subjects that now fall under new philosophy because they are recent additions to the field.
331
Logical atomism was dependent on truth-functional logic for its explication. In other words, analytic philosophers generally turned to logic as the science par excellence that set the standard for philosophy.
G. E . M O O R E
Who was G.E. Moore?
George Edward Moore (18731958) successfully revived epistemological and metaphysical realism and supported a common sense philosophical method. He spent most of his career at Cambridge University, becoming a professor there in 1925. As an undergraduate, Moore was a member of the Cambridge Apostles, a select intellectual group of Cambridge University undergraduates. He was editor of the top analytic journal, Mind (19211947). Moores main books are Philosophical Studies (1922), Principia Ethica (1903), and Some Main Problems of Philosophy (1953).
332
A NA LY T IC PHIL OSOPH Y
When the Cambridge spy ring was disclosed in 1951, four of its members were former Apostles, and two, who were employed in high government offices, had given the KGB sensitive information. (The Cambridge spy ring consisted of five British young men who attended Cambridge University and were recruited to spy for the Soviet Union during the 1930s. They infiltrated the highest levels of British government and betrayed top secrets to the Soviet Union.)
he had two hands, from which it followed that the external world existed, from which it followed that there was no ground for the skeptics doubt about its existence.
T R U T H - F U N C T I O NA L L O G I C
What is truth-functional logic?
AN D
L O G I C A L AT O M I S M
Truth functional logic preserves logical truth by substituting terms according to the rules of logic. The truth or falsity of a statement can be calculated according to the truth of its parts. For example, if A or not-A (the law of non-contradiction) is a rule, then if A is true, not-A must be false; if A is false, then not-A must be true. Compound sentences are true or false depending only on whether their components are true or false. For example, the sentence It is raining and cold is true if It is raining is true and It is cold is true.
333
Truth functional logic is typically applied according to tables that indicate the truth values of sentences that contain clauses linked by the connectives if, and, not, if-then, and if and only if. The truth or falsity of the whole sentence depends on the truth or falsity of its components, according to the rules of logic that apply to each of the connectives.
B E RT R A N D R U S S E L L
Who was Bertrand Russell?
Arthur William Bertrand Third Earl Russell (18721970), who was known to his friends as Bertie, is hailed as the founder of analytic philosophy, along with G.E. Moore (18731958) and Ludwig Wittgenstein(18891951). He studied and lectured at Cambridge University, losing his position there between 1916 and 1944 because of his pacifist views and activism. He won the Nobel Prize in 1950. His writings on philosophical, political, scientific, and social reform topics are all in beautifully executed prose, which he was said to have been able to compose from the first draft. Russell is now best known for his failed attempt with Alfred North Whitehead (18611947) to reduce mathematics to logic, his theory of descriptions, his theory of types, and his ruling doctrine that the work of philosophy is to analyze propositions (the meanings of sentences) and that the only propositions worthy of such analysis
334
must have constituents with which we are acquainted (have direct knowledge of). Russell was one of the most productive philosophical authors of all time. He published hundreds of articles and essays and scores of books. Among the most noteworthy are On Denoting, Mind (Vol. 14, 1905); Philosophical Essays (1910); The Problems of Philosophy (1912); Principia Mathematica, with Alfred North Whitehead, three volumes (19101913); Why I am Not a Christian (1927); A History of Western Philosophy and Its Connection with Political and Social Circumstances from the Earliest Times to the Present Day (1946); and The Autobiography of Bertrand Russell (19671969).
A NA LY T IC PHIL OSOPH Y
His pacifist activities won Bertrand Russell a Nobel Prize, while as a philosopher he was the most productive author of his day, publishing scores of books (AP).
335
lthough he suffered from depression on and off throughout his life, this did not suppress Russells wit, as the following quotes show:
The whole problem with the world is that fools and fanatics are always so certain of themselves, and wiser people so full of doubts. I would never die for my beliefs because I might be wrong. It has been said that man is a rational animal. All my life I have been searching for evidence which could support this. Aristotle maintained that women have fewer teeth than men; although he was twice married, it never occurred to him to verify this statement by examining his wives mouths.
not members of themselves, or C, itself a member of itself? This question seems valid, but Russell showed that it leads to contradictions: If C is a member of itself then it should not be in D, which is the class of classes that are not members of themselves, but if C is a member of itself, it will be in D. But if C is not a member of itself, then it should be in D, and C is a member of itself. Russells answer was that there is a hierarchy of types of things that restricts what can be said about them. So we can say that Russell is an analytic philosopher, but not that a group of people are an analytic philosopher.
LU D WI G WIT TG E N STE I N
Who was Ludwig Wittgenstein?
Ludwig Wittgenstein (18891951) had two distinct philosophical periods. First, was his ambitious development of logical atomism that was influenced by his teacher Bertrand Russell (18721970), resulting in his writing Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (1921). Second was Wittgensteins original, ordinary language theory of philoso-
336
phy. This was an original insight about ordinary language. Wittgenstein was unquestionably a genius.
A NA LY T IC PHIL OSOPH Y
337
1970)Arthur Schopenhauer (17881860) was another influence on the work although he said at the end of this work: My propositions serve as elucidations in the following way: anyone who understands me eventually recognizes them as nonsensical. At the beginning of the book, Wittgenstein claims that his main purpose is ethical. The Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus consists of seven sets of numbered propositions or statements, which are believed to be about the connection between language and the world. It seems to present an account of the essence of language as expressive of thought. Thought, according to Wittgenstein, is limited to what is factual so that the propositions of language are representations of the world. The propositions of logic, on the other hand, convey no factual informationlogic consists of tautologies. Logic is very useful, but all of its conclusions are true by definition. Wittgenstein believed that a meaningful sentence must have a precise structure that is made up of simple (in Russells language, atomic) sentences or simple names. Atomic sentences are pictures of states of affairs. Working backwards from this picture theory of meaning it would follow that, given the ideal logical language, the world itself has a logical structure. Wittgenstein was to later abandon this view in favor of philosophical activity that consisted of descriptive analysis of ordinary language. But before he did that, the Tractatus had enormous influence on the new twentieth century school of thought known as logical positivism.
OTH E R LO G I C IAN S
Who was Kurt Gdel?
338
Kurt Gdel (19061978) is famous for his theorem about mathematical systems, which appeared in a 1931 article titled On Formally Undecidable Propositions in
Principia Mathematica and Related Systems, originally published in German in the 1931 volume of the journal Monatshefte fr Mathematik (Monthly Journal of Mathematics). According to Gdels Theorem, every formal (mathematical or logical) system is incomplete because there can always be a sentence expressing a truth that cant be proved in the system. To prove his theorem, Gdel invented a method for correlating formulas in logic with positive integers.
A NA LY T IC PHIL OSOPH Y
LO G I CAL P O S I TI V I S M
What is logical positivism?
A new generation of thinkers who were influenced by Bertrand Russell (18721970) and Ludwig Wittgenstein (18891951) created a twentieth century version of Auguste Comtes (17981857) nineteenth century intellectual endorsement of science. The term logical positivism was coined in 1930 by two supporters: E. Kaila and A. Petzll, philosophers who were part of the early movement that logical positivism came to represent. The twentieth century positivists Moritz Schlick (18821936), Rudolf Carnap (18911970), Otto Neurath (18821945), and in England, A.J. Ayer (19101989) were members of what became known as the Vienna Circle.
T H E V I E N NA C I R C L E
Was the Vienna Circle an actual organization?
Yes, it was a discussion group of scientists and philosophers in Vienna, who held meetings from 1922 to 1938. Its members were highly influential in setting the subject matter of future analytic philosophy, ethics, political philosophy, philosophy of science, philosophy of language (excluding ordinary language philosophy), and philosophy of mind.
339
The manifesto of the Circle was Wissenschaftliche Weltauffassung: Der Wiener Kreis (The Scientific Conception of the World: The Vienna Circle) was published in 1929 and translated by Otto Neurath (18821945) in his Empiricism and Sociology (1973). The manifesto proclaims that the scientific world-conception of the Vienna Circle is distinguished essentially by two features. First it is empiricist and positivist: there is knowledge only from experience. Second, the scientific world-conception is marked by the application of a certain method, namely logical analysis. Logical analysis is a way of using symbolic logic to determine whether sentences or their components refer to experience. Many logical positivists were also phenomenalists.
What is phenomenalism?
Not to be confused with phenomenology, phenomenalism is the empiricist doctrine that sense data, or the sensory organs impression of perception, could be used to explain the meaning of sentences about perceptual objects. Some believed that perceptual objects themselves, such as a computer, a desk, or a car, could be reduced to sense data. This last ontological version of phenomenalism would involve a general commitment to philosophical idealism or the doctrine that the only things that are real are mental phenomena.
What is verificationism?
Verificationism is a theory of meaning. The meaning of a statement is its empirical methods of verification that ultimately yield sensory information. For contemporary verificationists such as Michael Dummett (1925) this meant that the truth of sentences must be related to the ways in which they are or can be verified.
340
A NA LY T IC PHIL OSOPH Y
341
Unlike earlier logical positivists, Carnap addressed the problem of inconclusive evidence for actual scientific verification and the meaning of scientific terms. He argued for the use of probability in determining degrees of confirmation in place of absolute verification. Carnaps principle works include The Logical Structure of the World (1928; English translation, 1967), Philosophy and Logical Syntax (1935), Introduction to Semantics (1942), Formalization of Logic (1943), Meaning and Necessity: A Study in Semantics and Modal Logic (1947), and Logical Foundations of Probability (1950).
342
We are like sailors who on the open sea must reconstruct their ship but are never able to start afresh from the bottom. Where a beam is taken away a new one must at once be put there, and for this the rest of the ship is used as support. In this way, by using the old beams and driftwood the ship can be shaped entirely anew, but only by gradual reconstruction. Second, Neurath did not think that phenomenalism could provide a valid foundation for scientific language because sense data are subjective. His alternative was to propose that mathematical physics be used for objective descriptions, a doctrine known as physicalism. Furthermore, language itself could be described in the language of mathematical physics because it is material, constituted by sounds and graphic symbols.
A NA LY T IC PHIL OSOPH Y
What are some other interesting facts about A.J. Ayers life and career?
Ayer was a prominent subject of academic gossip for his womanizing (he was married four times) and for his engagement in fashionable popular culture. There was an overall glamour to his life. Ayers mothers family founded the French Citron car company, and his father worked for the wealthy Rothchild family of bankers. He attended Eton, won a scholarship to Oxford, and served in the SOE (Special Operations Executive) during World War II. Before the war, while on a visit to New York, Ayer made a record with actress Lauren Bacall. He supported the Tottenham Hotspur Football Club and was known to its fans as The Prof.
343
Ayer was also a secular humanist. He was honorary associate of the Rationalist Press Association after 1947, and a successor to evolutionary biologist and humanist Julian Huxley when he became president of the British Humanist Association. In 1965, Ayer was named the first president of the Agnostics Adoption Society. He edited the anthology The Humanist Outlook in 1965. At the peak of his career, Ayer served as a sort of in-house atheist for the British Broadcasting Corporation. He debated the Jesuit philosopher Frederick Copleston (19071994) on the subject of religion. Copleston was the author of the nine-volume History of Philosophy (19461975), so the two were matched in erudition. Ayer (apparently briefly) revised his life-long atheism after a near-death experience in 1989brought on by choking on a piece of smoked salmon. Toward the end of his life, though, he said, What I should have said is that my experiences have weakened, not my belief that there is no life after death, but my inflexible attitude towards that belief.
344
Ayer maintained that the question itself was not meaningful because no possible experience could determine its truth or falsity. Ayers ethical theory was emotivist, that is, ethical judgments were held to be expressions of emotions.
A NA LY T IC PHIL OSOPH Y
O R D I NARY LAN G UA G E P H I LO S O P HY
What is ordinary language philosophy?
First, ordinary language philosophy should be distinguished from philosophy of language, which is a subfield of analytic philosophy. Ordinary language philosophy is an historical episode in analytic philosophy whose practitioners, inspired by Ludwig Wittgenstein (18891951), believed that all of the major problems of philosophy were either pseudo-problems that could be dispelled with reference to ordinary language, or genuine problems that could be solved by investigating how certain words were used. It should be stressed, however, that although ordinary language philosophers focused on how words were used, they were not interested in simply describing common usage. Rather, they were interested in the meanings of words or the concepts named by words; ordinary usage was investigated in order to determine meaning. Indeed, Wittgenstein himself was aware that language, taken superficially, could be bewitching. Furthermore, this determination of meaning seems to have been a reflective, rather than an empirical process. The ordinary language philosophers conducted no surveys; neither did they attempt to determine actual usage by consulting with sociologists or linguists. (This is important, because in the early twenty-first century experimental philosophy proceeds by just such empiricism.) In addition to Wittgenstein, prominent practitioners in the heyday of ordinary language philosophy included the American advocates O.K. Bouwsma (18981978)
345
and Norman Malcolm (19111990), and the British discussants John Wisdom, (19041993), J.L. Austin (19111960), and H.P. Grice (19131988).
What was Ludwig Wittgensteins major insight concerning ordinary language and philosophy?
Wittgensteins (18891951) work in ordinary language philosophy was published posthumously; his lecture notes and notebooks came out as Philosophical Investigations (1953) and The Blue and Brown Books (1948). Wittgensteins interest in ordinary language represented a shift from his earlier interest in an ideal representational or picture theory of language to the ways in which human beings actively use language to go about the business of life. Wittgenstein believed that the multiple uses of language cannot be codified and that key words cannot be neatly defined, but rather that we are engaged in overlapping series of language games. Language games are like other games that are loosely related through family resemblance, even though it is impossible to provide a definition of a game that will cover all of them. Wittgenstein used the simile of family resemblance because if one looks at the members of a large family, while they do not look exactly alike, there may be features that some share. For example, siblings and cousins might have the same hair color, or they might share certain similar facial structures inherited from their parents. What Wittengstein meant in calling language a game was that how we use language is a self-contained system of practices with many implicit rules. Sometimes we cannot even say what the rules are, so Wittgenstein thought it was better not to concentrate on describing the rules, but to pay attention to actual language usage instead.
Words and their meanings might seem like simple concepts on the surface, but Ludwig Wittgenstein maintained that language usage is not easily defined at all. (iStock).
in real life. Such investigation is a kind of philosophical therapy against an occupational tendency to create abstractions and strictly imposed generalizations. Philosophers should turn to language so as to let the fly out of the bottle. This was Wittgensteins metaphor and philosophers still use it when they want to describe solving a problem by changing the framework in which the problem is posed. For example, in letting the fly out of the bottle, one doesnt try to influence the fly directly, but instead changes the angle at which the bottle is held.
A NA LY T IC PHIL OSOPH Y
347
348
You may think its obvious that other people have minds just as you do, but for philosophers this notion is not so easily proven (iStock).
(18891951) influence he began a project of examining different approaches toward philosophical problems. Wisdoms publications in that area include Other Minds (1952), Philosophy and Psychoanalysis (1953), and Paradox and Discovery (1964). Wisdom discursively reflected on why philosophers say and write very strange things, and refuted skepticism about the existence of other minds. Wisdom brought the discussion of the other minds problem into twentieth century analytic contexts by ruling out the possibility of direct knowledge of other minds and at the same time showing why the claim that our knowledge is restricted to momentary sensations does not hold up. Overall, he argued that philosophers have always relied on the use of language and that there are historical precedents in philosophy for deciding when language gets the main subjects of philosophy right, as well as wrong. Wisdom thought that the main subjects of philosophy were categories of being in reality and kinds of statements in language. He held that relevant distinctions within these subjects were implicit in language. He is also the author of Philosophical Papers (1962).
A NA LY T IC PHIL OSOPH Y
349
of utterance, as well as certain rules of cooperation in speech. These rules include: be informative, do not be more informative than required, do not state what you know is false, do not state what you have no evidence for, be relevant, do not be obscure, do not be ambiguous, do not use more words than you must, and observe order. When speakers break one or more of these rules, the result is that what speakers say is not always equivalent to the literal meaning of their words. For example, if a speaker is asked how a play was and responds that the furniture used in the set was very nice, this irrelevance will imply a negative judgment of the play. Grice developed his speech theory with considerable complexity, and it is of interest to logicians and analysts of language. Grice was thus was able to demonstrate the existence of a lot of linguistic structurewith possibilities for neatly implied alternative meanings in contexts of conversation. This was a huge setback to the confidence of ordinary language analysts that meandering investigations of overlapping linguistic practices could yield stable meanings for certain words. Grice showed that meaning depends on context. But on the other hand, Grices work emphasizes the complexity of ordinary language as life practices, similar to self contained games, like baseball, but unlike baseball, capable of adding meaning to the most important events in our existence. Grices writings have been collected and published as Philosophical Grounds of Rationality (1986), Studies in the Ways of Words (1989), and Aspects of Reason (2001).
ANALY TI C ETH I C S
What is analytic ethics?
Analytic ethics is the application of both or either logical positivism and ordinary language analysis to ethics.
350
A NA LY T IC PHIL OSOPH Y
We all have times when we feel conflict within ourselves. In ordinary life, ethics has to do with how we make good versus bad judgments regarding public behavior, whereas morals deals with this conflict on a personal level (iStock).
351
though there are different viewpoints about what is morally right, some of those viewpoints are simply wrong, and then their job is to show how they are wrong.
352
The novelist and feminist essayist Virginia Woolf was part of the Bloomsbury group (AP).
A NA LY T IC PHIL OSOPH Y
he Bloomsbury group was a loose group of friends, the men of which were Cambridge graduates. They met in the evenings for drink and talk at the house of author Virginia Woolfs sister, Vanessa Bell. (The house was in the Bloomsbury district of London, and hence this name.) Its initial members, before 1910, were: the novelists E.M. Forster, Mary MacCarthy, and Virginia Woolf; economist John Maynard Keynes; the novelist, biographer, and critic Lytton Strachey; and the painters Duncan Grant, Vanessa Bell, and Roger Fry. All were close or intimate friends long before they individually became famous. G.E. Moore (18731958) served as an intellectual ideal and mentor to the group. He was particularly revered by the others for his Principia Ethica (1903), and the model of clarity he provided for all intellectual work. Above all, the Bloomsbury members were inspired by Moores idea that art and friendship have intrinsic valuetheyre good in themselves and serve no higher purpose.
A.J. Ayer (19101989) put forth this view in Language, Truth and Logic (1936). A more comprehensive account was given by Charles L. Stevenson (19081979) in Ethics and Language (1944). Stevenson argued that moral judgments do not have cognitive meaning, but rather emotive meaning. He meant that moral judgments are not factual in nature, but are rather emotional reactions to facts, which are sometimes meant to influence others. If the facts or other circumstances changed, so could the moral judgment.
353
354
her philosophy of objectivism. Her most popular novels are We the Living (1936), The Fountainhead (1943), and Atlas Shrugged (1957).
A NA LY T IC PHIL OSOPH Y
In novels like Atlas Shrugged author Ayn Rand put forth her ideas that people should selfishly pursue their own happiness (AP).
What is consequentialism?
Consequentialism is the twentieth century version of nineteenth century utilitarianism. The utilitarian moral system held that we should act so that the greatest pleasure
355
or happiness for the greatest number results, with everyone counting for one and no one counting for more than one. G.E. Moores (18731958) ideal utilitarianism specified that the goods we should seek as the result of our actions are aesthetic experiences and relations of friendship. Consequentialism is a more general form of utilitarianism that holds that we should act so as to bring about the best consequences, or act to maximize the results. Contemporary consequentialists often speak of preference-satisfaction as the ultimate consequence that has intrinsic value. (Preference satisfaction is getting what one wants.) There is also discussion about the distribution of consequences, whether it is better that all involved get equal shares or whether it is sufficient if the total good or average good is increased. Act consequentialism specifies that we should do the action that has the best consequences, and rule consequentialism specifies that we should do the action that is an instance of the rule that has the best consequences. All of these issues and others have been discussed in J.J.C. Smart (1920) and Bernard Williams (19292003) Utilitarianism: For and Against (1973) and Samuel Schefflers (1951) The Rejection of Consequentialism (1994). There have also been attempts to relate consequentialism to ordinary language philosophy, most notably by R. Hare (19192002).
356
Anscombe is also famous for her defense of Thomas Aquinas (c. 12251274) doctrine of double effect (DDE). According to DDE, an action is morally permissible if it
A NA LY T IC PHIL OSOPH Y
In addition, applied ethics can be more critical as it applies theoretical moral systems and moral theories to practices and fields outside of philosophy. Existing rules and behavior in a given field may be theoretically justified or criticized by philosophical ethicists. In some cases, new moral directions may emerge. Environmental ethics is a good example of the theoretical dimension of applied ethics.
has known bad consequences but it is not the intention or goal of the person performing the action to bring about those consequences. In Jesuit moral reasoning about performing craniotomies (operations to crush a babys skull so that the baby can be extracted to save its mothers life), DDE has been used. If it is not the obstetricians goal to kill the baby but merely to extract it, craniotomies are deemed permissible. Anscombe provided this example: say she meets her mortal enemy on a cliff. If her enemy falls off because she accidentally falls against him, she is blameless, even though the unintended effect of the enemys death is welcome to her (after the fact). Others have criticized the ways in which consequentialism seems to ignore issues of justice in cases where an unjust act or even a human sacrifice might serve to maximize benefits for others.
357
that six others who need organ transplants may live. But the rule followed in the sacrifice of the healthy patient would undermine confidence in doctors, and in the long term more harm than good would result from killing the healthy patient. Others have pointed out the obvious problem of calculating consequences in the future. Another strong objection to consequentialism, voiced by Bernard Williams (19192003), is that the focus on results with everyone counting the same undermines the integrity of an agent by ignoring the importance of personal projects to that agent. In a famous example, Williams imagines that a traveler is asked to kill one Indian to save nine more from being shot. He argues that the consequentialist approach violates the importance to the traveler of his own moral identity as someone who does not kill others.
ANALY T I C P O LITI CA L P H I LO S O P HY
What is distinctive about analytical political philosophy?
Twentieth century analytic political philosophers have for the most part supported liberal and egalitarian values, and they have done so in formal writing that is in itself apolitical.
358
Others with positive liberties may not be able to fully exercise them due to economic or social limitations. Berlin argued that, largely due to the Romantic and German idealist tradition, political theorists had been preoccupied with positive liberties as effects of particular forms of government. He believed that the idea of positive liberty was coopted by both German national socialism and communism. In the case of communism, the goal of liberty became identical to the goal of state control in the name of collective rationality. For the Nazis, it was the destiny of Germany and its master race that became an overriding value affecting individual lives.
A NA LY T IC PHIL OSOPH Y
Isaiah Berlin was famous for his work on ideals of liberty in democratic societies (AP).
Berlin was an advocate of negative liberty in the tradition of John Stuart Mill (18061873), which emphasized the importance of minimal government constraint. In other words, he did not think government was a viable source of values or projects for individual life plans because when government did assume that function it was likely to become totalitarian and repressive.
359
and grew up near Ludwig Wittgenstein (18891951) in Vienna, Austria, but not under wealthy circumstances. He had to leave Germany in the late 1930s, and after teaching in New Zealand he was a professor at the London School of Economics. Popper is as famous for his philosophy of science as for his political thought, which he developed in The Open Society and Its Enemies (1945, fifth revised edition, 1965).
A NA LY T IC PHIL OSOPH Y
o, Rawls (19212002) was not an advocate of total distributive justice or the ideal that all members of society should receive equal amounts of everything. But he applied the standard of fairness to inequalities through his difference principle: inequalities must be of the greatest benefit to the least-advantaged members of society.
conceptions of justice. Rawls conception of justice was that it can be understood as fairness. On that model he proposed that a society would be just if its fundamental institutions were just, which would entail equal access to official positions. As a way of determining how fundamental institutions could be just, Rawls proposed a thought experiment that posited an original position. In the original position, the framers of just institutions would do their work behind a veil of ignorance. This veil of ignorance would prevent them from knowing their own positions or interests in the society whose institutions they were framing. Rawls wrote: No one knows his place in society, his class position or social status, nor does anyone know his fortune in the distribution of natural assets and abilities, his intelligence, strength, and the like. I shall even assume that the parties do not know their conceptions of the good or their special psychological propensities. The principles of justice are chosen behind a veil of ignorance. Rawls thought experiment guarantees a hypothetical condition of disinterestedness on the part of original framers. This posits them as Kantian rational agents, who because they are autonomous or self-ruling, can and should make choices about what is most important in their lives. That they do not know their personal interests but nonetheless frame institutions that will affect everyones personal interests is fair in the same way as having one child cut a piece of cake and the second child choose the piece she wants. The premise that individuals with interests in society consent to the basic institutions echoes the necessity for the consent of those governed in social contract theory. Social contract theory is also based on the premise that government must justify itself as beneficial to those governed. Rawls original position promises a test of even greater benefits than allowed by original social contract theorists, such as John Locke (16321704), who assumed that only property owners would be represented in government. Rawls model permits us to ask whether anyone in society who could be represented behind the veil of ignorance would choose a given state of state of affairs. If not, then that state of affairs is not just or fair.
361
362
A NA LY T IC PHIL OSOPH Y
363
E P I ST E M O LO GY A N D M ETA P HYS I C S AF T E R LO G I CA L P O S I TI V I S M
What was new in metaphysics and epistemology after logical positivism?
Metaphysics and epistemology made a new empirical start that was thoroughly informed by science. P.F. Strawson (19192006) defended a common sense metaphysics, and, like Wilfred Sellars (19121989), he developed the idea of a common perspective that was opposed to science. Strawson did much to reclaim for philosophy a common sense approach to the world, which the logical positivists would have thought was meaningless, because it was not about science. Nelson Goodman (19061998) resurrected the perennial problem of inductionreasoning that begins with experience and builds toward knowledge. W.V.O. Quine (19082000) uniquely redirected the course of twentieth century philosophy by combining pragmatist insights with a rigorous philosophical method. Also, perhaps partly as a result of Quines work, Hilary Putnam (1926) reinterpreted pragmatist epistemology by applying its insights to questions of truth in the sciences.
364
A NA LY T IC PHIL OSOPH Y
hose analytic twentieth century philosophers who explicated a manifest image of the world sought to reconcile the common view of the world with the scientific view. The term was coined by Wilfred Sellars (19121989).
What is grue?
Nelson Goodman (19061998) supposed that all emeralds before time T, which is the present, are green. But if this is true, then G is also true: Emeralds before time T are green or emeralds after time T are blue. The reason it is true that emeralds after time T are either green or blue is that the time after time T is the future and we do not know what the future will hold for emeraldsor for anything else. G defines the predicate grue (a term Goodman made up) as a quality of emeralds: All of the emeralds that qualify as grue could be blue after time T. Nevertheless, Goodman maintained that we would prefer to call them blue after time T. He believed this showed that confirmation cannot be a purely logical or syntactic process, but that it reflects our linguistic preferences, which go beyond what we actually know.
W. V. O . Q U I N E
Who was W.V.O. Quine?
W.V.O. (Willard Van Orman) Quine (19082000) represents the apogee of twentieth century scientific philosophy; in many ways he combined the best of logical positivism, pragmatism, and scientific empiricism. He was born in Akron, Ohio, and studied at Oberlin College and then Harvard. He earned his Ph.D. in 1932 and then became a Harvard Fellow. This allowed four years for research and travel before beginning his 50-year Harvard teaching career in 1936.
365
His influence is considered monumental, and he has been highly regarded, even revered, as a person. Quines main books are Word and Object (1964), The Ways of Paradox, and Other Essays (1976), Ontological Relativity (1977), From a Logical Point of View: Nine Logico-Philosophical Essays (1980), From Stimulus to Science (1998), Theories and Things (1986), Pursuit of Truth (1992), and Quiddities: An Intermittently Philosophical Dictionary (1989).
Quine did not think that the analyticsynthetic distinction could be defended, because he did not think that analytic could be defined in a non-circular way. He had a holistic view of knowledge, likening the whole of all of our theories to a web. He believed that assertions of existence were relative to specific theories, and he thought that philosophical epistemology should be naturalized. By this he meant that philosophical epistemology should be consistent with standards for scientific truth.
366
A NA LY T IC PHIL OSOPH Y
o, and many have been grateful for this. As a philosopher, Quine has been criticized for his ivory tower view of the field and his claim that philosophers are not particularly qualified for helping to get society on an even keel. However, in real life, Quine was very involved in resisting Nazism. After he visited Germany as a Harvard fellow in the 1930s and met the logical positivists of the Vienna Circle, he reacted against the Nazis incursions into philosophy (one of which was an avowedly racist mathematical journal, Deutsche Mathematik) by volunteering for the U.S. Navy. After he returned to teaching at Harvard, he organized symposia and talks for members of the Vienna Circle from 1938 to 1941, particularly for Rudolf Carnap (18911970), although Carnap was later hired by the University of Chicago. Quine also helped Alfred Tarski (19021983) gain employment at City College in New York.
