Conant - Varieties of Skepticism
Conant - Varieties of Skepticism
Conant - Varieties of Skepticism
VARIETIES OF SCEPTICISM
James Conant
97
JAMES CONANT
98
VARIETIES OF SCEPTICISM
:i
JAMES CONANT
thoughts are true, which of his experiences are veridical. The Cartesian
sceptic therefore worries about the transition from a sensory experience
to a judgement, from a thought to (what Frege calls) its truth-value.
Hence the Cartesian problematic inquires into the grounds of truth:
given that this is what we are inclined to judge, do we know that we
judge truthfully in so judging? The Kantian sceptic seems to deprive
us of the resources for so much as being able to enjoy an experience
(waking or dreaming), for so much as being able to frame a thought
(true or false). The Kantian problematic inquires into the grounds of
the possibility of being able to enjoy an experience, entertain a thoughtcontent. The Kantian asks: what does it take to have thoughts that are
vulnerable to how things are? The Kantian problematic is concerned, in
the first instance, not with truth but with what it is to stick your neck
out in thinking, with what Kant calls the objective validity of judgement
(the possibility of something's being a candidate for truth or falsehood)
-with what I will henceforth call the objective purport of judgement.
I will briefly indicate here a few of the guises in which Cartesian and
Kantian problematics surface across a number of (supposedly distinct)
'areas' of philosophy:
Philosophy of perception. This is the most classic instance of each of
these varieties of sceptical problematic. The Cartesian sceptic asks: how
can I know things are as my senses present them as being? Is there really
an external world? I am having an experience of a certain sort (say, that
I am here in my dressing-gown, sitting by the fire) but how can I know
that things are as my experience presents them as being? The case
under consideration is a best case of knowledge, 6 and yet there still seems
to be room for the question: how can I know that I am not, in fact, lying
undressed in my bed dreaming that I am here in my dressing-gown,
sitting by the fire? The Cartesian paradox thus takes the following
form: if I don't know this, then how can I be said to know anything? Why
should I ever trust the testimony of my senses? Should I ever endorse the
appearances with which my senses present me? The gap the Cartesian
seeks to bridge is from his own mind to the outer world. The paradox
lies in our apparent inability to answer the following question: how can
I penetrate the veil of sensory ideas and attain a view of what is really
happening outside of my mind? The Kantian sceptic is preoccupied by
different questions: how can my senses so much as presrnl things as being
a certain way? How can my ~xperience so much as be intelligibly of an
external world? The Kant ian problematic is fon1sed on the probkm how
the st:nscs must be so as to able to fun1ish testimouy. 'Vhat sort of unity
IllUSt experience possess in order to be able to prf'sent an appearance
about which the question could arise 'Shall I endorse it'? How am I
100
VARIETIES OF SCEPTICISM
.JA:'vfES CO:\'ANT
!02
VARIETIES OF SCEPTICISM
103
JAMES CONANT
VARIETIES OF SCEPTICISM
JAMES CONANT
variant of, say, Cartesian scepticism will exhibit all nine of the mentioned
features. It is an idealisation because most philosophical discussions that
exhibit any one of the features (drawn from one of the two above lists offeatures) will not necessarily exhibit all of them (though it will probably exhibit
many of them). Thus, it should be understood that, henceforth, when I speak
of 'a Cartesian problematic', for example, I will mean a philosophical discussion that exhibits at least a large number of the Cartesian features specified
below, but not necessarily all of them. 1
The second dimension of idealisation concerns the way in which the
presentation of these feature-spaces may appear to preclude the possibility
of their overlap - to preclude an intermingling of Cartesian and Kantian
features within a single philosophical problematic. That is both a desirable
and a potentially misleading aspect of the presentation that follows. It is
desirable in as much as it is part of my aim to illuminate something about
the internal structure of each of these two (admittedly idealised) varieties
of philosophical problematic. Each has its own logic. The co-occurrence of
such features within a single philosophical discussion is generally (though
not necessarily 12) a symptom of philosophical confusion on the part of an
author; and it is part of my purpose to facilitate the diagnosis and treatment
of such forms of confusion. Nevertheless, it is potentially misleading because
- even if, in a resolutely executed philosophical enquiry, Cartesian and
Kantian features will tend to drive one another out -in the irresoluteness of
actual philosophical practice, such features can often be found squashed up
against one another. Borrowing some terms from Cavell's theory of genre 1\
one might say that Kantian scepticism represents an adjacent genre of scepticism- one in which each of the features of Cartesian scepticism is displaced 14
in a certain way. And, just as different genres of film (say, a western and a
romantic comedy) can be crossed with another- often (though not always)
with aesthetically jarring results - so, too, these genres of scepticism can
be crossed with another. In philosophy, when this happens, usually (though
not always) it is a sign that the author is no longer clear which of these two
philosophical problematics he wishes to inhabit.
The third dimension of idealisation concerns the presentation of each of
the features as apparently distinct from at least most of the other eight. One
reason for thus presenting them has already been indicated: If one reviews
actual philosophical discussions some of these features will feature explicitly
while others will not. So, by provisionally treating the features in question
as apparently distinct, we equip ourselves with a classificatory scheme that
can be applied more widely. Yet this raises a number of questions about how
we are to understand the philosophical discussions we are thus classifying:
are these features all really (as opposed to merely notationally) distinct?
And even where distinct, how independent are thf"y? Is it perhaps the case
that' any philosophical discussion that explicitly bears some of them must
106
VARIETIES OF SCEPTICISM
Cartesian genre
With these cautionary remarks to be borne in mind, I will henceforth refer
to the following nine generic features of the Cartesian genre of scepticism
as Cartesian.features:
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
First feature
To say that an exploration of the Cartesian problematic begins always with
'a best case of knowledge' is to say that it begins always with a carefully
selected example- one that possesses (or at least appears able simultaneously
to possess) at least the following four characteristics. First, the example
must involve a concrete claim to know: a particular person, at a particular time
and place must enter the claim. Second, the claim in question must be able
to serve as an exemplar of an entire class of claims: it must be sufficiently
representative so th;1t each of us can rehearse a version of such a claim in the
privacy of our own epistemological closet. Third, the claim must be directed
at an unremarkable object - the sort of o~ject which requires no special sort of
expertise in order to be able to tell one when you see one. Thus (what one
might be tempted to call) 'a kind of object' figur~s in Cartesian rxamples
- a hand, a tomato, an envelope, a chair (but ne\"er a nine i1on, an l'vi-16
rifte, ajapanese beetle, a goldfitiCh or a bubble chamber). One must begin
107
JAMEi-1
CO~A:"'T
with the .-ight sort of example, in order to get the Cartesian problematic up
and running. 11 Fourth, the object must be encountered under optimal conditions: in good lighting, at short range, for an extended period of time, etc.
An important part of exploring the Cartesian problematic lies in exploring
the character and the legitimacy of the examples employed to introduce a
Cartesian sceptical recital and ascertaining whether they really do simultaneously possess all four of the required characteristics. A preoccupation with
~uch examples is a hallmark of the Cartesian problematic.
