GR 203335 Disini V Sec of Justice

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 100

EN BANC

G.R. No. 203335 - JOSE JESUS M. DISINI, JR., et al, Petitioners, v. THE
SECRETARY OF JUSTICE, et al., Respondents; G.R. No. 203299 - LOUIS
"BAROL" C. BIRAOGO, Petitioner, \r. NATIONAL BUREAU OF
INVESTIGATION and PHILIPPINE NATIONAL POLICE, Respondents;
G.R. No. 203306 - ALAB NG MAMAMAHAYAG (ALAM), et al.,
Petitioners, v. OFFICE OF THE PRESIDENT, et al., Respondents; G.R.
No. 203359 - SENATOR TEOFISTO GUINGONA III, Petitioner, v. THE
EXECUTIVE SEC~TARY, et al.,_ Respondents; G.R. No. 203378 ALEXANDER ADONIS, et al., Petitioners, v. THE EXECUTIVE
SECRETARY, et al., Respondents; G.R. No. 203391 - HON. RAYMOND
PALATINO, et al., Petitioners, v. HON. PAQUITO OCHOA, JR., et al.,
Respondents; G.R. No. 203407
BAGONG ALYANSANG
MAKABAYAN SECRETARY GENERAL RENATO M. REYES, JR., et
al., Petitioners, v. BENIGNO SIMEON AQUINO III, et al., Respondents;
G.R. No. 203440 - MELENCIO STA. MARIA, et al., Petitioners, v. HON.
PAQUITO OCHOA, JR., et al., Respondents; G.R. No. 203453 - PAUL
CORNELIUS CASTILLO, et al., Petitioners, v. HIS EXCELLENCY
BENIGNO AQUINO III, et al., Respondents; G.R. No. 203454 ANTHONY IAN CRUZ, et al., Petitipners, v. HIS EXCELLENCY
BENIGNO AQUINO III, et al., Respondents;" G.R. No. 203501 PHILIPPINE BAR ASSOCIATION, INC., Petitioner, v. HIS
EXCELLENCY BENIGNO SIMEON AQUINO III, et al., Respondents;
G.R. No. 203509 - BAYAN _MUNA REPRESENTATIVE NERI
COLMENARES, Petitioner, v. THE EXECUTIVE SECRETARY
PAQUITO OCHOA, JR., Respondent; G.R. No. 203515 - NATIONAL
PRESS CLUB OF THE PHILIPPINES, INC., et al., Petitioner, v. OFFICE
OF THE PRESIDENT BENIGNO SIMEON AQUINO III, et al.,
Respondents; G.R. No. 203518 - PHILIPPINE INTERNET FREEDOM
ASSOCIATION, et al., Petitioners, v. THE EXECUTIVE SECRETARY, et
al. Respondents
Promulgated:
FEBRUARY 18,
x

201,v

DISSENTING AND CONCURRING OPINION


LEONEN,J.:

Most of the challenges to the constitutionality of some provisions of


the Cybercrime Prevention Act of 2012 (Republic Act No. 10175) are raised
without an actual case or controversy. Thus, the consolidated petitions
should fail except for those that raise questions that involve the imminent
possibility that the constitutional guarantees to freedom of expression will be

Dissenting & Concurring

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

stifled because of the broadness of the scope of the text of the provision. In
view of the primacy of this fundamental right, judicial review of the statute
itself, even absent an actual case, is viable.
With this approach, I am of the opinion that the constitution requires
that libel as presently contained in the Revised Penal Code and as reenacted
in the Cybercrime Prevention Act of 2012 (Rep. Act No. 10175) be struck
down as infringing upon the guarantee of freedom of expression provided in
Article III, Section 4 of our Constitution. I am also of the firm view that the
provisions on cybersex as well as the provisions increasing the penalties of
all crimes committed with the use of computers are unconstitutional. The
provision limiting unsolicited commercial communications should survive
facial review and should not be declared as unconstitutional.
I concur with the majority insofar as they declare that the take down
clause, the provision allowing dual prosecutions of all cybercrimes, and the
provision that broadly allows warrantless searches and seizures of traffic
data, are unconstitutional. This is mainly because these present unwarranted
chilling effects on the guaranteed and fundamental rights of expression.
I
Framework of this Opinion
Reality can become far richer and more complex than our collective
ability to imagine and predict. Thus, conscious and deliberate restraint at
times may be the better part of judicial wisdom.
The judiciarys constitutionally mandated role is to interpret and apply
the law. It is not to create or amend law on the basis of speculative facts
which have not yet happened and which have not yet fully ripened into clear
breaches of legally demandable rights or obligations. Without facts that
present an actual controversy, our inquiry will be roving and unlimited. We
substitute our ability to predict for the rigor required by issues properly
shaped in adversarial argument of the real. We become oracles rather than a
court of law.
This is especially so when the law is made to apply in an environment
of rapidly evolving technologies that have deep and far-reaching
consequences on human expression, interaction, and relationships. The
internet creates communities which virtually cross cultures, creating
cosmopolitarian actors present in so many ways and in platforms that we are
yet starting to understand.

Dissenting & Concurring

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

Petitioners came to this court via several petitions for certiorari and/or
prohibition under Rule 65 of the Rules of Court. They seek to declare certain
provisions of Rep. Act No. 10175 or the Cybercrime Prevention Act of
20121 as unconstitutional. They allege grave abuse of discretion on the part
of Congress. They invoke our power of judicial review on the basis of the
textual provisions of the statute in question, their reading of provisions of the
Constitution, and their speculation of facts that have not happened may or
may not happen in the context of one of the many technologies available
and evolving in cyberspace. They ask us to choose the most evil among the
many possible but still ambiguous future factual permutations and on that
basis declare provisions not yet implemented by the Executive or affecting
rights in the concrete as unconstitutional. In effect, they ask us to do what
the Constitution has not even granted to the President: a provision-byprovision veto in the guise of their interpretation of judicial review.
Although pleaded, it is difficult to assess whether there was grave
abuse of discretion on the part of the Executive. This court issued a
temporary restraining order to even proceed with the drafting of the
implementing rules. There has been no execution of any of the provisions of
the law.
This is facial review in its most concrete form. We are asked to render
a pre-enforcement advisory opinion of a criminal statute. Generally, this
cannot be done if we are to be faithful to the design of our Constitution.
The only instance when a facial review is permissible is when there is
a clear showing that the provisions are too broad under any reasonable
reading that it imminently threatens expression. In these cases, there must be
more of a showing than simply the in terrorem effect of a criminal statute. It
must clearly and convincingly show that there can be no determinable
standards that can guide interpretation. Freedom of expression enjoys a
primordial status in the scheme of our basic rights. It is fundamental to the
concept of the people as sovereign. Any law regardless of stage of
implementation that allows vague and unlimited latitude for law
enforcers to do prior restraints on speech must be struck down on its face.
This is the framework taken by this opinion.
The discussion in this dissenting and concurring opinion is presented
in the following order:
1. Justiciability
2. The Complexity of the Internet and the Context of the Law
1

Rep. Act No. 10175, sec. 1. The law was the product of Senate Bill No. 2796 and House Bill No. 5808.

Dissenting & Concurring

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

3. The Doctrine of Overbreadth and the Internet


4. Take Down Clause
5. Libel Clauses
6. Cybersex Provisions
7. Speech Component in the Collection of Traffic Data
8. Commercial Speech
I (A)
Justiciability
Judicial review the power to declare a law, ordinance, or treaty as
unconstitutional or invalid is inherent in judicial power.2 It includes the
power to settle actual controversies involving rights which are legally
demandable 3 and to determine whether or not there has been a grave abuse
of discretion amounting to lack or excess of jurisdiction on any part of any
branch or instrumentality of Government. 4 The second aspect of judicial
review articulated in the 1987 Constitution nuances the political question
doctrine. 5 It is not licensed to do away with the requirements of
justiciability.
The general rule is still that: the constitutionality of a statute will be
passed on only if, and to the extent that, it is directly and necessarily
involved in a justiciable controversy and is essential to the protection of the
rights of the parties concerned. 6 Justiciability on the other hand requires
that: (a) there must be an actual case or controversy involving legal rights
that are capable of judicial determination; (b) the parties raising the issue
must have standing or locus standi to raise the constitutional issue; (c) the
constitutionality must be raised at the earliest possible opportunity, thus ripe
for adjudication; and (d) the constitutionality must be the very lis mota of the
case, or the constitutionality must be essential to the disposition of the case. 7
It is essential that there be an actual case or controversy. 8 There
must be existing conflicts ripe for judicial determination not conjectural
2

Consti., art. VIII, sec. 1 which provides the following:


Judicial power shall be vested in one Supreme Court and in such lower courts as may be
established by law.

3
4
5
6

Judicial power includes the duty of courts of justice to settle actual controversies involving rights
which are legally demandable and enforceable, and to determine whether or not there has been a grave
abuse of discretion amounting to lack or excess of jurisdiction on the part of any branch or
instrumentality of Government.
Consti., art. VIII, sec. 1.
Consti., art. VIII, sec. 1.
Tanada v. Cuenco, G.R. No. L-10520, 100 Phil. 1101 (1957) [Per J. Concepcion, En Banc].
Philippine Association of Colleges and Universities v. Secretary of Education, 97 Phil. 806, 809 (1955)
[Per J. Bengzon, En Banc].
Levy Macasiano v. National Housing Authority, G.R. No. 107921, July 1, 1993, 224 SCRA 236, 242
[Per CJ Davide, Jr., En Banc].
Angara v. Electoral Commission, 63 Phil. 139, 158 (1936) [Per J. Laurel, En Banc].

Dissenting & Concurring

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

or anticipatory. Otherwise, the decision of the Court will amount to an


advisory opinion. 9
In Information Technology Foundation of the Phils. v. COMELEC, 10
this court described the standard within which to ascertain the existence of
an actual case or controversy:
It is well-established in this jurisdiction that "x x x for a court to
exercise its power of adjudication, there must be an actual case or
controversy -- one which involves a conflict of legal rights, an
assertion of opposite legal claims susceptible of judicial resolution;
the case must not be moot or academic or based on extra-legal or
other similar considerations not cognizable by a court of justice. x
x x [C]ourts do not sit to adjudicate mere academic questions to
satisfy scholarly interest, however intellectually challenging." The
controversy must be justiciable -- definite and concrete, touching
on the legal relations of parties having adverse legal interests. In
other words, the pleadings must show an active antagonistic
assertion of a legal right, on the one hand, and a denial thereof
on the other; that is, it must concern a real and not a merely
theoretical question or issue. There ought to be an actual and
substantial controversy admitting of specific relief through a
decree conclusive in nature, as distinguished from an opinion
advising what the law would be upon a hypothetical state of
facts. 11 (Citations omitted, emphasis supplied)

In Lozano v. Nograles, 12 this court also dismissed the petitions to


nullify House Resolution No. 1109 or A Resolution Calling upon the
Members of Congress to Convene for the Purpose of Considering Proposals
to Amend or Revise the Constitution, Upon a Three-fourths Vote of All the
Members of Congress. In dismissing the petitions, this court held:
It is well settled that it is the duty of the judiciary to say what the
law is. The determination of the nature, scope and extent of the
powers of government is the exclusive province of the judiciary,
such that any mediation on the part of the latter for the allocation
of constitutional boundaries would amount, not to its supremacy,
but to its mere fulfillment of its "solemn and sacred obligation"
under the Constitution. This Courts power of review may be
awesome, but it is limited to actual cases and controversies dealing
with parties having adversely legal claims, to be exercised after
full opportunity of argument by the parties, and limited further to
the constitutional question raised or the very lis mota presented.
The "case-or-controversy" requirement bans this court from
deciding "abstract, hypothetical or contingent questions,"5 lest
9

10
11
12

Southern Hemisphere Engagement Network v. Anti-Terrorism Council, G.R. No. 178552, October 5,
2010, 632 SCRA 146, 176 [Per J. Carpio-Morales, En Banc], citing Republic Telecommunications
Holding, Inc. v. Santiago, 556 Phil. 83, 91 (2007) [Per J. Tinga, Second Division].
499 Phil. 281 (2005) [Per C.J. Panganiban, En Banc].
Id. at 304-305.
G.R. No. 187883, June 16, 2009, 589 SCRA 356 [Per C.J. Puno, En Banc].

Dissenting & Concurring

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion
the court give opinions in the nature of advice concerning
legislative or executive action.(Emphasis supplied) 13

Then, citing the classic words in Angara v. Electoral Commission: 14


Any attempt at abstraction could only lead to dialectics and barren
legal questions and to sterile conclusions unrelated to actualities.
Narrowed as its function is in this manner, the judiciary does not
pass upon questions of wisdom, justice or expediency of
legislation. More than that, courts accord the presumption of
constitutionality to legislative enactments, not only because the
legislature is presumed to abide by the Constitution but also
because the judiciary in the determination of actual cases and
controversies must reflect the wisdom and justice of the people as
expressed through their representatives in the executive and
legislative departments of the government. 15 (Citations omitted)

In Republic of the Philippines v. Herminio Harry Roque et al., 16 this


court ruled in favor of the petitioner and dismissed the petitions for
declaratory relief filed by respondents before the Quezon City Regional
Trial Court against certain provisions of the Human Security Act. In that
case, the court discussed the necessity of the requirement of an actual case or
controversy:
Pertinently, a justiciable controversy refers to an existing
case or controversy that is appropriate or ripe for judicial
determination, not one that is conjectural or merely anticipatory.
Corollary thereto, by "ripening seeds" it is meant, not that
sufficient accrued facts may be dispensed with, but that a dispute
may be tried at its inception before it has accumulated the
asperity, distemper, animosity, passion, and violence of a full
blown battle that looms ahead. The concept describes a state of
facts indicating imminent and inevitable litigation provided that the
issue is not settled and stabilized by tranquilizing declaration.
A perusal of private respondents petition for declaratory
relief would show that they have failed to demonstrate how they
are left to sustain or are in immediate danger to sustain some
direct injury as a result of the enforcement of the assailed
provisions of RA 9372. Not far removed from the factual milieu in
the Southern Hemisphere cases, private respondents only assert
general interests as citizens, and taxpayers and infractions which
the government could prospectively commit if the enforcement of
the said law would remain untrammeled. As their petition would
disclose, private respondents fear of prosecution was solely based
on remarks of certain government officials which were addressed
to the general public. They, however, failed to show how these
13
14
15
16

Id. at 357-358.
63 Phil. 139 (1936) [Per J. Laurel, En Banc].
Id. at 158.
G.R. No. 204603, September 24, 2013 [Per J. Perlas-Bernabe, En Banc].

Dissenting & Concurring

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion
remarks tended towards any prosecutorial or governmental action
geared towards the implementation of RA 9372 against them. In
other words, there was no particular, real or imminent threat to any
of them. 17 (Emphasis supplied)

Referring to Southern Hemisphere Engagement Network, Inc. v. AntiTerrorism Council: 18


Without any justiciable controversy, the petitions have
become pleas for declaratory relief, over which the Court has no
original jurisdiction. Then again, declaratory actions characterized
by "double contingency," where both the activity the petitioners
intend to undertake and the anticipated reaction to it of a public
official are merely theorized, lie beyond judicial review for lack of
ripeness.
The possibility of abuse in the implementation of RA 9372
does not avail to take the present petitions out of the realm of the
surreal and merely imagined. Such possibility is not peculiar to
RA 9372 since the exercise of any power granted by law may be
abused. Allegations of abuse must be anchored on real events
before courts may step in to settle actual controversies involving
rights which are legally demandable and enforceable. (Emphasis
supplied; citations omitted) 19

None of the petitioners in this case have been charged of any offense
arising from the law being challenged for having committed any act which
they have committed or are about to commit. No private party or any agency
of government has invoked any of the statutory provisions in question
against any of the petitioners. The invocations of the various constitutional
provisions cited in petitions are in the abstract. Generally, petitioners have
ardently argued possible applications of statutory provisions to be invoked
for future but theoretical state of facts.
The blanket prayer of assailing the validity of the provisions cannot be
allowed without the proper factual bases emanating from an actual case or
controversy.
II
The Complexity of the Internet
and the Context of the Law
This is especially so when the milieu is cyberspace.

17
18

19

Id.
Southern Hemisphere Engagement Network, Inc. v. Anti-Terrorism Council, G.R. No. 178552, October
5, 2010, 632 SCRA 146, 176 [Per J. Carpio-Morales, En Banc].
Id. at 179.

Dissenting & Concurring

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

The internet or cyberspace is a complex phenomenon. It has pervasive


effects and are, by now, ubiquitous in many communities. Its possibilities
for reordering human relationships are limited only by the state of its
constantly evolving technologies and the designs of various user interfaces.
The internet contains exciting potentials as well as pernicious dangers.
The essential framework for governance of the parts of cyberspace
that have reasonable connections with our territory and our people should
find definite references in our Constitution. However, effective governance
of cyberspace requires cooperation and harmonization with other approaches
in other jurisdictions. Certainly, its scope and continuous evolution require
that we calibrate our constitutional doctrines carefully: in concrete steps and
with full and deeper understanding of incidents that involve various parts of
this phenomenon. The internet is neither just one relationship nor is it a
single technology. It is an interrelationship of many technologies and
cultures.
An overview may be necessary if only to show that judicial preenforcement review or a facial evaluation of only the statute in question
may be inadvisable. Cases that involve cyberspace are the paradigmatic
examples where courts should do an evaluation of enshrined constitutional
rights only in the context of real and actual controversies.
II (A)
A Network of Networks 20
The very concept of an internet envisions pervasiveness. The first
recorded description of the interactions that would come to typify the
internet was contained in a series of memos in August 1962 by J.C.R.
Licklider. In these memos, the pioneering head of the computer research
program at the United States Department of Defenses Advanced Research
Projects Agency (ARPA) discussed his concept of a Galactic Network. 21
The term internet is an abbreviation for inter-networking. 22 It
refers to a combination of networks that communicate between
themselves. 23 A network pertains to the interconnection of several
20

21

22

23

D. MACLEAN, Herding Schrdingers Cats: Some Conceptual Tools For Thinking About Internet
Governance, Background Paper for the ITU Workshop on Internet Governance, Geneva, February 2627, 2004, 8 <http://www.itu.int/osg/spu/forum/intgov04/contributions/itu-workshop-feb-04-internetgovernance-background.pdf> (visited October 16, 2013).
Brief History of the Internet <http://www.internetsociety.org/internet/what-internet/historyinternet/brief-history-internet> (visited October 16, 2013).
'Comprehensive Study on Cybercrime prepared by United Nations Office on Drugs and Crime for the
Intergovernmental
Expert
Group
on
Cybercrime,
February
2013,
<http://www.unodc.org/documents/commissions/CCPCJ_session22/13
80699_Ebook_2013_study_CRP5.pdf> (visited October 16, 2013).
Id.

Dissenting & Concurring

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

distinct components. To speak of an internet is, therefore, to speak of the


interconnection of interconnections. Thus, [t]he Internet today is a
widespread information infrastructure. 24 It is at once a world-wide
broadcasting capability, a mechanism for information dissemination, and a
medium for collaboration and interaction between individuals and their
computers without regard for geographic location. 25
The internet grew from ARPAs ARPANet. It took off from the
revolutionary concept of packet-switching as opposed to circuit switching.
Packet switching eliminated the need for connecting at the circuit level
where individual bits of data are passed synchronously along an end-to-end
circuit between two end locations. Instead, packet switching allowed for the
partitioning of data into packets, which are then transmitted individually and
independently, even through varying and disjointed paths. The packets are
then reassembled in their destination. 26 At any given microsecond, without
our jurisdiction, complete content may be sent from any computer connected
by wire or wirelessly to the internet. At the same time, there can be small
parts or packets of information passing through other computers destined to
be reassembled in a requesting computer somewhere in this planet.
Packet switching requires that open architecture networking be the
underlying technical foundation of the internet. Separately designed and
developed networks are connected to each other. Each of these participating
networks may have its own unique interfaces that it offers to its users. Every
user in each of these separate but participating networks, however, remains
connected to each other. 27
This open-architecture network environment in turn requires a
communications protocol that allows a uniform way of joining different
networks. 28 Developed in 1973, this protocol eventually came to be known
as the Transmission Control Protocol/Internet Protocol (TCP/IP). 29 The
Internet Protocol (IP) sets how data is broken down into chunks for
transmission, as well as how the source and destination addresses are
specified. 30
24

25
26
27
28

29

30

Brief History of the Internet <http://www.internetsociety.org/internet/what-internet/historyinternet/brief-history-internet> (visited October 16, 2013).


Id.
Id. at 3.
Id.
Comprehensive Study on Cybercrime prepared by United Nations Office on Drugs and Crime for the
Intergovernmental
Expert
Group
on
Cybercrime,
February
2013,
282
<http://www.unodc.org/documents/commissions/CCPCJ_session22/1380699_Ebook_2013_study_CRP5.pdf> (visited October 16, 2013).
Brief History of the Internet, p. 4 <http://www.internetsociety.org/internet/what-internet/historyinternet/brief-history-internet> (visited October 16, 2013).
Comprehensive Study on Cybercrime prepared by United Nations Office on Drugs and Crime for the
Intergovernmental
Expert
Group
on
Cybercrime,
February
2013,
278
<http://www.unodc.org/documents/commissions/CCPCJ_session22/1380699_Ebook_2013_study_CRP5.pdf> (visited October 16, 2013).

10

Dissenting & Concurring

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

To identify connected devices, each device on the internet is assigned


a unique address in the form of a dotted quad, otherwise known as the IP
address (100.962.28.27). These IP addresses are used to route data packets to
their respective destinations.31 There are a finite number of IP addresses
available. With the growth of the internet beyond all expectations, the
expansion of available IP addresses became imperative. There is now an
ongoing effort to shift from IP version 4 (IPv4) to IP version 6 (Ipv6). From
a communication protocol that allows for roughly 4.3 billion unique
addresses, the new version will allow for 2128 unique addresses. Written in
ordinary decimal form, this number is 39 digits long. 32
TCP/IP addressed the need for connected devices to have a unique
identification and designation. But, to make these addresses accessible and
readable to its human users, domain names were introduced. Internet
addresses are now also written as domain names under what is known as
the Domain Name System (DNS). 33 The internet address of this court is
thus: sc.judiciary.gov.ph.
The allocation of unique identifiers for the internet, such as IP
addresses and domain names, is administered not by a public 34 entity but by
a nonprofit public benefit corporation based in the United States of America:
the Internet Corporation for Assigned Names and Numbers (ICANN).
ICANN allocates IP addresses and administers the DNS through delegated
authority to domain name registries. 35 These registries consist of databases
of all domain names registered in generic top level domains (gTLD), such as
.com, .org, .gov, and country code top level domains (ccTLD), such as .ph
and .sg. 36
II (B)
Openness and the World Wide Web
In 1989, Tim Berners-Lee of the European Organization for Nuclear
Research (CERN) developed the World Wide Web (WWW). The World
Wide Web allowed documents, or pages, to link to other documents stored
across a network. 37 Together with electronic mail (email), the World Wide
Web has been the driving force of the internet. 38 The World Wide Web
provided the impetus for others to develop software called browsers,
which allowed the user to navigate access to content as well as to exchange
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38

Id.
Id. at 279.
Id.
Id. Government or state-run.
Id.
Id.
Id. at 282.
Id. at 280.

Dissenting & Concurring

11

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

information through web pages. Information can be carried through


different media. Thus, text can be combined with pictures, audio, and video.
These media can likewise be hyperlinked or marked so that it could
provide easy access to other pages containing related information.
This new form of interface hastened the internets environment of
openness. 39 It is this openness and the innovation it continuously engendered
that enabled the internet to eclipse networks built around appliances
connected or tethered to specific proprietary infrastructure such as America
Online and CompuServe. 40 It is this openness that enabled the internet to
become the present-day widespread information infrastructure 41 or
universal network of networks. 42
Today, the use of the internet and its prevalence are not only
inevitable facts, these are also escalating phenomena. By the end of 2011, it
was estimated that some 2.3 billion individuals, or more than one-third of
the worlds population, had access to the internet. 43 The use of the internet is
inevitably bound to increase as wireless or mobile broadband services
become more affordable and available. By 2015, the estimates are that the
extent of global internet users will rise to nearly two-thirds of the worlds
population. 44
II (C)
The Inevitability of Use and Increasing
Dependency on the Internet
Contemporary developments also challenge the nature of internet use.
No longer are we confined to a desktop computer to access information on
the internet. There are more mobile and wireless broadband subscriptions.
As of 2011, the number of networked devices 45 has exceeded the global
39

40
41

42

43

44
45

Some call this generativity, i.e. a systems capacity to produce unanticipated change through
unfiltered contributions from broad and varied audiences. J. L. ZITTRAIN, THE FUTURE OF THE
INTERNET AND HOW TO STOP IT 70 (2008).
J. L. ZITTRAIN, THE FUTURE OF THE INTERNET AND HOW TO STOP IT (2008).
Brief History of the Internet <http://www.internetsociety.org/internet/what-internet/historyinternet/brief-history-internet> (visited October 16, 2013).
D. MACLEAN, Herding Schrdingers Cats: Some Conceptual Tools For Thinking About Internet
Governance, Background Paper for the ITU Workshop on Internet Governance, Geneva, February 2627, 2004, 8 <http://www.itu.int/osg/spu/forum/intgov04/contributions/itu-workshop-feb-04-internetgovernance-background.pdf> (visited October 16, 2013).
Measuring the Information Society 2012, International Telecommunication Union, 2012, Geneva,
Switzerland,
6-7
<http://www.itu.int/en/ITUD/Statistics/Documents/publications/mis2012/MIS2012_without_Annex_4.pdf> (visited October 16,
2013). The International Telecommunication Union (ITU) is the United Nations specialized agency
for information and communication technologies (ICTs).
Id. at 10.
In the Internet of things, objects such as household appliances, vehicles, power and water meters,
medicines or even personal belongings such as clothes, will be capable of being assigned an IP
address, and of identifying themselves and communicating using technology such as RFID and NFC.
Comprehensive Study on Cybercrime prepared by United Nations Office on Drugs and Crime for the
Intergovernmental
Expert
Group
on
Cybercrime,
February
2013,
2

Dissenting & Concurring

12

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

population. By 2020, this disparity of connected devices as opposed to


connected individuals is expected to escalate to a ratio of six to one. 46
Today, individuals may have all or a combination of a desktop, a mobile
laptop, a tablet, several smart mobile phones, a smart television, and a
version of an Xbox or a PlayStation or gaming devices that may connect to
the internet. It is now common to find homes with Wi-Fi routers having
broadband connection to the internet.
This reality has increased the density of communication among
individuals. A July 2011 study reported that every day, 294 billion electronic
mails (emails) and 5 billion phone messages are exchanged worldwide. 47
Another survey yielded the following: 48
Global

Philippines

Percentage of respondents who said they access the Internet 89%


many or several times a day

78%

Percentage of respondents who used e-mail at least once a day

87%

79%

Percentage of respondents who used social media at least once 60%


a day

72%

Percentage of respondents who used instant messaging at least 43%


once a day

51%

The accelerating rate of increase of internet users is relevant to


developing countries like the Philippines. Reports reveal that, as of 2011,
[i]nternet user growth was higher in developing (16 per cent) than
developed (5 per cent) countries. 49 Thus, [i]nternet user penetration rates
in developing countries have tripled over the past five years, and the
developing countries share of the worlds total number of Internet users has

46
47

48

49

<http://www.unodc.org/documents/commissions/CCPCJ_session22/1380699_Ebook_2013_study_CRP5.pdf> (visited October 16, 2013).