367
alled by professional philosophers the indispensability argument for mathematical realism, it basically asserted the existence of mathematical entities. W.V.O. Quine (19082000) and Hilary Putnam (1926) argued that we have to commit to the existence of, or have ontological commitments to, things that are indispensable for the best science. Mathematical entities qualify as indispensable. Therefore, we must commit to their existence.
independently of each other. Quine thought that all of our scientific and lay theories were interconnected with the most general and abstract truthsfor example, the truths of arithmeticin the center of a web. Toward the periphery of this web were more specific generalizations and factual claims that were easier to give up in the face of an experience that contradicted them. It is this aspect of Quines thought that places him in the tradition of pragmatism.
H I L A RY P U T M A N
Who was Hilary Putnam?
Hilary Putnams (1926) extraordinarily productive career has encompassed metaphysics, epistemology, philosophy of mathematics, philosophy of mind, and philosophy of language. He began to flourish in the philosophical generation after W.V.O. Quine (19082000), becoming a professor at Harvard in 1965. He collaborated with Quine on the ontology of mathematical entities and agreed with him about the analytic-synthetic distinction. In collaboration with his wife, Ruth Anna Jacobs, he helped revive late-twentieth century interest in the work of John Dewey (18591952). Putnam has also revived interest in William James (18421910) work. Putnams major publications include Mathematics, Matter and Method, Philosophical Papers, vol. 1. (1975), 2nd ed. (1985); Mind, Language and Reality, Philosophical Papers, vol. 2 (1975); Meaning and the Moral Sciences (1978); Reason, Truth, and History (1981); Realism and Reason, Philosophical Papers, vol. 3 (1983); The Many Faces of Realism (1987); Representation and Reality (1988); Renewing Philosophy (1992); and Pragmatism: An Open Question (1995).
How did Hilary Putnam agree with W.V.O. Quine on the analytic-synthetic distinction?
368
In 1957 Putnam published the article The Analytic and the Synthetic, in the anthology Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, edited by H. Feigl and G. Maxwell
(1962), in which he showed how the history of the definitions of kinetic energy made it impossible to divide statements about kinetic energy into analytic and empirical, or synthetic ones.
A NA LY T IC PHIL OSOPH Y
P H I LO S O P HY O F S C I E N C E
What happened in analytic philosophy of science over the course of the twentieth century?
The twentieth century was an extraordinary period of conceptual upheaval in how science was regarded. There was a rejection of hard-core logical positivism, beginning with Hans Reichenbach (18911953). Just as metaphysics and epistemology drew closer to the actual sciences, philosophy of science itself began to look more humanistic as traditional inductive confidence in objective facts was first dislodged by Karl Popper (19021994). Thomas S. Kuhn (19221996) then inverted the relationship between facts and theories with his notion of a paradigm and scientific revolutions. Over the same time period, any lingering hopes in vitalism or some non-objective life force were put to rest by James D. Watson and Francis Cricks discovery of the double helix structure of DNA. However, the mapping of the human genome at the turn of the twenty-first century did provoke more nuanced views on biological determinism, opening the possibility of a new philosophy of science of biology.
369
at Los Angeles. His main works include Experience and Prediction (1938), The Theory of Probability (19391949), and the posthumous The Direction of Time (1956).
How did ideas about life change when it came to the philosophy of science?
Many notions of a mysterious vitalism, or life force, at the heart of the reproduction of living beings were exchanged for materialist (physical) accounts after James Watson and Francis Crick discovered the double helix in 1953. Watson and Cricks discovery of the structure of DNA took the mystery out of the idea of life because it could account for the reproduction of genetic material in purely chemical terms. The double helix was a three-dimensional model of the twisted-ladder structure of deoxyribonucleic acid (DNA), which showed how sequences of acids and bases would replicate themselves through chemical reactions. Watson and Cricks discovery paved the way for gene-based studies in heredity, culminating in the mapping of the human genome (totality of genes) by the early twenty-first century.
40 years. His The Structure of Science (1961) is probably the last important logical positivist account of scientific investigation. Nagel extended the principles of the covering law model, whereby explanation is based on a generalization that has been inductively built up, for the social sciences. He argued that although historical events are unique and non-recurring, historical explanation implies that such events would happen again, given the same conditions and proven generalizations.
A NA LY T IC PHIL OSOPH Y
Karl Popper claimed that hypotheses can never be completely confirmed because we cant know what the future will hold with certainty (AP).
371
What is the story about Karl Popper and Ludwig Wittgensteins poker?
itnesses disagree, but the most neutral account is that there was a meeting of the Moral Sciences Club in Room H3 at Kings College, Cambridge, on October 25, 1946. Bertrand Russell (18721970) presided, and Karl Popper (19021994) came to give a critical paper on Ludwig Wittgensteins (18891951) language game theory of truth and how to do philosophy. For one thing, Popper thought that there were moral rules.
At some point, Wittgenstein picked up a poker from the fireplace. He either did this to make a point or out of anger; stories differ. When Wittgenstein asked Popper what the example of a moral rule was, Popper is said to have replied, Not to threaten visiting lecturers with pokers. Bertrand Russell, who was by then alienated from Wittgenstein, may or may not have interceded and told them to calm down. A very entertaining book has been written about this episode and the lives and times of Popper and Wittgenstein by British Broadcasting Corporation journalists David Edmonds and John Eidinow: Wittgensteins Poker (2001).
Poppers notion of falsification required that one falsifying instance either lead to the rejection of the original hypothesis, or more likely, to a reexamination of initial conditions. For example, if the hypothesis is that water freezes at 32 degrees Fahrenheit and a body of water does not freeze at that temperature, the rule or hypothesis that water freezes at that temperature is unlikely to be discarded. Rather, the thermometer may need to be checked, as well as the chemical composition of the liquid presumed to be water.
372
intellectual communities, because he showed how science proceeds by quantum leaps when new theories overthrow old theories. After Kuhn became very famous and attended a conference on his work, where everyone used his term paradigm almost as loosely as they do today, he is reported to have told someone, I am not a Kuhnian.
A NA LY T IC PHIL OSOPH Y
373
za Lakatos de Cskszentsimon (18901967) was a Hungarian general during World War II, as well as prime minister of Hungary from August to October of 1944. In August 1944, Lakatos and Mikls Horthy overthrew the German government of Hungary with one tank. While in power, they prevented the deportation of Jews. The Germans retaliated by kidnapping Horthys son. Horthy surrendered and Lakatos stepped down. When the war was over, Lakatos immigrated to Australia. Imre adopted Lakatos name because he found his personal courage in the service of freedom very inspirational.
State University, but then was imprisoned for revisionism from 1950 to 1953 for ideas that reinterpreted Marxist doctrine in a way that Marxist authorities considered to be undermining to their official views. He then fled Hungary after the 1956 Soviet invasion. Lakatos earned his doctorate at Cambridge University in 1961 and lectured at the London School of Economics. Lakatos major works include Proofs and Refutations (1976), which is based on his doctoral dissertation, The Methodology of Scientific Research Programs: Philosophical Papers Volume 1, and Mathematics, Science and Epistemology: Philosophical Papers Volume 2 (1978).
How did Imre Lakatos research program reconcile Popper and Kuhns work?
Lakatos (19221974) described a scientific method to both allow for progress and explain how science had developed. Instead of talking about theories, he introduced the notion of a research program, which consisted of both theories and accepted research practices in a given field. Every research program has a core, or protective belt, of claims that could not be falsified. Degenerating research programs have growing protective belts and fail to predict new facts or create new projects for discovery; they survive by adding ad hoc hypotheses. Progressive research programs are able to support new projects of discovery that
374
do not produce vast amounts of falsifying data requiring revision of the core; they do not significantly rely on ad hoc hypotheses. The way that Lakatos reconciled the discrepancy between Popper and Kuhns account of science was to shift ground from the static relationship between facts and theories to the dynamic nature of scientific practice. Poppers view was that scientific truth changes when theories are falsified, whereas Kuhn thought that theories were not falsified so much as overthrown. Lakatos made scientific practice, rather than beliefs about the truth of theories, his subject.
A NA LY T IC PHIL OSOPH Y
375
P H I LO S O P HY O F M I N D A N D P H I LO S O P HY O F LA N G UA G E
What is the connection between philosophy of mind and philosophy of language in analytic philosophy?
Their development has been intertwined since the end of the behaviorist explanation of language learning. The new field of cognitive science, which arose from Noam Chomskys (1929) philosophical treatment of linguistics that disproved behaviorism, shows how philosophy of language is connected to philosophy of mind. When Chomsky proved that language learning required innate linguistic capacities, the whole tabula rasa or blank slate theory of mind came tumbling down.
What is behaviorism?
Propounded by psychologists Ivan Pavlov (18591936) and John Broadus (J.B.) Watson (18781958) and streamlined by Burhus Frederick (B.F.) Skinner (19041990), behaviorism was the thesis that introspection had no use for a science of mind. Behavior is modified by its consequences in ways that can be described without any recourse to the mind in terms of intentions, beliefs, or prior knowledge. Human psychology was no more than behavior that could observed in the laboratory, without considering that behavior from the point of view of the subject who was behaving. Learning is conditioning, a series of automatic responses to repetitive rewards and punishment. Watson propounded the theory of behaviorism in his book Behaviorism (1925). Noam Chomskys (1929) review of Skinners 1959 classic tome Verbal Behavior is taken to have demolished Skinners behaviorist theory of language learning, and behaviorism more generally. This is important to philosophy in two ways. First it restores the importance of how things seem or are experienced by a human subject. Second, it allows for speculation and analysis of how what is going on in the subjects mind is organized and processed in the brain.
376
Psychologist Ivan Pavlov helped show that peoples behaviors can be modified over time (Art Archive).
N OAM C H O M S KY
Who is Noam Chomsky?
Avram Noam Chomsky (1928) is an American philosopher of linguistics and one of the most widely influential critics of contemporary politics over the twentieth century and beyond. Now a professor emeritus of linguistics at the Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Chomsky is recognized as an important founder of cognitive science in linguistics, psychology, and philosophy of mind, as well as computer science. His major publications that are relevant to philosophy of language and mind include: Syntactic Structures (1957), Cartesian Linguistics (1966), Current Issues in Linguistic Theory (1964), Aspects of the Theory of Syntax (1965), The Sound Pattern of English (with Morris Hall; 1968), Language and Mind (1968), Studies on Semantics in Generative Grammar (1972), The Logical Structure of Linguistic Theory (1975), Reflections on Language (1975), Essays on Form and Interpretation (1977), Rules and Representations (1980), Language and the Study of Mind (1982), Modular Approaches to the Study of the Mind (1984), Knowledge of Language: Its Nature, Origin, and Use (1986), (Barriers Linguistic Inquiry Monograph Thirteen) (1986), Language and Thought (1993), The Minimalist Program (1998), On Language (1998), and New Horizons in the Study of Language and Mind (2000).
A NA LY T IC PHIL OSOPH Y
377
Whether the mind is equated with the physical brain or held to be closely connected to it, analytic philosophers of mind have been united in a materialist view since Gilbert Ryle (19001976) wrote The Concept of Mind (1949).
Noam Chomsky is a brilliant linguist who developed a Universal Grammar that limited possible languages and showed that the human mind can be studied like a natural phenomenon (AP).
J E R RY F O D O R
Who is Jerry Fodor?
378
Jerry Alan Fodor (1935), a philosopher of cognitive science at Rutgers University, is perhaps best known for his modular theory of mind and his concept of the lan-
guage of thought. Fodors books include: Psychological Explanation (1968), The Language of Thought (1975), Representations: Essays on the Foundations of Cognitive Science (1979), The Modularity of Mind: An Essay on Faculty Psychology (1983), Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind (1987), A Theory of Content and Other Essays (1990) The Elm and the Expert, Mentalese and Its Semantics (1994), Concepts: Where Cognitive Science Went Wrong (1998), In Critical Condition (1998), The Mind Doesnt Work that Way: The Scope and Limits of Computational Psychology (2000), and Hume Variations (2003). Fodor also writes about opera for the London Review of Books. His writing style is uniquely witty and peppered with joyful mockery, as well as homespun analogies and references.
A NA LY T IC PHIL OSOPH Y
379
Nothing is known about how the structure of our minds depends on the structure of our brains. Nobody even knows which brain structures it is that our cognitive capacities depend on. Unlike our minds, our brains are, by any gross measure, very like those of apes. So it looks as though relatively small alterations of brain structure must have produced very large behavioural discontinuities in the transition from the ancestral apes to us. If thats right, then you dont have to assume that cognitive complexity is shaped by the gradual action of Darwinian selection on prehuman behavioural phenotypes. In other words, Fodor claims that it might be unnecessary to posit specific environmental conditions, or even a progression of adaptive changes, in order to account for the complexity of the human mind. For all we know, one small mutation might have made all the important mental difference between apes and us.
Thus, having a belief is being in a computational relation to a representation, as is having a desire. Every primitive concept in thought has a neural symbol in the brain. The end result of this in behavior is that the representation that is a belief causes an individual to behave as if it were true, whereas the representation that is a desire causes the individual to behave to make it true.
that operate according to different causal principles than our own. Indeed, Hilary Putnam (1926) himself later rejected functionalism on the grounds that beliefs could not be computational states because their content was determined by external facts, and beliefs were also part of a whole system of knowledge. At the same time as Paul Kripke (1940) and Keith Donnellan (1931), he developed a new causal or direct theory of meaning, which was published in The Meaning of Meaning (1975).
A NA LY T IC PHIL OSOPH Y
Thomas Nagel criticized reductionist views of the human mind with his famous article What Is It Like to Be a Bat? (AP).
381
After long and careful deliberation, Nagel decided to liberate the spider. He carefully removed it from the urinal with a paper towel and placed it in a corner of the room. At first the spider did not move, and Nagel assumed it was getting its bearings. He left town over a holiday weekend, and when he returned the poor spider had still not moved. It was quite dry and quite dead. Nagel recounts this episode in The View from Nowhere (1986). His implication seems to be that even the greatest compassion and best intentions may miss their objective, due to a lack of understanding of the circumstances of another.
Nagels main motivations for holding out for the irreducibility of subjective experience are both moral and epistemological. He has shown that the whole of scientific investigation proceeds to increasing points of objectivity toward an ideal view from nowhere, whereas concrete experience is always someones view from somewhere. Books by Nagel include: The Possibility of Altruism (1970), Mortal Questions (1979), and The View from Nowhere (1986). Nagels short introduction to philosophy, What Does It All Mean? (1987), is very accessible.
382
Principal publications by Paul Churchland include Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind (1979), Eliminative Materialism and the Propositional Attitudes (published in the Journal of Philosophy in 1981), and The Engine of Reason, the Seat of the Soul (1996); both Paul and Patricia penned On the Contrary (1998).
A NA LY T IC PHIL OSOPH Y
Alan Turing was a British cryptologist and mathematician who is credited with founding modern computer science (Art Archive).
383
Adherents to a computational theory of mind, in response to Searles position, would probably claim that unless we go back to a mysterious ghost in the machine, the behavior of the person locked in the room is exactly what is meant by understanding Chinese. As to who is right in this argument, no one knows for sure. As Jerry Fodor (1935) noted, we, meaning philosophers of mind, do not yet have an adequate theory of mind. If you think you do, then try explaining exactly how your desire to raise your right arm results in that arm going up.
highly influential in philosophy of mind discussions, in part as a result of John Searles (1932) treatment of it.
384
NEW PHILOSOPHY
How can there be new philosophy?
Western philosophy began during the seventh century B.C.E., so its a good question how there can be anything new in the field. Toward the end of the twentieth century, philosophy began a revitalization by adding fields and reconfiguring old problems. Some of the subjects added had originated in philosophy, developed as other disciplines, and then returned to philosophy so that philosophers could sort out the real intellectual issues. Feminism, environmentalism, and to some extent studies of race all fall under this category, as does cognitive science and new philosophies of psychology and biology. Post-structuralism, or deconstructionism, which is also known as postmodern philosophy, always was considered philosophy in Europe, but it has only recently been recognized as such at philosophy departments in American universities. Socalled other philosophies from Latin America, Asia, and Africa have also begun to achieve recognition in the United States. There has been a revival of pragmatism, too. Brand new on the horizon is experimental philosophy. There is, in addition, a new philosophy of biology, philosophy of film and television, philosophy of technology, and philosophy for children, not to mention the new mysterianism.
Which of these new philosophies are fads and which will last?
The history of philosophy teaches that the focus of a generation or two can slip into obscurity as new methods and subjects catch attention. So it is impossible to predict which philosophers and books will be read 100, 50, or even 20 years from now. In one way or another, the ideas and writers considered in this chapter signal the end of philosophy via its dissolution into literature, cultural criticism, or empirical science. But philosophy has endured for over 2,000 years, so news of its death may be premature at this point. It also remains to be seen whether these new strains of thought
385
his is, of course, not a matter of the age of philosophers. The old tradition remains robust, and its practitioners have repudiated each of these new philosophies as not real philosophy. Still, as their practitioners secure posts in philosophy departments, which they increasingly do, that dismissal becomes untenable. If someone who has been trained by philosophers publishes work in philosophy journals or books, is hired to teach philosophy, and identifies as a philosopher, that person is as much a philosopher as the bird that waddles, quacks, and swims is a duck! The point is that philosophers customarily disagree and repudiate each others thoughts when they are among friends. So one would expect no less than this kind of reaction to the new philosophies who have diverged from the mainstream.
will themselves become entrenched in ways that are distinctly philosophical according to the old tradition, or whether the old tradition will just sail on grandly, oblivious of current distractions.
P O STM O D E R N P H I LO S O P HY
What world facts inform postmodernism?
The term postmodern came from the field of architecture. Meaning after modern, it is a phrase that connotes, sometimes ironically, borrowing from the past in irreverent ways. Postmodern philosophy arose after major historical changes: the different scientific world views represented by Albert Einsteins theories of relativity and sub-atomic physics; the enormous destructive power of twentieth century warfare; the liberation of former colonies, as well as women and nonwhites in Europe and the United States; the economic, political, and social conditions of post-colonialism; and a breakdown in
386
traditional social institutions such as the nuclear family, changes in womens roles, global capitalism, new economic inequalities, and environmental crises.
JA C Q U E S D E R R I DA
AN D
D E C O N STRU CTI O N I S M
387
(1962, 1989), Of Spirit: Heidegger and the Question (1989), and The Gift of Death (1995). Derrida is most famous for Of Grammatology (1972).
What is deconstructionism?
Deconstructionism is a method for interpreting texts (the term for written works used by deconstructionists) that is based on the premise that the meaning of texts depends as much on the writers background historical conditions and those of the reader, as it does on what is in the text itself.
388
erridas contemporary Michel Foucault (19261984), who many have regarded as a structuralist, accused him of practicing a terrorism of obscurantism. Foucault meant that those who could not understand Derrida (that is, most of his philosophical contemporaries) were attacked by Derrida as idiots. American philosophers such as Noam Chomsky (1929), John Searle (1932), and Richard Rorty (19312007) have mocked and dismissed Derrida. Searle referred to the deliberate obscurantism of the prose, the wildly exaggerated claims, and the constant striving to give the appearance of profundity by making claims that seem paradoxical, but under analysis often turn out to be silly or trivial. Chomsky thought that Derridas work was typical of the local eccentric tradition of Parisian intellectuals. Without it being an explicit issue for them, Chomsky and Searle assume that meaning itself is stable and their theoretical work proceeds on that basis. However, Rorty, who has claimed that it might be impossible to understand Derridas metaphysics, has a view similar to Derridas about the false pretensions to truth that philosophers entertain.
de Saussures (18571913) structuralist view that there is a system of meaning constituted by speech, for which the written word is somewhat secondary, if not unnecessarythat earned Derrida the label poststructuralist, beginning in 1968. Derrida criticized the structuralist tradition as moving from center to center in futility.
R I C H A R D R O RT Y
Who was Richard Rorty?
Richard McKay Rorty (19312007) was probably the most widely read contemporary American philosopher who is not considered to be doing philosophy by analytic and empirical philosophers. He taught at Wellesley, Princeton, the University of Virginia, and Stanford. Rorty began as an analytic philosopher, arguing in favor of eliminative materialism, but with Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (1979) he began in the late 1970s to criticize analytic philosophy from a pragmatic perspective that drew on Continental thought. As a neo-pragmatist, Rorty believed that most philosophical problems are illusions caused by language, that truth is a somewhat arbitrary and relative ideal, and that philosophy is just a literary genre. His main writings include Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, Consequences of Pragmatism (1982), Philosophy in History (1985), Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity (1989), Objectivity, Relativism and Truth: Philo-
389
sophical Papers I (1991), Essays on Heidegger and Others: Philosophical Papers II (1991), Achieving Our Country: Leftist Thought in Twentieth Century America (1998), Truth and Progress: Philosophical Papers III (1998), Philosophy and Social Hope, (2000), Against Bosses, Against Oligarchies: A Conversation with Richard Rorty (2002), The Future of Religion with Gianni Vattimo (2005), and Philosophy as Cultural Politics: Philosophical Papers IV (2007).
Rorty (19312007) criticized the idea that all we know are ideas that represent the world, or representationalism; he also challenged the special intellectual role of philosophers. He thought that true is just an honorific term used within linguistic and knowledge communities to mean justified to the hilt. Rorty called this epistemological position liberal ironism because it rested on ideals of human freedom. He thought that commitment alone is adequate justification for belief. This view led Rorty into relativism.
Richard Rorty believed that most philosophical problems are illusions caused by language and that truth is an arbitrary ideal (AP).
J RG E N HAB E RMAS
Who is Jrgen Habermas?
Jrgen Habermas (1929) is a German philosopher and social theorist who combines the critical theory of the Frankfurt School with American pragmatism. With this combination he is postmodern in his emphasis on public speech and dialogue as a political way of life. His engagements with contemporary thinkersfrom Jacques Derrida (1930
390
orty (19312007) practiced a highly sophisticated relativism that allowed him to present a position that his audience would agree with, and at the same time show how that position could be plausibly contested by those who held a very different position that was unacceptable to him and his audience. Concerning fundamentalist religious beliefs, for example, he taught views opposed to them with apparent strong commitment, and at the same time tried to show how his perspective was deeply offensive and even counter-productive in changing the minds of those who held those beliefs.
2004) to John Rawls (19212002) to Pope Benedict XVI (when he was Cardinal Ratzinger)exemplify his theory. However, it should be noted that unlike most avowed postmodern philosophers, Habermas defends Enlightenment democratic values. Habermas major works include The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere (1962), Theory and Practice (1963), On the Logic of the Social Sciences (1967), Knowledge and Human Interest (1967), Toward a Rational Society (1967), Technology and Science as Ideology (1968), The Theory of Communicative Action (1981), On the Pragmatics of Communication (1992), The Postnational Constellation (1998), Old Europe, New Europe, Core Europe (2005), The Divided West (2006), and with Joseph Ratzinger The Dialectics of Secularization (2007).
391
M O R E F R E N C H P O STM O D E R N P H I LO S O P H E R S
Who was Jean Baudrillard?
Jean Baudrillard (1929) is a social theorist who writes about the absence of the kind of educated public discourse described by Jrgen Habermas (1929) in pessimistic but elegant and evocative prose. He is, like Richard Rorty (19312007), a very readable postmodernist, but less sanguine. Baudrillards thought on terrorism in In the Shadow of the Silent Majority (1982) and The Spirit of Terrorism: And Requiem for the Twin Towers (2002) identifies it as a media-manipulating appropriation of public attention in a culture where only the spectacle is taken seriously. This is not a frivolous view insofar as it is based on a thorough-going analysis of contemporary life as in large part virtual, made up of simulacra of previous forms of human existence.
392
An example of this would be the way that newly constructed old towns are simulacra of historical places, and American pizza is a simulacrum of Italian food. This is
apparently not just a question of things lacking authenticity, according to Baudrillard, but of a mass preference for virtuality instead of reality. Thus in The Gulf War Did Not Take Place (1991) he describes how experiences of the first Gulf War, even and especially for the troops, were mediated by its representation on television, radio, and other media forms, according to externally determined scripts that only captured bits and pieces of the actual experience.
393
individuals creating their own news outlets through blogging, rather than people all relying on the same few sources for information. Progressive trends could be identified as micropolitics, schizoanalysis, and becoming-woman.
394
illes Deleuze (19251995) and Pierre-Flix Guatarri (19301992) took pride in using new terms that they did not define, but which they thought readers would understand. Mutant universes of value seems to refer to new systems of value that are unconventional and popular. Examples in our time would be interests in vampires in entertainment, the growing importance of electronic communication, and the change in household pets from mere pets to members of the families with whom they live. The importance of townhall meetings in the United States would be an example of micropolitics. Schizoanalysis, which suggests contradictory meanings, was used to refer to Deleuze and Guatarris project of getting rid of the idea of the Freudian idea of the unconscious as a way of explaining human behavior. Becoming-woman refers to the fact that contemporary women are actively involved in defining their own social roles.
The question left by Sokals work is this: Does such political condemnation of an entire field of thought respect hard-won principles of academic freedom? And if standards of political worthiness are being applied to postmodernism, is that application fair, given over two and half centuries of philosophy that has been largely irrelevant to its immediate political contexts? While its true that much postmodern work was sparked by widespread student protests in France in 1968, so has much politically ineffective, if not irrelevant, work in the history of philosophy been inspired by instant political events. Moreover, political criticism of postmodernism requires some understanding of its intellectual, poststructuralist context, which Sokal seems to lack. Finally, the issue of political relevance is separate from the question of whether a body of work is nonsense.
OT H E R AM E R I CA N P H I LO S O P H I E S
What are the other American philosophies?
The term here refers to philosophies that represent groups in the Americas that have been politically subordinate to the groups historically represented by the U.S. government. These philosophies themselves have long histories in their cultures of origin, but their concerns have recently become part of Anglo-American mainstream academic philosophy. As a result, new philosophical subfields emerged toward the end of the twentieth century: African American, Native American, and Latin American philosophy. Each of these traditions has developed as a form of cultural criticism, and insofar
395
as its analyses of oppression would not immediately be recognized as such by perpetrators, each is a distinctive critical theory.
What makes the concerns of these historically disadvantaged groups part of philosophy?
When philosophers take up these concerns, as many have in recent decades, they become part of the official curriculum of philosophy in higher education. In addition, the issues raised require the methods of both analytic and continental philosophy to resolve. Some of these issues are ethical and others are directly related to political philosophy and public policy, both of which are now part of the canon of contemporary philosophy.
AF R I CAN AM E R I CAN P H I LO S O P HY
What is African American philosophy?
African American philosophy has had at least three periods: in the nineteenth century period it is usually associated with abolitionism, most notably in the writings of Frederick Douglass (c. 18181895); in the early twentieth century, it is distinguished by the work of Alain Locke (18851954) and W.E.B. Dubois. Not until the 1970s did African American philosophy begin to function as a subfield within academic philosophy, and that was the beginning of its third period, which continues until the present day. Aside from recognizing historically overlooked thinkers and ideas, African American philosophy has focused on identity, racism and its remedies, questions of reparations for black chattel slavery before the U.S. Civil War, and the question of whether there is a scientific foundation for the division of human beings into biological races. A skeletal list of core classic readings in African American philosophy would include: Alexander Crummells (1819 1898) Destiny and Race: Selected Writings, 18401898 (2000), Frederick Douglass A Narrative of the Life of Frederick Douglass, an American Slave (1845), W.E.B. DuBois (18681963) The Souls of Black Folk and Dusk of Dawn (1945), Alain Lockes (18861954) The New Negro (1925), Booker T. Washingtons (1886 1915) Up from Slavery: An Autobiography (1901), and Martin Luther Kings (1929
396
Among the many luminaries of African American philosophy was W.E.B. Dubois, a civil rights activist, historian, sociologist, and Pan-Africanist who dedicated his life to solving the problem of racism (Library of Congress).
1968) A Testament of Hope: The Essential Writings and Speeches of Martin Luther King, Jr. (1986).
What were the main themes and claims in classic African American literature?
Until the Emancipation Proclamation (1862), the main issue was the abolition of black slavery. From the end of the Civil War until the Civil Rights movement of the late 1950s that resulted in legislation against discrimination in 1964, the issue was discrimination against blacks and their social and legal exclusion from opportunities in employment, education on all levels, housing, adequate medical care, and fairness in the criminal justice system. At the same time, support for and construction of positive identities for African Americans was a central concern.
397
tionally, strong racial or ethnic identities have developed among members of oppressed groups, sometimes based on the very things that are used against them by racists. On the other hand, strong racial identities among disadvantaged groups may prevent young people from aspiring to and achieving success in a dominant white society. Beyond these pragmatic concerns is a current consensus that all social and psychological racial identities are socially constructed, rather than biologically determined.
What have been the major themes and issues in African American philosophy?
Analyses of racism, questions about racial identity, and questions about the reality of race are all important issues in African American philosophy.
398
N AT I V E A M E R I C A N P H I L O S O P H Y
What is Native American philosophy?