Secondfeature
The Cartesian paradox results from the susceptibility of the existence of
such an object to doubt. The Cartesian investigation initiates an enquiry into
the question what (in our experience of the relevant phenomenon) does and
does not admit of the possibility of doubt. It thereby seeks to decompose our
experience into two sorts of elements: those which are inherently indubitable
and those which involve some (even if perhaps minimal) element of risk. The
viability of the ensuing doubt lies in the disclosure of a reliance (on the part
of the candidate claim to knowledge) upon those strata of our experience involving this identifiable element of risk. Under the pressure of the Cartesian
investigator's demand for certainty; we are led to the discovery that very little
in our experience is invulnerable to such forms of doubt.
Thirdfeature
108
VARIETIES OF SCEPTICISM
Fourth .ftature
The possibility of such a doubt seems to yield a discovery. The sceptical
discovery takes the form of seeing through the surface of our practices to how
they really are. For the results of the Cartesian investigation seem to stand
in sharp conflict with our ordinary ways of talking and living. Our practices
of entering knowledge claims seem to be fundamentally at odds with what it
is that the investigation shows we are really entitled to claim. So, even if the
Cartesian inquirer finds himself unable to do other than to continue to speak
with the vulgar and to participate in ordinary ways of speaking and acting,
nonetheless, in the light of his discovery, these practices must now seem to
him to be unmasked as resting upon a tissue of illusion. To the extent that
the Cartesian acquiesces in the conclusion his investigation seems to force
upon him, he thereby takes himself to be able to see more clearly and deeply
into the true nature of these practices than the majority of his fellows who
unreflectively participate in them.
Fiflhfiature
The initial thrill of discovery gives way to a mood of disappointment with
knowledge. There no longer seems to any way for the sort of knowledge in
question to live up to its name. And this gives rise to a mood of disillusionment. One takes oneself to have an understanding of what would have had
to have been the case for this sort of knowledge to have been possible. But
it transpires that, at least for beings such as ourselves, that possibility is not
attainable. One is thus left with the feeling that there is something that
ought to have been possible but which, as it happens, turns out, at least for
us, not to be possible. (The mood of Cartesian scepticism is that of the heroes
of Shakespeare's tragedies: one of disappointment at being fated to live in a
world that will necessarily betray one's trust in it. 1") Such a prevailing mood
of disappointment or disillusionment as the apparently inescapable response
to philosophical enquiry is symptomatic of entanglement in a variant of the
Cartesian problematic.
Sixth feature
The disappointment lies in our not being actually able to do something that
we had always taken to be possible (we are unable to know that things are as
they appear). The world we had pre-reflectively taken ourselves to inhabit
-a world in which we were capable of attaining knowledge of a certain sort
- threatens to turn out not to be the world we actually inhabit. We can
formulate thoughts about what such a world would be like and can perhaps
still enjoy experiences that purport to be of such a world, but we now are
no longer able in our reflective moments to endorse the contents of such
thoughts and experiences.
109
.JAMES CONANT
Seventhftature
The structure of the situation we inhabit therefore now seems to come
into view as one in which we cannot do something we want to be (and prereflectively thought of ourselves as fully) able to do. The sceptical discovery
seems to disclose a limit to our cognitive abilities- a limit that kicks in at a
far earlier point in the cognitive process than we, prior to our philosophical
investigation, had any reason to expect, a limit that we cannot penetrate or
circumvent, try as we might.
Eighth ftature
This inability is taken to be a function of our inability to bridge a certain sort
of gap. In the case of philosophy of perception, the gap looms between my
inner life and the outer world; in the case of other minds, it opens up between
his outer behaviour and his inner life, etc. The Cartesian takes himself to
have made a genuine discovery in having disclosed the existence of such a
gap. Cartesian strategies for finding a way around the Cartesian paradox
involve attempts to find a way to live with this gap. The Cartesian who wants
to avoid a sceptical conclusion wants to be able to negotiate his way across
the gap. (Descartes himself famously looked to God for some assistance in
this matter.) But the gap itself is one he still takes to be just there. As long
as one operates within the confines of the Cartesian problematic, the only
possible form of 'solution' to the problem of scepticism lies in attempting to
construct some such sort of bridge across the gap. I will call the sort of gap at
issue here 'a Cartesian gap'.
Ninth .feature
The Cartesian inquirer will wish to distinguish theoretical doubt from practical
doubt. His doubt, he will tell us, is a merely theoretical one. Though, as such,
it represents, he will insist, a perfectly intelligible outcome to an intellectual
enquiry; nevertheless, he will also insist, conviction in such a conclusion cannot be sustained by someone caught up in the midst of a practical situation.
Cartesian sceptical doubt thus possesses an inherent instability due to the
impossibility of its realisation in practice. 17 Indeed, we are often reassured by
philosophers who wish to introduce us to this problematic that the Cartesian
enquiry is one that can and should be suspended for practical purposes. 18
Such reassurances presuppose the standing possibility of practically abstaining from one's sceptical surmise andre-embracing the modes of experience,
thought and expression thereby brought into question. Such an insistence
upon the purely theoretical character of the generality of the form of doubt
that is at issue in philosophical enquiry is a hallmark of the Cartesian problematic.19
HO
VARIETIES OF SCEPTICISM
Kantian genre
Kantian scepticism does not quite share any of the above nine generic features. The Kantian genre of scepticism exhibits instead the following nine
Kantian features - each of which involves a peculiar displacement or reversal
or inversion of the corresponding Cartesian feature:
2
3
4
5
6
8
9
First ftature
To say that it is constitutive of the Kant ian problematic that it is characterised by the absence qf a special category qf example is to say no more or less than
what Kant means to say when he says that transcendental logic, though it
does not abstract entirely from objects, is concerned only with the conditions
of the possibility of the pure thought of an object: with what it is for thought
to be able so much as to be able to have a bearing on the world, what it is for
our thought to be related to objects uberhaupt. Transcendental logic must abstract from all differences between objects- from what it is to be cognitively
related to this rather than that sort of object- but not from relatedness to
an object as such. The two sides of the Kantian problematic, in its classical
formulation, turn on how sensibility can yield deliverances that are of objects
and how thought can be directed at a (mind-independent) world. The problematic that unfolds here homogenises the field of possible examples. The
questions 'What it is to dream that I am in front of a fireplace?' and 'What is
Hl
JAMES CONANT
Second feature
Under the pressure of the Kantian question, all our cognitive capacities (the
capacity to doubt among them) come to seem equally questionable. Having
worked his way far into a particular philosophical dialectic, the Kantian sceptic comes to an impasse: it suddenly no longer seems to him possible that one
should be able so much as to frame thoughts that are about the world (or to
experience another's bodily movements as expressions of emotion, or to traffic in forms of words that are replete with meaning, etc.). This sort of sceptic
becomes perplexed as to what it is to be experiencing or thinking or meaning
things in ways that he also cannot help but take himself to be doing in and
through the very act of asking his sceptical question. To move in the direction
in which his question leads is apparently to deprive his question (along with
the whole of the rest of his 'thought') of the capacity to possess determinate
content. And yet he is unable to dismiss his question. It has come to seem
intellectually compulsory. So his mind boggles. Such a boggling of the mind, in
the face of a looming conclusion that can neither be approached nor avoided
- neither fully comprehended nor simply dismissed on the grounds of its
incomprehensibility- is a mark of entanglement in a variant of the Kantian
problematic.