Id.
Issues Monitor: Cyber Crime--A Growing Challenge for Governments, KPMG International 2014, 2
<http://www.kpmg.com/Global/en/IssuesAndInsights/ArticlesPublications/Documents/cybercrime.pdf> (visited October 16, 2013).
The Global Internet User Survey is [a] worldwide survey of more than 10,000 Internet users in 20
countries conducted by the Internet Society revealed attitudes towards the Internet and user behavior
online. The Global Internet User Survey is one of the broadest surveys of Internet user attitudes on key
issues facing the Internet. This year's survey covered areas such as how users manage personal
information online, attitudes toward the Internet and human rights, censorship, and the potential for the
Internet to address issues such as economic development and education. The results are available at
<https://www.Internetsociety.org/news/global-Internet-user-survey-reveals-attitudes-usage-andbehavior> (visited October 16, 2013). See also Global Internet User Survey 2012
<https://www.Internetsociety.org/sites/default/files/GIUS2012-GlobalData-Table-20121120_0.pdf>
(visited October 16, 2013).
Measuring the Information Society 2012, International Telecommunication Union, 2012, Geneva,
Switzerland,
7
<http://www.itu.int/en/ITUD/Statistics/Documents/publications/mis2012/MIS2012_without_Annex_4.pdf> (visited October 16,
2013).

Dissenting & Concurring

13

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

increased, from 44 per cent in 2006 to 62 per cent in 2011. 50 Consistent


with this accelerating trend, the internet-user penetration rate for developing
countries stood at 24% at the end of 2011; the estimates are that this will
double by 2015. 51 There are more citizens in developing countries using the
internet. The share, in internet traffic, by developing countries, has also
increased as compared with developed countries.
The attitude of users shows a marked trend towards dependence. A
survey showed that the internet is viewed by its users as playing a positive
role; not only for individual lives but also for society at large. Moreover, the
internet has come to be perceived as somewhat of an imperative. Of its many
findings, the following data from the 2012 Global Internet Survey are
particularly notable: 52
Percentage
of
respondents who
agreed or agreed
strongly

Percentage
of
respondents who
agreed or agreed
strongly

(GLOBAL)

(PHILIPPINES)

The Internet does more to help society than it does to 83%


hurt it

91%

Their lives have improved due to using the Internet

85%

93%

The Internet is essential to their knowledge and 89%


education

96%

The Internet can play a significant role in:

50
51
52

1. Increasing global trade and economic 81%


relationships among countries
2. Achieving universal primary school education 76%

95%

3. Promoting gender equality

70%

89%

4. Protecting the environment

74%

92%

5. Helping to combat serious diseases

72%

92%

6. Eliminating extreme poverty and hunger

61%

75%

7. Improving maternal health

65%

84%

8. Reducing child mortality

63%

80%

9. Improving emergency response and assistance 77%


during natural disasters

92%

91%

Id.
Id. at 10.
Global Internet User Survey 2012 <https://www.Internetsociety.org/sites/default/files/GIUS2012GlobalData-Table-20121120_0.pdf> (visited October 16, 2013).

Dissenting & Concurring

14

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion
10. Preventing the trafficking of women and 69%
children
11. Improving the quality of education
80%

84%

12. Improving social problems by increasing 76%


communication between and among various
groups in society
13. Reducing rural and remote community 80%
isolation
14. Keeping local experts in or bringing experts 75%
back to their country because they can use
technology to create business

93%

95%

96%
94%

Of more pronounced legal significance are the following findings: 53


Percentage
of
respondents who
agreed or agreed
strongly

Percentage
of
respondents
who
agreed or agreed
strongly

(GLOBAL)

(PHILIPPINES)

The Internet should be considered a basic human 83%


right

88%

Their respective governments have an obligation to 80%


ensure that they have the opportunity to access the
Internet

85%

Freedom of expression should be guaranteed on the 86%


Internet

86%

Services such as social media enhance their right to 80%


peaceful assembly and association

91%

The relationship of internet use and growth in the economy has


likewise been established. The significance of the internet is as real as it is
perceived, thus:
Research by the World Bank suggests that a 10% increase in
broadband penetration could boost GDP by 1.38% in low- and middleincome countries. 54 More specifically, it cited that, in the Philippines,
[m]obile broadband adoption was found to contribute an annual 0.32% of
GDP, [representing] 6.9% of all GDP growth for the economy during the
past decade. 55
53
54

55

Id.
The State of Broadband 2012: Achieving Digital Inclusion for All, Report prepared by the
Broadband
Commission
for
Digital
Development,
September
2012,
23
<http://www.broadbandcommission.org/documents/bb-annualreport2012.pdf> (visited October 16,
2013).
As cited by the Broadband Commission for Digital Development in The State of Broadband 2012:
Achieving Digital Inclusion for All. The Broadband Commission was set up by the ITU and the
United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organization (UNESCO) pursuant to the

Dissenting & Concurring

15

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

II (D)
The Dangers in the Internet
While the internet has engendered innovation and growth, it has also
engendered new types of disruption. A noted expert employs an
evolutionary metaphor as he asserts:
[Generative technologies] encourage mutations, branchings away from
the status quosome that are curious dead ends, others that spread like
wildre. They invite disruptionalong with the good things and bad
things that can come with such disruption. 56

Addressing the implications of disruption, he adds:


Disruption benets some while others lose, and the power of the
generative Internet, available to anyone with a modicum of knowledge
and a broadband connection, can be turned to network-destroying ends. x
x x [T]he Internets very generativity combined with that of the PCs
attached sows the seeds for a digital Pearl Harbor. 57

The internet is an infrastructure that allows for a network of


networks. 58 It is also a means for several purposes. As with all other
means enhancing capabilities of human interaction, 59 it can be used to
facilitate benefits as well as nefarious ends. The internet can be a means for
criminal activity.
Parallel to the unprecedented escalation of the use of the internet and
its various technologies is also an escalation in what has been termed as
cybercrimes. As noted in the 2010 Salvador Declaration on Comprehensive
Strategies for Global Challenges, annexed to United Nations General
Assembly resolution 65/230:

56
57

58

59

Millennium Development Goals (MDGs), 78 <http://www.broadbandcommission.org/documents/bbannualreport2012.pdf> (visited October 16, 2013).


J. L. ZITTRAIN, THE FUTURE OF THE INTERNET AND HOW TO STOP IT 96-97 (2008).
The term is said to have been coined in 1991 by D. James Bidzos, the then-president of RSA Data
Security, when he said that the governments digital signature standard provided no assurance that
foreign governments cannot break the system, running the risk of a digital Pearl Harbor. x x x The
term has since become prominent in public debate, being employed most notably by former member of
the National Security Council Richard A. Clarke. J. L. ZITTRAIN, THE FUTURE OF THE INTERNET AND
HOW TO STOP IT 97 and 275 (2008).
D. MACLEAN, Herding Schrdingers Cats: Some Conceptual Tools For Thinking About Internet
Governance, Background Paper for the ITU Workshop on Internet Governance, Geneva, February 2627, 2004, 8 <http://www.itu.int/osg/spu/forum/intgov04/contributions/itu-workshop-feb-04-internetgovernance-background.pdf> (visited October 16, 2013).
Comprehensive Study on Cybercrime prepared by United Nations Office on Drugs and Crime for the
Intergovernmental
Expert
Group
on
Cybercrime,
February
2013,
5
<http://www.unodc.org/documents/commissions/CCPCJ_session22/1380699_Ebook_2013_study_CRP5.pdf> (visited October 16, 2013).

16

Dissenting & Concurring

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion
[The] development of information and communications technologies and
the increasing use of the Internet create new opportunities for offenders
and facilitate the growth of crime. 60

Also as observed elsewhere:


Over the past few years, the global cyber crime landscape has changed
dramatically, with criminals employing more sophisticated technology and
greater knowledge of cyber security. Until recently, malware, spam emails,
hacking into corporate sites and other attacks of this nature were mostly the work
of computer geniuses showcasing their talent. These attacks, which were rarely
malicious, have gradually evolved into cyber crime syndicates siphoning off
money through illegal cyber channels. By 2010, however, politically motivated
cyber crime had penetrated global cyberspace. In fact, weaponry and command
and control systems have also transitioned into the cyberspace to deploy and
execute espionage and sabotage, as seen in the example of digital espionage
attacks on computer networks at Lockheed Martin and NASA. 61

Computer-related criminal activity is not peculiar to the 21st


century. 62 One of the first reported major instances of cybercrime was in
2000 when the mass-mailed I Love You Worm (which originated from
Pandacan, Manila) 63 affected nearly 45 million computer users
worldwide. 64 This entailed as much as US$ 15 billion to repair the damage.
Cyber attacks have morphed into myriad forms. The following is just a
summary of some of the known attacks: 65
Type of Attack

Details

Viruses and worms

Viruses and worms are computer programs that affect the storage
devices of a computer or network, which then replicate information
without the knowledge of the user.

Spam emails

Spam emails are unsolicited emails or junk newsgroup postings. Spam


emails are sent without the consent of the receiver potentially

60
61

62

63

64

65

Id. at 6-7.
Issues Monitor: Cyber Crime--A Growing Challenge for Governments, KPMG International 2014, 3
<http://www.kpmg.com/Global/en/IssuesAndInsights/ArticlesPublications/Documents/cybercrime.pdf> (visited October 16, 2013), citing National insecurity, Information Age, January 26, 2011
and Stuxnet was about what happened next, FT.com, February 16, 2011.
In 1994, the United Nations Manual on the Prevention and Control of Computer Related Crime noted
that fraud by computer manipulation; computer forgery; damage to or modifications of computer data
or programs; unauthorized access to computer systems and service; and unauthorized reproduction of
legally protected computer programs were common types of computer crime. Comprehensive Study
on Cybercrime prepared by United Nations Office on Drugs and Crime for the Intergovernmental
Expert
Group
on
Cybercrime,
February
2013,
5
<http://www.unodc.org/documents/commissions/CCPCJ_session22/13
80699_Ebook_2013_study_CRP5.pdf> (visited October 16, 2013).
Love bug hacker is Pandacan man, 23 <http://www.philstar.com/networks/83717/love-bug-hackerpandacan-man-23> (visited October 16, 2013).
Issues Monitor: Cyber Crime--A Growing Challenge for Governments, KPMG International 2014, 2
<http://www.kpmg.com/Global/en/IssuesAndInsights/ArticlesPublications/Documents/cybercrime.pdf> (visited October 16, 2013).
Id. at 2, citing Cyber attacks: from Facebook to nuclear weapons, The Telegraph, February 4, 2011; A
Good Decade for Cybercrime, McAfee, 2010; Spamhaus on March 10, 2011; PCMeg.com on March
10, 2011; and The cost of cybercrime, Detica, February 2011.

Dissenting & Concurring

17

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion
creating a wide range of problems if they are not filtered appropriately.
Trojan

A Trojan is a program that appears legitimate. However, once run, it


moves on to locate password information or makes the system more
vulnerable to future entry. Or a Trojan may simply destroy programs or
data on the hard disk.

Denial-of-service
(DoS)

DoS occurs when criminals attempt to bring down or cripple individual


websites, computers or networks, often by flooding them with
messages.

Malware

Malware is a software that takes control of any individuals computer


to spread a bug to other peoples devices or social networking profiles.
Such software can also be used to create a botnet a network of
computers controlled remotely by hackers, known as herders, to
spread spam or viruses.

Scareware

Using fear tactics, some cyber criminals compel users to download


certain software. While such software is usually presented as antivirus
software, after some time, these programs start attacking the users
system. The user then has to pay the criminals to remove such viruses.

Phishing

Phishing attacks are designed to steal a persons login and password.


For instance, the phisher can access the victims bank accounts or
assume control of their social network.

Fiscal fraud

By targeting official online payment channels, cyber attackers can


hamper processes such as tax collection or make fraudulent claims for
benefits.

State cyber attacks

Experts believe that some government agencies may also be using


cyber attacks as a new means of warfare. One such attack occurred in
2010, when a computer virus called Stuxnet was used to carry out an
invisible attack on Irans secret nuclear program. The virus was aimed
at disabling Irans uranium enrichment centrifuges.

Carders

Stealing bank or credit card details is another major cyber crime.


Duplicate cards are then used to withdraw cash at ATMs or in shops.

The shift from wired to mobile devices has also brought with it the
escalation of attacks on mobile devices. As reported by IT security group
McAfee, [t]he number of pieces of new mobile malware in 2010 increased
by 46 percent compared with 2009. 66 Hackers have also increased targeting
mobile devices using Apples iOS and Googles Android systems as these
increased their market share. As McAfee put it, cybercriminals are keeping
tabs on whats popular. 67

66

67

McAfee Q4 Threat Report Identifies New Attacks on Mobile Devices; Malware Growth at All-Time
High <http://www.mcafee.com/mx/about/news/2011/q1/20110208-01.aspx> (visited October 16,
2013).
Id.

Dissenting & Concurring

18

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

Cybercrimes come at tremendous costs. A report notes that [i]n the


US over the course of one year in 2009, the amount of information lost to
cyber crime nearly doubled, from US$265 million in 2008 to US$560
million x x x. 68 In the United Kingdom, the annual cost arising from
cybercrime was estimated at GBP27 billion (US$ 43 billion). Of this
amount, intellectual property theft accounts for GBP9.2 billion (US$ 14
billion), while espionage activities account for more than GBP7 billion (US$
11 billion). 69 In Germany, a joint report by the information technology trade
group Bitkom and the German Federal Criminal Police Office estimates
phishing to have increased 70 percent year on year in 2010, resulting in a
loss of as much as EUR 17 million (US$ 22 million). 70
The costs in the Philippines are certainly present, but the revelation of
its magnitude awaits research that may come as a result of the
implementation of the Cybercrime Prevention Act of 2012.
Another report summarizes the costs to government as follows: 71
1.
-

Costs in anticipation of cyber crime


Security measures, such as antiviral software installation, cost of
insurance and IT security standards maintenance.

2.
-

Costs as a consequence of cyber crime


Monetary losses to organizations, such as gaps in business
continuity and losses due to IP theft.

3.
-

Costs in response to cyber crime


Paying regulatory fines and compensations to victims of identity
theft, and cost associated with investigation of the crime.

4.
-

Indirect costs associated with cyber crime


Costs resulting from reputational damage to organizations and
loss of confidence in cyber transactions.

II (E)
The Challenges for
Internet Governance
All these have triggered spirited discussion on what has been termed
as internet governance or internet/cyberspace regulation.
Particularly challenging are the jurisdictional challenges that virtual
computer networks posed to territorially constituted nation states x x
68

69
70
71

Issues Monitor: Cyber Crime--A Growing Challenge for Governments, KPMG International 2014, 6
<http://www.kpmg.com/Global/en/IssuesAndInsights/ArticlesPublications/Documents/cybercrime.pdf> (visited October 16, 2013)
Id., citing The cost of cybercrime, Detica, February 2011.
Id., citing Cybercrime in Germany on the rise, DW World, September 7, 2010.
Id., citing The cost of cybercrime, Cabinet Office (UK), February 2011.

Dissenting & Concurring

19

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

x. 72John Perry Barlow, for example, proclaimed in his Declaration of the


Independence of Cyberspace:
Governments of the Industrial World, you weary giants of flesh and
steel, I come from Cyberspace, the new home of Mind. On behalf of the
future, I ask you of the past to leave us alone. You are not welcome
among us. You have no sovereignty where we gather. 73

Many have considered the internet as ungovernable, 74 having the


ability to undermine traditional forms of governance, 75 and radically
subvert[ing] a system of rule-making based on borders between physical
spaces, at least with respect to the claim that cyberspace should naturally be
governed by territorially defined rules. 76
Adding to the complexity of internet regulation is the private character
of the internet as manifested in: (1) the ownership and operation of internet
infrastructure; and (2) the organizational framework of the internet. This
private character, in turn, gives rise to pressing questions on legitimacy and
accountability.
The United Nations Office on Drugs and Crime (UNODC) describes
the private ownership and operation of internet infrastructure as follows:
A significant proportion of internet infrastructure is owned and operated
by the private sector. Internet access requires a passive infrastructure layer of
trenches, ducts, optical fibre, mobile base stations, and satellite hardware. It also
requires an active infrastructure layer of electronic equipment, and a service
layer of content services and applications.
xxxx
As an infrastructure, the internets growth can be compared to the
development of roads, railways, and electricity, which are dependent on private
sector investment, construction and maintenance, but regulated and incentivized
by national governments. At the same time, the internet is often regarded as more
private-sector led. 77

72

73
74
75
76

77

M. Ziewitz and I. Brown, A Prehistory of Internet Governance, in RESEARCH HANDBOOK ON


GOVERNANCE OF THE INTERNET 27 (2013). Available at <http://ssrn.com/abstract=1844720 (visited
October 16, 2013).
Id.
Id.
Id.
Johnson, D. R. and D. Post (1995), 'Law and borders: The rise of law in cyberspace', Stan. L. Rev.,48,
1367, cited in M. Ziewitz and I. Brown, A Prehistory of Internet Governance, in RESEARCH
HANDBOOK
ON
GOVERNANCE
OF
THE
INTERNET
27
(2013).
Available
at
<http://ssrn.com/abstract=1844720 (visited October 16, 2013).
Comprehensive Study on Cybercrime prepared by United Nations Office on Drugs and Crime for the
Intergovernmental
Expert
Group
on
Cybercrime,
February
2013,
3-4
<http://www.unodc.org/documents/commissions/CCPCJ_session22/1380699_Ebook_2013_study_CRP5.pdf> (visited October 16, 2013).

Dissenting & Concurring

20

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

As to the organizational framework of the internet, a professor writes:


As far as the organizational framework of the Internet is concerned, the
present system is mainly designed by private bodies and organizations, i.e. a
self-regulatory system applies in reality. Thereby, the key player is the Internet
Corporation for Assigned Names and Numbers (ICANN), being in place since
November 1998. 78

There are private bodies and organizations that exist for the purpose of
regulation. There are commercial entities vendors and service providers
that emerge as de facto regulators. A noted expert observes that an
increasing response has been the creation of devices and services which rely
on a continuing relationship with vendors and service providers who are then
accountable for ensuring security and privacy. 79 There is now a marked
tendency to resort to sterile appliances tethered to a network of control. 80
This may stunt the very capacity to produce unanticipated change through
unfiltered contributions from broad and varied audiences. 81 It is these
unanticipated changes which facilitated the internets rise to ubiquity.
The fear is that too much reliance on commercial vendors and their
standards and technologies transfers control over the all important internet
from innovation from varied sources. In a way, it stunts democratic
creativity of an important media.
On the other end, states have consciously started more legal
intervention. As observed by the United Nations Office on Drugs and Crime:
Legal measures play a key role in the prevention and combating of
cybercrime. Law is [a] dynamic tool that enables the state to respond to new
societal and security challenges, such as the appropriate balance between privacy
and crime control, or the extent of liability of corporations that provide services.
In addition to national laws, at the international level, the law of nations
international law covers relations between states in all their myriad forms.
Provisions in both national laws and international law are relevant to
cybercrime. 82

At the normative level, legal measures address, if not negate,


apprehensions of legitimacy, consent, and accountability. Functionally, legal
measures are vital in:

78

79
80
81
82

R. H. Weber, Accountability in Internet Governance, University of Zurich Professor, 154


<http://ijclp.net/files/ijclp_web-doc_8-13-2009.pdf> (visited October 16, 2013).
J. L. ZITTRAIN, THE FUTURE OF THE INTERNET AND HOW TO STOP IT (2008).
Id. at 3.
Id. at 70.
Comprehensive Study on Cybercrime prepared by United Nations Office on Drugs and Crime for the
Intergovernmental
Expert
Group
on
Cybercrime,
February
2013,
51
<http://www.unodc.org/documents/commissions/CCPCJ_session22/1380699_Ebook_2013_study_CRP5.pdf> (visited October 16, 2013).

Dissenting & Concurring

21

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion
1. Setting clear standards of behavior for the use of computer devices;
2. Deterring perpetrators and protecting citizens;
3. Enabling law enforcement investigations while protecting individual
privacy;
4. Providing fair and effective criminal justice procedures;
5. Requiring minimum protection standards in areas such as data handling
and retention; and
6. Enabling cooperation between countries in criminal matters involving
cybercrime and electronic evidence. 83

In performing these functions, legal measures must adapt to emerging


exigencies. This includes the emergence of a virtual, rather than physical,
field of governance. It also includes specific approaches for specific acts and
specific technologies. Effective internet governance through law cannot be
approached too generally or in the abstract:
The technological developments associated with cybercrime mean that
while traditional laws can be applied to some extent legislation must also
grapple with new concepts and objects, not traditionally addressed by law. In
many states, laws on technical developments date back to the 19th century. These
laws were, and to a great extent, still are, focused on physical objects around
which the daily life of industrial society revolved. For this reason, many
traditional general laws do not take into account the particularities of information
and information technology that are associated with cybercrime and crimes
generating electronic evidence. These acts are largely characterized by new
intangible objects, such as data or information.
xxxx
This raises the question of whether cybercrime should be covered by
general, existing criminal law provisions, or whether new, computer-specific
offences are required. The question cannot be answered generally, but rather
depends upon the nature of individual acts, and the scope and interpretation
of national laws. 84 (Emphasis provided)

II (F)
The Lack of a Universal
Policy Consensus: Political
Nature of the Content of
Cybercrime Legislation
The description of the acts in cyberspace which relates to new
concepts and objects, not traditionally addressed by law 85 challenges the
very concept of crimes. This is of preeminent significance as there can be no
83
84
85

Id. at 52.
Id. at 51-52.
Id. at 51.

Dissenting & Concurring

22

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

crime where there is no law punishing an act (nullum crimen, nulla poena
sine lege). 86
The Comprehensive Study on Cybercrime prepared by UNODC for
the Intergovernmental Expert Group on Cybercrime, February 2013, reports
that a survey of almost 200 pieces of national legislation fails to establish a
clear definition of cybercrime. If at all, domestic laws tend to evade having
to use the term cybercrime altogether:
Out of almost 200 items of national legislation cited by countries in
response to the Study questionnaire, fewer than five per cent used the
word cybercrime in the title or scope of legislative provisions. Rather,
legislation more commonly referred to computer crimes, electronic
communications, information technologies, or high-tech crime. In
practice, many of these pieces of legislation created criminal offences
that are included in the concept of cybercrime, such as unauthorized
access to a computer system, or interference with a computer system or
data. Where national legislation did specifically use cybercrime in the
title of an act or section (such as Cybercrime Act), the definitional
section of the legislation rarely included a definition for the word
cybercrime. When the term cybercrime was included as a legal
definition, a common approach was to define it simply as the crimes
referred to in this law. 87

International or regional legal instruments are also important for states


because they articulate a consensus, established or emerging, among several
jurisdictions. With respect to international or legal instruments however, the
United Nations Office on Drugs and Crime notes the same lack of a
conceptual consensus as to what makes cybercrimes:
In a similar manner, very few international or regional legal instruments
define cybercrime. Neither the Council of Europe Cybercrime Convention, the
League of Arab States Convention, nor the Draft African Union Convention, for
example, contains a definition of cybercrime for the purposes of the instrument.
The Commonwealth of Independent States Agreement, without using the term
cybercrime, defines an offence relating to computer information as a
criminal act of which the target is computer information. Similarly, the
Shanghai Cooperation Organization Agreement defines information offences
as the use of information resources and (or) the impact on them in the
informational sphere for illegal purposes. 88

More than defining the term cybercrime, international legal


instruments list acts which may be considered as falling under the broad
umbrella of cybercrimes. As surveyed in 'The Comprehensive Study on
Cybercrime prepared by UNODC for the Intergovernmental Expert Group
on Cybercrime, February 2013,' there are sixteen (16) international or
regional instruments which exist with the objective of countering
86
87
88

Id. at 53.
Id. at 11-12.
Id. at 12.

