Creativity Communication and Cultural Value
Creativity Communication and Cultural Value
Creativity Communication and Cultural Value
qxd
3/27/04 12:27 PM
Page i
Creativity,
Communication and
Cultural Value
Negus-Prelims.qxd
3/27/04 12:27 PM
Page ii
Negus-Prelims.qxd
3/27/04 12:27 PM
Page iii
Creativity,
Communication and
Cultural Value
Keith Negus and Michael Pickering
SAGE Publications
London Thousand Oaks New Delhi
Negus-Prelims.qxd
3/27/04 12:27 PM
Page iv
Negus-Prelims.qxd
3/27/04 12:27 PM
Page v
Contents
Preface
vi
Creation
Experience
22
Industry
46
Convention
68
Tradition
91
Division
115
Genius
138
Bibliography
162
Index
173
Negus-Prelims.qxd
3/27/04 12:27 PM
Page vi
Preface
It is hard to avoid the term creativity. It is one of the most used and abused of
terms at one moment invoked to praise a specific technical skill, at another uttered
in the most vague and casual manner. In any newspaper or magazine we pick up,
we are able to read about the creative work of film directors, actresses, novelists,
musicians, singers and all manner of celebrities. Now a staple byword of the discourse of advertising, were told about creative promotions and campaigns, and
about the personnel awarded for their creative contributions to the industry. The
term is used by teachers in their encouragement of children to express themselves,
expand and grow, and by management consultants seeking to stimulate lateral
thinking at work with the aim of improving company profitability. Scientists are
trained to follow set procedures and methods, but cannot properly explain how they
have come up with a model or theorem in these terms and so resort to notions of
creative inspiration. The term creativity is deployed in so many different contexts,
and with reference to so many different activities, that we may well ask if it has not
been drained of any valid meaning or any useful critical application.
It is because we feel that the term is still worth thinking with, despite sometimes appearing as another specious item of jargon, that we have written this
book. One of our aims is to counter both fallacious and opportunistic uses of it.
There are of course certain words which historically have acquired so much ideological baggage that they are no longer of any valid or acceptable use in contemporary society, but we dont feel that creativity is one of these. It certainly carries
baggage. Indeed, it comes to us laden with a host of meanings, connotations and
applications which are regularly imported into a range of discourses, institutions
and settings. In one sense, this is indicative of its importance. Yet, while the value
and significance of the term are routinely noted, its conceptual status is frequently
taken as an unquestioned commonplace. It is often assumed to be self-evident that
we know what creativity is, or at least we do when we meet it. This assumption
needs challenging. The term has been used in a variety of ways to describe many
diverse actions and activities. More often than not, it is used vaguely and imprecisely, and sometimes in quite contradictory ways. The result usually mystifies more
than it clarifies. This is not only the case with its use in contemporary mundane
discourse; it is often casually introduced into cultural analysis and cultural policy
debates as an uncritically received idea, bringing with it all manner of implications.
In this way creativity is a dominant category, but a residual concept.
In this book we hope to clear some of the accumulated debris surrounding
the notion of creativity and work towards a more refined understanding of it as a
Negus-Prelims.qxd
3/27/04 12:27 PM
Page vii
P R E FA C E
vii
Negus-Prelims.qxd
viii
3/27/04 12:27 PM
Page viii
Negus-Prelims.qxd
3/27/04 12:27 PM
Page ix
P R E FA C E
ix
Negus-Prelims.qxd
3/27/04 12:27 PM
Page x
demands of academic jobs and family life. Writing the book has occasionally been
a frustrating experience, as weve searched for a way to clarify our first muddled
thoughts on an issue or to argue our case with greater coherence. At the same
time, it has benefited from being co-written, as weve honed each others prose
and pooled our knowledge. Were very aware that this book is neither a definitive
nor a conclusive final say on the subject and we wouldnt wish it to be taken as
such. Our hope is that what weve written will provoke and encourage further
thinking, dialogue and critical debate about an activity and process central to our
humanity. We dedicate the book to our children Lucy, Joseph and Oscar who
have continually shown, in their imaginative encounters with the peculiarities of
the world, the mark of their own creative responses and impulses.
Negus-01.qxd
3/27/04 12:27 PM
Page 1
1
Creation
A tangled web of meanings and associations has grown up around the word
creativity. These threads link together conceptions of the elevated and the
mundane, the exceptional and the ordinary. They are a legacy of the terms
etymological development which are usually ignored, but are highly significant.
They are important elements in the range of characteristics that have been
attached to the term creativity.
It has often only been either the elevated and exceptional, or the everyday and ordinary, which have been highlighted. One confers on the term a
rarefied and occasionally mystical air, the other can make the word seem commonplace and even banal. Rarely have the links between both these senses of
the term creativity been retained and explored.
We seek to recover the power inherent in the term for bringing the elevated and the mundane into conjunction, and for illuminating how the exceptional and the ordinary feed off each other. In this chapter we begin exploring
these connections and tensions by tracing the changing meanings of the term
creativity within an influential western trajectory of thought. In doing this, we
highlight the legacies that are carried into contemporary discussions and the
false dichotomies and practical dynamics they produce.
Negus-01.qxd
3/27/04 12:27 PM
Page 2
Negus-01.qxd
3/27/04 12:27 PM
Page 3
C R E AT I O N
as the terms creation and creativity have themselves been more radically
changed. The earliest example (1728) of an explicit connection of imaginative
human creation with a noumenal source, in the mythological personification
of an artistically inspiring goddess, mingles earlier and later senses together in
one rolling phrase: companion of the Muse, Creative Power, Imagination
(Williams, 1976: 73). The reference to imagination is a specifically modern
emphasis, while its companion connects back to the idea of some otherworldly assistance in the creative process.
The idea of a transcendent muse has for a long time seemed decidedly
dated, with all the resonance of a mannered literary conceit, yet the conception of divine inspiration in the act of writing poetry remained a remarkably
strong, even if less than central, element in modernism. The characteristic
effect has been to play down the act of writing itself, as a deliberately learned
and practised craft. This is a point to which we shall return but, as an example,
it can be detected in Yeatss description of the act of poetic creation I made
it out of a mouthful of air as if his own shaping mind had been absent from
the activity of composition. A poem for Yeats was self-begotten. It would be
wrong to suppose that this way of accounting for the act of poetic creation is
merely an enchanting legacy of the Celtic Twilight. Throughout the twentieth
century, when the term creativity became established as denoting the faculty
to which the verb create relates as a process, these earlier associations
continued to be invoked as a very active and more than residual sense of the
term. In his essay The Painter of Modern Life, Baudelaire wrote of
the way in which, for the true artist, the ideal execution becomes unconscious and flowing (1972: 4078). Similarly, John Lennon distinguished
between the songs that he composed simply because a new album had to be
produced, and the real musicthe music of the spheres, the music that surpasses understandingIm just a channelI transcribe it like a medium
(Waters, 1988). The composer, John Taverner, uses the same metaphor, and
refers to auditory visions when he feels that music is being dictated to him
(Barber, 1999).
These descriptions of creative inspiration derive from the conception of
it that grew to prominence during the Romantic period. This accommodated
both the notion of being spoken through, used as a mouthpiece of the muse,
and an emphasis on individual imagination and feeling, for it was through such
faculties that authentic self-expression was felt to flow. More significantly, it was
through imagination and feeling that the artist connected with the impulse of
Nature, with the spirit, as Wordsworth felt it, that is deeply interfused in all
living things and impels all objects of our thought. Allowing this impulse, this
hidden current of life, to speak through us came to define the human act of
creation for Romantic thinkers, with the artist become an emissary of the
divine. The creative artist looked inward for a sense of providential order,
Negus-01.qxd
3/27/04 12:27 PM
Page 4
Negus-01.qxd
3/27/04 12:27 PM
Page 5
C R E AT I O N
substitute for religion in recompense for loss of faith or materialist values which
are thereby disavowed.
From the Romantics onwards, loss of religious faith or antipathy to the
values of industrial capitalism could generate a need for escape from the realities
of material life. The sense of artistic creativity offered a spiritual alternative to what
was seen as an aesthetically debased, socially hostile, money-grubbing world where
goodness, love and beauty were fleeting. So, for example, William Morris wrote
of young men of his generation having grown up during a period of dull bourgeois
philistinism and so being forced to turn back on ourselves, for only in ourselves
and the world of art and literature was there any hope (Thompson, 1977: 14).
Art and literature remained a continuing source of refuge from the mundane realities of the street, the factory and the counting house. It is the opposition between
them that underlies the pathos of Yeatss lines of retrospective self-assessment:
Players and painted stage took all my love,
And not those things that they were emblems of.
The tension between mystical ideal and mundane life or put another way,
between poetic representation and prosaic reality is central to modern
conceptions of art and creativity. Indeed, it is the contrast between the metaphysical and the material, the elevated and the profane, which make the concept of creativity both fascinating and frustrating.
We want to argue that an informed understanding of this can be
reached by attempting to reintegrate both the exceptional and pervasive meanings of the term. Three sets of issues accompany this attempt. Each of them
follow, in different ways, from the inherited meanings and associations of the
term which derive from its historical development.
First, any effort to articulate the experience of the creative process
pushes us to the edge of what words can say. It inevitably involves having to
bridge the gap between the sensational experience of creating whether a
song, poem or painting and the necessity of translating an understanding of
that experience into language that can be communicated to others. The
endurance of this gap is perhaps unavoidable, since those acts of creativity in
which someone is immersed and at one with the act itself are quite distinct
from subsequent, relatively self-conscious efforts to describe what the creative
process involves. This is why we often look to metaphorical forms of expression in referring to the phenomenological experience of creating and it is why
certain creative experiences are rendered in a pseudo-religious or non-rational
manner. Yet because creativity is always achieved within quite specific social,
historical and political circumstances, we should at least be cautious about
making or accepting any grand generalisations about this or any aspect of the
creative process.
Negus-01.qxd
3/27/04 12:27 PM
Page 6
Negus-01.qxd
3/27/04 12:27 PM
Page 7
C R E AT I O N
Negus-01.qxd
3/27/04 12:27 PM
Page 8
Romantics believed. The Romantic argument has been that science has
de-spiritualised Nature as the external world, robbing it of its mystery and
magic, while industrial capitalism has tamed and now threatens to destroy it.
While we can no longer be innocently attuned to Nature as a source of unquestionable moral good, an enduring spiritual need for art and art-making runs
parallel to the desire for an integrated relationship to the natural world. It is
partly because of this that ecological and environmental issues have become a
rallying point of recent social movements. At the same time, Nature, construed
in either sense, is no longer the locus of the creative imagination in the same
way as it was for the Romantic movement.
The locus may have changed, but the value hasnt. The creative imagination continues to exert a strong pull against rationalistic modes of thought
and action. It is commonly recognised that the twin traditions of the
Enlightenment and Romanticism have guided us in quite contrary directions.
What is not so commonly recognised is that their profound influence over the
past two centuries lies also in attempts somehow to reconcile them, to draw
on the powers of both disengaged reason and the creative imagination. So
much of modern culture swings back and forth between them, but moving
towards ways of resolving the tensions between them is also characteristically
modern, even if the impetus towards such a reconciliation comes originally
from Romanticism.
The Romantic vision of integration and wholeness conceived of spiritual
and intellectual fulfilment as one. This has proved widely influential. So, for
example, Marxs ideal of the all-round person embodied the central values of
Romantic humanism. William Morris, likewise, fiercely opposed Victorian
middle-class individualism while maintaining an intense interest in a free, full
life in conscious pursuit of its broadest creative potential. The aspiration to full
consciousness and all-roundness in life has remained in circulation ever since.
It certainly informed Adornos critique of the negative consequences of
Enlightenment thought, and his polemics against the use of culture for propaganda and by the culture industry. It was his hope briefly glimpsed perhaps
in the work of Beethoven and Schoenberg of a union of subject/object, individual/totality that informed his despair at the way such possibilities are
impeded by modern forms of commercial culture. Today, people may feel
sceptical of the Romantic ideals of a spiritualised nature and of self-completion
through art, but because of loss of faith in both God and science, they continue
to aspire to expressive wholeness, or to this in combination with deliberative
rationality. Creativity would not have developed and maintained its largely
positive connotations in the modern period without this continuing aspiration.
The aim of self-creation requires appropriate models, and chief among
these is art. The link forged between artistic creation and self-discovery or selfmaking remains important as an alternative resource to religious faith, or to
Negus-01.qxd
3/27/04 12:27 PM
Page 9
C R E AT I O N
scientism and the iron cage of reason. Ideas about creativity have become
integral to the modern sense of individuality because the sense of being ourselves implies expressing ourselves, in speech and in action, and so arriving at
what is distinctive and special about us, or what it is we strive towards. Since
the days of Herder and Hegel and the European Romantics, the expressivist
turn has fed directly into this modern conception of the individual, and the
artist has been heroised as the agent par excellence of original self-creation:
Artistic creation becomes the paradigm mode in which people can come to
self-definition (Taylor, 1991: 62).
Many writers and artists have come to revere this conception of selfdefinition through the long historical route in which the twin traditions of the
Enlightenment and Romanticism have played themselves off in a cultural tango
across time. The search for a model of mature self-identity has switched
between both traditions, yet it is the artist, and artistic imagination, which
remain paradigmatic, rather than the scientist and scientific rationality. Albert
Einstein, perhaps the most iconic figure of modern western science, readily
acknowledged this debt to artistic inspiration when he said that Im enough of
an artist to draw freely on my imagination, which I think is more important
than knowledge. Knowledge is limited. Imagination encircles the world
(Viereck, 1929).
Imagination remains key to thinking about creativity because it is continually regarded as the source of challenge to rules and conventions, as a way
of recombining different aspects of tradition and knowledge in their previous
arrangements, and perhaps most importantly, as a means to move beyond
existing horizons of experience. What has accompanied the modern value
placed on imagination has been a decisive move to the dynamic sense of creating difference, in both art and self-development. This has shifted the model
of both art and individuality from imitation (mimesis) to innovation (creation).
The ascendancy of innovation as a cultural value is the second major consequence of the transfer of creation and originality from God to the human imagination, and it is to this that we now turn.
Negus-01.qxd
10
3/27/04 12:27 PM
Page 10
Negus-01.qxd
3/27/04 12:27 PM
Page 11
C R E AT I O N
11
Negus-01.qxd
12
3/27/04 12:27 PM
Page 12
aesthetics and commodity culture developed out of the same dynamic of social
and historical change, and both were cultural formations in the western capitalist order. Their coexistence has continued across the past two centuries. The
Romantic sensibility fed into modern consumerism by encouraging and legitimising the myth of autonomous hedonism, while at the same time offering a
philosophy of recreation manifest in the search for self-expression and selfrealisation necessary for a dynamic consumerism. Hence the premium on
ever-renewing novelty. Romanticism also provided a vision that has been taken
over by consumer culture, promising to satisfy the need for passion, plenitude,
creative dreaming and an integrated self.
So the stark differentiation between art and marketised culture is
clearly ideological: Modern societies simultaneously need exposure to
broaden the market and the consumption of goods in order to increase the
rate of profit and distinction which, in order to confront the massifying
effects of exposure, recreates the signs that differentiate the hegemonic
sectors (Garca Canclini, 1995: 17, emphases in original). In practice, many
people have moved and increasingly move between high culture and commodity culture and are not everywhere stratified into fixed positions of attachment and affiliation.
Critical opposition to a consumerist aesthetic, which has taken various
political shades, assumes that consumerism is a promise which is as ever unfulfilled as it is endlessly repeated. While empirical evidence for this is often lacking, it is clear that consumerism can hardly bear the burdens of self-definition,
appetite and longing which are placed upon it. Consumer spectacle and pleasure are one side of modern life. On its reverse are resentment, frustration and
dissatisfaction with the limits of commodity culture, where the dreams of consumption collapse into disappointment because they cannot satisfy our more
radical needs for new ways of being in the world. Since they do not, they
shouldnt detract from the force of the opposition to cold calculation and a
strict means-end approach to social organisation and arrangements. It is
central to our argument that this opposition derives a good deal of its force
from the alternative values vested in the idea of creativity, and in turn of creativity as an alternative source of innovation. These alternative values and the
practices associated with them may be exploited in business and marketing,
but they remain distinct from commercial logic and are not always and everywhere synonymous with consumer culture.
Such opposition may seem increasingly in danger of being absorbed by
consumer culture but it retains sources of creative fantasy and dreaming outside of consumerism. Critical evaluation of experience, both inner experience
and the experience of social encounters and relationships, as represented in
ballad, novel, biography or film, is also clearly based on far more than market
efficiency and personal satisfaction. Confining attention to such efficiency and
Negus-01.qxd
3/27/04 12:27 PM
Page 13
C R E AT I O N
satisfaction is the Benthamite position, leading directly to the view that push-pin
is of equal value with poetry (Bentham, 1962: 253). Evaluation is built on
qualitative contrasts, and abandonment of such contrasts is a utilitarian option.
To take this option would leave us only with calculative methods when faced
with situations where calculation is not appropriate. It would leave us without
a vocabulary for expressing and assigning differential values to things. Without
such a vocabulary, our lives would be mechanical and shallow and our sense
of agency seriously diminished.
The concept of agency brings us back to the question of self-discovery
and self-making. If agency is vital for an adequate sense of selfhood, then to
be a person is to be an agent who has an understanding of self as agent
(Taylor, 1985: 103). Agency in this sense enables a move beyond the utilitarian scheduling of satisfactions, towards a critical evaluation of wants and
desires in terms of their quality and worth. The capacity for strength of evaluation is therefore not just a condition of articulacy about preferences, but also
about the quality of life, the kind of beings we are or want to be (ibid.: 26).
Such capacity is a condition of identity, and while there are numerous conditions involved in the formation of identity, many people continue to feel that
who they are or want to be is bound up with what they value and where they
find expressive quality that stirs them, in things they can speak of and things
that seem to fly beyond the confines of what they can say, even as they feel
them very strongly.
Such value and quality are not only found in established literary and
artistic canons, since they are located in the whole range of cultural experience, in popular culture as much as in the classics. In this respect, the premium put upon novelty is not necessarily at odds with exemplary past
achievements. Bearing in mind the negative evaluations that are still placed on
novelty, the continuance of a positive dimension for the term is what is especially interesting about the associative properties it has acquired. This dimension of its meaning continues to co-exist with the emphasis on short-lived,
superficial features and their quality of inherent redundancy, but it now places
an alternative emphasis on the newness in what is novel as a quality that is
actively endorsed and identified with, even if we may feel an occasional need
to support this with a qualifying adverb, as in truly novel. This sort of evaluation is, of course, problematic. What is truly novel is always easy to claim
but difficult to establish, particularly when it exceeds anyones specific cultural
experience, as for instance of a narrative genre involving an appreciation of its
finer variations and cumulative accretions of development. This is not available
to those with little knowledge of, or with actual distaste for, what they see as
its characteristic features. The same is true of other forms of art and cultural
production. So, for instance, Roger Scruton, in responding to grunge rock and
heavy metal, can only call such genres a negation of music, a dehumanising
13
Negus-01.qxd
14
3/27/04 12:27 PM
Page 14
of the spirit of song because of his use of aesthetic standards and criteria from
the tradition of harmonic texture and tonality associated with western art
music, and because of his failure to attend to what informed popular audiences
experience and understand when they listen to such genres (2002: 131; and
see Gracyk, 2002: 13547).
Despite the difficulties of evaluation and judgement, cultural practices
are continually being drawn on, updated and revised in everyday life. This is
what happens when we borrow a figurative phrase we have heard and apply
it in a different situation for comic or dramatic effect; when we tell a story
about certain experiences in our lives, drawing on, yet subtly diverging from,
the tacitly known rules and repertoires of storytelling; when we take an old
song and use it in a new social context; or when we collaborate with others in
organising and thinking up novel elements for a specific public performance,
such as a commemorative event, or a local exhibition or pageant. What occurs
in such cases is modification and variation, leading to degrees of newness in
relation to what is established and already in social circulation. These adaptations operate within established cultural themes, codes and conventions, but
are worked up to suit specific people or social groups and an immediate social
purpose. As Ruth Finnegan has put it, they can represent an intensely personal creation, not just an automatic reflection of the cultural resources which
both mould and are moulded by them (1997a: 93). For certain cultural practices and artistic modes, then, it is only through the co-operative observance
of agreed conventions and collaborative networks that individuals actively
participate (Finnegan, 1997b: 129).
The active participation in these revisions, and sometimes subtly
realised qualities of newness, is quite different to the moment of innovation
which is subsequently evaluated as a radical disruption of generic rules and
expectations. Yet both require and entail the practice of creativity, and so pluralise its meaning and value. The different kinds of creative response to what
is culturally novel and to the various discoveries that people make in the course
of individual lives can be vitally important in growing up, in learning and in
exploring the worlds of both natural and social reality. In taking these discoveries into account, we have to recognise the full range of creative practice and
response, and the tensions of use, participation and understanding that run
across it. These cover intensely personal creations, and hitherto unrealised
conjugations of images, styles and idioms that affect a whole artistic or cultural
field. They involve both modifications to what is commonplace and ordinary,
and abrupt shifts from familiar form and settled convention, when a new quality of discovery opens up in what is now suddenly knowable rather than
already, durably, known. Such contrasts give the idea of creativity its dynamic
sense and force of meaning.
Negus-01.qxd
3/27/04 12:27 PM
Page 15
C R E AT I O N
15
Negus-01.qxd
16
3/27/04 12:27 PM
Page 16
musical artists speak of not being in control of their own bodies or thought
processes when composing, writing or improvising.
We can neither accept nor dismiss these as metaphorical conceits or
misguided delusions. They are actually integral to the issue were concerned
with. Although we live in an apparently cynical and knowing postmodern age,
we still have to engage with religious and metaphysical explanations of creative
inspiration because of the ways in which they distil important spiritual and aesthetic concerns for many people. That is why we have emphasised the links
with notions of spirituality and spiritual life which are retained in the modern,
secularised conception of creativity. Our broader interest lies in establishing the
relations between the ordinary and the exceptional, and clearly an approach
which locates art on the border of numinous experience runs against this in
associating creativity exclusively with radical innovation and an ethereal artistic inspiration as its source. That, in turn, is why we have dwelt at length on
the difficulties associated with ideas about novelty as these vacillate between
inclusive and exclusive senses of what is new or what is to be evaluated as new.
So while spiritual and aesthetic concerns are part of the continuing evaluative meanings associated with creativity, we need to place them within the
general gamut of its significances without at the same time widening them to
the extent that the term dissolves into banality. One way of doing this is to consider how anyone may become adept at an artistic or cultural practice in the
first place. There is no one, fixed, or universally applicable route through
which this process occurs but, as an example of a particular approach, we
want to draw on and adapt the phenomenology of human learning provided
by Hubert and Stuart Dreyfus (Dreyfus and Dreyfus, 1986; see also Dreyfus,
2001; Flyvbjerg, 2001). This was developed in a different tradition of enquiry
to that which concerns us here, and their model fights shy of dealing substantively with creativity. It nevertheless seems to us suggestive in thinking about
the human acquisition of skills, attributes and abilities in a manner appropriate
to the aspects of creativity were discussing. The outline we sketch takes us
beyond the point of becoming competent where skills and capacities are raised
to a level of practice that attains or seems to attain its own dynamic rhythm
and movement. This is more or less the way many musicians, poets and writers talk of creative practice, in both the fine and popular arts, when they refer
to being at one with what they do, forgetting the means by which their
making or performing is accomplished and losing sense of where they are,
temporally and spatially. It is then as if their skills and capacities are not consciously applied and the process of making or performing feels different and
is perceived in a different way. This difference is sometimes caught in the contrast people make between doing something deliberately and doing the same
thing naturally, as for instance with dancing or playing a musical instrument.
Although what naturally means here is problematic and in need of qualification,
Negus-01.qxd
3/27/04 12:27 PM
Page 17
C R E AT I O N
17
Negus-01.qxd
18
3/27/04 12:27 PM
Page 18
dexterity and flair, but they do not learn the conventional vocabulary of
motives and explanations for their work (Becker, 1984: 266). Their explanations are often highly idiosyncratic and for this reason they may be dismissed
as eccentric or cranky. This dismissal is usually made on the basis of a level of
competence conventional within the art world and not that of their own immediate social circle or their own perceptions and values. In some ways, though,
applying Bourdieus explanation of competence to the attainment of creative
proficiency in art and cultural production may reduce skills and abilities to
social class, upbringing and education.
Creative competence and skill is acquired from more than formal education. Competence operates with a grasp of what is objectively possible, but
in becoming proficient there is an ascent of experience and understanding
from analytical rationality to an unencumbered command of action happening
in tune with situation and context. In writing, dancing or making music,
acting, sculpting or painting, the difference is between thinking what to do and
no longer distinguishing between thinking and doing. It is about bridging the
ideological divide between rationality and intuition, for what is happening now
is a rational grasp of what is intuitively right and an intuitive grasp of what is
rationally possible. It is effort becoming effortless. Analytical rationality cannot
grasp such performance, yet we all know it when we see it, whether this is on
a football pitch or a concert stage. The performer plays like an angel.