Third feature
What is at issue in the Kantian problematic is the possibility of making
claims in general, not knowledge claims in particular. This means that the
point of departure for a Kantian inn,stigation is not a particular case of
knowledge, but rather the topic of the vulnerability of our thought to reality.
This in a certain sense, reverses the direction of the Cartesian investigation:
The 'Kantian paradox is not the result of moving from a conclusion about
the character of our experience of a particular case to a general conclusion
112
VARIETIES OF SCEPTICISM
about all objects of experience, but rather a result of inability to see how
there could so much as be an experience which purports to be qf a particular.
To respond to the Kantian sceptic is to show how our thinking can have a
sort of dependence on the world that allows our activity of making claims
to come intelligibly into view as one of claim-making at all. In the absence
of an adequate response here, the world threatens to recede from our grasp
- to the point where not only do we have reason to fear, with the Cartesian
sceptic, that we are unable to know which of our claims about it are true, but
rather- to the point where we cannot any longer even make sense of the idea
that we are able to enter claims about anything of a sufficiently determinate
character to be either true or false. This sense of the fading away of the
possibility of determinate empirical content in our thought, experience and
discourse is a mark of entanglement in the Kantian problematic.
Fourth fiature
We can only discover that which we can think. The Cartesian investigation
can issue in a discovery, because the Cartesian takes himself to be able to
form a stable conception of that which he discovers we do not have. The
Kant ian paradox takes the form not of a discovery, but of a mystery. In each of
the three variants of Kant ian scepticism briefly sketched above, the Kant ian
paradox is one in which the possibility of a sort of appearance usually taken
for granted in the corresponding variant of Cartesian scepticism suddenly
comes to seem mysterious: how what impinges on my senses could so much
as appear to be revelatory of the world; how the inert fleshy matter comprising someone's body could so much as appear to be revelatory of his inner
life; and how a mere sequence of dead signs could so much as appear to be
alive with significance. Our ordinary cognitive capacities appear intolerably
mysterious now and therefore seem to call for a philosophical project that
\\-i.ll relieve our discomfort by providing an account of these capacities that
drains them of their mystery. 21
Fifth feature
If such a Kantian imestigation (into the very possibility of our being able to
frame thoughts, enjoy experiences, express meanings, etc.) ends in sceptical
paradox, the resulting mood is not one of disappointment - for disappointment (like discovery) is possible only \vhere some glimmering of what it is
that one wants (but cannot have) is also available to one. Kant says (concerning what he calls) scepticism, that it is a 'way of thinking, in which reason
moves against itself with such violence, that it could never ha,-e ari.;en except
in volliger Ver.;:weifiung of achieving satisfaction with re10pect to reason's most
important aspirations' (Kant 1977 (1783): 19). The violence with which here,
in what K11nt calls scepticism, reasen turns against itself is a violence ef the
113
JAMES CONANT
most extreme possible sort. What reason questions is itself. Our faculty for
rational thought arrives at the point where it asks itself (not just how this or
that cognitive capacity is possible, but) how it itself is possible, questioning
the possibility of the exercise of the very capacity exercised in the framing
of such a question. This question is one that reason would be driven to pose
only if it found itself in a state of volliger Verzweiflung- complete desperation
or despair- we might say: despair born of desperation. (The mood ofKantian
scepticism is that of the heroes of Kafka's parables: one of bewilderment at
the dissolution of the world's conditions of intelligibility.22 )
Sixth feature
When reason thus questions its own possibility, the natural history of reason
enters a new and radical stage - a sceptical paradox of a different order
from the Cartesian is broached. The problem is no longer to understand how
something we took to be possible can be actual. The problem is now one that
threatens the entire array of cognitive capacities which the Cartesian sceptic
takes to be unproblematically available: the capacities to doubt and dream,
to feel and think and believe, to enjoy sensory impressions of fireplaces and
frame hypotheses about evil demons. The problem now is to understand how
something that we take to be actual - for example, the exercise of those
cognitive capacities evidently actualised in our philosophical reflections
(reflections that themselves seek to address the question of the possibility of
such capacities)- can be possibleY
Seventh Jeature
This collapse of the space of possibilities leaves it looking not - as in the
Cartesian case - as if there is something we cannot do. Now it looks as if
there is nothing to do (not even to dream) where we had previously thought
there must be something. The Kantian sceptical discovery, rather than
disclosing a boundary which our cognitive abilities run up against, seems to
deprive us of any territory through which such a boundary might be able to
run. This sense that, in our philosophical enquiry, we have found a way to
make the Cartesian limit disintegrate (though at the possible cost of ceasing
to be able to make sense of our lives) is symptomatic of entanglement in the
Kantian problematic.
Eighth Jeature
The Cartesian takes himself to run up against a gap in his philosophising
{a gap between mind and world, between the body of th_c oth~r and hi~ soul,
between interpretation and meaning, etc.). He takes h_nnsdf to have made
a genuine discovery in having disdo~ed the existeue<~ ol such a gap. The gap
114
VARIETIES OF SCEPTICISM
itself is just there. The Kantian also seems to encounter a certain sort of gap
in his philosophising (between sensory blindness and sensory consciousness,
between an inexpressive expanse of mere flesh and the animated field of
an expressive human body, between meaningless sequences of marks and
noises and determinately meaningful expressions of thought, etc.). But it is
not clear what it would be to acquiesce in the existence of his gap. It must
already be bridged (as evidenced by his present ability to exercise his capacities for perception, expression, and thought); and yet, as long as the threat
of Kantian paradox has yet to be averted, it also appears that there is no way
to bridge the gap. Thus, the Kantian problematic tends to be most lucidly
adumbrated in the writings of kinds ofKantian who aim to show that where
we seem to be confronted with a Kantian gap, we are confronted with only
the illusion of a gap.