23

Dissenting & Concurring

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

cybercrime. The UNODC notes that nine (9) of these instruments are
binding, 89 while seven (7) are non-binding. 90 In all, these instruments
include a total of eighty-two (82) countries which have signed and/or ratified
them. Of these, it is the Council of Europe Cybercrime Convention which
has the widest coverage: Forty-eight (48) countries, 91 including five (5) nonmember states of the Council of Europe, have ratified and/or acceded to it.
Other instruments have significantly smaller scopes. For example, the
League of Arab States Convention only included eighteen (18) countries or
territories; the Commonwealth of Independent States Agreement, with ten
(10) countries; and the Shanghai Cooperation Organization Agreement, with
six (6) countries. 92

89
90
91
92

93

94
95

96

97

98

99

100

101

102

103

ITU / CARICOM
/ CTU (Model
Legislative
Texts 104
League of Arab
States
(Convention) 105
League of Arab
States
(Model
Law) 106
Shanghai
Cooperation
Organization 107
United
Nations
(CRC OP) 108

(Directive
2011/92/EU and
2002/58/EC) 103

(Directive
Framewrok
Decision
2001/413/JHA) 102
European Union

European Union

European
Union
(Directive
Proposal
2010/0273) 101

European
Union
(Framework Decision
100
2005/222/JHA)

ECOWAS 99

Council of Europe
(Lanzarote
Convention) 98

Council of Europe
(Budapest
Convention) 97

The
Commonwealth 95

COMESA 94

African Union 93

Criminalized Act

Commonwealth of
Independent
States 96

Surveying these sixteen (16) instruments, the United Nations Office


on Drugs and Crime summarizes acts of cybercrimes vis-a-vis the
instruments (and specific provisions of such instruments) covering each act
as follows:

Id. at 64.
Id.
Id. at 67.
Comprehensive Study on Cybercrime prepared by United Nations Office on Drugs and Crime for the
Intergovernmental
Expert
Group
on
Cybercrime,
February
2013,
64
<http://www.unodc.org/documents/commissions/CCPCJ_session22/1380699_Ebook_2013_study_CRP5.pdf> (visited October 16, 2013).
African Union, 2012. Draft Convention on the Establishment of a Legal Framework Conducive to
Cybersecurity in Africa.
Common Market for Eastern and Southern Africa (COMESA), 2011. Cybersecurity Draft Model Bill.
The Commonwealth, 2002. (i) Computer and Computer Related Crimes Bill and (ii) Model Law on
Electronic Evidence.
Commonwealth of Independent States, 2001. Agreement on Cooperation in Combating Offences
related to Computer Information.
Council of Europe, 2001. Convention on Cybercrime and Additional Protocol to the Convention on
Cybercrime, concerning the criminalisation of acts of a racist and xenophobic nature committed
through computer systems.
Council of Europe, 2007. Convention on the Protection of Children against Sexual Exploitation and
Sexual Abuse.
Economic Community of West African States (ECOWAS), 2009. Draft Directive on Fighting
Cybercrime within ECOWAS.
European Union, 2005. Council Framework Decision 2002/222/JHA on attacks against information
systems.
European Union, 2010. Proposal COM (2010) 517 final for a Directive of the European Parliament and
of the Council on attacks against information systems and repealing Council Framework Decision
2005/222/JHA.
European Union, 2001. Council Framework Decision 2001/413/JHA combating fraud and
counterfeiting of non-cash means of payment.
European Union, 2011. Directive 2011/92/EU of the European Parliament and of the Council on
combating the sexual abuse and sexual exploitation of children and child pornography, and replacing
Council Framework Decision 2004/68/JHA and European Union, 2002. Directive 2002/58/EC of the
European Parliament and of the Council concerning the processing of personal data and the protection
of privacy in the electronic communications sector.

24

Dissenting & Concurring

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion
1

Illegal access to Art. Art. Art. 5


a
computer
18 and 7
system
III and
(15) 19

Art. 2

Art. Art.
2 2(1)
and
3

Art. 3

Art. 4 and Art. 6 Art. 3,


5
5, 15
and 22

Art. 6

Art. 6 and Art. 6, Art. 3


8
7 and and 8
18

III
(16)

Illegal access,
interception or
acquisition of
computer data

Art. Art. Art. 5 Art. 3 (1) Art. 2


and 3
III 19 and 8 (a)
(23) and
21

Art.
6

Illegal
intereference
with computer
data

Art. Art. Art. 6 Art. 3 (1) Art. 4


(c)
III 20
(19) and
,
22(a
(20) )
and
(24)

Art. Art. 4 Art. 5 Art. 3


5
and
7

Art. 7

Art. 8 Art. 6

Illegal
intereference
with a computer
system

Art. Art. Art. 7 Art. 3 (1) Art. 5


(c)
III 22
(18) (a)
and
(19)

Art. Art. 3 Art. 4 Art. 3


4

Art. 9

Art. 6 Art. 7

Computer
misuse tools

Art. Art. Art. 9 Art. 3 (1) Art. 6


(b)
III 22
(22) (b)
and
(c)

Art. Art. 5 Art. 7 Art. 4


12

Art. 10

Art. 9

Breach of
privacy or data
protection
measures

Art.
III
(27)
and
(54)

Computerrelated forgery

Art. Art.
III 23
(24)
and
(25)

Art. 7

Art.
8

Art. 2 and 4

Art. 11

Art. 10 Art. 4
and 18

Computerrelated fraud

Art. Art.
III 24
(25) (a)
,
and
(26) (b)
and
(41)

Art. 8

Art.
9,
10
and
23

Art. 2 and 4

Art. 12

Art. 11 Art. 10,


11 and
12

Electronic
payment tools
offenses

Art. 3

Art. 2

10 Identity-related
crime
11 Computerrelated copyright
and trademark
offenses

104

105
106

107

108

Art. 15 (a) (1)

Art.
11

Art. 18 Art. 11

Art. 14

Art. 3 (1) Art. 10


(d)

Art. 17 Art. 14

International Telecommunication Union (ITU)/Caribbean Community (CARICOM)/Caribbean


Telecommunications Union (CTU), 2010. (i) Model Legislative Texts on Cybercrime/e-Crimes and (ii)
Electronic Evidence.
League of Arab States, 2010. Arab Convention on Combating Information Technology Offences.
League of Arab States, 2004. Model Arab Law on Combating Offences related to Information
Technology Systems.
Shanghai Cooperation Organization, 2010. Agreement on Cooperation in the Field of International
Information Security.
United Nations, 2000. Optional Protocol to the Convention on the Rights of the Child on the sale of
children, child prostitution, and child pornography.

25

Dissenting & Concurring

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion
12 Spam

Art. 13 (3)

Art.
19
(g)

13 Computerrelated
harassment,
extortion or acts
causing personal
harm

Art. Art.
III 25
(40)
and
(41)

14 Computerrelated acts
involving racism
or xenophobia

Art.
III
(34)
,
(35)
and
(36)

Art. 18

15 ComputerArt.
related denial or III
justification of (37)
genocide or
crimes against
humanity
16 Computerrelated
production,
distribution, or
possession of
child
pornography

Art.
III
(29)
,
(30)
,
(31)
and
(32)

Art.
10

Art. 3, 4,
5 (OP)

Art.
18,
19
and
20

Art. 6
(OP)

Art.
21

Art. 9

17 Computerrelated
solicitation or
grooming of
children
18 Computerrelated acts in
support of
terrorism

Art. 15

Art. 20

Art. 5

Art,
14,
15,
16
and
17

Art. 23

Art. 13

Art. 9

Art. 12

Art. 6

Art. 15 Art. 21

Art. Art.
III 18,
(40) 19,
20
and
22
(a)

19 Computerrelated offenses
involving money
laundering

Art. 15 Art. 19

20 Computerrelated offenses
involving illicit
trafficking

Art. 16 Art. 17
and 18

21 Computerrelated offenses
against public
order, morality
or security

Art.
14,
15,
16
and
17

22 Law
Art.
enforcement
III
(54)
investigationrelated offenses

Art.
13
and
21

Art. 16
(3), 20
(3) and
21 (3)

Art. 16
and 17

23 Aggravating
Art.
circumstances III
for conventional (40)
crime committed
by means of a
computer system
24 Attempt and
aiding or

Art. 12, Art. 13,


13, 14 16 and
and 15 20

Art. 21

Art.
22

Art.
26

Art. 11
and 7

Art. 24

Art. 23
(3), 28
(3) and
29 (3)

Art. 8

Art. 3

26

Dissenting & Concurring

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion
abetting
25 Corporate
liability

(OP)
Art.
27

Art. 12

Art. 26

Informed by the various approaches and challenges to defining


cybercrime, 'The Comprehensive Study on Cybercrime prepared by
UNODC for the Intergovernmental Expert Group on Cybercrime, February
2013' suggests that cybercrime is best considered as a collection of acts
or conduct. 109 Thus, in a manner consistent with the approach adopted by
international instruments such as the United Nations Convention Against
Corruption, 110 it identifies a list, or basket, of acts which could constitute
cybercrime. 111 The list, however, is tentative and not exhaustive, provided
with a view to establishing a basis for analysis, 112 rather than to represent
legal definitions. 113 These acts are organized in three broad categories, 114
as follows:
1. Acts against the confidentiality, integrity and availability of
computer data or systems
a. Illegal access to a computer system
b. Illegal access, interception or acquisition of computer data
c. Illegal interference with a computer system or computer data
d. Production, distribution or possession of computer misuse tools
e. Breach of privacy or data protection measures
2. Computer-related acts for personal or financial gain or harm
a. Computer-related fraud or forgery
b. Computer-related identity offences
c. Computer-related copyright or trademark offences
d. Sending or controlling sending of Spam
e. Computer-related acts causing personal harm
f. Computer-related solicitation or 'grooming' of children
3. Computer content-related acts
a. Computer-related acts involving hate speech
b. Computer-related production, distribution or possession of child
pornography
109

110

111
112
113
114

Comprehensive Study on Cybercrime prepared by United Nations Office on Drugs and Crime for the
Intergovernmental
Expert
Group
on
Cybercrime,
February
2013,
12
<http://www.unodc.org/documents/commissions/CCPCJ_session22/1380699_Ebook_2013_study_CRP5.pdf> (visited October 16, 2013).
The United Nations Convention Against Corruption does not define corruption, but rather obliges
States Parties to criminalize a specific set of conduct which can be more effectively described.
Comprehensive Study on Cybercrime prepared by United Nations Office on Drugs and Crime for the
Intergovernmental
Expert
Group
on
Cybercrime,
February
2013,
12
<http://www.unodc.org/documents/commissions/CCPCJ_session22/1380699_Ebook_2013_study_CRP5.pdf> (visited October 16, 2013).
Id.
Id. at 16.
Id.
Id.

27

Dissenting & Concurring

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

c. Computer-related acts in support of terrorism offences 115


Apart from the conceptual and definitional mooring of cybercrimes,
equally significant are the procedural powers including search, seizure,
orders for computer data, real-time collection of computer data, and
preservation of data x x x. 116 As noted by the United Nations Office on
Drugs and Crime, these procedural powers, along with the criminalization of
certain acts and obligations for international cooperation, form the core
provisions shared by international and legal instruments. 117

115
116
117
118

119
120

121

122

123

124

125

126

127

128

129

130
131

132

133

League
of
Arab
States
(Model Law) 131
Shanghai
Cooperation
Organization 132
United Nations
(CRC OP) 133

League of Arab States


(Convention) 130

ITU / CARICOM / CTU


(Model
Legislative
Texts 129

European Union
(Directive 2011/92/EU
and 2002/58/EC) 128

European Union
(Directive
Framewrok Decision
2001/413/JHA) 127

European Union
(Directive Proposal
2010/0273) 126

European Union
(Framework Decision
2005/222/JHA) 125

ECOWAS 124

Council of Europe
(Lanzarote
Convention) 123

Council of Europe
(Budapest
Convention) 122

The
Commonwealth 120

COMESA 119

African Union 118

Procedural Power

Commonwealth
of
Independent States 121

The United Nations Office on Drugs and Crimes survey of key


international and regional instruments summarizes each instruments
provision of procedural powers as follows:

Id.
Id. at 70.
Id.
African Union, 2012. Draft Convention on the Establishment of a Legal Framework Conducive to
Cybersecurity in Africa.
Common Market for Eastern and Southern Africa (COMESA), 2011. Cybersecurity Draft Model Bill.
The Commonwealth, 2002. (i) Computer and Computer Related Crimes Bill and (ii) Model Law on
Electronic Evidence.
Commonwealth of Independent States, 2001. Agreement on Cooperation in Combating Offences
related to Computer Information.
Council of Europe, 2001. Convention on Cybercrime and Additional Protocol to the Convention on
Cybercrime, concerning the criminalisation of acts of a racist and xenophobic nature committed
through computer systems.
Council of Europe, 2007. Convention on the Protection of Children against Sexual Exploitation and
Sexual Abuse.
Economic Community of West African States (ECOWAS), 2009. Draft Directive on Fighting
Cybercrime within ECOWAS.
European Union, 2005. Council Framework Decision 2002/222/JHA on attacks against information
systems.
European Union, 2010. Proposal COM (2010) 517 final for a Directive of the European Parliament and
of the Council on attacks against information systems and repealing Council Framework Decision
2005/222/JHA.
European Union, 2001. Council Framework Decision 2001/413/JHA combating fraud and
counterfeiting of non-cash means of payment.
European Union, 2011. Directive 2011/92/EU of the European Parliament and of the Council on
combating the sexual abuse and sexual exploitation of children and child pornography, and replacing
Council Framework Decision 2004/68/JHA and European Union, 2002. Directive 2002/58/EC of the
European Parliament and of the Council concerning the processing of personal data and the protection
of privacy in the electronic communications sector.
International Telecommunication Union (ITU)/Caribbean Community (CARICOM)/Caribbean
Telecommunications Union (CTU), 2010. (i) Model Legislative Texts on Cybercrime/e-Crimes and (ii)
Electronic Evidence.
League of Arab States, 2010. Arab Convention on Combating Information Technology Offences.
League of Arab States, 2004. Model Arab Law on Combating Offences related to Information
Technology Systems.
Shanghai Cooperation Organization, 2010. Agreement on Cooperation in the Field of International
Information Security.
United Nations, 2000. Optional Protocol to the Convention on the Rights of the Child on the sale of
children, child prostitution, and child pornography.

28

Dissenting & Concurring

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion
1

Search for computer Art. Art. Art. 12


hardware or data
III
37
(50) (a)
and
(b)

Art. 19
(1) and
(2)

Art.
33

Art. 20

Art. 26

Seizure of computer Art. Art. Art. 12


hardware or data
III
37 and 14
(51) (c)

Art. 19
(3)

Art.
33

Art. 20

Art. 27 (1)

Order for stored


computer date

Art. Art. 15
36
(a)

Art. 18
(1)(1)

Art. 22 (a) Art. 25 (1)

Order for subscriber


information

Art.
36
(b)

Art. 18
(1) (b)

Art. 22 (b) Art. 25 (2)

Order for stored


traffic data

Art. Art. 16
34
(a)
(ii)

Art. 17
(1) (b)

Art. 24

Art. 24

Real-time collection
of traffic data

Art. Art. 19
38

At. 20

Art. 25

Art. 28

Real-time collection Art. Art. Art. 18


of content-data
39
III
(55)

Art. 21

Art. 26

Art. 29

Expedited
preservation of
computer-data

Art. 23

Art. 23 (2)

Use of (remote)
forensic tools

10

Trans-border access
to computer data

Art.
49
(b)

Art. 32
(b)

11

Provision of
assistance

Art. Art. 13
37
(d)

Art. 19
(4)

12

Retention of
computer data

Art.
29,
30
and
31

Art. Art. Art. 17


III
33,
(53) 34
(a)
(i)
and
35

Art. 16,
17 (1) (a)

Art.
33

Art. 15

Art. 30
(5)

Art. 27

Art. 40 (2)

Art. 21

Art. 27 (2)

Art. 3
and 6

In the Philippines, Republic Act No. 10175 adopts an approach which


is similar to the UNODCs appreciation of cybercrimes as a collection of
acts or conduct. We have thus transplanted some of the provisions that are
still part of an emerging consensus. Thus, the Cybercrime Prevention Act of
2012 in question provides for the following basket of punishable acts:
CHAPTER II
PUNISHABLE ACTS
SEC. 4. Cybercrime Offenses. The following acts constitute the offense
of cybercrime punishable under this Act:

Dissenting & Concurring

29

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion
(a)
Offenses against the confidentiality, integrity and availability of
computer data and systems:
(1)

Illegal Access. The access to the whole or any part of a computer


system without right.

(2)

Illegal Interception. The interception made by technical means


without right of any non-public transmission of computer data to,
from, or within a computer system including electromagnetic
emissions from a computer system carrying such computer data.

(3)

Data Interference. The intentional or reckless alteration,


damaging, deletion or deterioration of computer data, electronic
document, or electronic data message, without right, including the
introduction or transmission of viruses.

(4)

System Interference. The intentional alteration or reckless


hindering or interference with the functioning of a computer or
computer network by inputting, transmitting, damaging, deleting,
deteriorating, altering or suppressing computer data or program,
electronic document, or electronic data message, without right or
authority, including the introduction or transmission of viruses.

(5)

Misuse of Devices.

(i)
The use, production, sale, procurement, importation, distribution,
or otherwise making available, without right, of:
(aa) A device, including a computer program, designed or adapted
primarily for the purpose of committing any of the offenses under this Act;
or
(bb) A computer password, access code, or similar data by which the
whole or any part of a computer system is capable of being accessed with
intent that it be used for the purpose of committing any of the offenses
under this Act.
(ii)
The possession of an item referred to in paragraphs 5(i)(aa) or (bb)
above with intent to use said devices for the purpose of committing any of
the offenses under this section.
(6)
Cyber-squatting. The acquisition of a domain name over the
internet in bad faith to profit, mislead, destroy reputation, and deprive
others from registering the same, if such a domain name is:
(i)
Similar, identical, or confusingly similar to an existing trademark
registered with the appropriate government agency at the time of the
domain name registration:
(ii)
Identical or in any way similar with the name of a person other
than the registrant, in case of a personal name; and
(iii)

Acquired without right or with intellectual property interests in it.

(b)

Computer-related Offenses:

Dissenting & Concurring

30

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion
(1)

Computer-related Forgery.

(i)
The input, alteration, or deletion of any computer data without
right resulting in inauthentic data with the intent that it be considered or
acted upon for legal purposes as if it were authentic, regardless whether or
not the data is directly readable and intelligible; or
(ii)
The act of knowingly using computer data which is the product of
computer-related forgery as defined herein, for the purpose of perpetuating
a fraudulent or dishonest design.
(2)
Computer-related Fraud. The unauthorized input, alteration, or
deletion of computer data or program or interference in the functioning of
a computer system, causing damage thereby with fraudulent intent:
Provided, That if no damage has yet been caused, the penalty imposable
shall be one (1) degree lower.
(3)
Computer-related Identity Theft. The intentional acquisition, use,
misuse, transfer, possession, alteration or deletion of identifying
information belonging to another, whether natural or juridical, without
right: Provided, That if no damage has yet been caused, the penalty
imposable shall be one (1) degree lower.
(c)

Content-related Offenses:

(1)
Cybersex. The willful engagement, maintenance, control, or
operation, directly or indirectly, of any lascivious exhibition of sexual
organs or sexual activity, with the aid of a computer system, for favor or
consideration.
(2)
Child Pornography. The unlawful or prohibited acts defined and
punishable by Republic Act No. 9775 or the Anti-Child Pornography Act
of 2009, committed through a computer system: Provided, That the
penalty to be imposed shall be (1) one degree higher than that provided for
in Republic Act No. 9775.
(3)
Unsolicited Commercial Communications. The transmission of
commercial electronic communication with the use of computer system
which seek to advertise, sell, or offer for sale products and services are
prohibited unless:
(i)

There is prior affirmative consent from the recipient; or

(ii)
The primary intent of the communication is for service and/or
administrative announcements from the sender to its existing users,
subscribers or customers; or
(iii)

The following conditions are present:

(aa) The commercial electronic communication contains a simple,


valid, and reliable way for the recipient to reject receipt of further
commercial electronic messages (opt-out) from the same source;
(bb) The commercial electronic communication does not purposely
disguise the source of the electronic message; and

Dissenting & Concurring

31

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion
(cc) The commercial electronic communication does not purposely
include misleading information in any part of the message in order to
induce the recipients to read the message.
(4)
Libel. The unlawful or prohibited acts of libel as defined in
Article 355 of the Revised Penal Code, as amended, committed through a
computer system or any other similar means which may be devised in the
future.
SEC. 5. Other Offenses. The following acts shall also constitute an
offense:
(a)
Aiding or Abetting in the Commission of Cybercrime. Any
person who willfully abets or aids in the commission of any of the
offenses enumerated in this Act shall be held liable.
(b)
Attempt in the Commission of Cybercrime. Any person who
willfully attempts to commit any of the offenses enumerated in this Act
shall be held liable.

II (G)
No Actual Controversy
The overview of the internet and the context of cyberspace regulation
should readily highlight the dangers of proceeding to rule on the
constitutional challenges presented by these consolidated petitions barren of
actual controversies. The platforms and technologies that move through an
ever expanding network of networks are varied. The activities of its users,
administrators, commercial vendors, and governments are also as complex
as they are varied.
The internet continues to grow. End User License Agreements
(EULA) of various applications may change its terms based on the feedback
of its users. Technology may progress to ensure that some of the fears that
amount to a violation of a constitutional right or privilege will be addressed.
Possibly, the violations, with new technologies, may become more intrusive
and malignant than jurisprudential cures that we can only imagine at present.
All these point to various reasons for judicial restraint as a natural
component of judicial review when there is no actual case. The courts
power is extraordinary and residual. That is, it should be invoked only
when private actors or other public instrumentalities fail to comply with
the law or the provisions of the Constitution. Our faith in deliberative
democracy requires that we presume that political forums are as
competent to read the Constitution as this court.
Also, the courts competence to deal with these issues needs to
evolve as we understand the context and detail of each technology

Dissenting & Concurring

32

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

implicated in acts that are alleged to violate law or the Constitution. The
internet is an environment, a phenomenon, a network of complex
relationships and, thus, a subject that cannot be fully grasped at first
instance. This is where adversarial positions with concrete contending
claims of rights violated or duties not exercised will become important.
Without the benefit of these adversarial presentations, the implications
and consequences of judicial pronouncements cannot be fully evaluated.
Finally, judicial economy and adjudicative pragmatism requires that
we stay our hand when the facts are not clear. Our pronouncements may
not be enough or may be too detailed. Parties might be required to
adjudicate again. Without an actual case, our pronouncements may also
be irrelevant to the technologies and relationships that really exist. This
will tend to undermine our own credibility as an institution.
We are possessed with none of the facts. We have no context of the
assertion of any right or the failure of any duty contained in the Constitution.
To borrow a meme that has now become popular in virtual environments:
We cannot be asked to doubt the application of provisions of law with most
of the facts in the cloud.
III
Limited Exception: Overbreadth Doctrine
There is, however, a limited instance where facial review of a statute
is not only allowed but essential: when the provision in question is so broad
that there is a clear and imminent threat that actually operates or it can be
used as a prior restraint of speech. This is when there can be an invalidation
of the statute on its face rather than as applied.
The use of the doctrine gained attention in this jurisdiction within a
separate opinion by Justice Mendoza in Cruz v. Secretary of Environment
and Natural Resources,134 thus:
The only instance where a facial challenge to a statute is
allowed is when it operates in the area of freedom of
expression. In such instance, the overbreadth doctrine permits a
party to challenge the validity of a statute even though as applied
to him it is not unconstitutional but it might be if applied to others
not before the Court whose activities are constitutionally protected.
Invalidation of the statute on its face rather than as applied is
permitted in the interest of preventing a chilling effect on
freedom of expression. But in other cases, even if it is found that a
provision of a statute is unconstitutional, courts will decree only
partial invalidity unless the invalid portion is so far inseparable
134

400 Phil. 904 (2002) [Per Curiam, En Banc].

Dissenting & Concurring

33

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion
from the rest of the statute that a declaration of partial invalidity is
not possible. 135 (Emphasis supplied)

The doctrine was again revisited in the celebrated plunder case of


former President Joseph Estrada, when Justice Mendoza, in his concurring
opinion, explained at length when a facial challenge may be allowed:
A facial challenge is allowed to be made to a vague statute and to
one which is overbroad because of possible chilling effect upon
protected speech. The theory is that [w]hen statutes regulate or
proscribe speech and no readily apparent construction suggests
itself as a vehicle for rehabilitating the statutes in a single
prosecution, the transcendent value to all society of
constitutionally protected expression is deemed to justify allowing
attacks on overly broad statutes with no requirement that the
person making the attack demonstrate that his own conduct could
not be regulated by a statute drawn with narrow specificity. The
possible harm to society in permitting some unprotected speech to
go unpunished is outweighed by the possibility that the protected
speech of others may be deterred and perceived grievances left to
fester because of possible inhibitory effects of overly broad
statutes.
This rationale does not apply to penal statutes. Criminal statutes
have general in terrorem effect resulting from their very existence,
and, if facial challenge is allowed for this reason alone, the State
may well be prevented from enacting laws against socially harmful
conduct. In the area of criminal law, the law cannot take chances as
in the area of free speech.
The overbreadth and vagueness doctrines then have special
application only to free speech cases. They are inapt for testing the
validity of penal statutes. As the U.S. Supreme Court put it, in an
opinion by Chief Justice Rehnquist, we have not recognized an
overbreadth doctrine outside the limited context of the First
Amendment. In Broadrick v. Oklahoma, the Court ruled that
claims of facial overbreadth have been entertained in cases
involving statutes which, by their terms, seek to regulate only
spoken words and, again, that overbreadth claims, if entertained
at all, have been curtailed when invoked against ordinary criminal
laws that are sought to be applied to protected conduct. For this
reason, it has been held that a facial challenge to a legislative Act
is the most difficult challenge to mount successfully, since the
challenger must establish that no set of circumstances exists under
which the Act would be valid. As for the vagueness doctrine, it is
said that a litigant may challenge a statute on its face only if it is
vague in all its possible applications. A plaintiff who engages in
some conduct that is clearly proscribed cannot complain of the
vagueness of the law as applied to the conduct of others.