This colloquialism is an appropriate expression for what is involved in
the appreciation of such performance, even if it is somewhat hackneyed. It
shows how people use a metaphorical expression with connections to religious
mythology and spirituality in order to indicate their feeling of delight in excellence, but they use a clich in order to maintain its links with ordinariness. So
we need to stress that it doesnt belong in a privileged aesthetic realm. Our
examples deliberately bring high and low culture together in disqualification of
the divide between them, while consciously playing on the word play in doing
this. For it is this unselfconscious absorption in the play that is important,
enabling us to use a clich to rejuvenate a clich. The simultaneous loss and
realisation of self in play occurs in every cultural form and entails a move
beyond the rational accomplishment of competence.
This move beyond competence in the creative process cannot be
explained entirely by reference to the structures and gradations of social difference. If this was the case then all artistic and cultural production would be
causally linked to peoples relative position in the social structure and to what
this position makes objectively possible. Certainly class or other social differences may be ideologically inscribed in aesthetic judgements about creativity
and innovation, but this is different to the realisation of creative practice, at
whatever gradation this occurs. Creativity is not simply the functional correlation of competence and social class. The danger remains that of subsuming all
Negus-01.qxd
3/27/04 12:27 PM
Page 19
C R E AT I O N
questions not only of aesthetic significance and value, but also of cultural
production and performance, into their sociological explanation.
The path were tracing is from learning how to act in already structured
situations to knowing how to respond to situations which are relatively unstructured. This requires a synthesis of abstract knowledge and concrete know-how.
It involves a shift from exercising deliberative rationality contextually and adaptively, to embodied involvement in performance where we move on the turning wing with what is being done. There is in this movement an implicit
rejection of the false divide between rationality and intuition, for they have
come to act in concert with each other, in a mutually enhancing absorption
and understanding.
This is different to analytical rationality. Such rationality has its own
values, but these are not absolute. In the embrace of human experience they
are applicable to some practices, but not to all. Failing to recognise this leads
to a foreshortened view in the social analysis of art and culture, and at times
even to a justification of this failure in the interests of demystification. We share
in those interests, and not least because in referring to the intuitive grasp of
skills and conventions in creative practice, we are not at all invoking some mystical spirit that guides anyone towards the goal of artistic originality.
Nonetheless, we do want to find a way of encompassing what people tangibly
experience as creative proficiency, as talent in sure touch with its own actions
and its self-absorbed flow.
This is clearly related to the sense of being taken over by the process of
acting creatively. In one way we can regard the retention of metaphysical
traces in many peoples conception of creativity as resulting from the difficulty
they have in explaining it, but in quite another way this aspect of their conception remains a positive value to which they consciously adhere. Many
poets, musicians, painters and writers have spoken of the experience of being
so caught up in the making of their art that they seem to be taken over, as if
the strokes of the brush or pen are occurring of their own accord. When interviewed and asked to reflect on how he wrote drama scripts, Dennis Potter
spoke of the skills involved, his awareness of how these skills were different to
other forms of writing, and the sense of both shaping and being shaped by the
writing the sensation which comes when effort becomes effortless:
It doesnt feel like writing an essay. It doesnt feel like making an argument. It
doesnt feel like having a purpose. It feels like something you knew but didnt
know you knew. It feels like dreaming. Sometimes you get that sense of dj vu,
then you say, Ive been here, or, surely youve said that before. That slightly
creepy, prickly feeling that theres a script. Or a memory will come plunging at
you through an old piece of music, however banal, or through a smell or a shape.
The way a room is patterned will remind you of another room, one you havent
thought about in thirty or forty years.
19
Negus-01.qxd
20
3/27/04 12:27 PM
Page 20
Writing is like that. I never have a plot. I dont have a schema. I want to know
whats happening. I want to know why. But I dont do it because I want to know
why. Im doing it, and then I want to know why
When youre doing it, its a bit like a dream, but a troubled dream the kind of
dream you want to wake from, although not a nightmare. But the intensity of the
experience is such that you are almost receiving what youre writing. Of course,
youre shaping it at the same time, and then you add to it also. Its an odd thing,
knowing that a scene has got to come to an end, or that youve got to make a
turn. You dont know what its going to be, just that you must then its done. Its
being on a trip. Its being subject to it as well as controlling it. (Potter, 1993: 268)
Negus-01.qxd
3/27/04 12:27 PM
Page 21
C R E AT I O N
21
Negus-02.qxd
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 22
2
Experience
Thinking about creativity entails understanding an experience or range of
experiences as much as engaging with the changing meanings of a concept.
The creative experience is something which is intensely felt. It often seems to
defy language as if words are incapable of fully capturing the sensation
involved, or of explaining what went into the making of a particular artistic
form. While we must keep this in mind, it remains the case that the creative
experience requires a will to expression, and to communication with others.
This is evident in numerous narratives and anecdotes through which artists and
inventors have sought to provide an account of what their creative efforts have
involved and been driven by.
In devoting a chapter to experience, we wish to emphasise these two
issues: expression and communication. In doing this we dont mean to present
experience as something which comes prior to or which simply follows artistic expression and communication. Instead, we argue that our experience of
the world is shaped and given significance by the act of creation, and that our
understanding of the world is realised through the process of communication.
People do not as artists, writers, musicians have some pre-formed condition which they then seek to express in an art form and communicate to
others. The contours and characteristics of experience are given form, meaning and value through the process of expression and communication.
If this sounds rather abstract we can take a couple of simple examples.
A songwriter may decide to write a sad song, regardless of how theyre feeling at that moment. A painter may wish to convey a sense of anger at the
atrocities of war. We may hear the song or see the painting and interpret it as
an example of someone condensing their experience into song form or pictorial representation and then relaying it to us. But the act of expressing whatever sadness or anger we may recognise and relate to is realised in the act of
making the song and painting. It doesnt exist in some pure or prior state
which words, music or paint then approximate in some way or other. And
while different media may impart certain features and characteristics to what
is communicated, they do not in themselves account for the significance of
what is communicated.
Negus-02.qxd
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 23
EXPERIENCE
23
Negus-02.qxd
24
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 24
Negus-02.qxd
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 25
EXPERIENCE
exist independently of the creative product and which simply result from the
intention to communicate them. They only exist as realised in their expressive
medium. Expression in this sense condenses experience into meaningful shape
through the words, images and sounds given to it. In referring to expression
were not suggesting that a painter, writer or musician is engaged in directly
relaying either a pre-given psychological state or some essential aspect of
social experience. How we understand jealousy, for example, or how were
able to relate to what people may have suffered, physically or emotionally, is
inseparable from the form in which it is communicated. It is within their art
and practice that painters, writers and musicians give a voice to and convey a
potent sense of such states and experiences as combinations of sounds, words
and images. Poets or songwriters are not simply aware of the prior meaning
of what they feel in their hearts and then merely find the words and rhythms
to express this feeling. This is a Romantic fallacy. What is felt is mediated by
the verse, lyrics, rhythm or beat as a form of creative expression. It is realised
in sounds, words and gestures. Psychological states of experience like love or
anger are given form by the language and music in which they achieve expression even though they dont consist entirely of this expression. The expression
itself partly forms them, in dynamic interaction with known or intuitively
sensed inter-emotional states or feelings.
So we dont have a fully formed, reflexively comprehended experience
which we then reproduce in verbal, sonic or plastic form. What this experience
means to us, and how we may value it, is usually only discovered in the form
of utterance or figuration that is given to it. The expression not only forms the
experience but also transforms it, making it into something whose meaning
changes our understanding of it. Without its representation in words or sounds
an experience often doesnt signify for us at all, for a feeling or an idea associated with it is made manifest through the combination of materials that characterise any particular cultural representation. Its because of this that poets,
composers and musicians are often taken aback at what they create and often
only retrospectively comprehend what they were attempting to express. For
example, John Ashbery, an American poet, has said of his writing: If I did not
write, I would have no idea of what I can write. I suppose that I write so as to
find what I have to write (Clark, 1997: 18). The French philosopher MerleauPonty put it this way my own words take me by surprise and teach me what
I think (ibid.: 19). For some, the experience of surprise may provide the basis
for an urge to create and express precisely what the experience signifies. The
surrealist painter de Chirico couched his sense of exceeding the limits of any
conscious artistic intent in terms of the strangeness of everything in the world:
I remember one vivid winters day at Versailles. Silence and calm reigned
supreme. Everything gazed at me with mysterious, questioning eyes. And then I
25
Negus-02.qxd
26
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 26
realised that every corner of the palace, every column, every window possessed
a spirit, an impenetrable soul. I looked around at the marble heroes, motionless
in the lucid air, beneath the frozen rays of that winter sun which pours down on
us without love, like perfect song. A bird was warbling in a window cage. At that
moment I grew aware of the mystery which urges men to create certain strange
forms. And the creation appeared more extraordinary than the creators. (cited in
Harrison and Wood, 2001: 601, emphasis in original)
Negus-02.qxd
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 27
EXPERIENCE
27
Negus-02.qxd
28
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 28
Negus-02.qxd
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 29
EXPERIENCE
29
Negus-02.qxd
30
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 30
Negus-02.qxd
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 31
EXPERIENCE
31
Negus-02.qxd
32
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 32
scene there for a moment as if it was fixed, carved out of time, producing in
her the feeling that all outcomes, on all scales from the tiniest to the most
colossal were already in place:
Whatever happened in the future, however superficially strange or shocking,
would also have an unsurprising, familiar quality, inviting her to say, but only to
herself, Oh yes, of course. That. I should have known. (McEwan, 2002: 53)
Negus-02.qxd
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 33
EXPERIENCE
We turn experience into stories all the time in our everyday life, and
these stories range in their importance according to how significant they
become for us in the present, in memories and in the re-evaluations we make
of them in successive periods of our lives. The actions and experiences of
other people are made intelligible by the stories told of them or by them. Our
own actions and experiences are rendered meaningful by the narratives in
which they are placed and as these communicate with other people. It is
because we all live out narratives in our lives and because we understand our
own lives in terms of the narratives that we live out that the form of narrative
is appropriate for understanding the actions of others. Narrative is thus
central to understanding human action: I can only answer the question What
am I to do? if I can answer the prior question Of what story or stories do I
find myself a part (MacIntyre, 1985: 212, 216). Indeed, the importance of
narrative is such that it has been claimed as perhaps the most fundamental
form for making sense of experience, for narratives not only give meaningful
form to experiences we have lived through but also provide us a forward
glance, helping us to anticipate situations even before we encounter them,
allowing us to envision alternative futures (Flyvbjerg, 2001: 137). Richard
Rorty has claimed that narrative, and storytelling, are central to how we
acquire knowledge of ourselves and other people and cultures in the modern
world. He argues that the novel, the movie, and the TV programme have,
gradually but steadily, replaced the sermon and the treatise as the principle
vehicles of moral change and progress (1989: xvi).
Communicating experience through the stories we make of it allows us
to share our experience with others and so help to make sense of it. Refiguring
our lives in narrative form does not occur spontaneously but is shaped by social
location, historical circumstances and interaction with parents, siblings, friends
and strangers. In communicating through stories we draw on shared linguistic
and cultural resources and shape them to our will. It is in this shaping of experience to form that creativity often achieves its value for us, whether as producers or perceivers of its results.
Sometimes putting events, episodes or relationships into narrative form
enables us to see and understand them differently. We may respond to existing social conditions and circumstances through the distance which stories
afford. It is then through such stories that were able to loosen their hold on
us, so enabling us to move on and away from what has previously tied us
down.
The formation of individual narratives is closely related to the ideal of
self-determination in modern societies whereby it is believed that the primary
responsibility for our own self-development lies with us and not with anyone
else. This common ideal has been reinforced by the growth of a critically
reflexive approach to our biographical past and the spread of an ethically
33
Negus-02.qxd
34
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 34
loaded notion that we actively construct our own life-narratives. The sense
that we are creators of our identities is manifest in the expressive form we give
to them.
Narrative is the way in which we make sense of memories and prognoses, chance and coincidence, limits and possibilities. In life we frequently
occupy the position of a storyteller in the midst of the story we are living.
Striving to bring together the teller, the telling and the told for ourselves and
for others is then the problem of identity, articulating our experience of reality as both acting on us, and being acted on by us, in a reciprocal relation. In
communicating experience we creatively transform it, bringing into synthesis
what would otherwise remain diffuse and dispersed, and in that synthesis posing a new set of possibilities. In the various forms and genres we utilise, we
recreate the past and so transform it into something different, whether this is
based on childhood experience or remembered events such as a car crash, a
political demonstration or a celebritys public humiliation. Creativity works with
the materials given to it by experience in order to make something more
meaningful, compelling or true than experience itself as, for instance, may be
the case with a love poem, a gospel song or a Greek tragedy. The creative
realisation of experience in this sense seems to make it more real.
As this occurs, the creative realisation of experience may sometimes
involve an intense, even anguished struggle against inherited meanings
and forms. Trying to say something in an innovative way, or move beyond
common-sense meanings and conventional storylines, can be an arduous and
not necessarily fruitful quest. It may seem that that the past weighs down
heavily on the effort to achieve a new way of expressing our experience or,
in the face of stock codes and outworn conventions, articulating a more faithful narration of it in a changed present. This is, for instance, why James
Joyce felt that it was imperative to escape from the nets of nationality, language and religion which bore down on him as components of his education
and heritage. His escape from these nets involved a self-chosen exile, an
intransigent absence from his homeland which he maintained in order to give
force to his artistic vocation...to sustain the strictest opposition to what was
familiar (Said, 1984: 168). There his achievement as a novelist was in forging innovative fictional modes for encompassing ordinary experience in
everyday life, so de-familiarising it and showing us how extraordinary it is. His
novel Ulysses bears marvellous witness to this. Exile abroad also creatively
freed him from the illusion of authorial omniscience and the need to provide
his readers with an apparently secure and transparent position in relation to
the narrative text. His writing became inherently multifaceted, playful,
ambiguous, even in Finnegans Wake cacophonous in its break with the
sense of any necessary relay between literary representation and a reality outside language and discourse.
Negus-02.qxd
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 35
EXPERIENCE
Later generations of Irish writers have, in different ways, felt the same
need to break with the national ethos, to subvert expectation and escape
restriction. In the late 1930s, Patrick Kavanagh moved to Dublin from the
border county of Monaghan. He was installed in the self-styled literary metropolis of Dublin as the authentic peasant by those he later denounced as rascals
pretending to have an interest in poetry. Kavanagh defied this rustic inscription since he found it deeply patronising stereotypically stage-Irish, offering
only a self-limiting passivity. The configuration of Irish national literature which
he confronted was at that time set in the shadow of the late Celtic Twilight,
with its hugely rhetorical investment in a false pastoral, a view of Ireland
invented by Yeats, Lady Gregory and Synge, and subsequently lauded for supposedly distilling the Irish quality. Put that together with peasant quality and
you have a measure of the difficulties facing Kavanagh in his effort to write
honestly about his own experience. His view was caustic. The so-called Irish
literary movement was for him a thoroughly English-bred lie, while the
Irishness it advanced was little other than anti-art (Kavanagh, 1964: 9, 12,
15, 223).
Each generation faces new kinds of restriction and reduction of who
they are or might be. These stand in need of challenge and disruption. The
successors of Kavanagh in this regard include those contemporary women
poets in Ireland who seek in their work to subvert the incarnation of land and
nation in such clichd, ornamental figures as Cathleen ni Houlihan or Dark
Rosaleen: passive, controlled images that instruct and obstruct the expression
of womens experience. For Eavan Boland, for instance, the national ethos has
to be resisted and circumvented where the permissions it issues as to what
poetry can be about deny that articulation of female experience, in the lives of
ordinary Irish women. Ideologically it turns the woman as subject into the
image as object. The transaction of the passive/feminine/national and the
active/expressive/male Irish poet is for her the major form of these negative
permissions and reductions, and it is this which has now been disestablished:
I cant think of anything more disruptive than that Irish women within a
generation should alter that arrangement and break the terms of that longstanding contract (Bowland, 1995: 445; see also Ryan, 2002).
In grappling with experience creativity can be thwarted by the pain and
misery of remembering what that experience involved. Certain experiences
may be repressed because the trauma associated with them has become too
much for our conscious selves to carry in their full recognition. Sexual abuse,
rape, sadistic forms of humiliation or the wartime experience of violence and
brutality all provide examples of experiences whose repression runs counter to
an exhilarating narrative sense of Proustian recovery, when what emerges
from involuntary memory produces a feeling of renewal, freshness and light.
Resistance to communicating past experience may arise from reasons we
35
Negus-02.qxd
36
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 36
Negus-02.qxd
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 37
EXPERIENCE
Despite the blockages, ruptures and severe twists of memory that can
obstruct our remembering and retellings of the past, we live our lives through
our attempts to make a coherent narrative out of them. We develop an understanding of ourselves by configuring our lives as a developing narrative. This
informs our sense of who we are by providing a notion of how we have
become and of where we are going (Taylor, 1989: 47). Of course, in the
stories we tell of our lives, or the attention we pay to the stories other people
tell of their lives, we follow certain narrative conventions, certain ways of effectively aligning form and content in the communication of experience. Tacitly
or otherwise, we identify general features in such storytelling, as for example
the placing of events and episodes in temporal sequence and order, or the
charting of an intelligible plot that comes to unite them. These are ways of
organising experience, and attaining to some form of coherence across all that
happens to us in our lives. In Ruth Finnegans words, it is through storytelling
that we experience and recognise that experience. In doing so, in their selfnarratives, people play a creative role in formulating both their own identities
and, by extension, the culture in which they are participants (Finnegan,
1997a: 767).
37
Negus-02.qxd
38
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 38
an audience (ibid.: 31). Williams suggested that for art to succeed it must
convey an experience to others in such a form that the experience is actively
re-created not contemplated, not examined, not passively received, but by
response to the means, actually lived through, by those to whom it is offered.
At this stage, a number of art-works already fail (ibid.: 345).
The virtue of thinking of creativity as the effectively achieved and
actively received communication of experience is that it affirms a view of creativity as a socially inclusive rather than exclusive ability without evading the
value question, and leads us away from a focus simply on the text itself. The
whole point of trying to understand creativity in terms of the quality of communicated experience and the forms in which such experience is re-created is
that it refuses the reification of artistic or cultural work, whether this is a novel,
a painting, a popular song or a film. Reification, in this sense, occurs when an
artwork or performance is conceived in abstract isolation, as a text or practice
removed from the social contexts of which it is or was a component part.
Reification in cultural analysis relates to the outmoded, yet still prevalent, view
that a cultural text or performance has only inherent meaning.
So for instance, in this view music, particularly that selectively identified
and canonised as great, has an intrinsic autonomy that raises it above the
social and political world. This autonomy guarantees its greatness. Reified aesthetics have been applied not only to art music but also to certain forms of
popular music. For example, Carl Engel, in an organicist metaphor adopted
without acknowledgement by Cecil Sharp, described what have become
known as folk songs as akin to the wild flowers indigenous to a country, which
thrive unaided by art (Engel, 1866: 23; Sharp, 1907: 1). In England, during
the later nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, this notion informed and
supported the co-option of folk music in the nationalist mission of its musical
renaissance (see Hughes and Stradling, 2001). But the aesthetics of music in
itself have had a much broader influence, acting, for instance, as a central
tenet of professional musicologys maintenance of boundaries and enclosures
and providing appropriate collateral for a life and works paradigm of intellectual scholarship which fails to connect musical composition and structure to
ideology, or social space, or power, or to the formation of an individual (and
by no means sovereign) ego (Said, 1991: xiixiii).
Our emphasis on achieving communicative value through experience is
intended to connect music and other forms of art not only with these large-scale
sociological issues, but also with the realisation of creative possibility in the phenomena of everyday life. A nice example of what this involves, bringing art and
popular music together and confounding their artificial separation, is the way in
which Mahler drew on his childhood experience of apparently unrelated sounds
coming from different directions, as for instance in his Third Symphony. Natalie
Bauer-Lechner recalled a trip to a country fair with the composer:
Negus-02.qxd
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 39
EXPERIENCE
39
Negus-02.qxd
40
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 40
Negus-02.qxd
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 41
EXPERIENCE
of it is based on the degree to which we realise and exceed the finite illusion
of the mutual separation of cultures and histories. This is where our imaginative grasp of the possibilities posed by other cultures, traditions and languages
becomes a locus of creative extension of our own temporally and spatially specific cultural experience. It is the creation of an enduring relationship between
the near and the far which becomes a key dynamic of cultural change and creative renewal.
41
Negus-02.qxd
42
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 42
Deweys argument for a democratic art and aesthetic lay not only in
these now familiar criticisms of officially accredited art and aestheticism but
also in his conception of art and the aesthetic as constitutive of experience.
This emerges from his refusal to set art and the aesthetic off from everyday
life. Their spiritualised separation from everyday life, with upper-case Art
becoming the beauty parlour of civilisation (1980: 14), is a loss for both art
and the everyday. Art becomes irrelevant to everyday life when cut off from its
intimate social connection, while everyday life is considered primarily in instrumental terms as the realm from which labour can be extracted and utilised
without reference to the need people have for an imaginative, affective and
holistic engagement in what they do, day by day, when they work. Art
becomes a place of refuge and escape; labour becomes alienated from its own
sources of satisfaction and reward.
Art is important for everyday life because it can change our way of
seeing, thinking and experiencing, and not just incidentally or peripherally. For
Dewey, though, the main point at issue is this: the conditions that create the
gulf which exists generally between producer and consumer in modern society
operate to create also a chasm between ordinary and aesthetic experience,
with so much of production a form of postponed living and so much of consumption a form of superimposed enjoyment (1980: 10, 27). These divides
in modern life result in an asocially conceived aestheticism and the beauty parlour conception of art, along with a hierarchical division of artistic and cultural
production. Dewey opposed this by emphasising the importance of ordinary
experience in creating and receiving artworks and cultural products. What
matters aesthetically is thus not the work of art or cultural product as objects
which, once reified, become commodified and fetishised. What matters is how
artistic creativity and cultural production relate to experience, what an art
product does with and in experience, how experience becomes aesthetically
funded and so resonant with expressive meaning. It is then that the rhythm of
genuinely creative or appreciative experience is not broken by the shift
between means and end, for means here are never merely means nor are
ends superlatively and aloofly set off by themselves (Geiger, 1974: 345).
Art, as Dewey wrote, is the sole alternative to luck; and divorce from each
other of the meaning and value of instrumentalities and ends is the essence of
luck. The esoteric character of [high] culture and the supernatural quality of
religion are both expressions of the divorce (1925: 372).
Experience and what is made of it, the art object and how it is experienced, are concurrent and cut across the false dichotomies of mind and body,
subject and object, feeling and thought, high and low art. Such distinctions
create artificial boundaries and exclusions, made in fear of what life may bring
forth (1980: 22; and Armstrong, 2000: 164). Deweys opposition to these artificial boundaries and exclusions was consonant with his critique of conventional
Negus-02.qxd
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 43
EXPERIENCE
43
Negus-02.qxd
44
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 44
examples and cases come from the fine arts and high culture Rembrandt,
Keats, Beethoven but the main tenets of his argument apply just as well to
popular culture and the popular arts, and central to these is the set of relations
between art and experience. Rather than seeing popular forms as inferior
because they are so much a part of everyday life, we need to see high cultural
aesthetics as deficient when their connections with the everyday are denied.
What counts for any cultural product or performance is not how it is aesthetically ranked, but how it runs its course to fulfilment. Focusing on creativity as
the communication of experience returns art to time, but a time of heightened
vitality when an experience is completed because it absorbs the past and future
into itself in a new and dynamic resolution. Through the expressive and narrative forms given to experiences of this kind, we realise the meanings of experiences we have lived through, and gain forward glances to new possibilities.
These are the moments of creativity in which our lives are illuminated
backwards and forwards, but the illumination they bring is only realised in acts
of communication. Our lives as a series of experiences are woven together and
given significance through the ways they attain communicative value. This
value lies in its connections of the ordinary and the exceptional. Artforms of
whatever kind alter and enhance our ways of conceiving and communicating
experience. They are not independent of the realm of everyday experience
since they inform, question, intensify and clarify our response to what occurs
in such experience. In this sense it is not possible to understand experience
without reference to the category of the aesthetic. Here is where analytic rationality falls short, or hits its own limit, at which point it can only see art as wayward, subjectivist or esoteric. Any theory of experience falls short if it casts this
category aside or gives it only minimal consideration as happens, for example,
when experience is treated solely in terms of cognition.