Ninth feature
If, as was said above, the philosophical outcome that now looms is one that
threatens the array of cognitive capacities which the Cartesian sceptic takes
to be unproblematically available (the capacities to doubt and dream, to feel
and think and believe, to enjoy sensory impressions of fireplaces and frame
hypotheses about evil demons), then the full import ofKantian sceptical paradox must remain intellectually unschematisable. There can be no such thing
as getting 'it' fully into focus, for getting things into focus seems precisely
to be just a further instance of the sort of thing which we now seem bound
to conclude we are unable to do. The Kantian worry is not merely (like the
Cartesian one) a form of philosophical perplexity that ceases to be sustainable when the attempt is made to translate it into practice. It cannot even be
sustained at the level of theory. The practical possibility of abstaining from
the modes of experience and thought and expression that are here brought
into question is not an option that can present itself even momentarily as a
live one. This form of sceptical paradox is therefore not unstable merely in
the way the Cartesian one is (i.e. because we cannot sustain our conviction
in it, as we leave the closet of our philosophy and immerse ourselves in the
practical exigencies of life), the Kantian paradoxical surmise already occupies a state of radical instability qua surmise. 21 The Kantian sceptic finds
himself drawn to a question he is both unable to hold stably in his mind and
yet unable to dismiss.25
JAMES CONANT
'scepti~al paradox', etc. Moreover, which register- Cartesian or Kantian- a
philosopher is operating in will also determine the manner in which a great
deal of the rest of his philosophical vocabulary is inflected. Equipped with the
preceding overview of Cartesian and Kantian features, it becomes possible,
for example, to survey the history of twentieth-century analytic philosophy
and to notice that philosophers (in their discussions of what they call 'scepticism') often tend to be preoccupied with one of these two registers to the exclusion of the other. Most of the mainstream of analytic philosophy has been
obsessed with the Cartesian problematic. Moore, Russell, Broad, Ayer, Price
and Chisholm are among the most distinguished members of this Cartesian
branch of the analytic tradition. But there is also a branch of the analytic
tradition that, though it has fewer members, is equally as distinguished,
and occupies itself almost entirely with the Kantian problematic. It includes
among its members C.l. Lewis, Wilfrid Sellars and Peter Strawson. If one
then examines how a great deal of philosophical vocabulary ('experience',
'epistemic', 'object', 'the given', etc.) is employed, one notices that it acquires
a very different inflection in the writings of one of these sets of authors than
it acquires in the writings of the other. 26
Not only individual bits of vocabulary but whole phrases, clauses, sentences and questions acquire a different philosophical valence depending
upon whether they occur in the context of the investigation of a Cartesian or
a Kantian problematic. Thus, for example, consider the following question:
'Can our cognitive powers reach all the way to the objects themselves?' This
can express a Cartesian anxiety about the existence of a gap between our
representations of outer objects and those outer objects themselves (the
anxiety here is that our cognitive powers always operate at an awkward
remove from the objects they represent), or it can express a Kantian anxiety about our capacity to direct our thought at objects (the anxiety here is
that our so-called cognitive powers are unable to furnish us with anything
which even amounts to a 'representation'.) Since the same form of words
can, on a particular occasion, express either a Cartesian or a Kantian anxiety, it becomes possible, as we shall soon see, for two philosophers to take
themselves to be in agreement with one another when they are not, or to
take themselves to be in disagreement with one another when they are not.
It thus becomes important, when seeking to identify the sort of philosophical
problematic in which a philosopher is entangled, to look beyond the most
superficial features of a his work, such as the forms of words that he is drawn
to employ when framing his problem. One must look instead to the character of the features that characterise his problematic. One philosopher may
adopt another philosopher's mode of speaking wholesale and yet miss his
.
.
problematic entirelyY
The remaining sections of this chapter will develop tlus pomt- that one
may be tempted by such superficial similarities _of \"Ocabulary to ~hor~10rJI
a sceptical paradox bearing Kantian featurc5 Jllto a proble~natlc ol the
116
VARIETIES OF SCEPTICISM
Cartesian form and vice versa - to clarify how some of Wittgenstein's most
distinguished commentators have misunderstood one another. Wittgenstein
and Kant are the outstanding figures in the history of philosophy whose
writings have been concerned to explore the nature and structure of the
Cartesian and K.antian problematics alike and, above all, to explore the relation between them. 28 By failing to identify clearly these varieties of sceptical
problematic while also failing to see that in both Kant's and Wittgenstein's
writings the term 'scepticism' is inflected broadly enough to range over both
these varieties (thereby failing to appreciate Kant's and Wittgenstein's
respective interests in their connection), otherwise insightful commentators have believed that they agree with one another (and with Kant or
Wittgenstein) when they do not and have believed that they disagree with
one another when they do not. I will illustrate this point here only in connection with Wittgenstein's work. As a first example of such a misunderstanding,
let us consider a misencounter between Hilary Putnam and John McDowell.
JAMES CONANT
VARIETIES OF SCEPTICISyl
words such as these in both of these ways at once that Putnam gets entangled both in his understanding of the structure and aim of the argument of
McDowell's Mind and World and in his proposals for a way out of the problems
that currently plague contemporary philosophy.
One sign that some slippage has taken place is that the Wittgenstein
passage -and McDowell's book generally- is concerned with the possibility
of meaning (with the possibility of our being able to mean something- rather
than nothing- by our words), whereas much of the Dewe; Lectures are focally
concerned with the possibility of knowledge (with how it is that we can know
things are as they seem). In his opening remarks, Putnam expresses the
thought he seeks to vindicate in his lectures as follows: 'there is a way to do
justice to our sense that knowledge claims are responsible to reality without
recoiling into metaphysical fantasy' (Putnam 1999: 4). But from McDowell's
point of view, the focus here on knowledge claims (as the paradigm for understanding the kind of responsibility to reality which philosophy brings
into question) must count as at best misleading, and at worst misguided.
For it invites a misidentification of the strand of philosophy that McDowell
is focally concerned to treat: it invites the substitution of a Cartesian for a
Kantian problematic. McDowell would, of course, not want to deny that we
should view knowledge claims as responsible to reality. But he would want to
insist that, for the purposes of his investigation, they constitute only a special
case of a more general (Kantian) problematic concerning the possibility of
the vulnerability of any claim to how things are. The sort of vulnerability to
reality under investigation in his book is exhibited in false claims equally
fully as in true ones, in our capacity for thinking (indeed, dreaming) as it
does in our capacity for knowing. McDO\vell's investigation does not single
out those of our claims that are knowledgeable. This is because it is concerned with what must be the case for any sort of human intellectual activity
to be intelligible as one of claim-making at all. It is the possibility of making
claims in general, not knowledge claims in particular, that comes to seem at
risk when our entitlement to the truism in Wittgenstein's remark seems to
come under threat.
As he proceeds in his lectures, as we shall see in a moment, Putnam
himself describes the issue with which he is concerned in terms that make
no particular reference to knowledge, for instance as the 'how does language
hook on to the world' issue. So it may seem an uncharitable quibble to raise
worries about h.is opening formulation of the issue in terms of knowledge.
But what I said above about the phrase 'our cognitive powers cannot reach
all the way to the objects themselves' applies equally to the question 'how
does language hook on the world?' In the pages of Putnam's Dewey Lectures,
these forms of words hover unstably between the expression of a Cartesian
and a Kantian worry- and that instability can be resolved only at the cost of
depriving Putnam's preferred diagnosis of the source of contemporary philosophy's ills of its intended generality. Putnam insists in his Dewey Lectures
119
JAMES CONANT
120
VARIETIES OF SCEPTICISM
If this sequence is taken as offering a diagnosis of most of what ails contemporary philosophy, and if the question at issue is taken to express both
the worry made urgent by the interface conception and yet somehow at the
same time the one that animates the sorts of philosophical worry McDowell
seeks to address in Mind and World, then Putnam may not claim McDowell as
an ally. What McDowell will take to be unsatisfactory in Putnam's diagnosis
can be put as follows: Putnam, in effect, suggests that the various forms of
Kantian scepticism that have come to seem so urgent in recent philosophy
can be exorcised simply through the treatment of Cartesian scepticism.