135

See the Separate Opinion of Justice Mendoza in Cruz v. Secretary of Environment and Natural
Resources, 400 Phil. 904,1092 (2002) [Per Curiam, En Banc].

Dissenting & Concurring

34

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion
In sum, the doctrines of strict scrutiny, overbreadth, and vagueness
are analytical tools developed for testing on their faces statutes
in free speech cases or, as they are called in American law, First
Amendment cases. They cannot be made to do service when what
is involved is a criminal statute. With respect to such statute, the
established rule is that one to whom application of a statute is
constitutional will not be heard to attack the statute on the ground
that impliedly it might also be taken as applying to other persons or
other situations in which its application might be unconstitutional.
As has been pointed out, vagueness challenges in the First
Amendment context, like overbreadth challenges typically produce
facial invalidation, while statutes found vague as a matter of due
process typically are invalidated [only] as applied to a particular
defendant.Consequently, there is no basis for petitioners claim
that this Court review the Anti-Plunder Law on its face and in its
entirety. 136

The overbreadth doctrine in the context of a facial challenge was


refined further in David v. Arroyo, 137 where this court speaking through
Justice Sandoval-Gutierrez disallowed petitioners from challenging
Proclamation No. 1017 on its face for being overbroad. In doing so, it laid
down the guidelines for when a facial challenge may be properly brought
before this court, thus:
First and foremost, the overbreadth doctrine is an analytical tool
developed for testing on their faces statutes in free speech cases,
also known under the American Law as First Amendment cases.
xxxx
Moreover, the overbreadth doctrine is not intended for testing the
validity of a law that reflects legitimate state interest in
maintaining comprehensive control over harmful, constitutionally
unprotected conduct. x x x
xxxx
Thus, claims of facial overbreadth are entertained in cases
involving statutes which, by their terms, seek to regulate only
spoken words and again, that overbreadth claims, if
entertained at all, have been curtailed when invoked against
ordinary criminal laws that are sought to be applied to
protected conduct. Here, the incontrovertible fact remains that
PP 1017 pertains to a spectrum of conduct, not free speech, which
is manifestly subject to state regulation.
136

137

See the Concurring Opinion of Justice Mendoza in Estrada v. Sandiganbayan, 421 Phil. 290, 430-432
(2001) [Per J. Bellosillo, En Banc] citing Gooding v. Wilson, 405 U.S. 518, 521, 31 L.Ed.2d 408, 413
(1972); United States v. Salerno, 481 U.S. 739, 745, 95 L.Ed.2d 697, 707 (1987); People v. De la
Piedra, 403 Phil. 31 (2001); Broadrick v. Oklahoma, 413 U.S. 601, 612-613, 37 L. Ed. 2d 830, 840841 (1973); Village of Hoffman Estates v. Flipside, Hoffman Estates, Inc., 455 U.S. 489, 494-95, 71
L.Ed.2d 362, 369 (1982); United States v. Raines, 362 U.S. 17, 21, 4 L.Ed.2d 524, 529 (1960); Yazoo
& Mississippi Valley RR. v. Jackson Vinegar Co., 226 U.S. 217, 57 L.Ed. 193 (1912).
522 Phil. 705 (2006) [Per J. Sandoval-Gutierrez, En Banc].

Dissenting & Concurring

35

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

Second, facial invalidation of laws is considered as manifestly


strong medicine, to be used sparingly and only as a last
resort, and is generally disfavored; The reason for this is
obvious. Embedded in the traditional rules governing constitutional
adjudication is the principle that a person to whom a law may be
applied will not be heard to challenge a law on the ground that it
may conceivably be applied unconstitutionally to others, i.e., in
other situations not before the Court. A writer and scholar in
Constitutional Law explains further:
The most distinctive feature of the overbreadth technique is
that it marks an exception to some of the usual rules of
constitutional litigation. Ordinarily, a particular litigant claims
that a statute is unconstitutional as applied to him or her; if the
litigant prevails, the courts carve away the unconstitutional
aspects of the law by invalidating its improper applications on
a case to case basis. Moreover, challengers to a law are not
permitted to raise the rights of third parties and can only
assert their own interests. In overbreadth analysis, those rules
give way; challenges are permitted to raise the rights of third
parties; and the court invalidates the entire statute on its face,
not merely as applied for so that the overbroad law becomes
unenforceable until a properly authorized court construes it more
narrowly. The factor that motivates courts to depart from the
normal adjudicatory rules is the concern with the chilling;
deterrent effect of the overbroad statute on third parties not
courageous enough to bring suit. The Court assumes that an
overbroad laws very existence may cause others not before the
court to refrain from constitutionally protected speech or
expression. An overbreadth ruling is designed to remove that
deterrent effect on the speech of those third parties.
In other words, a facial challenge using the overbreadth doctrine
will require the Court to examine PP 1017 and pinpoint its flaws
and defects, not on the basis of its actual operation to petitioners,
but on the assumption or prediction that its very existence may
cause others not before the Court to refrain from constitutionally
protected speech or expression. In Younger v. Harris, it was held
that:
[T]he task of analyzing a proposed statute, pinpointing its
deficiencies, and requiring correction of these deficiencies before
the statute is put into effect, is rarely if ever an appropriate task for
the judiciary. The combination of the relative remoteness of the
controversy, the impact on the legislative process of the relief
sought, and above all the speculative and amorphous nature of
the
required
line-by-line
analysis
of
detailed
statutes,...ordinarily results in a kind of case that is wholly
unsatisfactory for deciding constitutional questions, whichever
way they might be decided.
And third, a facial challenge on the ground of overbreadth is the
most difficult challenge to mount successfully, since the challenger
must establish that there can be no instance when the assailed

Dissenting & Concurring

36

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion
law may be valid. Here, petitioners did not even attempt to show
whether this situation exists. 138 (Emphasis originally provided)

The Mendoza opinion, however, found its way back into the legal
spectrum when it was eventually adopted by this court in the cases of
Romualdez v. Sandiganbayan 139 and Romualdez v. Commission on
Elections. 140 Upon motion for reconsideration in Romualdez v. Commission
on Elections, 141 however, this court revised its earlier pronouncement that a
facial challenge only applies to free speech cases, thereby expanding its
scope and usage. It stated that:
x x x The rule established in our jurisdiction is, only statutes on
free speech, religious freedom, and other fundamental rights may
be facially challenged. Under no case may ordinary penal statutes
be subjected to a facial challenge. 142

However, the latest pronouncement of this court on the doctrine was


the case of Southern Hemisphere Engagement Network, Inc. v. AntiTerrorism Council. 143 In it, this court, while reiterating Justice Mendozas
opinion as cited in the Romualdez cases, explained further the difference
between a facial challenge and an as applied challenge.
Distinguished from an as-applied challenge which considers only
extant facts affecting real litigants, a facial invalidation is an
examination of the entire law, pinpointing its flaws and defects,
not only on the basis of its actual operation to the parties, but also
on the assumption or prediction that its very existence may cause
others not before the court to refrain from constitutionally
protected speech or activities.
Justice Mendoza accurately phrased the subtitle in his concurring
opinion that the vagueness and overbreadth doctrines, as grounds
for a facial challenge, are not applicable to penal laws. A litigant
cannot thus successfully mount a facial challenge against a
criminal statute on either vagueness or overbreadth grounds.
The allowance of a facial challenge in free speech cases is justified
by the aim to avert the chilling effect on protected speech, the
exercise of which should not at all times be abridged. As reflected
earlier, this rationale is inapplicable to plain penal statutes that
generally bear an in terrorem effect in deterring socially harmful
138

139
140
141
142

143

David v. Arroyo, 522 Phil. 705 (2006) [Per J. Sandoval-Gutierrez, En Banc] citing the
Concurring Opinion of Justice Mendoza in Estrada v. Sandiganbayan, 421 Phil. 290, 430-432
(2001) [Per J. Bellosillo, En Banc]; Broadrick v. Oklahoma, 413 U.S. 601 (1973); Younger v. Harris,
401 U.S. 37, 52-53, 27 L.Ed.2d 669, 680 (1971); United States v. Raines, 362 U.S. 17, 4 L.Ed.2d 524
(1960); Board of Trustees, State Univ. of N.Y v. Fox, 492 U.S. 469, 106 L.Ed.2d 388 (1989).
479 Phil. 265 (2004) [Per J. Panganiban, En Banc].
576 Phil. 357 (2008) [Per J. Chico-Nazario, En Banc].
573 SCRA 639 (2008) [Per J. Chico-Nazario, En Banc].
Romualdez v. Commission on Elections, G.R. No. 167011, December 11, 2008, 573 SCRA 639, 645
[Per J. Chico-Nazario, En Banc].
G.R. No. 178552, October 5, 2010, 632 SCRA 146 [Per J. Carpio-Morales, En Banc].

Dissenting & Concurring

37

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion
conduct. In fact, the legislature may even forbid and penalize acts
formerly considered innocent and lawful, so long as it refrains
from diminishing or dissuading the exercise of constitutionally
protected rights.
The Court reiterated that there are critical limitations by which a
criminal statute may be challenged and underscored that an onits-face invalidation of penal statutes x x x may not be allowed.
[T]he rule established in our jurisdiction is, only statutes on free speech,
religious freedom, and other fundamental rights may be facially
challenged. Under no case may ordinary penal statutes be subjected
to a facial challenge. The rationale is obvious. If a facial challenge to a
penal statute is permitted, the prosecution of crimes may be hampered.
No prosecution would be possible. A strong criticism against employing
a facial challenge in the case of penal statutes, if the same is allowed,
would effectively go against the grain of the doctrinal requirement of an
existing and concrete controversy before judicial power may be
appropriately exercised. A facial challenge against a penal statute is, at
best, amorphous and speculative. It would, essentially, force the court to
consider third parties who are not before it. As I have said in my
opposition to the allowance of a facial challenge to attack penal statutes,
such a test will impair the States ability to deal with crime. If warranted,
there would be nothing that can hinder an accused from defeating the
States power to prosecute on a mere showing that, as applied to third
parties, the penal statute is vague or overbroad, notwithstanding that the
law is clear as applied to him.

It is settled, on the other hand, that the application of the


overbreadth doctrine is limited to a facial kind of challenge
and, owing to the given rationale of a facial challenge,
applicable only to free speech cases.
By its nature, the overbreadth doctrine has to necessarily apply a
facial type of invalidation in order to plot areas of protected
speech, inevitably almost always under situations not before the
court, that are impermissibly swept by the substantially overbroad
regulation. Otherwise stated, a statute cannot be properly analyzed
for being substantially overbroad if the court confines itself only to
facts as applied to the litigants.
xxxx
In restricting the overbreadth doctrine to free speech claims, the
Court, in at least two cases, observed that the US Supreme Court
has not recognized an overbreadth doctrine outside the limited
context of the First Amendment, and that claims of facial
overbreadth have been entertained in cases involving statutes
which, by their terms, seek to regulate only spoken words. In
Virginia v. Hicks, it was held that rarely, if ever, will an
overbreadth challenge succeed against a law or regulation that is
not specifically addressed to speech or speech-related conduct.
Attacks on overly broad statutes are justified by the transcendent
value to all society of constitutionally protected expression. 144
(Emphasis and underscoring originally supplied)
144

Southern Hemisphere Engagement Network, Inc. v. Anti-Terrorism Council, G.R. No. 178552, October
5, 2010, 632 SCRA 146, 186-189 [Per J. Carpio-Morales, En Banc], citing David v. Macapagal-

Dissenting & Concurring

38

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

III (A)
Test for Allowable Facial Review
In my view, the prevailing doctrine now is that a facial challenge
only applies to cases where the free speech and its cognates are asserted
before the court. While as a general rule penal statutes cannot be
subjected to facial attacks, a provision in a statute can be struck down as
unconstitutional when there is a clear showing that there is an imminent
possibility that its broad language will allow ordinary law enforcement to
cause prior restraints of speech and the value of that speech is such that its
absence will be socially irreparable.

This, therefore, requires the following:


First, the ground for the challenge of the provision in the statute is that
it violates freedom of expression or any of its cognates;
Second, the language in the statute is impermissibly vague;
Third, the vagueness in the text of the statute in question allows for an
interpretation that will allow prior restraints;
Fourth, the chilling effect is not simply because the provision is
found in a penal statute but because there can be a clear showing that there
are special circumstances which show the imminence that the provision will
be invoked by law enforcers;
Fifth, the application of the provision in question will entail prior
restraints; and
Sixth, the value of the speech that will be restrained is such that its
absence will be socially irreparable. This will necessarily mean balancing
between the state interests protected by the regulation and the value of the
speech excluded from society.

Arroyo, 489 SCRA 160, 239 (2006) [Per J. Sandoval-Gutierrez, En Banc]; Romualdez v. Commission
on Elections, 573 SCRA 639 (2008) [Per J. Chico-Nazario, En Banc]; Estrada v. Sandiganbayan, Phil.
290 (2001) [Per J. Bellosillo, En Banc]; Consti., art. III, sec. 4; People v. Siton, 600 SCRA 476, 485
(2009) [Per J. Ynares-Santiago, En Banc]; Virginia v. Hicks, 539 U.S. 113, 156 L. Ed. 2d 148 (2003);
Gooding v. Wilson, 405 U.S. 518, 31 L. Ed 2d 408 (1972).

Dissenting & Concurring

39

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

III (B)
Reason for the Doctrine
The reason for this exception can be easily discerned.

The right to free speech and freedom of expression take paramount


consideration among all the rights of the sovereign people. In Philippine
Blooming Mills Employment Organization et al. v. Philippine Blooming
Mills, Co. Inc., 145 this court discussed this hierarchy at length:
(1) In a democracy, the preservation and enhancement of the
dignity and worth of the human personality is the central core as
well as the cardinal article of faith of our civilization. The
inviolable character of man as an individual must be "protected to
the largest possible extent in his thoughts and in his beliefs as the
citadel of his person."
(2) The Bill of Rights is designed to preserve the ideals of liberty,
equality and security "against the assaults of opportunism, the
expediency of the passing hour, the erosion of small
encroachments, and the scorn and derision of those who have no
patience with general principles."
In the pithy language of Mr. Justice Robert Jackson, the purpose of
the Bill of Rights is to withdraw "certain subjects from the
vicissitudes of political controversy, to place them beyond the
reach of majorities and officials, and to establish them as legal
principles to be applied by the courts. One's rights to life, liberty
and property, to free speech, or free press, freedom of worship and
assembly, and other fundamental rights may not be submitted to a
vote; they depend on the outcome of no elections." Laski
proclaimed that "the happiness of the individual, not the well-being
of the State, was the criterion by which its behaviour was to be
judged. His interests, not its power, set the limits to the authority it
was entitled to exercise."
(3) The freedoms of expression and of assembly as well as the
right to petition are included among the immunities reserved by the
sovereign people, in the rhetorical aphorism of Justice Holmes, to
protect the ideas that we abhor or hate more than the ideas we
cherish; or as Socrates insinuated, not only to protect the minority
who want to talk, but also to benefit the majority who refuse to
listen. And as Justice Douglas cogently stresses it, the liberties of
one are the liberties of all; and the liberties of one are not safe
unless the liberties of all are protected.
(4) The rights of free expression, free assembly and petition, are
not only civil rights but also political rights essential to man's
enjoyment of his life, to his happiness and to his full and complete
fulfillment. Thru these freedoms the citizens can participate not
145

151-A Phil. 656 (1973) [Per J. Makasiar, En Banc].

Dissenting & Concurring

40

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion
merely in the periodic establishment of the government through
their suffrage but also in the administration of public affairs as well
as in the discipline of abusive public officers. The citizen is
accorded these rights so that he can appeal to the appropriate
governmental officers or agencies for redress and protection as
well as for the imposition of the lawful sanctions on erring public
officers and employees.
(5) While the Bill of Rights also protects property rights, the
primacy of human rights over property rights is recognized.
Because these freedoms are "delicate and vulnerable, as well as
supremely precious in our society" and the "threat of sanctions
may deter their exercise almost as potently as the actual application
of sanctions," they "need breathing space to survive," permitting
government regulation only "with narrow specificity."
Property and property rights can be lost thru prescription; but
human rights are imprescriptible. If human rights are extinguished
by the passage of time, then the Bill of Rights is a useless attempt
to limit the power of government and ceases to be an efficacious
shield against the tyranny of officials, of majorities, of the
influential and powerful, and of oligarchs political, economic or
otherwise.
In the hierarchy of civil liberties, the rights of free expression and
of assembly occupy a preferred position as they are essential to the
preservation and vitality of our civil and political institutions; and
such priority "gives these liberties the sanctity and the sanction not
permitting dubious intrusions."
The superiority of these freedoms over property rights is
underscored by the fact that a mere reasonable or rational relation
between the means employed by the law and its object or purpose
that the law is neither arbitrary nor discriminatory nor
oppressive would suffice to validate a law which restricts or
impairs property rights. On the other hand, a constitutional or valid
infringement of human rights requires a more stringent criterion,
namely existence of a grave and immediate danger of a substantive
evil which the State has the right to prevent. 146 (Citations omitted)

The right to freedom of expression is a primordial right because it is


not only an affirmation but a positive execution of the basic nature of the
state defined in Article II, Section 1 of the 1987 Constitution:
The Philippines is a democratic and republican State. Sovereignty
resides in the people and all government authority emanates from
them.

The power of the State is derived from the authority and mandate
given to it by the people, through their representatives elected in the
146

Philippine Blooming Mills Employment Organization et al v. Philippine Blooming Mills, Co. Inc., 151A Phil. 656, 674-676 (1973) [Per J. Makasiar, En Banc].

Dissenting & Concurring

41

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

legislative and executive branches of government. The sovereignty of the


Filipino people is dependent on their ability to freely express themselves
without fear of undue reprisal by the government. Government, too, is
shaped by comments and criticisms of the various publics that it serves.
The ability to express and communicate also defines individual and
collective autonomies. That is, we shape and refine our identity and,
therefore, also our thoughts as well as our viewpoints through interaction
with others. We choose the modes of our expression that will also affect the
way that others receive our ideas. Thoughts remembered when expressed
with witty eloquence are imbibed through art. Ideas, however, can be
rejected with a passion when expressed through uncouth caustic verbal
remarks or presented with tasteless memes. In any of these instances, those
who receive the message see the speaker in a particular way, perhaps even
belonging to a category or culture.
Furthermore, what we learn from others bears on what we think as
well as what and how we express. For the quality of our own expression, it is
as important to tolerate the expression of others.
This fundamental and primordial freedom has its important inherent
and utilitarian justifications. With the imminent possibility of prior
restraints, the protection must be extraordinarily vigilant.
In Chavez v. Gonzales, 147 the court elaborated further on the primacy
of the right to freedom of speech:
Freedom of speech and of the press means something more than
the right to approve existing political beliefs or economic
arrangements, to lend support to official measures, and to take
refuge in the existing climate of opinion on any matter of public
consequence. When atrophied, the right becomes meaningless. The
right belongs as well if not more to those who question, who do
not conform, who differ. The ideas that may be expressed under
this freedom are confined not only to those that are conventional or
acceptable to the majority. To be truly meaningful, freedom of
speech and of the press should allow and even encourage the
articulation of the unorthodox view, though it be hostile to or
derided by others; or though such view induces a condition of
unrest, creates dissatisfaction with conditions as they are, or even
stirs people to anger. To paraphrase Justice Holmes, it is freedom
for the thought that we hate, no less than for the thought that agrees
with us.
The scope of freedom of expression is so broad that it extends
protection to nearly all forms of communication. It protects speech,
print and assembly regarding secular as well as political causes,
147

569 Phil. 155 (2008) [Per C.J. Puno, En Banc].

Dissenting & Concurring

42

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion
and is not confined to any particular field of human interest. The
protection covers myriad matters of public interest or concern
embracing all issues, about which information is needed or
appropriate, so as to enable members of society to cope with the
exigencies of their period. The constitutional protection assures the
broadest possible exercise of free speech and free press for
religious, political, economic, scientific, news, or informational
ends, inasmuch as the Constitution's basic guarantee of freedom to
advocate ideas is not confined to the expression of ideas that are
conventional or shared by a majority.
The constitutional protection is not limited to the exposition of
ideas. The protection afforded free speech extends to speech or
publications that are entertaining as well as instructive or
informative. Specifically, in Eastern Broadcasting Corporation
(DYRE) v. Dans, this Court stated that all forms of media, whether
print or broadcast, are entitled to the broad protection of the clause
on freedom of speech and of expression. (Citations omitted) 148

III (C)
Overbreadth versus Vagueness
A facial challenge, however, can only be raised on the basis of
overbreadth, not vagueness. Vagueness relates to a violation of the rights of
due process. A facial challenge, on the other hand, can only be raised on the
basis of overbreadth, which affects freedom of expression.
Southern Hemisphere provided the necessary distinction:
A statute or act suffers from the defect of vagueness when
it lacks comprehensible standards that men of common intelligence
must necessarily guess at its meaning and differ as to its
application. It is repugnant to the Constitution in two respects: (1)
it violates due process for failure to accord persons, especially the
parties targeted by it, fair notice of the conduct to avoid; and (2) it
leaves law enforcers unbridled discretion in carrying out its
provisions and becomes an arbitrary flexing of the Government
muscle. The overbreadth doctrine, meanwhile, decrees that a
governmental purpose to control or prevent activities
constitutionally subject to state regulations may not be achieved by
means which sweep unnecessarily broadly and thereby invade the
area of protected freedoms.
As distinguished from the vagueness doctrine, the
overbreadth doctrine assumes that individuals will understand what
a statute prohibits and will accordingly refrain from that behavior,
even though some of it is protected. 149

148
149

Chavez v. Gonzales, 569 Phil. 155, 197-198 (2008) [Per C.J. Puno, En Banc].
Southern Hemisphere Engagement Network, Inc. v. Anti-Terrorism Council, G.R. No. 178552, October
5, 2010, 632 SCRA 146, 185 [Per J. Carpio-Morales, En Banc].

Dissenting & Concurring

43

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

The facial challenge is different from an as-applied challenge or


determination of a penal law. In an as-applied challenge, the court
undertakes judicial review of the constitutionality of legislation as applied
to particular facts, parties or defendants and on a case-to-case basis. In a
challenge as applied, the violation also involves an abridgement of the due
process clause. In such instances, the burden of the petitioner must be to
show that the only reasonable interpretation is one that is arbitrary or unfair.
III (D)
Chilling Effect
In the petitions before this court, the facial challenge can be used but
only insofar as those provisions that are so broad as to ordinarily produce a
chilling effect on speech.
We have transplanted and adopted the doctrine relating to chilling
effects from the jurisprudence of the United States Supreme Court. The
evolution of their doctrine, therefore, should be advisory but not binding for
this court.
The concept of a chilling effect was first introduced in the case of
Wieman v. Updegraff. 150 In that case, the United States Supreme Court
declared as unconstitutional Oklahoma state legislature which authorized the
docking of salaries of employees within the state who failed to render a
loyalty oath disavowing membership in communist organizations. The
validity of the Oklahama state legislature included teachers in public schools
who alleged violations of the Due Process Clause. In his concurring opinion,
Justice Frankfurter first introduced the concept of a chilling effect, stating:
By limiting the power of the States to interfere with freedom of
speech and freedom of inquiry and freedom of association, the
Fourteenth Amendment protects all persons, no matter what their
calling. But, in view of the nature of the teacher's relation to the
effective exercise of the rights which are safeguarded by the Bill of
Rights and by the Fourteenth Amendment, inhibition of freedom of
thought, and of action upon thought, in the case of teachers brings
the safeguards of those amendments vividly into operation. Such
unwarranted inhibition upon the free spirit of teachers affects not
only those who, like the appellants, are immediately before the
Court. It has an unmistakable tendency to chill that free play of the
spirit which all teachers ought especially to cultivate and practice;
it makes for caution and timidity in their associations by potential
teachers. 151

150
151

344 U.S. 183 (1952).


Wieman v. Updegraff, 344 U.S. 183, 195 (1952).