The aesthetic dimension of experience is neither something separate
from everyday life, nor some special, rarefied kind of experience. It is generally only tacit in ordinary experience, and one of the values we place on artistic and cultural products of all kinds is their capacity to help us make this
dimension more palpable. Although this capacity may be realised anywhere
across a broad range of specific forms, it means that creativity has achieved
some form of communicative value. Intensifying, clarifying and shifting perception is part of what goes into an experience in the creative realisation of
itself, regardless of the form in which it occurs. The action and its consequences must be joined in perception. This relationship is what gives meaning;
to grasp it is the objective of all intelligence (Dewey, 1980: 44). Perception in
this sense is at one with the way experience advances, connects, and realises
that aesthetic dimension which makes art continuous with everyday living,
rather than separate from it as a special and refined object.
Negus-02.qxd
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 45
EXPERIENCE
45
Negus-03.qxd
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 46
3
Industry
Notions of creativity pervade the day-to-day working lives of practitioners
involved in media and cultural production, from the talent scout watching a
band in a smoky club to the producer considering a screenplay and the senior
executive weighing up the acquisition of companies and new media investment
opportunities. The annual reports of media and entertainment corporations
frequently emphasise their abilities to provide a creative working environment,
to recruit creative people, and to employ people with the ability to manage
such personnel. Inevitably, these claims are disputed by those who complain
about the very inability of such corporate institutions to facilitate the creative
process, and who counter that the increasingly conglomerate corporate organisation of cultural production has very little to do with artistic creativity. It can
exploit it, package it, and even impede its development, but large corporate
institutions cant act as facilitators of the creative process. From such an angle,
the phrase the creative industries is an oxymoron.
As we have seen, such a position is informed by an argument which can
be followed back to the Romantic response to the rise of industrial capitalism.
It continues to endure in debates that cluster around the apparent dichotomy
of commerce versus creativity whereby cultural production is characterised in
terms of a conflict between the two: commerce (industry) is posed as perpetually in conflict with creativity (the artists, producers, directors, novelists). Here
it is claimed that commerce corrupts creativity and leads to compromise, fake
or fabricated cultural forms which adhere to the most vulgar of market-oriented
formats and formulae. The polarised opposition of commerce and creativity,
and the polemical claims which follow from it, are not just a theoretical preserve of sociologists and political economists. For example, a key figure in the
advertising industry regards creative people as insecure, egotistical, stubborn,
rebellious, poor timekeeping perfectionists who seek fame (Fletcher, 1990).
Implicit in such a clichd definition is that quite contrary attributes are manifest by the so-called suits of advertising, and by managers and executives in
the cultural industries more generally. On the other side of the equation, the
belief that acting creatively is at odds with being controlled industrially continues to inform the view that subcultures, fans and audiences more generally can
Negus-03.qxd
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 47
INDUSTRY
creatively appropriate, resist, re-claim and hence transform the products that
are disseminated by the commercial industry. This is a stark divide.
In contrast, commerce is sometimes viewed as the condition that
inspires creativity a view found amongst many writings on and from the
world of big business. The commercial reward and the financial imperative
inspires people to create great songs, films, books and art. From this perspective, the corporate routines, organisational habits and stylistic formulas are not
so much constraints as necessary frameworks which focus peoples thinking.
James Ettema and Charles Whitney, for example, argue that the demands of
television production routines and the necessary constraints in organisational
politics do not so much compromise as energise the producers creative activities (1982: 8). At times a further claim is made: the commercial imperative
means that things get done without the financial contract as an incentive, no
one would do anything. This is often linked to an assumption that creative
artists are rather lazy and wouldnt stir themselves without the pressure of
deadlines and contractual imperatives. Such a claim has been made of Mozart,
Bing Crosby, and any number of rock musicians.
A third position proposes that commerce and creativity have become so
mixed-up and inextricably bound together in the modern economy as to be
indistinguishable. It is misleading to attempt to separate them, as if they are
autonomous forces. Instead, contemporary cultural production entails fusions,
blurrings and genre crossings at the level of both texts and occupational
worlds. This effectively dissolves the distinctions between commerce and creativity or advertising and art. So, for example, a novelist or scriptwriter may
work as a copywriter in an advertising agency whilst attempting to get their
books or scripts recognised and taken up. Acclaimed film directors make
advertisements and pop videos, just as songwriters may have once written jingles or may now compose music for computer games. Salman Rushdie, Alan
Parker and David Bowie all began their media careers in advertising. Martin
Amis can now write disparagingly about the ad world as a sunset home for literary talent, so adopting a similar tone of opposition to that of early twentiethcentury novelists like Joseph Conrad, H.G. Wells, Sinclair Lewis and Christopher
Isherwood, but one of his first jobs was as a trainee copywriter in the advertising agency, J. Walter Thompson (Amis, 2000: 34). When Fay Weldons
novel The Bulgari Connection was commissioned and printed by the Italian
jewellery firm Bulgari, and featured the company prominently in the narrative,
this was reported to have broken down one of the last barriers between art
and commerce by introducing product placement into literature (Kennedy,
2001: 4).
The assumption that the boundaries of art and business are dissolving,
and the stark dichotomy of commerce vs. creativity is no longer relevant, can
be found in Simon Friths and Howard Hornes celebration of the vibrant
47
Negus-03.qxd
48
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 48
contribution of British art schools to popular music culture (Frith and Horne,
1987) and in Fredric Jamesons (1991) melancholic account of the capitalist
cultures of postmodernity. Whether we accept both or either of these arguments in their entirety, they provide enough evidence to suggest that we must
develop ways of understanding the unstable and changing interplay of what
constitutes commerce and creativity at any one time.
We want to think about the various tensions that are generated during
the juxtaposition and meeting of creativity and commerce by acknowledging
these complexities. In doing so, we wish to retain a sense of two distinct
dynamics that are nevertheless intertwined. Capitalist industry obviously has an
impact on creative work and, indeed, on the very significance of what we now
understand as creative. Creative practice can be subtly or overtly shaped by
commercial agendas, uncritically accepted occupational roles, production routines and marketing routes. The very specific organisation of small and large
companies can directly impact upon the creation of aesthetic beliefs and reputations as much as it can mould the production of specific artefacts and
forms.
At the same time, the process is still relatively indeterminate. The businesses involved in cultural production dont possess any single set of criteria or
uniform guidelines for harnessing creative practices to the requirements of
their owners and shareholders. As in many industries which are dependent
upon the production of new or novel items, formal managerial control is often
less emphatic if only for purely practical reasons during the development of
new television programmes or popular music recordings. Following from this,
we wish to think about a slightly more subtle and occasionally overlooked
process, whereby these very businesses and industries have themselves been
constituted from creative practices in the first place. If commercially driven
industries undoubtedly mould creativity, we also have to realise that creativity
has influenced, and continues to influence, industrial production. We might
even say that the industries have been created.
Our purpose in this chapter is to highlight how understandings of creativity are linked to, but not determined by (and, indeed, do not themselves determine) modern industry and commerce. We start by considering the use of the
creative or culture industries as a descriptive category, highlighting how this fails
to acknowledge a set of value judgements. The qualifying term creative operates as more than a descriptive category when applied to industries. The use of
the label creativity provides a means of according value, and establishing a cultural hierarchy. It provides a means of evaluation, a way of positioning people
against one another. To designate specific practices as creative, or isolate particular businesses as culture industries, inevitably entails making value judgements
which often go unexamined (some things are, by implication, not creative).
Such designation of either practices or businesses means that a very particular
Negus-03.qxd
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 49
INDUSTRY
Abandoning Adorno
The very notion of a culture industry was introduced in the work of Theodor
Adorno and Max Horkheimer. They wrote at a time when ideas about collective democracy had moved from being associated with emancipatory political
movements and had become incorporated into the vocabularies used to comprehend the new electronic media of communication and aesthetic reproduction.
They coined the term culture industry to distance themselves from the idea
that mass culture could be equated with peoples culture as something like a
culture that arises spontaneously from the masses themselves (Adorno, 1991:
85). This was a time when new cultural forms such as radio, television and
cinema were being viewed as potentially liberating, and often seen as both of
the people and for the people, encouraging democracy and continuing a
process of greater public enlightenment, a possibility implied in some of Walter
Benjamins writings. Adorno and Horkheimer were suspicious of such apparently democratic possibilities of communicating to numerous people and vehemently critical of the impact of commerce on independent individual creative
work. Their point was that this was deceptive. The rhetoric of public democracy was being used commercially to generate profits for private corporations, and also politically for the purposes of propaganda. Adorno and
Horkheimer sought to challenge those who were celebrating the possibilities
provided by these new media and cultural technologies.
Adorno and Horkheimer wrote their famous culture industry essay in a
deliberately polemical and provocative manner. It is misleading to assume that
their references to the assembly line should be taken literally as if it was
intended as a description of an entity that was out there, something to be
empirically described or statistically verified. Despite his continual emphasis on
rational standardisation, Adorno also noted that producing hit songs still
remains at the handicraft stage (1990: 306). In making this and other observations he suggested that the standardisation which occurs in cultural production is not simply the same as the standardisation of motor car and breakfast
cereals (1990: 306). The song composer, novelist or filmmaker was not physically located on a rationally organised factory assembly line. Instead, the pressure to adhere to formulas was induced by the need to compete for attention
in a commercial market where standard patterns were more easily distributed,
promoted and recognised. Adorno and Horkheimer were seeking to highlight
49
Negus-03.qxd
50
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 50
Negus-03.qxd
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 51
INDUSTRY
51
Negus-03.qxd
52
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 52
and other industries are not creative and somehow less concerned with
circulating meanings and influencing cultural practices.
Negus-03.qxd
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 53
INDUSTRY
as for instance when people are praised for being industrious. This distinction
is useful in reminding us that many cultural forms and artefacts are moving
across the world due to human cultural industry (hard work) and not as a result
of any corporate institution. This may be construed as a pedantic point but we
think it crucial, for it is usually neglected by those writers who present overtly
mechanistic or deterministic models of industries and who forget that human
industry is part of corporate industry.
Whilst many artists, novelists, musicians and actors might be internationally successful because of the investment, resources and promotional techniques utilised by the major entertainment corporations, there are many others
who are internationally successful despite them. A simple and basic contrast
might be between the well-organised and in many respects imperialist strategies and struggles through which the sounds, words and images of a major
superstar are distributed, and the more ad hoc and chaotic matrices of transnational cultural flow (Hannerz, 1996) through which a blues singer, a poet, a
DJ, a painter or an alternative film maker may connect with diverse listeners,
viewers and readers across the world. These movements are facilitated by the
activity of a plethora of enthusiasts whose actions contribute to the formation
of creative networks which may facilitate small-scale business practices and
forms of promotion and publicity, but whose cultural industry is far from institutionalised in the manner of the major corporations.
If we focus in a little more detail on these practices and institutional
interactions we can find a continual series of tensions about access and availability. This is inevitable when a finite number of books, films and recordings
are released every year, a relatively small number of new art works are displayed, new plays staged and television programmes commissioned. Despite
their restriction of access and participation, the media and cultural industries
have been characterised as new types of industry, populated by progressive
thinking, cultural intermediary occupations where jobs and careers have not
yet acquired the rigidity of the older bureaucratic professions (Bourdieu,
1986: 151). Gaining access to work is assumed to be less dependent upon a
meritocracy or assessment and recruitment according to formal qualifications.
Justin OConnor has written of how workers within the culture and media
industries become ever more significant in contributing to social change in
what he calls an a era of post-scarcity when the cultural hierarchies are
much more fragmented and plural (1999: 7).
To what extent are these industries of art, culture, media and entertainment any more or less open than other types of profession? The critical questions here are about who is admitted or excluded, how this occurs, how access
may vary across different arts and media industries. Anecdotally, there is much
evidence (in biographies and trade magazines) to suggest that the film industry, for example, is dominated by very strong family connections. Not only are
53
Negus-03.qxd
54
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 54
actors and actresses often drawn from very well-established family dynasties,
so too are producers and directors. In a newspaper profile of the actress
Sigourney Weaver, to cite one case, it becomes clear that the recognition of
her talent and her subsequent success have been facilitated by the environment, economic support and cultural capital provided by a family background
of entertainment aristocracy (Mackenzie, 2000: 11).
Researching in the late 1980s and into the 1990s, one of us has found
that most of the key decision makers within the British music industry shared
many features in common, and constitute a coherent class grouping (Negus,
1992; 1999). Those executives who had been in the business for 25 to
30 years and who were in senior management had been drawn from a very
particular class background or habitus. Recruited into the music industry
during the late 1960s and early 1970s, most senior executives were middleclass white males who had received a privately funded education at public
schools, or attended state grammar schools, and completed studies at university. Their formative experience had been shaped during the period when rock
was gaining cultural value, becoming self-consciously intellectual and
respectable; a period when various elements of rhythm and blues and rocknroll were appropriated and rechristened rock or progressive music by its
recently enfranchised grammar school, student and hip middle class audience
(Chambers, 1985: 84). A simultaneous expansion of the universities and institutions of cultural production provided an impetus which facilitated the recruitment into the music business of a group of mildly bohemian young people
associated with the counter-culture. Many of these young executives had
initially been involved in booking bands, often as university entertainment
officers, and a considerable number had played in rock bands. This context
provided a particular series of orientations, assumptions, dispositions and values
which were carried into the organisations of music production and came to
dominate agendas within the expanding recording industry. Despite being
presented as a fairly liberal business, populated by personnel who are in touch
with the street, these agendas were not a reflection of the diversity of music
being played and listened to in Britain. Instead they represented, in condensed
form, the preferences and judgements of a small, relatively elite educated,
middle class, white male faction.
The aesthetic and social consequences of this have been profound. At
a decisive phase in its expansion and growth, the British music industry was
re-organised around a series of dichotomies in which rock artists were
favoured over pop or soul performers; albums were favoured over singles; and
self-contained bands or solo artists who were judged, from a position derived
from Romanticism, to express themselves through writing their own songs,
were favoured over the more collaborative ways in which singers or groups of
performers have, for many years, worked with arrangers, session musicians
Negus-03.qxd
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 55
INDUSTRY
55
Negus-03.qxd
56
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 56
and returning art to time (Benjamin, 1970: 2245, 234; 1977: 98). Whatever
the opportunities provided, and however they are assessed, the interlocking
organisations and techniques of modern cultural production entail a necessary
reliance on the institutional networks already set in place by an industry. An
individual can no more realise the creation and exhibition of a movie than be
able to manufacture and make function (with water and electricity) a washing
machine. Hence, all judgements about the value and possibilities of creativity
inevitably involve consideration of the human relationships and social
processes through which an individual or group of people may have come to
realise a particular creation.
This is particularly so with regard to cinema. Film has been viewed as a
cultural form that has facilitated inherently collective or collaborative processes
of creation. Its because of this that contemporary studios whether
Dreamworks, Disney or Universal promote themselves as providing a creative
environment when seeking to attract directors, actors and investors. The claim
that film production ushered in a new type of collective creativity has been challenged by those who view the work of making films as a struggle of lone directing auteurs against the collective inertia of the studio and distribution system.
Obviously enough, directors do not operate alone; film production depends
upon the high degree of division of labour in the industry. As Ian Jarvie has
observed: Films can be made or marred in such a large number of ways, and
decisions made at such a number of levels in the organisation, that there is a
genuine question as to whether there is sufficient centralisation of decisionmaking to attribute the finished product to any one individual (1970: 267).
Film might be assessed as a result of its social production and the degree
of collective synthesis emerging from its production, yet throughout the first
century of cinema history, the predominant tendency has been to assess it as
a result of individual creativity. The social production, with its complex division
of labour, may at least be acknowledged, as for instance in the different categories assigned to the Academy Awards, but the habit persists of thinking that
what truly makes or mars a film is the individual stamp of directorial identity.
This has been articulated, at one extreme, in auteurisms cult of the personality and Romantic notions of autonomous creativity, but speaking of a Spielberg
movie or an Alan Parker film is a feature of everyday evaluative discourse. As
Robert Lapsley and Michael Westlake put it: despite the sustained and theoretically decisive critique of auteurism, mainstream discussion of cinema is still
dominated by the quest for the author, its main critical concerns being to distinguish authors from the anonymous mass of directors, to establish their identity by reference to their most characteristic work and distinguishing style or
thematic focus, and to pass judgement as to their respective merits (1991: 127).
The canonical status of someone like Hitchcock is to some extent the result
of distinctive marks of an authorial, indeed a self-referential presence
Negus-03.qxd
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 57
INDUSTRY
(Maltby, 1996: 437), but the conferral of status in this sense usually obscures
the commercial marketing of auteurism (Karpis, 1992) and the institutional
complexities of contribution and influence in a films overall planning, production and marketing. Even relatively distinctive film directors are not immune to
unwelcome interference, which can occur at any stage of the production
process. The films of Orson Welles, for instance, were often carved up and
rendered incoherent by the meddlers who influenced the editing process at various Hollywood studios, most notoriously during the confused editing, reshooting and rescoring that was inflicted upon The Magnificent Ambersons.
Far from being inimical to a films success, either at the box office or
in the critical reviews, the complex organisation of its production, as in the
Hollywood studio system for instance, may be said to make possible the
attainment of high professional standards in cinematic entertainment. We
note here again that the self of self-expression in cultural creativity is a legacy
of Romantic aesthetics that, so far as the entertainment industries are concerned, mistakes idealised instances of production or performance for the
essence of a cultural artefact and is responsible for nave juxtapositions of art
and commerce (Jarvie, 1970: 27). This attitude frequently sets up the key
issue in terms of a dualistic opposition between constraint and creativity.
Cultural work of any significant kind in media organisations, such as those of
music manufacture and distribution, book publishing, television production,
journalism, and film production and marketing, is commonly conceived as
having been achieved against the commercial constraints imposed by these
organisations. For example, Duncan Petrie argues that filmic creativity is
essentially an artistic/cultural process which is structured by material constraints
(1991: 1) with subjective intentionality and objective structuring, lying at the
heart of the creative process (ibid.: 12).
Creative freedom or professional autonomy are not pre-given entities of
absolute value rigidly set against media organisations, operational routines,
state censorship or market criteria. What is commercial is also frequently only
realised in retrospect. For example, a spokesperson for Decca Records is said
to have rejected The Beatles because groups of guitars are on their way out,
while a concert manager advised Elvis Presley, in 1954, to go back to driving
a truck. In 1927, the Warner Brothers president, Harry Warner, peremptorily
dismissed the talkies who the hell wants to hear actors talk? while a manager
at MGM, after an initial screening of The Wizard of Oz to company executives, is said to have barked at its director: That rainbow songs no good take
it out! As these unfortunate judgements show, it is perhaps more useful to
view the commercial as a dynamic which people work towards and seek to
make happen. Songs, movies and novels do not, in general, appear carrying
definitive commercial qualities or characteristics. A process occurs whereby
they are made commercial and this is why modern economies employ so
57
Negus-03.qxd
58
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 58
many people in marketing, publicity and public relations. Their aim is to connect
the work of cultural producer with the lives of consumers.
Residues of Romanticism can inform a sense of creativity operating
ideally as a free play of productive forces. When this is portrayed as constantly
in danger of being shackled by institutional, bureaucratic and economic monoliths, the resulting picture is crude and simplistic. It obscures the actual asymmetries of power and resources that distinguish those involved in various
sectors and spheres of cultural production around the world. In addition, such
a model, implying the need for (an ill-defined) freedom, would seem of little
value in trying to account for creative work that has emerged from conditions
of outright oppression or social exclusion.
In thinking about questions of intervention, autonomy, manipulation
and artistic freedom we need a more nuanced view of the differential position
of the creative artist, one which acknowledges the benefits acquired through
commercial success and stardom. Not that all creative artists who sign to film
agents, record companies, book publishers, or literary agents will become
stars, but the imperative of stardom drives the industry due to the rewards that
it offers.
When artists are struggling for recognition theyre often labouring long
hours, subject to all sorts of pressures and contract constraints. Whether a
musician, novelist, painter or actress, they are in a weak bargaining position.
They might be recording songs they dont like, wearing clothes they hate, writing copy in an advertising agency, acting in roles they detest, whilst working
part time as waitresses, models, warehouse operatives or office clerks. At a
certain point this changes. The labour of the artist and all those other industry
personnel who contribute to the creation of the artists persona, transform
that person into a commodity which accumulates ever more capital value. The
film star, rock star or star author becomes a commodity amongst commodities... the cybernetic monitor which returns all efforts to the same apparent
core of meaning (King, 1987: 149). The success of films, books, recordings,
and a whole range of associated products, merchandise and events, have
become ever more dependent upon the star image. The success of these
chains of commodities increases or decreases the bargaining position of the
star. Stars become a capital investment, worth so many millions of dollars to
the budget of, say, a film or Broadway musical. They act as a guarantee a
guarantee of further investment from financial backers: that theatres will show
the film; that shops will stock the book; that television and radio will showcase
the band.
This leads to a degree of power and influence, unimaginable at the
moment of acquisition, as the industries become organised around the stars.
Not only do stars exert influence by establishing production companies, record
labels, merchandising chains, restaurants, clubs, or purchasing jet aircraft,
Negus-03.qxd
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 59
INDUSTRY
59
Negus-03.qxd
60
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 60
Negus-03.qxd
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 61
INDUSTRY
and to ensure that the results of human creativity were made available to the
public. The logic went (and still goes) something like this: to invent something,
to come up with a new idea, can take considerable effort, financial expense
and time. Yet, as soon as something is made available to the public, it can very
quickly be copied. It can be imitated and reproduced by someone else who has
not spent all that time and effort in creating it in the first place. In short, it can
be appropriated.
Copyright was introduced to solve the problem of appropriation and the
assumption that the existence of copying would act as an impediment, inhibiting people from coming up with new ideas. Why spend all that effort if someone else can instantly copy your creation and benefit from it? During the early
days of capitalism, in the Venetian city state, this represented an attempt to
regulate the so-called free, competitive, market. The laws passed in Venice in
1474 formed the foundation of the ideas about copyright which exist today. It
was stipulated that any person who produced an ingenious device should
make it known to the authorities, so that it could be used. It was then forbidden for any other person to make and use an identical device, without the consent and license of the author, for a period of 10 years. If anyone chose to do
so, then the Venetian city authorities had the right to fine the infringer and
destroy their device (cited in Merges, 1995: 105).
Although this has obviously gone through numerous modifications since,
having been adapted to specific circumstances, whether in Britain, France,
Japan, the United States or elsewhere, this is the basis of patent law, copyright
and intellectual property legislation. The principle it enshrines can be observed
operating now in the music industry, the film industry and the business of book
publishing. The originators are granted a limited time of exclusivity, during
which the item cannot be reproduced or used without permissions being
granted and payments being made to the rights holders. The idea is that this
encourages creativity amongst individuals and benefits them collectively; it is for
the public good, encouraging a thriving, creative, human society. Copyright
arises out of the potential tension between individual and collective and
attempts to balance the desire to spread culture and the need to reward authors.
If we think about this principle in terms of the institutions of contemporary media and cultural production, a key question arises: does copyright
law still benefit the individual and the collective and, if so, which individuals and
which collectives? For a number of writers, the answer to this question is obvious. Copyright law has been established to protect the creative efforts of
authors, composers and artistic originators. This notion is central to the practices of those organisations which act on behalf of authors and composers and
can usually be found in their mission statements and annual reports.
From research on copyright in the music business, Dave Laing (1993,
2003) has suggested that there can be a degree of truth in this claim, but it is
61
Negus-03.qxd
62
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 62
only part of the story and has changed historically. Laing argues that between
the 1880s and the 1930s, the process of copyright reform and changing
copyright law did represent the predominant interests of composers, songwriters, and literary and dramatic writers. It benefited those authors who were
able to influence copyright law through the various collective organisations that
they formed. However, from the 1920s, with the growth of the mechanical
and electronic media, a series of other parties began to have a vested interest
in the way copyright was instituted. These included singers, performers (who
made use of copyrighted work) and recording companies, film studios, and radio
and television broadcasters. Subsequently, governments have recognised the
importance of copyright to their economies and copyright has been drawn into
attempts to regulate international trade.
Laings argument implies that copyright intersects with a series of
broader power struggles. How different writers conceive of such struggles will
inevitably influence their judgements about the consequences of copyright law.
For some writers such tensions are resolved in the interests of all, whether this
entails a rather benign harmonious alliance (Ehrlich, 1988) or a more fraught
process of knowledge diplomacy (Ryan, 1998), entailing negotiation and a
plurality of interests finding common ground through diplomatic means. This
process may implicate governments, lawyers, various professional groups (scientists, composers, biotechnologists), corporations (entertainment, pharmaceuticals), non-governmental organisations, universities, various manufacturers
and users of technology.
In contrast, Ronald Bettig (1996) views copyright law and intellectual
property legislation as tools actively used by capitalist corporations to further
their interests, facilitating ever greater patterns of ownership and cultural
commodification. For Bettig, relevant law enables the increasing commodification of social life as intangible ideas (sounds, words, images) are transformed into a property that can be owned. Bettig argues that the major
corporations are able to control and benefit from the circulation of knowledge
and ideas due to the way that, under pressure, originators must enter
into deals with corporations to have their creations made and distributed
(whether song publishers, game manufacturers or medicine manufacturers).