McDowell would want to press the following question: Is Putnam right in
claiming that the 'how does language hook on to the world?' issue is, at bottom, simply a replay of the old 'how does perception hook on to the world?'
issue? The correct answer to this question is: it depends on which 'how does
language hook on to the world' issue is at issue. (As I have indicated above,
there is a Cartesian and a Kantian version of the issue.) McDowell would
contend that Putnam's claim is not right about the version of the problem
that is, for the most part, the one that figures at the centre of concern in
the writings of, for example, Lewis or Sellars or Kripkenstein. The Kantian
difficulty (concerning thought's or language's capacity to be vulnerable to
reality), with which each of the aforementioned authors struggles, does not,
for the most part, have its source in a Cartesian difficulty (concerning the
indirect character of all perceptual contact with the 'external' world). None
of these authors is evidently concerned to urge a version of (what the Dewey
Lectures calls) the 'received' view of perception; and Putnam's efforts to highlight the dubious assumptions underlying the 'received' view do not evidently
bear on their problems.
Although it is true that McDowell, like Putnam, is concerned to vindicate
(what Putnam, following James, calls) 'the natural realism of the common
man', it is not an exaggeration to say that McDowell's diagnosis of the
sources of the perplexities with which contemporary philosophy struggles is
roughly the reverse of Putnam's most recent one: where Putnam argues that
it is only if we think through what is confused in the Cartesian sceptic's question 'Do we really see houses and chairs?' that will we free ourselves from the
confusions visited upon us by the analytical-Kantian sceptical question 'how
does language hook on to the world?', McDowell thinks that it is only once
we think through \'1-hat is hopeless about the sort of Kantian bind in which
someone like C. I. Lewis threatens to place himselfl- one in which it is no
longer possibk to see how thought can so much as be answerable to reality
-that we will be able fully to free ourselves from Cartesian worries about the
character of our perceptual relatedness to hou:ses and chairs. For Putnam,
in the Dtwey Lectures, the Cartesian paradox is the fundamental source of
(what Putnam calls) 'the broader epistemological and metaphysical is 8 ues'
that continue to 'preoccupy us' in contemporary philosophy (Putnam 1999:
II). For McDawell, in Mind flnd World, the Cartesian worry is an intelligible,
121
JAMES CONANT
122
VARIETIES OF SCEPTICISM
JAMES CONANT
VARIETIES OF SCEPTICISM
in which Kant seeks to push him: not only following the sceptic's presuppositions out to their ultimate consequences, but also examining the initial steps
in the Cartesian sceptic's progress towards doubt, identifying how the sceptic
passes from ordinary to philosophical doubt, from a claim to a non-claim
context, pinpointing the decisive movement in the philosophical conjuring
trick and diagnosing why it is the one that is bound to seem most innocent.
Thus, we might say, the Kantian way drives the sceptic forward in his doubt,
seeking to propel the sceptic to grace by forcing him to pass through utter
despair, whereas the Wittgensteinian way supplements this prospective
movement with a retrospective one, leading the sceptic back to the point of
entry into his problematic, returning him to the lost innocence of the everyday. The Kantian way compels the sceptic to progress further and further
forward, further and further from the ordinary, and deeper and deeper into
philosophical perplexity, to an ever more violent form of questioning, to the
point at which the sceptic's question consumes itself. The Wittgensteinian
way adds to this pressure an additional one that seeks to bring the sceptic
back to the place where he started, where he already is and never left, but in
such a way that he is able to recognise it for the first time.
These two movements that Wittgenstein's philosophical practice alternately seeks to execute are nicely summarised in the following two remarks:
My aim is: to teach you to pass from a piece of disguised nonsense to
a piece of undisguised nonsense.
(PI 464)
What we do is to bring words back from their metaphysical to their
everyday use.
(PI 116)
We come therefore now to a further aspect of the fourth form of philosophical insight that a perspicuous overview of the various kinds of philosophical response to scepticism can afford. Commentators on Wittgenstein
can easily talk by one another by failing to keep in view the complementarity
of these two movements in later Wittgenstein's writingsY
We saw, while reviewing Putnam's misencounter with McDowell, how
McDowell wished to privilege the Kantian problematic over the Cartesian
one; and we saw in Cavell's misencounter with Kripke how Cavell seemed
to want to privilege the Cartesian problematic over the Kantian one. Thus,
based on the evidence reviewed thus far, the following conclusion might seem
tempting: McDowell is primarily concerned to explore the Kantian problematic and Cavell the Cartesian. This is not right, however, about the bulk of
either McDowell's or Cavell's work (or that of almost any other sensitive
commentator on Wittgenstein). What happens rather, in their respective
writi-ngs "bout;Wittgenatein,''is;'that Wittgenst~in'.s exploration of one of
l:l5
JAMES CONANT
these two sceptical problematics tends alternately to come into focus while
the other recedes into the background. (And, indeed, I think it is almost
inevitable that, in working on later Wittgenstein, one should find this happening to one in one's writing about him.) To illustrate the point, I will place
side by side some further passages from Cavell and McDowell - passages in
which their roles have been reversed - now McDowell will appear to be the
one more preoccupied by the Cartesian dimension and Cavell by the Kantian
dimension ofWittgenstein's concerns.
McDowell, in 'Criteria, Defeasibility and Knowledge', argues that (what
Wittgenstein calls) criteria are internally related to the justification of
claims to knowledge in the following way: if a claim to know that such-andsuch turns out not to be justified then the criteria for claiming such-and-such
were only apparently satisfied. Thus, for example, if you claim that someone
is in pain, and it turns out that that person is only pretending to be in pain,
then the criteria for pain were only apparently satisfied. Here is McDowell:
Commentators [on Wittgenstein] often take it that the possibility
of pretence shows that criteria are defeasible. This requires the
assumption that in successful deception one brings it about that
criteria for something 'internal' are satisfied, although the ascription for which they are criteria would be false. But is the assumption
obligatory? Here is a possible alternative; in pretending, one causes
it to appear that criteria for something 'internal' are satisfied (that
is, one causes it to appear that someone else could know, by what
one says and does, that one is in, say, some 'inner' state); but the
criteria are not really satisfied (that is, the knowledge is not really
available).