Dissenting & Concurring

44

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

The concept of a chilling effect was further elaborated in the


landmark case of New York Times v. Sullivan: 152
We should be particularly careful, therefore, adequately to protect
the liberties which are embodied in the First and Fourteenth
Amendments. It may be urged that deliberately and maliciously
false statements have no conceivable value as free speech. That
argument, however, is not responsive to the real issue presented by
this case, which is whether that freedom of speech which all agree
is constitutionally protected can be effectively safeguarded by a
rule allowing the imposition of liability upon a jury's evaluation of
the speaker's state of mind. If individual citizens may be held liable
in damages for strong words, which a jury finds false and
maliciously motivated, there can be little doubt that public debate
and advocacy will be constrained. And if newspapers, publishing
advertisements dealing with public issues, thereby risk liability,
there can also be little doubt that the ability of minority groups to
secure publication of their views on public affairs and to seek
support for their causes will be greatly diminished. Cf. Farmers
Educational & Coop. Union v. WDAY, Inc., 360 U.S. 525, 530.
The opinion of the Court conclusively demonstrates the chilling
effect of the Alabama libel laws on First Amendment freedoms in
the area of race relations. The American Colonists were not
willing, nor should we be, to take the risk that "[m]en who injure
and oppress the people under their administration [and] provoke
them to cry out and complain" will also be empowered to "make
that very complaint the foundation for new oppressions and
prosecutions." The Trial of John Peter Zenger, 17 Howell's St. Tr.
675, 721-722 (1735) (argument of counsel to the jury). To impose
liability for critical, albeit erroneous or even malicious, comments
on official conduct would effectively resurrect "the obsolete
doctrine that the governed must not criticize their governors." Cf.
Sweeney v. Patterson, 76 U.S.App.D.C. 23, 24, 128 F.2d 457,
458. 153

In National Association for the Advancement of Colored People v.


Button, 154 the United States Supreme Court categorically qualified the
concept of a chilling effect:
Our concern is with the impact of enforcement of Chapter 33 upon
First Amendment freedoms.
xxxx
For, in appraising a statute's inhibitory effect upon such rights, this
Court has not hesitated to take into account possible applications of
the statute in other factual contexts besides that at bar. Thornhill v.
Alabama, 310 U. S. 88, 310 U. S. 97-98; Winters v. New York,
supra,at 333 U. S. 518-520. Cf. Staub v. City of Baxley, 355 U. S.
152
153
154

376 U.S. 254 (1964).


New York Times v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254, 300-301(1964).
371 U.S. 415 (1963).

Dissenting & Concurring

45

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion
313. It makes no difference that the instant case was not a criminal
prosecution, and not based on a refusal to comply with a licensing
requirement. The objectionable quality of vagueness and
overbreadth does not depend upon absence of fair notice to a
criminally accused or upon unchanneled delegation of
legislative powers, but upon the danger of tolerating, in the
area of First Amendment freedoms, the existence of a penal
statute susceptible of sweeping and improper application.
Marcus v. Search Warrant, 367 U. S. 717, 367 U. S. 733. These
freedoms are delicate and vulnerable, as well as supremely
precious in our society. The threat of sanctions may deter their
exercise almost as potently as the actual application of
sanctions. Cf. Smith v. California, supra, at 361 U. S. 151-154;
Speiser v. Randall, 357 U. S. 513, 357 U. S. 526. Because First
Amendment freedoms need breathing space to survive,
government may regulate in the area only with narrow specificity.
Cantwell v. Connecticut, 310 U. S. 296, 3 310 U. S. 11. (Emphasis
supplied) 155

Philippine jurisprudence has incorporated the concept of a chilling


effect, but the definition has remained abstract. In Chavez v. Gonzales, 156
this court stated that a chilling effect took place upon the issuance of a
press release by the National Telecommunications Commission warning
radio and television broadcasters from using taped conversations involving
former President Gloria Macapagal-Arroyo and the allegations of fixing
elections:
We rule that not every violation of a law will justify
straitjacketing the exercise of freedom of speech and of the
press. Our laws are of different kinds and doubtless, some of
them provide norms of conduct which even if violated have only
an adverse effect on a persons private comfort but does not
endanger national security. There are laws of great significance but
their violation, by itself and without more, cannot support
suppression of free speech and free press. In fine, violation of law
is just a factor, a vital one to be sure, which should be weighed in
adjudging whether to restrain freedom of speech and of the press.
The totality of the injurious effects of the violation to private and
public interest must be calibrated in light of the preferred status
accorded by the Constitution and by related international covenants
protecting freedom of speech and of the press. In calling for a
careful and calibrated measurement of the circumference of all
these factors to determine compliance with the clear and present
danger test, the Court should not be misinterpreted as
devaluing violations of law. By all means, violations of law
should be vigorously prosecuted by the State for they breed their
own evil consequence. But to repeat, the need to prevent their
violation cannot per se trump the exercise of free speech and
free press, a preferred right whose breach can lead to greater
evils. For this failure of the respondents alone to offer proof to
satisfy the clear and present danger test, the Court has no option
155
156

National Association for the Advancement of Colored People v. Button, 371 U.S. 415, 431-433 (1963).
569 Phil. 155 (2008) [Per C.J. Puno, En Banc].

Dissenting & Concurring

46

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion
but to uphold the exercise of free speech and free press. There is no
showing that the feared violation of the anti-wiretapping law
clearly endangers the national security of the State.
This is not all the faultline in the stance of the respondents.
We slide to the issue of whether the mere press statements of the
Secretary of Justice and of the NTC in question constitute a form
of content-based prior restraint that has transgressed the
Constitution. In resolving this issue, we hold that it is not decisive
that the press statements made by respondents were not
reduced in or followed up with formal orders or circulars. It is
sufficient that the press statements were made by respondents
while in the exercise of their official functions. Undoubtedly,
respondent Gonzales made his statements as Secretary of Justice,
while the NTC issued its statement as the regulatory body of
media. Any act done, such as a speech uttered, for and on
behalf of the government in an official capacity is covered by
the rule on prior restraint. The concept of an act does not
limit itself to acts already converted to a formal order or
official circular. Otherwise, the non formalization of an act
into an official order or circular will result in the easy
circumvention of the prohibition on prior restraint. The press
statements at bar are acts that should be struck down as they
constitute impermissible forms of prior restraints on the right to
free speech and press.
There is enough evidence of chilling effect of the
complained acts on record. The warnings given to media came
from no less the NTC, a regulatory agency that can cancel the
Certificate of Authority of the radio and broadcast media. They
also came from the Secretary of Justice, the alter ego of the
Executive, who wields the awesome power to prosecute those
perceived to be violating the laws of the land. After the warnings,
the KBP inexplicably joined the NTC in issuing an ambivalent
Joint Press Statement. After the warnings, petitioner Chavez was
left alone to fight this battle for freedom of speech and of the press.
This silence on the sidelines on the part of some media
practitioners is too deafening to be the subject of misinterpretation.
The constitutional imperative for us to strike down
unconstitutional acts should always be exercised with care and in
light of the distinct facts of each case. For there are no hard and
fast rules when it comes to slippery constitutional questions, and
the limits and construct of relative freedoms are never set in stone.
Issues revolving on their construct must be decided on a case to
case basis, always based on the peculiar shapes and shadows of
each case. But in cases where the challenged acts are patent
invasions of a constitutionally protected right, we should be swift
in striking them down as nullities per se. A blow too soon struck
for freedom is preferred than a blow too late. 157

Taking all these into consideration, as mentioned earlier, a facial


attack of a provision can only succeed when the basis is freedom of
157

Chavez v. Gonzales, 569 Phil. 155, 219-221 (2008) [Per C.J. Puno, En Banc].

47

Dissenting & Concurring

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

expression, when there is a clear showing that there is an imminent


possibility that its broad language will allow ordinary law enforcement to
cause prior restraints of speech, and when the value of that speech is such
that its absence will be socially irreparable.
Among all the provisions challenged in these consolidated petitions,
there are only four instances when the chilling effect on speech can be
palpable: (a) the take down provision; (b) the provision on cyber libel; (c)
the provision on cybersex; and (d) the clause relating to unbridled
surveillance of traffic data. The provisions that provide for higher penalties
for these as well as for dual prosecutions should likewise be declared
unconstitutional because they magnify the chilling effect that stifles
protected expression.
For this reason
unconstitutional.

alone,

these

provisions

and

clauses

are

IV
The Take Down Clause
Section 19 of Republic Act No. 10175 is unconstitutional because it
clearly allows prior restraint. This section provides:
SEC. 19. Restricting or Blocking Access to Computer Data
When a computer data is prima facie found to be in violation of the
provisions of this Act, the DOJ shall issue an order to restrict or
block access to such computer data.

Among all the provisions, this is the sole provision that the Office of
the Solicitor General agrees to be declared as unconstitutional.
IV (A)
A Paradigmatic Example of Prior Restraint
There is no doubt of the chilling effect of Section 19 of Republic
Act No. 10175. It is indeed an example of an instance when law enforcers
are clearly invited to do prior restraints within vague parameters. It is
blatantlyunconstitutional.
Chavez v. Gonzales presents a clear and concise summary of the
doctrines governing prior restraint:
Prior restraint refers to official governmental restrictions on the
press or other forms of expression in advance of actual publication

Dissenting & Concurring

48

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion
or dissemination. Freedom from prior restraint is largely freedom
from government censorship of publications, whatever the form of
censorship, and regardless of whether it is wielded by the
executive, legislative or judicial branch of the government. Thus, it
precludes governmental acts that required approval of a proposal to
publish; licensing or permits as prerequisites to publication
including the payment of license taxes for the privilege to publish;
and even injunctions against publication. Even the closure of the
business and printing offices of certain newspapers, resulting in the
discontinuation of their printing and publication, are deemed as
previous restraint or censorship. Any law or official that requires
some form of permission to be had before publication can be made,
commits an infringement of the constitutional right, and remedy
can be had at the courts.
Given that deeply ensconced in our fundamental law is the hostility
against all prior restraints on speech, and any act that restrains
speech is presumed invalid, and "any act that restrains speech is
hobbled by the presumption of invalidity and should be greeted
with furrowed brows," it is important to stress not all prior
restraints on speech are invalid. Certain previous restraints may
be permitted by the Constitution, but determined only upon a
careful evaluation of the challenged act as against the appropriate
test by which it should be measured against.

As worded, Section 19 provides an arbitrary standard by which the


Department of Justice may exercise this power to restrict or block access. A
prima facie finding is sui generis and cannot be accepted as basis to stop
speech even before it is made. It does not provide for judicially determinable
parameters. It, thus, ensures that all computer data will automatically be
subject to the control and power of the Department of Justice. This provision
is a looming threat that hampers the possibility of free speech and expression
through the internet. The sheer possibility that the State has the ability to
unilaterally decide whether data, ideas or thoughts constitute evidence of a
prima facie commission of a cybercrime will limit the free exchange of
ideas, criticism, and communication that is the bulwark of a free democracy.
There is no question that Section 19 is, thus, unconstitutional.
V
Cyber Libel
Also unconstitutional is Section 4(c)(4) which reads:
SEC. 4. Cybercrime Offenses. The following acts constitute the
offense of cybercrime punishable under this Act:
xxxx
(c) Content-related Offenses:
(4) Libel. The unlawful or prohibited acts of libel as defined in
Article 355 of the Revised Penal Code, as amended, committed

Dissenting & Concurring

49

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion
through a computer system or any other similar means which may
be devised in the future.

The intent of this provision seems to be to prohibit the defense that


libel committed through the use of a computer is not punishable.
Respondents counter that, to date, libel has not been declared
unconstitutional as a violation of the rights to free speech, freedom of
expression, and of the press.
Reference to Article 355 of the Revised Penal Code in Section 4(c)(4)
resulted in the implied incorporation of Articles 353 and 354 as well.
Articles 353 to 355 of the Revised Penal Code provide:
Title Thirteen
CRIMES AGAINST HONOR
Chapter One
LIBEL
Section One. Definitions, forms, and punishment of this crime.
Art. 353. Definition of libel. A libel is public and malicious
imputation of a crime, or of a vice or defect, real or imaginary, or
any act, omission, condition, status, or circumstance tending to
cause the dishonor, discredit, or contempt of a natural or juridical
person, or to blacken the memory of one who is dead.
Art. 354. Requirement for publicity. Every defamatory
imputation is presumed to be malicious, even if it be true, if no
good intention and justifiable motive for making it is shown,
except in the following cases:
1. A private communication made by any person to another in the
performance of any legal, moral or social duty; and
2. A fair and true report, made in good faith, without any
comments or remarks, of any judicial, legislative or other official
proceedings which are not of confidential nature, or of any
statement, report or speech delivered in said proceedings, or of any
other act performed by public officers in the exercise of their
functions.
Art. 355. Libel means by writings or similar means. A libel
committed by means of writing, printing, lithography, engraving,
radio, phonograph, painting, theatrical exhibition, cinematographic
exhibition, or any similar means, shall be punished by prision
correccional in its minimum and medium periods or a fine ranging
from 200 to 6,000 pesos, or both, in addition to the civil action
which may be brought by the offended party.

Dissenting & Concurring

50

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

The ponencia claims that libel is not a constitutionally protected


speech and that government has an obligation to protect private
individuals from defamation. 158
I strongly dissent from the first statement. Libel is a label that is often
used to stifle protected speech. I agree with the second statement but only to
the extent that defamation can be protected with civil rather than criminal
liabilities.
Given the statutory text, the history of the concept of criminal libel
and our courts experience with libel, I am of the view that its continued
criminalization especially in platforms using the internet unqualifiedly
produces a chilling effect that stifles our fundamental guarantees of
free expression. Criminalizing libel contradicts our notions of a genuinely
democratic society.
V (B)
As Currently Worded,
Libel is Unconstitutional
The crime of libel in its 1930 version in the Revised Penal Code was
again reenacted through the Cybercrime Prevention Act of 2012. It simply
added the use of the internet as one of the means to commit the criminal
acts. The reenactment of these archaic provisions is unconstitutional for
many reasons. At minimum, it failed to take into consideration
refinements in the interpretation of the old law through decades of
jurisprudence. It now stands starkly in contrast with the required
constitutional protection of freedom of expression.
The ponencia fails to account for the evolution of the requirement of
malice in situations involving public officers and public figures. At best, the
majority will have us believe that jurisprudence can be read into the current
text of the libel law as referred to in the Cybercrime Prevention Act of 2012.
However, this does not appear to be the intent of the legislature based
on the text of the provision. Congress reenacted the provisions defining and
characterizing the crime of libel as it was worded in 1930. I concur with
Justice Carpios observations that the law as crafted fails to distinguish the
malice requirement for criticisms of public officers (and public figures) on
the one hand and that for ordinary defamation of private citizens carefully
crafted by jurisprudence. Understandably, it creates doubt on the part of
those who may be subject to its provisions. The vagueness of the current
text, reenacted by reference by Rep. Act No. 10175 is as plain as day.
158

Ponencia, J. Abad, p. 24.

Dissenting & Concurring

51

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

It is difficult to accept the majoritys view that present jurisprudence


is read into the present version of the law. This is troubling as it is
perplexing. The majority of the 200 plus members of the House of
Representatives and the 24 Senators chose the old text defining the crime of
libel. The old text does not conform to the delicate balance carved out by
jurisprudence. Just the sheer number of distinguished and learned lawyers in
both chambers would rule out oversight or negligence. As representatives of
our people, they would have wanted the crime to be clearly and plainly
spelled out so that the public will be properly informed. They could not have
wanted the ordinary Filipino to consult the volumes of Philippine Reports in
order to find out that the text did not mean plainly what it contained before
they exercised their right to express.
It is, thus, reasonable to presume that Congress insists on the plain
meaning of the old text. Possibly, through inaction, they would replace
jurisprudential interpretation of the freedom of expression clause in relation
to defamation by reenacting the same 1930 provisions.
V (C)
Negating the Balance Struck
Through Jurisprudence
A survey of these constant efforts in jurisprudence to qualify libel as
provided in the old statute is needed to understand this point.
United States v. Bustos 159 interpreted the requirement of malice for
libel under Act No. 277. 160 This court ruled that malice in fact is required
to sustain a conviction under the law when there are justifiable motives
present in a case. Thus:
In an action for libel suppose the defendant fails to prove that the
injurious publication or communication was true. Can he relieve
himself from liability by showing that it was published with
"justifiable motives" whether such publication was true or false or
even malicious? There is no malice in law when "justifiable
motives" exist, and, in the absence of malice, there is no libel
under the law. (U. S. vs. Lerma, supra.) But if there is malice in
fact, justifiable motives can not exist. The law will not allow one
person to injure another by an injurious publication, under the
cloak of "good ends" or "justifiable motives," when, as a matter of
fact, the publication was made with a malicious intent. It is then a
159
160

13 Phil. 690 (1918) [Per J. Johnson].


An Act defining the law of libel and threats to publish a libel, making libel and threats to publish a
libel misdemeanors, giving a right of civil action therefor, and making obscene or indecent
publications misdemeanors. This was repealed by the Revised Penal Code via Article 367, Repealing
Clause.

Dissenting & Concurring

52

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion
malicious defamation. The law punishes a malicious defamation
and it was not intended to permit one to maliciously injure
another under the garb of "justifiable motives." When malice
in fact is shown to exist the publisher can not be relieved from
liability by a pretense of "justifiable motives." Section 3
relieves the plaintiff from the necessity of proving malice
simply when no justifiable motives are shown, but it does not
relieve the defendant from liability under the guise of
"justifiable motives" when malice actually is proved. The
defense of "the truth" of the "injurious publication" (sec. 4) and its
character as a privileged communication (sec. 9) means nothing
more than the truth in one instance and the occasion of making it in
the other together with proof of justifiable motive, rebuts the prima
facie inference of malice in law and throws upon the plaintiff or
the State, the onus of proving malice in fact. The publication of a
malicious defamation, whether it be true or not, is clearly an
offense under Act No. 277. 161 (Emphasis supplied)

Actual malice as a requirement evolved further.


It was in the American case of New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 162
which this court adopted later on, 163 that the actual malice 164 requirement
was expounded and categorically required for cases of libel involving public
officers. In resolving the issue of whether x x x an action brought by a
public official against critics of his official conduct, abridges the freedom of
speech and of the press that is guaranteed by the First and Fourteenth
Amendments, 165 the New York Times case required that actual malice
should be proven when a case for defamation includes matters of public
concern, public men, and candidates for office. 166 Thus:
Like insurrection, contempt, advocacy of unlawful acts,
breach of the peace, obscenity, solicitation of legal business, and
the various other formulae for the repression of expression that
have been challenged in this Court, libel can claim no talismanic
immunity from constitutional limitations. It must be measured
by standards that satisfy the First Amendment.
The general proposition that freedom of expression upon
public questions is secured by the First Amendment has long been
settled by our decisions. The constitutional safeguard, we have
said, "was fashioned to assure unfettered interchange of ideas
for the bringing about of political and social changes desired
by the people." Roth v. United States, 354 U.S. 476, 484.
161
162
163

164

165
166

U.S. v. Bustos, 13 Phil. 690, 698 (1918) [Per J. Johnson].


New York Times v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254 (1964).
See Lopez v. Court of Appeals, 145 Phil. 219 (1970) [Per J. Fernando, En Banc]; Mercado v. Court of
First Instance, 201 Phil. 565 (1982) [Per J. Fernando, Second Division]; and Adiong vs. Commission
on Elections, G.R. No. 103956, March 31, 1992, 207 SCRA 712 [Per J. Gutierrez, En Banc].
Actual malice may mean that it was with the knowledge that it was false or with reckless disregard of
whether it was false or not. See New York Times v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254, 268 (1964).
New York Times v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254, 268 (1964).
Id. at 281-282.

Dissenting & Concurring

53

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion
The maintenance of the opportunity for free political
discussion to the end that government may be responsive to the
will of the people and that changes may be obtained by lawful
means, an opportunity essential to the security of the Republic,
is a fundamental principle of our constitutional system.
xxxx
Injury to official reputation affords no more warrant
for repressing speech that would otherwise be free than does
factual error. Where judicial officers are involved, this Court
has held that concern for the dignity and reputation of the
courts does not justify the punishment as criminal contempt of
criticism of the judge or his decision. Bridges v. California, 314
U.S. 252.This is true even though the utterance contains "halftruths" and "misinformation." Pennekamp v. Florida, 328 U.S.
331, 342, 343, n. 5, 345. Such repression can be justified, if at all,
only by a clear and present danger of the obstruction of justice. See
also Craig v. Harney, 331 U.S. 367; Wood v. Georgia, 370 U.S.
375. If judges are to be treated as "men of fortitude, able to thrive
in a hardy climate," Craig v. Harney, supra, 331 U.S. at 376, surely
the same must be true of other government officials, such as
elected city commissioners. Criticism of their official conduct
does not lose its constitutional protection merely because it is
effective criticism, and hence diminishes their official
reputations. Stromberg v. California, 283 U.S. 359, 369. 167
(Emphasis supplied)

Ayer Productions Pty. Ltd and McElroy & McElroy Film Productions
v. Hon. Ignacio M. Capulong, 168 as affirmed in the case of Borjal v. Court of
Appeals, 169 adopted the doctrine in New York Times to public figures. In
Ayer Productions:
A limited intrusion into a person's privacy has long been regarded
as permissible where that person is a public figure and the
information sought to be elicited from him or to be published about
him constitute of a public character. Succinctly put, the right of
privacy cannot be invoked resist publication and dissemination of
matters of public interest. The interest sought to be protected by
the right of privacy is the right to be free from unwarranted
publicity, from the wrongful publicizing of the private affairs and
activities of an individual which are outside the realm of legitimate
public concern. 170

Public figures were defined as:

167
168
169
170

Id. at 269-273.
243 Phil. 1007 (1988) [Per J. Feliciano, En Banc].
361 Phil. 1 (1999) [Per J. Bellosillo, Second Division].
Ayer Productions Pty. Ltd and McElroy & McElroy Film Productions v. Hon. Ignacio M. Capulong,
243 Phil. 1007, 1018-1019 (1988) [Per J. Feliciano, En Banc].

Dissenting & Concurring

54

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion
A public figure has been defined as a person who, by his
accomplishments, fame, or mode of living, or by adopting a
profession or calling which gives the public a legitimate interest
in his doings, his affairs, and his character, has become a 'public
personage.' He is, in other words, a celebrity. Obviously to be
included in this category are those who have achieved some degree
of reputation by appearing before the public, as in the case of an
actor, a professional baseball player, a pugilist, or any other
entertainment. The list is, however, broader than this. It includes
public officers, famous inventors and explorers, war heroes and
even ordinary soldiers, an infant prodigy, and no less a personage
than the Grand Exalted Ruler of a lodge. It includes, in short,
anyone who has arrived at a position where public attention is
focused upon him as a person.
Such public figures were held to have lost, to some extent at
least, their tight to privacy. Three reasons were given, more or less
indiscriminately, in the decisions" that they had sought publicity
and consented to it, and so could not complaint when they received
it; that their personalities and their affairs has already public, and
could no longer be regarded as their own private business; and
that the press had a privilege, under the Constitution, to inform the
public about those who have become legitimate matters of public
interest. On one or another of these grounds, and sometimes all, it
was held that there was no liability when they were given
additional publicity, as to matters legitimately within the scope of
the public interest they had aroused.
The privilege of giving publicity to news, and other matters
of public interest, was held to arise out of the desire and the right
of the public to know what is going on in the world, and the
freedom of the press and other agencies of information to tell it.
"News" includes all events and items of information which are out
of the ordinary hum-drum routine, and which have 'that indefinable
quality of information which arouses public attention.' To a very
great extent the press, with its experience or instinct as to what its
readers will want, has succeeded in making its own definition of
news, as a glance at any morning newspaper will sufficiently
indicate. It includes homicide and other crimes, arrests and police
raids, suicides, marriages and divorces, accidents, a death from the
use of narcotics, a woman with a rare disease, the birth of a child to
a twelve year old girl, the reappearance of one supposed to have
been murdered years ago, and undoubtedly many other similar
matters of genuine, if more or less deplorable, popular appeal.
The privilege of enlightening the public was not, however,
limited, to the dissemination of news in the scene of current events.
It extended also to information or education, or even entertainment
and amusement, by books, articles, pictures, films and broadcasts
concerning interesting phases of human activity in general, as well
as the reproduction of the public scene in newsreels and
travelogues. In determining where to draw the line, the courts were
invited to exercise a species of censorship over what the public

Dissenting & Concurring

55

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion
may be permitted to read; and they were understandably liberal in
allowing the benefit of the doubt. 171 (Emphasis supplied)

This doctrine was reiterated in Vasquez v. Court of Appeals. 172


Petitioner was charged with libel for allegedly defaming his Barangay
Chairperson in an article published in the newspaper, Ang Tinig ng Masa.
Petitioner allegedly caused the dishonor and discredit of the Barangay
Chairperson through the malicious imputation that the public officer
landgrabbed and that he was involved in other illegal activities. In acquitting
the petitioner:
The question is whether from the fact that the statements
were defamatory, malice can be presumed so that it was incumbent
upon petitioner to overcome such presumption. Under Art. 361 of
the Revised Penal Code, if the defamatory statement is made
against a public official with respect to the discharge of his official
duties and functions and the truth of the allegation is shown, the
accused will be entitled to an acquittal even though he does not
prove that the imputation was published with good motives and for
justifiable ends.
xxxx
In denouncing the barangay chairman in this case,
petitioner and the other residents of the Tondo Foreshore Area
were not only acting in their self-interest but engaging in the
performance of a civic duty to see to it that public duty is
discharged faithfully and well by those on whom such duty is
incumbent. The recognition of this right and duty of every
citizen in a democracy is inconsistent with any requirement
placing on him the burden of proving that he acted with good
motives and for justifiable ends.
For that matter, even if the defamatory statement is
false, no liability can attach if it relates to official conduct,
unless the public official concerned proves that the statement
was made with actual malicethat is, with knowledge that it
was false or with reckless disregard of whether it was false or
not. This is the gist of the ruling in the landmark case of New
York Times v. Sullivan, which this Court has cited with
approval in several of its own decisions. This is the rule of
actual malice.
A rule placing on the accused the burden of showing the
truth of allegations of official misconduct and/or good motives
and justifiable ends for making such allegations would not only
be contrary to Art. 361 of the Revised Penal Code. It would,
above all, infringe on the constitutionally guaranteed freedom
of expression. Such a rule would deter citizens from performing
171

172

Id. at 1023-1024, citing Professors William Lloyd Prosser and W. Page Keeton, Prosser and Keeton on
Torts, 5th ed. at 859861 (1984).
373 Phil. 238 (1999) [Per J. Mendoza, En Banc].