Native American tribes and nations have held well-developed world views, religions, epistemologies, metaphysics, and social and political views long before Europeans invaded and appropriated their lands. Much of this knowledge was transmitted orally and subject to loss and fragmentation, following what many indigenous people call the Native American Holocaust. The development of Native American philosophy as a subfield in academic philosophy requires not just reconstruction of past knowledge but some acceptance of the methods of Western philosophy. The problem is that these methods are highly problematic for most indigenous thinkers. Furthermore, after centuries of distorted descriptions of their cultures by anthropologists and government officials, most Native American philosophers have a strong preference for speaking in their own voices, rather than agreeing to let others present their perspectives. There are not very many Native Americans in U.S. university philosophy departments at this timeperhaps fewer than 50. Nevertheless, since the 1980s a canon of Native American philosophy has developed, which includes the following sources: The Sacred Hoop by Paula Gunn Allen (1986); How It Is: The Native American Philosophy of V. F. Cordova by Linda Hogan, by Kathleen Dean Moore, Kurt Peters, and Ted Jojoba (2007); Cultural Sites of Critical Insight: Philosophy, Aesthetics, and African American and Native American Womens Writings, by Angela L. Cotton and Christa Davis (2007); American Indian Thought: Philosophical Essays, by Anne Waters (2003); and Defending Mother Earth: Native American Perspectives on Environmental Justice, by Jace Weaver (1996).
399
American communities have been able to use profits from their casinos to purchase those ancestral lands that the U.S. promised them in unfulfilled treaties. Viola Cordova (19372002), a university professor and the first Native American to earn a doctorate in philosophy (she was also part Hispanic), argued that the history of Western philosophy has an overwhelming Christian bias and influence in ways that are incomprehensible to thinkers in Native cultures. Anne Waters, another Native American philosopher, as well as an attorney who teaches at California State University at Bakersfield, has challenged the myth of European discovery of the Americas, referring to oral traditions claiming that Native Americans have always inhabited the Americas. Native American women writers such as Paula Gunn Allen have traced matriarchal patterns in indigenous political history, which were dislodged by European settlers who refused to negotiate with female leaders. This suggests very different feminist concerns among Native American women compared to Western feminists, recovering political power instead of attaining it.
L AT I N A M E R I C A N P H I L O S O P H Y
What is Latin American philosophy?
Latin American philosophy is either or both the thought of philosophers who reside in Latin American countries or the newer work of Latino-Latina/Hispanic-American philosophers. Like African American and Native American philosophy, it is a subfield to the academic discipline that formed after 1930, although it was not duly recognized until after 1980. Contemporary considerations of philosophy in Latin America, written by philosophers who also reflect on the Latino-Latina/Hispanic-American experience include the following books: Linda Alcoff and Eduardo Mendieta, Thinking from the Underside of History: Enrique Dusells Philosophy of Liberation (2000); Jorge J.E. Gracia, Mireya Camurati, editors, Philosophy and Literature in Latin America (1989); Jorge J.E. Gracia and Elizabeth Millan-Zaibert, editors, Latin American Philosophy for the 21st Century: The Human Condition, Values, and the Search for Identity (1989); Eduardo Mendieta, Global Fragments: Critical Theory, Latin America and Globalizations (2007); Susana Nuccetelli, Latin American Thought: Philosophical Problems and Arguments (2002); and Ofelia Schutte, Cultural Identity and Social Liberation in Latin American Thought (1993).
Americans and questions centered on the difference between race (as false biology) and ethnicity (as culture).
OT H E R C O NTI N E NTA L TR A D I TI O N S
What other continental traditions are new to Western philosophy?
Recent decades have seen renewed interest in African, Japanese, Chinese, and Indian philosophies among Euro-American philosophers. Some of this work has been called comparative philosophy because it seeks to relate themes that are well-established and well-developed philosophies in their continents of origin to traditional interests in Western philosophy. Japanese, Chinese, and Indian philosophies admit to the comparative treatment because they have long, well-established textual traditions. However, African philosophy is a less clear case, not because it fails to treat issues that in the Western tradition would without doubt be considered philosophical, but because much of it has endured through oral traditions. Still, a broad recognition of African culture and its historical civilizations, after the 1960s, led to the Euro-American perspective of Afro-centrism among some members of the African Diaspora.
401
AFRO - C E NTRI S M
AN D
AF R I CAN P H I LO S O P HY
402
The context is not Afro-centrist because Africans who remained in Africa and were not brought to Europe or the Americas had no need for the distinctive uplift of Afro-
centrism. Instead, the focus on Africa from an African perspective turns on the question of what the multiplicity of countries and cultures in Africa, each with distinct languages and traditions, have in common so that they can view themselves as African. They share a colonized past and poverty in the present world; they have been designated by biological race, though this is an illusion. Contemporary philosophical sources for African philosophy include Kwame Anthony Appiah, In My Fathers House: Africa in the Philosophy of Culture (1992); Kwame Gyeke, Tradition and Modernity (1997); Emmanuel Eze, editor, Postcolonial African Philosophy (1970); Paulin J. Hountondji, African Philosophy: Myth and Reality (1983); John Mbiti, African Religions and Philosophy (1970); Albert Mosley, editor, African Philosophy: Selected Readings (1995); H. Odera Oruka, editor, Sage Philosophy (1990); Tsenay Serequeberhan, editor, African Philosophy: The Essential Readings (1991); Kwasi Wiredu, editor, A Companion to African Philosophy (2004); and Richard Wright, editor, African Philosophy: An Introduction (1984).
BUDDHISM
AN D
How have Japanese, Chinese, and Indian philosophy recently entered AngloAmerican philosophy?
Asian philosophy came to the West as Buddhism from Japanese, Chinese and Indian philosophy, and Neo-Confucianism from Chinese philosophy. Given the common thread of Buddhism throughout Asia, many might be tempted to designate all philosophy from Japan, China, and India as Asian philosophy or Eastern philosophy, but there are other systems of thought and religion just as diverse as Buddhist traditions. Also, the different Buddhist traditions derive from cultures that have very distinctive histories, as well as very different current political and economic situations and ties to the West. That their theological dimensions are not Christian, Jewish, or Muslim, is probably all that the philosophies of these areasbroadly understood to be more than Buddhism and Confucianismhave in common. Although Euro-American intellectuals in other fields have well-developed scholarly traditions based on Eastern texts, it should be noted that philosophers, as a pro-
403
fession, are relative latecomers to Eastern philosophy. For instance: the British biochemist Joseph Needham (19001995) wrote extensively on technology and science in the history of China; the nineteenth century German novelist Herman Hesse introduced an international readership to Indian thought and Buddhism in his 1922 novel, Siddhartha; and philosophys own Gottfried Leibniz (16461716) was fascinated by Chinese thought. The question is what do philosophers put on their curricula from Eastern thought in new ways that emphasize a commonality of philosophical interests? Again, the answer is Buddhism, on account of its resonance with Western metaphysics and epistemology, and Confucianism for what it teaches about virtue ethics.
What is Buddhism?
Buddhism was founded in India by Siddhartha Gautama. The majority of Indian scholars place his lifespan as c. 563c. 483 B.C.E. Indian Buddhism divided into Theravada, or Hinayana or Lesser Vehicle, and Mahayana, or Greater Vehicle. Indian Buddhism was no longer a vibrant religion in India after the thirteenth century, but it had by then spread geographically. Theravada Buddhism is practiced in Thailand, Laos, Cambodia, and Sri Lanka. Mahayana Buddhism is practiced in China, Japan, Nepal, and the United States. Tibetan Buddhism, in addition to including the Greater and Lesser Vehicles, has a form known as Vairayana. All of the three vehicles are practiced in Himalayan parts of Mongolia, Northeastern China, and Russia. Zen Buddhism is practiced in Japan as a kind of meditation called zazen that repudiates texts (even though there is a written tradition) and focuses on unmediated direct experience. Zen originated in India and emerged in China in the seventh century C.E., from which it spread to Vietnam, Korea, and Japan. Zen includes Yoga ca ra, which is a form of philosophical idealism that uses yoga exercises to achieve disbelief in the existence of physical objects.
404
Buddhism is often associated with China, Japan, and Nepal, but it actually began in India, where it was started by Siddhartha Gautama, the Buddha (iStock).
people, money, power, fame, objects, and anything else. By following the Eightfold Path, a practitioner will snuff out his or her flame of desire and no longer need to return to this earth. There are three precepts or self-evident truths: that all life is unhappy or unsatisfying, that all life is impermanent, and that there is no eternal or even permanent self or soul. From these precepts, the Eightfold Path manifests itself: right speech, right action, right livelihood, right effort, right mindfulness, right concentration, right views, and right intentions.
What is Confucianism?
Confucius (551479 B.C.E.) was born in Shantung, China, where he advanced from poverty to an influential administrative post. He was a member of the Ju (the literal
405
meaning of ju is weaklings), a social group of ritualists and teachers. Confucius and his colleagues and followers became members of the Ju-chia, the School of the Ju. They sought to develop and restore traditional ideals of concern for all living things and reverence toward other human beings by determining and following proper rules of conduct. In 496 Confucius left his position to talk to rulers about the Ju-chias doctrines. During a time when warlords were chaotically vying for control of the declining Chou dynasty, he sought to import moral principles and the traditional virtues into government. Confucius thoughts were put together by his pupils in the Lun Y, or Analects.
406
However, a number of contemporary moral philosophers have found some appeal in the Confucian egalitarian ideal of respect for all beings. Confucianism has also been received as an alternative virtue ethics theory, as well as for its utilitarian/consequentialist notion that correct behavior will maximize happiness. Such comparative ideas, as well as contemporary interpretations and applications of Confucianism, can be found in the following sources: Bo Mou, Comparative Approaches to Chinese Philosophy (2003), Li-Hsiang Lisa Rosenlee, Confucianism and Women: A Philosophical Interpretation (2006); Philip J. Ivanhoe, Ethics in the Confucian Tradition: The Thought of Mengzi and Wang Yangming (2002); Bryan W. van Norden, Confucius and the Analects: New Essays (2002); and Kwong-loi Shun and David B. Wong, Confucian Ethics: A Comparative Study of Self, Autonomy, and Community (2004).
F E M I N I ST P H I LO S O P HY
What is feminism and feminist philosophy?
Feminism involves both thought and practice aimed at improving the well-being of women. On the side of practice it is often thought of as the womens movement. Intellectually, feminism is a critical theory because it contains analysis of social conditions and prescriptions for improving them toward its end. Also on the intellectual side, feminism is now a multidisciplinary academic field with participation from all of the humanities, contemporary cultural criticism, the social sciences, and womens studies. Feminist philosophy is the philosophical dimension of intellectual feminism. Many feminist philosophers understand their intellectual history and the history of the womens movement in terms of three waves.
407
women), she interviewed her classmates, who had graduated in 1942. Many had achieved the approved social ambition of a husband, home, and children, but they were dissatisfied with their lives and in some instances agonizingly unfulfilled. Friedan argued, in ways that resonated throughout American society and Europe, that women as human beings needed education and meaningful work, mental stimulation, and fully adult responsibilities. By the 1970s, further development of Friedans ideas found expression in the third wave. The womens liberation moveProminent feminist Betty Friedan wrote about the ment was associated with the following disatisfaction many American women were feeling about achievements: Title VII of the Civil Rights their lives in the mid-twentieth century (AP). Act of 1964 prohibited discrimination in employment on the grounds of gender, as well as race; the U.S. Supreme Court decision of Roe v. Wade in 1973 legitimized the right to abortion based on bodily privacy. These legal innovations combined with the pill (birth control medication), provided a new degree of sexual freedom, huge increases in womens employment outside the home, and access to higher education. Women entered the professions in unprecedented numbers and the rest is history in the sense that it is now taken for granted by American society that women should have opportunities equal to mens.
408
traditional philosophical approaches that were created by male philosophers. For example, political philosophers have often assumed that the basic political unit is a male head of household, thereby neglecting both female workers and the kind of unpaid work performed by women in traditional families. Feminist philosophers seek revisions and expansions of such assumptions so as to include women.
409
Marcus ground-breaking journal articles are collected in Modalities: Philosophical Essays (1993). She received the American Philosophical Association Quinn Prize for service to the profession in 2007.
410
y no means. A number of male philosophers have endeavored to both learn and support feminism and include feminist subjects in their own more traditional work. These men have published such books as Rethinking Masculinity: Philosophical Explorations in Light of Feminism (1992), edited by Larry May and Robert Strikwerda; Men Doing Feminism (1998), edited by Tom Digby; and Michael A. Slotes The Ethics of Care and Empathy (2007).
There were womens separatist social movements in the 1970s, but this has never been a viable option in academia. The radical feminist philosopher of religion Mary Daly (1936), who taught at Boston College for 33 years, was forced to retire in 1999 for barring men from some of her classes. Daly was always on thin ice at this Jesuit institution, especially after the publication of her first book, The Church and the Second Sex (1968). Dalys work is about how men have appropriated the roles and power of women in religion, particularly in Catholic ritual. Philosophical feminism has evinced strong support for lesbian feminism on the grounds that lesbians have been oppressed in society and that lesbians may recognize the personhood of women more easily than men. Nevertheless, freedom of sexual preference entails that heterosexuality remains a respected preference, just as freedom of choice in abortion has not led feminists to invalidate, on moral or political grounds, pregnancy and childbirth. On motherhood, for example, Sara Ruddicks Maternal Thinking: Toward a Politics of Peace (1990) shows how childcare develops distinctive ways of thinking, although childbirth and rearing is not limited to heterosexual women. Much of French feminist writing assumes strong male-female sexual differences.
Kourany (1943) edited The Gender of Science (2002) and Scientific Knowledge (1987, 1998), which relate some of the feminist critique of traditional science to standing issues in mainstream philosophy of science.
411
tice and the Politics of Difference (1990) and Inclusion and Democracy (2000). Young also addressed womens disempowered bodily comportment in her 1980 essay Throwing Like a Girl (included in a book by the same name in 1990). In addition, feminist philosophers have welcomed and discussed the work of University of Michigan Law School professor Catherine MacKinnon.
412
What is Julia Kristevas idea of the abject and the nature of women?
Kristeva has emphasized the rejection of mothers by both male and female children due to male-dominated cultural patterns that render the mother herself abject, which is to say, totally other, disgusting, and monstrous. Kristeva thinks that the solution to this problem requires a rediscovery and healing of narcissism in womens psyches and an acceptance of adult love between women. However, Kristeva rejects the label woman as a universal term, and has refused to define women. She apparently believes that every woman is fundamentally different in how she is a woman or what being a woman means. As she wrote: It is there, in the analysis of her difficult relation to her mother and to her own difference from everybody else, men and women, that a woman encounters the enigma of the feminine. I favour an understanding of femininity that would have as many feminines as there are women.
413
Kristevas main theoretical writings are: About Chinese Women (1977), Desire in Language: A Semiotic Approach to Literature and Art (1980), Powers of Horror: An Essay on Abjection (1982), Revolution in Poetic Language (1984), and New Maladies of the Soul (1995).
414
Since the 1970s, feminist advocates have pointed out that clinical medicine has traditionally been based on the male body. Some diseases have different symptoms in men and womenfor example, heart disease. At this time, female doctors are commonplace, particularly in the practice of gynecology, and there is greater attention, overall, to womens health problems. Historical information on the 1970s womens health movement can be found at CWLU Herstory Project: The Online History of the Chicago Womens Liberation Union is at http://www.cwluherstory.com.
Why are LBGT studies and queer theory part of philosophy now?
They have become part of philosophy along with an overall interest in expanding cultural studies to include attention to issues previously neglected. This change has been part of the humanities, generally, and philosophers have focused on conceptual issues related to these fields. Queer theory emerged in the 1990s, along with LGBT (Lesbian Gay Bisexual Transsexual) studies, as a positive affirmation of sexual difference that does not fit into any of its predecessor categories, including lesbianism. Good overviews on the subject may be found in Naomi Schors Feminism Meets Queer Theory (1997), and helpful works on transsexuality are Susan Strykers Transgender History (2008), and Laurie Shrages Youve Changed (2009).
415
lectual women. Two books crystallized this complaint: bell hooks (she spelled her name in all lowercase letters) Aint I a Woman?: Black Women and Feminism (1981) brought attention to oppression due to race suffered by women of color. Elizabeth V. Spelman pointed out the problems of a universalizing trend within feminism that left out differences among women in Inessential Woman: Problems of Exclusion in Feminist Thought (1988). White feminist complaints about glass ceilings, or invisible barriers to top positions in business, on the one hand and the stultifying aspects of home-making on the other, did not resonate with all other women. Poor women and women of color had worked outside their own homes, in factories and fields, or the homes of other women, for centuries; the second shift was not new to them. Because of this, a third wave was needed to address all womens needs.
Wave Theory of Womens Commonality (2005), is that all women share a relation to an historical category that has been oppressed: the group of mothers, or birth females, or mens heterosexual choices. A second, developed by Cressida J. Heyes in Line Drawings: Defining Women Through Feminist Practice, is that women share Wittgensteinian family resemblances.
E NVI RO N M E NTA L P H I LO S O P HY
What is environmentalism?
Environmentalism is the study of the relationship between living organisms (including human beings) and natural environments, usually with the aim of preserving natural environments and renewable resources. Environmentalism is now a multifaceted, multi-disciplinary field, extending widely into both theory and practice.
417
Environmental philosophy has drawn on many traditions and subfields within philosophy, including: ethics, social philosophy, continental philosophy, aesthetics, and feminism. Each of these areas refers basic questions about our relation to the environment to fundamental philosophical viewpoints.
418
mans on the natural planet and the dependence of the natural health of parts of the planet on human activity will probably become an even more absorbing, distressing, and contentious subject than it already is. Since of all the new subjects in philosophy, environmentalism is probably the most popular, it should be noted that the following books are all good sources of additional information: William F. Baxter, People or Penguins: The Case for Maximum Pollution (1974); Ted Benton, Natural Relations: Ecology, Animal Rights & Social Justice (1993); Jay Bernstein, Adorno: Disenchantment and Ethics (2001); J.B. Callicott, In Defense of the Land Ethic: Essays in Environmental Philosophy (1989); B. Devall and G. Sessions, Deep Ecology: Living as if Nature Mattered (1985); Robert Heilbroner, What Has Posterity Ever Done for Me?, in New York Times Magazine (January 19, 1975); Thomas E. Hill, Ideals of Human Virture and Preserving the Natural Environment, in Ethics, Volume 5 (1983); D. Jamieson, editor, A Companion to Environmental Philosophy (2001); Aldo Leopold, A Sand County Almanac (1949); A. Naess, Ecology, Community, Lifestyle (reprint, 1989); R. Nash, The Rights of Nature: A History of Environmental Ethics (1989); V. Plumwood, Environmental Culture (2002); and Peter Singer, Animal Liberation: A New Ethics for our Treatment of Animals, (1975, 1977, 1983).
419
human beings, for example, are mere knots in the net and ought to forgo some of their preoccupation with their own individual existence and selfish interests.
420
A caricature of Peter Singer, who has been criticized for saying that healthy adult animals are more valuable than severely impaired human infants (BigStock Photos).
What do critics of the deep ecological and animal value views claim?
William F. Baxter, a law professor who passed away in 1998, argued in People or Penguins: The Case for Maximum Pollution (1974) that the cost of a pollution-free soci-
421
ety would be harmful to humans. He assumed that humanism requires that humans are what matter above all else. Baxter expressed a general critical view of environmentalism held by human beings who do not believe that animals have intrinsic worth or rights equal to those of humans.
What religious issues are involved in environmental thought, pro and con?
Some of the critical perspective derives from a Christian view imbedded in Western political philosophy that God gave the earth and everything on it to humankind to rule over for our use; only humans have the spark of divinity that justifies intrinsic value. Nonetheless, many religious groups have proclaimed an obligation of benevolent stewardship over parts of the earth. But, insofar as part of this stewardship is for the sake of future generations, a perplexing question arises: How can we have obligations to those who do not exist? Robert Heilbroner (19192005) has examined this issue in What Has Posterity Ever Done for Me?, a widely quoted and reprinted 1975 essay that first appeared in New York Magazine.
422
OTH E R TR E N D S I N N E W P H I LO S O P HY
What is the philosophy of biology?
Strictly speaking, philosophy of biology is not new because it has been part of philosophy since Aristotle (384322 B.C.E.). However, recent thought about how living systems are different from the inert subject matter of physics and chemistry have resulted in new philosophies of biology as a distinct theoretical/philosophical subject. Moreover, social controversies, such as popular debates about creationism and evolution, and beliefs in individual self-determination versus genetic determinism, have injected new vitality into older issues in philosophy of biology.
423
The Brights Movement motto is Illuminating and Elevating the Naturalistic Worldview. The organization has three major aims: promote public awareness of the naturalistic worldview, achieve recognition that individuals who hold this worldview can behave in principled ways in important civic matters, and educate all members of society to recognize and accept the participation of Brights.
whereas cranes are ways of understanding a later stage based on the design of an earlier one. Dennett has argued that consciousness, the contents of consciousness, and even the products of consciousness, such as Shakespeares plays, can be naturalistically understood in the same way that physical evolution is understandable. Neural systems create multiple drafts of the same thing so that the brain itself is a sort of dung heap in which the larvae of other peoples ideas renew themselves. Dennett is also a proponent of the doctrine of memes, whereby certain patterns of behavior are products of evolution that are physically inherited. His extreme materialism has attracted many critics, as well as supporters.
What is a meme?
In The Selfish Gene (1976) British evolutionary biologist, professor, and author Richard Dawkins coined the term as being on a par with gene. A memefor instance, a tune, recipe, moral system, or style of dressgets passed on from one generation to the next via cultural interaction. Although memes are not usually held to be physically inherited the way that genes are, social biologists believe them to be subject to natural selection and mutation.
424
425
What is our relationship to technology? How does it affect our lives and our perception of our world? These are questions the philosophy of technology may address (BigStock Photos).
and medicine. Such knowledge understands itself, according to universals and causes. It can be taught and is distinct from physis, or nature. Contemporary philosophy of technology is a multi-disciplinary field dedicated to studying the cultural effects and causes of technology, both historically and in its emergent forms. The American Philosophical Association publishes a newsletter on Philosophy and Computers, and there are academic journals such as Ends and Means, NetFutureTechnology and Human Responsibility, and Techn: Research in Philosophy and Technology.
426
While psychologist Jean Piaget set the paradigm that children are not able to think about thinking or engage in philosophy before about age 12, philosopher Gareth Matthews (1929) argues in Philosophy and the Young Child (1980) that there was evidence of philosophical thought and speech in Piagets own young subjects. Before then, Matthew Lipman (1922) had introduced philosophy to middle school children in Montclair, New Jersey, with his 96-page philosophical novel for children, Harry Stottlemeiers Discovery (1974). (A philosophical novel for children is a story that raises philosophical issues in language that a child can understand.) Both Mathews and Lipman have stressed the active nature of childrens philosophical interests. By contrast, Norwegian author Jostein Gaarders best-selling young adult novel Sophies World: A Novel about the History of Philosophy (1994) leads the reader through a series of studies about philosophy. Thus, philosophy for teenagers may be more didactic than the philosophy already taught to children. Contemporary journals devoted to teaching children philosophy include Analytic Teaching, The Community of Inquiry Journal, Critical & Creative Thinking, The Australasian Journal of Philosophy for Children, Questions: Philosophy for Young People, and Thinking: The Journal of Philosophy for Children.
Ideologies of Western Dominance (1990); Eric Higgs anthology Technology and the Good Life (2000); and Hans Achterhuis, American Philosophy of Technology (2001).
427
of broad beliefs in contemporary culture, and philosophers who turn to film for examples in ethics, aesthetics, political philosophy, feminism, and many other philosophical interests and subfields. As well, some films directly raise philosophical questions, such as the questions about what is real in The Matrix (1999) and its sequels, and the nature of memory and identity raised by Momento (2000) and the childrens film The NeverEnding Story (1984). There are, moreover, films that are directly about philosophy and philosophers such as The Ister (2004), which is about Martin Heidegger (18891976). Contemporary sources on philosophy and film include: Richard Allen and Murray Smith, editors, Film Theory and Philosophy (1997); Gregory Currie, Image and Mind: Film, Philosophy, and Cognitive Science (1995); and Cynthia A. Freeland and Thomas E. Wartenberg, Philosophy and Film (1995). The online journal Film-Philosophy: A Philosophical Review of Film Studies and World Cinema is an ongoing source of contemporary work and additional sources.
What is mysterianism?
Mysterianism is the view that it is impossible for us to explain consciousness. This perspective, sometimes held by philosophers, is now called the new mysterianism and is based on the writings of Colin McGinn (1950), such as The Problem of Consciousness (1991), The Mysterious Flame (1999), and Consciousness and Its Objects (2004). The name new mysterians was bestowed by Owen Flanagan (1949) in his Science of the Mind (1991), and it was based on the rock group Question Mark and the Mysterians. Past philosophers such as Gottfried Leibniz (16461716) similarly believed that the emergence of consciousness could not be fully understood by conscious beings. What is striking about the new mysterianism, though, is that it cropped up after almost a century of rigorous philosophical attempts to provide theories of consciousness and cognition. It is different from claiming, as Jerry Fodor (1935) does, that we do not now know how the mind is connected to the body because it claims that we cant ever know that, or even what the mind itself is. Some aspects of this thought are reminiscent of skepticism in the ancient world and in the sixteenth century.
428
Glossary
Note: words and terms that appear here have broad philosophical use and meaning. More specific references to the text, as well as individual philosophers are listed in the index. abolitionism Nineteenth century arguments and action to abolish chattel slavery in the United States and Great Britain. absolute Hegels idea of a non-material something developing over history and determining the progression of events, forms of society, and types of knowledge, while at the same time being expressed in them. accidents Non-essential qualities or characteristics of a thing, which can change while the thing remains what it essentially is (see essence). aesthetics Philosophical study of what constitutes beauty and of the creation and appreciation of artworks. affirmative action A policy of affirming minority racial identities or those of women by giving them opportunities in employment and education on the basis of race or gender instead of, or in addition to, the opportunities they would get given their other skills, largely illegal at present if based solely on race, without considering other skills and aptitudes. a fortiori Reasoning from a premise stronger than the one needed to come to a conclusion at hand. African American philosophy Moral, social, and political philosophy based on the American experience, identities, and concerns of African Americans. African philosophy Broadly understood as the oral and written traditions and knowledge of varied cultures in Africa; as a distinct philosophy, occupied with both philosophical problems of its own identity, questions about the possibility of one African philosophy, and engagement with questions in traditional Western philosophy. alchemy Medieval and Renaissance proto-chemical practice with goals of turning base metals into gold and concocting the elixir of life (aqua vitae). altruism Doctrine that we do or should help others, even to the extent of sacrificing our own interests. American Philosophical Association (APA) Contemporary professional organization of American philosophy.
429
American philosophy Philosophy that originated in and is mainly practiced in the USA, refers mainly but not exclusively to pragmatism. analogy A comparison based on functions or structures (e.g., swimming in water is analogous to walking on land). analysis Intellectual process of breaking complex ideas down into simpler components; examination of whether an argument is logically valid. analytic philosophy A form of philosophy that analyzes concepts, proceeds with respect for science and does not rely on metaphysical speculation. analytic truth A statement that is true wholly because of the meaning of its terms (e.g., All bachelors are unmarried men.) anarchism Political theory that society can be improved with the elimination of central government and be replaced by local cooperative organizations formed by workers; action toward achieving anarchist goals. a posteriori After experience. A posteriori truths require experience or observation to be formulated. a priori Before experience. A priori truths do not require experience or observation to be formulated. artificial intelligence (AI) Idea of higher cognition in machines, proposed by midtwentieth century cognitive philosophers to both solve the mindbody problem and create models for how the human mind works.
artificial language Formal language constructed for a precise purposesuch as in logic, computer science, mathematicsor the use of formal language by analytic philosophies. atomism Metaphysical principle that all physical objects and things are made up of particles that cannot be further divided; scientific principle that some part of reality or language has small parts that are foundational for larger parts or objects and that it is the task of thinkers to discover what those atoms are in a particular domain. argument A train of thought or sequence of sentences that is meant to prove or be persuasive. Proof requires logical validity; persuasion can be achieved with a probable conclusion or appeal to common sense or intuition. assumption A statement believed to be true before proceeding on to another subject. atheism Theological or non-religious position that there is no deity or supernatural entity; belief that God does not exist. autonomy Self-rule or control by the individual over important aspects of his or her life. axiology Study of values. bad faith Self-deception; in existentialism bad faith consists of denying the nature of consciousness, evading responsibility, or denying the reality of ones situation.
430
begging the question Fallacy in reasoning whereby one assumes beforehand what remains to be proved. behaviorism Early twentieth century psychological theory of human learning, attributed to J.B. Watson and B.F. Skinner, that is based on stimulus and response model of conditioning, with strong rejection of introspection as source of information for all human mentation or psychological theories. Buddhism Way of thought and life founded in India by Siddhartha Gautama during the sixth century B.C.E. and later practiced all over the world. canon A set of traditional writings that the student is expected to master in a field. Cartesian Pertaining to or derived from the thought of Ren Descartes, usually in reference to claims that the mind is separate from the body, or that the mind and body are two radically different things or substances. categorical imperative Absolute moral obligation formulated by Kant in two ways: Act so that you can will the maxim of your action to be a general law for rational beings; never treat another, or yourself, as a means, but always as an end (with intrinsic worth). catharsis Release of pity and fear caused by viewing tragedy in Aristotles sense. causal theory of meaning Also known as reference theory of meaning; view that meaning is not mental but in the objects named by words and that words come to
name objects based on an original baptism linking the word to the object. causation The reality and study of how events are connected so that one event or one type of event results in another event or another type of event. chance An occurrence of two events or type of occurrence, with no known causal connections. Chance may be an appearance only, due to lack of information about relevant courses, or chance may be viewed as an effect of the randomness of some events that cannot be determined. character Human disposition to act in certain ways, which may be good or bad. choice A situation in which it is possible to do one or more of several things, or an exercise of autonomy. circular argument An argument where the conclusion is the same as its premises. cogito Latin, literally meaning I think; name for Ren Descartess conclusion that he exists, in the argument: I think, therefore I am. cognition Mental processes that impart or transmit knowledge, often presumed to be unemotional or not determined by emotion. cognitive science Study of human and primate mental processes, including the processing of perceptual information, and learning. common sense What most people believe and are considered correct or justified in believing; received opinion.