Corporations also finance creations that require considerable investment, as
in the production of films, the development of new or existing technologies,
or the invention of new drugs. Consequently, many originators are forced to
assign their rights to commercial corporations. As such corporations ultimately own the rights to so many products and inventions, it is argued that
copyright has become a further means of controlling and profiting from
human creative labour, not to mention the creative labour whose results have
accumulated as collective knowledge in the long-established traditions of
indigenous peoples. Rather than benefiting the creators and society as a
Negus-03.qxd
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 63
INDUSTRY
63
Negus-03.qxd
64
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 64
We cannot ignore how many creative producers are acutely aware of such circumstances, actively commodifying their body and art in this way, whilst also seeking recognition and reward for their creations or requesting recompense if their
work is appropriated. It is surely a nave postmodern conceit to assert that creativity simply involves processes of theft from previous forms, and that these are
an essential part of any culture (Ltticken, 2002). As we have argued so far in
this book, there is a lot more to creativity than re-combining existing elements of
culture. Equally, it is simplistic to assume that copyright can be reduced or collapsed into commodification and economic transactions. Copyright is a clue to the
way people seek recognition and the will to communicate and reciprocate, no
matter how this may have been incorporated into various systems of capitalism.
This is a theme we draw from the work of Jane Gaines who suggests
that a focus on copyright provides an insight into the contested character of
cultural production, reproduction and consumption. Gaines stresses the contradictory character of the dynamics involved, arguing that it is not enough to
claim that consumer culture has become commodified or that cultural forms
have become reified:
Certainly there are ways in which copyright protection and its accompanying
property rights do commodify, solidify, and tie up elements of culture. But there
are also ways in which legal protection facilitates cultural circulation. Copyrights
monopoly grant, whether we like it or not, does work as an incentive to publish
and consequently to disseminate. Copyright protection is always and at the same
time circulation and restriction. (Gaines, 1991: 122)
Gaines offers a detailed analysis of images, voices and identities, and stresses
this dynamic of circulation and restriction, arguing that copyright makes
available aspects of a common culture at the same time that it restricts the way
it can be used.
Negus-03.qxd
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 65
INDUSTRY
65
Negus-03.qxd
66
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 66
the sign? Who allows the image to be circulated? Who allows it to appear in
another context? How do signs appear in an advert, a movie, or come to be
reproduced in a textbook? Who controls their use, and what is their market
value? How is this value acquired?
Gainess work enables us to think about the links between how creative
artefacts and images are produced; the social use of artefacts and images; their
circulation as commodities; and their appearance in specific representations.
Threading throughout, and linking these elements together, is the dynamic of
commodification. This can involve the increasing colonisation of and corporate intervention into public and private life, but commodification also means
making cultural forms available. It involves circulation to a wider public. In this,
process, the public use of such commodities can pose a problem for ownership and control in a way that conventional political economy seems to have
problems recognising. Things and objects have a social life (Appadurai, 1986)
and accumulate all manner of values and sentimental attachments way beyond
their appearance in the market as a commodity. This is clearly relevant to the
multifaceted approach to the value of creativity which we are developing in
this book.
There is a further issue lurking within Gainess general argument. It
entails a question which might appear simple, yet is central to much of the discussion in this book: What is a copy? Its a question at the heart of copyright
law. Its an issue implied in Adornos notion of standardisation and pseudoindividuality, and in Benjamins comments on culture in the age of mechanical
reproduction, along with all the subsequent attempts to grapple with debates
about mass culture and the meeting of culture and industry.
As Gaines points out when thinking about this issue: the law cannot
question its own categories such as authorship, private property, and right.
All it can do is maintain them in a circular manner: The law asks what is an
author? and replies An author is an originator. So, we ask: What is an
originator? and the law responds An originator is an author (1991: 15).
Copyright law is used to resolve competing claims to ownership of a work. It
is used to solve the riddle of originality. But it is clearly fraught with ambiguities. Gaines refers to legal sources which suggest that originality does not
imply novelty; it only implies that the copyright claimant did not copy from
someone else (ibid.: 58), and argues that a tautology operates at the heart of
intellectual property law:
All works of authorship are original. Why? Because they originate with
authorsevery work is an original work, regardless of whether it is aesthetically
unoriginal, banal, or, in some cases, imitative. Every individual person is also a
potential author whose writings will be as original as those of a renowned or
acclaimed literary figureCopyrights minimal point of origin requirement, which
considers light fixtures and belt buckles as works of authorship, performs a
Negus-03.qxd
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 67
INDUSTRY
67
Negus-04.qxd
3/27/04 12:28 PM
Page 68
4
Convention
Creativity carries with it associations of freedom, agency and the unshackling
of constraints. This is a beguiling but misleading view because creativity does
not operate, unbounded, in an autonomous fashion. It is usually shaped by
convention. It is about giving form to the material we draw on and transform,
and this cannot be done without reference to existing rules, devices, codes and
procedures.
Conventions enable cultural forms and practices to be recognised and
differentiated from each other. Conventions allow for agreements (and disputes) about these forms and practices and what is characteristic of them.
They can be explicitly formulated and followed, as for instance in the rules of
grammar, or the rules of a game. These rules are conventional to the way writing is constructed and read, or a game played and watched. More generally,
conventions are tacitly acknowledged as taken-for-granted ways of engaging
in, seeing, or listening to the varieties of human communication. So, for example, at the simplest level, we can easily distinguish between a friendly and a
rude gesture when we are driving a car in heavy traffic.
Conventions enable communication to occur and to be understood.
In regulating behaviour, they allow human interaction to occur without coordination problems (Lewis, 1969). This is as applicable to ballroom dancers,
marching bands in parades, or lovers on a date, as it is to members of
government committees, or cyclists negotiating a roundabout. Such conventions may be perceived as artificial constructs, historically contingent in their
acceptance, application and use. But recognition of their artificiality should not
be taken as synonymous with falseness, contrivance, or outdated barriers that
stand only to be broken. These unfavourable senses developed from the late
eighteenth century, and in themselves became conventional antitheses to the
Romantic premium on spontaneity and innovation.
It is common to see convention only in negative terms. But conventions
are enabling, for within them are inscribed the cultural arrangements that
enable communication, co-existence, and self-awareness within particular
contexts and particular periods (McClary, 2000: 6). Conventions allow
communication interpersonal, artistic and human dialogue to occur in all
Negus-04.qxd
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 69
CON VENTION
69
Negus-04.qxd
70
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 70
Negus-04.qxd
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 71
CON VENTION
71
Negus-04.qxd
72
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 72
Fabbri also highlights how genre rules inform the postures and movements
of singers and instrumentalists, the spacing of participants at a musical event
and the use of the body to signify so that, for example, punk bass players
must communicate their punk-ness through their physical movements and posture. These are not strict requirements of the music they play but are conventions of effort. At the same time, genres imply certain rules of dress. We often
see a poster on a wall or a photograph in a magazine and know the type of
music involved without having heard the artists. We judge the clothes, the posture, the hairstyle and, sometimes crucially, the names. The first sign of a new
recording artist is often the name. This signals the genre to which an artist
belongs. So, for example, punk culture is associated with its rebellion against
various forms of social convention, but it has social conventions of its own.
Thats why the names Rat Scabies, Sid Vicious and Johnny Rotten seemed
appropriate stage names they would hardly have been suitable for a jazz or
country musician or a member of a boy band.
These visual and nominative aspects are directly related to the ideological beliefs that go with genres. These are often articulated in assumptions
about collectivity or community and authenticity, as for example with notions
of a rock community that were prevalent in the 1960s and 1970s, or the idea
of being real in hip hop during the 1990s. Such beliefs imply some sense of
belonging or shared belief system which link artist to audience and are central
to attempts to imagine themselves part of a broader community or group.
Historically, many of the ideological rules of genres have depended
upon exclusionary and essentialist beliefs. In many biographies of jazz and rock
musicians you will frequently find quite clear views expressed about the place
of women. While women have played a significant role in jazz from its earliest
days, the popular stereotype unfairly restricts the female contribution primarily to vocal music: the classic blues singers, the girl vocalists of the swing and
bebop eras, and an occasional pianist (Tirro, 1993: 189). During the early
1970s, rock developed quite clear ideological rules about the place of women.
They belonged neither in bands nor in the studio, but were conceded a particular role on a tour, such as caterer, make-up specialist or groupie.
In addition, there are various essentialist ideological beliefs about who
can authentically play certain types of music who is authentic, who is real?
and, of course, the issue of race and ethnicity permeates these type of
debates. Early in the twentieth century, much of the debate about whether
white performers could sing the blues foreshadowed later debates about
authenticity in hip hop. These ideological standards and conventions also concern the use of instruments. When Bob Dylan went electric, swapping his
acoustic guitar for an electric guitar in 1965 and 1966, this was seen as a
betrayal by many folk fans, who saw him as having sold out to mass culture.
Some even considered it comparable to an act of profane transgression, as
Negus-04.qxd
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 73
CON VENTION
one commentator put it: It was as if all of a sudden you saw Martin Luther
King doing a cigarette ad (Filene, 2000: 184). In the second English folk
music revival, sterile prohibitions outlawed the piano as a bourgeois imposition, despite its prominence in working-class culture as a staple of informal
singing and dancing sessions. Some people even argued that authentic English
folk songs should not be accompanied by alien guitars or banjos (Pickering and
Green, 1987: 33). Similar prejudices go with the territory of many genres.
We adduce these various examples in order to make the point that
different genres can imply distinct beliefs, values and ideological positions.
Aesthetic identities and creative practices can form part of broader sets of
social relationships and cultural practices, and through these the creative
actions of production can be co-ordinated through a shared set of beliefs, values and knowledge. For example, those involved in the production of country
music in Nashville have, for some years, spoken of themselves as a music
community (Negus, 1999). Such a music community is lived and experienced
in two identifiable ways. First, it involves a geographical sense of community
created as a result of living and working in one specific physical place. Hence,
those working with country musicians in Nashville have enjoyed a sense of
camaraderie through numerous lunchtime meetings, evening gigs, golf days
and fan events, along with the socialising which occurs between peers who are
employed in the same profession and share working spaces, residential neighbourhoods and leisure pursuits. In this sense, those making music in Nashville
often liken themselves to a family which has been created over time as a
similar group of people have gradually become closer through playing in
bands, producing, collaborating and competing with one another. This has led
to the formation of enduring friendships and close personal ties and these have
come to shape the working world of country music production in Nashville. At
the same time, those involved in country music might be thought of as constituting a broader community which is not necessarily confined to the geographic borders of a specific place. Although never meeting all other
members, the sense of community is lived as a known entity that is bigger,
beyond and of greater significance than the commercial country category and
the organisational department or record label. This broader community would
take in songwriters, musicians and producers physically located in New York
State, Texas, California, Canada and elsewhere.
A slightly similar notion of genre community has been used to identify
affiliative ties amongst consumers. In his study of film, Rick Altman suggests
that genre communities emerge due to the way that genre buffs more commonly imagine themselves communing with absent like-minded fans (1999:
160). He argues that the farther we range from live entertainment (that is, the
more we deal with separate audiences, absent to each other, yet sharing the
same experience), the more powerful are appeals to an absent and yet
73
Negus-04.qxd
74
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 74
Negus-04.qxd
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 75
CON VENTION
75
Negus-04.qxd
76
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 76
Negus-04.qxd
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 77
CON VENTION
studying youth subcultures researchers have stressed the link between musical
taste and social type, with musical taste actively used to signify a sense of belonging and difference. Such examples cannot be taken paradigmatically, for they
may be exceptional in their intermapping of social identity and music preference.
Its not only a question of individual tastes changing and developing, but also of
diversifying and being enriched by promiscuous movements between genres,
against the grain of marketing expertise or peer group disapproval, and their
emphasis on established cool rules and commercial rituals.
It is at this point that we begin to see not only the limitations of notions
of genre community, but some of the more general limitations of the notion of
genre. As Steve Neale has observed: There is an assumption built into nearly
all genre theory that audiences and readers not only consume some or all of
the genres on offer in exactly the same way, but also that they consume nothing else (2000: 226). Genre communities are not a universal characteristic of
cultural affiliation, and so shouldnt be seen as the only or even as a major
communal sense of bond in peoples lives. Notions of genre communities can
easily imply a simple, one-track relationship between cultural producers and
their public or audience, but not all cultural producers and not all audiences
exist within or share one genre world or culture. There is a spurious link
between the genre associated with a band, a novelist or an actor and the cultural preferences, aesthetic inclinations, and reading, viewing and listening
habits of individuals. Preferences are often eclectic, and defy any simple
assumptions about a direct connection between taste (or niche market), subcultural grouping, occupational genre practice and social identities. Many rock
groups, for example, are a tense collusion and collision of factions, cliques and
alliances, and the units style is often the result of a degree of antagonism, compromise and occasional synthesis.
The act of belonging to a genre community may be a strategic choice,
and entail no clear link between public and private cultural preference. Or it
may be a particularly temporal and temporary phenomena. Following the
example we cited above, we should note that not all people who produce
country music, let alone who listen to it, may maintain collective feelings of
attachment (whether in their neighbourhood or across expansive space). Many
people who enjoy country music singers and songs may feel a sense of
extreme ambivalence to any such notion of ties of a country community.
Against this it could also be argued that country music is a very particular
example, and that perhaps music in general is more associated with distinct
patterns of genre affiliation. But even here, the relationship between musical
engagement and a sense of identity may entail a sense of ambivalence or outright feeling of detachment (Negus and Romn-Velzquez, 2002). So, to what
extent can we claim that the public join or imagine themselves as part of a
community by attending a concert, play or film, buying a book or watching a
77
Negus-04.qxd
78
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 78
Negus-04.qxd
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 79
CON VENTION
79
Negus-04.qxd
80
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 80
Negus-04.qxd
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 81
CON VENTION
81
Negus-04.qxd
82
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 82
much about why their art took the form it did and why they adopted their
specific aesthetic strategies. If not as its saviour, the avant-garde artist certainly
became the symbol of heroic resistance to all that is oppressive and corrupt
in bourgeois civilisation. This was an artist as an individualist and risk taker in
a sheepish societyaffording new insight as well as sight, a new vision of what
art as life can be a comprehensive new enlightenment (Kuspit, 1993: 1).
The Romantic overtones here are unmistakable, and extend into the figure of
the bohemian whose artistic experimentation and unconventional lifestyle
were designed to challenge utilitarian values and bourgeois philistinism.
Largely deriving from the affluent middle class, bohemians delivered not so
much a radical alternative as a radical inversion of the bourgeois self-image.
The bohemian ideal sought for an amalgamation of the spiritual life represented in art with the carnal life associated with the carnivalesque body, but in
the main the bohemian art world because of, rather than despite its eccentricities, excesses and extremities merely offered a mirror image of the bourgeois commercial world. If the bourgeoisie represented ambition without
passion, possessiveness without depth of desire, power without grandeur,
everything that was spiritually paltry and anti-vital, everything that was inadequate and pettily self-protective, bohemians turned this imbalance the opposite way in a stereotypically Romantic manner (Grana, 1964: 69; see also
Campbell, 1987: 195201; Wilson, 2000). The paradox of the bohemian lay
in embodying dissidence, opposition and resistance while at the same time
performing a drama in compulsive counterpoint to middle-class respectability
and sanctimony. Bohemian stories of genius, glamour, outlawry and doom
have always been good copy, avidly consumed at the bourgeois hearth
(Wilson, 2000: 3). Similarly, a category of outsider art a label applied to the
creations of those marginalised through institutionalisation in mental hospitals,
old peoples homes, prisons, homelessness has been actively appropriated,
used as a source of inspiration and brought inside the aesthetic canon. This
has been in large part due to the way that it appealed to art world
cognoscenti, not only visually, but because of its congruence with Romantic
notions of the authentic, misunderstood, creative geniusas outsider art
became fashionable, outsiders became insiders (Zolberg and Cherbo, 1997:
2). Outsider art partly represents a challenge to the art world from without, yet
its disruptive possibilities are selectively incorporated to maintain the conventions of the art world.
A consideration of how the conventions of art worlds have been challenged highlights how fragile the artistic consensus can be. It also begins to
reveal some of the limitations of Beckers approach. This presupposes a sense
of belonging, of affiliation to the art world and a willingness to cooperate in its
conventions even as some of these are broken. Despite his attempt to ground
conventions in the tangible interactions amongst art world participants, the
Negus-04.qxd
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 83
CON VENTION
conventions themselves can become reified as the bonds that link people.
The assumption that the art world is bounded and maintained according to cooperation and agreement faces criticism similar to that raised by the idea of
genre communities. In our daily lives we live with the known and the unknown.
In various creative activities, the familiar and the unexpected do not exist in
separate worlds, or run along parallel tracks that never meet. They continually
jostle and collide with each other. Beckers art worlds collude with the tendency
of genre theory towards the abstraction of certain characteristic features
detached from their living, changing context and a process of theoretical
reification whereby the bounded genre (or art world) seems to hover threateningly over and around the creative practices which are being studied.
The limitations of Beckers emphasis on collaboration and co-operation,
and his undeveloped analysis of the motives and the consequences of mavericks, can be supplemented by turning to Bourdieu who provides an immediate
contrast by emphasising the competitive arena within which struggles take
place over resources and access to them. If Becker tends to do little more than
relativize artistic conventions, Bourdieu relates them to how individuals and
groups are positioned in relation to one another. He focuses on the power
struggles that occur between individuals and groups as they compete within the
space of position takings which constitutes the field of cultural production.
Like Becker, he conceives of creative practices as occurring within certain
types of networks but these are characterised by antagonism rather than
co-operation.
Along with many other sociologists of culture, Bourdieus analysis of the
cultural field is posed against those who place an emphasis on the unique talent
and peculiar life experiences of great individuals. Bourdieus field is made up of
a series of positions that are occupied by artists, whether they be poets, novelists, painters or musicians. These are positions adopted by individuals, but this
approach emphasises the positions taken by particular genres, or sub-categories
of art and literature. Bourdieu observes that different genres of writing, of
music are not simply defined according to their own internal conventions,
codes and practices, but through their relationship to other categories.
Take, for example, the field of literature. The critical and commercial
status of different types of literature is visibly articulated in book shops, publishers catalogues, the teaching programmes in universities and schools, or the
organisation of literature suggested in the arts sections of newspapers and
magazines. How much space is devoted to a new novel by Ian McEwan or
Julian Barnes compared to a new crime novel? All this will give a tangible
sense of how specific genres and writers are positioned in relation to one
another.
So, the crime writer or writer of spy stories occupies a particular location within the field of literary production, positioned in relation to genres such
83
Negus-04.qxd
84
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 84
as romance, science fiction, and also in relation to modern novels and the
selection of texts categorised as classics. When John Le Carrs A Perfect Spy
was first published in 1986, Philip Roth reviewed it in The Observer and
declared it to be the best English novel since the war. There then followed a
debate amongst various writers and critics within the literary field as to whether
this was a novel or merely a piece of genre fiction. Was Le Carr now a
modern novelist or still a writer of genre fiction (spy novels)? For some, Le
Carr was using the spy form but with pretensionstowards writing literature
and adopting highly stylised techniques, particularly in his opening chapters
(Bradbury, 1990: 1306). Yet Le Carrs work has continually communicated
beyond the spy genre, using the form critically as he reacts against the constraints imposed by playing with, even mocking, their conventions (Hayes,
1990: 119). Here we may be referring to debates about style, but their consequences for reputations and careers can be profound. Whilst the novelist will
still make money, there is far greater prestige to be gained from assuming the
position of modern novelist than that of genre fiction writer, not to mention
different types of recognition, reputation and reward.
Bourdieus point here is that the meaning of an artistic work, and the
conditions of its production, can only be understood in these relational contexts. To view genres and art forms relationally is not a particularly new observation, but Bourdieus insight is to stress the sociological struggles over
position, power and prestige which underpin the production of textual forms
and artistic reputations, and how the specific networks of power relations
orient the strategies of artists. If you want to publish a novel, or get a record
contract, or act in a movie, or display your sculpture, your chances may well
be shaped by a certain talent and acquired repertoire of skills. But there are
specific positions that have to be assumed in different fields in order to realise
such possibilities. And as other people will be competing, the chance of realising such possibilities may be more to do with struggles over position than
with any skill, proficiency or talent. It may have more to do with professional
manoeuvrings, and wheeler-dealing, than the sustained application of creative
skills or inspiration.
Writers, musicians and artists continually struggle to influence how their
work is judged. Here both Becker and Bourdieu are concerned with the production of beliefs and values which legitimate art. Since it is not an inherent
quality of the art object, the question for Becker is how art comes to be labelled
as art. A key issue concerns the dynamics of distribution and the systems in
place that enable art works to be circulated. If art cant get distributed, how can
we ever know about it? Becker gives the example of e.e. cummingss poetry,
noting that printers were reluctant to set the poetry on the page as cummings
had specified, and that this held up publication. He also refers to sculptures
that are too large for an exhibition space. There may be a play or musical
Negus-04.qxd
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 85
CON VENTION
Hence, the lack of distribution channels, of a public arena or outlet for the
work, does not halt the creative process, but it does influence the form it takes
(written less with any sense of communication to distinct audiences, and more
for an internal dialogue). But it still has a communicative form. Ligetis compositions use inherited forms and ideas that people had communicated to him,
and he used these in his own way in the form that had the potential to reach
the public he still composed music. The creative act, even that which might
seem lone and private, is social and operates within a chain of communicated
experiences.
A further issue which follows from this last point concerns the importance of those who are in a position to influence the attribution of value.
Becker argues that to understand the attribution of aesthetic value we must
examine how art worlds produce particular people with the authority
to speak legitimately about art. The art world produces the ideas through
which the art is judged. The production of art comes hand-in-hand with the
85
Negus-04.qxd
86
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 86
Negus-04.qxd
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 87
CON VENTION
87
Negus-04.qxd
88
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 88
work of some artists, selling them at auction and signalling his ability to make
and break artists, even to end a historical moment (Jones, 2003: 14). Jake
and Dinos Chapmans sculpture of the physicist Stephen Hawking perched on
a crag in his wheel-chair and entitled Ubermensch went for a humiliating
10,350, a tenth of the prices paid for minor works by Hirst and Whiteread.
They were subsequently dropped by their dealer, Victoria Miro (ibid.: 14). A fifth
distinct way that Saatchi sought to define the meaning of art and establish
reputations was through the promotion of a new aesthetic category, applied to
a younger generation of artists which he labelled as neurotic realists. This was
decidedly less successful. He was unable to persuade the critics and many
ridiculed him, questioning his credentials as a legitimate authority on art.
Saatchis attempt to promote a new group of artists as neurotic realists
provided intimations of his precarious position within the artistic field, and
raised questions about his authority and legitimacy. This became even more
pronounced in the spring of 2003 when he launched a new gallery in a prominent position on the banks of the River Thames, in the somewhat unlikely
location of an old London council building. The Independent referred to it as
admans artbright and shiny, shitty and bloody, rude and jokey. Left-wing
critics, with memories of Saatchis support for the Thatcher government, were
wholeheartedly critical. Yet so were conservatives. George Walden, an ex-Tory
minister, described it as backward, provincial and sad Theres more merit in
one episode of The Simpsons than in his gallery. There was also discontent
about Saatchis style of intervention into the field, with the editor of Art
Monthly remarking: Its an unequal power struggle. In the end, its all about
Saatchi (all quotes from Bennett, 2003: 1617).
This latter point makes an explicit connection between the classification struggles over artistic value and the struggle for power. In Jonathan
Joness newspaper profile of Saatchi and his activities, he asks a more general
question about what art collectors seek to achieve. As he observes, most art
collectors do not need money, and do not collect art as a way of making
money. Instead, more often than not it is power the collector craves. The
power to make and break reputations, to influence museums, to establish critical consensus, to change history (2003: 14). The desire for such power is perhaps even more profound than this. Ritta Hatton and John Walker (2000: 96)
suggest that knowledge, mastery and controlare three recurrent motives for
collecting, whether this entails the accumulation of stamps, marbles or postcards. This mastery and collecting, classifying and ordering does seem a
particularly male preserve connected, in this instance, with a distinct attempt
to achieve what Hatton and Walker identify as three types of power economic, ideological and aesthetic/cultural/semiotic. As Bourdieu argues, it is
ultimately a type of institutional power political, economic, social which
informs the entire field of artistic production, influencing the establishment of
Negus-04.qxd
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 89
CON VENTION
reputations and struggles over economic, cultural and political resources. The
conventions of creativity are continually implicated in the wielding of, resistance to and struggle for power.
89
Negus-04.qxd
90
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 90
Negus-05.qxd
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 91
5
Tradition
It is a common misconception to regard innovation and tradition as
diametrically opposed to each other. When innovation is valued as a defining characteristic of the creative process, tradition often becomes set up
against it as inevitably static and unchanging. In this view, tradition inhibits,
and is seen as an impediment to be overcome.