Dissenting & Concurring

56

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion
their duties as members of a self-governing community. Without
free speech and assembly, discussions of our most abiding
concerns as a nation would be stifled. As Justice Brandeis has said,
public discussion is a political duty and the greatest menace to
freedom is an inert people. 173 (Emphasis supplied)

Guingguing v. Court of Appeals 174 involved the publication of


information on private complainants criminal cases including photographs
of him being arrested. This court again reiterated:
[Article 354 of the Revised Penal Code], as applied to public
figures complaining of criminal libel, must be construed in light of
the constitutional guarantee of free expression, and this Courts
precedents upholding the standard of actual malice with the
necessary implication that a statement regarding a public figure if
true is not libelous. The provision itself allows for such leeway,
accepting as a defense good intention and justifiable motive. The
exercise of free expression, and its concordant assurance of
commentary on public affairs and public figures, certainly qualify
as justifiable motive, if not good intention.
xxxx
As adverted earlier, the guarantee of free speech was enacted
to protect not only polite speech, but even expression in its
most unsophisticated form. Criminal libel stands as a necessary
qualification to any absolutist interpretation of the free speech
clause, if only because it prevents the proliferation of untruths
which if unrefuted, would gain an undue influence in the public
discourse. But in order to safeguard against fears that the
public debate might be muted due to the reckless enforcement
of libel laws, truth has been sanctioned as a defense, much
more in the case when the statements in question address
public issues or involve public figures. 175 (Emphasis supplied)

In Villanueva v. Philippine Daily Inquirer, Inc., 176 despite the


respondents false reporting, this court continued to apply the actual malice
doctrine that evolved from Ayer Productions. Hence:
A newspaper, especially one national in reach and
coverage, should be free to report on events and developments in
which the public has a legitimate interest with minimum fear of
being hauled to court by one group or another on criminal or civil
charges for malice or damages, i.e. libel, so long as the newspaper
respects and keeps within the standards of morality and civility
prevailing within the general community. 177
173
174
175
176
177

Id. at 250-255.
508 Phil. 193 (2005) [Per J. Tinga, Second Division].
Id. at 221-222.
G.R. No. 164437, May 15, 2009, 588 SCRA 1 [Per J. Quisumbing, Second Division].
Villanueva v. Philippine Daily Inquirer, Inc., G.R. No. 164437, May 15, 2009, 588 SCRA 1, 15 [Per J.
Quisumbing, Second Division].

Dissenting & Concurring

57

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

V (D)
Overbreadth by Reenactment
With the definite evolution of jurisprudence to accommodate free
speech values, it is clear that the reenactment of the old text of libel is now
unconstitutional. Articles 353, 354, and 355 of the Revised Penal Code
and by reference, Section 4(c)4 of the law in question are now
overbroad as it prescribes a definition and presumption that have been
repeatedly struck down by this court for several decades.
A statute falls under the overbreadth doctrine when a governmental
purpose may not be achieved by means which sweep unnecessarily broadly
and thereby invade the area of protected freedoms. 178 Section 4(c)(4) of
Rep. Act No. 10175 and Articles 353, 354, and 355 produce a chilling effect
on speech by being fatally inconsistent with Ayer Productions as well as by
imposing criminal liability in addition to civil ones. Not only once, but
several times, did this court uphold the freedom of speech and expression
under Article III, Section 4 of the 1987 Constitution 179 over an alleged
infringement of privacy or defamation. This trend implies an evolving
rejection of the criminal nature of libel and must be expressly recognized in
view of this courts duty to uphold the guarantees under the Constitution.
The threat to freedom of speech and the publics participation in
matters of general public interest is greater than any satisfaction from
imprisonment of one who has allegedly malicious[ly] imput[ed] x x x a
crime, or x x x a vice or defect, real or imaginary, or any act, omission,
condition, status, or circumstance tending to cause the dishonor, discredit, or
contempt of a natural or juridical person, or xxx blacken[ed] the memory of
[the] dead. 180 The law provides for other means of preventing abuse and
unwarranted attacks on the reputation or credibility of a private person.
Among others, this remedy is granted under the Chapter on Human
Relations in the Civil Code, particularly Articles 19, 181 20, 182 21, 183 and even
26. 184 There is, thus, no cogent reason that a penal statute would
178

179

180

181
182

183

184

Estrada v. Sandiganbayan, 421 Phil. 290, 353 (2001) [Per J. Bellosillo, En Banc] citing NAACP v.
Alabama, 377 U.S. 288, 307, 12 L.Ed.2d 325, 338 (1958); Shelton v. Tucker, 364 U.S. 479, 5 L.Ed.2d
231 (1960).
Sec. 4. No law shall be passed abridging the freedom of speech, of expression, or of the press, or the
right of the people peaceably to assemble and petition the government for redress of grievances.
Revised Penal Code, Art. 353.
Art. 19. Every person must, in the exercise of his rights and in the performance of his duties, act with
justice, give everyone his due, and observe honesty and good faith.
Art. 20. Every person who, contrary to law, wilfully or negligently causes damage to another, shall
indemnify the latter for the same.
Art. 21. Any person who wilfully causes loss or injury to another in manner that is contrary to morals,
good customs or public policy shall compensate the latter for the damage.
Art. 26. Every person shall respect the dignity, personality, privacy and peace of mind of his neighbors
and other persons. The following and similar acts, though they may not constitute a criminal offense,
shall produce a cause of action for damages, prevention and other relief:

Dissenting & Concurring

58

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

overbroadly subsume the primordial right of freedom of speech provided


for in the Constitution.
V (E)
Dangers to Protected Speech Posed by Libel
Exacerbated in the Internet
The effect on speech of the dangerously broad provisions of the
current law on libel is even more palpable in the internet.
Libel under Article 353 is textually defined as the:
x x x public and malicious imputation of a crime, or of a
vice or defect, real or imaginary, or any act, omission, condition,
status, or circumstance tending to cause the dishonor, discredit, or
contempt of a natural or juridical person, or to blacken the memory
of one who is dead. (Emphasis supplied)

Social media allows users to create various groups of various sizes.


Some of these sites are for specific purposes. Others are only open to a select
group of friends or followers. The ponencias distinction between the
author and those who share (or simply express their approval) of the posted
message oversimplifies the phenomenon of exchanges through these sites.
Social media or social networking sites are websites that primarily
exist to allow users to post a profile online and exchange or broadcast
messages and information with their friends and contacts. 185
Social media or social networking as it is used today began in the
United States in 1994 when Beverly Hills Internet created the online
community known as Geocities. 186 In Geocities, individuals were able to
design custom-made websites using hypertext mark-up language or HTML
and upload content online. This community then paved the way for
widespread online interaction, leading to the inception of America Onlines
Instant Messenger, where subscribers of the internet service provider could
(1) Prying into the privacy of another's residence;
(2) Meddling with or disturbing the private life or family relations of another;
(3) Intriguing to cause another to be alienated from his friends;
(4) Vexing or humiliating another on account of his religious beliefs, lowly station in life, place of
birth, physical defect, or other personal condition.

185

186

See also Justice Carpios dissenting opinion in MVRS Publications, Inc., v. Islamic Dawah Council of
the Philippines, Inc., 444 Phil. 230 (2004) [Per J. Bellosillo, En Banc]. Justice Carpio was of the view
that the defamatory article published in the case fell under Article 26 of the Civil Code.
See Tucker, C. and A. Matthews, Social Networks, Advertising and Antitrust, in GEORGE MASON LAW
REVIEW, 19 Geo. Mason L. Rev. 1211, 1214.
See < http://www2.uncp.edu/home/acurtis/NewMedia/SocialMedia/SocialMediaHistory.html> (visited
February 19, 2014).

Dissenting & Concurring

59

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

send real-time exchanges through the network. This led to the prevalence of
instant messaging applications such as ICQ and online chatrooms such as
mIRC. 187 In 1999, British website Friends Reunited was the first popular
online hub whose primary purpose was to allow users to interact and
reconnect with former classmates through the internet. 188 Friendster,
launched in 2002, became one the first and largest online social networking
sites, reaching up to 117 million users before its decline. 189 The site was
dedicated to connecting with as many people as possible, without a need for
prior physical contact or established relationships. MySpace, another social
networking site launched in 2003, garnered more visitors than popular
search engine sites Google and Yahoo in 2006. 190 These online social
networking sites have had several popular iterations such as Multiply,
LiveJournal or Blogger, which serve as venues for individuals who wish to
post individual journal entries, photographs or videos.
Today, the most popular social networking sites are Facebook and
Twitter. Facebook, which was initially known as Facesmash for exclusive
use of Harvard University students and alumni, began in 2003. Eventually,
Facebook became the most prevalent and ubiquitous online social
networking site, with some 750 million users worldwide, as of July 2011. 191
Twitter gained popularity immediately after its founding in 2006. It
gained prominence by positioning itself as a real-time information network
while allowing ease of access and immediate sharing to an expanding set of
users. To date, Twitter has about 750 million registered users, with about
200 million users making use of the platform on a regular basis. 192 In its
latest initial public offering, Twitter disclosed that there are over 500 million
tweets (messages with a140-character limit) made in a day. 193
The most recent social networking phenomenon is Instagram, which
was launched in October 2010. This application allows instantaneous
sharing of photographs especially through smartphones. Today, Instagram
has 150 million active users and with over 1.5 billion likes of photos
shared on the network every day. 194

187
188
189

190

191

192

193

194

See < http://im.about.com/od/imbasics/a/imhistory_3.htm> (visited February 19, 2014).


See < http://www.friendsreunited.com/About> (visited February 19, 2014).
D. Garcia, P. Mavrodiev, and F. Schweitzer, Social Resilience in Online Communities: The Autopsy of
Friendster. Available at < http://arxiv.org/pdf/1302.6109v1.pdf> (visited February 19, 2014).
See < http://www.huffingtonpost.com/2011/06/29/myspace-historytimeline_n_887059.html#s299557&title=July_2006_Number> (visited February 19, 2014).
See S. Davis, STUDENT COMMENT: Social Media Activity & the Workplace: Updating the Status of
Social Media, 39 Ohio N.U.L. Rev. 359, 361.
See < http://venturebeat.com/2013/09/16/how-twitter-plans-to-make-its-750m-users-like-its-250mreal-users/> (visited February 19, 2014).
See < http://abcnews.go.com/Business/twitter-ipo-filing-reveals-500-million-tweetsday/story?id=20460493> (visited February 19, 2014).
See < http://sourcedigit.com/4023-instagram-timeline-history/> (visited February 19, 2014).

Dissenting & Concurring

60

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

These platforms in social media allow users to establish their own


social network. It enables instantaneous online interaction, with each social
networking platform thriving on its ability to engage more and more users.
In order to acquire more users, the owners and developers of these social
media sites constantly provide their users with more features, and with more
opportunities to interact. The number of networks grows as each participant
is invited to bring in more of their friends and acquaintances to use the
platforms. Social media platforms, thus, continue to expand in terms of its
influence and its ability to serve as a medium for human interaction. These
also encourage self-expression through words, pictures, video, and a
combination of these genres.
There can be personal networks created through these platforms
simply for conversations among friends. Like its counterpart in the real
world, this can be similar to a meeting over coffee where friends or
acquaintances exchange views about any and all matters of their interest. In
normal conversation, the context provided by the participants relationships
assure levels of confidence that will allow them to exchange remarks that
may be caustic, ironic, sarcastic or even defamatory.
With social media, ones message in virtual conversations may be
reposted and may come in different forms. On Facebook, the post can be
shared while on Twitter, the message can be retweeted. In these
instances, the author remains the same but the reposted message can be put
in a different context by the one sharing it which the author may not have
originally intended. The message that someone is a thief and an idiot in
friendly and private conversation when taken out of that context will become
defamatory. This applies regardless of the standing of the subject of
conversation: The person called a thief and an idiot may be an important
public figure or an ordinary person.
The ponencia proposes to exonerate the user who reposts but maintain
the liability of the author. This classification is not clear anywhere in the text
of the law. Parenthetically, whether calling someone a thief or an idiot is
considered defamatory is not also clear in the text of the law.
Even if we assume arguendo that this is a reasonable text-based
distinction, the result proposed by the majority does not meet the proposed
intent of the law. Private individuals (as opposed to public officials or
figures) are similarly maligned by reposts.
This shows the arbitrariness of the text of the law as well as the
categorization proposed by the ponencia. It leaves too much room for the
law enforcer to decide which kinds of posts or reposts are defamatory. The

Dissenting & Concurring

61

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

limits will not be clear to the speaker or writer. Hence, they will then limit
their expression or stifle the sharing of their ideas. They are definite victims
of the chilling effect of the vagueness of the provisions in question.
The problem becomes compounded with messages that are reposted
with or without comment. The following tweets are examples which will
provide the heuristic to understand the problem:
Form A: @marvicleonen: RT @somebody: Juan is a liar,
a thief and an idiot #thetruth
Form B: @marvicleonen: This! RT @somebody: Juan is a
liar, a thief and an idiot #thetruth

Both are posts from a user with the handle @marvicleonen. RT means
that the following message was only reposted (retweeted), and the hashtag
#thetruth is simply a way of categorizing ones messages. The hashtag itself
may also contain speech elements.
Form A is a simple repost. The reasons for reposting are ambiguous.
Since reposting is only a matter of a click of a button, it could be that it was
done without a lot of deliberation. It is also possible that the user agreed with
the message and wanted his network to know of his agreement. It is possible
that the user also wanted his network to understand and accept the message.
Form B is a repost with a comment This!. While it may be clearer
that there is some deliberation in the intent to share, it is not clear whether
this is an endorsement of the statement or simply sarcasm. This form is not
part of the categorization proposed by the ponencia.
There are other permutations as there are new platforms that continue
to emerge. Viber and WhatsApp for instance now enable SMS users to
create their own network.
There are other problems created by such broad law in the internet.
The network made by the original author may only be of real friends of
about 10 people. The network where his or her post was shared might
consist of a thousand participants. Again, the current law on libel fails to
take these problems of context into consideration.
A post, comment or status message regarding government or a public
figure has the tendency to be shared. It easily becomes viral. After all,
there will be more interest among those who use the internet with messages
that involve issues that are common to them or are about people that are
known to themusually public officers and public figures. When the

Dissenting & Concurring

62

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

decision in this case will be made known to the public, it is certain to


stimulate internet users to initially post their gut reactions. It will also entice
others to write thought pieces that will also be shared among their friends
and followers.
Then, there is the problem of extraterritoriality and the evils that it
spawns on speech. Enforcement of the crime of libel will be viable only if
the speaker is within our national territory. Those residing in other countries
are beyond our jurisdiction. To be extradited, they will have to have laws
similar to ours. If they reside in a state different from our 1930 version of
libel, then we will have the phenomenon of foreigners or expatriates having
more leeway to criticize and contribute to democratic exchanges than those
who have stayed within our borders.
The broad and simplistic formulation now in Article 353 of the
Revised Penal Code essential for the punishment of cyber libel can only
cope with these variations produced by the technologies in the internet by
giving law enforcers wide latitude to determine which acts are defamatory.
There are no judicially determinable standards. The approach will allow
subjective case-by-case ad hoc determination. There will be no real notice to
the speaker or writer. The speaker or writer will calibrate speech not on the
basis of what the law provides but on who enforces it.
This is quintessentially the chilling effect of this law.
The threat of being prosecuted for libel stifles the dynamism of the
conversations that take place in cyberspace. These conversations can be
loose yet full of emotion. These can be analytical and the product of
painstaking deliberation. Other conversations can just be exponential
combinations of these forms that provide canisters to evolving ideas as
people from different communities with varied identities and cultures come
together to test their messages.
Certainly, there will be a mix of the public and the private; the serious
and the not so serious. But, this might be the kind of democratic spaces
needed by our society: a mishmash of emotion and logic that may creatively
spring solutions to grave public issues in better and more entertaining ways
than a symposium of scholars. Libel with its broad bright lines, thus, is an
anachronistic tool that may have had its uses in older societies: a monkey
wrench that will steal inspiration from the democratic mob.

Dissenting & Concurring

63

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

V (F)
No State Interest in Criminalizing Libel
The kinds of speech that are actually deterred by libel law are more
valuable than the state interest that is sought to be protected by the crime.
Besides, there are less draconian alternatives which have very minimal
impact on the publics fundamental right of expression. Civil actions for
defamation do not threaten the publics fundamental right to free speech.
They narrow its availability such that there is no unnecessary chilling effect
on criticisms of public officials or policy. They also place the proper
economic burden on the complainant and, therefore, reduce the possibility
that they be used as tools to harass or silence dissenters.
The purposes of criminalizing libel come to better light when we
review its history. This court has had the opportunity to trace its historical
development. Guingguing v. Court of Appeals 195 narrated:
Originally, the truth of a defamatory imputation was not
considered a defense in the prosecution for libel. In the landmark
opinion of England's Star Chamber in the Libelis Famosis case in
1603, two major propositions in the prosecution of defamatory
remarks were established: first, that libel against a public person is
a greater offense than one directed against an ordinary man, and
second, that it is immaterial that the libel be true. These
propositions were due to the fact that the law of defamatory libel
was developed under the common law to help government
protect itself from criticism and to provide an outlet for
individuals to defend their honor and reputation so they would
not resort to taking the law into their own hands.
Our understanding of criminal libel changed in 1735 with
the trial and acquittal of John Peter Zenger for seditious libel in the
then English colony of New York. Zenger, the publisher of the
New-York Weekly Journal, had been charged with seditious libel,
for his papers consistent attacks against Colonel William Cosby,
the Royal Governor of New York. In his defense, Zengers
counsel, Andrew Hamilton, argued that the criticisms against
Governor Cosby were the right of every free-born subject to
make when the matters so published can be supported with
truth. The jury, by acquitting Zenger, acknowledged albeit
unofficially the defense of truth in a libel action. The Zenger case
also laid to rest the idea that public officials were immune from
criticism.
The Zenger case is crucial, not only to the evolution of the
doctrine of criminal libel, but also to the emergence of the
American democratic ideal. It has been characterized as the first
landmark in the tradition of a free press, then a somewhat radical
notion that eventually evolved into the First Amendment in the
195

Guingguing v. Court of Appeals, 508 Phil. 193 (2005) [Per J. Tinga, Second Division].

Dissenting & Concurring

64

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion
American Bill of Rights and also proved an essential weapon in the
war of words that led into the American War for Independence.
Yet even in the young American state, the government paid
less than ideal fealty to the proposition that Congress shall pass no
law abridging the freedom of speech. The notorious Alien and
Sedition Acts of 1798 made it a crime for any person who, by
writing, speaking or printing, should threaten an officer of the
government with damage to his character, person, or estate. The
law was passed at the insistence of President John Adams, whose
Federalist Party had held a majority in Congress, and who had
faced persistent criticism from political opponents belonging to the
Jeffersonian Republican Party. As a result, at least twenty-five
people, mostly Jeffersonian Republican editors, were arrested
under the law. The Acts were never challenged before the U.S.
Supreme Court, but they were not subsequently renewed upon their
expiration.
The massive unpopularity of the Alien and Sedition Acts
contributed to the electoral defeat of President Adams in 1800. In
his stead was elected Thomas Jefferson, a man who once famously
opined, Were it left to me to decide whether we should have a
government without newspapers, or newspapers without a
government, I should not hesitate a moment to prefer the latter. 196

It was in that case where the court noted the history of early American
media that focused on a mad dog rhetoric approach. This, in turn, led the
court to conclude that [t]hese observations are important in light of the
misconception that freedom of expression extends only to polite, temperate,
or reasoned expression. x x x Evidently, the First Amendment was designed
to protect expression even at its most rambunctious and vitriolic form as it
had prevalently taken during the time the clause was enacted. 197
The case that has defined our understanding of the concept of modern
libel the New York Times Co. v. Sullivan 198 then followed. As discussed
earlier, the New York Times case required proof of actual malice when a case
for defamation includes matters of public concern, public men, and
candidates for office. 199
The cases of Garrison v. Louisiana, and Curtis Publishing Co. v.
Butts both expanded the New York Times actual malice test to public
officials and public figures, respectively. 200

196

197
198
199
200

Guingguing v. Court of Appeals, 508 Phil. 193, 204-206 (2005) [Per J. Tinga, Second Division], citing
New York Times v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254, 300-301(1964).
Id. at 207.
376 U.S. 254 (1964).
New York Times v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254, 281-282 (1964).
See Guingguing v. Court of Appeals, 508 Phil. 193, 209-211 (2005) [Per J. Tinga, Second Division],
citing Garrison v. Louisiana, 379 U.S. 64 (1964) and Curtis Publishing Co. v. Butts, 388 U.S. 130,
163-164 (1967), CJ Warren, concurring.

Dissenting & Concurring

65

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

Libel in the Philippines first emerged during the Spanish colonial


times. The Spanish Penal Code criminalized rebellion, sedition, assaults,
upon persons in authority, and their agents, and contempts, insults, injurias,
and threats against persons in authority and insults, injurias, and threats
against their agents and other public officers. 201 Thus, noting the
developments in both the Spanish and American colonial periods, it was
correctly observed that:
The use of criminal libel to regulate speech especially
speech critical of foreign rule or advocating Philippine
independence was a feature of both the Spanish and
American colonial regimes. The Spanish Penal Code and
the Penal Code of the Philippines made insult and calumny
a crime. In the early 1900s, the Philippine Commission
(whose members were all appointed by the President of the
United States) punished both civil and criminal libel under
Act No. 277, one of its earliest laws. 202

During the American occupation, Governor-General William Howard


Taft explained how libel was made into a criminal offense in the
Philippines because the limitations of free speech are not very well
understood unlike in the US203 Then came the case of U.S. v. Ocampo, 204
where Martin Ocampo, Teodoro M. Kalaw, Lope K. Santos, Fidel A. Reyes,
and Faustino Aguilar were charged with libel in connection with the
publication of the article Birds of Prey in the newspaper El Renacimiento.
The article allegedly defamed Philippine Commission member and Interior
Secretary Mr. Dean C. Worcester. This court affirmed the conviction of
Ocampo and Kalaw stating that there were no justifiable motives found in
the publication of the article.
In essence, Philippine libel law is a fusion of the Spanish law on
defamacion and the American law on libel. 205 It started as a legal tool to
protect government and the status quo. The bare text of the law had to be
qualified through jurisprudential interpretation as the fundamental right to
expression became clearer. In theory, libel prosecution has slowly evolved
from protecting both private citizens and public figures to its modern notion
of shielding only private parties from defamatory utterances.
But, a survey of libel cases during the past two (2) decades will reveal
that the libel cases that have gone up to the Supreme Court 206 generally
involved notable personalities for parties. Relatively, libel cases that involve
201
202
203
204
205

206

D. G. K. Carreon, A Long History, in LIBEL AS POLITICS 70 (2008).


J. M. I. Diokno, A Human Rights Perspective, in LIBEL AS POLITICS 17-18 (2008).
D. G. K. Carreon, A Long History, in LIBEL AS POLITICS 71 (2008).
18 Phil. 1 (1910) [Per J. Johnson].
J. M. I. Diokno, A Human Rights Perspective, in LIBEL AS POLITICS 18 (2008) citing People v. Del
Rosario, 86 Phil. 163 (1950).
These include cases that resolved the issue of guilt for the offense as well as cases that tackled
procedural or jurisdictional issues and remanded the main issue to the trial court.