431
Glo ssar y
common sense philosophy Approach to philosophical problems that relies on common sense or ordinary opinions, attributed to Thomas Reid, G.E. Moore and others. concept An idea, or more accurately, the meaning of a word. conceptual analysis Philosophical analysis of the meaning of terms. confirmation Proof of truth. Confucianism Moral and social theory begun in sixth century B.C.E. China, which is based on the individual virtues and wider social benefits of specific familial and social roles. conscience Moral intuition that a person has certain obligations, or that some kinds of behavior are morally wrong. consciousness Awareness, the human mind in operation, or the human subject as self-aware. consequentialism Moral system in which an action is right if it has good consequences, or better consequences than another action. constructed Not natural, a human trait or activity is constructed or socially constructed if it is the result of custom or social rules and practices. contingent Uncertain to happen or something that could be or could have been otherwise. contradiction A statement that both asserts and denies the same thing. The law of non-contradiction in logic states
that either A or not-A must be true, not both, and not neither. contrary Two things or statements are logical contraries if they cannot both be true, but can both be false. conversational implicature Theory of spoken language developed by H.P. Grice, according to which accepted rules of communication, together with a speech context, determine meaning, and the meaning is understood to change when the rules are violated. Copernican revolution Named after Nicolaus Copernicus, change in world view from geocentric to heliocentric theory. corroboration Scientific standard of confirmation that is less than full proof; the statement that is corroborated could turn out to be false in the future. cosmological argument Argument for the proof of God as the creator of the universe, on the grounds that something must have created the universe; because all events and things have causes, then so must the universe as a whole. cosmopolitanism Idea throughout intellectual history that one should be a citizen of the world, opposed to localism and chauvinism. counter-factual Hypothetical about the past; e.g., if Aristotles texts had been lost forever, Western philosophy would have been more platonic. covering law model Standard for scientific explanation whereby specific events are explained by showing how they are instances of generalizations; e.g., The
432
pond is frozen because its below 32 degrees Fahrenheit and water freezes at 32 degrees. critical theory A system of thought that makes assertions about social reality in critical ways. The assertions are often negative evaluations in contrast to a desired ideal and those who they are made about need not agree with them for critical theorists to accept them. May also mean Marxist analysis produced by twentieth century scholars. critique Verb or noun referring to criticism that originates from a well-formed intellectual perspective. cynicism Ancient doctrine of withdrawal from society and return to what is simple and natural, which may be obnoxious to those who are refined. deconstruction Postmodern philosophical perspective that regards meanings as unstable and analyzes classic writings in ways that go beyond authors stated intentions. deduction Method of logical reasoning that is determined by the laws of logic alone. deep ecology Position that non-human and non-sentient natural beings have intrinsic value that humans should respect. deliberate Quality of an action where the agent is aware of what he or she is doing. demonology Form of practical magic involving calling up, using, and interacting with demons or daimons.
deontology Moral system based on obligations or duties. determinism Doctrine that all events, including human actions, have causes and that the future can in principle be predicted. dialectical A progressive process involving what are believed to be opposites, in either conversation or reality, which aims toward truth in conversation and creates change in reality; a philosophical method that posits an initial set of terms or principles and shows how they interact and result in new terms and principles. dialogue In philosophy, a conversation about a topic in which different views are argued back and forth so that more of the truth is uncovered than would be if one person spoke or if the discussants stated their views separately and independently. dichotomy A compelling difference in meaning between two things, so that they are of an either-or nature. dignity Intrinsic worth that deserves respect. According to Immanuel Kant, rational agents have a dignity that cannot be bought or sold (priced). disposition Tendency to behave in a certain way, without there being an inherent substance causing the behavior. For example, according to Aristotle, virtues are dispositions to behave, fully evident in past and present behavior, and not inert or fixed qualities of mind or soul. doctrine of double effects (DDE) Principle that a person is morally responsible only for what she intends, even if an unintend-
433
Glo ssar y
ed consequence of an action, of which she was aware, is something desired. duality Separation or split between two things, so that they are radically different, for example, the Cartesian duality between mind and body. Eastern philosophy Philosophical study of religions and thought systems from Asian cultures and nations such as, for example, India, China, and Japan. egoism Principle that humans act out of self interest, egoism can be a description of human behavior or a prescription for it. eliminative materialism View in analytic philosophy of mind that references to subject states and attitudes (wanting, willing, intending, feeling, etc.) should be eliminated from scientific and empirical philosophical discourse. emotivism Theory of ethics and aesthetics, according to which moral and aesthetic judgments are only the expression of emotions and desires. empiricism Philosophical position that all knowledge of the world is and should be based on perceptual experience, either directly or indirectly. Enlightenment A large part and theme of eighteenth century philosophy according to which mankind will progress based on reason, universal human rights, and the fundamental dignity and goodness of humankind. environmental philosophy Moral and social philosophy based on environmental concerns.
epicurianism Philosophy attributed to Epicurus, which includes atomism, and living well by pursuing only enduring, quiet pleasures. epigenisis Early modern idea that living things develop over time, opposed to preformationism. epistemology Theory of knowledge, what counts as knowledge, and how beliefs are justified so as to qualify as knowledge. essence Aristotelian idea of that in a thing which makes it what it is and which is also present in all other things of the same category. ethics Philosophical study of what is right and wrong, good and bad, in matters that primarily concern human harm or well-being. etymology Study of the history and development of words and concepts. events Occurrences in time, usually distinguished from things or substances. evidence Grounds for believing something is true, usually used in empirical context. existentialism Philosophical doctrine that truth for humankind begins in concrete human existence instead of from abstractions, and that humans have no pre-constructed nature or essence but must create their characters and lives through actions that they choose to do, and values and meanings that they actively bestow. experience Everything or anything that happens to or is encountered by a subject; in empirical philosophy, perceptual
434
or sensory occurrences; in pragmatism, the whole of all events, without a subject-object distinction. experimental philosophy Early twentyfirst century philosophical method of checking the intuitions philosophers have about widespread beliefs by empirically investigating those beliefs. external reality Everything except consciousness or the human mental subject, including the subjects physical body. faith Type of belief or attitude that does not require empirical evidence or logical reasoning. fallacy Mistake in logic or informal argument. falsifiability Standard for the scientific nature of theories and hypotheses, according to Karl Popper; so that if how a theory would be falsified cannot be specified, then it is not scientific. falsification Process whereby an empirical belief is proved false by a prediction that fails to happen or an event that contradicts an hypothesis. fatalism Non-philosophical form of determinism that does not posit causal chains but specific inevitable events. feminism Intellectual theory and practical programs that have the aim of furthering the well-being of women. forms, platonic Timeless, ideal entities that enable the appearance of entities in this world and set standards for their excellence.
freedom Ability of the human subject to choose and determine his or her life, usually discussed in the context of free will. Freedom is not the same as liberty, which often refers to the absence of external constraints. functionalism Analytic philosophical theory of mind that defines mental processes in terms of computations that are related to brain states. gender In the modern period, the social roles and psychology assigned to biological males and females, believed to be based on their biology; in the early modern period, the social roles of male and female were believed to determine their male or female biological sex in some cases; in postmodern feminism, a generally sexed category of women determined by race and social class. God, gods Transcendent immortal beings with or without high moral qualities, who are more powerful than mortals and are capable of affecting human life as well as creating its material conditions. hedonism Doctrine that the aim of life is pleasure, that people always or should pursue their own pleasure; hedonism is often opposed to altruism, although some accounts of pleasure address pleasures of friendship and helping others. hermeneutic Philosophical method in which texts and also reality are interpreted, usually on the basis of their relation to human consciousness. historicism Theory of society and human nature, attributed to Karl Marx, holding that impersonal historical forces determine individual situations and life des-
435
Glo ssar y
tinies, as well as social and historical events. holism Doctrine that the components in an area of study are inter-connected in ways that form one coherent whole. hypothetical Not certain or declarative; a classic hypothetical has the form If _____, then _____. idea Something before the mind intellectually, which may or may not represent something outside of the mind. idealism Philosophical doctrine that what is ultimately real is mental, rather than physical, sometimes leading to a denial of the existence of an external world. identity The nature of a thing whereby it is what it is; in contemporary social philosophy, the social nature, understood as constructed, of different types of human beings in terms of race, ethnicity, or gender. identity of indiscernibles Gottfried Leibnizs principle that if two things are exactly the same then they are the same thing, from which it follows that two things cannot be exactly the same. ideology Set of beliefs about how things ought to be or interpretations of events based on ideas of how they ought to be; ideologies are not easily falsified. incommensurable Two theories or systems of thought are incommensurable if their key terms cannot be translated into one another. individualism Doctrines that value the separate individual, distinct from relationships with others.
induction Process of reasoning that proceeds from experience to build up knowledge. infinite Immeasurably and unthinkably great in magnitude; magnitude without limit. innate ideas Ideas or structures present in the mind from birth, which may be literally present in fully developed form, or emerge as the child develops. intentionality The aspect of consciousness that is about something other than itself, such as wanting, thinking, willing, desiring, etc. intuitionism Doctrine that some things, qualities, or truths, are known directly, with no need for empirical evidence or logical proof. ipse-dixitism Jeremy Benthams term for moral systems based on sympathy and antipathy. irony In postmodern philosophy, a mode or attitude in speech and writing that does not view itself as ultimately true or certain, and which may be playful, humorous, self-doubting, or tentative. James-Lange theory of emotion View that emotions are experiences of the persons bodily processes, first developed by Ren Descartes, named after William James and C.G. Lange, who proposed it independently in the late-nineteenth century. justice As fairness, justice is treating those who are equal in some respect, the same way, or treating equals equally; distributive justice pertains to how the
436
goods of life are divided among members of a community, nation, or the world. knowledge The goal of intellectual activity; in classic epistemology, knowledge is defined as true belief that has been arrived at in justified ways; i.e., I do not know something if I believe it and it is true, but I do not know why I believe it or how I have come to believe it. Neither do I know it, if it is true and I think its true because I dreamt it or I heard a voice in my head. Latin American philosophy The intellectual tradition of philosophical work in Latin America, dating from 1550 and composed of colonial, independentist, positivist, and contemporary periods. Some contemporary Latin American philosophy overlaps with Latino-a/Hispanic American philosophy. Latino-a/Hispanic American philosophy Contemporary emerging philosophy about questions arising from the experience of Latin American groups in the United States, together with reflection on the history of Latin American philosophy and dialogue with both Latin American and North American philosophers, especially on questions of ethnic and racial identities. laws of nature Regularity, so that events of one type are always followed by another; causal regularity; in religious philosophy, Gods laws for human behavior. liberty The absence of external constraints on important aspects of human autonomy or self-rule; e.g., freedom of speech and religion are liberties. lifeworld The artificial, natural, and social world inhabited by human beings
in their daily lives; term attributed to Jrgen Habermas, referring to human existence; term coined by Edmund Husserl to mean what appears to consciousness. logic Formal systems of rules of inference. logical atomism View that an ideal philosophical language can be constructed in which basic terms will represent fundamental units of reality, usually attributed to Bertrand Russell and Ludwig Wittgenstein (in his early work). logical positivism Philosophical doctrine that the physical sciences should set the concerns and subject matter of philosophers; epistemological doctrine that a statement is meaningful if it can be said what in perceptual experience would have some bearing on its truth, or ideally, verify or falsify it. manifest image Idea of a world view, attributed to W. Sellars, in which philosophy matches the findings of the relevant sciences. Marxism Intellectual doctrines that derive from the work of Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, who focused on the material conditions and needs of human existence and created an ideology with the goal of distributive justice; in practical politics Marxism is associated with socialist ideals. materialism Doctrine that what is ultimately real is physical. matter Physical stuff or things, the material world.
437
Glo ssar y
meaning The concept (connotation), or thing(s) in the world (denotation), that a word or term symbolizes. mechanism Explanation of reality in terms of causes and effects that do not make reference to anything distinctive about living things, but refer only to the movements of inert objects in space. metaphysics In philosophy, abstract explanations of ordinary things, events, and experience, that refer to entities or processes that are not directly accessible to human perception, but are believed to be foundational for what is perceived. mind What is not matter, pertaining to the conscious human subject, a synonym for soul; the complex of perceptions, ideas, thoughts, emotions, memory, feeling, and self-reflection, considered as a whole. modernity Period of time from about 1800 to 1950 and its corresponding intellectual products; philosophical thought associated with the modern historical period. monad Self-contained, individual unit of awareness or perception, which is the basic unit of substance; in modern philosophy a monad is a single oneness deriving from Gottfried Leibnizs philosophical system. monism Doctrine that there is only one thing in the whole of existence, or that all things are part of the one thing. moral conventionalism View that what is right is what social conventions hold to be right.
moral philosophy In the modern period, all philosophical subjects that pertain to ethics, politics, values, and society. morals In ordinary life, personal behavior that can be judged right or wrong. moral system A theory of the moral rules according to which human beings ought to behave, such as virtue ethics, deontology, or consequentialism. moral theory Abstract branch of philosophical ethics that analyzes meanings of core terms, such as good and right, and which may compare different moral systems. mysterianism Doctrine that we cannot know the ultimate causes or reality of our most important concerns; new mysterianism is the doctrine that we will never know the nature of consciousness or how the mind is related to the body. mysticism System of belief that posits knowledge without logical reasoning processes or sensory experience. mythology In Western intellectual history, term used to refer to accounts, usually poetic or literary, of the nature and actions of ancient deities; broadly used to refer to narratives within a culture pertaining to beliefs that have no scientific foundation. Native American philosophy Broadly construed, the religion and worldviews of indigenous peoples in the Americas, largely transmitted via oral traditions; in philosophy, a new subfield that seeks to present Native American thought and work from Native American perspectives to critique Western philosophy.
438
naturalism Analytic and pragmatic philosophical methodology that seeks explanations and solutions to philosophical problems in ways that are compatible with or derived from scientific explanations. naturalistic fallacy G.E. Moores doctrine that goodness is a non-natural quality so that if one defines it in terms of desired consequences or pleasure, or any other natural property, it can always be asked of something fitting the definition, Is it good? natural kind A type of thing that is naturally formed to be what it is and where all members of the kind share certain characteristics. natural language Human languages developed over time, such as English, Italian, French, German, Chinese, and so forth. natural philosophy Term for early modern physics, astronomy, and proto-chemistry. natural religion Belief in a deity based on combination of reason and experience, rather than revelation. nature The non-human world, or the human idea of the non-human world. necessary causal condition An event or thing that is always present if an effect is present (the effect need not be present if it is present; e.g., oxygen is a necessary condition for fire). necessity Type of connection that is logical in that it cannot be denied without contradiction, or connection between
real events such that effects are inevitable given their causes. Neoplatonism Doctrine from the ancient world, influential throughout philosophical history thereafter, that there exists a transcendental reality in which events determine what happens in this world. nominalism Doctrine that all natural kinds are arbitrarily designated as such by human intellectual concerns and activity and that there are no universals in reality, but only in language; in its modern form, credited to John Locke though Bothius first formulated it, that essences are in the mind and made up by the mind. non-Euclidian geometry Coherent geometries with principles other than those laid down by Euclid, allowing, e.g., that parallel lines meet and angles in triangles add up to less than 180 degrees; geometric revolution in the nineteenth century that paved the way for Albert Einsteins theory of general relativity. noumena Things in themselves that are not directly perceived or describable by us, contrasted by Immanuel Kant with phenomena, which we can perceive. numerology Ancient doctrine, attributed to Pythagoras and his followers, that numbers are real entities, present throughout reality, in ways that determine the non-numerical properties of things. objective Independent of the mind, as in objective reality; in human discourse, a lack of bias; in science, the presumption that the same experiments will yield the same data to different observers.
439
Glo ssar y
objectivism Philosophical system developed by Ayn Rand based on the existence of an external objective world and belief that that the Aristotelian law of identity, A is A, yields a metaphysical truth about that world. observation Perceptual process, with or without the use of manmade instruments (e.g., thermometers, cameras), for recording what happens. occasionalism Causal doctrine attributed to Nicolas Malebranche and others that because we cannot perceive causal connections, there are none in reality, although they do exist in the mind of God. One, the In Neoplatonism, ultimate ontological, ruling, moral and unified basis of existence that is itself separate from existence and/or may be expressed in it. ontological argument Proof for the existence of God, used by Ren Descartes and others, that proceeds from Gods qualities, as we think them, to his necessary existence. ontology The science and study of what exists, pursued as a distinct inquiry, or of what is believed to exist, in a specific domain of inquiry, pursued as a distinct inquiry. Martin Heidegger treated ontology in the first sense, W.V.O. Quine in the second. ordinary language philosophy View developed by Ludwig Wittgenstein in his later writings that ordinary language assigns varieties of meanings through usage in different contexts, and that the analysis of ordinary language can yield solutions
to many traditional philosophical problems. other minds, problem of The problem of how we know that other people have minds, since we cannot directly experience the mind of another as that person experiences it. paradigm According to Thomas Kuhn, a paradigm is an agreed upon set of beliefs in a mature science that determines the ontology of the field, its experimental methods, and appropriate objects of study. Used more loosely after Kuhn, a paradigm is any dominant worldview, in any area of human activity. particulars Concrete, variable instances of something. patriarchy Feminist notion of rule by the fathers as a social principle that has historically been oppressive to women. phenomena The appearances of things or things as they show themselves; evidence; in Heideggerian philosophy, that which shows itself to man. phenomenalism Logical atomist or logical positivist view that material objects are made up of sense data. phenomenology Philosophical methodology, attributed to Edmund Husserl, in which the structures, processes, and intentional objects of consciousness are observed and analyzed. philosophes Term for French intellectuals whose work preceded and influenced the French Revolution, usually including Diderot, Montesquieu, Rousseau, Voltaire, and others.
440
philosophy of biology New twentieth century subfield in philosophy of science that addresses the distinct nature of living things and the scientific questions and methodologies that characterize biology. philosophy of science Study of the principles used for scientific discovery and theory construction, as well as progress in science. Philosophy of science may and has been both descriptive and prescriptive. phrenology The now-held-to-be-pseudoscientific views of F.J. Gall that a persons psychological traits were evident by the bumps and other configurations on the surface of the skull. phronesis Practical wisdom; in ancient Greece, both good judgment in ordinary affairs and knowledge of the ultimate goods and ends of life. Platonism Systems of thought or ideas deriving from Plato, according to which there are transcendent entities that support the existence of, and are the ideals or essences of, every kind of thing in the world that humans experience. pleasure principle Utilitarian principle that pleasure is the greatest value, and moral goodness consists in increasing pleasure for the greatest number of sentient beings. pluralism Pluralistic views of thought accept different belief systems and methodologies for arriving at truth; pluralism in political theory advocates a multiplicity of perspectives and groups with different agendas and interests, democratically coexisting in society; plu-
ralism in ontology holds that there is more than one type of thing in a given domain. positivism View developed by Auguste Comte that social sciences should use mathematics, explanation has the same logical structure as prediction, and social science findings can be used to solve major problems of governing and society. possible Not logically contradictory to imagine; what is possible in events need not be probable or likely. post-modernism Also known as poststructuralism or deconstructionism, the continental school of thought after Jacques Lacan, principally attributed to Jacques Derrida, in which meanings are considered dependent on other symbols in an unstable system. pragmatism American philosophy, known for an analysis of experience and social relevance; a method that analyzes experience as an interactive process between the conscious subject and the world. pre-formationism Pre-modern biological theory that sperm and eggs contain miniature versions of fully developed humans or animals. Presocratics Literally, those philosophers who lived before Socrates; Greek philosophers from the seventh to fifth century B.C.E., who are viewed as the originators/founders of both Western science and Western philosophy. prime mover Aristotles idea of the ultimate cause of the universe, posited because without it causal chains would
441
Glo ssar y
be infinite; interpreted theologically as an argument for Gods existence. probability Likelihood of an event happening; standard for prediction that is considered reliable, although it falls short of certainty; theory of how probability is assigned, the logic of likelihood. process philosophy Usually attributed to A.N. Whitehead, an ontological perspective that reality and everything in it is made up of events, instead of stable entities; method of analysis whereby what were believed to be things, turn out to be events or happenings over time. proof A process involving the manipulation of symbols, which is required to proceed in a certain way in mathematics or logic, for the conclusion to be justified; whenever the conclusion of an argument cannot be false if its premises are true. proper name The name of an individual that is not usually believed to have any meaning beyond its reference to that individual; e.g., Naomi Zack and Ed DAngelo are proper names. proposition The meaning of a sentence. qualities In ancient philosophy, qualities were considered accidents of substances. In early modern philosophy, a distinction was made between primary and secondary qualities. Primary qualities were mass, size, velocity, number of atoms, etc., whereas secondary qualities were color, odor, sound, etc.; the primary qualities were believed to cause the secondary qualities of perceptions as the result of the effects of the atoms in perceptible objects on sense organs.
quietism Withdrawal from the world based on intellectual reasons, such as in ancient skepticism, the impossibility of knowledge. race(s) Group or groups of human beings believed to be different biologically and culturally; the biological difference now believed not to have scientific support; the cultural difference accepted as a fact of social reality. rationalism Doctrine opposed to empiricism, according to which knowledge about the world can be present or developed by means of reason, without prior experience. rationality Good sense, following the rules of logic and accepting available evidence in forming beliefs and making decisions about action. realism Nave realism is the philosophical version of the ordinary belief in the existence of an external physical world, which common sense philosophers think requires no special proof; in medieval philosophy, the belief that universals exist apart from particular objects that are similar, or exist in those objects. reductionism Doctrine that some things are nothing but other more fundamental or perceptible things, as in reducing material objects to atoms or sense data; methodological principle of explanation, whereby one statement or theory is reduced to another if it can be logically derived from it; e.g., the reduction of statements about chemical interactions in chemistry to statements about atoms in physics.
442
reference Process by which a symbol or sign points to or designates an object; for example, a road sign (Tulsa City next exit) refers to a town along the road. relativism Descriptive moral doctrine that different circumstances, agents, and cultures have different and often conflicting rules of behavior or value; prescriptive moral doctrine that there are no universal rules of behavior or human values. research program Concept of scientific progress and change, developed by Imre Lakatos, encompassing both research activity and scientific theory; progressive research programs need few ad hoc hypotheses, while degenerative ones need increasing numbers of ad hoc hypotheses to provide explanations of data. rhetoric The art or skill of speaking or writing to persuade or impress listeners or readers. rights Legal conditions necessary to preserve a prior condition of human worth and dignity, as in universal rights, property rights, rights to free speech, and rights to own property. scholasticism Tradition of commentary on ancient sources in relation to thencontemporary philosophical problems, or in relation to Christian theology, practiced during the medieval period. science Precise, rigorous, and formal system of thought and study of the world, including human beings, which in Aristotelian and Cartesian thought was believed to yield certain knowledge, but by the modern period was accepted as most probable knowledge. Since the nineteenth century the sciences have been
divided into the physical sciences (e.g., physics, astrology, mathematics, chemistry, geology, biology) and the social sciences (e.g., psychology, sociology, anthropology, history), with more theoretical agreement and precision about data attributed to the physical sciences. scientific revolution The beginning of modern empirical science, in practice and theory, during the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, following the Copernican revolution and epitomized by Isaac Newton; term used by Thomas Kuhn to refer to radical change in perspective within a scientific field. semantics Meanings or theory of meaning. sense data Sensory impressions of different senses (e.g., greenness, hardness, coldness) directly experienced in the present; believed by logical positivists to be the foundation of empirical knowledge. sex Traditionally, the biological difference between males and females; sexual activity; in early modern and postmodern feminism, male or female sex was believed to be the result of male or female gender that was determined by social roles and hierarchies. sexism Term used during early Second Wave (19601980) feminism to refer to contempt, bias, aversion, or other devaluation of women based solely on their sex. skepticism Doubt about otherwise plausible claims, as in skepticism about the existence of the external world or other minds. Before the modern period, skepticism was often used to show that knowledge was impossible so that other men-
443
Glo ssar y
tal attitudes, such as quietude or faith, could be pursued. Academic skepticism was the view that no knowledge is possible, pyrrhonic skepticism the view that we cannot know whether any knowledge is possible. social contract theory Foundational theory for modern democratic government, attributed to Hobbes, Locke, Rousseau, and others, according to which legitimate government requires the original explicit or implied consent of those governed. The contract may be between subjects and rulers or among subjects to designate rulers. Social Darwinism Late-nineteenth century application of principles of Darwinian evolution to human society, stressing competition and survival of the fittest, often used or misused to support social inequality and advocate eugenics programs. social philosophy Analysis of problems and meanings in culture and society; theories for public policy. solipsism Doctrine that I cannot know anything except my own mind and its contents; doctrine that I cannot know that anything exists beyond myself and my mind. sophism Form of rhetoric in ancient Greece whereby either side of an argument could be taken up; also associated with cultural relativism and cosmopolitanism during that time. soul Immaterial part of the self, considered paramount for morality and identity, and which may or not be believed to survive death.
soundness A sound argument is in accordance with the rules of logic, so it is valid, and its premises are also true, so that its conclusion is true. space According to Isaac Newton, space is an objective reality; according to Immanuel Kant it is a condition for human experience. speciesism Animal rights activists and theorists designation of the view that human beings are of greater value than other life forms. Some believe specieism to be as unjust as racism or sexism. state of nature An historical or hypothetical human condition, without or before civil government, usually posited to justify the need for a particular type of government, in social contract theory. stoicism Beginning in ancient Greece, doctrine of accepting or withdrawing from what the individual cannot control; associated with universal humanism and cosmopolitanism. structuralism Philosophical and social theory that takes psychic or social structures as its subject matter. subjectivism Belief or implication that knowledge is completely dependent on the wants, needs, experience, or distortions of each individual. substance According to Aristotle and medieval philosophers, a living thing or other being that can exist independently; ultimate substratum of reality, as in Ren Descartess material and immaterial substances; category of thought according to Immanuel Kant. The idea of substance as underlying substratum was
444
rejected by empirical philosophers beginning with John Locke. sufficient cause Something that if present always has a certain effect, although it need not be present whenever the effect is. sufficient reason The principle of sufficient reason states that all things that exist must have causes that necessitate them. sufism Mystical branch of Islam. symbolic order The arrangement of language and other symbols in a culture that mediate all human psychic activities and is a source of meaning generally. One subject of structuralism. synthetic truth A statement that is true of the world. teleological Determined by a future end, goal, or purpose. theism Belief in transcendental or nonnatural beings or god(s). theology A rational system of thought that has a particular religion as its subject; for example, Christian theology, or Jewish theology. theoretical terms Symbols for unobserved, or even unobservable entities that are posited in scientific theories in order to explain what can be observed. theory A linguistic system that can be used to explain experience, although everything asserted in the theory may not have a foundation in experience.
time Aristotle defined time as a measurement of events. Since then, distinctions have been made between objective time as measured by clocks, time as a condition of perceptual experience (Immanuel Kant), and time as subjective experience (Henri Bergson), and time as constructed by the human apprehension of past, present, and future (Martin Heidegger). Bertrand Russell said that it was a contingent matter that we remember the past instead of the future. token-type distinction The type is the general kind, the token an instance of it, as in dogs and my dog, Maggy. tragedy A dramatic genre that dates before the time of Aristotle in which the hero is a good man who makes an error, from which his doom ensues. Tragedy has universal themes and a plot that is determined by events within the play. It moves the audience to great pity and fear that, according to Aristotle, provokes a process of catharsis. transcendental argument Philosophical method attributed to Immanuel Kant of determining what must be true for human beings to be able to have the kind of experience they do; this process of transcendental deduction is rigorous in that it does not posit more than is necessary to account for experience. transcendentalism Positing entities that exist separately from experience; New England transcendentalism was a nineteenth century philosophical and literary movement that combined romantic ideas of the individual in natural environments with philosophical ideas from both Plato and Immanuel Kant.