(McDowell 1998b: 380)
Cavell, in The Claim f!!Reason, is concerned to challenge almost exactly the
same interpretation ofWittgenstein on criteria that McDowell is concerned
to challenge and for many of the same reasons. Yet Cavell comes to (what is
at least verbally) precisely the opposite conclusion with regard to how to employ the concept of a criterion in connection with the very sorts of examples
that McDowell discusses. Thus, Cavell concludes that even if someone is only
pretending to be in pain, if it is pain that he is pretending to be in, then his
behaviour satisfies the criteria for pain. Here is Cavell:
[O]nly certain eventualities will count as [someone's] not being in
pain ... Circumstances, namely; ... in which we will say (he will be)
feigning, rehearsing, hoaxing, etc. Why such circumstances? What
differentiates such circumstances from those in which he is (said to
be) clearing his throat, responding to a joke, etc.? Just that for 'He's
rehearsing' or 'feigning', or 'It's a hoax', etc. to satisfy us as explana126
VARIETIES OF SCEPTICISM
tions for his not being in pain ... what he is feigning must be precisely
pain, what he is rehearsing must be the part of a man in pain, the
hoax depends on his simulating pain, etc. These circumstances are
ones in appealing to which, in describing which, we retain the concept
(here, of pain) whose application these criteria determine. And this
means to me: In all such circumstances he has satisfied the criteria
we use for applying the concept of pain to others. It is because of that
satisfaction that we know that he is feigning pain (i.e., that it is pain
he is feigning), and that he knows what to do to feign pain. Criteria
are 'criteria for something's being so', not in the sense that they tell
us of a thing's existence, but of something like its identity, not of its
being so, but of its being so.
(Cavelll979: 45)
The first thing to notice is that McDowell and Cavell appear, at first blush,
simply to disagree: in cases of pretending to be in pain, McDowell says the
criteria for pain are not satisfied, Cavell says they are. The second thing to
notice is that their roles now seem, as promised, to be reversed. McDowell
takes Wittgensteinian criteria to operate at a Cartesian level. The question
that is settled, according to him, if criteria are satisfied, is one concerning the
truth of a claim, the existence of the pain, the reality of the phenomenon.
Cavell takes Wittgensteinian criteria to operate at a Kantian level. The
question that is settled, according to Cavell, if criteria are satisfied, is not
one concerning the truth of a claim but one concerning its purport, not one
concerning the existence of something which falls under a concept but the
applicability of the concept itself, not one concerning the reality of a phenomenon but one concerning its possibility. Whichever of these two readers
of Wittgenstein you take to be on the right track, it is worth noticing that
this is the structure of the disagreement here, and that the level at which
you take criteria to operate, e.g. in connection with phenomena such as pain,
will have decisive consequences for the sort of response to scepticism that
,will issue from an appeal to 'criteria'. Now I myself take it that Cavell has
got the merely exegetical question right (about what question is settled if
Wittgensteinian criteria are satisfied) and McDowell has got it wrong. But I
will not argue that point here. (Nor does their difference over this interpretative question mean that there is any substantive philosophical disagreement
between McDowell and Cavell here. 38) What interests me here is the very
fact that their disagreement should, at this juncture, have this particular
structure. This has a twofold irony, stemming from the ways in which each
of them seems to have given up his previous role in the two misencounters
canvassed above.
The first irony is to be found in the fact that, in most of his writing about
Wittgenstein, McDowell appears to read Wittgenstein as - and in Mind
and Ji11orld follows his Wittgenstein in - seeking to take exclusively (what I
127
JAMES CONANT
called at the beginning of this section) the 'Kantian way' with scepticism.
McDowell tends to see the Cartesian craving for epistemic security as an
intelligible, though inept, response to an inchoate form of the philosophical
anxiety that only arrives at clear expression when it is posed as a Kantian
sceptical paradox. Thus, despite his Cartesian construal of the grammar of
the concept of a criterion in his earlier essay, in Mind and World, McDowell
proceeds as if the treatment of philosophical scepticism can be prosecuted
primarily through attending to the Kantian problematic as a self-standing
form of philosophical confusion. Especially in Mind and World, he seems to
assume, in the manner of Kant himself, not only that the Cartesian sceptical
paradox can be shown to be merely a special case of a more general worry,
but more importantly that, once this is shown, Cartesian ism will be robbed of
all its force and will wither away of its own accord without requiring any additional form of specialised treatment. Whereas Cavell, despite his resolutely
Kantian construal of the grammar of a criterion, concentrates, above all, in
his philosophical writings, on the movement with which the Wittgensteinian
way supplements the Kantian way: the return to the ordinary. Cavell takes
(and takes Wittgenstein to take) the achievement of such a return to play an
essential role in attaining an understanding of the phenomenon of scepticism.39
The second irony to be noted in connection with the structure ofMcDowell's
and Cavell's disagreement about Wittgenstein's concept of a criterion lies in
the fact that Cavell, though he is far too acute a reader of Wittgenstein to
fail to appreciate that the Philosophical Investigations is frequently operating at
a Kantian level, nonetheless never sees that, for Wittgenstein, as for Kant,
the term 'scepticism' ranges over far more than a merely Cartesian sceptical
problematic - thus over far more varieties of philosophical perplexity than
a merely Cartesian inflection of the term is able to encompass. Nonetheless,
Cavell, through carefully following out the inner movement of the dialectic
traced in Wittgenstein's investigations, often finds himself fetching up in the
terrain of the Kantian problematic. Here is a characteristic passage that may
stand for a hundred others:
If you do not know the (non-grammatical) criteria of an Austinian
object (can't identify it, name it) then you lack a piece of information, a bit of knowledge, and you can be told its name, told what it
is, told what it is (officially) called. But if you do not know the grammatical criteria ofWittgensteinian objects, then you lack, as it were,
not only a piece of information or knowledge, but the possibility of
acquiring any information about such objects uberhaupt; you cannot
be told the name of that object, because there is as yet no object of
that kind for you to attach a forthcoming name to.
(Cavell 1979: 77)
128
VARIETIES OF SCEPTICISM
What is threatened here, with the loss of (what Cavell calls) Wittgenstein
criteria, is not merely the possibility of isolating an unimpeachable item
of knowledge, but the possibility of so much as turning up a candidate for
knowledge. At one point in The Claim ofReason, Cavell quotes the following
four passages from Philosophical Investigations in rapid succession:
... [O]nly of a living human being and what resembles (behaves
like) a living human being can one say: it has sensations; it sees; is
blind; hears; is deaf; is conscious or unconscious.
(PI 281)
What has to be accepted, the given, is - so one could say -forms of
life.
(PI 226)
What gives us so much as the idea that living beings, things, can feel?
(PI 283)
The human body is the best picture of the human soul.