Dissenting & Concurring

66

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

private parties before the Supreme Court are sparse. 207 Dean Raul
Pangalangan, former dean of the University of the Philippines College of
Law and now publisher of the Philippine Daily Inquirer, observed that libel
cases are pursued to their conclusion mainly by public figures, x x x [since
those filed] by private persons are settled amicably before the prosecutor. 208
Among the cases that reached the Supreme Court were those involving
offended parties who were electoral candidates, 209 ambassadors and business
tycoons, 210 lawyers, 211 actors or celebrities, 212 corporations, 213 and, public
officers. 214 Even court officials have been involved as complainants in libel
cases. 215
This attests to the propensity to use the advantages of criminal libel by
those who are powerful and influential to silence their critics. Without doubt,
the continuous evolution and reiteration of the jurisprudential limitations in
the interpretation of criminal libel as currently worded has not been a
deterrent. The present law on libel as reenacted by Section 4(c)(4) of Rep.
Act No. 10175 will certainly do little to shield protected speech. This is clear
because there has been no improvement in statutory text from its version in
1930.
207

208

209

210

211

212

213

214

215

See Magno v. People, 516 Phil. 72 (2006) [Per J. Garcia, Second Division]; See also MVRS
Publications, Inc. v. Islamic Dawah Council of the Philippines, Inc., 444 Phil. 230 (2004) [Per J.
Bellosillo, En Banc]; Villamar-Sandoval v. Cailipan, G.R. No. 200727, March 4, 2013, 692 SCRA 339
(2013) [Per J. Perlas-Bernabe, Second Division].
R. Pangalangan, Libel as Politics, in LIBEL AS POLITICS 11 (2008). Note, however, our ruling in
Crespo v. Mogul, 235 Phil. 465 (1987), where we said that, it is the duty of the fiscal to proceed with
the presentation of evidence of the prosecution to the Court to enable the Court to arrive at its own
independent judgment as to whether the accused should be convicted or acquitted. x x x The rule
therefore in this jurisdiction is that once a complaint or information is filed in Court any disposition of
the case as its dismissal or the conviction or acquittal of the accused rests in the sound discretion of the
Court.
See Brillante v. Court of Appeals, 483 Phil. 568 (2004) [Per J. Tinga, Second Division]; Villanueva v.
Philippine Daily Inquirer, Inc., G.R. No. 164437, May 15, 2009, 588 SCRA 1 [Per J. Quisumbing,
Second Division].
See Yuchengco v. Manila Chronicle Publishing Corporation, G.R. No. 184315, November 25, 2009,
605 SCRA 684 [Per J. Chico-Nazario, Third Division]; Bonifacio v. Regional Trial Court of Makati,
Branch 149, G.R. No. 184800, May 5, 2010, 620 SCRA 268 [Per J. Carpio-Morales, First Division].
This case involved allegedly libelous articles published in websites.
See Buatis v. People, 520 Phil. 149 (2006) [Per J. Austria-Martinez, First Division]; See also Tulfo v.
People, 587 Phil. 64 (2008) [Per J. Velasco, Jr., Second Division]; and Fortun v. Quinsayas, G.R. No.
194578, February 13, 2013, 690 SCRA 623 [Per J. Carpio, Second Division]. This case originated as a
special civil action for contempt involving Atty. Sigfrid A. Fortun and several media outfits. However,
this court expanded the concept of public figures to lawyers, stating that lawyers of high-profile cases
involving public concern become public figures.
See Fermin v. People, G.R. No. 157643, March 28, 2008, 550 SCRA 132 [Per J. Nachura, Third
Division]; Bautista v. Cuneta-Pangilinan, G.R. No. 189754, October 24, 2012, 684 SCRA 521 [Per J.
Peralta, Third Division].
See Banal III v. Panganiban, 511 Phil. 605 (2005) [Per J. Ynares-Santiago, First Division]. See also
Insular Life Assurance Company, Limited v. Serrano, 552 Phil. 469 (2007) [Per C.J. Puno, First
Division].
See Lagaya v. People, G.R. No. 176251, July 25, 2012, 677 SCRA 478 [Per J. Del Castillo, First
Division]; Lopez v. People, G.R. No. 172203, February 14, 2011 642 SCRA 668 [Per J. Del Castillo,
First Division]; Binay v. Secretary of Justice, 532 Phil. 742 (2006) [Per J. Ynares-Santiago, First
Division]; See also Jalandoni v. Drilon, 383 Phil. 855 (2000) [Per J. Buena, Second Division];
Macasaet v. Co, Jr., G.R. No. 156759, June 5, 2013, 697 SCRA 187; Tulfo v. People, 587 Phil. 64
(2008) [Per J. Velasco, Jr., Second Division].
See Yambot v. Tuquero, G.R. No. 169895, March 23, 2011, 646 SCRA 249 [Per J. Leonardo-De
Castro, First Division].

Dissenting & Concurring

67

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

Libel law now is used not so much to prosecute but to deter speech.
What is charged as criminal libel may contain precious protected speech.
There is very little to support the view of the majority that the law will not
continue to have this effect on speech.
This court has adopted the American case of Garrison v. Louisiana,
albeit qualifiedly, in recognizing that there is an international trend in
diminishing the scope, if not the viability, of criminal libel prosecutions. 216
Garrison struck down the Louisiana Criminal Defamation Statute and held
that the statute incorporated constitutionally invalid standards when it came
to criticizing or commenting on the official conduct of public officials.
It is time that we now go further and declare libel, as provided in the
Revised Penal Code and in the Cybercrime Prevention Act of 2012, as
unconstitutional.
This does not mean that abuse and unwarranted attacks on the
reputation or credibility of a private person will not be legally addressed.
The legal remedy is civil in nature and granted in provisions such as the
Chapter on Human Relations in the Civil Code, particularly Articles 19, 20,
and 21. 217 These articles provide:
Art. 19. Every person must, in the exercise of his rights and in the
performance of his duties, act with justice, give everyone his due,
and observe honesty and good faith.
216

Guingguing v. Court of Appeals, 508 Phil. 193, 214 (2005), citing Garrison, 379 U.S. 64 (1964). This
court in Guingguing said that:
Lest the impression be laid that criminal libel law was rendered extinct in regards to
public officials, the Court made this important qualification in Garrison:

217

The use of calculated falsehood, however, would put a different cast on the
constitutional question. Although honest utterance, even if inaccurate, may further the
fruitful exercise of the right of free speech, it does not follow that the lie, knowingly and
deliberately published about a public official, should enjoy a like immunity. At the time
the First Amendment was adopted, as today, there were those unscrupulous enough and
skillful enough to use the deliberate or reckless falsehood as an effective political tool to
unseat the public servant or even topple an administration. That speech is used as a tool
for political ends does not automatically bring it under the protective mantle of the
Constitution. For the use of the known lie as a tool is at once with odds with the premises
of democratic government and with the orderly manner in which economic, social, or
political change is to be effected.
See also Justice Carpios dissenting opinion in MVRS Publications, Inc. v. Islamic Dawah Council of
the Philippines, Inc. 444 Phil. 230 (2004) [Per J. Bellosillo, En Banc] where he opined that the
defamatory article published in the case falls under Article 26 of the Civil Code.
Article 26. Every person shall respect the dignity, personality, privacy and peace of mind of his
neighbors and other persons. The following and similar acts, though they may not constitute a criminal
offense, shall produce a cause of action for damages, prevention and other relief:
(1) Prying into the privacy of another's residence;
(2) Meddling with or disturbing the private life or family relations of another;
(3) Intriguing to cause another to be alienated from his friends;
(4) Vexing or humiliating another on account of his religious beliefs, lowly station in life, place of
birth, physical defect, or other personal condition.

Dissenting & Concurring

68

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

Article 20. Every person who, contrary to law, wilfully or


negligently causes damage to another, shall indemnify the latter for
the same.
Article 21. Any person who wilfully causes loss or injury to
another in manner that is contrary to morals, good customs or
public policy shall compensate the latter for the damage.

This court previously discussed the nature and applicability of Articles


19 to 21 of the Civil Code, stating that:
[Article 19], known to contain what is commonly referred
to as the principle of abuse of rights, sets certain standards which
must be observed not only in the exercise of one's rights but also in
the performance of one's duties. These standards are the following:
to act with justice; to give everyone his due; and to observe
honesty and good faith. The law, therefore, recognizes a primordial
limitation on all rights; that in their exercise, the norms of human
conduct set forth in Article 19 must be observed. A right, though
by itself legal because recognized or granted by law as such, may
nevertheless become the source of some illegality. When a right is
exercised in a manner which does not conform with the norms
enshrined in Article 19 and results in damage to another, a legal
wrong is thereby committed for which the wrongdoer must be held
responsible. But while Article 19 lays down a rule of conduct for
the government of human relations and for the maintenance of
social order, it does not provide a remedy for its violation.
Generally, an action for damages under either Article 20 or Article
21 would be proper.
Article 20, which pertains to damage arising from a
violation of law, provides that:
Art. 20. Every person who contrary to law, wilfully or negligently
causes damage to another, shall indemnify the latter for the same.
x x x Article 21 of the Civil Code provides that:
Art. 21. Any person who wilfully causes loss or injury to another
in a manner that is contrary to morals, good customs or public
policy shall compensate the latter for the damage.
This article, adopted to remedy the "countless gaps in the
statutes, which leave so many victims of moral wrongs helpless,
even though they have actually suffered material and moral injury"
[Id.] should "vouchsafe adequate legal remedy for that untold
number of moral wrongs which it is impossible for human
foresight to provide for specifically in the statutes" [Id. it p. 40; See
also PNB v. CA, G.R. No. L-27155, May 18, 1978, 83 SCRA 237,
247].
In determining whether or not the principle of abuse of
rights may be invoked, there is no rigid test which can be applied.

Dissenting & Concurring

69

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion
While the Court has not hesitated to apply Article 19 whether the
legal and factual circumstances called for its application [See for
e.g., Velayo v. Shell Co. of the Phil., Ltd., 100 Phil. 186 (1956);
PNB v. CA, supra; Grand Union Supermarket, Inc. v. Espino, Jr.,
G.R. No. L-48250, December 28, 1979, 94 SCRA 953; PAL v.
CA, G.R. No. L-46558, July 31, 1981,106 SCRA 391; United
General Industries, Inc, v. Paler G.R. No. L-30205, March
15,1982,112 SCRA 404; Rubio v. CA, G.R. No. 50911, August 21,
1987, 153 SCRA 183] the question of whether or not the principle
of abuse of rights has been violated resulting in damages under
Article 20 or Article 21 or other applicable provision of law,
depends on the circumstances of each case. x x x. 218

In affirming award of damages under Article 19 of the Civil Code, this


court has said that [t]he legitimate state interest underlying the law of libel
is the compensation of the individuals for the harm inflicted upon them by
defamatory falsehood. After all, the individuals right to protection of his
own good name reflects no more than our basic concept of the essential
dignity and worth of every human being a concept at the root of any decent
system of ordered liberty. 219
In a civil action, the complainant decides what to allege in the
complaint, how much damages to request, whether to proceed or at what
point to compromise with the defendant. Whether reputation is tarnished or
not is a matter that depends on the toleration, maturity, and notoriety of the
person involved. Varying personal thresholds exists. Various social contexts
will vary at these levels of toleration. Sarcasm, for instance, may be
acceptable in some conversations but highly improper in others.
In a criminal action, on the other hand, the offended party does not
have full control of the case. He or she must get the concurrence of the
public prosecutor as well as the court whenever he or she wants the
complaint to be dismissed. The state, thus, has its own agency. It will decide
for itself through the prosecutor and the court.
Criminalizing libel imposes a standard threshold and context for the
entire society. It masks individual differences and unique contexts. Criminal
libel, in the guise of protecting reputation, makes differences invisible.
Libel as an element of civil liability makes defamation a matter
between the parties. Of course, because trial is always public, it also
provides for measured retribution for the offended person. The possibility of
being sued also provides for some degree of deterrence.
218

219

Globe Mackay Cable and Radio Corp. v. Court of Appeals, 257 Phil. 783, 783-785 (1989) [Per J.
Cortes, Third Division].
Philippine Journalists, Inc. (Peoples Journal) v. Thoenen, 513 Phil. 607, 625 (2005) [Per J. ChicoNazario, Second Division], citing Garrison v. Louisiana, 379 US 64 (1964), which in turn cited Justice
Stewarts concurring opinion in Rosenblatt v. Baer, 383 US 75 (1966).

70

Dissenting & Concurring

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

The states interest to protect private defamation is better served with


laws providing for civil remedies for the affected party. It is entirely within
the control of the offended party. The facts that will constitute the cause of
action will be narrowly tailored to address the perceived wrong. The relief,
whether injunctive or in damages, will be appropriate to the wrong.
Declaring criminal libel as unconstitutional, therefore, does not mean
that the state countenances private defamation. It is just consistent with our
democratic values.
VI
Cybersex is Unconstitutional
Section 4(c)(1) of Rep. Act No. 10175 is also overbroad and,
therefore, unconstitutional. As presently worded:

SEC. 4. Cybercrime Offenses. The following acts constitute the


offense of cybercrime punishable under this Act:
(c) Content-related Offenses:
(1) Cybersex. The willful engagement, maintenance, control, or
operation, directly or indirectly, of any lascivious exhibition of
sexual organs or sexual activity, with the aid of a computer system,
for favor or consideration.

The ponencia invites us to go beyond the plain and ordinary text of


the law and replace it with the deliberations in committees that prepared the
provision. Thus, it claims: (t)he Act actually seeks to punish cyber
prostitution, white slave trade, and pornography for favor and consideration.
This includes interactive prostitution and pornography, i.e. by webcam. 220
The majority is not clear why the tighter language defining the crimes
of prostitution and white slavery was not referred to clearly in the provision.
Neither does it explain the states interest in prohibiting intimate private
exhibition (even for favor or consideration) by web cam as opposed to
physical carnal knowledge required now in the crime of prostitution.
Worse, the ponencia fails to appreciate the precarious balance that
decades of jurisprudence carved out in relation to criminalizing expression
with sexual content. Instead, the ponencia points out that the x x x subject
220

Ponencia, J. Abad, 17-18. Citations omitted.

Dissenting & Concurring

71

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

of section 4(c)(1)lascivious exhibition of sexual organs or sexual


activityis not novel. Article 201 of the RPC punishes obscene
publications and exhibitions and indecent shows. 221 Again, we are thrown
back to the 1930 version of the Revised Penal Code. With constant and
painstaking tests that will bring enlightenment to expression with sexual
content evolved through jurisprudence, it seems that we, as a society, are
being thrown back to the dark ages.
VI (B)
Sweeping Scope of Section 4(c)(1)
This provision is too sweeping in its scope.
As worded, it unreasonably empowers the state to police intimate
human expression. The standard for lascivious exhibition and the meaning
of sexual organ or sexual activity empowers law enforcers to pass off their
very personal standards of their own morality. Enforcement will be strict or
loose depending on their tastes. Works of art sold in the market in the form
of photographs, paintings, memes, and other genre posted in the internet
would have to shape their expression in accordance with the tastes of local
law enforcers. Art whether free, sold or bartered will not expand our
horizons; it will be limited by the status quo in our culture wherein the
dominant themes will remain dominant. There will be patriarchal control
over what is acceptable intimate expression.
This provision, thus, produces a chilling effect. It provides for no
restrictions to power and allows power to determine what is lascivious and
what is not.
Respondents concede that certain artistic works even if they feature
nudity and the sexual act are protected speech. They argue that the
interpretation of the provision should allow for these kinds of expression.
However, this reading cannot be found from the current text of the
provision. The Solicitor General, though an important public officer, is not
the local policeman in either an urban or rural setting in the Philippines.
Certain art works that depict the nude human body or the various
forms of human intimacies will necessarily have a certain degree of
lasciviousness. Human intimacy, depicted in the sexual act, is not sterile. It
is necessarily evocative, expressive, and full of emotions. Sexual expression
can be titillating and engaging. It is to be felt perhaps more than it should be
rationally understood.

221

Id. at 18.

Dissenting & Concurring

72

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

Michaelangelos marble statue, David, powerfully depicted an


exposed Biblical hero. Sandro Boticellis painting, Birth of Venus,
emphatically portrays the naked, full-grown mythological Roman goddess
Venus. The Moche erotic pots of Peru depict various sexual acts. These
representations of human nakedness may be lascivious for some but
expressively educational for others. This can be in images, video files,
scientific publications, or simply the modes of expression by internet users
that can be exchanged in public.
VI (C)
Standards for Obscenity
This is not the first time that this court deals with sexually-related
expression. This court has carefully crafted operative parameters to
distinguish the obscene from the protected sexual expression. While I do
not necessarily agree with the current standards as these have evolved, it is
clear that even these standards have not been met by the provision in
question. I definitely agree that lascivious is a standard that is too loose
and, therefore, unconstitutional.
Even for this reason, the provision cannot survive the constitutional
challenge.
Obscenity is not easy to define. 222 In Pita v. Court of Appeals, we
recognized that individual tastes develop, adapt to wide-ranging influences,
and keep in step with the rapid advance of civilization. What shocked our
forebears, say, five decades ago, is not necessarily repulsive to the present
generation. James Joyce and D.H. Lawrence were censored in the thirties yet
their works are considered important literature today. 223
Using the concept of obscenity or defining this term is far from being
settled. 224 The courts task, therefore, is to [evolve] standards for proper
police conduct faced with the problem and not so much as to arrive at the
perfect definition. 225
In Gonzales v. Kalaw-Katigbak, 226 we noted the persuasiveness of
Roth v. United States 227 and borrowed some of its concepts in judging
obscenity.
222

223

224
225
226
227

Pita v. Court of Appeals, 258-A Phil. 134, 146 (1989) [Per J. Sarmiento, En Banc], cited in Fernando
v. Court of Appeals, 539 Phil. 407, 416 (2006) [Per J. Quisumbing, Third Division].
Id., citing Kingsley Pictures v. N.Y. Regents, 360 US 684 (1959). The case involved the movie version
in Lady Chatterley's Lover.
Id. at 146.
Id. at 147.
Gonzales v. Kalaw-Katigbak, 222 Phil. 225 (1985) [Per C.J. Fernando, En Banc].
354 US 476, 487 (1957).

Dissenting & Concurring

73

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

There is persuasiveness to the approach followed in Roth: The


early leading standard of obscenity allowed material to be judged
merely by the effect of an isolated excerpt upon particularly
susceptible persons. Regina v. Hicklin [1968] LR 3 QB 360. Some
American courts adopted this standard but later decisions have
rejected it and substituted this test: whether to the average
person, applying contemporary community standards, the
dominant theme of the material taken as a whole appeals to
prurient interest. The Hicklin test, judging obscenity by the effect
of isolated passages upon the most susceptible persons, might well
encompass material legitimately treating with sex, and so it must
be rejected as unconstitutionally restrictive of the freedoms of
speech and press. On the other hand, the substituted standard
provides safeguards to withstand the charge of constitutional
infirmity. 228 (Emphasis supplied)

Thus, at present, we follow Miller v. California, 229 a United States


case, as the latest authority on the guidelines in characterizing obscenity. 230
The guidelines, which already integrated the Roth standard on prurient
interest, are as follows:
a.
Whether the average person, applying contemporary
standards would find the work, taken as a whole, appeals to the
prurient interest x x x;
b.
Whether the work depicts or describes, in a patently
offensive way, sexual conduct specifically defined by the
applicable state law; and
c.
Whether the work, taken as a whole, lacks serious literary,
artistic, political or scientific value. 231

The guidelines in Miller were adopted in Pita v. Court of Appeals 232


and Fernando v. Court of Appeals. 233 It was also cited in the 2009 case of
Soriano v. Laguardia 234 wherein we stated:
Following the contextual lessons of the cited case of Miller
v. California a patently offensive utterance would come
within the pale of the term obscenity should it appeal to the
prurient interest of an average listener applying
contemporary standards. 235
228
229
230

231

232
233
234
235

Gonzales v. Kalaw-Katigbak, 222 Phil. 225, 232 (1985).


413 US 15 (1973).
Pita v. Court of Appeals, 258-A Phil. 134, 145 (1989) [Per J. Sarmiento, En Banc], cited in Fernando
v. Court of Appeals, 539 Phil. 407, 417 (2006) [Per J. Quisumbing, Third Division].
Id., cited in Pita v. Court of Appeals, 258-A Phil. 134, 145 (1989) and cited in Fernando v. Court of
Appeals, 539 Phil. 407, 417 (2006).
258-A Phil. 134, 145 (1989) [Per J. Sarmiento, En Banc].
539 Phil. 407, 417 [Per J. Quisumbing, Third Division].
G.R. No. 164785 and G.R. No. 165636, April 29, 2009, 587 SCRA 79 [Per J. Velasco, En Banc].
Id. at 101.

Dissenting & Concurring

74

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

The tests or guidelines cited above were created and applied as


demarcations between protected expression or speech and obscene
expressions. The distinction is crucial because censorship or prohibition
beyond these guidelines is a possible danger to the protected freedom. For
this reason, the courts, as guard[ians] against any impermissible
infringement on the freedom of x x x expression, should be mindful that
no violation of such is freedom is allowable. 236
The scope of the cybersex provision is defective. Contrary to the
minimum standards evolved through jurisprudence, the law inexplicably
reverts to the use of the term lascivious to qualify the prohibited exhibition
of ones sexuality. This effectively broadens state intrusion. It is an attempt
to reset this courts interpretation of the constitutional guarantee of freedom
of expression as it applies to sexual expression.
First, the current text does not refer to the standpoint of the average
person, applying contemporary standards. Rather it refers only to the law
enforcers taste.
Second, there is no requirement that the work depicts or describes in
a patently offensive way sexual conduct 237 properly defined by law.
Instead, it simply requires exhibition of sexual organs or sexual activity 238
without reference to its impact on its audience.
Third, there is no reference to a judgment of the work taken as a
whole 239 and that this work lacks serious literary, artistic, political or
scientific value. Rather, it simply needs to be lascivious. 240
Roth v. United States 241 sheds light on the relationship between sex
and obscenity, and ultimately, cybersex as defined in Rep. Act No. 10175
and obscenity:
However, sex and obscenity are not synonymous. Obscene
material is material which deals with sex in a manner appealing to
prurient interest. The portrayal of sex, e.g. in art, literature and
scientific works, is not itself sufficient reason to deny material the
constitutional protection of freedom of speech and press. Sex, a
great and mysterious motive force in human life, has indisputably
been a subject of absorbing interest to mankind through the ages; it
236
237
238
239
240
241

Gonzales v. Kalaw-Katigbak, 222 Phil. 225, 232 (1985) [Per C.J. Fernando, En Banc].
Pita v. Court of Appeals, 258-A Phil. 134, 145 (1989) [Per J. Sarmiento, En Banc],
Rep. Act No. 10175, sec. 4(c)(1).
Pita v. Court of Appeals, 258-A Phil. 134, 145 (1989) [Per J. Sarmiento, En Banc],
Rep. Act No. 10175, sec. 4(c)(1).
354 US 476 (1957).

Dissenting & Concurring

75

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion
is one of the vital problems of human interest and public
concern. 242

This court adopted these views in Gonzales v. Kalaw-Katigbak. 243


VI (D)
Obscenity and Equal Protection
Some of the petitioners have raised potential violations of the equal
protection clause in relation to provisions relating to obscenity.
We are aware that certain kinds of offensive and obscene expression
can be stricken down as unconstitutional as it violates the equal protection
clause. At this point, any assessment of this argument must require the
framework of adversarial positions arising from actual facts. However, a
survey of this argument may be necessary in order to show that even the
current text will not be able to survive this challenge.
Catharine MacKinnon suggests that there is a conflict between the
application of doctrines on free expression and the idea of equality between
the sexes. 244 The issue of obscenity, particularly pornography, is legally
framed as a vehicle for the expression of ideas. 245 Pornography, in essence,
is treated as only words or expressions that are distinct from what it does
(from its acts). 246 As such, it is accorded the status of preferred freedom,
without regard to its harmful effects, that is perpetuating a social reality that
women are subordinate to men. 247 Hence, in protecting pornography as an
expression, the actions depicted become protected in the name of free
expression. 248
The issue of inequality had, in the past, been rendered irrelevant when
faced with the issue of obscenity or pornography. 249 This was not addressed
by our jurisprudence on obscenity. 250 The guidelines on determining what is
obscene are premised on the idea that men and women are equal and viewed

242
243
244
245
246
247

248
249
250

Id.
Gonzales v. Kalaw-Katigbak, 222 Phil. 225, 233 (1985) [Per C.J. Fernando, En Banc].
See C. MacKinnon, ONLY WORDS (1993).
Id. at 14.
Id. at 14-15, 89-90.
Id. at 14-15, 88-91. Catharine MacKinnon and Andrea Dworkin proposed a law that defines
pornography as graphic sexually explicit materials that subordinate women through pictures or
words, p. 22.
Id. at 9.
Id. at 87-88.
Id at 87. See also C. MacKinnon, From Pornography, Civil Rights, and Speech, in DOING ETHICS 303
(2009).