445
Glo ssar y
truth In modern analytic philosophy, a quality of statements or propositions. A statement is true according to the correspondence theory of truth if it accurately represents reality; in the coherence theory, true statements are compatible or consistent with other accepted knowledge. universal grammar Innate grammar present in all human beings, enabling them to learn a finite number of natural languages, as posited in different formulations by Noam Chomsky. universals General terms like cat and dog. From ancient Greek through early modern philosophy there was a debate about whether universals themselves were real or only particulars were real, or universals were real insofar as they existed in particulars. utilitarianism Moral system attributed to Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill holding that an action is good if it promotes the greatest happiness for the greatest number, whereby everyone counts as one unit and no one counts for more than one. utopia Theory or imaginary depiction of an ideal human society which does not exist; the term was coined by Thomas More whose novel of the same name depicted an ideal society that existed
nowhere, derived from the Greek words ou, meaning not, and topos, meaning place. Mores novel makes frequent mention of Platos Republic, perhaps the first example of a utopian society in the history of philosophy. validity Characteristic of an argument that proceeds according to rules of logic. value Something worth having, striving for, or retaining, which has intrinsic, usually non-monetary worth, or imparts such worth to other things. verificationism Logical positivist doctrine that the meaning of a sentence is how it would be verified or falsified in perceptual experience and that only sentences that can be verified or falsified by perception are meaningful. vice Trait of character considered immoral or unethical, or a disposition to behave in such ways. virtue Trait of character considered excellent or morally good, or a disposition to behave in such ways. vitalism Scientifically outdated view of a life force accounting for what is distinct about living things and their abilities to reproduce themselves, which was largely put to rest by James Watson and Francis Cricks discovery of the model of DNA.
446
Select Bibliography
More extensive lists of primary sources are given in the text of the chapters. The sources below are for the key figures and subjects. The most up-to-date, in-print editions have been selected. Many recent compilations do not have the same titles as the original works, although they contain the original works. Many of the classic sources and other important philosophical texts are available free online at Project Gutenberg: http://www.gutenberg.org/wiki/Main_Page. Wikipedia, the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, and other free sources listed in online searches have entries for many of the philosophers and schools of thought covered in this book, but all secondary sources should be checked against primary sources by scholarly students. Websites for environmental philosophy include: The International Association for Environmental Philosophy, http://www.environmentalphilosophy.org/; Erratic ImpactThe Philosophy of Nature, http://www.erraticimpact.com/~ecologic/; The Center for Environmental Philosophy, http://www.cep.unt.edu/centerfo.html; and The International Society for Environmental Ethics, http://www.cep.unt.edu/ISEE.html.
THE BASICS
One-Volume Histories of Philosophy Durant, Will. The Story of Philosophy: From Plato to Voltaire and the French Enlightenment (read by Grover Gardner) 9 CDs. Audio Partner Publishing Company, 2004. Popkin, Richard H. The Columbia History of Philosophy. New York: Columbia University Press, 1999. Russell, Bertrand. History of Western Philosophy. New York: Simon & Schuster, 1967, Routledge Classics, 2004.
447
For a continental history of philosophy, from the ancient Greeks through Heidegger, see: Schrmann, Reiner. Broken Hegemonies. tr. by Reginald Lilly. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 2003. For a general account of some philosophers lives, see: Sharfstein, B.A. The Philosophers: Their Lives and the Nature of Their Thought, New York: Oxford University Press, 1980.
ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY
Greek Pre-Socratics Burnet, John. Early Greek Philosophy. Meridian Books, New York, 1957. Colli, Giorgio. The Greek Wisdom (La Sapienza greca). 3 vols. Milan 19771980. Curd, Patricia, ed. A Presocratics Reader. Indianpolis, IN: Hackett, 1996. Kirk, G.S., J.E. Raven, and M. Schofield. The Presocratic Philosophers, 2nd ed. Cambridge University Press, 1983. The Sophists Guthrie, W.K.C. Vol. 3 of History of Greek Philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1969. Jarratt, Susan C. Rereading the Sophists: Classical Rhetoric Refigured, Carbondale & Edwardsville: Southern Illinois University Press, 1991. Plato Cooper, John M., and D.H. Dutchinson, eds. Plato, Complete Works. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Co., 1997. Grube, B.M.A. Platos Thought. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Co., 1980. Aristotle Aristotle. Selections (from all major works). Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Co., 1995. Aristotle. Nicomachean Ethics. Terrence Irwin, tr. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Co., 2000. Robinson, Timothy A. Aristotle in Outline. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Co., 1995. Hellenistic and Roman Philosophy Epicurus. The Epicurus Reader. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Co., 1994. Fanthan, Elaine, et. al. Women in the Classic World. New York: Oxford University Press, 1994.
448
Inwood, Brad, and Lloyd P. Gerson, eds. Hellenistic Philosophy: Introductory Readings. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Co., 1999. Inwood, Brad, and Lloyd P. Gerson, eds. The Stoic Reader. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Co., 2008. Women Philosophers in Ancient Greece and Rome Elaine Fanthan, et. al. Women in the Classic World, New York: Oxford University Press, 1994. Ward, Julie K., ed. Feminism and Ancient Philosophy. New York: Routledge, 1996.
Se le ct B i b li o g rap hy
449
450
Medicine and Philosophy Burton, Robert. The Anatomy of Melancholy. William H. Gass, ed. New York: New York Review of Books, 2001. Gregory, Andrew. Harveys Heart: The Discovery of Blood Circulation. Cambridge, UK: Icon Books, 2001. Nutton, Vivia. Ancient Medicine: Sciences of Antiquity. New York: Routledge, 2004. Ragner, Louis N. A History of Medicine. Boca Raton, FL: Taylor & Francis, 2005.
Se le ct B i b li o g rap hy
451
452
453
Se le ct B i b li o g rap hy
Fichte, Johann Gottleib. The Science of Knowledge. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1982. Materialism, Marxism, and Anarchists Engels, Friedrich. The Condition of the Working Class in England. New York: Penguin Classics, 1987. Kropotkin, Peter. Mutual Aid: A Factor of Evolution. London: Freedom Press, 1987. Marx, Karl. Selected Writings. Lawrence H. Simon, ed. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1994. Wartofsky, Marx W. Feuerbach. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1977. Woodcock, George. Anarchism: A History of Libertarian Ideas and Movements. Peterborough, Ontario: Broadview, 2004. Psychology and Social Theory Brentano, Franz Clemens. Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint. Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press, 1973. Chisholm, Robert M. Brentano and Meinong Studies. New York: Rodopi Press, 1982. Dilthey, Wilhelm. Descriptive Psychology and Historical Understanding. The Hague, Netherlands: Nijhoff, 1977. Durkheim, Emile. Suicide: A Study in Sociology. New York: Free Press,(Simon and Schuster) 1979. Freud, Sigmund. The Psychopathology of Everyday Life. New York: A.A. Brill, 2005. Freud, Sigmund. The Interpretation of Dreams. Nu Vision Publications (www. nuvision.com), 2007. Simmel, Georg. The Philosophy of Money, New York: Routledge, 1978. Weber, Max. The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism. North Chelmsford, MA: Dover Courier, 2003.
CONTINENTAL PHILOSOPHY
Existentialism Useful general overviews are: Barnes, Hazel. An Existentialist Ethics. New York: Knopf 1967. Arendt, Hannah, The Human Condition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press (1958). Barrett, William. Irrational Man: A Study in Existential Philosophy. Garden City: Doubleday, 1962. Kaufmann, Walter. Existentialism from Dostoevsky to Sartre. Cleveland: Meridian Books, 1968. McBride, William, ed. The Development and Meaning of Twentieth Century Existentialism. New York: Garland Publishers, 1997. Warnock, Mary. Existentialist Ethics. London: Macmillan & Co., 1967.
454
Primary existentialist texts are: Beauvoir, Simone de. The Second Sex. H.M. Parshley, tr. New York: Vintage Books, 1989. Buber, Martin. Between Man and Man. Ronald Gregor Smith, tr. New York: Macmillan, 1978. Buber, Martin. I and Thou. Walter Kaufmann, tr. New York: Scribner, 1970. Camus, Albert. The Myth of Sisyphus and Other Essays. Justin OBrien, tr., New York: Knopf, 1955. Camus, Albert. The Stranger. Matthew Ward, tr. New York: Knopf, 1988. Dostoevsky, Fyodor. The Brothers Karamazov: The Constance Garnett Translation Revised by Ralph E. Matlaw. New York: Norton, 1976. Jaspers, Karl. Reason and Existenz. William Earle, tr. New York: Noonday Press, 1968. Kierkegaard, Sren. The Essential Kierkegaard. Howard V. Hong and Edna H. Hong, eds. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2000. Kierkegaard, Sren. Concluding Unscientific Postscript. David Swenson and Walter Lowrie, trs. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1971. Kierkegaard, Sren. Fear and Trembling. Howard V. Hong and Edna H. Hong, trs. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1983. Marcel, Gabriel. The Philosophy of Existentialism. New York: Citadel Press, 1968. Marcel, Gabriel. Being and Having. Katherine Farrer, tr., London: Westminster, 1949. Nietzsche, Friedrich. On the Genealogy of Morals. Walter Kaufmann, tr., New York: Vintage Books, 1969. Nietzsche, Friedrich. The Gay Science. Walter Kaufmann, tr. New York: Vintage Books, 1974. Nietzsche, Friedrich. Thus Spoke Zarathustra, in The Portable Nietzsche. Walter Kaufmann, tr. New York: Viking Press, 1975. Sartre, Jean-Paul. Nausea. Lloyd Alexander, tr. New York: New Directions, 1965. Sartre, John Paul. Being and Nothingness. Hazel Barnes, tr. New York: Washington Square Press, 1992. Sartre, Jean-Paul. Search for a Method. Hazel Barnes, tr. New York: Vintage Books, 1968. Tillich, Paul. The Courage to Be. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2000. Wahl, Jean. A Short History of Existentialism. Forrest Williams and Stanley Maron, trs. New York: Philosophical Library, 1949. Phenomenology Arendt, Hannah, Heidegger at Eighty, in Heidegger and Modern Philosophy, Michael Murray, ed., New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1978. Heidegger, M., Being and Time. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson, trs. New York: Harper & Row, 1962.
455
Se le ct B i b li o g rap hy
Husserl, Edmund. Logical Investigations. Dermot Moran, J.N. Findlay, and Michael Dummet, eds. New York: Routledge, 2001. Lacan, Jacques. Psychology. Sean Horner, ed. New York: Routledge, 2005. Merleau-Ponty, M. Adventures of the Dialectic. Joseph Bien, tr. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1973. Saussure, Ferdinand. Course in General Linguistics. New York: McGraw Hill, 1966. Critical Theory and Structuralism Poster, M. Existential Marxism in Postwar France: From Sartre to Althusser. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1975. Ricoeur, P. Freud and Philosophy: An Essay on Interpretation. Denis Savage, tr. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1970. Ricoeur, P. Oneself as Another. Kathleen Blamey, tr. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995. Wigershaus, Paul. The Frankfurt School: Its History, Theories, and Political Significance. Boston: MIT Press, 1995.
AMERICAN PHILOSOPHY
For a general overview of American Philosophy, see: Kuklick, Bruce. A History of Philosophy in America 17202000. New York: Oxford University Press, 2001. Early American Philosophical Strains Emerson, Ralph Waldo. The Essential Writings of Ralph Waldo Emerson, Brooks Atkinson, and Mary Oliver, eds. New York: Modern Library Classics, 2000. Gill, Jerry H. Native American World Views: An Introduction, Amherst NY: Humanities Books, 2002. Pirsig, Robert. Lila. New York: Bantam, 1992. Snider, Denton J. St. Louis Movement in Philosophy, Literature, Education, Psychologywith Chapters of Autobiography. Sterling, VA: Thoemmes Press, 2001 Thoreau, Henry David. The Portable Thoreau. Carl Bode, ed. New York: Penguin Classics, 1964. Pragmatism and Process Philosophy Dewey, John. Dewey and His Critics, Essays from The Journal of Philosophy. Sidney Morgenbesser, ed. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1977. James, William. Pragmatism. Bruce Kuklick, ed. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1981. Lewis, Clarence Irving. Mind and the World Order: Outline of a Theory of Knowledge. Mineola, NY: Dover Books on Western Philosophy, 1991.
456
Peirce, Charles S. The Essential Peirce: Selected Philosophical Writings, 18931913. Peirce Edition Project, Nathan Houser, and Jonathan R. Eller, eds. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 1998. Royce, Josiah. The Philosophy of Josiah Royce. John K. Roth, ed. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1982. Santayana, George. Persons and Places. William G. Holzberger, Herman J. Saatkamp, Jr., and Richard C. Lyon, eds. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1988. White, Alfred North. Process and Reality. New York: The Free Press, 1978.
Se le ct B i b li o g rap hy
ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY
Early Twentieth Century Analytic Philosophy Feferman, Anita Burdman, and Solomon Feferman. Alfred Tarski: Life and Logic. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge Concise Histories, 2008. Levy, Paul. Moore: G.E. Moore and the Cambridge Apostles. New York: Oxford Paperbacks, 1981. Moore, G.E. Philosophical Studies. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2007. Russell, Bertrand. The Basic Writings of Bertrand Russell. New York: Routledge, 2002. Smith, Peter. An Introduction to Gdels Theorems (Cambridge Introductions to Philosophy). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2007. Wittgenstein, Ludwig. Tractatus Logico Philosophicus. New York: Routledge Classics, 2001. Logical Positivism Ayer, A.J. Language Truth and Logic. New York: Penguin Modern Classics, 2001. Carnap, Rudolf. The Logical Structure of the World and Pseudoproblems in Philosophy. Peru, IL: Open Court Classics, 2003. Schlick, Moritz. General Theory of Knowledge. New York: Library of Exact Philosophy, 1985. Stadler, Friedrich. The Vienna Circle: Studies in the Origin, Development, and Influence of Logical Empiricism. New York: Sprnger-Verlag Wien, 2001. Ordinary Language Analysis Anscombe, G.E.M. Human Life, Action and Ethics: Essays by G.E.M. Anscombe (St. Andrews Studies in Philosophy & Public Affairs). Exeter, UK: Imprint Academic, 2006. Austin, J.L. How to Do Things with Words, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1975. Bouwsma, O.K. Philosophical Essays. Kansas City, KS: Landmark Edition, 1982. Malcolm, Norman. Ludwig Wittgenstein: A Memoir. New York: Oxford University Press, 2001.
457
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. Philosophical Investigations: The German Text, with a Revised English Translation, 50th Anniversary Commemorative Edition. London: Blackwell, 2003. Analytic Ethics Foot, Philippa. Natural Goodness. New York: Oxford University Press, 2002. MacIntyre, Alastair. After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2007. Moore, G.E. Principia Ethica (Principles of Ethics). Mineola, NY: Philosophical Classics, Dover, 2004. Smith, Tara. Ayn Rands Normative Ethics: The Virtuous Egoist. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2007. Smart, J.J.C., and Bernard Williams. Utilitarianism: For and Against. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1973. Scheffler, Israel. The Rejection of Consequentialism. New York: Oxford University Press, 1995. Stevenson, Charles L. Facts and Values: Studies in Ethical Analysis. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1963. Analytic Political Philosophy Berlin, Isaiah. The Proper Study of Mankind: An Anthology of Essays. New York: Farrar, Straus, Giroux, 2000. Nozick, Robert. Anarchy, State and Utopia. London: Blackwell, 2003. Popper, Karl. The Open Society and its Enemies. New York: Routledge Classics, 2002. Rawls, John. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971. Strauss, Leo. Liberalism Ancient and Modern. New York: Harper Collins, 1995. Epistemology and Metaphysics after Logical Positivism Goodman, Nelson. Fact, Fiction and Forecast. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2006. Putnam, Hilary. Pragmatism: An Open Question. London: Blackwell, 2000. Quine, W.V.O. From a Logical Point of View: Nine Logico-Philosophical Essays. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2006. Sellars, Wilfred. Science, Perception and Reality. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Publishing 1963. Strawson, P.F. The Bounds of Sense: An Essay on Kants Critique of Pure Reason. New York: Routledge, 1990. Philosophy of Science
458
Feyerabend, Paul. Against Method: Outline of an Anarchistic Theory of Knowledge. Brooklyn, NY: Verso, 1993.
Kuhn, Thomas. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990. Lakatos, Imre. Proofs and Refutations: The Logic of Mathematical Discovery. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1976. Lewontin, Richard. The Triple Helix: Gene, Organism, and Environment. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000. Nagel, Ernest. The Structure of Science. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1979. Popper, Karl. The Logic of Scientific Discovery. New York: Routledge, 2002. Reichenbach, Hans. Experience and Prediction. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2006. Philosophy of Mind and Philosophy of Language Chomsky, Noam. Reflections on Language. New York: Pantheon, 1975. Churchland, Paul. Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1979. Dreyfus, H. What Computers Cant Do: The Limits of Artificial Intelligence. New York: Harper Colophon, 1979. Fodor, Jerry Alan. The Mind Doesnt Work That Way: The Scope and Limits of Computational Psychology. Boston, MA: MIT Press, 2000. Nagel, Thomas. The View from Nowhere. New York: Oxford University Press, 1986. Ryle, Gilbert. The Concept of Mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2000. Schwartz, Stephen P., ed. Naming, Necessity and Natural Kinds. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1977. Skinner, B.F. Verbal Behavior. New York: Prentice Hall, 1957. Turing, Alan Mathison. The Essential Turing. New York: Oxford University Press, 2004. Watson, J.B. Behaviorism. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers, 1997.
Se le ct B i b li o g rap hy
NEW PHILOSOPHY
Postmodern Philosophy Baudrillard, Jean. Simulacra and Simulation. Shiela Faria Glaser, ed. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1994. Deleuze, Gilles, Felix Guattari and Brian Massumi. A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press, 1987. Derrida, Jacques. Philosophy Guidebook to Derrida on Deconstruction. Barry Stocker, ed. New York: Routledge, 2006. Findlayson, James Gordon. Habermas: A Very Short Introduction. New York: Oxford University Press, 2005. Lyotard, Jean Francois. The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge. Frederic Jameson, ed. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press, 1984.
459
Rorty, Richard. Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1989.
460
Outlaw, Lucius. On Race and Philosophy. New York: Routledge, 1996. Roberts, Rodney C., ed. Injustice and Rectification. New York: Peter Lang Publishers, 2002. Thomas, Laurence. Vessels of Evil: American Slavery and the Holocaust. Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press, 1993. West, Cornel. Prophesy Deliverance! An Afro-American Revolutionary Christianity. Westminster, PA: John Knox Press, 1982. Yancy, George, ed. African-American Philosophers, 17 Conversations. New York: Routledge, 1998. Zack, Naomi. Thinking about Race. Belmont, CA: Thomson Wadsworth, 2006. Native American Philosophy Allen, Paula Gunn. The Sacred Hoop. Boston, MA: Beacon Press, 1992. Cordova, V.F. How It Is: The Native American Philosophy of V.F. Cordova. Linda Hogan, Kathleen Dean Moore, Kurt Peters, and Ted Jojoba, eds. Tucson, AZ: University of Arizona Press, 2007. Cotton, Angela L., and Christa Acampora Crista Davis, eds. Cultural Sites of Critical Insight: Philosophy, Aesthetics, and African American and Native American Womens Writings. New York: SUNY Press, 2007. Waters, Anne. American Indian Thought: Philosophical Essays. London: Blackwell, 2003. Weaver, Jace. Defending Mother Earth: Native American Perspectives on Environmental Justice. Maryknoll, NY: Orbis Books, 1996. Latin American Philosophy Alcoff, Linda, and Eduardo Mendieta. Thinking from the Underside of History: Enrique Dusells Philosophy of Liberation. Lanham, MD: Roman & Littlefield, 2000. Gracia, Jorge J.E., and Elizabeth Millan-Zaibert, eds. Latin American Philosophy for the 21st Century: The Human Condition, Values, and the Search for Identity. Buffalo, NY: Prometheus Books, 2003. Mendieta, Eduardo. Global Fragments: Critical Theory, Latin America and Globalizations. New York: SUNY Press, 2007. Nuccetelli, Susana. Latin American Thought: Philosophical Problems and Arguments. Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 2002. Schutte, Ofelia. Cultural Identity and Social Liberation in Latin American Thought. New York: SUNY Press, 1993.
Se le ct B i b li o g rap hy
461
Asante, Molefi. The Afrocentric Idea. Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press, 1998. Bernal, Martin. Black Athena: The Afroasiatic Roots of Classical Civilization. 3 vols. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press, 19872006. Gordon, Lewis R. Her Majestys Other Children: Sketches of Racism from a Neocolonial Age. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 1997. Gyeke, Kwame. Tradition and Modernity. New York: Oxford University Press, 1997. Eze, Emmanuel, ed. Postcolonial African Philosophy. London: Blackwell, 1997. Hountondji, Paulin J. African Philosophy: Myth and Reality. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 1996. Mbiti, John. African Religions and Philosophy. New York: Doubleday, 1970. Mosley, Albert, ed. African Philosophy: Selected Readings. New York: Prentice Hall, 1995. Serequeberhan Tsenay, ed. African Philosophy: The Essential Readings. New York: Paragon House, 1991. Buddhism and Confucianism Abe, Masao, and Steven Hein. Zen and Comparative Studies. Honolulu, HI: University of Hawaii Press, 1997. Bo Mu, Bo. Comparative Approaches to Chinese Philosophy. Farnham, Surrey, UK: Ashgate Publishing, 2003. Cheng, Chung-Ying. New Dimensions of Confucian and Neo-Confucian Philosophy. New York: SUNY Press, 1991. Ivanhoe, Philip J. Ethics in the Confucian Tradition: The Thought of Mengzi and Wang Yangming. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 2002. Keown, Damien. The Nature of Buddhist Ethics. Basingstoke, Hampshire, UK: Palgrave Macmillan, 2001. Li-Hsiang, Lisa Rosenlee, Confucianism and Women: A Philosophical Interpretation, Roger T. Ames, ed. New York: SUNY Press, 2006. Lusthaus, Dan. Buddhist Phenomenology: A Philosophical Investigation of Yogacara Buddhism. New York: Routledge, Chapman, & Hall, 1997. Norden, Bryan W. van. Confucius and the Analects: New Essays. New York: Oxford University Press, 2002. Rosenlee, Li-Hsiang Lisa. Confucianism and Women: A Philosophical Interpretation. Roger T. Ames, ed. New York: SUNY Press, 2006. Shun Kwong-loi, and David B. Wong, Confucian Ethics: A Comparative Study of Self, Autonomy, and Community, New York: Cambridge University Press, 2004. Suzuki, Daisetz Teitaro. Manuel of Zen Buddhism. New York: Grove, 1960. Yao, Xinzhong and Hsin-chung Yao. An Introduction to Confusianism. Cambridge University Press, 2000.
462
Feminist Philosophy Afshar, Haleh, ed. Women and Politics in the Third World. New York: Routledge, 1996. Alcoff, Linda and Elizabeth Potter, eds. Feminist Epistemologies, New York: Routledge, 1993. Bartke, Sandra Lee. Femininity and Domination. New York: Routledge, 1990. Butler, Judith. Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion of Identity. New York: Routledge, 1990. Beauvoir, Simone de. The Second Sex. New York: Knopf, 1953. Chodorow, Nancy. The Reproduction of Mothering. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1978. Cixous, Hlne. The Hlne Cixous Reader. Susan Sellars and Jacques Derrida, eds. New York: Routledge, 1994. Daly, Mary. The Church and the Second Sex. Boston, MA: Beacon Press, 1986. Digby, Tom, ed. Men Doing Feminism. New York: Routledge, 1998. Friedan, Betty. The Feminine Mystique. New York: W.W. Norton, 1963. Frye, Marilyn. The Politics of Reality: Essays in Feminist Theory. Berkeley, CA: Crossing Press, 1983. Gilligan, Carol. In a Different Voice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1982. Harding, Sandra G. Whose Science? Whose Knowledge: Thinking from Womens Lives. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1991. hooks, bell. Aint I a Woman? Black Women and Feminism. Cambridge, MA: South End Press, 2007. Heyes, Cressida J. in Line Drawings: Defining Women through Feminist Practice. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2000. Hochschild, Arlie Russell, and Anne Machung. The Second Shift. New York: Avon Books, 1990. Irigaray, Luce. The Forgetting of Air in Martin Heidegger (Constructs Series). Mary Beth Mader, tr. Austin, TX: University of Texas Press, 1999. Jagger, Alison M., and Marion Young. A Companion to Feminist Philosophy. London: Blackwell, 2000. Kittay, Eva. Loves Labor: Essays on Women, Equality and Dependence. New York: Routledge, 1999. Kourany, Janet, ed. The Gender of Science, Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall, 2002. Kristeva, Julia. The Kristeva Reader. Toril Moi, ed. New York: Columbia University Press, 1986. Lloyd, Genevieve. The Man of Reason: Male and Female in Western Philosophy. New York: Routledge, 1993. MacKinnon, Catherine (with Andrea Dworkin). Pornography and Civil Rights: A NewDay for Womens Equality. Minneapolis, MN: Organizing against Pornography, 1988.
463
Se le ct B i b li o g rap hy
Marcus, Ruth Barkan. Modalities: Philosophical Essays. New York: Oxford University Press, 1993. Noddings, Nell. Caring: A Feminist Approach to Ethics and Moral Education. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1982. Pateman, Carole. The Sexual Contract. San Francisco, CA: Stanford University Press, 1988. Ruddick, Sara. Maternal Thinking: Toward a Politics of Peace. Boston, MA: Beacon Press, 1990. Slote, Michael A. The Ethics of Care and Empathy. New York: Routledge, 2007. Strikwerda, Robert, and Larry May, eds. Rethinking Masculinity: Philosophical Explorations in Light of Feminism. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 1996. Shrage, Laurie. Abortion and Social Responsibility: Depolarizing the Debate. New York: Oxford University Press, 2003. Spelman, Elizabeth V. in Inessential Woman: Problems of Exclusion in Feminist Thought. Boston, MA: Beacon Press, 1990. Weed, Elizabeth, and Naomi Schor, eds. Feminism Meets Queer Theory. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 1997. Zack, Naomi in Inclusive Feminism: A Third Wave Theory of Womens Commonality. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 2005. Environmental Philosophy Benton, Ted. Natural Relations: Ecology, Animal Rights & Social Justice. Brooklyn, NY: Verso, 1993. Bernstein, Jay. Adorno: Disenchantment and Ethics. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2001. Callicott, Baird, and Roger T. Ames. Nature in Asian Traditions of Thought. New York: SUNY Press, 1989. Callicott, J.B. In Defense of the Land Ethic: Essays in Environmental Philosophy. New York: SUNY Press, 1989. Carson, Rachel. Silent Spring. New York: Houghton Miflin Books, 2002. Clark, S.R.L. The Moral Status of Animals. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press, 1977. Cohen, M.P. The Pathless Way: John Muir and American Wilderness. Milwaukee, WI: University of Wisconsin Press, 1984. Cuomo, Chris. Feminism and Ecological Communities: An Ethic of Flourishing. New York: Routledge, 1997. Dasgupta, Partha. Human Well-being and the Natural Environment. New York: Oxford University Press, 2001. Devall, B., and G. Sessions. Deep Ecology: Living as if Nature Mattered. Layton, UT: Gibbs Smith, 1985. Dobson, A., ed. Fairness and Futurity: Essays on Environmental Sustainability and Social Justice. New York: Oxford University Press, 1999.
464
Gaard, Greta, ed. Ecofeminism: Women, Animals, Nature. Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press, 1993. Goodin, Robert E. Green Political Theory. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press, 1992. Gore, Al. An Inconvenient Truth: The Planetary Emergency of Global Warming and What We Can Do about It. New York: Rodale Press, 2006. Graham, Harvey. Animism: Respecting the Living World. New York: Columbia University Press, 2005. Hill, Thomas E. Ideals of Human Virture and Preserving the Natural Environment, in Ethics, vol. 5. (1983). Jamieson, D., ed. A Companion to Environmental Philosophy. Malden, MA: Blackwell, 2001. Leopold, Aldo. Sand County Almanac. New York: Ballantine Books, 1949. Naess, A. Ecology, Community, Lifestyle. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1989. Nash, R. The Rights of Nature: A History of Environmental Ethics. Madison, WI: University of Wisconsin Press, 1989. Plumwood, V. Environmental Culture. New York: Routledge, 2002. Reagan, Tom. The Case for Animal Rights. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1983. Singer, Peter. Animal Liberation: A New Ethics for Our Treatment of Animals. London, UK: Jonathan Cape, 1983. Vogel, S. Against Nature: The Concept of Nature in Critical Theory. New York: SUNY Press, 1996. Warren, K.L., ed. Ecological Feminism. New York: Routledge, 1994. Westra, Laura, and Bill E. Lawson. Environmental Racism: Confronting Issues of Global Justice. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 2001. Zimmerman, M. Contesting Earths Future: Radical Ecology and Postmodernity. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1994. Other Trends in New Philosophy Allen, Richard and Murray Smith, eds. Film Theory and Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press, 1997. Appiah, Kwame Anthony. Experiments in Ethics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2008. Dennett, Daniel. Sweet Dreams: Philosophical Obstacles to a Science of Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2005. Gaarder, Jostein. Sophies World: A Novel about the History of Philosophy. Berkeley, CA: Berkeley Books, 1994. Higgs, Eric, Andrew Light, and David Strong, eds. Technology and the Good Life. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2000.
465
Se le ct B i b li o g rap hy
McGinn, Colin. The Mysterious Flame: Conscious Minds in a Material World. New York: Basic Books, 1999. Nichols, Shaun, and Joshua Michael Knobe. Experimental Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press, 2008. Wartenberg, Thomas E., and Angela Curran, eds. Philosophy and Film. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell, 2005.