(PI 178)
These are passages in which Wittgenstein presents what Cavell says he
understands 'as the background against which our criteria do their work;
even make sense' (Cavell 1979: 83). They are also quintessential examples
of moments in his work in which Wittgenstein's investigations move {from
the Cartesian) to the Kantian level. And, in commenting on these passages,
Cavell (taking the problem of other minds here as his example of a sceptical
problematic)) expresses what he takes to be the significance of such passages
in Wittgenstein's work:
To withhold, or hedge, our concepts of psychological states from a
given creature, on the ground that our criteria cannot reach to the
inner life of the creature, is specifically to withhold the source of my
idea that living beings are things that feel; it is to withhold myself,
to reject my response to anything as a living being; to blank so much
as my idea of anything as having a body. To describe this condition as
one in which I do not know (am not certain) of the existence of other
minds is empty. There is now nothing there of the right kind, to be
known. There is nothing to read from that body, nothing the body
is l!f; it does not go beyond itself, it expresses nothing; it does not
so much as behave. There is no body left to manifest consciousness
(or unconsciousness). It is not dead, but inanimate; it hides nothing
129
jAMES CONANT
8 Conclusion
The aim of this chapter has been to suggest that a perspicuous overview of
various kinds of scepticism and the kinds of response they engender affords
a number of different kinds of philosophical benefit: it allows one to command a clearer view of the sorts of relations that obtain across apparently
distinct areas of philosophy; it allows one to distinguish the very different
sorts of things philosophers mean when they employ (what is apparently)
VARIETIES OF SCEPTICISM
the same philosophical vocabulary; and it allows one to see more clearly why
authors such as Wittgenstein are often misread. {Here, I have also tried to
show how and why some of his best commentators misread one another and
misunderstand themselves -taking themselves to disagree with one another
when they do not, taking themselves to agree with one another when they do
not, and taking themselves to be in agreement with themselves when they
are not.) It may also allow one to see more clearly what is distinctive about
Wittgenstein's contributions to the history of thought about scepticism; but
a proper treatment of that issue must wait for another occasion.4
Notes
=:~-
JAMES CONANT
I0
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
ought to be suspicious of the idea that one should be able to limn the skeleton of
philosophy at its joints merely by effecting a division into areas based solely on
differences in subject-matter- ethics, science, mathematics, etc.
For some discussion of the presence of an incipiently Kantian problematic in
Descartes' thought, see Conant 1991. What I call in that paper 'a different kind
of Cartesianism' is a variant of (what I call in this chapter) 'Kantian scepticism'.
I speak here, rather tentatively, of varieties (rather thangenera) of scepticism, and
of these varieties as subtending variants (rather than species) of Cartesian and
Kantian scepticism respectively, in order to leave this question open. However, I
myself do favour a particular line, namely that the apparent 'kinds' in question
are, in the end, to be recognised as only apparently distinct kinds.
I do not mean to claim that either of these sets of features exhaustively characterise either of these varieties of scepticism.
I do not mean hereby to rule out cases of philosophical discussion that do
perfectly exemplify, without blemishes, either the Cartesian or Kantian format
respectively, but only to indicate that they are surprisingly rare.
For it not to be a symptom of (at least some degree of) confusion on an author's
part requires, I think, that the author already have thought through- and thus
have come to some stable view of his own concerning - the relation between
these two varieties of scepticism. There are such authors, but not many.
See Cavell 1981 and I996a.
Cavell's term for this is negated.
Cavell suggests we call the sort of object that figures in such examples 'a generic
object' (Cavell 1979: 52-3).
The internal relation between Cartesian scepticism and Shakespearean tragedy
is explored by Cavell in the essays collected in Cavell 1987.
This conflict between our ordinary practice and our philosophical reflection on
that practice is the source of the aura of paradox that accompanies any attempt
to acquiesce in a Cartesian sceptical conclusion. That conclusion, taken in isolation, does not have the outward form of a paradoxical assertion (in the way, say,
that the liar paradox does); its paradoxical aspect lies instead in our inability to
sustain our conviction in such a conclusion when, as Hume puts it, we leave our
philosophical study and return to the backgammon table.
For most everyday purposes, we cannot and should not try to do otherwise than
to take the perceptual appearances that present themselves to us - say, the
sudden appearance of an oncoming car- to constitute genuine instances of perceptual knowledge. The Cartesian sceptic knows this. He knows that we cannot
help but take someone writhing in pain to be in pain; we cannot help but take
certain ossified habits of interpretation to disclose the meaning of a sign; etc.
If he understands the structure of the Cartesian problematic, he will not take
such observations to impugn his procedures. Some philosophers have thought
- and have thought that later Wittgenstein thought - that such observations
themselves could suffice to overturn such forms of scepticism. That is a misunderstanding of Cartesian scepticism- and a misunderstanding of Wittgenstein's
understanding of it. This is not to deny that such observations (or 'reminders', as
Wittgenstein preferred to call them) might have a role to play i_n the tr~atment
of Cartesian scepticism. But they hardly suffice to overturn any mterestmg form
of scepticism.
Someone who is disinclined to believe in the trustworthiness of the government's
pronouncements, or the promises issued in television advertisements, or the
impartiality ofjudicial proceedings, etc., is sometimes called a sceptic i~ ordinary
language. I will refer to this character as the hard-headed customer. The differences
VARIETIES OF SCEPTICISM
20
21
22
23
24
between the hard-headed customer and the Cartesian sceptic are perhaps most
evident in the light of this ninth feature: There is no difficulty in imagining
that the hard-headed customer might be able to convert his various theoretical
doubts into practical ones: He may take care not to align his beliefs and actions
in accordance with the expectation that the government's pronouncements
will be fulfilled, he may make a point of not purchasing items advertised on
television, etc. Reflecting on the differences between the hard-headed customer
and the Cartesian sceptic can help to bring out how the nine Cartesian features,
listed above, are internally related to one another; a proper understanding of
each depends upon an appreciation of how it is related to the others. That the
hard-headed customer does not suffer from Cartesian scepticism can be seen
in part from the fact that he fails to begin with a sufficiently generic object;
this, in turn, can be seen from the way in which his doubt fails to generalise as
precipitously as in the Cartesian problematic, etc.
More precisely: the differences between these sorts of examples cease to be
relevant for the bulk of the Kantian enquiry. At a late stage in the enquiry, it
will become important to a Kant ian inquirer to recover these sorts of differences
- differences that underwrite the movement of thought in a Cartesian
investigation - but only once the Kantian paradox has been averted and the
intelligibility of object-directed thought and experience no longer stands under
threat.
Hence, in recent years, the increasingly important relationship between various
sorts of philosophical project calling for some sort of naturalistic reduction, on
the one hand, and the Kantian problematic in philosophy, on the other. The
demand for such reductions in the absence of a plausible programme for their
execution can, on the one hand, give rise to the relevant sense of mystery; while
a philosophically independently fuelled sense of Kantian paradox can, on the
other hand, fuel the sense that a programme of naturalistic reduction is the only
possible form of solution to the most urgent philosophical problems that face us
today.
I explore the engagement with a philosophical problematic of this sort in Kafka's
parables in Conant 2001.
To sum up this sixth Kant ian feature, one might adapt a joke -which I first heard
from Dan Dennett - in the following way: 'Scientists want to know whether
something possible is actual. Philosophers want to know whether something
actual is possible.'
Unlike the concluding statement affirmed by a Cartesian sceptic (see n. 17
above), formulations of the Kantian sceptical paradox tend to converge on
conclusions that have the canonical form of a logical paradox. This is perhaps
particularly evident if one considers the philosophy of language variant of
Kantian scepticism. Borrowing, for the moment, the terms in which Kripke
couches the paradox, the sceptical conclusion for this variant might, for
example, be formulated as follows: 'There is no fact of the matter as to whether
this sentence has a meaning.' Or more radically still: 'There isn't anything which
this sentence means.' The variant of Kant ian scepticism for which this is perhaps
least evident is perhaps that of (so-called) 'scepticism regarding other minds'.