We want to challenge this notion of tradition. As with convention in its
primary negative sense, tradition shouldnt be taken as the antithesis of innovation. Rather than seeing them as deeply divided, we want to consider tradition and innovative forms and practices as informing and supporting each
other. It is only by thinking about their interrelationship that we can understand
processes of creativity and cultural change. Creativity doesnt emerge out of a
vacuum, but builds on one or more existing cultural traditions. This is true of
poetry, architecture, film-making, styles of singing and any number of other
examples. In this sense creative talent requires a tradition so that it can learn
how to go further within it, or beyond it. Innovation should be understood by
rejecting those approaches which set it squarely against tradition and established cultural practice.
We nevertheless come to this issue with certain pre-formed views about
the role of innovation in social and historical processes, and about the quality
it brings to intellectual and cultural life. When a high value is placed on innovation, as has often been the case during the course of the modern period,
prejudices against tradition can easily arise. This is one obstacle to the understanding of innovation and tradition we want to discuss in this chapter, but
there is an equally weighty obstacle standing in the other direction. This is the
attitude of opposing innovation in principle, without regard for case or context, on the grounds that it is highly unlikely it will lead to any good. Such an
attitude can easily conflate what is good with what is past or what is settled into
its conventional place, and so turn against the future.
We start the chapter with a consideration of the philosophies of two
major figures, Edmund Burke and Friedrich Hayek, because they represent a
very strong current of thinking about tradition in opposition to political, cultural
and aesthetic change. Burkes writings feed into a conservative philosophy and
Negus-05.qxd
92
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 92
policy on heritage, and his legacy has haunted recent discussions about the
value of a range of landscapes, settings and buildings. For example, the parish
church of St Marys the Virgin in Putney is a key site in Britains revolutionary
past it was there in the autumn of 1647 that Levellers in Cromwells army
argued their case for a radically democratic state. In an article about the
significance of this church, Tristram Hunt and Giles Fraser cite Burke as the
originator of the practice of elevating custom and tradition above politics and
culture. They make the point that metropolitan liberals may sneer at local
museums or visitor centres, but immigrant and marginalised communities are
keen to rediscover their pasts and celebrate their ethnic or local heritage
Thanks to the metropolitan lefts cultural aversion to heritage, the historic
monuments and symbols of our radical past are being sorely neglected (Hunt
and Fraser, 2003; and see Brailsford, 1976, on the Putney debates). Such an
aversion leaves the stage wide open for official, establishment views of heritage
the Oxbridge colleges, stately homes and old cathedrals and for keeping
the concept of tradition conservative. This is why we begin with Burke, whose
importance extends considerably beyond an argument about constitutional history. We then move on to Hayek as a more contemporary example of the
reactionary defence of tradition. We devote attention to these figures because
they are conspicuously absent in latter-day cultural studies, which has its own
canonical agenda and preferred lines of dispute, and a predisposition to avoiding questions of custom and tradition, continuity and inheritances from the
past.
Negus-05.qxd
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 93
TRADITION
until the present day (1991: 29). Such thinking has taken its cue from Burke
in opposing large-scale transformation as a remedy for social ills and inequalities. Conservatism condemns socialists and liberals alike for seeking in such
transformation a solution to problems that cannot be solved, and so threatening the body politic with the malady of agitation (ibid.: 1). It is along lines
such as this that Burkes contribution to conservative political thought has been
enormous and far-reaching, extending considerably beyond the scorn for liberal do-gooders and social reformers that has been the prerogative of crusty
reactionaries across the intervening centuries.
Veneration of this contribution was initiated by the later Wordsworths
praise for Burkes endorsement of the vital power of social ties endeared by
custom. Though in different contexts the terms are distinct, custom here can
be understood as continuous with tradition. Similarly, Burkes claim for legitimacy of the British constitution, whose sole authority is that it has existed time
out of mind (cited in Briggs, 1965: 176), is the same as that claimed for the
value of tradition. Few people would now openly espouse such a primordialist
claim, but an implicit conflation of unquestioned value and assumed longevity
has often enough been the basis of opposition to change, regardless of
whether any appropriate distinctions have been made between custom and tradition. Burkes advocacy of the vital power of tradition in cementing social
ties helped develop a line of criticism setting off old against new, continuity
against change.
Burke viewed tradition as the ancient permanent sense of mankind
(Burke, 1852: 361). The accumulation of this sense and the associated
achievements contributing to it constitute a sublime inheritance running
through the generations and ensuring a stable social order. By contrast, a
spirit of innovation represents only the result of a selfish temper and confined
views. For Burke, the only effective counter to this was tradition, which he
defined in a classic contradiction in terms as wisdom without reflection
(Burke, 1978: 119). This conception of tradition presents us with an acquiescent acceptance of what has gone before. It leaves no place for reflexive practice, for creative uses of the past and creative responses to moments of
innovation, challenge and change. These are quite different to the empiricist
pragmatism with which Burke allied his populist conservatism. The following
passage from his most famous work illustrates very well the damage of sticking to the tried and trusted:
You see, Sir, that in this enlightened age I am bold enough to confess that we are
generally men of untaught feelings; we cherish them to a very considerable
degree, and, to take more shame to ourselves, we cherish them because they
are prejudices; and the longer they have lasted, and the more generally they
have prevailed, the more we cherish them. (ibid.: 183)
93
Negus-05.qxd
94
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 94
Negus-05.qxd
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 95
TRADITION
and valued from the perspectives of living people in the present. There is no
intrinsic reason why they should be valued, and any judgements are understood from contemporary perspectives and not simply discovered in some pristine, elemental form. We may turn to traditions as particular sources or
resources in response to deficiencies in the present, such as when architects
continue to be inspired and influenced by the buildings of ancient Greece,
Egypt or China, or when writers continue to draw on Sappho, Homer,
Catullus or Li Po and Tu Fu. It is the friction between past models and conventions, and the felt urgencies of contemporary forces and pressures, that can
inspire the creative process.
Burkes figurative reference to tradition as the general capital of nations
and ages aptly conveys his belief that the pursuit of economic self-interest is in
accord with social co-operation. Subsequently, it has become fundamental to
conservative thinking that tradition, in Burkes sense of a repository of authoritative common-sense prejudices, is compatible with the market economy as
an open-ended sphere of collective rationality. So understood, tradition is
another instance of the phenomenon that is exhibited by a market the phenomenon of tacit and collective understanding, realised through social intercourse, with neither regarded as amenable to centralised control or rational
planning (Scruton, 1991: 67). It was for this reason that Burke defended the
free-market theories of Adam Smith. His defence of Smiths laissez-faire economics in conjunction with his conservative defence of tradition further underscores Burkes importance in the history of conservative thought. He was, in
Scrutons estimation, the first serious thinker to attempt a reconciliation
between the ideas of economic freedom and traditional order (1991: 29).
This line of thinking, pursuing the reconciliation of tradition and selfinterest, has more recently been extended by Friedrich Hayek (18891992), a
leading exponent of unregulated market forces, key mentor to the British Tory
governments during the 1980s, and influential figure in contributions to the
intellectual rationale of neo-liberal economic policies in Eastern Europe following the collapse of the Soviet bloc. As with Burke, Hayeks conception of
tradition was informed by his opposition to any large-scale, collective attempts
to influence the direction of social development and change. Anti-collectivism
and the cultivation of competitive market dynamics through enterprising individuals are key Hayekian themes. These may not seem at first to be commensurate with his reverence for tradition, which is clearly in any particular case a
collective rather than an individual achievement. It is Hayeks understanding of
the epistemological basis of tradition that appears to reconcile his dogmatic
individualism with his championing of a free market order, despite cases of
traditions being destroyed by the modern market economy. The workings of
the market are never as spontaneous, haphazard and finally magical as he
always claimed.
95
Negus-05.qxd
96
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 96
Negus-05.qxd
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 97
TRADITION
process of tradition which Hayek favoured above anything that can be produced
by human ingenuity and creativity, for custom and tradition stand between
instinct and reason, and what can be rationally considered, chosen and
planned is, in Hayeks view, radically limited. This view is central to what Anna
Elisabetta Galeotti (1987: 170) has described as Hayeks philosophical anthropology of ignorance. In Hayeks own words, though governed in our conduct
by what we have learnt, we often do not know why we do what we do (Hayek,
1992: 23). This expresses Hayeks notion that we enter the world socially
blindfold. The blindfold we wear is tradition, and blindfolded by what we take
from the past, we operate entirely by tacit skills and capacities what he called
knowledge of time and circumstance as this is adapted from what is inherited
(Hayek, 1949: 80). Such knowledge defines the limits of what we can properly do and know. For Hayek it follows that we cannot know the social consequences of our actions, and that any attempt to reflexively monitor and
self-consciously modify the outcomes of our action is to infringe the liberty of
others.
Against this, we want to argue that defining liberty as freedom from
coercion by others entails a fatalistic acceptance of social inequality and injustice. To see social order as the unintended sum of innumerable separate decisions and actions, which in their collective manifestation cannot be taken as
coercive, is to falsely equate public good with the private pursuit of self-interest.
That of course was also Adam Smiths position, and the result is the same. The
term public is drained of any intrinsic positive meaning. Such a position is
based on an authoritarian view of the subject. This is difficult to square for
all its appeal to unintended outcomes leading to spontaneous order with
Hayeks theory of social evolution. Hayek simply falls back on an appeal to
moral tradition as a longstop to the socially destabilising effects of allcalculating, ruthless competition between autonomous individuals. As
Hilary Wainwright has pointed out, Hayeks arguments led him, despite his libertarian starting-point, to favour order and tradition over human creativity. His
social philosophy in general, and free-market model in particular, provide for
only the semblance of individual and collaborative creativity (1994: 5, 567).
His theory of society is atomistic and his theory of knowledge asocial, for all
that anyones mental compass can effectively comprehend are the facts of the
narrow circle of which he [sic] is the centre (Hayek, 1949: 14). This contradicts any possibility of participating in or learning from traditions as resources
of collective knowledge, fallible though they may be, or of a social order which
recognizes the distinct role, for good or ill, of human agency and creativity
(Wainwright, 1994: 60).
The conception of tradition found in both Burke and Hayek denies us a
critically reflexive perspective by claiming an exclusive reliance on established
codes and procedures, the general capital of ages past. It reifies tradition as a
97
Negus-05.qxd
98
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 98
Negus-05.qxd
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 99
TRADITION
99
Negus-05.qxd
100
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 100
habitual of daily routines. Its as if risk society begins where tradition ends, but
this is a false polarisation suggesting that tradition is synonymous with fate and
incompatible with a reflexive, individualised way of living ones life. To the contrary, for one response to a heightened sense of risk, contingency and rapid
change has entailed a revaluing of tradition and attempts to enhance its symbolic value. In this sense, contemporary understandings of tradition are a
response to the changes and anxieties associated with modernity.
As modernity has been experienced in different times and places, people
have come to re-assess and reflect upon how a sense of history and tradition
mediates their everyday lives. How people view tradition, in their families, in
government institutions, in intellectual disciplines or when involved in art
worlds, will tend to change as historical conditions and circumstances change.
Tradition is always viewed historically, and will be characterised and valued in
different ways. As we write this book, that sense of difference has perhaps
never been more expansive. Most of us have now developed a much sharper
awareness of the past as always in part a specific reconstruction, and of the
partial ways in which that reconstruction is accomplished, whether on the
page, through the screen, or inside the museum.
An expectation has developed that, as modernity advances, tradition
will inevitably decline and its values diminish in significance. This has not happened. Contrary to the Enlightenment and modernist thinking, which negatively associated it with distorted or spurious forms of thinking and acting,
tradition has neither disappeared as a dimension of various cultural systems
nor proved incompatible with modern political, technological and cultural
developments. It may seem that some traditions have dwindled and declined,
their values appearing less relevant in modern times, yet how we know this,
aside from very specific and finite cases, is always a perilous exercise, as is
obvious from the examples of religion and ethnicity. Just as likely, if not more
so, is the possibility of traditions adapting, mutating, being inverted or living
on in different forms, practices or objects. Although they remain seen as traditions, their meanings and values dont remain unaltered. This is precisely
why they continue to be relevant to people and continue to attract allegiance
and support. Certain traditions have been relocated to alternative sites and
media, or been discovered by different social groups and movements, who
have used them creatively as a cultural resource that is alternative to what has
otherwise been available to them, whether in their own regional class or ethnically based cultures, or in modern consumer society. Tradition as a cultural
dimension has, in short, proved to be co-extensive with modernity, and it has
done so in part because it has provided resources for cultural creativity and
invention which modernity may appear to have foregone.
The blues provides a good example of a cultural tradition that has
emerged and developed during modernity and proved adaptable to transfer
Negus-05.qxd
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 101
TRADITION
from country to city, from acoustic to electrically amplified forms, and from
dismissal by 1960s black power activists as accommodative and appropriated
by whites to its more recent rehabilitation by a new generation of black performers like Corey Harris, Guy Davis and Eric Bibb. Its resilience as a cultural
tradition is attributable to the resources it offers for extension and reinvention
as well as for apprenticeship in a wide range of expressive styles and structures.
Susan McClary has described the blues as a genre that succeeds magnificently in balancing convention and expression (McClary, 2000: 34). This is
exactly right, but we shouldnt exaggerate expression at the expense of convention. That is McClarys point. Albert Murray also stressed this in the 1970s
when he wrote of blues musicianship as being far more to do with convention
and tradition than with impulse. As he put it, you dont just have the blues and
then give direct personal release to the raw emotion brought on by suffering
(2000: 126).
The blues cannot be used expressively until you have at least a reasonable orientation with its idiomatic conventions and how these have developed
within the tradition. Even when this has been acquired, the result is characterised by imitation, variation and counterstatement rather than by originality:
It is not so much what blues musicians bring out of themselves on the spur of
the moment as what they do with existing conventions (ibid.), as they take
them over and extend or actively respond to them, as did Bessie Smith with
Ma Raineys singing style, and Robert Johnson with Son Houses playing style.
This may chafe against the cherished notions of a commonplace romanticism
about the blues, but it is only in this way that the blues tradition is extended
and renewed: a musician must have internalised its procedures in order to participate creatively within its ongoing conversation (McClary, 2000: 33). This
is true even of those who attain preeminence in the art: The unchallenged
supremacy of Duke Ellington is not based on pure invention but on the fact
that his oeuvre represents the most comprehensive assimilation, counterstatement, and elaboration of most, if not all, of the elements of blues musicianship (Murray, 2000: 126).
As this example of a particular cultural tradition and musical meta-genre
shows, we should rethink tradition in the light of its resilience its adaptability
and extendability in modern societies rather than seeing it merely as a residue
of past social formations. This step is central to our argument in this chapter.
It means understanding that we can only be original on the basis of some existing tradition, and that an abiding value of tradition lies in providing opportunities for its extension and transformation. Such an understanding is not as
widely accepted as it should be because of the prevalent ways in which both
tradition and innovation have been conceived. Viewing tradition simply as the
antithesis of modernity is part of the same conceptual pattern as the other
binary dichotomies inherited from classical sociology and anthropology.
101
Negus-05.qxd
102
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 102
Negus-05.qxd
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 103
TRADITION
103
Negus-05.qxd
104
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 104
Intelligibility is possible only in its coherence within tradition, but that doesnt
mean that tradition is to be defined as a mere process of serial repetition.
Intelligible order is grounded in tradition, but our understanding of it is possible because of, and not in spite of, temporal distance.
Tradition is never simply passed on across time. If this was true it would
stand little chance of avoiding its dissolution at the restless hands of change.
Instead, we should see tradition as involving an interplay of difference and
similitude, continuity and change, encounter and distance. As such it is integral to the broader process of developing a historical understanding, which is
embraced by changing temporal horizons and moves with them (Pickering,
1999). That is why, when tradition acts as the bridge between memory and
imagination, meaning and value, theory and practice, it is a bridge that is
always being built. It can never be completed for all time because time is always
moving beyond that which it seeks to bridge.
To conceive tradition in this way means that traditions only remain vital
when they are being re-created. This is where the recent emphasis given to the
inventedness of national traditions and the more general use of the term
invented traditions is rather misleading. The coinage derives from a widely
influential book, edited by Eric Hobsbawm and Terence Ranger, whose argument, backed up by various case studies, is that traditions which are held to be
ancient are often recent, selective, fabricated and manipulative. In his introduction to the book, Hobsbawm emphasises the purpose of invented traditions
as seeking to inculcate certain values and norms of behaviour by repetition,
implying automatic continuity with a suitable historical past which is largely
fictitious: In short, they are responses to novel situations which take the form
of reference to old situations, or which establish their own past by quasiobligatory repetition (1984: 12). Invented traditions are not characteristic
of any particular epoch or social formation but, as Hobsbawm suggests, they
are likely to become more frequent during times of rapid social change when
relatively settled configurations of experience and action are disrupted, damaged or destroyed. As weve seen, such change is particularly associated with
Western forms of modernity. While this shouldnt be taken as implying that
older traditions, or traditions outside the West, were inflexible or havent
changed over time, invented traditions, nevertheless, cluster during the modern period (ibid.: 45).
Hobsbawm argues that the period from 1870 to 1914 in Europe was
characterised by many mass-produced traditions which succeeded in proportion to their popular resonance. David Cannadine illustrates this in his documentation of the manufacture of British monarchical ritual and pageantry as
largely the product of the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries. The
general phenomenon of newly formalised traditions is equally well demonstrated in other chapters. Hugh Trevor-Ropers chapter, for example, deals
Negus-05.qxd
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 105
TRADITION
105
Negus-05.qxd
106
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 106
Negus-05.qxd
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 107
TRADITION
Second Empire (Hobsbawm and Ranger, 1984: 307). Even so, invented
traditions in the sense preferred by Hobsbawm assume the production of
forms of collective delusion. This implies the presence of a historian or social
theorist who can see through the delusion and never fall prey to such manipulation themselves. Their professional credentials in this respect are burnished by their selective use of evidence proving the duplicity of invented
traditions, and by their supposition, based on virtually no empirical research or
secondary evidence, that the public are readily seduced by this duplicity. In this
respect, the invention of tradition thesis is reminiscent of early twentiethcentury mass culture critique. In its loose and generalised extensions, it has
appeared as a strong throwback to such critique.
Even where this is not actually the case, the politics of representation
can make it appear as such. During the early 1990s, considerable controversy
was stirred up in Aotearoa/New Zealand by the press reporting of an article
by a North American anthropologist, Allan Hanson (1989). For example, one
front-page headline read: US Expert Says Maori Culture Invented (The
Dominion (Wellington), 24 February 1990: 1). The main import of the news
story was that Maori cultural tradition, which is central to their identity and history, was invented by European colonialists in the nineteenth century, and that
much of this invented material had been retained over the subsequent period.
Discussion of this in the country at the time was understandably hostile. Maori
scholars were angry with what was taken as a claim of inauthenticity since, not
unreasonably, they understood invented not in the modernist aesthetic sense
of make it new, but as denoting falsehood and contrivance. Although newspaper coverage of the article noted that Hanson did not seek to denigrate
Maori culture or castigate it as inauthentic, it was felt that criticising that culture as invented for political purposes, in order to enhance the assimilation
of the Maoris by white settlers, nevertheless undermined Maori pride in their
cultural distinctiveness, and weakened the basis of Maori land claims in the
sesquicentennial anniversary of the Treaty of Waitangi. The charge of invention seemed yet another piece of reactionary white revisionism in the face of
Maoritanga (Maoriness). The historian Ranginui Walker pointed out that in any
case Hansons article was based on white settler writings, and didnt take into
account Maori oral traditions, which were harboured in maraes hidden from
early Pakeha view (ibid.).
It was only on a subsequent reading of Hansons journal article that the
extent of press simplification became obvious. Academic and journalistic discourse concerning issues of authenticity and invention were widely divergent. As was the case with Maori cultural tradition, this can have unfortunate
consequences, for invention is clearly a double-edged blade: it can cut into
both subaltern forms of cultural inheritance and resistance as well as the chicanery of powerful governing elites. Since it can, it calls into question the role
107
Negus-05.qxd
108
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 108
Sahlins then asks: What else can one say about it, except that some people
have all the historical luck? and adds, with a final comic twist: On the other
hand, the historical lesson could be that all is not lost (Sahlins, 2002: 35).
While this sketch of the Renaissance as invented tradition is partly
spoof, it is also deadly serious in what it says about the politics of postcolonial
interpretation, whether these apply to Pacific cultures or elsewhere. These politics have been played out across the whole period of European colonial
encounter and domination, often around the very conception of tradition.
Nicholas Thomas has clearly identified the discrepancies between understandings of tradition among rural people in contemporary Oceania and western representations of tribal tradition. He refers to a modernity-and-tradition model
being imposed on the Fijians, producing a thatched versus corrugated tin roofs
view of the apparent corrosion of tradition, whereas the concern for tradition
among the Fijians is with social practice, values and ethics. Such tradition isnt
timeless. It has changed radically over the past 150 years or so, partly as a result
of colonial rule, partly as a result of opposition to the former British regime.
Thomas writes that it would be quite wrong to infer from this transformation in
modern times that contemporary rural Fijian life is not traditional, and adds:
now customs conceived as such really do regulate social life, and, in fact, it is
much more traditional than it could have been before (Thomas, 1997: 1823).
So, in modern Fiji, as a creative response to historical change, rural culture and identity have become, extensively and intensively, more traditional
rather than less. This reactive process has to be understood in terms of interaction and self-fashioning in the face of difference: the process of choosing
emblematic activities, dispositions, or material artefacts is indissociable from a
history of encounters and what is at issue in those particular encounters
Negus-05.qxd
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 109
TRADITION
(ibid.: 187). Yet where indigenous tradition has been reified, responses to this
may be negative or ambivalent as well as positive. The objectification of tradition is best understood not as crude fabrication or invention, but as an imaginative process in which Fijians creatively refashioned the relationships that
they had the opportunity to articulate (ibid.: 200). At the same time, the fact
of articulation always permitted a rejection of what was customary in favour of
its antithesis: this is what can be described as the negation of tradition, or as
an indigenous modernism that repudiated the custom-bound past and various
forms of obligation and constraint that epitomised it (ibid.: 202). The invented
tradition model is too blunt to be able to capture the intricate relations of this
kind of cultural dynamism. As Thomas shows, we need a more sophisticated
analysis of tradition if were going to grasp how it can be acted upon or
deployed to diverse ends (ibid.: 208).
More broadly than this, the crudity of the invention of tradition thesis, the
uncritical acceptance of it as a pioneering intervention, and its routine incantation in some writings about the modern mass media, reveal a widespread misconception of tradition and how it operates. It is easy enough to see that
traditions have been used ideologically, but this does not mean that all traditions
are a manipulative sham. This would be quite absurd, and yet the drift of much
subsequent discussion, following the initial publication of Hobsbawn and
Rangers edited collection, has certainly moved towards this assumption. In doing
this it has taken its cue from the one-sidedness of the invention of tradition thesis, the critique of manufactured continuities with a mythical past and the
assumption that the public believes and buys into it. As Jonathan Friedman has
remarked: If all culture is invention then there is nothing with which to compare
a particular cultural product, no authentic foundation. It implies a serious contradiction between the often asserted commonality of cultural creativity and a discourse that consistently attributes inauthenticity to modern cultural products
(1996: 145). In its critical one-sidedness, the thesis is relentlessly modernist:
secular, rationalist, objectivist, and based on a dichotomous opposition between
the represented and the real. To quote Friedman again: it divides the world of
representation into objective truth vs folk or ideological models of the world
(ibid.: 136). This divisive approach, with the clarity of exposition on one side and
the opacity of delusion on the other, evades the enduring appeal of tradition and
forms of cultural practice oriented towards this particular relation with the past.
So, for example, folk music in Europe and the United States is recreated tradition and would have little continuing value if this were not the case. Its
meanings have been mediated by collectors and scholars with preconceptions
and beliefs about the value of the music that has not necessarily been that of
vernacular singers and musicians, but this dissonance is of critical importance. It
shouldnt be taken as implying the same political functionality as a state
ceremony or royal ritual invented as tradition. As tradition, folk music is not
109
Negus-05.qxd
110
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 110
Negus-05.qxd
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 111
TRADITION
111
Negus-05.qxd
112
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 112
Negus-05.qxd
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 113
TRADITION
113
Negus-05.qxd
114
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 114
as when battles from the English Civil War are re-enacted, or when the Mardi
Gras is celebrated in New Orleans. We can also detect it in the way that the
public are encouraged to visit Dickenss London, take a trail around Mozarts
Vienna or Picassos Paris, followed by some Latin music, African dancing or
Indian food. But, even here, these experiences are not simply inauthentic and
falsely contrived. In some small way they always refer to the historical tradition
from which they have been adapted, even if middle-class connoisseurs might
aspire to a highly discerning approach and seek what is thought to be truly
authentic cuisine or truly authentic forms of dance or music during their
nights out.
In contrast to these strongly marked but never entirely successful tendencies to abstract, reify and package tradition, there is our experience of
coming into contact with more ambiguous and less easily coded traditions and
the myriad meanings and identities they generate for diverse groups of people.