466
Index
Note: (ill.) indicates photos and illustrations.
A
a posteriori knowledge, 32526 a priori knowledge, 220, 221, 32526 a priori speculation, 166 Abe, Masao, 405 Abelard, Peter, 61, 63 (ill.), 6364 abject mother, 413 abolitionism, 3045, 3067, 396 the Absolute, 226, 234, 300 absolute knowledge, 229 absolute motion, 109 absolute place, 109 absolute space, 109 Absolute Spirit, 229 absolute time, 109 abstract thinking, 229 academic Skepticism, 88 Academic Skeptics, 4041 Academy (Plato), 28 acceleration, 99 Achterhuis, Hans, 427 act consequentialism, 356 ad hoc hypotheses, 37475 Adas, Michael, 42627 Addams, Jane, 32022, 321 (ill.) Adorno, Theodore, 285, 286 Aenesidemus, 40 aesthetic theory, 235 aesthetic valuation, 326 aesthetics, 5, 323
affected, 36 African American philosophy biological race, 398 definition of, 396 discrimination, 397 important books, 397 literary themes, 397 racial identity, 39798 African philosophy, 401, 4023 Afshared, Haleh, 417 Aiken, Conrad, 322 air, 15 Akademe, 299 Alberdi, Juan Bautista, 401 Albertus Magnus, 72, 76 (ill.), 7677 alchemy, 11516 Alcmaeon, 11213 Alcoff, Linda, 400, 410 Alcott, Amos Bronson, 299, 300301, 304, 306 Alcott, Louisa May, 300 Alembert, Jean le Rond d, 184, 185 Alexander the Great, 33, 34 Diogenes, 45 end of classical period, 39 Pyrrho of Elis, 40 Algarrotti, Francesco, 110 Alkindus, 66 Allen, Anita, 397 Allen, Paula Gunn, 399, 400 Allen, Richard, 428 Althusser, Louis, 29091
altruism, 212 altruistic suicide, 252 Ambrose, Bishop, 58 American philosophies, 39596. See also African American philosophy; Latin American philosophy; Native American philosophy American philosophy, 255, 295, 307. See also early American philosophy; pragmatism nineteenth-century evolutionary thought, 307 progress, 309 Ammonius Saccas, 50 Amyntas II, King, 33 anachronism, 194 analytic ethics applied ethics, 357 Bloomsbury group, 353 consequentialism, 355, 35658 definition of, 350 emotivist theory of ethics, 35253 ethical egoism, 355 ethical naturalism, 354 ethical relativism, 35152 ethical subjectivism, 353 ethics vs. morals, 350 Foot, Philippa, 354 Hare, R., 356 MacIntyre, Alasdair, 354
467
468
moral conventionalism, 351 moral system vs. moral theory, 350 naturalistic fallacy, 352 objectivism, 355 Rand, Ayn, 35455, 355 (ill.) virtue ethics, 353, 354 analytic philosophy, 5, 331, 334. See also analytic ethics; analytic political philosophy; early twentieth century analytic philosophy; epistemology and metaphysics after logical positivism; logical positivism; ordinary language philosophy; philosophy of language; philosophy of mind; philosophy of science analytic philosophy of mind causal theory of meaning, 381 eliminative materialism, 38283 functionalism, 380 materialism, 378 meaning, 383 Nagel, Thomas, 381 (ill.), 38182 Ryle, Gilbert, 378 Sellars, Wilfred, 380 Turing, Alan Mathison, 383 (ill.), 38384 analytic philosophy of science, 369 analytic political philosophy Berlin, Isaiah, 35859, 359 (ill.) definition of, 358 difference principle, 361 justice, 36061 liberty, 35859 Locke-Nozick solution, 362 Marxist historicism, 359 Nozick, Robert, 362 open society, 360 Popper, Karl, 35960 Rawls, John, 36062
Strauss, Leo, 363 analytic-synthetic distinction, 366, 36869 analytic truths, 32526 anarchism, 236 definition of, 240 Proudhon, Pierre-Joseph, 240 (ill.), 24041 reaction against Hegelianism, 235 anarchist-communism, 243 The Anatomy of Melancholy (Burton), 11718 Anaxagoras basic elements, 13 mind, 18 Pre-Socratics, 12 Anaximander apeiron as primary substance, 15 as main Pre-Socratics, 12 Pre-Socratics, 1415 unbounded, 13 Anaximenes of Miletus as main Pre-Socratics, 12 and revision of theories of Anaximander, 15 unbounded, 13 ancient philosophy, 5, 11. See also Aristotle; Hellenistic and Roman philosophy; Plato; Pre-Socratics; Socrates; Sophists; women philosophers Anders, Gnther, 287 Andronicus of Rhodes, 34 Angelic Doctor, 75 animal rights, 42122 animals, 421 animunculi, 135 Anne, Queen, 159 Anne of Denmark, 123 anomic suicide, 252 Anscombe, Elizabeth, 35657 Anselm of Canterbury, St., 6162, 329 anti-Aristotelianism, 90, 91 antipathy, 175 Antisthenes of Athens, 43 (ill.), 44
apeiron, 15 Apollo, 46 The Apology of Raimond Sebond (Montaigne), 85, 87 Apology (Plato), 2526 aporia, 387 apparitions, 316 appearance, 1718 Appiah, Kwame Anthony, 397, 403, 425 applied ethics, 357 Arcesilaus, 39 arche-writing, 388 Archelaus, 25 Archimedes of Syracuse, 96 Arden, Jane, 183 Arendt, Hannah, 279, 285, 286, 287 (ill.), 28788 Arete of Cyrene, 47 Aristarchus of Samos, 96 Aristides the Just, 23 Aristipus, 47 Aristophanes, 22, 27, 32 Aristotelian idea of God, 7172 Aristotle, 33 (ill.) Abelard, Peter, 6364 Academy (Plato), 28 Albertus Magnus, 76 Alcmaeon, 113 anti-Aristotelianism, 90, 91 appearance, 18 Averros, 69 Avicenna, 66 Christian philosophy, 49 dog, 55 four causes, 36, 37 Gassendi, Pierre, 91 government and politics, 38 ideals of government first theorized by, 7 law of identity, 355 life of, 3334 logic, 35 lost work, 34 main contribution to Western philosophy, 3233
medicine, 112 medieval philosophy, 49 morality, 38 vs. Plato, 35 Prodicus, 23 scientific revolution, 94 sense of humor, 38 syllogism, 35 technology, 425 ten categories of existing things, 36 Thomas Aquinas, 72 unmoved mover, 37 views on women, 153 virtue ethics, 353 virtues, 3738 works of, 3435 writings of, 12 Aristotle Club, 299 Arouet, Franois-Marie. See Voltaire artificial intelligence, 383 Asante, Molefi, 402 Asclepigenia of Athens, 57 Ashe, St. George, 159 Asian philosophy, 4034 Aspasia of Miletus, 46 Astell, Mary, 15455, 182 astrology, 7677 astronomy, 101 ataraxia, 89 atheism, 150 Athenian school, 53 atomic theory, 92, 106 atoms, 42 August, Sophie Charlotte, 13435 Augustine, Saint, 287 Augustine, St., 5759, 58 (ill.) confessional focus of, 82 Confessions, 5859 Please God, make me good (St. Augustine), 59 theology of the Church, 59 Austin, J. L., 345, 346, 349 auto-icon, 176 Averros, 67, 68 (ill.), 6869
Avicenna, 6667, 67 (ill.), 114 awareness, 271 Ayer, A. J., 339, 343, 34445, 353
In d e x
B
Babylonian Captivity, 77 Bacall, Lauren, 343 bachelors, 152 Bacon, Francis, 102 (ill.) British Royal Society, 104 cave, idols of, 102 experimentation, 1023 furthering ideas of, 104 and Hobbes, Thomas, 140 idols of, 102 induction, 102 influence of, 103 life of, 1034 marketplace, idols of, 102 and Mill, John Stuart, 205 Newton, Isaac, 103 scientific revolution, 84, 93, 94, 1012 theatre, idols of, 102 tribe, idols of, 102 Bacon, Nicholas, 103 Bakunin, Mikhail Alexandrovich, 240, 24142 Balfour, Eleanor Mildred, 21415 Barnham, Alice, 103 Barrison, David, 278 Bartke, Sandra Lee, 410 Bateson, Patrick, 423 Baudrillard, Jean, 39293 Baumgarten, Eduard, 278 Baxter, William F., 419, 42122 beauty, 329 Beauvoir, Simone de, 26870, 269 (ill.) as French material feminist, 413 Sade, Marquis de, 198 second wave of feminism, 407 womens movement, 7
Beauvoir, Sylvie Le Bon de, 269 Beccaria, Cesare, 184 becoming-woman, 395 behaviorism, 376, 377 Behn, Alphra, 15354 Being, 276, 28182 Being John Malkovich, 64 Bell, Vanessa, 353 Bellarmine, Cardinal Robert, 99 Beltrami, Eugenio, 219, 221 (ill.) Benedict XVI, Pope, 391 Benjamin, Walter, 285, 286, 287 Bentham, Jeremy, 17475 auto-icon, 176 embalmed body of, 176 hedonic calculus, 17576 moral theory, 215 non-human beings, 420 philosophes, 184 pleasure principle, 206, 207 Principle of Utility, 175 prison reform, 176 Wisdom, John, 348 Benton, Ted, 419 Bergson, Henri, 216 (ill.), 21617 Berkeley, George aberration vs. obstacle, 161 causation, 163 critique of Newtonian science, 164 Edwards, Jonathan, 190 idealism as perplexing, 161 ideas, 162 importance of ideas, 16162 influence on, 16263 Malebranche, Nicolas, death of, 13233 vs. nineteenth-century German idealists, 223 primary vs. secondary qualities, 163 tar water, 164
469
470
To be is to be perceived, 161 tree falling in forest making sound, 164 Vanhomrigh, Esther, 197 vision vs. matter and physical existence, 16061 Berlin, Isaiah, 196, 35859 Bernal, Martin, 402 Bernstein, Jay, 419 Bias of Priene, 11 Bingham, Hiram IV, 287 biological race, 398 birth control medication, 408 birth of tragedy, 26364 blood, 11617 Blood, Fanny, 183, 184 Bloom, Alan, 363 Blcher, Heinrich, 287 Bodin, Jean, 89 Bothius, 5556 Abelard, Peter, 63 as Encyclopedist, 60 Boleyn, Anne, 80 Bollingbroke, Lord, 195 Bolyai, Janos, 219 Bombast von Hohenheim, Philippus Aureolus Theophrastus, 114 Borges, Jorge Luis, 130 Bosanquet, Bernard, 23334 aesthetic theory, 235 community values, 234 idealist doctrine, 234 social philosophy, 23435 Bouwsma, O. K., 345, 347 Boxill, Bernard, 397 Boyle, Robert, 105 (ill.), 1067 atomic theory, 106 founding of chemistry, 6 materialism, 107 method of transdiction, 106 Petty, William, 104 scientific influences of, 106 scientific revolution, 93, 94
bracketing of truth, 276 Bradley, F. H., 21314, 215 Brahe, Tycho, 100, 100 (ill.), 101, 204 Brahms, Johannes, 337 Brentano, Franz empirical psychology, 245 Freud, Sigmund, 248 Heidegger, Martin, 279 Husserl, Edmund, 244, 273 Meinong, Alexius, 244 right and wrong, 245 sense of intentionality, 275 Breuer, Josef, 248 Bricmont, Jean, 394 British Association of Science, 204 British Royal Society, 104 Brokmeyer, Henry C., 298, 299 Brouncker, Lord, 105 Bruno, Giodano, 98 brutal nihilism, 363 Buber, Martin, 270, 271, 317 Buddhism, 4035, 404 (ill.) Burke, Edmund, 19495, 195 (ill.) Burks, Arthur, 311 Burton, Robert, 116 Bush, George W., 363 Butler, Judith, 412
C
cabala, 150 Caine, Michael, 199 Calas, Jean, 187 calculus, 134, 135 Calkins, Mary, 314 Callicott, J. B., 419 Cambridge Apostles, 333 Cambridge Neoplatonists, 150 Cambridge Platoism, 14950 Cambridge Platonists, 190 Campanella, Tommaso, 98 Campbell, Naomi, 344 Camurati, Mireya, 400
Camus, Albert, 27172, 272 (ill.) capitalism, 186, 238, 254 Cardin, Pierre, 198 Carlyle, Thomas, 303, 305, 309 Carnap, Rudolf, 339, 341, 342, 365, 367, 369 Carneades, 40 Carnegie, Andrew, 308 Carson, Rachel, 419 Cartesianism, 130, 19293 categorical imperative, 17980 categorical rule, 179 Catholic Church, 83, 91 causal explanation, 244 causal theory of meaning, 381 causal theory of reference, 409 causation, 13132, 163, 16667, 205 cave, idols of, 102 cave simile, 30 Cavendish, Lord, 13940 Cavendish, Margaret, 107 celestial movement, 99 Census of Hallucinations, 316 central systems, 379 Channing, William Ellery, 300 Charcot, J. M., 248 charioteers, 25 Charles I, King, 104, 117 Charles II, King, 105, 107 Charles the Sledgehammer, 65 Charlton, Walter, 106 Chtelet, Marquise Du, 187 Cheng, Chung-Ying, 406 Chicago, Illinois, 298 childhood experience, 247 children, 427 childrens education, 320 Chilon of Sparta, 11 Chinese philosophy, 4034 Chinese Room Argument, 384 Chisholm, Roderick, 246
Chodorow, Nancy, 410 Chomsky, Noam, 377, 378 (ill.) behaviorism, 377 Derrida, Jacques, 389 founding of cognitive science, 7 Skinner, B. F., 376 theory of language, 37778 Christian European philosophy, 66 Christian philosophy, 57 Christian theology, 57 Christianity, 49, 6566, 265 Christina of Sweden, Queen, 124 Chrusippus, 41 Churchill, Ward, 399 Churchland, Patricia and Paul, 38283 Cicero, 39, 39 (ill.), 41 civil disobedience, 301 Civil Rights Act of 1964, 408 Cixous, Hlne, 413, 415 Clarke, Edward, 14748 classical political philosophy, 363 Cleanthes, 41 Cleobulus of Lindos, 11 Cleveland, Grover, 354 closed circulatory system of blood, 11617 The Clouds (Aristophanes), 27 Cohen, Morris Raphael, 314 coherence, 204 coherence theory of truth, 34243 Coleridge, Samuel Taylor, 130, 303 colligation, 204 colonial period of Latin American philosophy, 401 common sense, 173 common sense philosophy, 33233 communism, 237 community relationships, 270 community values, 234
In d e x
community well-being, 297 comparative philosophy, 401 compulsive heterosexuality, 412 computation, 37980 computer science, 383 Comte, Auguste, 211, 211 (ill.) altruism, 212 first sociologist, 7 positivism, 211 sociological ideas, 21112 conceptualism, 77 Concord School of Philosophy, 29899 Confessions (St. Augustine), 5859 Confucianism, 4057, 406 (ill.) Conley, Berena Andermatt, 415 connotative meaning, 381 consciousness, 127, 225, 229, 26768, 424, 428 consequentialism, 355, 35658 consilience, 204 The Consolation of Philosophy (Bothius), 5556 consummation, 320 contemporary period of Latin American philosophy, 401 continental philosophy, 255. See also critical theory; existentialism; phenomenology; structuralism conversational implicature, 34950 Conway, Anne, 151 Conway, Edward, 151 Copernican Revolution, 178 Copernican system, 100 Copernican theory, 98 Copernicus, Nicolaus calendar, 95 Ptolemaic system, 97 recoinage, 109 scientific revolution, 92, 93, 95 (ill.), 9596 Copleston, Frederick, 344 Cordova, Viola, 399, 400
Cotton, Angela L., 399 Counter-Enlightenment figures, 19194 Burke, Edmund, 19496 lasting effects on philosophy, 191 Sade, Marquis de, 19799, 198 (ill.) Swift, Jonathan, 196 (ill.), 19697 Vico, Giambattista, 19194 County Kilkenny, Ireland, 160 (ill.) covering law model, 371 cranes, 42324 Crates of Thebes, 44 Crick, Francis, 369, 370 critical theory, 255, 28485 Adorno, Theodore, 286 Arendt, Hannah, 287 (ill.), 28788 Benjamin, Walter, 286 Davis, Angela, 288 (ill.), 28889 Frankfurt School, 28485 Fromm, Erich, 289 Gramsci, Antonio, 285 (ill.), 28586 Horkheimer, Max, 286 Marcuse, Herbert, 288 structuralism, 284 Cromwell, Oliver, 153 Crummell, Alexander, 396 Cudworth, Damaris (Lady Masham), 148, 150 Cudworth, Ralph, 150 culture, 327 Culverwell, Nathaniel, 150 Cuomo, Chris, 422 Currie, Gregory, 428 Cusack, John, 64 Cynics, 4345 Cyril of Alexandria, Saint, 57
D
Daly, Mary, 411 Dante Alighieri, 90, 90 (ill.) Dark Ages philosophy, 59
471
472
Darwin, Charles, 307, 308 (ill.) Darwinism, 24344 Dasein, 280, 281 Davidson, Thomas, 300 Davis, Angela, 288 (ill.), 28889, 397 Davis, Christa, 399 Dawkins, Richard, 423, 424, 425 (ill.) De Divisione Naturae (Eriugena), 6061 death, 280 deconstructionism, 38789 deep ecology, 41920 Defert, Daniel, 293 definite descriptions, 335, 364 degenerating research programs, 374 Deism, 307 Deleuze, Gilles, 392, 39394, 394 (ill.), 395 Delphy, Christine, 413 democracy, 38 Democratus, 19 (ill.) atoms, 13, 19 Pre-Socratics, 12 Prodicus, 22 Pyrrho of Elis, 40 demonology, 53 Dendy, Helen, 234 Dennett, Daniel C., 42324 denotative meaning, 381 Derrida, Jacques, 38789, 388 (ill.), 39091 Descartes, Francine, 121 Descartes, Ren, 126 (ill.) as bachelor, 152 Cartesianism, 126 Christina, Queen, 124 clear and distinct ideas, 125 consideration of women, 154 evil demon hypothesis, 126 Gassendi, Pierre, 92 geometry, 160 God, 12526, 127
and Hobbes, Thomas, 139, 140 (ill.) and Hume, David, 168 Inquisition, 12223 James-Lange theory, 314 life of, 12021 love, 153 mathematics, 125 as mechanistic philosopher, 149 Meditations on First Philosophy (Descartes), 12526 mental activity, 377 mind-body problem, 23, 13132, 141 More, Henry, 15051 origins of philosophical work, 122 Passions of the Soul, 12627 personality of, 121 as philosophical rationalist, 84 royal female correspondents, 123 Sartre, Jean-Paul, 267 scientific revolution, 84 senses, 125 sleep, 125 substance, 128 Swedenborg, Emmanuel, 316 Vico, Giovanni Battista, 19293 descriptive ethical egoism, 355 descriptive relativism, 351 desire, 4045 determinism, 42425 Devall, B., 419 Devereux, Robert, 103 Dewey, John, 31718, 318 (ill.) childrens education, 320 direct writing style, 297 life, 31819 main philosophical ideas of, 319 metaphysics, 319 Putnam, Hilary, 368
technology, 426 theory of art, 31920 Unity of Science project, 342 The Dial, 305, 306 Diamond, Jared, 423 Diderot, Denis, 170, 184, 185, 185 (ill.) differance/difference, 388 difference principle, 361 Digby, Tom, 411 Dilthey, Wilhelm, 244, 273 Diogenes of Sinope, 44 (ill.), 4445 Dionysian element, 26364 Dionysius, St., 60 Dionysius the Elder, 27 Dionysius the Younger, 27 Diotima of Mantinea, 32, 47 discourse, 391, 392 discrimination laws, 416 diverse populations, 297 Divinity School Address (Emerson), 305 DNA, 369, 370 doctrine of double effect (DDE), 35657 Dodley, Robert, 195 dogmatism, 89, 22425 dogs, 44, 5455 doing, 36 domestic animals, 421 Dostoyevsky, Fyodor, 25961, 260 (ill.) double helix, 370 Douglass, Frederick, 305, 306 (ill.), 3067, 396 dreams, 348 Du Bois, W. E. B., 7, 314, 396 Dudley, Robert, 103 Dumartheray, Franois, 243 Dummett, Michael, 340 Duns Scotus, John, 61, 7576, 76 (ill.) Durkheim, Emil, 252 Dworkin, Andrea, 19899, 412
E
early American philosophy. See also New England transcendentalists; Social Darwinism; St. Louis Hegelians most influential strains, 295 Native Americans, 29697 Sagoewatha, 297 Tenskwatawa, 29697 early modern philosophy definition of, 119 epistemological rationalism, 11920 proponents of, 119 early twentieth century analytic philosophy Gdel, Kurt, 33839 important themes, 33132 logical atomism, 334 Tarski, Alfred, 339 truth-functional logic, 33334 Earth, 9598 Eastern philosophy, 29899, 4034 ecology, 399 economics, 186, 206 Edison, Thomas, 309, 309 (ill.) Edmonds, David, 372 education, 14748, 320 Edwards, John, 148 Edwards, Jonathan, 18990 God, 19091 lack of mercy, 19091 view of God, 190 efficient and final causation, 137 efficient cause, 36 egoism, 225 egoistic suicide, 252 Eichmann, Adolf, 288 eidetic intuition, 276 eidetic reduction, 276 Eidinow, John, 372 Eightfold Path, 405
In d e x
Einstein, Albert, 103, 109, 130, 220, 327, 340 Eisele, Carolyn, 311 Eleatic school, 1618 Electra complex, 249 eliminative materialism, 38283 Eliot, George, 130 Eliot, T. S., 322 elixir of life, 115 Elizabeth I, Queen, 103, 104 Elizabeth of Bohemia, Princess, 12324 Elkaim, Arlette, 26869 Eloise, 64 Elstob, Elizabeth, 155, 182 Emancipation Proclamation, 307 embryology, 135 (ill.), 13536 emergence, 323 Emerson, Ralph Waldo, 3025, 303 (ill.) as abolitionist, 3045 the Dial, 306 Divinity School Address, 305 life of, 303 as New England Transcendentalist, 300 over-soul, 304 requirements for a scholar, 304 St. Louis Philosophical Society, 299 transcendentalism definition, 303 Emerson, Thomas I., 412 emotion, 14142, 314 emotivist theory of ethics, 35253 Empedocles, 19 (ill.) four elements, 13, 18, 22 Pre-Socratics, 12 empirical ego, 18081 empirical psychology, 245 empiricism, 77, 84, 110, 159, 17374 Enckendorf, Marie-Luise, 253 encyclopedists, 184
endeavors, 142 Engels, Friedrich, 23739 Enlightenment period, 155, 227. See also Bentham, Jeremy; Berkeley, George; Counter-Enlightenment figures; Hume, David; Kant, Immanuel; philosophes; Reid, Thomas; Rousseau, Jean-Jacques; Wollstonecraft, Mary definition of, 157 effect on United States, 190 Enlightenment philosophers vs. other intellectuals, 158 pessimists, 15859 philosophy, 157 reason, 158 Romantics, 15859 themes, 15758 enthusiasm, 150 environmental philosophy animal rights, 42122 criticism of deep ecological and animal value views, 42122 deep ecology, 41920 definition of, 41718 domestic animals, 421 ethics, 422 feminism, 422 Jonas, Hans, 271 Naess, Arne, 41920 problems of, 41718 racial and international studies, 422 religion issues, 422 reverence of Earth, 41718 shallow ecology, 41920 start of, 419 environmentalism, 399. See also environmental philosophy Epictetus, 4142 Epicurus, 42, 43 (ill.), 80 epicycle, 97 epigenesis, 135 epistemological rationalism, 11920
473
474
epistemology, 17778 definition of, 4 epistemology and metaphysics after logical positivism. See also Putnam, Hilary; Quine, W. V. O. Goodman, Nelson, 365 grue, 365 manifest image, 365 Sellars, Wilfred, 364 Strawson, P. F., 364 equality, 361 Erasmus, Desiderius, 79 (ill.), 7980, 87 Eriugena, Johannes Scotus, 6061 Ernst August, 133, 134 Eros, 248 Essay Concerning Human Understanding (Locke), 147 An Essay in Defense of the Female Sex (Locke), 155 essence, 324 eternal recurrence, 264 eternity, 72 ethical egoism, 355 ethical relativism, 35152 ethical subjectivism, 353 ethics, 4, 25, 205, 350 ethics of ambiguity, 269 Etymologiae (St. Isadore), 61 Eudoxus of Cnidos, 28, 96 European Romantics, 300 Euthyphro (Plato), 25 evil, 12930 evolution, 251, 308, 312, 380 existence, 367 existentialism, 255, 28182. see also Dostoyevsky, Fyodor; Kierkegaard, Sren; Nietzsche, Friedrich; Sartre, Jean-Paul definition, 256 Foucault, Michel, 29293 humanist, 270, 27172 phenomenology, 256 religious, 27071 experience, 31920, 340
experimental philosophy, 42425 expression, 6364 extension, 163 Eze, Emmanuel, 403
F
Fabricius, Hieronymus, 116 fads, 38586 Faguet, mile, 196 faith, 7374, 83, 87 falsification, 37172, 375 family resemblance, 346 fashion, 253 fatalistic suicide, 252 fava beans, 17 Fay, Harriet Melusina, 313 feminism, 181, 270, 4078, 422 feminist epistemology, 410 feminist philosophy Cixous, Hlne, 415 definition of, 407 feminism, 4078 feminist epistemology, 410 feminist philosophy of science, 410 feminist reclamation, 409 French feminism, 413, 414 gender, 412 intersectionality, 41617 Irigaray, Luce, 41415 key philosophers, 41011 Kristeva, Julia, 413 414 lesbian gay bisexual transsexual (LGBT) studies, 415 MacKinnon, Catherine, 412 male feminists, 411 Marcus, Ruth Barcan, 40910 philosophical aspects of, 4089 philosophical feminism, 409 pornography, 412 queer theory, 415
race, 416 second wave feminism, 41112, 417 sexual harassment, 412 third wave feminism, 41516 unity of women, 417 womens health movement, 41415 feminist philosophy of science, 410 feminist reclamation, 409 Feuerbach, Ludwig Andreas von food, 237 ideas, 236 influence of, 23637 man, 237 materialist, 236 Feyerabend, Paul, 375, 382 Fichte, Johann Gottlieb, 223 career highlights, 22324 freedom, 225 ideas of, 22425 Kant, Immanuel, 223, 224 morality, 223 political philosophy, 225 Schopenhauer, Arthur, 233 Ficino, Marsilio, 78, 78 (ill.), 149 fideism, 85 Filmer, Robert, 145 final cause, 36, 37, 38 Finch, Heneage, 151 Fink, Eugen, 27374 Fisher, Eugen, 278 Fiske, John, 308 Flanagan, Owen, 428 Fodor, Jerry, 37879 evolution, 380 language of thought hypothesis, 37980 modular theory of mind, 379 theory of mind, 384, 428 folk psychology, 382 Foot, Philippa, 353, 354 forces, 349 formal cause, 36
forms, 28, 29, 31, 35 Forster, E. M., 353 Foucault, Michel, 291 Derrida, Jacques, 389 as existentialist, 29293 formation of cultural criticism, 291 philosophical development of, 29192 four elements (earth, wind, fire, water), 18, 22, 22 (ill.) Franoise-Louise de Warens, 170 Frank, Philip, 341 Frankfurt School, 28485 Frankfurter, Felix, 322 Franklin, Benjamin, 184, 189 (ill.), 190 Frasier, Alexander Campbell, 132 Frederick the Great of Prussia, 187 Frederick V, 123 free society, 17273 free speech, 207 free thinkers, 90 free will Bergson, Henri, 217 Erasmus, Desiderius, 80 experimental philosophy, 42425 Hobbes, Thomas, 142 Hume, David, 169 James, William, 315 Reid, Thomas, 174 freedom, 225, 226, 272 freedom of man, 79 Freeland, Cynthia, 428 Frege, Gottlob, 221, 335, 337 Freidan, Betty, 4078, 408 (ill.) French feminism, 413, 414, 415 Freud, Lucien, 248 Freud, Sigmund, 247 (ill.), 24748 Brentano, Franz, 245 hysteria, 248 Iragary, Luce, 414 life, 248 Marcuse, Herbert, 288
oedipal theory, 24849, 249 (ill.) Schopenhauer, Arthur, 233 self-analysis, 24950 Spinoza, Benedict de, 130 Froissy, Juliette, 313 Fromm, Erich, 285, 289 Frost, Robert, 322 Fry, Roger, 353 Frye, Marilyn, 412 Fuller, Margaret, 305 functionalism, 364, 38081, 38182 fundamental ideas, 203 Fuseli, Henry, 183 Futrell, Mynga, 424
G
Gaarder, Jostein, 427 Gabriel (angel), 65 Galen of Pergamum, 11314, 117 Galilei, Galileo, 99 (ill.), 99100 Feyerabend, Paul, 375 natural philosophy, 83 scientific investigation, 81 scientific revolution, 93, 94 telescopes, 140 Gall, Franz Joseph, 379 Gallienus, Emperor, 51 Garbo, Greta, 124 garden, 82 Gassendi, Pierre, 9091 Boyle, Robert, 106 Hobbes, Thomas, 140 Meditations on First Philosophy (Descartes), 122 mitigated Skepticism, 9192 as priest, 152 Pyrrhonic antiAristotelianism, 89 reaction to views of, 92 religion and science, 91 Gaunilon (monk), 62
Gauss, Carl Friedrich, 219, 220 gay science, 264 Geisert, Paul, 424 gender, 412 General Theory of Relativity, 220 gentle nihilism, 363 geometry, 160, 219 Georg Ludwig, 133 George I, King, 133 German idealism, 223. See also Bosanquet, Bernard; Fichte, Johann Gottlieb; Hegel, Friedrich; Schelling, Friedrich; Schopenhauer, Arthur Ghazali, Abu Hamid al-, 6768, 83 Gibbens, Alice, 314 Gibbon, Edward, 184 Gilligan, Carol, 410 God cycles of history, 194 Edwards, Jonathan, 19091 existence of, 181 as greatest being, 6162 knowledge of, 7071 Malebranche, Nicolas, 13132 and philosophy, 4 Spinoza, Benedict de, 12930 Gdel, Kurt, 33839 Godwin, William, 181, 240 Goethe, Johann Wolfgang von, 227 gold, 107, 115 Golden Rule, 180 good, 12930 Goodman, Nelson, 364, 365 goodness, 352 goodness of man, 171 Gordianus III, Emperor, 5051 Gordon, Lewis R., 397, 402 Gorgias of Leontini, 20, 2122, 44 Gould, Stephen Jay, 423 government, 38, 185, 227
475
In d e x
government theory, 14546 Gracia, Jorge J. E., 400 Gramsci, Antonio, 285 (ill.), 28586, 292 Grant, Duncan, 353 Grant, Jacquelyn, 397 Grant, Madison, 309 gravity, 99 Greater Vehicle, 404 Greek Pre-Socratics. See Pre-Socratics Gregory XIII, Pope, 81 Grice, H. P., 346 Grotius, Hugo, 139, 194 grue, 365 Guattari, Pierre-Flix, 392, 39394, 395 Guide of the Perplexed (Maimonides), 70 (ill.), 7072 Guillaumin, Colette, 413 Gullivers Travels (Swift), 197 Gutmann, Amy, 397 Gyeke, Kwame, 403
H
Habermas, Jrgen, 39091, 392 (ill.) discourse, 391, 392 Frankfurt School, 285 lifeworld, 20 main ideas of, 391 haecceity, 76 Hahn, Hans, 341 Halifax, Charles, 111 Hall, G. Stanley, 318 Halley, Edmund, 111 Hamann, Johann Georg, 192 Hamilton, William, 21213 Harding, Sandra, 410, 417 Hare, R., 356 Harris, Leonard, 326, 397 Harris, William T., 298, 299 Harrison, William Henry, 29697 Hartlib, Samuel, 104 Hartshorne, Charles, 297, 311, 329 Harvey, William, 104, 11617, 117 (ill.)