This is partly because, once we think the Kantian variant of this problem all
the way through, we come to see that this ceases to be an apt way of denoting
the variety of scepticism that here comes to be at issue. To see that even this
variant veers towards a conclusion that has a self-annihilating structure, it is
important to see that the structure of the Kant ian version of this problem is one
in which the initial Cartesian distinction between the (putatively indubitable)
case of my own mindedness and. the (putatively comparatively dubitable) case
133,
JAMES CONANT
of the mindedness of others is cut out from underneath one. The Kantian
25
26
27
28
29
30
sceptical conclusion here is not just that there is nothing which could count as
his expressing his mental states in a manner that could enable me to know them,
but rather: there is nothing which could count as anyone~ (and therefore: my)
expressing a mental state.
Just as it is important to distinguish the Cartesian sceptic from the hard-headed
customer, so, too, one should not confuse the Kantian sceptic with yet another
character who is often called a 'sceptic' in ordinary language: someone who does
not believe in divine revelation, or extrasensory perception, or astrology, etc.
I will refer to this character as the debunker. He differs from the hard-headed
customer in that he believes that the phenomena about which he is 'sceptical' are
such as not even to be possible. The harded-headed customer need not call into
question the bare possibility of a trustworthy government or a truthful television
advertisement; what he doubts is merely their actuality. The debunker's doubt,
on the other hand, is directed at the possibility of certain phenomena. Yet it
would be a confusion to think the debunker is a Kantian sceptic just because he
doubts something to be possible that others take to be actual. His doubt is not a
philosophical doubt any more than that of the hard-headed customer is: It does
not issue in philosophical paradox. That a successful bout of debunking does not
issue in a specifically .Kantian variety of paradox can be seen from the way in
which the outcome fails properly to satisfy any of the nine Kantian features listed
above. This is perhaps most evident in the case of the ninth feature: There is no
difficulty in imagining that the debunker might be able to dispense altogether
with recourse to, say, divine revelation. His capacity to conceive the impossibility
of divine revelation does not appear in any way to be an exercise of a capacity
whose very possibility has thereby been called into question. Reflecting on the
differences between the debunker and the Kantian sceptic may, again, help to
bring out how the nine Kantian features, listed above, are internally related
to one another: That the debunker does not suffer from Kantian scepticism
can be seen in part from the fact that he begins with a very particular sort of
example; its debunking does not eventuate in a Kantian boggle; for he is under
no intellectual obligation to take the phenomena (that thereby seem to him not
to be possible) to be actual, etc.
The distinction between these two varieties of scepticism can provide philosophically far less superficial categories for sorting philosophers into groups than those
we usually rely upon, such as the alleged divide between analytic and Continental
philosophy. One can learn to see past the common philosophical reference points
and superficial similarities in philosophical tradition and style that unite thinkers such as Heidegger and Sartre, on the one hand, and Wilfrid Sellars and H.H.
Price, on the other, and begin to discern certain fundamental divergences, thus
enabling one to notice fundamental philosophical affinities between thinkers
from different traditions, allowing one to sort together Heidegger and Sellars,
on the one hand, and Sartre and Price, on the other.
Conversely, one may resolutely avoid a particular philosopher's ways of speaking
as a strategy for avoiding his problems and yet end up mired in precisely the
philosophical problematic one sought thereby to avoid. This is part of the reason
why Richard Rorty's preferred strategies for dissolving philosophical problems
tend to be so ineffectual.
.
I argue for this claim in the longer version of this chapter cited in note 1.
Putnam ~s Dewey Uclures were given at Columbia University in March of 1994 and
first published inJqumal 'IfPhi!IJsop/ly. They are reprinted in Putnam ( 1999) and
all references to them will be to that publication.
The context ,,fthe previous quotation makes this evident.
134
VARIETIES OF SCEPTICISM
135
JAMES CONANT
the rruwemntl up 1M dialectictd ladJJrr (towards nonsense) and the movement down the
dia/eaical /adO.r (towards the ordinary). This way of putting things helps to bring
out both a fundamental moment of continuity and a fundamental moment of
discontinuity between Wittgenstein's early and later philosophical practice. The
former of these two remarks could seJVe equally aptly as a characterisation of the
aim of the author the Tmetatru. The latter could not. What I am herecalling'the
Wittgensteinian way' is therefore meant to designate a way with scepticism that
we first find only when we turn to Wittgenstein's later writings.
38 Cavell, if he were brought to see how McDowell is employing the term 'criterion',
could concede, without harm to any of his philosophical commitments, something
along the following lines: 'Well, that is not howWittgenstein uses the term; but
if you are determined to use the term in this (un-Wittgensteinian) way, then
the right (i.e. philosophieally Wittgensteinian) thing to go on and say, so using
it, is just what you say (e.g. that in cases of pretending the criteria for pain are
only apparently satisfied).' And McDowell, equally, if he were taught Cavell's
understanding of the term (criteria are not criteria for something's being so, but
for its being so) would have no ~ason not to concede that the right thing to say,
so using the term, is just what Cavell says (i.e, that in cases of pretending, if it
is pain you are pretending to be in, then the criteria for pain are satisfied). The
disagreement between Cavell and McDowell about criteria is a further instance
of a merely apparent disagreement in which the appearance of disagreement
is engendered through an unacknowledged transition from a Cartesian to a
Kantian problematic. Both McDowell and Cavell are in profound disagreement
with their respective and very similar sets of interlocutors (Baker, Wright,
Albritton, Malcolm, etc.), but they are disagreeing with them about different
things. (McDowell's point has to do with how justification and knowledge are
internally- and not merely externally- related to one another; Cavell's has to
do with how an appeal to criteria cannot do a sort of work that Wittgenstein calls
upon it to do, if criteria are understood in the manner of such commentators.)
Their respective focal philosophical motivations for disagreeing with such
commentators are perfectly compatible. This is not to deny that the differences
here in what they have to say about Wittgenstein's response to scepticism may be
tied to substantive differences in the details of their respective understandings
of the character of that response. It is only to insist that these differences can be
assessed only after we appreciate that what the one here affirms and the other
here denies (in affirming and denying that, in the case of someone's pretending
to be in pain, the criteria for pain are satisfied) are not the same thing.
39 It is worth noting that nothing McDowell says anywhere, as far as I can see, ever
denies the importance of such a return (and thus the sort of attention to the ordinary upon which Cavell places so much emphasis in his reading ofWittgenstein).
Indeed, much of what McDowell says would seem to presuppose it.
40 As should be evident to anyone familiar with their work, the project of this
chapter is pervasively indebted to the writings of Stanley Cavell,John McDowell,
and Hilary Putnam. This particular version of the chapter, as it appears here, is
indebted to Denis McManus- both for his suggestions about how to organise and
edit it and for his forbearance with its author.
l36