Kofi Agawu provides intimations of such encounters with multiple traditions
when he makes an important point about considering sameness alongside
questions of difference. He calls for an approach which can facilitate a better
understanding of the peculiar juxtapositions of cultural practices that define
modern Africa. It would explain how a Sierra Leonean, Nigerian, or Ghanaian
can be equally moved by a hymn, a traditional dance, a local proverb, a quotation from Shakespeare, a piece of reggae, the Wedding March, and the
latest Highlife music (2003: 235). Similarly, we may be moved by an
Appalachian string band, qawwali or contemporary fado. It can be these types
of encounters which provide the most exhilarating conditions for dialogue
between difference and sameness, making connections with changing times
and places. The vantage point it gives helps us appreciate how living traditions
are often unstable and at times likely to change dramatically in character.
These two experiences of tradition the reductively ritual and the
ambivalent and unstable dialogic should not be elided, but neither should they
be treated as discrete entities. We cannot simply treat traditions as unambiguously invented and fast-frozen, nor treat them as distinct from other forms and
experiences of tradition that are assumed to be more authentic, radical or in
tune with lived realities. Traditions are simultaneously lived and (re)invented.
Any institutional attempt to produce an unambiguous single representation will
always be subject to critical assessment, reappraisal, reinterpretation and
creative appropriation. This is why authoritarian states have had so many
problems enforcing their singular and partial versions of national symbols,
heroes and narratives. An avant-garde or radical aversion to tradition as a dead
weight to be thrown off, and a conservative reverence for tradition as fixed and
sacrosanct, are equally misleading. Such melancholic stances are ultimately
futile in the face of how creative practice continually draws upon, transforms
and animates the living spirit of tradition.
Negus-06.qxd
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 115
6
Division
As creativity has acquired its modern meanings, it has become associated with
beliefs that can be construed as both elitist and essentialist. Elitist conceptions
of creativity assume that only some people have the potential to be or become
creative and only certain forms of creativity really matter, whilst essentialist
assumptions lead to beliefs that certain types of creativity are a natural gift of
biological or social inheritance.
Elitist conceptions have been pervasive in the western art tradition.
Social and ideological divisions have separated groups of people even as the
divisions themselves have been grappled with as points of departure for
re-defining the practice and meaning of creative activity. It is here that the figure
of the white, middle-class, European male becomes both stereotype and symbol
of a set of questions about access, attribution and canonisation.
Essentialist assumptions about creativity have often been signalled in the
use of such terms as black music, working-class or primitive art, womens
fiction and Indian film. Such categories can be just as exclusive, assuming
correspondences between people and creative forms. When successful, these
attributions have exerted considerable power over how creativity has been conceived within different artistic areas, and informed judgements about who is
capable of being recognised as a legitimate creator. They have impeded
the black pianist wishing to stage an opera or play in a symphony orchestra,
the woman wishing to be more than a muse to painters or composers, and the
middle-class white European male wishing to play blues, jazz or hip hop.
A central feature of its modern history has involved contesting these
essentialist and elitist understandings of creativity, showing how creativity does
not respect social divisions and yet how such divisions have obstructed and
obscured certain creative forms and practices that do not conform to attempts
at fixed definition and privileged attribution. This has not been easy, and the
reappraisal of the dynamics, characteristics and meaning of creativity is as
we hope we have made clear by now a continuing process. Social living
entails the continual confrontation of various divisions, attempts to overcome
them, and often despite the best intentions of those involved the production of yet new divisions. Creativity is shaped by divisions, continually generates
Negus-06.qxd
116
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 116
Negus-06.qxd
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 117
DIVISION
the struggles that constitute the fields of cultural production. Bourdieu has
featured earlier in this book, and one of the key points we have taken from his
research is his argument that the consecrated arts have not been open to
everyone, while access has always been available to those from particular privileged backgrounds. The possibility of achieving a dominant or influential position within officially accredited fields of cultural production is informed by the
ability to gain access to and accrue economic, political and cultural capital.
Hence from Bourdieu in particular (although others have also made this
point) we can recognise that aspiration, ability and the will to write poetry,
compose music or produce ideas is simply not enough. If the person involved
is to achieve a significant place within the world of art and letters and deemed
to be a recognised cultural producer occupying a legitimate position, they will
require considerably more than simply raw talent. Economic power and political influence may help, but what is crucial is the ability to make use of the influence afforded by the accumulation of cultural capital the repertoire of artistic
knowledge, values, beliefs and information and command over its application, which is necessary for the artist to gain entry into the social circles and
settings required for artistic recognition. Thomas Hardy wrote of the plight of
an autodidact, or self-taught, stonemason in his novel Jude the Obscure,
set in late-nineteenth-century Britain. Jude undertook an intense process of
self-education with the dream of being able to study and discuss ideas in
Christminster (Oxford):
It was not till now, when he found himself actually on the spot of his enthusiasm,
that Jude perceived how far away from the object of that enthusiasm he really
was. Only a wall divided him from those happy young contemporaries of his with
whom he shared a common mental life; men who had nothing to do from morning till night but to read, mark, learn, and inwardly digest. Only a wall but what
a wall!
Every day, every hour, as he went in search of labour, he saw them going and
coming also, rubbed shoulders with them, heard their voices, marked their movements. The conversation of some of the more thoughtful among them seemed
oftentimes, owing to his long and persistent preparation for this place, to be
peculiarly akin to his own thoughts.Yet he was as far from them as if he had been
in the antipodes. Of course he was. He was a young workman in a white blouse,
and with stone-dust in the creases of his clothes; and in passing him they did not
even see him, or hear him, rather saw through him as through a pane of glass at
their familiars beyond. Whatever they were to him, he to them was not on the spot
at all; and yet he fancied he would be close to their lives by coming there. (Hardy,
1929: 102)
If social class is an obvious barrier, we should immediately note that this makes
Jude socially invisible to other men, the gowned university students and dons
with whom he shares an incommunicable affinity. Hardy was acutely aware of
117
Negus-06.qxd
118
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 118
the limitations placed upon working-class men with artistic and intellectual
ambitions, but the gulf between manual labour and scholarly pursuits registered
in this quotation is one between classed men, not between men and women,
whether across the class divide or within a particular class. The whole question
of creativity has been riven not only by class but also by gender.
The social categories of gender and social class intersect in various
ways, and while historically they have defined the denials and limits of creativity, these are not simply imposed from outside. They can be internalised as
part of who people believe they are or are able to become. So, for example,
working-class men in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries had at
times to hide their interest in music, literature or painting if they were to avoid
the attribution of effeminacy. Although employed as a colliery blacksmith, Sid
Chaplin, from the north-east of England, had to write under pseudonyms during the three years of his mining apprenticeship and make his writing a secret
occupation because it was regarded as somehow feminine. A working mans
masculine identity in the pit communities of Northumberland and Durham was
founded in his muscular strength and ability, or agility, whereas writing was
very effeminate, so I said nothing about it. Here, class and gender in their
internalised combination were experienced as obstacles to Chaplins aspirations. Even as a closely guarded clandestine activity, his writing involved a
terrible jump in his cultural expectations and self-identity: I think I went to the
pillar box about six times before I parted with my first piece, and then I felt
rather relieved when I never heard about it again (Pickering and Robins,
1984: 143). The relief was not only to do with feelings of self-worth, but
also with the anxiety that if found out, hed be stuck with the attribution of
effeminacy.
The struggles of working-class autodidacts in the era of industrial capitalism were, of course, largely male struggles, but middle-class women faced
equally difficult obstacles in their aspirations to creative expression. Here we
confront the gendering of creativity itself. If writing poetry or short stories was
somehow feminine for working-class men, somewhat paradoxically, across
class lines during the same era, creativity as a middle-class cultural value
became increasingly male-oriented. In the early nineteenth century, for example, the poet Robert Southey declared that literature is not the business of a
womans life, and cannot be, while, for Gerald Manley Hopkins in the late
nineteenth century, the male quality is the creative gift (cited in Gilbert and
Gubar, 1984: 3, 8). Masculinising the arts reduced the threat of their association with femininity and effeminacy, and by the time of modernism the exclusion of women from literary and musical creativity was highly advanced (see,
for example, McClary, 1991: 1718; Citron, 2000: 50). This didnt mean that
middle-class women in the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries ceased to
produce art or engage in cultural production. But it did mean that they were
Negus-06.qxd
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 119
DIVISION
barred from various cultural institutions because of their gender, with only a
token few being included as honorary members or granted occasional participation as guests of men. A deeper injury was that their engagement in writing, painting or composing entailed risks to their moral reputation and social
standing. A womans artistic creations were treated as if gender made a crucial difference to her identity and the value of what she produced.
In Britain, the assumed difference in the identity and value of womens
involvement in artistic and cultural practice stemmed from the stereotypical
ideal of femininity prevalent in the Victorian and Edwardian periods. This
ideal, whose repudiation has required over a century of struggle, placed
women tendentiously in positions of peripheral support and appreciation
rather than of dynamic involvement in the creative practices that were held in
greatest esteem. The social critic and writer on art and architecture, John
Ruskin, encapsulated the ideal in his lecture Of Queens Gardens:
The mans power is active, progressive, defensive. He is eminently the doer, the
creator, the discoverer, the defender. His intellect is for speculation and invention [Womans intellect] is not for invention and creation, but for sweet ordering, arrangement, and decision. She sees the qualities of things, their claims,
and their places. Her greatest function is Praise: she enters into no contest, but
infallibly adjudges the crown of contest. (Ruskin, 1907: 1356)
This was not the only view of womens place and function: Mary
Wollstonecraft and John Stuart Mill, for example, represent alternative, early
feminist conceptions of gender difference. But the Ruskinian ideal was strongly
echoed by others Thomas Carlyle considered a womans purpose in life to be
a beautiful reflex of her man and its influence was enormous, with cultural
institutions and practices playing a considerable part in its power and reach
(Wolff, 1990: 1618). The Ruskinian ideal was closely related to the dichotomy
of male/public and female/private realms and the celebration of domesticity as
a cherished haven in a tempestuous world. The stereotypical angel in the
house in Coventry Patmores famous phrase was the saint at the centre of
this haven, with her binary counterpart, the whore or fallen woman, banished
to the street outside (Patmore, 1885; see also Christ, 1977). Whether as Dora
Spenlow or Agnes Wickfield in Dickenss David Copperfield, Esther
Summerson in Dickenss Bleak House, or Rosie Mackenzie in Thackerays The
Newcomes, the angel in the house was intended as the epitome of moral
refinement, spiritual grace and physical virtue, the domestic exemplar and
guardian of traditional values in a rapidly changing industrial age one whose
main role in life was to support men and endorse all they did: Man must be
pleased; but him to please is womans pleasure (Patmore, 1885: 73).
The biological essentialism of this gender model, and its accompanying
notion of men and women belonging to separate spheres, relegated womens
119
Negus-06.qxd
120
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 120
Negus-06.qxd
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 121
DIVISION
121
Negus-06.qxd
122
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 122
Vanburgh lifted off his velvet cap and reverently bared his head; then he continued,
That is what an artist should be, by nature. (Craik, 1850: 161, cited in Parker
and Pollock, 1981: 83)
Negus-06.qxd
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 123
DIVISION
defined role given to women in the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries
(1981: 58; and see Parker, 1984). Within this period, the status of an artist
increasingly determined the way their art was seen, with artistic exceptionality
or genius becoming an exclusively male possession. Such was the force of
existing social stereotypes that any claim to such a possession by a woman, or
even of independent consciousness, would have been to court distrust, censure
and infamy. That is why Marie Bashkirtseff could only rail against those idiots
who think that my painting is the amusement of a woman of the world (Parker
and Pollock, 1981: 109).
A further barrier which has confronted women who wanted to write,
paint or compose music has been their relative lack of suitable precursors in
the face of canonical male authority. While the contemporary female writer
may feel that she is helping to create a viable tradition which is at last definitively emerging (Gilbert and Gubar, 1984: 50), female writers in the past have
not had the benefit of appropriate validating paradigms of aesthetic convention, creativity and self-creation as artists.
To some extent this continues to be the case. In Harold Blooms formulation, the dynamics of artistic creativity arise from an anxiety of influence
and an heroic Oedipal struggle to overcome ones male precursors. While this
is a dubious model in itself, it is inapplicable to a female artist when her male
precursors incarnate patriarchal authority and endorse the social stereotypes
which deny her subjectivity, her autonomy, her creativity: Thus the anxiety
of influence that a male poet experiences is felt by a female poet as an even
more primary anxiety of authorship a radical fear that she cannot create
(ibid.: 489).
Marcia Citron has noted that this anxiety for female artists in the past
often translated itself into deference to male views and judgements, and an
ambivalence about womens relationship to the creative process. She traces
this among a number of women composers, such as Fanny Hensel
(180547), and Clara Schumann (181996), who noted in her diary: I once
believed that I had creative talent, but I have given up this idea; a woman must
not wish to compose there never was one able to do it (Citron, 2000:
567; see also Reich, 1985: 2289). There is great pathos in these words,
but who was speaking here, and to whom? It is difficult, perhaps impossible,
to say. The problem goes deeper. It not only included undervaluing personal
achievement, or losing belief in a sense of personal creative ability, or exaggerating personal singularity as a female artist. It could also entail a dislocating confusion about their identity as artists. For female musicians of this
period, the lack of autonomous female precursors or contemporaries might
lead, as it did with Clara Schumann, to a split sense of selfhood: a strong subjected self when it came to performing, a self tending toward objectified
Other when it came to composing (Citron, 2000: 56). Once again, men
123
Negus-06.qxd
124
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 124
Negus-06.qxd
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 125
DIVISION
125
Negus-06.qxd
126
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 126
think, while others do not, and we cannot treat this distinction wholly in terms
of the issue of who decides what is great literature and whose definitions of
greatness stick. What makes this issue more complicated is that it may suggest that the common reader cannot make such decisions, or can only
parrot the definitions they have internalised. A history of working-class autodidacticism based on the assumption that its subjects were simply class ventriloquists would clearly be deeply compromised and flawed. While the question
of class influence is always relevant, it shouldnt be taken as denying the ability of ordinary people to articulate those encounters with literary texts which
they have found transformative.
Many common readers in the past may have believed that only canonical literature could produce epiphanies and only great books could inspire
them to write (Rose, 2001: 371), but this does not absolve Taylor from the
charge of confining his discussion of epiphanic artworks to those of the
western high literary tradition. The sources of selfhood in the modern period
do not belong exclusively to this tradition. Martha Nussbaum has pointed to
Taylors lack of attention to African, Asian and Latino/a traditions, all of
which, in various ways, have contributed to the sense of self of most
Americans and many Europeans. Many citizens in the West define their identity quite centrally in terms of those traditions rather than those of Europe or
North America. Moreover, in a globalised world, questions of cultural identity
and social justice cannot be confined to western aesthetic and ethical sources
(Nussbaum, 1990). This confinement of focus is true more specifically of
Taylors account of authentic art as well. He draws almost exclusively on high
cultural art and aesthetics, with the epiphany of translucence being not far
away from a reified text in itself, and the life and works paradigm of literary
or artistic creation, which we critiqued in chapter two.
The spiritual dimension in the semantics of creativity clearly lives on in
epiphanic art, yet not just the art of high culture. It is found in popular culture
as well, as when people speak of a sense of revelation or of being emotionally
transfixed on first hearing a particular popular song. It may be that for certain
people a kind of pietystill surrounds art and artists in our time, and that this
comes from the sense that what they reveal has great moral and spiritual significance, that in it lies the key to a certain depth, or fullness, or seriousness,
or intensity of life, or to a certain wholeness (Taylor, 1989: 422). Even more
than in the early twentieth century, such piety seems now to be characteristic
of a social minority with a high stake in the cultural capital associated with a
rarefied sense of aesthetic value. The distance of such aesthetics from the
everyday world of majority populations only exaggerates the sense of that
world as out of joint, forsaken or spiritless, as a heartless world where instrumentalism and commercialism are dominant. This may be a convenient distancing strategy, but it tells us nothing of value about popular aesthetics.
Negus-06.qxd
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 127
DIVISION
So the significance of blues and jazz in the development of modern popular music cannot be reduced to questionable (sometimes essentialist) notions
of racial expression. There has always been some more profound crossover
involving movement beyond the parameters of black musics labelled ethnic
127
Negus-06.qxd
128
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 128
origin and racial stereotypes. In criticising the absence of such protean musical
forms as blues and jazz from Taylors account, Nussbaum observes that they
are, in Taylors own sense, moral sources of enormous depth and power:
How many of his readers, when they think about love or pain, owe as much to
Trollope or Eliot or Holderlin as they do to Bessie Smith or Billie Holiday? And is
the vision of suffering, joy, endurance and justice that unfolds in the searing,
broken cadences of Holidays last recordings any less worthy of close philosophical scrutiny than the forms of art and literature that Taylor does discuss?
(Nussbaum, 1990: 32)
Rushdies observations, part celebratory, are in keeping with his other pronouncements about the cultural value of mixing and a hybrid aesthetic. But he
also makes a more critical point about the contradictory tensions which link
liberation and restriction as a result of the crossing of various frontiers:
Negus-06.qxd
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 129
DIVISION
Anyone who has crossed a language frontier will readily understand that such a
journey involves a form of shape-shifting or self-translation. The change of language changes us. All languages permit slightly varying forms of thought, imagination and play. I find my tongue doing slightly different things with Urdu than I
do with, to borrow the title of a story by Hanif Kureishi, your tongue down my
throat. (ibid.: 6)
129
Negus-06.qxd
130
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 130
Negus-06.qxd
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 131
DIVISION
131
Negus-06.qxd
132
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 132
Negus-06.qxd
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 133
DIVISION
the genre boundaries and informing the commissioning strategies that would
subsequently lead to the promotion of other types of world literature. These
writers sought publishers, and in the emergent post-colonial context became
an attractive proposition to a publishing industry seeking to take advantage of
a growing market for West Indian literature. Mike Phillips has even remarked
that for a long time it was easier for a black writer living in the Commonwealth
to be published in Britain than for a black person born and brought up in
London or Birmingham (2001: 146).
Yet these writers from the Commonwealth occupied an ambivalent
position. Not fully integrated within or belonging to host networks, their
involvement with the publishing industry was by no means a straightforward
process. Like many artistic creators they had a range of personal motives and
agendas. We can explain neither their art nor their engagement with the
career of writer in terms of coercion by an imperialist capitalist industry, or
exertion of their own free will and their ambition to succeed. The formation of
English language Caribbean literature as a commodity resulted in a number of
tensions. Authors such as Rex Nettleford and George Lamming argued that in
entering into these types of literary relationships and in creating such literature
the writer began to construct a very different Caribbean form of writing, one
that (in part) was being produced to appeal to readers who were not geographically located in the Caribbean. To quote Rex Nettleford:
The question of the marketcannot be ignored. Who does the Caribbean writer
really write for?for the Caribbean readership still growing but yet to offer the
critical mass which brings profits? Is he addressing the more affluent North
American suburban class or the intelligentsia? Does he write for the British
literati with a long tradition of playing patron to sibling talents from the outposts
of empire? (1993: 56)
133
Negus-06.qxd
134
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 134
Negus-06.qxd
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 135
DIVISION
Just how a writers style might change within this nexus is an interesting and
under-researched issue, but it is clearly more complex than a straightforward
accommodation to metropolitan values. Through its very presence such literature can contribute to changing artistic perceptions and may facilitate a transformation of metropolitan literary values, adding new dialects and innovative
styles that extend the use of the English language (Griffiths, 1978). One obvious aesthetic impact of this is that English literature, or being a British writer, is
no longer the preserve of an ethnically specific designation (Nixon, 1992: 43).
The cultural form, the identity of the writer, the identity of the literary
circles and the identity of the publishing industry are all transformed during
these movements, as creativity occurs across the frontiers of culture, language
and ethnicity. For this reason, we must stress that a discussion of creativity and
social divisions should adamantly refuse the assumption of an unchanging
racial, gendered or class position. People move and change. Creativity not
only entails the transformation of aesthetic materials, it can also entail the
transformation of individuals, groups and values, and the ways these are
represented.
Such transformations cannot be glibly celebrated as facilitators and harbingers of new hybrid social identities and aesthetic forms any more than they
can be roundly condemned as inauthentic responses to various patterns of
domination. In thinking about and attempting to understand how creativity is
realised through social and geographical movements which constitute some
form of exile, we should be attentive to the enduring tensions arising around
and through such divisions. We should also be aware of the various struggles
(for recognition, economic reward, power and influence) which inform the
transformations of literary style and convention.
The writers we have been discussing, who left the Caribbean, shared a
similar education and a set of acquired middle-class mores. Their orientation
to literature and the process of becoming a writer was not incompatible with
that of those they found in metropolitan London. In certain respects they were
indeed in a superior position to the black British writers (as Phillips suggests)
or to many of the white working class in Europe (as Sinfield observes). The dispositions and knowledge of these exiled writers allowed for their acceptance in
metropolitan literary London, facilitating various creative dialogues.
What soured such dialogues was the unanticipated racial labelling which
greeted these writers, almost instantly. The realisation that in London they
were, pejoratively, black, disrupted their sense of belonging or full participation in the middle-class literary world. The experience of finding oneself
labelled black, and stereotyped accordingly, would subsequently lead to further
and different types of dialogue. The middle-class Caribbean writer suddenly
had something in common with black working-class musicians and film
makers due to the way that race and racism impacted upon the realisation and
135
Negus-06.qxd
136
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 136
Negus-06.qxd
3/27/04 12:29 PM
Page 137
DIVISION
from something threatening, and on the other of having suffered a tragic break
in their history. Learning to live with that ambiguity is difficult but it has to be
done If they do succeed, then their time of waiting in exile, actively waiting, will
become for them a time of hope. (Faundez, 1989: 11)
The skill is to turn loss and irresolvable ambiguity into hope and artistic
triumph. In this perilous shift lies the enigma of creative arrival and travel from
the local and particular towards another enigma, the universal.
137
Negus-07.qxd
3/27/04 12:30 PM
Page 138
7
Genius
For many years, social and cultural theorists have tended to avoid or oppose
the identification and recognition of exceptionality with which genius is associated. The very notion is often rejected as inherently mystifying or elitist.
While we may be able to critically dismiss certain aspects of the idea of genius
as no longer valid, this should not lead to a wholesale rejection of the concept.
We want to encourage an approach which can think of the activity and its
judgement as distinct, without collapsing them as if the idea of genius only
arises as an ideologically laden value judgement and not in a very exceptional
human achievement to which the act of according value is just one response.
The epithet genius is a medieval inheritance from Latin, denoting an
attendant inner spirit assigned to every person at birth, governing their fortunes and determining their character. By extension, the sense of genius as
guardian spirit was applied to specific groups, or to a particular place, as in the
term genius loci. The Roman attribution of genius was thus widespread, and
although as a guardian spirit within any particular family it was conceived as
being embodied in the paterfamilias, it was not confined to a few singularly
endowed individuals elevated above the broad mass of citizens.
The modern concept of genius is characterised by a move away from
this spiritual sense of a guiding light through life that is available to all, and
from its broader association with the whole spectrum of human endeavour.
This has involved a shift from a relatively inclusive to a relatively exclusive
meaning of the term. The basis for this shift was laid in the seventeenth century by the combination of the Latin sense of genius with another Latin word,
ingenium, referring to an innate ability or talent. Genius still referred to a quality possessed by a person, rather than a specific category of person, but by the
end of the eighteenth century, genius had become the designation for a distinct human type. This was one (invariably male) possessed by an inner spirit
or daemon impelling him to strive towards the dizzy heights of artistic achievement. Such heights came to be conceived as the creation of an original imaginative vision of the world, and an original style or character of artistic
expression. Hence the exclusivity, which then helped to harden other social
divisions over the course of the next two centuries. Genius became an
Negus-07.qxd
3/27/04 12:30 PM
Page 139
GENIUS
extraordinary single individual, raised above time and responsible for the finest
of the fine arts. The genius was perceived as someone acutely innovative,
original and superior, set apart from ordinary mortals, and as a creator ex
nihilo, seeming to be close to the very forces of creation.
Art was the primary site for the transposition of religious conceptions
about the origin of the world into secular ideas about originality, and those of
creation into the modern sense of creativity. The artist and above all the
artistic genius was the chief beneficiary of this transfer, becoming the new
modern paradigm of individual development as self-creation. The more everyday life was conceived in opposition to self-creation and the search for originality, the more artists were elevated above mundane affairs and ordinary folk,
at least during the Romantic period, and in less dramatic ways ever since. In
their most exceptional moments of creativity artists were considered to be
divinely inspired, and those granted the prodigious creative powers of the
genius were considered, above all, as the fittest agents for the gradually secularising transition of creation from God to Man, producing, in Coleridges conception, a repetition in the finite mind of the eternal act of creation
(Coleridge, 1910: 159). In this sense, artistic creativity was an intense reaction
to the modern disenchantment of the world, with an artwork conceived as a
presence which opens onto the infinite, so that, in Robertss crisp formulation, modern art is the continuation of the sacred by other means (1994:
173). This transcendent conception of creativity and art brought the individual
and the universal into an apparently paradoxical relation, with the power of
genius being that of reuniting the universal and particular in an original vision
of the world. It was the belief in this power which helped reduce the sense of
exceptionality to a single individual, representative of a distinct personality
type.