476
hating, 245 having, 36 Hawthorne, Nathaniel, 303 heat, 81 hedonic calculus, 17576 Hegel, Friedrich, 226, 228 (ill.) Absolute, 236 absolute knowledge, 229 abstract thinking, 229 Bosanquet, Bernard, 234 career, 22628 cunning of reason, 194 highest form of spirit, 230 interpreted by Snider, 300 Kierkegaard, Sren, 258 main ideas of, 228 Peirce, Charles, 31011 radical vs. romantic, 230 Right and Left Hegelians, 23031 spirit, 229 St. Louis Hegelians, 299 system, 22829 Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, 7, 33, 53, 84 Hegelian subject, 319 hegemony, 286 Heidegger, Martin, 27677, 277 (ill.) Arendt, Hannah, 28788 Being, 28182 Dasein, 280 existentialism vs. humanism, 28182 as existentialist, 280 film about, 428 German language, 282 Husserl, Edmund, 273 life of, 279 Nazis, 27779 ontology, 276, 277 space, 281 technology, 282, 426 the they, 280 time, 281 views on death, 280 Heilbroner, Robert, 422 Hein, Steven, 405
Heine, Heinrich, 130 heliocentric theory, 9596 Hellenistic and Roman philosophy Academic Skeptics, 4041 ancient Cynicism, 4344 Athens, 39 Epicureanism, 4243 middle Stoicism, 4142 political events after decline of Greece, 39 Pyrrho of Elis, 40 pyrrhonic skepticism, 4041 Roman Stoicism, 4142 Skepticism, 3940 Stoicism, 41 Helmont, Franciscus Mercurius van, 151 Henry IV, King, 107 Henry VIIII, King, 80 Heraclitus, 12, 13 Herder, Johann Gottfried von, 192 Hermarchus, 42 Hermes Trismegistus, 78, 98, 149 Hermias, 33 Herphyllis, 33 Hervet, Gentian, 88 Hesse, Herman, 404 Heyes, Cressida J., 417 Higgs, Eric, 427 higher pleasures, 206 Hill, Thomas E., 419, 420 Hipparchus of Nicaea, 96 Hippias of Elis, 20, 22 Hippocrates, 113 Hispanic-American philosophy. See Latin American philosophy historically disadvantaged groups, 396 history, 191, 194 Hitler, Adolf, 278, 288 Hoagland, Sara Lucia, 412 Hobbes, Thomas as bachelor, 152 consideration of women, 154 emotion, 14142
free will, 142 ideals of government first theorized by, 7 imagination, 14142 life of, 13940 matter, 16061 memory, 14142 mind-body problem, 141 origins of modern, democratic government, 8 response to Meditations on First Philosophy (Descartes), 122, 128 scientific revolution, 84 sensation, 14142 social contract, 143, 145 stories about, 141 theory of government, 142 (ill.), 143 thought, 14142 true religion, 149 Vico, Giambattista, 194 women left out of modern social contract theory, 411 Hochschild, Arlie Russell, 408 Hoffman, Abbie, 288 Hogan, Linda, 399 Holbach, Baron Paul-HenriDietrich d, 184, 185 Hlderlin, Johann Christian Friedrich, 22627, 230, 262 Holmes, Oliver Wendell, 314 Holt, Edwin B., 325 homunculi, 135 Honorius III, Pope, 6061 Hooke, Robert, 111 hooks, bell, 415 horde, 252 Horkheimer, Marx, 285, 286 Horthy, Mikls, 374 Hountondji, Paulin J., 403 Hsun Tzu, 406 Hull House, 32122 human experience, 319 human genome, 369, 370 human nature, 20, 196 human world, 3 humanism, 28182
In d e x
humanist existentialism, 270, 27172 Hume, David, 165 (ill.), 16566 ambition, 166 Berkeley, George, 159 causation, 16667 contradictions, 169 empiricism, 84 free will, 169 ideas in the real world, 212 matter, 161 Meinong, Alexius, 246 and Mill, John Stuart, 205 miracles, 168 perceptions, 16768 philosophes, 184 problem of induction, 167 religion, 168 and Rousseau, JeanJacques, 169 science of the mind, 166 scientific revolution, 84 self, 167, 168 skeptical writings about religion, 4 theory of the emotions, 16869 humor, sense of, 217 humors, 113, 116 Husserl, Edmund, 27273 and Brentano, Franz, 244 and Heidegger, Martin, 278 intentionality, 275 life of, 27374 lifeworld, 20 phenomenological method, 276 separation of mathematics and logic from psychology, 275 Stein, Edith, 27475 two types of self, 276 Huygens, Christian, 128 Hypatia of Alexandria, 5657 hypothetical rule, 179
I
Iamblichus of Syria, 52, 53 Ibn al-Nafis, 116 idealism, 214, 31112 idealist doctrine, 234 ideas, 16162 ideas of imagination, 162 ideas of sense, 162 idols, 102 illocutionary forces, 349 imagination, 14142, 162 Imlay, Gilbert, 183 immanent intentionality, 245 immortality, 29 independentist period of Latin American philosophy, 401 indeterminacy, 370 Indian Buddhism, 404 Indian philosophy, 4034 individual freedom, 287 individualism, 225 induction, 167, 2034 inertia, 101 injustice, 174 Innocent VIII, Pope, 79 input systems, 379 Inquisition, 12223 insomnia, 11213 instinct theory, 248 intellectual intuition, 76 Intelligence, 52 intensional meaning, 381 intentionality, 246, 275 International Institute of Social Research, 285 International Working Mens Association, 241 interpretant, 312 intersectionality, 41617 intuitionism Bergson, Henri, 216 (ill.), 21617 Bradley, F. H., 21314, 215
477
the conditioned, 213 Hamilton, William, 21213 Martineau, James, 216 moral theory, 21516 nineteenth century, 212 Scottish Common Sense Philosophy, 212 Sidgwick, Henry, 21415, 21516 and Whewell, William, 212 intuitions, 42425 inventions, 93 Invisible College, 104 ipse-dixitism, 175 Irigaray, Luce, 413, 41415 irony, 2425 Isidore of Seville, St., 60, 61 Islam Averros, 68 (ill.), 6869 Avicenna, 66 beginning of, 65 Christian European philosophy, 66 vs. Christianity, 6566 Ghazali, Abu Hamid al-, 6768 Jewish and Islamic philosophy, 6465 Kindi, Abu Yusuf al-, 66 military invasion of Europe, 6566 Sufism, 6768 Isocrates, 28 isotype, 342 Ivanhoe, Philip J., 407 Ives, David, 130
J
Jackson, George, 288 Jackson, Lydia, 304 Jacobs, Ruth Anna, 368 Jagger, Alison M., 409 James, William, 313 development of pragmatism, 31415 founding of psychology, 6 life, 31314
main contribution to psychology, 314 main pragmatic interests, 315 pragmatic epistemology, 315 pragmatic ethics, 315 and Putnam, Hilary, 368 religion and free will, 315 supernatural, 316 will to believe, 316 James I, King, 103, 117 James-Lange theory of the emotions, 314 James VI of Scotland, 123 Jamieson, D., 419 Jans, Helena, 121 Japanese philosophy, 4034 Jaspers, Karl, 270, 273, 279, 287 Jefferson, Thomas, 189 (ill.), 190 jen, 406 Jesus, 305 Jewish philosophy, 69 Johann Friedrich, Duke of Hanover, 133 John Paul II, Pope, 274 John the Bold, King, 60 John XXII, Pope, 77 Johnson, Esther, 197 Johnson, Joseph, 183 Jojoba, Ted, 399 Jonas, Hans, 271 Jonson, Ben, 104 Ju, 4056 Judaism, 270 Julia Domna, 46 Julian, 52 justice, 22, 174, 36061 Justinian, 55
K
Kaila, E., 339 Kant, Immanuel, 17677, 177 (ill.) and Anselm, St., 62 categorical imperative, 17980
478
Copernican Revolution, 178 dogmatism, 225 Empiricism, 84 epistemology, 17778 Fichte, Johann Gottlieb, 223, 224 foundations for knowledge, 178 founding of anthropology, 7 Frege, Gottlob, 221 Golden Rule, 180 and Hamilton, William, 213 intrinsic value, 420 metaphysics, 17778 metaphysics as religious, 216 moral system, 179 moral theory, 215 Peirce, Charles, 31011 and Poincar, Jules Henri, 220 proof of Gods existence, 181 recluse, 180 Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, 180 Schopenhauer, Arthur, 23132 self, 18081 synthetic a priori knowledge, 17879 transcendental deduction, 17879 Transcendental forms, 303 and Whewell, William, 2023 Kant Club, 299 Kaufmann, Walter, 266 Kauppinen, Antti, 425 Keller, Rose, 198 Kepler, Johannes Copernican system, 100101 elliptical shape of planetary orbits, 140, 204 scientific revolution, 93 Keynes, John Maynard, 353
Kierkegaard, Sren, 256, 256 (ill.) Christianity, 257 criticism of, 259 emotional conditions of, 25657 Empiricism, reaction against, 84 Hegel, Friedrich, 258 Marcel, Gabriel, 270 question of existence of God, 258 religious life of, 259 stages on lifes way, 258 Kindi, Abu Yusuf al-, 66 Kinel, Gertrud, 253 King, Martin Luther, 39697 Kingsley, Charles, 56 Kittay, Eva, 410 Knobe, Joshua, 425 knowledge, 147, 2023 knowledge by acquaintance, 335 knowledge by description, 335 Knutzen, Marin, 176 Kohlberg, Lawrence, 410 Kourany, Janet, 41011 Kripke, Saul, 409 Kristeva, Julia, 41314 Kristol, William, 363 Kropotkin, Pyotr Alexeyevich, 240, 242, 242 (ill.) anarchist-communism, 243 Darwinism, 24344 life philosophy, 24243 Kuhn, Thomas, 94, 369, 37273, 37475
L
La Mothe Le Vayer, Franois de, 90 Lacan, Jacques, 198, 290, 387, 414 Lakatos, Gza, 373, 374 Lakatos, Imre, 37374, 375 Lange, Carl Georg, 314 language Chomsky, Noam, 37778
linguistic turn, 28990 Neurath, Otto, 34243 Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 338 language games, 346 language of thought hypothesis, 37980 Lao Tzu, 279 Laplace, Pierre-Simon, 218 (ill.), 21819 Las Casas, Bartolom de, 401 Latin American philosophy, 400401 Latino-Latina philosophy. See Latin American philosophy laughter, 217 law of gravity, 110 law of identity, 355 laws of motion, 109, 110 Lawson, Bill E., 397, 422 Le Loyer, Pierre, 89 Leeuwenhoek, Antoni de, 13536 Left Hegelians, 23031 leftist syndicalism, 271 Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm, 133, 133 (ill.) and calculus, 134, 135 Chinese philosophy, 404 consciousness, 428 Conway, Anne, 151 embryology, 135 (ill.), 13536 influence on George Berkeley, 162 life of, 13335 love, 153 Malebranche, Nicolas, 132 monadology, 138 Newton, Isaac, 111 occasionalism, 12728 Pangloss, Dr., 137 Spinoza, Benedict de, 128 Voltaire, 187 Lens Crafters Society, 131 Leo X, Pope, 95 Leopold, Aldo, 419 lesbian feminism, 411
In d e x
lesbian gay bisexual transsexual (LGBT) studies, 415 Lesser Vehicle, 404 Lessing, Gotthold, 184 let the fly out of the bottle, 347 Leucippus, 12, 19 Levasseur, Thrse, 170, 172 Lvi-Strauss, Claude, 290, 290 (ill.) Leviathan (Hobbes), 142 (ill.), 143 Levinas, Emmanuel, 271 Levy, Bnny, 268 Lewis, C. I., 314, 32526 Lewontin, Richard, 370, 423 liberal ironism, 390 liberty, 35859 libido, 248 life force, 370 limits of reason, 71 linguistics, 37778 Lipman, Matthew, 427 Lippman, Walter, 322 Lloyd, Genevieve, 410 Lobachevsky, Nikolai, 219 location, 328 Locke, Alain, 314, 326, 327 Locke, John, 144 (ill.) as bachelor, 152 and Berkeley, George, 159 children, 14748 consideration of women, 154 and Descartes, Ren, 128 education, 14748 Edwards, Jonathan, 190 An Essay in Defense of the Female Sex, 155 happy final years, 148 ideals of government first theorized by, 7 importance of, 14345 love, 153 matter, 161 mind-body problem, 14647 natural law vs. government theory, 14546
479
and Newton, Isaac, 111 origins of modern, democratic government, 8 publications, 14445 religion, 149 scientific revolution, 84 social contract, 145 substance vs. knowledge, 147 and Swedenborg, Emmanuel, 316 tabula rasa, 146 Voltaire, 188 women left out of modern social contract theory, 411 Locke-Nozick solution, 362 locutionary forces, 349 logic, 209110, 336. See also mathematics and logic logical analysis, 340 logical atomism, 332, 334 logical empiricism, 370 logical holism, 334 logical positivism, 339. See also Vienna Circle logical quantification, 221 logos, 16 Lombard, Peter, 61, 63, 72 Lord Ashley, Earl of Shaftesbury, 14445 Lott, Tommy L., 397 Louis XV, King, 170, 187 Lovejoy, Elijah P., 304 loving, 245 lower pleasures, 206 loyalty, 317 Lucretius, 39 Ludwig, Kirk, 425 Lugones, Mara C., 416 Lusthaus, Dan, 405 Luther, Martin, 7980, 88 Lutterell, John, 77 Lyotard, Jean-Franois, 393
M
480
MacCarthy, Mary, 353 Machung, Anne, 408 MacIntyre, Alasdair, 353, 354
MacKinnon, Catherine, 412 Madyhamika School, 405 magnetism, 226 Mahayana Buddhism, 404 Maimonides Guide of the Perplexed, 70 (ill.), 7072 intellectual contributions of, 70 Jewish philosophy, 69 philosophy and religion, 71 Maistre, Joseph-Marie de, 19596, 196 (ill.) majority rule, 207 Makrina, 46 Malcolm, Norman, 346 male feminists, 411 Malebranche, Nicolas, 131 Berkeley, George, influence on, 162 causation, 13132 Descartes mind-body problem, 13132 Edwards, Jonathan, 190 God, 13132 life of, 13233 occasionalism, 127 Malkovich, John, 64 man as universal subject, 292 Manicaeanism, 58 manifest image, 364, 365 Marcel, Gabriel, 27071 Marcus Aurelius, 41, 42 (ill.), 50, 114 Marcuse, Herbert, 279, 285, 288 Maria Christina Alexandra, 124 marketplace, idols of, 102 marriage, 15253, 183, 209 Marshall, Cordelia, 202 Martineau, James, 216 Marvin, Walter T., 325 Marx, Karl, 235 (ill.), 237, 238 (ill.) Althusser, Louis, 290 Bakunin, Mikhail Alexandrovich, 241
Feuerbach, Ludwig Andreas von, 236, 237 and Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, 7 Popper, Karl, 360 poverty of, 239 Proudhon, Pierre-Joseph, 241 Marxism Adorno, Theodore, 286 Benjamin, Walter, 286 definition of, 235 Horkheimer, Marx, 286 Poulantzas, Nicos, 292 reactions against Hegelianism, 235 Marxist historicism, 359 Mary, Princess of Orange, 145 Mary Queen of Scots, 103 Masham, Francis, 148 material cause, 36 materialism, 107, 235, 378. See also Feuerbach, Ludwig Andreas von mathematics and logic Frege, Gottlob, 22122 Hypatia of Alexandria, 56 Laplace, Pierre-Simon, 218 (ill.), 21819 mathematics vs. logic, 222 nineteenth century philosophy of, 218 non-Euclidian geometry, 21920 Poincar, Jules Henri, 220 probability, 21819 scientific revolution, 9394 Venn diagrams, 220, 221 (ill.) Vico, Giambattista, 19293 matter, 127, 16061, 163 Matthews, Gareth, 427 May, Larry, 411 Mayr, Ernst, 423 Mbiti, John, 403 McGary, Howard, 397
McGinn, Colin, 428 Mead, George Herbert, 320, 322, 323 meaning, 222, 340, 383 mechanics, 99 medicine and philosophy alchemy, 11516 Alcmaeon, 11213 Burton, Robert, 11718 Galen of Pergamum, 11314 Harvey, William, 11617, 117 (ill.) Hippocrates, 113 history of, 112 Paracelsus, 114 (ill.), 11415 medieval philosophy. See also Islam; Maimonides; Scholastics; Thomas Aquinas, St. Albertus Magnus, 76 (ill.), 7677 Aristotle, 49 Augustine, St., 5759, 58 (ill.) Christian philosophy vs. Christian theology, 57 Dark Ages philosophy, 59 definition of, 5, 57 Duns Scotus, John, 7576, 76 (ill.) Encyclopedists, 60 Eriugena, Johannes Scotus, 6061 Isadores, St., encyclopedia, 61 Plato, 49 William of Ockam, 77 Meditations on First Philosophy (Descartes), 122, 126, 12728 Meinong, Alexius, 244, 246, 247, 248 melancholy, 118 Meletus, 25 Mellisus of Samos, 16 Melville, Herman, 300 meme, 424 memory, 14142, 174 memory trace, 348 Mencius, 406
Mendieta, Eduardo, 400 Mengele, Joseph, 278 Meno (Plato), 29 mental states, 380 Mercado, Toms de, 401 Merleau-Ponty, Maurice, 28283 irony of his death, 283 life of, 283 phenomenology of perception, 28384 Mersenne, Marin, 89, 122, 152 Metaphysical Club, 314 metaphysical phase of science, 212 metaphysics. See also epistemology and metaphysics after logical positivism definition of, 5 Kant, Immanuel, 17778 Surez, Francisco, 120 Thomas Aquinas, 75 method of transdiction, 106 methodology, 103 Metrodorus of Lampsacus, 42 mice, 74 micropolitics, 395 middle Stoicism, 41 Mill, James, 175 Mill, John Stuart achievements of, 205 assessment of religious belief, 208 free speech, 207 Hamilton, William, 213 higher vs. lower pleasures, 206 ideals of government first theorized by, 7 importance of, 205, 205 (ill.) influential publications of, 2056 logic, 209110 majority rule, 207 marriage, 209 matter, 161 methodology, 103 negative liberty, 359
pleasure principle, 206, 207 scientific methodology, 209110 scientific revolution, 84 as socialist and capitalist, 2067 The Subjection of Women, 2089 Taylor, Harriet, 210 utilitarianism, 208 Whewell, William, criticism of, 213 women, 2089 Millan-Zaibert, Elizabeth, 400 Mills, Charles W., 397 mind Burton, Robert, 11718 Descartes, Ren, 124, 127 as first cause of motion, 18 modular theory of mind, 379 Ryle, Gilbert, 378 Schelling, Friedrich, 225 mind-body problem, 14647 minimal state, 362 miracles, 168 mitigated Skepticism, 9192 moderate realism, 73 moderate Skepticism, 9192 modern idealism, 159 modern philosophy, 5 modular theory of mind, 379 Molyneux, William, 160 monadology, 138 monetary reform, 95 money, 253 monism, 129 Monk, Ray, 337 Montague, William Pepperell, 325 Montaigne, Michel de, 87 fideism, 85, 85 (ill.) ideas of, 8586 importance of, 8485 notable works by, 8687 Pyrrhonic Skepticism, 87 reason vs. faith, 87 wit of, 86
481
In d e x
Moody-Adams, Michele M., 397 Moore, G. E., 332 Bloomsbury group, 353 Cambridge Apostles, 333 common sense philosophy, 331, 33233 idealism, 325 naturalistic fallacy, 352 as realist, 333 Scottish Common Sense Philosophy, 173 two hands argument, 33233 Moore, Kathleen Dean, 399 moral conventionalism, 351 moral naturalism, 354 moral relativism, 351 moral system, 179, 350 moral theory, 215, 350 morality, 38, 223 morals, 350 More, Henry, 150 (ill.), 15051 More, Thomas, 80 (ill.), 8081, 150, 243 More than Subtle Doctor, 77 Morris, George Sylvester, 318 Moses, 150 Moses, Greg, 397 Moses Maimonides. See Maimonides Mosley, Albert, 397, 403 motherhood, 411 Mou, Bo, 407 Muhammad (prophet), 65 Muir, John, 419 Mller, Max, 278 mutant universes of value, 395 mysterianism, 428 mysticism, 82, 83
N
482
Naess, Arne, 7, 41920 Nagel, Ernest, 37071 Nagel, Thomas, 381 (ill.), 38182
nave realism, 333 Napoleon Bonaparte, 219 Narayan, Uma, 417 Nash, R., 419 Native American philosophy, 399400 Native Americans, 29697 natural law, 13839, 14546 natural philosophy, 6, 83, 89 natural world, 3 naturalistic fallacy, 352 naturalistic worldview, 424 nature, 229, 3012, 323 Naude, Gabriel, 90 necessary truth, 91 necessitarianism, 142 Needham, Joseph, 404 negative liberty, 35859 negative theology, 71 Neilsen, Kai, 357 Nelbck, Johann, 341 Neoplatonism alchemy, 11516 Athenian school, 53 Augustine, St., 5859 Bothius, 50, 54 (ill.), 5456 Christianity, 50 definition of, 49 demonology, 53 Enneads (Plotinus), 51 Iamblichus, 52 Platos Laws, 51 Plotinus, 5051, 51 (ill.) popularity of, 50 problem of universals, 54, 54 (ill.) Proclus, 5354 soul, 52 women philosophers, 5657 Neurath, Otto, 339, 340, 341, 34243 New Atlantis (Bacon), 104 New England Transcendentalists Alcott, Amos Bronson, 300301 The Dial, 306 Douglass, Frederick, 306 (ill.), 3067
Emerson, Ralph Waldo, 3025, 303 (ill.) Fuller, Margaret, 305 Thoreau, Henry David, 301 (ill.), 3012 new mysterianism, 428 new philosophy, 385. See also American philosophies; environmental philosophy; feminist philosophy; postmodern philosophy Brights Movement, 424 experimental philosophy, 42425 fads, 38586 major themes, 386 meme, 424 mysterianism, 428 old philosophers, feelings towards, 386 philosophy for children, 427 philosophy of biology, 42424 philosophy of film, 42728 philosophy of technology, 42527 Newton, Isaac, 108 (ill.) and Bacon, Francis, 103 career accomplishments, 1089 eccentric personality of, 11012 founding of chemistry, 6 and God, 101, 109 Leibniz, Gottfried, and the calculus, 134, 135 natural philosophy, 6, 83 Newtons Laws, 110 occult, 111 recoinage, 109 scientific revolution, 92, 93, 94 scientific system, 109 Voltaire, 188 Newtonian science, 164 Nichols, Shaun, 425 Nichomachus, 33
Nietzsche, Friedrich, 26162, 262 (ill.) birth of tragedy, 26364 Christianity, 265 Dostoyevsky, Fyodor, 260 against Empiricism, 84 gay science, 264 health of, 263 important works of, 26263 and Marcuse, Herbert, 288 oppression, 266 Overman, 26465, 265 (ill.) power, 26566 Schopenhauer, Arthur, 233 Thus Spoke Zarathustra, 264 nihilism, 363 nineteenth century empiricism, 2012. See also Comte, Auguste; Mill, John Stuart; Whewell, William nineteenth century intuitionism, 212 nineteenth century philosophy, 5, 201 noble lie, 363 Noble Truths of Buddhism, 232 Noddings, Nell, 410 non-American philosophies African Diaspora, 402 African philosophy, 401, 4023 Afro-centrism, 402, 403 Asian philosophy, 4034 Buddhism, 4035, 404 (ill.) Chinese philosophy, 4034 Confucianism, 4057, 406 (ill.) continental traditions, 401 Eastern philosophy, 4034 Indian philosophy, 4034 Japanese philosophy, 4034
non-Euclidian geometry, 21920 nonexistent objects, 246 Nordic Superiority, 309 noumenal world, 23132 Novalis, 130 Novum Organum (Bacon), 102 Nozick, Robert, 362 Nuccetelli, Susana, 400 Nuh Ibn Mansur, 66
O
object, 312 object theory, 246 objective spirit, 229 objectivism, 355 objectivity, 9394 obscurantism, 389 occasionalism, 162, 163 occult, 111 Ockams Razor, 77 oedipal theory, 24849, 249 (ill.) Of Grammatology (Derrida), 38889 Oken, Lorenz, 226 Oldenburg, Henry, 128 olives, 14 Olson, Regine, 259 On Liberty (Mill), 206 On the Subjection of Women (Mill), 206 the One, 17, 4950, 5152 one sex theory, 153 ontological argument of existence of God, 62 ontology, 246, 276, 277, 324 open society, 360 opinion, 2 oppression, 266 Oration on the Dignity of Man (Pico della Mirandola), 79 ordinary language philosophy Austin, J. L., 349 Bouwsma, O. K., 347 definition, 34546 Grice, H. P., 34950
language games, 346 Malcolm, Norman, 348 method behind, 34647 other minds problem, 348, 349 private language argument, 347 Wisdom, John, 34849 Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 34547 organism, 318 Oruka, H. Odera, 403 Ossoli, Giovanni, 305 Outlaw, Lucius, 397 over-soul, 304 Overman, 26465, 265 (ill.) ovism, 135 owning class, 23839
In d e x
P
pain, 43, 17576 Paine, Thomas, 183, 190 Panaetius, 41 pantheism, 6061 papacy, 77 Paracelsus, 114 (ill.), 11415, 116 paradigm theory, 373 paradoxes, 24 paranormal, 215 Parmenides appearance, 1718 change, 13 Eleatic school, 1618 intellectual mysticism, 32 Leucippus, 19 the One, 1718 Pre-Socratics, 12 Parsons, Terence, 246 Pascal, Blaise, 188 Passions of the Soul (Descartes), 12627 Pateman, Carole, 411 Patin, Guy, 90 Patmore, Coventry, 209 patriarchy, 411 Patrick, Simon, 150 Pavlov, Ivan, 376, 376 (ill.) Peirce, Charles Sanders and Dewey, John, 318
483
484
fourth system, 31213 idealist, 31112 and James, Williams, 315 jobs, 313 life of, 31011 Metaphysical Club, 314 posthumous publication of works of, 311 pragmaticism of, 312 penis envy, 249 Pepys, Samuel, 111 perception, 28384 perceptions, 16768, 174 Periander of Corinth, 11 Pericles, 21, 46 Perictione I, 46 perlocutionary forces, 349 Perry, Ralph Barton, 314, 32425, 326 personal relationships, 270 Peters, Kurt, 399 Petri, Elfride, 279 pets, 421 Petty, William, 104 Petzll, A., 339 Peyrre, Isaac la, 90 Phaenarete, 23 phaneron, 311 Pheidippides, 27 phenomenalism, 340 phenomenology, 255, 256. See also Heidegger, Martin; Husserl, Edmund; Merleau-Ponty, Maurice phenomenology of perception, 28384 Philip of Macedonia, King, 33 philosophes, 184 Alembert, Jean le Rond d, 185 Beccaria, Cesare, 186 Diderot, Denis, 185 Edwards, Jonathan, 18991 encyclopedists, 184 Gibbon, Edward, 186 Holbach, Baron PaulHenri-Dietrich d, 185 Lessing, Gotthold, 186
