Sum, Ergo Cogito: Nietzsch
Sum, Ergo Cogito: Nietzsch
Sum, Ergo Cogito: Nietzsch
2—2015
Jonas Monte
I. Introduction
N
ietzsche’s aphorism 276 in The Gay Science addresses
Descartes’ epistemological scheme: “I still live, I still think:
I still have to live, for I still have to think. Sum, ergo cogito:
cogito, ergo sum” (GS 223). Ironically, Nietzsche inverts the logic in
Descartes’ famous statement “Cogito, ergo sum” as a caustic way, yet
poetic and stylish, of creating his own statement.1 He then delivers
his critique by putting his own version prior to that of Descartes.
Here, Nietzsche’s critique can be interpreted as a twofold overlap-
ping argument.
First, by reversing Descartes’ axiom into “Sum, ergo cogito,”
Nietzsche stresses that in fact a social ontology (which includes
metaphysical, logical, linguistic, and conceptual elements) has been
a condition that makes possible Descartes’ inference of human
existence from such pre-established values. Here, Descartes seems
not to have applied his methodical doubt completely, since to arrive
1 In light of Nietzsche’s inversion, this paper seeks to analyse Descartes’ Meditation Project, in
effect, the cogito as a device in itself. It does not consider the project’s metaphysical background,
including the issue of Descartes’ substance dualism. For an introduction to Cartesian dualism,
see Justin Skirry, “René Descartes: The Mind-Body Distinction,” Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
Jonas Monte is a senior currently studying in a joint honors program in philosophy and
political science at the University of Ottawa, Canada. His primary philosophical
interests are ethics, political philosophy, Nietzsche, and early modern philosophy.
After graduation, Jonas plans to pursue a PhD in philosophy.
14 Jonas Monte
holding this piece of paper in my hands, and soon. Again, how could
it be denied that these hands or this whole body are mine?” (13).
It is worthwhile recognizing that in the same passage, Descartes
excludes “madmen” contending that “such people are insane, and
I would be thought equally mad if I took anything from them as a
model for myself” (13). In other words, his experiment requires that
one must be aware of their direct experiences of the senses—as a
condition of not being deficient—in order to derive certainty. In this
case, the principle that knowledge gained under adverse conditions
of perception can be false succumbs to the proposition I am here
now doing such and such. Nevertheless, this leads to another difficulty,
which is known as the dream problem.
According to Descartes, the proposition I am here doing such and
such is also doubtful since it is possible one can be dreaming and yet
perceive that one is here (13). Although one can be aware of one’s
sensory experiences, there can be no consequent assurance that one
is not dreaming, since those same sensory experiences can occur in
a dream. However, Descartes will argue that there are some some
things that are not altered whether or not one is sleeping:
Arithmetic, geometry, and other subjects of this
kind, which deal only with the simplest and most
general things regardless of whether they really ex-
ist in nature or not, contain something certain and
indubitable. For whether I am awake or asleep, two
and three added together are five, and a square has
no more than four sides. It seems impossible that
such transparent truths should incur any suspicion
of being false. (14)
Significantly, although one’s ideas and perceptions can be a
dream that does not correspond to external factors but happens
totally within the mind, one still conceives of arithmetic and
geometry as true. Still, while the sciences of extension survive the
dream problem, they will succumb to the Evil Deceiver problem.
In this scenario, Descartes wrestles with the possibility that
there is an evil genius who makes one think that 2+4=6, when in
reality the total is 8 (14). How can one have certainty even of arith-
metic and geometry when one may be the victim of an evil God who
likes to deceive? Here, crucially, Descartes must address this problem
Nietzsche Re-orders Descartes 17
2 Author’s translation; the original reads: “… por conceber o pensamento em sua superfície—a
linguagem—escondendo que a lógica repousa na crença em uma verdade universal e necessária,
cujo único fundamento é postulação de um Deus sumamente bom.” In contrast to the suggestion
of Moto Itaparica, this paper submits that in BGE, Sec. 191, Nietzsche uses the concept of superfi-
ciality in a denotative sense to criticize Descartes
20 Jonas Monte
Final Considerations