While various examples from earlier periods or other places can be
identified, it was within European Romanticism, and especially Romanticism in
its British and Germanic contexts, that our continuing ideas about genius were
first developed and consolidated. The shift in reference to genius as an exclusive category of person was accorded its greatest value in this specific historical epoch and geographical region, but particular notions of creativity, artistic
expression, fine art and the figure of the artist spread beyond it, and continue
to remain influential both within Europe and beyond. So, for instance, it was
because of the expressivist realisation of artistic vision discussed in chapter one
that the sense developed of exceptional creative powers arising, in analogy
with natural growth, as the result of innate capabilities. These exceptional
powers were then ascribed to singular, gifted individuals for whom the category
of genius seemed ideally suited. Creative geniuses became exalted above and
beyond any cultural form, genre or tradition in which they worked, as well as
over everyday life and mundane practical skills.
139
Negus-07.qxd
140
3/27/04 12:30 PM
Page 140
The changed meanings and values associated with the category were
thus connected with a transformed understanding of creativity as the outpouring of natural impulse, a spontaneous expression of a new sense of subjectivity and individuality. The initial shift is signalled in two works dealing with the
subject of genius which were published in the third quarter of the eighteenth
century by Alexander Gerard (1774) and Edward Young (1759). Both offered
organic images of the creative process and refigured genius into a celebration
of uniqueness. The ideas in these accounts influenced such contemporary figures as Herder, Goethe and Kant, and have remained influential ways of thinking about exceptionality. In Kants Critique of Judgement, for example,
genius is defined as the innate mental disposition (ingenium) through which
nature gives the rule to art (1982). As an innate predisposition, genius is
beyond conceptual thinking in its originality, but as an exemplar is also responsible for forming or radically changing the ground rules of artistic expression
within a cultural tradition. Kant neither attributes genius to an inner daemon
(or in more modern terms, the forces of the unconscious) nor counters that
notion by simply emphasising years of hard toil, but what he delineates is artistic
genius as a conflux of sublimity and reason. This has remained central to our
understanding of the originality of genius.
The tension between an originality which cannot be known intellectually, and the consequent evidence of it which can only be known intellectually,
has characterised ways of thinking about innovation and exceptionality
throughout the modern period.
Negus-07.qxd
3/27/04 12:30 PM
Page 141
GENIUS
racist notions have now been discredited, largely because of their popularity
under Nazism, though they have remained implicit where selective sterilisation
has been practiced or the right of people with disabilities to have children has
been denied. Galtons ideas survive in standardised measurements of intelligence such as IQ tests, a key staple of twentieth-century British and North
American psychology. In the United States, IQ tests were used from the start
as a technique for identifying children with the genetic potential for genius.
Gifted may be todays preferred term for such potential, but giftedness
was initially used as a synonym for genius. It inherits the Galtonian link
between gene and genius, even if that link is no longer exclusively male. The
genetic transmission of intelligence and talent, unconnected with social
arrangements and opportunities, remains a common idea. It continues to
inform certain aspects of the academic curriculum when undergraduate discussion of the relationship between individual and society is conducted in the
terms of nature or nurture, coined by Galton himself.
Race-thinking affected another conception of genius in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries. This involved recycling the Romantic association between madness and genius. Creativity, genius and madness have been
sporadically associated in western culture since Aristotles time as if peaks of
cultural productivity are dependent on mental instability, if not illness but following the Romantic revaluation of madness as a source of true insight, the
association attained the status of a truism (Gilman, 1988: 21920). It acquired
even greater resonance in the late nineteenth century because of anxieties concerning racial hygiene and degeneration. For example, Cesare Lombroso
(1891) and others considered genius and madness as analogous on the basis of
their departure from normality. Normality in this period was, at least in part, a
racialised notion. As an aberration from normality in this sense, creativity
seemed confirmed in its association with pathological conditions.
So, for example, from the satanic figure of the Jewish genius, the association spread out into the antisemitic stereotypes and myths of the early
twentieth century. In response to this, Freud attempted to eliminate stereotypical
Jewish distinctiveness from his discussions of creativity, and instead examined
exceptional talent and creativity in the development of particular outstanding
individuals. In his writings on Leonardo da Vinci and Michelangelo, for example, Freud viewed creativity as displaced sexual energy, a sublimation of the id
into the realms of fantasy and the aesthetic. It is this idea which lies behind
Josef Breuers statement in Studies on Hysteria (co-written with Freud in
1895): Goethe did not feel he had dealt with an experience till he had discharged it in a creative artistic activity (Gilman, 1991: 139). This approach
not only makes male sexuality the wellspring of artistic creativity, it also makes
creativity dependent on sexual repression. So for Freud, creativity was akin to
neurosis and shared the same aetiology. Over the twentieth century, this
141
Negus-07.qxd
142
3/27/04 12:30 PM
Page 142
became a stock clich: the image of the artist who is not sexually fulfilled, and
who sublimates libidinous energy into artistic creation.
An obvious objection to equating sexual repression with creative expression is that such repression may be apparent without any necessary manifestation of creativity. Even if we partially accept this type of psycho-pathological
explanation of genius (or the behaviour which might be conducive to genius),
were still faced with the fact that although many people might be diagnosed
or labelled in this way, they dont necessarily produce the art or literature of
Michelangelo or Dostoevsky. A different stereotype could be produced, with
sexually frustrated males sublimating their energies into stamp collecting,
record collecting, train spotting or obsessive support for a football team.
The permeation of the category of genius with stereotype and myth has
been challenged in various ways by artists themselves. Instead of the pathological association of artistic creativity with madness and mental derangement,
social deviancy and racial degeneration, a positive identification is made with
creative departures from normality. Particularly, but by no means exclusively,
among the avant-garde common associations have been with children and
childhood play, with primitivism and native art, and with clowns and clowning. These associations have figured in two major ways. First, as a variable
alternative to utilitarian values, bureaucratic rationality, the work-ethic and
crass commercialism. Second, as a romanticised ideal in relation to the established order because the assumed raw, unspoiled vitality was considered superior to stereotypical bourgeois cultural norms and, more significantly, regarded
as close to the redemptive forces of creativity itself (see Ritter, 1989; Pickering,
2003 for art and the clowning tradition). Taking up just one of these cases,
primitivist art from Africa or Oceania became a source of inspiration within
modernism because its creative vigour was seen as supplying precisely the
qualities European art seemed to have lost intensive expressiveness, clarity
of structure and a forthright simplicity of technique (Gombrich, 1967: 428).
It also represented a radical compensation for what Klingender (1972) called
cashbox aesthetics. Such art spoke to a sense of lack in white subjectivity as
well as in high European culture, but its positive evaluation did not alter its aesthetic ranking. It was still seen as resulting from anonymous craft skills rather
than from individual artistic creation. Even today, the products of individual
artistic creation in economically privileged countries are displayed in art galleries, while the artworks of so-called primitive or undeveloped societies
remain largely relegated to museums of ethnology or anthropology. The ideology of creativity continues to divide the West from the Rest.
As we have seen, the divisions associated with creativity have invariably
stemmed from essentialist social identities and elitist sources of authority and
power. While these were formed around such structuring conditions as social
class, gender and ethnicity, so they led to various intersections across spatial
Negus-07.qxd
3/27/04 12:30 PM
Page 143
GENIUS
143
Negus-07.qxd
144
3/27/04 12:30 PM
Page 144
that would have been unthinkable coming from anyone else. Admirers describe
him as a philosopher, a wise man, someone who knew all the secrets of how to
live. (1988/2001: 45)
Negus-07.qxd
3/27/04 12:30 PM
Page 145
GENIUS
and attaining competence and skill, that is required before a sufficient level of
proficiency is reached at which creative acts can occur. Michael Howe offers
an example of this kind of explanation of genius when he writes that, like ordinary men and women, major authors have had to invest large amounts of time
and effort in order to become unusually skilled. He goes on: Their heavy
dependence upon training and preparation is one of the many aspects of
human experience that creative geniuses share with other people (Howe,
1999: 175). In contrast, there is an approach which locates the sources of
creativity as lying beyond rational principles and procedures. The emphasis is
on some form of inspiration, or alternatively on some value in creative practice that arises without any undue intellectual application, formulae or method.
A revised version of this is provided by Gabriel Garca Mrquez. When asked
about inspiration, Garca Mrquez distanced himself from the influence of
Romanticism before refining that influence by defining inspiration as a struggle which entails a reciprocity and interflow of writer and theme:
Its a word that has been discredited by the Romantics. I dont see it as a state of
grace nor as a breath from heaven but as the moment when, by tenacity and control, you are at one with your theme. When you write something, a kind of reciprocal tension is established between you and the theme, so you spur the theme
on and the theme spurs you on too. There comes a moment when all obstacles
fade away, all conflict disappears, things you never dreamt of occur to you and, at
that moment, there is absolutely nothing in the world better than writing. That is
what I would call inspiration. (Garca Mrquez and Apuleyo Mendoza, 1988: 34)
145
Negus-07.qxd
146
3/27/04 12:30 PM
Page 146
Negus-07.qxd
3/27/04 12:30 PM
Page 147
GENIUS
actresses are born, not made. This takes us no further than the notion of
creativity as simply the outpouring of spontaneous impulse.
As we have continually argued, the opposition between artistic vision
and humdrum, mechanical life can only diminish our understanding of the
range and scope of the creative process. The problem we continually
encounter is that any attempt to grapple with this process seems inevitably to
run up against a whole series of dichotomies and conflicting perspectives.
These cannot simply be resolved at a theoretical or conceptual level, for they
have their source in the tangible, sensory experiences that coincide with the
creative act. Yet when confronted with these divergent meanings, theres a
tendency for many writers to attempt to resolve them by prioritising one or the
other. This may, for example, be done either by claiming that only a select few
Plato, Dante, Hegel are truly creative (Steiner, 2001), or by arguing that all
everyday actions are potentially creative and adopting a dismissive or sceptical
stance towards any notion of exceptionality (Willis, 1990; Joas, 1996). For us,
the separation of these positions serves only to reinforce and perpetuate
another unhelpful, and still pervasive dichotomy: that of elitism/populism.
147
Negus-07.qxd
148
3/27/04 12:30 PM
Page 148
Negus-07.qxd
3/27/04 12:30 PM
Page 149
GENIUS
than a social and political construct makes it an empty concept there are no
geniuses, only the politics of genius. This leaves us with the unresolved problem of how exceptionality may be explained. Secondly, DeNora deconstructs
genius and the appreciation of genius not by contesting value, but by contesting motive, as if musical appreciation is only and entirely a matter of selfinterest or in Kivys lampooning take on this: Scratch a music lover and you
will, inevitably, find a status seeker or social climber beneath (2001: 208).
This reduces all musical aesthetics, including the aesthetics of popular music,
to acts of bad faith. Thirdly, it is important to distinguish, as clearly as one can,
between artistic and cultural production on the one hand, and its critical acceptance and celebration on the other. They cannot simply be conflated as in
Bourdieus terms the evidence of social and cultural capital. In Beethovens
case, this is an impoverishment of historical imagination. It fails to address the
question as to why his music endures beyond the time and place in which he
lived, or how it connects with huge numbers of people. Is this only due to the
social and political construction of belief in his genius, and nothing to do with
the music and the actions of its maker? Kivys response is to say that if genius
is explained solely as constructed reputation, anyone can become a genius if
theyre given the right connections and the requisite publicity. This is rationality running away with itself.
In noting these critical points, we have no wish to deny that the idea of
genius has been and can be used to legitimate a restrictive and socially divisive
canon, to justify the existence of educational institutions and practices privileging a small minority, and to rank male and female cultural achievements
according to unjust criteria. But the fact that the great praise and attention
accorded to various individuals, and the artworks or products associated with
them, may have served certain ideological interests doesnt mean that they or
their achievements are utterly subsumed by these interests. As Kivy carefully
notes, it is important to distinguish between mythical representations of genius
and the claim that genius is a myth. Blanket dismissal of the notion of genius
means that the question of exceptionality is avoided altogether. To treat it
merely as a reified bourgeois category, or to see it solely as the product of a
repressive aesthetic canon, is an evasion of the problems posed by genius. The
idea and value of genius as exceptionality exceeds its sociological critique.
In cultural studies and the sociology of culture, genius is often critiqued,
or dismissed entirely, because of an overriding concern to reconceive creativity as a more general phenomenon than that advanced in conventional aesthetic canons. While this is self-evidently laudable, it has created a huge
obstacle to thinking about exceptionality in cultural creativity. It is one thing to
argue against elitism, but quite another to attribute creativity, equally, to everyone. This is misleading flattening the concept into insignificance. A second
dubious step is to selectively approach genius only in terms of the most fallacious
149
Negus-07.qxd
150
3/27/04 12:30 PM
Page 150
uses to which the term has been put in the past. If creativity has become
recognised as ordinary, as an ability that we all have, why should we not also
acknowledge the extraordinary? Is the concept of genius invalid in a democratic society, an undesirable legacy from an inegalitarian age?
Kivy makes the crucial point that critiquing the elitism of social class,
race and gender doesnt necessarily entail the denial of exceptionality. He
asks: why in the world should I not recognise the eliteness of genius? He
accepts the genuine difficulty which genius poses for feminist sociology but
wishes to make clear that it is not so much the concept of genius which has
historically excluded the female genius, but rather the insidious (and false)
characterisations of women that prevent them from falling under that concept. So for feminism to deny the eliteness of its own genius is to give over
to the enemy (Kivy, 2001: 232, 237). A.C. Grayling has recently made the
point that discerning and appreciating marks of quality in an artistic or cultural
object is not in itself a mark of elitism, Eurocentrism, exclusivity or opposition
to demotic and non-western cultural traditions. Such discernment and appreciation are not the special endowment of any class, or ethnicity, or of either
gender (Grayling, 2002: 5). Marks of quality include fineness of observation,
skill in production, psychological acuity, wit, insight and inventiveness. These
can be found in folk and popular cultures as well as in artistic and literary
canons. Engaging and being engaged by them isnt necessarily equivalent to
cultural snobbery.
We can illustrate this issue further by reference to Adorno, whose critical insight and intellectual acumen we have drawn on elsewhere in the book.
Jrgen Habermas, when recalling his time working in the Frankfurt Institute of
Social Research, remarked: Adorno was a genius; I say that without reservation. This is as unequivocal a statement as could be made. Habermas based it
on the grounds that Adorno had a presence of mind, a spontaneity of
thought, a power of formulation that I have never seen before or since.
Habermas spoke of being unable to grasp the emerging process of Adornos
thoughts; they emerged, as it were, finished. That was his virtuosity. He also
added that it was denied Adorno, in a clearly painful way, ever to be trivial,
and yet his genius did not stand in contradiction to his egalitarian convictions.
By all notable standards, Adorno remained anti-elitist (Habermas, 1992:
1223).
There are a couple of immediate features that make these memories of
Adorno interesting. First, we have one of the most critically regarded sociologists in the recent European tradition invoking the term genius, and in a manner which could be construed as contributing to an Adorno myth did
Adornos thoughts really emerge as any more finished than Beethovens
compositions? This is perhaps a salient example of how a lack of sociological
reflexivity informs discussions of creative exceptionality, coming as it does
Negus-07.qxd
3/27/04 12:30 PM
Page 151
GENIUS
from one of the most astute and challenging of social theorists. A second point
concerns the way that Habermas links Adornos genius to his anti-elitism.
Anyone who is familiar with the way that Adornos work has been caricatured
in some of the more simplistic introductory sociological and cultural studies
textbooks, will know that Adorno has often been lazily labelled as an elitist.
This is a complacent claim which bothers itself with neither the conceptual
problem of exceptionality and elitism for cultural and social theory, nor with
the paradoxes and intricacies of Adornos life and writings. Adorno sometimes
provokes anxiety because there is a certain type of sociological squeamishness
when it comes to this issue, informed as it is by an often unquestioned posture
towards notions of democracy, equality and sociologys own presumed progressive credentials.
An unwillingness to reflect on some of these epistemological presuppositions and how they inform the disciplines of sociology and cultural studies
leads to the kind of sociological argument advanced by DeNora, which seems
either to confuse aesthetic judgement with political analysis or, worse, to collapse aesthetic judgement into political analysis. Whenever these moves occur,
they diminish the scope of the sociological imagination.
Sociology can provide important insights into how ordinary peoples
actions are constrained by historically established patterns, conventions and
limits within which everyday interaction occurs. But it has also to negotiate the
unconventional and at times surprising interpretations of the already established, the movement beyond existing limits. In social studies of art and culture,
such moments are often ignored. In arguing against the notion of genius as
natural endowment and uniqueness incarnate, the inclination of many sociologists is to identify the material conditions and contexts of everyday cultural
practice in which creative processes occur, and the necessarily public forms of
their communicability, including those of cultural markets, through which they
become distributed and known. These may be necessary analytical steps, even
if somewhat predictably conventional, but methodologically they have limits.
Such an approach tells us little about the passionate attachments and reflexive
identifications which people make with art and cultural products, whether
these are painting, dance, or popular music. As one particular branch of social
analysis, the sociology of art has remained largely disengaged from these
attachments and identifications. It has told us everything about art except why
we enjoy it.
It is curious that far more attention has been paid to the pleasures and
gratifications involved in the consumption of popular culture and the media.
The emphasis has invariably been on how these relate to the quotidian and to
the rhythms and textures of everyday life. Yet, inevitably, part of the enjoyment
of creativity involves the identification, and celebration, of exceptionality. We
can witness this in the museum and the gallery, at the rock concert and in the
151
Negus-07.qxd
152
3/27/04 12:30 PM
Page 152
Negus-07.qxd
3/27/04 12:30 PM
Page 153
GENIUS
153
Negus-07.qxd
154
3/27/04 12:30 PM
Page 154
(Sell, 2000: 144). This is why the poetry of Henry Vaughan can still speak,
movingly, to present-day atheists, since the human qualities they find in his
response to circumstance may positively inspire them in their own very different lives (ibid.: 145). Idealisation or mystification can begin at any point in this
conception of the communication of experience, but it is in this conception
that Romanticism provides us with the first fully developed example of the theory of an active audience. The disavowal of an ignorant and fickle public by
various modern writers, artists and composers, and the ascendancy of mass
culture criticism in the early twentieth century, were then part of a long detour
on the road to reactivating the audience whether this involves viewers, readers or listeners of particular cultural forms and seeing them as negotiating
with texts and performances on their own social and individual terms.
Just as the conception of an active audience in contemporary media
and cultural studies arose in reaction to an earlier mechanistic view of the audience in the effects tradition of mass communication research, so the conception of an active reader in Romantic thought arose in reaction to an earlier
mechanistic rationalism, with its attendant empiricist and utilitarian outlook.
Both emerged as correctives, and yet both can lead to an idealised view of
reader/viewer/listener activity in the process of cultural consumption. So, for
instance, Paul Willis (1990) stresses the symbolic creativity of young people in
recoding and transforming the meanings of consumer products in such a way
as not only to underwrite the ideology of consumer sovereignty, but also to
erase the distinction between symbolic value and the social. We may then need
to bend our thinking about the active audience back towards a notion of conditioned frames of improvised action, though we should not do so at the
expense of a creative sense of agency.
A creative and yet conditioned sense of agency is precisely what is
appealing about Eliass conception of sublimation as a process which allows
the mind its autonomous play while accommodating this within a specific
genre or stylistic framework. Here is the interplay between play and convention that helps an artwork or cultural product to achieve communicative value.
Elias refers to this as crossing the bridge of de-privatisation, by which he
means that the imaginative play and daydreaming of the artist are subordinated to the intrinsic regularities of the material, by means of which the
artists feelings and vision can be communicated to others. The painstakingly
acquired creative know-how of the painter, musician or writer is drawn on to
harness the stream of mental play and fantasy to certain devices and conventions while retaining the spirit of inventiveness. In spontaneously fusing
fantasy and framework, imagination and convention, the tensions arising
between them have constantly to be reconciled if artistic or cultural production is to achieve a concrete expressive form to which people can respond.
The resolution of these tensions results in cultural products that combine
Negus-07.qxd
3/27/04 12:30 PM
Page 155
GENIUS
I-relevance with you-, he-, she-, we- and they-relevance (Elias, 1993: 5862).
When this happens, a cultural product attains communicative value, and Elias
summarises its most exceptional moments in the following way:
The pinnacle of artistic creation is achieved when the spontaneity and inventiveness of the fantasy-stream are so fused with knowledge of the regularities of the
material and the judgement of the artists conscience that the innovative fantasies emerge as if by themselves in a way that matches the demands of both
material and conscience. This is one of the most socially fruitful types of sublimation process. (ibid.: 601)
155
Negus-07.qxd
156
3/27/04 12:30 PM
Page 156
Well, that night I was working with Cherokee and, as I did, I found that by using
the higher intervals of the chord as a melody line and backing them with appropriately related changes, I could play the thing Id been hearing. I came alive.
(ibid.: 264)
Negus-07.qxd
3/27/04 12:30 PM
Page 157
GENIUS
this song where it has a quite different form to that which it ultimately came
to have. For example, an earlier version was in waltz-time; the eventual time
signature only came with a later studio take. So work on the song could have
faltered, failing to coalesce in its final landmark form. It could have ended in
these preparatory efforts rather than paving the way to its revolutionary
achievement, even if in retrospect we can see how they helped move Dylan
forward to what he was striving to create, with no (settled or guaranteed) direction home.
The volatility of genius is not only subject to the vagaries of critical
judgement and the contingencies of historical forces and conditions that affect
such judgement. It is also subject to the flawed trials and false starts that are
always involved in the process of creativity. Added to this, those to whom the
label genius has been applied have not always been assured of their own ability to achieve the aims they have set themselves, and have suffered from the
denial of praise or have doubted what George Eliot called the attitudinising
deference which does not fatigue itself with the formation of real judgements
(1994: 55). These remarks closely relate to Eliot herself, yet critically she is
now commonly praised for her literary fiction, especially in Middlemarch,
which has achieved a unique status as both paradigm and paragon in discussion of the novel as a literary form (Lodge, 1981: 218). Felicia Bonaparte, for
example, remarks upon Eliots genius for imagining the inner lives of other
people, arguing that what distinguishes her exceptional talent from other contemporary novelists was the way her insights
were so radically new at the time that they caused a revolution in psychological
analysis and the creation of fictional characterFreud had not yet begun to do
the work that was to make his name but the ideas that were to become the field
we now call psychology were already in the airEliot was not, as some have
maintained, the first to put the action within the consciousness of her characters.
Many writers had done that, long before the Victorian age. The fact, however, that
her narratives keep circling through those subjective states that place us, for a
time at any rate and without corrective lenses, inside her characters point of view,
entitles her to be considered the first true psychological novelist. Eliot was also
one of the first to conceive of her characters in a fluid, modern way as a
process and an unfolding, to quote her own description of it, rather than, as
Dickens was doing, as entities with a solid core that remains in essence the
same. (Bonaparte,1997: xxiixxiii)
157
Negus-07.qxd
158
3/27/04 12:30 PM
Page 158
moments should be understood in the context of the longer span of toil and
struggle which make them possible. While genius may often be narrated in
terms of exceptional moments of often dramatic insight, these are firmly
embedded within an extended process of becoming at one with and synthesising from existing elements.
Negus-07.qxd
3/27/04 12:30 PM
Page 159
GENIUS
159
Negus-07.qxd
160
3/27/04 12:30 PM
Page 160
Negus-07.qxd
3/27/04 12:30 PM
Page 161
GENIUS
in contrast to what is ordinary. Isolating it in this way can lead to the myth
of monumental greatness, conceived in terms that are abstracted from any
sense of changing biographical circumstances, social relationships, economic imperatives, stylistic conventions and historical traditions. We may
say that an artistic product has proved to have lasting value because of these
very particular circumstances, rather than due to the way that it might
simply transcend them. Our feelings are engaged, sympathies awoken, bodies
moved and our taken-for-granted ways of thinking are transformed as they are
stimulated by a specific form, artefact or product from a quite particular time
and place. It is the way this connects with our sense of difference and sameness that allows us to make contrasts and comparisons, weigh up the relations of continuity and change, consider similarities and disparities, and
ultimately allow this creative form a valued place in our lives. It is through
the way that genius emerges out of the ordinary experience of human
endeavour that we can come to a deeper understanding of our changing
world and our changing historical identities.
161
Negus-Bibliography.qxd
3/27/04 12:30 PM
Page 162
Bibliography
Adorno, T. and Horkheimer, M. (1979) Dialectic of Enlightenment. London: Verso.
Adorno, T. (1990) On Popular Music, in S. Frith and A. Goodwin (eds) On Record.
London: Routledge.
Adorno, T. (1991) The Culture Industry: Selected Essays on Mass Culture. Edited
by J. Bernstein, London: Routledge.