Secondat, Charles-Louis de, Baron de La Brde et de Montesquieu, 185 Smith, Adam, 186, 186 (ill.) Voltaire, 18789, 188 (ill.) philosophical epistemology, 366 philosophical feminism, 409 philosophical novel, 427 philosophical rationalists, 84 philosophy beginning of, 1 as broad subject, 8 definition of, 1 difference from other intellectual pursuits, 2 as dry subject, 8 God, 4 Greek wisdom, 11 importance of, 2 jobs, 9 mind and body, 23 and ordinary life, 34, 9 origin of some sciences in, 67 practice vs. subject, 6 progress in, 8 psychology, 247 relationship to other fields, 6 and religion, 4 Seven Wise Men of Greece, 11 sociology, 252 specializations and subfields of, 45 splits within, 5 start of, in ancient Greece, 11 succession of other sciences, 6 use of, 2 Western, 3 worldwide, 8 philosophy for children, 427 philosophy of biology, 42324 philosophy of film, 42728
philosophy of language, 376. See also Fodor, Jerry philosophy of mind, 5, 376. See also Chomsky, Noam philosophy of science analytic philosophy of science, 369 definition of, 4 falsification, 37172 Feyerabend, Paul, 375 Kuhn, Thomas, 37273 Lakatos, Imre, 37374 life force, 370 logical empiricism, 370 Nagel, Ernest, 37071 paradigm theory, 373 Popper, Karl, 37172 random factors in the development of organisms, 370 Reichenbach, Hans, 36970 scientific revolution, 373 philosophy of technology, 42527 Phoenix, Joaquin, 199 physical equilibrium, 11213 physical existence, 16061 physicalism, 343, 370 physiochemical reactions, 319 Piaget, Jean, 427 Pico Della Mirandola, Giovanni, 79, 79 (ill.), 150 pineal gland, 127 Pirsig, Robert, 297 Pitkin, Walter Boughton, 325 Pittacus of Mytilene, 11 Pitts, Helen, 307 Pius XI, Pope, 81, 274 place, 36 Planck, Max, 341 planets, 9598, 101 Plato Academy, 28 appearance, 1718 vs. Aristotle, 35 changing philosophy, 31 Christian philosophy, 49 dialogues, 2829
Diogenes, 45 divided line, 3031 Ficino, Marsilio, 78 Foucault, Michel, 291 vs. German idealists, 223 Hermes Trismegistus, 78 ideals of government first theorized by, 7 ideas of, 29 just city, 2930 Laws, 51 life of, 27 medieval philosophy, 49 metaphysical theory of forms, 28 middle works, 29 Moses, 150 philosophy founded, 1 and Popper, Karl, 360 problem of universals, 5455 Republic, 22, 2930 simile of the cave, 30 Socrates, 2324, 2526 and Sophists, 20 speculative excesses, 33 technology, 425 theory of forms, 31 views of love, 32 writings of, 12 Plato Club, 299 Platonic love, 32 Please God, make me good (St. Augustine), 59 pleasure, 43, 17576 pleasure principle, 206, 207, 249 Plotinus, 5051, 51 (ill.) demonology, 53 Enneads, 5152 the One, 52 Platos Laws, 51 Porphyry, 53 Plumwood, V., 419 Plutarch of Athens, 53 Poincar, Jules Henri, 220 political oppression, 288 political psychology, 289 political theory, 195 Polwhele, Richard, 183
Polyaenus, 42 Pompadour, Madame de, 187 Pope, Alexander, 108, 137 Popper, Karl, 35960, 371 (ill.) falsification, 37172 Feyerabend, Paul, 375 Lakatos, Imre, 373, 37475 open society, 360 poker, 372 pornography, 412 Porphyry, 50, 52, 53, 54 Porter, Cole, 64 Posidonius, 41 position, 36 positive liberty, 35859 positivism, 211 positivist period of Latin American philosophy, 401 postmoderism. See postmodern philosophy postmodern philosophy. See also Derrida, Jacques; Habermas, Jrgen; Rorty, Richard Baudrillard, Jean, 39293 definition of, 5 Deleuze, Gilles, 39394, 394 (ill.), 395 distinctive methods, 387 Guattari, Pierre-Flix, 39394, 395 historical changes leading to, 38687 Lyotard, Jean-Franois, 393 Sokal, Alan, 39495 Potter, Elizabeth, 410 Poulantzas, Nicos, 292 power, 26566 practical ethics, 357 pragmatism, 19, 255, 295, 310. See also Addams, Jane; Dewey, John; James, William; Lewis, C. I.; Mead, George Herbert; Peirce, Charles Sanders; Perry, Ralph Barton; process philosophy; Royce, Josiah pre-established harmony, 16263
Pre-Socratics Anaxagoras, 18 definition of, 12 Democratus, 19 dialogue of, 13 Empedocles, 18 Heraclitus, 16, 16 (ill.) human world, 1 main ideas of, 13 main texts of, 12 natural vs. mythological explanations of, 12 Parmenides, 1618 Pythagorians and fava beans, 17 Zenos Paradoxes, 18 predictions, 204 preference satisfaction, 356 preformationism, 13536 prescriptive ethical egoism, 355 prescriptive relativism, 351 primary qualities, 1078, 163 primary substance, 36 primogeniture, 152 principle of the natural, 138 Principle of Utility, 175 principles of order, 137 Principles of Political Economy (Mill), 2056 prison reform, 176 private language argument, 347, 348 probability, 21819 problem of induction, 167 problem of the criterion, 87 process philosophy definition of, 32728 Hartshorne, Charles, 329 Whitehead, Alfred North, 32829 Proclus, 5354, 149 Prodicus of Ceos, 20, 22, 23 progress, 308, 309 progressive movements, 399 progressive research programs, 37475 proletariat, 238 proof of Gods existence, 181
485
In d e x
property, 240 property rights, 362 propositional attitudes, 245, 379 Protagoras of Abdera, 20, 21 Protestantism, 254 Protestants, 83 Proudhon, Pierre-Joseph, 240 (ill.), 24041 influences of, 24041 Marx, Karl, 241 property, 240 womens rights, 241 psychoanalytic theory, 247 psychological depression, 116 psychological ego, 276 psychology, 244, 247, 314 psychophysical transactions, 319 Ptolemaic system, 97 Ptolemaic theory, 9697 Ptolemy of Alexandria, 93, 9697 punishment, 186 Putnam, Hilary, 368 analytical-synthetic distinction, 36869 causal theory of meaning, 381, 409 neo-pragmatism of, 369 pragmatist epistemology, 364 Pyrrho of Elis, 40, 88 Pyrrhonic Skepticism, 4041, 87, 8889 Pyrrhonic tropes, 89 Pythagoras importance of, 1516 Moses, 150 numbers, 13 Pre-Socratics, 12, 15 (ill.), 1516 Themistocles, 46 Pythagorians, 17 Pythias, 33
queer theory, 415 Question Mark and the Mysterians, 428 Quills (movie), 199 Quine, W. V. O., 36566, 366 (ill.) analytic-synthetic distinction, 366, 36869 existence, 367 flexible view of knowledge, 367 holistic view of knowledge, 36768 Marcus, Ruth Barcan, 409 most influential ideas, 366 philosophical relevance, 367 pragmatism, 364 Quine-Putnam theory of mathematics, 368 Quine-Putnam theory of mathematics, 368
R
race, 327, 398, 416 racial identity, 39798 racism, 396 Rand, Ayn, 35455, 355 (ill.) Rawls, John, 36062, 391 real time, 217 realism, 333 reality, 214 reason, 87 recoinage, 109 Red Jacket, Chief, 297 reference, 222 Regan, Tom, 421 Reichenbach, Hans, 36970 Reid, Thomas empiricism, 17374 free will, 174 importance of, 173 naturalism, 213 Scottish Common Sense Philosophy, 212 reincarnation, 404 relation, 36 relativism, 1920, 21, 391
Q
486
quantification, 244 quantity, 36
religion and environmental philosophy, 422 vs. equality, 186 and free will, 315 and Hume, David, 168 and Locke, John, 149 and philosophy, 4 and Voltaire, 18889 religious existentialism, 27071 religious persecution, 149 Renaissance Humanism Erasmus, Desiderius, 79 (ill.), 7980 Ficino, Marsilio, 78, 78 (ill.) historical developments, 78 More, Thomas, 80 (ill.), 8081 Pico Della Mirandola, Giovanni, 79 Telesio, Bernardo, 81 Teresa of vila, St., 8182 reparations, 396 representationalism, 390 representative realism, 333 Republic (Plato), 26 research program, 37475 rhizomes, 39394 Ricoeur, Paul, 272 Riemann, Bernhard, 219 right and wrong, 245 Right Hegelians, 23031 Roberts, Rodney C., 397 Roe v. Wade, 408 Roman philosophy. See Hellenistic and Roman philosophy Roman Stoicism, 4142 Roosevelt, Franklin, 292 Roosevelt, Theodore, 314, 321 Rorty, Richard, 38990, 390 (ill.) Derrida, Jacques, 389 philosophy of, 390 relativism, 391 truth, 390 Rosenberg, Alexander, 423
Rosenlee, Li-Hsiang Lisa, 407 Rosicrucianism, 90 Ross, Daniel, 278 Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, 17071, 171 (ill.) on children, 172 as encyclopedist, 184 as father, 172 free society, 17273 and Hume, David, 169 as hypocrite, 172 ideas of, 17172 and Kant, Immanuel, 180 and Voltaire, 187 and Wollstonecraft, Mary, 182 Royal Society of London for the Improvement of Natural Knowledge, 105 Royce, Josiah, 31617 ethical and religious views, 317 metaphysical ideas, 317 Peirce, Charles, papers of, 311 and Santayana, George, 322 Rubio, Antonio, 401 Ruddick, Sara, 411 Ruse, Michael, 423 Rush, Geoffrey, 199 Ruskin, John, 209 Russell, Bertrand, 33435, 335 (ill.) analytic philosophy, 331 definite descriptions, 335 Dewey, John, defended by, 319 experimental philosophy, 425 Frege, Gottlob, 222 knowledge, 335 logic, 336 matter, 161 and Meinong, Alexius, 246 and Spinoza, Benedict de, 130 types, 33536
Unity of Science project, 342 wit of, 336 Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 337 Rust, George, 150 Ryle, Gilbert, 378
S
Sade, Marquis de, 191, 19799, 198 (ill.) Sagoewatha, 296, 297 Saint Louis Philosophical Society, 298 Sanchez, Francisco, 88, 88 (ill.) Sand, George, 130, 305 Santayana, George, 32223 final years, 324 and James, William, 314 ontology, 324 unclear pragmaticism, 323 Sarkar, Anil Kumar, 405 Sartre, Jean-Paul, 266, 267 (ill.) Beauvoir, Simone de, 26870, 269 (ill.) Camus, Albert, 272 consciousness, 26768, 276 existentialism, 26667 freedom, 26768 Heidegger, Martin, 279 Jewish question of, 268 as Marxist, 268 Merleau-Ponty, Maurice, 283 Ricoeur, Paul, 272 Saussure, Ferdinand de, 284, 289, 387 Saussure linguistics, 290 Scheffler, Samuel, 356 Schelling, Friedrich, 225 aesthetic views of culture, 226 and Hegel, Friedrich, 227, 230 major thesis, 22526 scandalous affair, 227
Schiller, Friedrich, 159 (ill.) schizoanalysis, 395 Schlegel, August Wilhelm von, 227 Schlick, Moritz, 339, 341 Scholastics Abelard, Peter, 63 (ill.), 6364 Anselm of Canterbury, St., 6162 definition of, 61 Lombard, Peter, 63 ontological argument of existence of God, 62 Schopenhauer, Arthur, 231, 232 (ill.) Fichte, Johann Gottlieb, 233 highlights of life, 231 influence of, 233 Kant, Immanuel, 23132 main ideas, 23132 moral system, 232 and Nietzsche, Friedrich, 263 personality, 233 WELT (acronym), 232 and Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 338 Schor, Naomi, 415 Schutte, Ofelia, 400 Schwartz, Stephen P., 381 science of the mind, 166 scientific methodology, 209110 scientific phase of science, 212 scientific revolution advances in medicine during, 116 Aristotelianism, 93 and Bacon, Francis, 1014 beginning of, 92 Boyle, Robert, 105 (ill.), 1067 Brahe, Tycho, 100, 100 (ill.), 101 British Royal Society, 107 Catholic Church, 93 Copernican theory, 98
487
In d e x
488
Copernicus, Nicolaus, 97 epicycle, 97 Galilei, Galileo, 99 impact on humanity, 94 Invisible College, 1045 Kepler, Johannes, 100101 key players, 93 and Kuhn, Thomas, 373 main ideas of, 9293 and modern empiricist philosophy, 84 Newton, Isaac, 108 (ill.), 10812 philosophical aspects of, 93 primary qualities, 1078 Ptolemaic system, 97 Ptolemaic theory, 9697 Ptolemy, 9697 revolutionary aspects of, 9395 Royal Society of London for the Improvement of Natural Knowledge, 105 secondary qualities, 1078 skepticism, 83 scientific verification, 341 Scottish Common Sense Philosophy, 173, 212 sances, 316 Searle, John, 384, 389 Sebond, Raimond, 85 second wave feminism, 408, 41112, 417 secondary qualities, 1078, 163 secondary substances, 36 Secondat, Charles-Louis de, Baron de La Brde et de Montesquieu, 184, 185 seduction theory, 248 Seleucus of Babylonia, 96 self, 167, 168, 18081, 276 self-determination, 392 selfhood, 270 selfishness, 35455 Sellars, Wilfred, 364, 380 semiotic, 413
Seneca the Younger, 41, 42 (ill.) sensation, 14142, 174 sensationalistic school, 203 sense, 162, 222 sense data, 163, 345 sense-data theory, 349 sense experience, 74 sense knowledge, 89 sense of humor, 217 senses, 106, 113 sensory experience, 146, 344 sensory information, 81 Serequeberhan, Tsenay, 403 Servetus, Michael, 116 Sessions, G., 419 settlement house movement, 32122 Seven Wise men of Greece, 11 seventeenth century empiricism. See also Hobbes, Thomas; Locke, John Grotius, Hugo, 139 natural law, 13839 seventeenth century rationalism. See Descartes, Ren; Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm; Malebranche, Nicolas; Spinoza, Benedict de; Surez, Francisco Sextus Empiricus, 40, 84, 86, 87 sexual harassment, 412 sexual intercourse, 153 sexuality, 415 Shakespeare, William, 250 shallow ecology, 41920 Shawnee tribe, 29697 Shelley, Mary, 184 Shelley, Percy Bysshe, 130 Shnberg, Arnold, 286 Shonborn, Johann Philipp von, 133 Shrage, Laurie, 417 Shulsky, Abram, 363 Shun, Kwong-loi, 407 Siddhartha Gautama, 404 Sidgwick, Henry, 21415, 21516, 316 Sidgwick, Nora, 316
sign, 312 sign-object-interpretant, 312 Silhon, Jean de, 92 Simmel, George, 25253 simple location, 328 simplicity, 3012 simulacra, 39293 Singer, Peter, 7, 419, 420 (ill.), 42021 Sisyphus, 272 Skepticism. See also Montaigne, Michel de academic, 88 anti-Aristotelianism, 90, 91 Catholic Church, 83 dogmatism, 88 faith and mysticism, 83 free thinkers, 90 Gassendi, Pierre, 9092 Luther, Martin, Dogmatism of, 88 Protestants, 83 Pyrrhonic, 8889 Pyrrhonic tropes, 89 Rosicrucianism, 90 and scientific revolution, 83 sense knowledge, 89 Skinner, Burhus Frederick (B. F.), 376 skyhooks, 42324 slavery, 396 slaves, 402 Slote, Michael A., 411 Smart, J. J. C., 356 Smith, Adam, 169, 184, 186, 186 (ill.) Smith, John, 150 Smith, John Maynard, 423 Smith, Mary Rozet, 321 Smith, Murray, 428 Snider, Denton Jacques, 298, 299, 300 Sober, Elliot, 423 social and political philosophy, 4 social conformity, 406 social contract, 143, 145, 361 Social Darwinism
definition of, 3078 evolution, 308 evolution vs. progress, 308 main Social Darwinists, 308 white supremacy, 309 social opinion, 206 social philosophy, 23435 social theory, 244. See also Brentano, Franz; Freud, Sigmund; Meinong, Alexius; Spencer, Herbert societies, 252, 36061 Society for Psychical Research, 215 sociology, 211 Durkheim, Emil, 252 Enckendorf, Marie-Luise, 253 fashion, 253 money, 253 and philosophy, 252 Protestantism and capitalism, 254 Simmel, Georg, 25253 Weber, Max, 253 (ill.), 25354 Socrates Antisthenes of Athens, 44 Arendt, Hannah, 288 The Clouds (Aristophanes), 27 death of, 2526, 26 (ill.) existence of, 2324, 24 (ill.) justice, 22, 26 key events, 2526 love, 32, 47 philosophy founded, 1 piety, 25 in Platos dialogues, 29 Prodicus, 23 Socratic irony, 2425 Socratic method, 26 Socratic paradoxes, 24 Strauss, Leo, 363 and Thales, 14 Socratic paradoxes, 24 Sokal, Alan, 39495 solar system, 96
In d e x
Solon of Athens, 11 Solovyov, Vladimir Sergeyevich, 260 Sontag, Susan, 363 Sophists definition of, 1920 Gorgias of Leontini, 2122 Hippias of Ellis, 22 human world, 1 ideas of, 2021 importance of, 20 vs. Pre-Socratics ideas, 2021 principal, 20 Prodicus of Ceos, 22 Protagoras of Abdera, 21 Socrates, 23 Thrasymachus of Bithynia, 22 Sophocles, 264 Sophroniscus, 23 Sosa, Ernest, 425 soul, 52, 7475, 14647, 291, 304 Southey, Robert, 183 space, 281 Spaulding, Edward Gleason, 325 speciesism, 421 spectator theory of knowledge, 319 Speculum of the Other Woman (Irigaray), 414 Spelman, Elizabeth V., 416 Spencer, Herbert, 250 (ill.), 25051 evolution, 251 personality of, 251 spermism, 135 Speusippus, 33 spider, 382 Spinoza, Benedict de, 128, 129 (ill.) as bachelor, 152 Cartesianism, 130 dual-aspect theory of God and nature, 127 emotions, 314 evil, 12930 good, 12930
legacy, 13031 Lens Crafters Society, 131 More, Henry, 151 philosophical goal, 12829 philosophical system, 129 spirit, 229 spirits, 161 spontaneous generation, 74 Sprat, Thomas, 105 St. Louis, Missouri, 298 St. Louis Hegelians, 298 current events, 298 and Eastern philosophers, 29899 founders of St. Louis Philosophical Society, 299300 other St. Louis philosophical activity, 299 shared goals, 299 St. Louis Philosophical Society, 299300 stages on lifes way, 258 Starr, Ellen Gates, 321 Staudinger, Hermann, 278 Stein, Edith, 273, 274 (ill.), 27475, 354 Stein, Gertrude, 314 Steinschneider, Malvine, 273 Sterry, Peter, 150 Stevens, Wallace, 322 Stevenson, Charles L., 353 Stillingfleet, Edward, 147 Stoa Poikile, 41 Stoicism, 41 Strachey, Lytton, 353 Strauss, Leo, 363 Strawson, P. F., 364 Strepsiades, 27 Strikwerda, Robert, 411 structuralism, 255 Althusser, Louis, 29091 critical theory, 284 Foucault, Michel, 29193 Lacan, Jacques, 290 Lvi-Strauss, Claude, 290, 290 (ill.) linguistic turn, 28990
489
Poulantzas, Nicos, 292 Saussure, Ferdinand de, 289 Surez, Francisco, 401 The Subjection of Women (Mill), 2089, 210 subjective spirit, 229 subjectivity, 393 substance, 36, 128, 129, 147, 405 Sufism, 6768 suicide, 252, 271 Sumner, William Graham, 308 Sun, 9598 supernatural, 316 survival of the fittest, 307 Swedenborg, Emmanuel, 316 Swift, Jonathan, 159, 191, 196 (ill.), 19697 Sydenham, Thomas, 144 syllogism, 35 syllogistics, 35 symbolic interaction, 322 sympathy, 175 synthetic a priori knowledge, 17879 synthetic truths, 32526 System of Logic (Mill), 205
T
T-sentences, 339 tabula rasa, 146 Tao, 406 tar water, 164 Tarski, Alfred, 339, 367 Taylor, Harriet, 210 Taylor, John, 210 Taylor, Paul W., 421 technology, 282, 425 Tecumseh, 296 Teedyuscung, 296 Telesio, Bernardo, 81 temporality, 281 Ten Bears, 297 Tenskwatawa, 29697 Teresa of vila, St., 8182 terrorism, 392 test theories, 204
490
texts, 388 Thales of Miletus accomplishments of, 14 behavior of, 14 Pre-Socratics, 12, 1314 Seven Wise Men of Greece, 11 unbounded, 13 water, 1314 Thanatos, 248 Theano I of Crotona, 46 Theano II, 46 Theatetus, 28 theatre, idols of, 102 Themistocles, 46 Theodoric the Great, 5556 theological phase of science, 212 Theophrastus, 12, 12 (ill.), 39, 113 theory of relativity, 327 theory of the emotions, 16869 Theravada Buddhism, 404 Theresa Benedicta of the Cross, St., 274 theurgy, 52 the they, 280 third man argument, 31 third wave of feminism, 41516 Third World, 417 Thomas, Laurence, 397 Thomas Aquinas, St. Angelic Doctor, 75 doctrine of double effect (DDE), 35657 faith vs. reason, 7374 as greatest medieval philosopher, 72, 73 (ill.) ideals of government first theorized by, 7 Latin American philosophy, 401 main original ideas, 7273 major works of, 72 metaphysics, 75 natural law, 138 philosophy vs. theology, 7374
religion and philosophy, 4 Scholastics, 61 science, 74 soul, 7475 spontaneous generation, 74 Thoreau, Henry David, 300, 301 (ill.), 3012, 309 Thoth, 98, 149 thought, 14142 thought vs. existence, 21 Thrasymachus, 20, 2223, 26 Three Essays on Religion (Mill), 206 The Thrice Greatest, 98 Thucydides, 140 Thus Spoke Zarathustra (Nietzsche), 264 Tibetan Buddhism, 404 Timbs, John, 164 time, 36, 281 Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, 408 To be is to be perceived (Berkeley), 161 Togliatti, Palmiro, 28586 Tomlinson, George, 333 totalitarianism, 287 Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (Wittgenstein), 33738 tragedy, 26364 transcendental deduction, 17879 transcendental ego, 18081, 225, 276 transducers, 379 trauma, 248 tree falling in forest making sound, 164 tribe, idols of, 102 trigonometry, 219 truth-functional logic, 33334 truths, 11920, 315 Tucher, Marie von, 230 Tucker, Ellen Louisa, 303 Turing, Alan Mathison, 383 (ill.), 38384 Turing machine, 383
U
unbounded, 13 Unitarians, 305 Unity of Science, 342 Universal Grammar, 377, 378 universal machine, 383 universals, 73 University of Toulouse, 85 unmoved mover, 37 Ursus, Nicolaus, 101 utilitarianism, 174, 208, 356 Utilitarianism (Mill), 206 Utopis (More), 80
V
value, 247, 326 Van Breda, Herman Leo, 274 Van Norden, Bryan W., 407 Vanhomrigh, Esther, 159, 197 veil of ignorance, 361 Venerable Bede of Britain, 60 Venn, John, 220 Venn diagrams, 220, 221 (ill.) Vera Cruz, Alonso de la, 401 verificationism, 340 Vico, Giambattista anachronism, 194 Cartesianism, 19293 cyclical idea of history, 194 first systematic historian, 7 Grotius, Hugo, 194 history, 194 Hobbes, Thomas, 194 interaction with Enlightenment thinkers, 192 mathematics, 19293 opposition to Enlightenment, 192 uniqueness of, 191
unusual autobiography, 193 Vienna Circle, 33940 Ayer, A. J., 34345 Carnap, Rudolf, 34142 mission of, 340 Neurath, Otto, 34243 phenomenalism, 340 Schlick, Moritz, 341 verificationism, 340 virtue, 20 virtue ethics, 353, 354 virtue of selfishness, 35455 Voltaire contributions to philosophy, 188 as encyclopedist, 184 Enlightenment, 181 Leibniz, Gottfried, 137 life of, 187, 188 (ill.) religious views of, 18889 Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, 187
W
Walden Pond, 3012 Walker, Timothy, 30910 Wallace, Alfred Russell, 316 Wallis, John, 140 Walpole, Sir Hugh Seymour, 164 Ward, Lester, 308 Ward, Seth, 140 Wartenberg, Thomas E., 428 Warton, Thomas, 117 Washington, Booker T., 396 Waters, Anne, 399, 400 Watson, James D., 369, 370 Watson, John Broadus (J. B.), 376 Weaver, Jace, 399 Weber, Max, 253 (ill.), 25354 Weil, Felix, 285 Weil, Simone, 271 Weiss, Paul, 311 WELT (acronym), 232 West, Cornel, 397 Western philosophy, 3, 401 Westra, Laura, 422
wheel of life, 404 Whewell, William, 202 British Association of Science, 204 fundamental antithesis of knowledge, 2023 fundamental ideas, 203 induction, 2034 Kant, Immanuel, disagreements with, 203 moral intuitionism, 212, 213 scientific methodology, 203 sensationalistic school, 203 test theories, 204 Whichcote, Benjamin, 150 white supremacy, 309 Whitehead, Alfred North, 328 career, 328 process philosophy, 328 and Russell, Bertrand, 334 world composed of actual occasions, 329 Whitman, Walt, 300 Wilkins, John, 107 will, 127 William III, King, 153 William of Ockam, 77 William of Orange, 145 Williams, Bernard, 356, 358 Wilson, Edward O., 423 Winslet, Kate, 199 Wiredu, Kwasi, 403 wisdom, 1 Wisdom, John, 346, 34849 Witt, Cornelis de, 130 Witt, Johan de, 130 Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 33637 Bouwsma, O. K., 347 life of, 337 logical atomism, 331, 334 Malcolm, Norman, 348 poker, 372 Putnam, Hilary, 369
491
In d e x
Tractatus LogicoPhilosophicus (Wittgenstein), 33738 Wittig, Monique, 413 Wolfowitz, Paul, 363 Wollstonecraft, Mary, 181 claim on behalf of women, 182 feminism, 407 Godwin, William, 183, 184 life of, 18384 main political ideas, 182 views on marriage, 183 womens traits theories, 182 woman as universal term, 413 women Mill, John Stuart, view of, 209 seventeenth-century views of themselves, 15354 women philosophers ancient Greece and Rome, 4547 Arete of Cyrene, 47 Asclepigenia of Athens, 57 Aspasia of Miletus, 46
Diotima of Mantinea, 47 gender as important topic, 15152 Hypatia of Alexandria, 5657 Julia Domna, 46 Makrina, 46 Neoplatonism, 5657 Perictione I, 46 recognized as part of philosophy, 47 Teresa of vila, St., 8182 Theano I of Crotona, 46 Theano II, 46 Themistocles, 46 womens equality, 305 womens health movement, 41415 womens liberation movement, 408 womens movement, 407 womens rights, 241 Wong, David B., 407 Woodhull, Victoria, 306 Woolf, Virginia, 352 (ill.), 353 Wordsworth, William, 130, 303 working class, 238 Worthington, John, 150
Wren, Christopher, 105 Wright, Chauncey, 308, 314 Wright, Richard, 403
X
Xantippe, 24 Xenophon, 24
Y
Yancy, George, 397 Yao, Hsin-chung, 406 Yao, Xinzhong, 406 Yogacara, 404 Yogacara branch of Madyhamika School, 405 Young, Ella Flagg, 320 Young, Iris, 41112 Young, Marion, 409
Z
Zack, Naomi, 397, 41617 Zen Buddhism, 404 Zeno of Citium, 41 Zeno of Elea, 12, 16, 17, 19 Zenos Paradoxes, 18 Zeus, 32
492