Adorno, T. (1994) The Stars Down to Earth. London: Routledge.
Agawu, K. (2003) Contesting Difference, A Critique of Africanist Ethnomusicology in
M. Clayton, T. Herbert and R. Middleton (eds), The Cultural Study of Music.
New York, London: Routledge.
Altman, R. (1999) Film/Genre. London: BFI Publishing.
Amis, M. (2000) Experience. London: Jonathan Cape.
Appadurai, A. (ed.) (1986) The Social Life of Things: Commodities in Cultural
Perspective. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Armstrong, I. (2000) The Radical Aesthetic. Oxford, UK and Malden, MA: Blackwell.
Babcock, B.A. (1993) At Home: No Women are Storytellers: Ceramic Creativity and
the Politics of Discourse in Cochiti Pueblo, in S. Lavie, K. Narayan and R. Rosaldo
(eds) Creativity/Anthropology. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Baily, J. (2001) Can You Stop the Birds Singing: The Censorship of Music in
Afghanistan. Copenhagen: Freemuse.
Barber, L. (1999) Simply Divine, The Observer, 28 February.
Barron, F. (1968) Creativity and Personal Freedom. London: D. Van Nostrand Co.
Baudelaire, C. (1972) Selected Writings on Art and Artists. Harmondsworth:
Penguin.
Beauvoir, S. de (1973) The Prime of Life. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Beck, A. (ed.) (2003) Cultural Work: Understanding the Cultural Industries.
London: Sage.
Becker, H. (1976) Art Worlds and Social Types, American Behavioural Scientist,
19: 70318.
Becker, H. (1984) Art Worlds. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.
Benjamin, W. (1970) Illuminations. London: Jonathan Cape.
Benjamin, W. (1977) Understanding Brecht. London: New Left Books.
Bennett, A. (2000) Popular Music and Youth Culture. Basingstoke and London:
Macmillan.
Bennett, T. (1998) Culture: A Reformers Science. London: Sage.
Bennett, O. (2003) so why has everyone got it in for Charles Saatchi? The
Independent on Sunday, 20 April, pp. 1617.
Benstock, S. (1987) Women of the Left Bank: Paris, 19001940. London: Virago.
Bentham, J. (1962) The Works of Jeremy Bentham, Vol 2. New York: Russell and Russell.
Benzon, W. (2001) Beethovens Anvil: Music in Mind and Culture. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Bernstein, J. (1991) Introduction, in T. Adorno The Culture Industry: Selected
Essays on Mass Culture. Edited by J. Bernstein, London: Routledge.
Negus-Bibliography.qxd
3/27/04 12:30 PM
Page 163
BIBLIOGRAPHY
163
Negus-Bibliography.qxd
164
3/27/04 12:30 PM
Page 164
Cole, C.M. (1996) Reading Blackface in West Africa: Wonders Taken for Signs,
Critical Inquiry, 23, Autumn, pp. 183215.
Coleridge, S. (1910) Biographia Literaria. London: J.M. Dent & Sons.
Connell, J. and Gibson, C. (2003) Sound Tracks: Popular Music, Identity and Place.
London and New York: Routledge.
Cook, R. (2000) The Mediated Manufacture of an Avant Garde: A Bourdieusian
Analysis of the Field of Contemporary Art in London, 19979, in B. Fowler (ed.),
Reading Bourdieu on Society and Culture. Oxford: Blackwell.
Coombe, R. (1998) The Cultural Life of Intellectual Properties. Durham: Duke
University Press.
Cowper, W. (1857) The Poetical Works. London: John Kendrick.
Craik, D. (1850) Olive. Oxford: Oxford Library.
Curran, J. (2000) Literary Editors, Social Networks and Cultural Tradition,
in J. Curran (ed.), Media Organisations in Society, London: Arnold, pp. 21539.
Dash, M. (1989) Introduction, in E. Glissant, Caribbean Discourse: Selected Essays.
Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia.
Davidoff, L. and Hall, C. (1997) Family Fortunes. London and New York: Routledge.
De Bono, E. (1996) Serious Creativity. London: HarperCollins.
DeNora, T. (1997) Beethoven and the Construction of Genius. Berkley: University of
California Press.
Dewey, J. (1925) Experience and Nature. Chicago: Open Court Publishing Company.
Dewey, J. (1980) Art as Experience. New York: Minton, Balch.
Dewey, J. (1938) Logic: The Theory of Inquiry. New York: Henry Holt.
Dick, K. (1972) Writers at Work. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Donnell, A. and Welsh, S. (eds) (1996) Reader in Caribbean Literature. London:
Routledge.
Dreyfus, H.L. (2001) On the Internet. London and New York: Routledge.
Dreyfus, H.L. and Dreyfus, S.E. (1986) Mind Over Machine. Oxford and New York:
Blackwell.
Dyer, C. (2000) Hirst pays up for Hymn that wasnt his, The Guardian, 19 May, p.1.
Ehrlich, C. (1988) Harmonious Alliance: A History of the Performing Right Society.
London: Oxford University Press.
Elias, N. (1993) Mozart: Portrait of a Genius. Cambridge: Polity.
Eliot, G. (1994) Impressions of Theophrastus Such. Iowa: University of Iowa Press.
Eliot, T.S. (1971) The Wasteland: A Facsimile and Transcript of the Original Drafts
including the Annotations of Ezra Pound. London: Faber & Faber.
Emerson, R.W. (1983) Essays and Lectures. New York: The Library of America.
Engel, C. (1866) An Introduction to the Study of National Music. London: Longman.
Ettema, J. and Whitney, D. (1982) Individuals in Mass Media Organisations: Creativity
and Constraint. London: Sage.
Fabbri, F. (1982) A Theory of Music Genres: Two Applications, in P. Tagg and
D. Horn (eds), Popular Music Perspectives. Gothenburg and Exeter: IASPM.
Fabbri, F. (1985) Patterns of Music Consumption in Milan and Reggio Emilia from
April to May 1983, in P. Tagg and D. Horn (eds), Popular Music Perspectives 2.
Gothenberg and Exeter: IASPM.
Fabbri, F. (1989) The System of Canzone in Italy today (1981) in S. Frith (ed.), World
Music, Politics and Social Change. Manchester: Manchester University Press.
Faundez, A. (1989) Learning to Question: A Pedagogy of Liberation. New York:
Continuum.
Negus-Bibliography.qxd
3/27/04 12:30 PM
Page 165
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Filene, B. (2000) Romancing the Folk: Public Memory and American Roots Music.
Chapel Hill and London: University of North Carolina Press.
Finnegan, R. (1997a) Storying the Self: Personal Narratives and Identity, in H. Mackay
(ed.), Consumption and Everyday Life. London: Sage.
Finnegan, R. (1997b) Music, Performance and Enactment, in H. Mackay (ed.),
Consumption and Everyday Life. London: Sage.
Fish, S. (1976) Is there a text in this class? Critical Enquiry, 2 (3): 46586.
Fletcher, W. (1990) Creative People: How to Manage Them and Maximise Their
Creativity. London: Century Hutchinson.
Flyvbjerg, B. (2001) Making Social Science Matter. Cambridge and New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Ford, M. (2002) Trust Yourself: Emerson and Dylan, in N. Corcoran (ed.), Do You,
Mr Jones? Bob Dylan with the Poets and Professors. London: Chatto & Windus.
Fowler, B. (1997) Pierre Bourdieu and Cultural Theory. London: Sage.
Friedman, J. (1996) Cultural Identity and Global Process. London: Sage.
Friedman, J. (2001) The Iron Cage of Creativity, in J. Liep (ed.), Locating Cultural
Creativity. London and Sterling, Virginia: Pluto Press.
Frith, S. (1996) Performing Rites: On the Value of Popular Music. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Frith, S. and Horne, H. (1987) Art into Pop. London and New York: Methuen.
Gadamer, H.-G. (1996) Truth and Method. London: Sheed & Ward.
Gaines, J. (1991) Contested Culture: The Image, the Voice and the Law. Chapel Hill:
University of North Carolina Press.
Galeotti, E.A. (1987) Individualism, Social Rules, Tradition: The Case of Friedrich A.
Hayek, Political Theory, 15 (2): 16381.
Galton, F. (1869) Hereditary Genius. London: Macmillan.
Garca Canclini, N. (1995) Hybrid Cultures. Minneapolis and London: University of
Minneapolis Press.
Garca Mrquez, G. and Apuleyo Mendoza, P. (1988) The Fragrance of Guava.
London and Boston: Faber & Faber.
Garnham, N. (1990) Capitalism and Communication: Global Culture and the
Economics of Information. London: Sage.
Geiger, G.R. (1974) John Dewey in Perspective. Westport, CT: Greenwood Press.
George, N. (1989) The Death of Rhythm and Blues. New York: Omnibus.
George, N. (1998) Hip Hop America. New York: Penguin.
Geraghty, C. (1991) Women and Soap Opera. Oxford: Polity Press.
Giddins, G. (1998) Visions of Jazz. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Giddins, G. (2000) Riding on a Blue Note, Jazz and American Pop. New York:
Da Capo Press.
Giddins, G. (2001) Satchmo: The Genius of Louis Armstrong. New York: Da Capo
Press.
Gilbert, S.M. and Gubar, S. (1984) The Madwoman in the Attic: The Woman Writer
and the Nineteenth Century Literary Imagination. New Haven and London: Yale
University Press.
Gilman, S. (1988) Difference and Pathology. Ithaca and London: Cornell University
Press.
Gilman, S. (1991) The Jews Body. New York and London: Routledge.
Glad, J. (ed.) (1990) Literature in Exile. Durham and London: Duke University Press.
Glissant, E. (1989) Caribbean Discourse. Virginia: University Press of Virginia.
165
Negus-Bibliography.qxd
166
3/27/04 12:30 PM
Page 166
Gombrich, E.H. (1967) The Story of Art. London and New York: Phaidon.
Goodman, N. (1968) Languages of Art. London: Oxford University Press.
Gracyk, T. (2002) Musics Wordly Uses, or How I Learned to Stop Worrying and To
Love Led Zeppelin, in A. Neill and A. Ridley (eds), Arguing about Art. London and
New York: Routledge.
Grana, C. (1964) Bohemian versus Bourgeois: French Society and the French Man
of Letters in the Nineteenth Century. New York: Basic Books.
Gray, J. (1984) Hayek on Liberty. Oxford and New York: Basil Blackwell.
Grayling, A.C. (2002) A Question of Discrimination, Guardian Review, 13 July,
pp. 46.
Griffiths, G. (1978) Double Exile: African and West Indian Writing Between Two
Cultures. London: Marim Boyars.
Griswold, W. (1987) The Fabrication of Meaning: Literary Interpretation in the United
States, Great Britain, and the West Indies, American Journal of Sociology, 92 (5):
1077117.
Habermas, J. (1984) The Theory of Communicative Action, Vol 1: Reason and the
Rationalisation of Society. Boston: Beacon Press.
Habermas, J. (1992) A Generation Apart from Adorno: An Interview, Philosophy
and Social Criticism, 18 (2): 11924.
Hall, C. (1981) Gender Divisions and Class Formation in the Birmingham Middle
Class, 17801850, in R. Samuel (ed.), Peoples History and Socialist Theory.
London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Halstead, J. (1997) The Woman Composer. Aldershot: Ashgate.
Hannerz, U. (1996) Transnational Connections. London and New York: Routledge.
Hanson, A. (1989) The Making of the Maori: Culture Invention and its Logic,
American Anthropologist, 91, pp. 890902.
Hardy, T. (1929) Jude the Obscure. London: Macmillan.
Hardy, T. (1967) Thomas Hardys Personal Writings. Edited by H. Orel. London and
Melbourne: Macmillan.
Harrison, C. and Wood, P. (eds.) (2001) Art in Theory, 19001990. Oxford and
Malden, MA: Blackwell.
Hasse, J. (1995) Beyond Category: The Life and Genius of Duke Ellington.
New York: Da Capo.
Hatton, R. and Walker, J. (2000) Supercollector, A Critique of Charles Saatchi.
London: Ellipsis.
Hayek, F. (1949) Individualism and Economic Order. London: Routledge.
Hayek, F. (1992) The Fatal Conceit. London: Routledge.
Hayes, M. (1990) Are You Telling Me Lies David? The Work of John le Carr, in
C. Bloom (ed.), Spy Thrillers, From Buchan to le Carr. Basingstoke: Macmillan.
pp. 113129.
Heelas, P., Lash, P. and Morris, P. (1996) Detraditionalization. Cambridge, MA. and
Oxford, UK: Blackwell.
Hegel, G.F.W. (1975) Aesthetics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hesmondhalgh, D. (2002) The Cultural Industries. London: Sage.
Hobsbawm, E. (1961) The Jazz Scene. Harmondsworth: Penguin [published under the
pseudonym of Francis Newton].
Hobsbawm, E. (1997) Nations and Nationalism since 1780. Cambridge and
New York: Cambridge University Press.
Negus-Bibliography.qxd
3/27/04 12:30 PM
Page 167
BIBLIOGRAPHY
167
Negus-Bibliography.qxd
168
3/27/04 12:30 PM
Page 168
Negus-Bibliography.qxd
3/27/04 12:30 PM
Page 169
BIBLIOGRAPHY
169
Negus-Bibliography.qxd
170
3/27/04 12:30 PM
Page 170
Reich, N.B. (1985) Clara Schumann: The Artist and the Woman. Ithaca and London:
Cornell University Press.
Richie, D. (1971) Japanese Cinema. New York: Doubleday.
Ritter, N. (1989) Art as Spectacle: Images of the Entertainer since Romanticism.
Columbia and London: University of Missouri Press.
Roberts, D. (1994) Sublime Theories: Reason and Imagination in Modernity, in
G. Robinson and J. Rundell (eds), Rethinking Imagination: Culture and Creativity.
London and New York: Routledge.
Romn Velzquez, P. (1999) The Making of Latin London: Salsa Music, Place and
Identity. Aldershot: Ashgate.
Rorty, R. (1989) Contingency, Irony and Solidarity. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Rose, J. (2001) The Intellectual Life of the British Working Class. New Haven and
London: Yale University Press.
Rushdie, S. (1991) Imaginary Homelands. London: Granta.
Rushdie, S. (2003) Divided Selves, The Guardian Review, 23 November, pp. 57.
Ruskin, J. (1907) Sesame and Lilies. London: George Allen.
Ryan, M. (1998) Knowledge Diplomacy: Global Competition and the Politics of
Intellectual Property. Washington DC: Brookings Institute.
Ryan, L. (2002) Gender, Identity and the Irish Press, 19221937. Lewiston,
Queenston, Lampeter: The Edwin Mellen Press.
Sahlins, M. (1985) Islands of History. Chicago: Chicago University Press.
Sahlins, M. (2002) Waiting for Foucault, Still. Chicago: Prickly Paradigm Press.
Said, E. (1983) The World, the Text, and the Critic. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Said, E. (1984) Reflections on Exile, Granta, 13, Autumn, pp. 15772.
Said, E. (1991) Musical Elaborations. London: Chatto and Windus.
Said, E. (1994) Culture and Imperialism. London: Vintage.
Saunders, D. (1992) Authorship and Copyright. London: Routledge.
Scruton, R. (1983) The Aesthetic Understanding. Manchester: Carcanet Press.
Scruton, R. (2002) The Decline of Musical Culture, in A. Neill and A. Ridley (eds),
Arguing about Art. London and New York: Routledge.
Scruton, R. (ed.) (1991) Conservative Texts. Basingstoke and New York: Macmillan.
Seed, J. (1988) Commerce and the Liberal Arts: The Political Economy of Art in
Manchester, 17751860, in J. Wolff and J. Seed (eds) The Culture of Capital: Art,
Power and the Nineteenth Century Middle Class. Manchester: Manchester University
Press.
Sell, R. (2000) Literature as Communication. Amsterdam and Philadelphia: John
Benjamins Publishing Company.
Sereny, G. (1999) Cries Unheard: The Story of Mary Bell. Basingstoke and London:
Macmillan.
Sharp, C. (1907) English Folk Song: Some Conclusions. London: Simpkin.
Shils, E. (1981) Tradition. London and Boston: Faber & Faber.
Sinfield, A. (1989) Literature, Politics and Culture in Postwar Britain. Oxford:
Blackwell.
Steiner, G. (2001) Grammars of Creation. London: Faber and Faber.
Taylor, C. (1985) Human Agency and Language: Philosophical Papers I. Cambridge,
London and New York: Cambridge University Press.
Negus-Bibliography.qxd
3/27/04 12:30 PM
Page 171
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Taylor, C. (1989) Sources of the Self: The Making of Modern Identity. Cambridge
and New York: Cambridge University Press.
Taylor, C. (1991) The Ethics of Authenticity. Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard
University Press.
Taylor, C. (1995) Philosophical Arguments. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Thomas, N. (1997) In Oceania. Durham and London: Duke University Press.
Thompson, E.P. (1977) William Morris: Romantic to Revolutionary. London: Merlin
Press.
Tirro, F. (1993) Jazz: A History. New York and London: W.W. Norton.
Todorov, T. (1990) Genres in Discourse. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Tolson, A. (1996) Mediations. London and New York: Arnold.
Tremlett, G. (1990) Rock Gold: The Music Millionaires. Unwin Hyman.
Troutt Powell, E.M. (2003) A Different Shade of Colonialism. Berkeley, Los Angeles,
London: University of California Press.
Ulanov, B. (1952) A History of Jazz in America. New York: Viking Press.
UNESCO (1982) Culture Industries: A Challenge for the Future of Culture. Paris:
UNESCO.
Viereck, S. (1929) What Life Means to Einstein: An Interview with Sylvester Viereck,
The Saturday Evening Post, 26 October.
Vladislav, J. (1990) Exile, Responsibility, Destiny, in J. Glad (ed.), Literature in Exile.
Durham and London: Duke University Press, pp. 1427.
Wainwright, H. (1994) Arguments for a New Left. Oxford UK and Cambridge USA:
Blackwell.
Walcott, D. (1998) What the Twilight Says. London: Faber and Faber.
Walmsley, A. (1992) The Caribbean Artists Movement 19661972. London:
New Beacon Books.
Ward, A. (1875) A History of English Dramatic Literature, 3 volumes. London:
Macmillan.
Warner, K.Q. (1992) Film, Literature and Identity in the Caribbean, in M.B. Cham
(ed.), Ex-Iles: Essays on Caribbean Cinema. Trenton, New Jersey: Africa World
Press Inc.
Warnke, G. (1995) Communicative Rationality and Cultural Values, in S.K. White
(ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Habermas. Cambridge and New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Waters, J. (1988) Deus ex Machina: The Band Who Grew to Earth, in E. Dunphy (ed.)
The Unforgettable Fire: The Story of U2. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Whitman, W. (1982) Slang in America, in his Complete Poetry and Collected Prose.
Edited by J. Kaplan. New York: Library of America.
Williams, P. (1993) The Alchemy of Race and Rights. London: Virago.
Williams, R. (1961) The Long Revolution. Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Williams, R. (1976) Keywords. Glasgow: Fontana.
Williams, R. (1977) Marxism and Literature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Williams, R. (1979) Politics and Letters. London: New Left Books.
Williams, R. (1989) Resources of Hope. London and New York: Verso.
Willis, P. (1990) Common Culture. Milton Keynes: Open University Press.
Wilson, E. (2000) Bohemians: The Glamorous Outcasts. London and New York:
I.B. Tauris.
Wolff, J. (1981) The Social Production of Art. London and Basingstoke: Macmillan.
171
Negus-Bibliography.qxd
172
3/27/04 12:30 PM
Page 172
Negus-Index.qxd
3/27/04 12:31 PM
Page 173
Index
Addison, J. 1456
Adorno, T. 8, 4951, 55, 66, 745,
81, 113, 1501
advertising 11, 15, 467, 50, 121
Agawu, K. 114
agency 13, 26, 68
Allen, W. 112
Altman, R. 734
Amis, M. 47
Anderson, B. 78
Armstrong, I. 41
Armstrong, L. 80, 127, 1434
Aristotle 6, 141, 145
art world 18, 78, 7982, 85, 89
Ashbery, J. 25
auteurism 567
authenticity ix, 34, 11, 72, 107,
10910, 114, 127, 134
Bach, J. S. 146, 158
Baldwin, J. 131
Barnes, J. 83
Barthes, R. 79
Bashkirtseff, M. 123
Baudelaire, C. 3
Bauer-Lechner, N. 38
BBC, the 132
Beatles 57, 65
Beck, U. 99
Becker, H. 18, 7886, 89, 148, 152
Beerbohm, M. 159
Beethoven, L. van, 113, 14650
Beiderbecke, B. 127
Bell, M. 36
Benjamin, W. 49, 55, 66
Bentham, J. 13
Benzon, W. 30
Bernstein, W. 49, 55, 66
Bettig, R. 623
Bibb, E. 101
Bloom, H. 123
Blues 1001, 103, 106
Book publishing 55, 59, 7980, 12935
Bonaparte, F. 157
Bowie, D. 47
Bowland, E. 35
Negus-Index.qxd
174
3/27/04 12:31 PM
Page 174
French, P. 112
French Revolution 92, 100
Freud, S. 141, 157
Friedman, J. 109
Frith, S. 478, 76
Gadamer, H.-G. 110
Gaines, J. 645, 667
Galeotti, A.E. 97
Galton, F. 140
Garca Canclini, N. 12
Garca Mrquez, G. 39, 145
Garnham, N. 51
Gauguin, P. 136
Geiger, G.R. 42
gender viii, 2, 35, 51, 54, 115,
11824, 129, 1356, 138, 1424, 150
generations 35
genius viii, 82, 112, 123, 13861
genre 1314, 34, 43, 69, 708, 834,
101, 112, 120, 133, 139, 144
George, N. 129
Geraghty, C. 74
Gerard, A. 140
Gibson, C. 110
Giddens, A. 99
Giddins, G. 80, 127, 1434, 155
Glissant, E. 39
Goethe, J.W. von 1401
Goodman, N. 41
Grayling, A.C. 150
Gregory, Lady 35
Griswold, W. 134
Groening, M. 65
Habermas, J. 1501
Hannerz, U. 53, 78
Hanson, A. 107
Hardy, T. 31, 39, 117
Harlem Renaissance 26
Harris, C. 101
Hatton, R. 88
Hawking, S. 88
Hawkins, C. 156
Haydn, F.J. 120
Hayek, F. 912, 959
Hegel, G.W.F. 9, 112, 147
Hensel, F. 123
Herder, J.G. 9, 140
Hikmet, N. 131
Hicks, G. 122
Himes, C. 131
Hirst, D. 65, 878
Hitchcock, A. 56
Negus-Index.qxd
3/27/04 12:31 PM
Page 175
INDEX
Le Carr, J. 84
Lennon, J. 3, 6
Leno, D. 159
Lewis, S. 47
Ligeti, G. 85
Li Po and Tu Fu 95
Lippard, L. 124
Lish, G. 80
local 6, 3940, 137, 159
Lodge, D. 157
Lombroso, C. 141
MacIntyre, A. 33, 98
Mahler, G. 389
Mandelstam, O. 131
Mardi Gras 114
Marx, K. 8, 55
Maori 107
Marsalis, W. 155
mass culture 10, 49, 66, 107
Max, D.T. 80
McClary, S. 68, 90, 101
McEwan, I. 312, 83
McRobbie, A. 51
memory 104, 106, 110
Merleau-Ponty, M. 25
Michelangelo 1412
Mige, B. 50, 51
Mill, J.S. 119
Miro, V. 88
Mittelhozer, E. 132
modernism 756, 90, 100, 103, 1067,
109, 125, 127, 132, 136
modernity 4, 89, 12, 33, 42, 92,
98100, 102, 104, 110
Morris, W. 5, 8
Morrison, B. 36
Mozart, W.A. 40, 47, 114, 120, 1523
Munif, A. 132, 134
music industry 5455, 59
Murray, A 101
Nabokov, V. 131
Naipaul, V.S. 1302
Narayan, R.K. 38
Nashville 73
nationalism 35, 38, 1057
Nature 24, 78
Neale, S. 71, 77
Nettleford, R. 133
Nixon, R. 1312
Nixon, S. 121
Novalis 2
novels 834, 12937
175
Negus-Index.qxd
176
3/27/04 12:31 PM
Page 176
Negus-Index.qxd
3/27/04 12:31 PM
Page 177
INDEX
Waters, E. 127
Weldon, F. 47
Welles, O. 57
Wells, H.G. 47
Westlake, M. 56
Wharton, E. 122
Whiteread, R. 878
Whitman, W. 2729
Whitney, C. 47
Williams, B. 136
Williams, R. 6, 234, 379, 52, 69
Willis, P. 154
Wilson, C. 103
Wolff, J. 152
Wollstonecraft, M. 119
Wordsworth, W. 3, 93, 125
Wright, R. 131
Wu Tang Clan 111
Yeats, W.B. 3, 5, 35
Young, E. 140
Zola, E. 6
177