Dissenting & Concurring

76

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

equally which basically pertains to the males point of view of equality


that women are inferior. 251
In treating pornography, therefore, as protected expression, it is
alleged that the State protects only the mens freedom of speech. 252
Simultaneously, however, womens freedom of speech is trampled upon. 253
Each time pornography is protected as free expression, the male view of
equality is perpetuated. 254 It becomes more and more integrated into the
consciousness of the society, silencing women, and rendering the reality of
female subordination so unremarkable that it becomes inconsequential and
even doubtful. 255
Others do not agree with MacKinnons view. According to Edwin
Baker, MacKinnons theory fails to recognize or provide for the primary
value of or justification for protecting expression. 256 It fails to recognize the
status of this freedom vis a vis individual liberty, and why this freedom is
fundamental. 257 More than through arguments about ideas, people induce
changes and transform their social and political environments through
expressive behavior. 258 Also, being able to participate in the process of
social and political change is encompassed in the protected liberty. 259
Baker provides an example, thus:
Even expression that is received less as argument than
masturbation material, becomes a part of a cultural or behavioral
debate about sexuality, about the nature of human relations, and
about pleasure and morality, as well as about the roles of men and
women. Historically, puritanical attempts to suppress sexually
explicit materials appear largely designed to shut down this
cultural contestation in favor of a traditional practice of keeping
women in the private sphere. Opening up this cultural debate has in
the past, and can in the future, contribute to progressive change. 260

251

252

253

254

255

256

257
258
259
260

See C. MacKinnon, ONLY WORDS (1993); See also C. MacKinnon, From Pornography, Civil Rights,
and Speech, in DOING ETHICS 301.
See C. MacKinnon, ONLY WORDS (1993); See also C. MacKinnon, From Pornography, Civil Rights,
and Speech, in DOING ETHICS 309.
See C. MacKinnon, ONLY WORDS (1993); See also C. MacKinnon, From Pornography, Civil Rights,
and Speech, in DOING ETHICS.
See C. MacKinnon, ONLY WORDS (1993); See also C. MacKinnon, From Pornography, Civil Rights,
and Speech, in DOING ETHICS 300-302.
See C. MacKinnon, ONLY WORDS (1993); See also C. MacKinnon, From Pornography, Civil Rights,
and Speech, in DOING ETHICS 301-302, 307.
Baker, E. C. REVIEW: Of Course, More Than Words. Only Words. Catharine A. MacKinnon. 61 U.
Chi. L. Rev. 1181 (1994) 1197.
Id.
Id.
Id.
Id. at 1194.

Dissenting & Concurring

77

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

Baker also points out that MacKinnon disregards that receivers of


communicated expressions are presumably autonomous agents who bear the
responsibility for their actions and are capable of moral choice. 261
The expression should also be treated as independent of the act or
offense. The expression or autonomous act of the speaker does not itself
cause x x x harm. Rather, the harm occurs through how the other person,
presumably an autonomous agent whom we normally treat as bearing the
responsibility for her own acts, responds. 262
Baker agrees that expressions [construct] the social reality in which
[offenses] take place. 263 However, the expression itself is not the offense. 264
Part of the reason to protect speech, or, more broadly, to protect liberty,
is a commitment to the view that people should be able to participate in
constructing their world, or to the belief that this popular participation
provides the best way to move toward a better world. The guarantee of
liberty represents a deep faith in people and in democracy. 265

Punishing or even threatening to punish lascivious exhibition of


sexual organs or sexual activity through the aid of a computer system for
favor or consideration does nothing to alleviate the subordination of
women. Rather, it facilitates the patriarchy. It will allow control of what a
woman does with her body in a society that will be dominated by men or by
the ideas that facilitate mens hegemony.
The current provision prohibiting cybersex will reduce, through its
chilling effect, the kind of expression that can be the subject of mature
discussion of our sexuality. The public will, therefore, lose out on the
exchanges relating to the various dimensions of our relationships with
others. The cybersex provisions stifles speech, aggravates inequalities
between genders, and will only succeed to encrust the views of the powerful.
If freedom of expression is a means that allows the minority to be
heard, then the current version of this law fails miserably to protect it. It is
overbroad and unconstitutional and should not be allowed to exist within our
constitutional order.

261
262
263
264
265

Id. at 1197-1211.
Id. at 1199.
Id. at 1203.
Id. at 1204.
Id.

Dissenting & Concurring

78

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

VI (E)
Child Pornography Different from Cybersex
It is apt to express some caution about how the parties confused child
pornography done through the internet and cybersex.
Section 4(c)(2), which pertains to child pornography, is different from
the cybersex provision. The provision on child pornography provides:
(2) Child Pornography. The unlawful or prohibited acts defined and
punishable by Republic Act No. 9775 or the Anti-Child Pornography Act
of 2009, committed through a computer system: Provided, That the
penalty to be imposed shall be (1) one degree higher than that provided
for in Republic Act No. 9775.

In my view, this provision should survive constitutional challenge.


Furthermore, it is not raised in this case. The explicit reference to the AntiPornography Law or Republic Act No. 9775 constitutes sufficient standard
within which to base the application of the law and which will allow it to
survive a facial challenge for now.
VII
Traffic Data and Warrants
Section 12 of the Cybercrime Prevention Act of 2012 provides:
Real-Time Collection of Traffic Data Law enforcement
authorities, with due cause, shall be authorized to collect or record
by technical or electronic means traffic data in real-time associated
with specified communications transmitted by means of a
computer system.
Traffic data refer only to the communications origin,
destination, route, time, date, size, duration, or type of underlying
service, but not content, nor identities.
All other data to be collected or seized or disclosed will
require a court warrant.
Service providers are required to cooperate and assist law
enforcement authorities in the collection or recording of the abovestated information.
The court warrant required under this section shall only be
issued or granted upon written application and the examination
under oath or affirmation of the applicant and the witnesses he may
produce and the showing:

Dissenting & Concurring

79

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

(1) that there are reasonable grounds to believe that any of


the crimes enumerated hereinabove has been committed, or is
being committed, or is about to be committed:
(2) that there are reasonable grounds to believe that
evidence that will be obtained is essential to the conviction of any
person for, or to the solution of, or to the prevention of, any such
crimes; and
(3) that there are no other means readily available for
obtaining such evidence.

VII (B)
Traffic Data and Expression
Traffic data, even as it is defined, still contains speech elements.
When, how, to whom, and how often messages are sent in the internet may
nuance the content of the speech. The message may be short (as in the 140character limit of a tweet) but when it is repeated often enough in the proper
context, it may imply emphasis or desperation. That a message used the
email with a limited number of recipients with some blind carbon copies
(Bcc) characterizes the message when it is compared to the possibility of
actually putting the same content in a public social media post.
The intended or unintended interception of these parts of the message
may be enough deterrent for some to make use of the space provided in
cyberspace. The parameters are so loosely and broadly defined as due
cause to be determined by law enforcers. Given the pervasive nature of
the internet, it can rightly be assumed by some users that law enforcers will
make use of this provision and, hence, will definitely chill their expression.
Besides, the provision insofar as it allows warrantless intrusion and
interception by law enforcers upon its own determination of due cause
does not specify the limits of the technologies that they can use. Traffic data
is related to and intimately bound to the content of the packets of
information sent from one user to the other or from one user to another
server. The provision is silent on the limits of the technologies and methods
that will be used by the law enforcer in tracking traffic data. This causes an
understandable apprehension on the part of those who make use of the same
servers but who are not the subject of the surveillance. Even those under
surveillance even only with respect to the traffic data have no
assurances that the method of interception will truly exclude the content of
the message.
As observed by one author who sees the effect of general and roving
searches on freedom of expression:

Dissenting & Concurring

80

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

Most broadly, freedom from random governmental


monitoringof both public spaces and recorded
transactionsmight be an essential predicate for self
definition and development of the viewpoints that make
democracy vibrant. This reason to be concerned about
virtual searches, while somewhat amorphous, is important
enough to have been remarked on by two Supreme Court
justices. The first wrote, walking and strolling and
wanderinghave been in part responsible for giving our
people the feeling of independence and self-confidence, the
feeling of creativity. These amenities have dignified the
right to dissent and have honoured the right to be
nonconformists and the right to defy submissiveness. They
have encouraged lives of high spirits rather than hushed
suffocating silence. The second justice wrote:
Suppose that the local police in a particular
jurisdiction were to decide to station a police car at the
entrance to the parking lot of a well-patronised bar from
5:30 p.m. to 7:30 p.m. every dayI would guess that the
great majority of peoplewould say that this is not a
proper police functionThere would be an uneasiness, and
I think a justified uneasiness, if those who patronised the
bar felt that their names were being taken down and filed
for future referenceThis ought not to be governmental
function when the facts are as extreme as I put them. 266

It will be different if it will be in the context of a warrant from a court


of law. Its duration, scope, and targets can be more defined. The methods
and technologies that will be used can be more limited. There will thus be an
assurance that the surveillance will be reasonably surgical and provided on
the basis of probable cause. Surveillance under warrant, therefore, will not
cause a chilling effect on internet expression.
In Blo Umpar Adiong v. COMELEC, 267 this court reiterated:
A statute is considered void for overbreadth when "it offends the
constitutional principle that a governmental purpose to control or
prevent activities constitutionally subject to state regulations may
not be achieved by means which sweep unnecessarily broadly and
thereby invade the area of protected freedoms." (Zwickler v.
Koota, 19 L ed 2d 444 [1967]).
In a series of decisions this Court has held that, even though the
governmental purpose be legitimate and substantial, that purpose
266

267

C. Slobogin, Is the Fourth Amendment Relevant in a Technological Age?, in J. Rosen and B. Wittes,
eds., Constitution 3.0, 23 (2011), citing Justice Douglas in Papachristou v Jacksonville, 405 U.S. 156,
164 (1972) and W. H. Rehnquist, Is an Expanded Right of Privacy Consistent with Fair and Effective
Law Enforcement?; or Privacy, Youve Come a Long Way, Baby, 23 Kansas Law Review 1, 9 (1974).
G.R. No. 103956, March 31, 1992, 207 SCRA 712.

Dissenting & Concurring

81

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion
cannot be pursued by means that broadly stifle fundamental
personal liberties when the end can be more narrowly achieved.
The breadth of legislative abridgment must be viewed in the light
of less drastic means for achieving the same basic purpose.
In Lovell v. Griffin, 303 US 444, 82 L ed 949, 58 S Ct 666, the
Court invalidated an ordinance prohibiting all distribution of
literature at any time or place in Griffin, Georgia, without a
license, pointing out that so broad an interference was unnecessary
to accomplish legitimate municipal aims. In Schneider v.
Irvington, 308 US 147, 84 L ed 155, 60 S Ct. 146, the Court dealt
with ordinances of four different municipalities which either
banned or imposed prior restraints upon the distribution of
handbills. In holding the ordinances invalid, the court noted that
where legislative abridgment of fundamental personal rights and
liberties is asserted, "the courts should be astute to examine the
effect of the challenged legislation. Mere legislative preferences or
beliefs respecting matters of public convenience may well support
regulation directed at other personal activities, but be insufficient
to justify such as diminishes the exercise of rights so vital to the
maintenance of democratic institutions," 308 US, at 161. In
Cantwell v Connecticut, 310 US 296, 84 L ed 1213, 60 S Ct. 900,
128 ALR 1352, the Court said that "[c]onduct remains subject to
regulation for the protection of society," but pointed out that in
each case "the power to regulate must be so exercised as not, in
attaining a permissible end, unduly to infringe the protected
freedom." (310 US at 304) (Shelton v. Tucker, 364 US 479
[1960] 268

Section 12 of Rep. Act No. 10175 broadly authorizes law enforcement


authorities with due cause to intercept traffic data in real time. Due
cause is a uniquely broad standard different from the probable cause
requirement in the constitution or the parameters of reasonable searches in
our jurisprudence.
The statute does not care to make use of labels of standards replete in
our jurisprudence. It foists upon the public a standard that will only be
defined by those who will execute the law. It therefore amounts to a carte
blanche and roving authority whose limits are not statutorily limited.
Affecting as it does our fundamental rights to expression, it therefore is
clearly unconstitutional.
VII (C)
Traffic Data and Privacy Rights
Traffic data is defined by the second paragraph of Section 12 of Rep.
Act No. 10175, thus:

268

Id. at 719-720.

Dissenting & Concurring

82

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion
Traffic data refer only to the communications origin,
destination, route, time, date, size, duration, or type of
underlying service, but not content, nor identities.

As worded, the collection, aggregation, analysis, storage and


dissemination of these types of data may implicate both the originators and
the recipients rights to privacy.
That these data move through privately owned networks, administered
by private internet service providers, and run through privately owned
internet exchange nodes is no moment. We will have to decide in some
future case (where the facts and controversy would be clearer and more
concrete) the nature and levels of intrusion that would be determined as a
reasonable search and the uses of such data that would be reasonable
seizures within the meaning of Article III, Section 2 of the Constitution. In
such cases, we will have to delimit the privacy interests in the datum in
question as well as in the data that may be collaterally acquired.
There are many types of searches.
There are instances when the observation is done only for purposes of
surveillance. In these types of searches, the law enforcers may not yet
have a specific criminal act in mind that has already been committed.
Perhaps, these are instances when government will just want to have access
to prevent the occurrence of cyber attacks of some kind. Surveillance can be
general, i.e., one where there is no specific actor being observed. Some
general surveillance may also be suspicionless. This means that there is no
concrete indication that there will be some perpetrator. It is the surveillance
itself that is the preventive action to deter any wrongdoing. It can also be
specific, i.e., that there is already an actor or a specific group or
classification of actors that is of interest to the government.
Then, there are the searches which are more properly called
investigations. That is, that there is already a crime that has been committed
or certain to be committed and law enforcers will want to find evidence to
support a case. Then there is the search that simply enables law enforcers
to enter a physical or virtual space in order to retrieve and preserve evidence
already known to law enforcers.
For the moment, it is enough to take note that almost all of our
jurisprudence in this regard has emerged from physical intrusions into
personal spaces.

Dissenting & Concurring

83

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

In In the Matter of the Petition for the Writ of the Petition for Issuance
of Writ of Habeas Corpus of Camilo L. Sabio v. Gordon, 269 this court
explained the determination of a violation of the right of privacy:
Zones of privacy are recognized and protected in our laws. Within
these zones, any form of intrusion is impermissible unless excused
by law and in accordance with customary legal process. The
meticulous regard we accord to these zones arises not only from
our conviction that the right to privacy is a "constitutional right"
and "the right most valued by civilized men," but also from our
adherence to the Universal Declaration of Human Rights which
mandates that, "no one shall be subjected to arbitrary interference
with his privacy" and "everyone has the right to the protection of
the law against such interference or attacks."
Our Bill of Rights, enshrined in Article III of the Constitution,
provides at least two guarantees that explicitly create zones of
privacy. It highlights a person's "right to be let alone" or the "right
to determine what, how much, to whom and when information
about himself shall be disclosed." Section 2 guarantees "the right
of the people to be secure in their persons, houses, papers and
effects against unreasonable searches and seizures of whatever
nature and for any purpose." Section 3 renders inviolable the
"privacy of communication and correspondence" and further
cautions that "any evidence obtained in violation of this or the
preceding section shall be inadmissible for any purpose in any
proceeding."
In evaluating a claim for violation of the right to privacy, a court
must determine whether a person has exhibited a reasonable
expectation of privacy and, if so, whether that expectation has been
violated by unreasonable government intrusion. 270

Reasonable expectations of privacy, however, may not be the only


criterion that may be useful in situations arising from internet use. Some
have suggested that in view of the infrastructure or the permeability of the
networks created virtually and its cosmopolitarian or cross-cultural
character, it may be difficult to identify what may be the normative
understanding of all the participants with respect to privacy. 271 It has been
suggested that privacy may best be understood in its phases, i.e., a core
inalienable category where personal information is within the control of the
individual, the right to initial disclosure, and the right for further
dissemination. 272

269
270
271
272

535 Phil. 687 (2006).


Id. at 714-715.
See for instance J. Rosen et al., CONSTITUTION 3.0 FREEDOM AND TECHNOLOGICAL CHANGE (2011).
See E.C. Baker, Autonomy and Informational Privacy, or Gossip: The Central Meaning of the First
Amendment,
<
http://www.yale.edu/lawweb/jbalkin/telecom/bakerautonomyandinformationalprivacy.pdf>
(visited
February 21, 2014).

Dissenting & Concurring

84

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

In People v. Chua Ho San, 273 this court made an explicit connection


between the right to privacy and the right against unreasonable searches and
seizures. Even then, based on the facts there alleged, a search was described
as a State intrusion to a persons body, personal effects or residence:
Enshrined in the Constitution is the inviolable right to privacy of
home and person. It explicitly ordains that people have the right to
be secure in their persons, houses, papers and effects against
unreasonable searches and seizures of whatever nature and for any
purpose. Inseparable, and not merely corollary or incidental to said
right and equally hallowed in and by the Constitution, is the
exclusionary principle which decrees that any evidence obtained in
violation of said right is inadmissible for any purpose in any
proceeding.
The Constitutional proscription against unreasonable searches and
seizures does not, of course, forestall reasonable searches and
seizure. What constitutes a reasonable or even an unreasonable
search in any particular case is purely a judicial question,
determinable from a consideration of the circumstances involved.
Verily, the rule is, the Constitution bars State intrusions to a
person's body, personal effects or residence except if conducted by
virtue of a valid search warrant issued in compliance with the
procedure outlined in the Constitution and reiterated in the Rules
of Court; otherwise such search and seizure become
unreasonable within the meaning of the aforementioned
constitutional provision. 274

In the more recent case of Valeroso v. People, 275 this court held that:
Unreasonable searches and seizures are the menace against which
the constitutional guarantees afford full protection. While the
power to search and seize may at times be necessary for public
welfare, still it may be exercised and the law enforced without
transgressing the constitutional rights of the citizens, for no
enforcement of any statute is of sufficient importance to justify
indifference to the basic principles of government. Those who are
supposed to enforce the law are not justified in disregarding the
rights of an individual in the name of order. Order is too high a
price to pay for the loss of liberty. 276

Very little consideration, if any, has been taken of the speed of


information transfers and the ephemeral character of information exchanged
in the internet.
I concede that the general rule is that in order for a search to be
considered reasonable, a warrant must be obtained. In Prudente v. Dayrit: 277
273
274
275
276
277

367 Phil. 703 (1999).


Id. at 715.
G.R. No. 164815, September 3, 2009, 598 SCRA 41.
Id. at 59.
259 Phil. 541 (1989).

Dissenting & Concurring

85

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

For a valid search warrant to issue, there must be probable cause,


which is to be determined personally by the judge, after
examination under oath or affirmation of the complainant and the
witnesses he may produce, and particularly describing the place to
be searched and the persons or things to be seized. The probable
cause must be in connection with one specific offense and the
judge must, before issuing the warrant, personally examine in the
form of searching questions and answers, in writing and under
oath, the complainant and any witness he may produce, on facts
personally known to them and attach to the record their sworn
statements together with any affidavits submitted.
The "probable cause" for a valid search warrant, has been defined
"as such facts and circumstances which would lead a reasonably
discreet arid prudent man to believe that an offense has been
committed, and that objects sought in connection with the offense
are in the place sought to be searched." This probable cause must
be shown to be within the personal knowledge of the complainant
or the witnesses he may produce and not based on mere hearsay. 278
(Citations omitted)

However, not all searches without a warrant are per se invalid.


Jurisprudence is replete with the exceptions to the general rule.
In People v. Rodrigueza, 279 this court reiterated the enumeration of the
instances when a search and seizure may be conducted reasonably without
the necessity of a search warrant:
As provided in the present Constitution, a search, to be valid, must
generally be authorized by a search warrant duly issued by the
proper government authority. True, in some instances, this Court
has allowed government authorities to conduct searches and
seizures even without a search warrant. Thus, when the owner of
the premises waives his right against such incursion; when the
search is incidental to a lawful arrest; when it is made on vessels
and aircraft for violation of customs laws; when it is made on
automobiles for the purpose of preventing violations of smuggling
or immigration laws; when it involves prohibited articles in plain
view; or in cases of inspection of buildings and other premises for
the enforcement of fire, sanitary and building regulations, a search
may be validly made even without a search warrant. 280 (Citations
omitted)

278
279
280

Id. at 549.
G.R. No. 95902, February 4, 1992, 205 SCRA 791.
Id. at 798.

Dissenting & Concurring

86

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

In specific instances involving computer data, there may be analogies


with searches of moving or movable vehicles. People v. Bagista 281 is one of
many that explains this exception:
The constitutional proscription against warrantless searches and
seizures admits of certain exceptions. Aside from a search incident
to a lawful arrest, a warrantless search had been upheld in cases of
a moving vehicle, and the seizure of evidence in plain view.
With regard to the search of moving vehicles, this had been
justified on the ground that the mobility of motor vehicles makes it
possible for the vehicle to be searched to move out of the locality
or jurisdiction in which the warrant must be sought.
This in no way, however, gives the police officers unlimited
discretion to conduct warrantless searches of automobiles in the
absence of probable cause. When a vehicle is stopped and
subjected to an extensive search, such a warrantless search has
been held to be valid only as long as the officers conducting the
search have reasonable or probable cause to believe before the
search that they will find the instrumentality or evidence pertaining
to a crime, in the vehicle to be searched. 282 (Citations omitted)

Then again in People v. Balingan, 283 this court held that there was a
valid search and seizure, even if done in a moving vehicle. It gave the
rationale for this holding:
We also find no merit in appellant's argument that the marijuana flowering
tops should be excluded as evidence, they being the products of an alleged
illegal warrantless search. The search and seizure in the case at bench
happened in a moving, public vehicle. In the recent case of People vs. Lo
Ho Wing, 193 SCRA 122 (1991), this Court gave its approval to a
warrantless search done on a taxicab which yielded the illegal drug
commonly known as shabu. In that case, we raciocinated:
xxxx

The contentions are without writ. As correctly averred by appellee,


that search and seizure must be supported by a valid warrant is not
an absolute rule. There are at least three (3) well-recognized
exceptions thereto. As set forth in the case of Manipon, Jr. vs.
Sandiganbayan, these are: [1] a search incidental to an arrest, [2] a
search of a moving vehicle, and [3] seizure of evidence in plain
view (emphasis supplied). The circumstances of the case clearly
show that the search in question was made as regards a moving
vehicle. Therefore, a valid warrant was not necessary to effect the
search on appellant and his co-accused.
In this connection, We cite with approval the averment of the Solicitor
General, as contained in the appellee's brief, that the rules governing
search and seizure have over the years been steadily liberalized whenever
281
282
283

G.R. No. 86218, September 18, 1992, 214 SCRA 63.


Id. at 68-69.
G.R. No. 105834, February 13, 1995, 241 SCRA 277.

Dissenting & Concurring

87

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion
a moving vehicle is the object of the search on the basis of practicality.
This is so considering that before a warrant could be obtained, the place,
things and persons to be searched must be described to the satisfaction of
the issuing judge a requirement which borders on the impossible in
the case of smuggling effected by the use of a moving vehicle that can
transport contraband from one place to another with impunity. We might
add that a warrantless search of a moving vehicle is justified on the
ground that "it is not practicable to secure a warrant because the vehicle
can be quickly moved out of the locality or jurisdiction in which the
warrant must be sought." 284

Another instance of a reasonable and valid warrantless search which


can be used analogously for facts arising from internet or computer use
would be in instances where the existence of the crime has been
categorically acknowledged. People v. De Gracia, 285 explains:
The next question that may be asked is whether or not there was a
valid search and seizure in this case. While the matter has not been
squarely put in issue, we deem it our bounden duty, in light of
advertence thereto by the parties, to delve into the legality of the
warrantless search conducted by the raiding team, considering the
gravity of the offense for which herein appellant stands to be
convicted and the penalty sought to be imposed.
It is admitted that the military operatives who raided the Eurocar
Sales Office were not armed with a search warrant at that time.
The raid was actually precipitated by intelligence reports that said
office was being used as headquarters by the RAM. Prior to the
raid, there was a surveillance conducted on the premises wherein
the surveillance team was fired at by a group of men coming from
the Eurocar building. When the military operatives raided the
place, the occupants thereof refused to open the door despite
requests for them to do so, thereby compelling the former to break
into the office. The Eurocar Sales Office is obviously not a gun
store and it is definitely not an armory or arsenal which are the
usual depositories for explosives and ammunition. It is primarily
and solely engaged in the sale of automobiles. The presence of an
unusual quantity of high-powered firearms and explosives could
not be justifiably or even colorably explained. In addition, there
was general chaos and disorder at that time because of
simultaneous and intense firing within the vicinity of the office and
in the nearby Camp Aguinaldo which was under attack by rebel
forces. The courts in the surrounding areas were obviously closed
and, for that matter, the building and houses therein were deserted.
Under the foregoing circumstances, it is our considered opinion
that the instant case falls under one of the exceptions to the
prohibition against a warrantless search. In the first place, the
military operatives, taking into account the facts obtaining in this
case, had reasonable ground to believe that a crime was being
committed. There was consequently more than sufficient probable
cause to warrant their action. Furthermore, under the situation then
284
285

Id. at 283-284.
G.R. Nos. 102009-10, July 6, 1994, 233 SCRA 716.

Dissenting & Concurring

88

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion
prevailing, the raiding team had no opportunity to apply for and
secure a search warrant from the courts. The trial judge himself
manifested that on December 5, 1989 when the raid was
conducted, his court was closed. Under such urgency and exigency
of the moment, a search warrant could lawfully be dispensed
with. 286

But the internet has created other dangers to privacy which may not be
present in the usual physical spaces that have been the subject of searches
and seizures in the past. Commercial owners of servers and information
technologies as well as some governments have collected data without the
knowledge of the users of the internet. It may be that our Data Privacy
Law 287 may be sufficient.
Absent an actual case therefore, I am not prepared to declare Section
12 of Rep. Act 10175 as unconstitutional on the basis of Section 2 or Section
3(a) of Article III of the Constitution. My vote only extends to its declaration
of unconstitutionality because the unlimited breadth of discretion given to
law enforcers to acquire traffic data for due cause chills expression in the
internet. For now, it should be stricken down because it violates Article III,
Section 4 of the Constitution.
VIII
Limitations on Commercial Speech
are Constitutional
I dissent from the majority in their holding that Section 4(c)(3) of Rep.
Act No. 10175 is unconstitutional. This provides:
(3) Unsolicited Commercial Communications. The
transmission of commercial electronic communication with
the use of computer system which seek to advertise, sell, or
offer for sale product and services are prohibited unless:
(i) there is prior affirmative consent from the
recipient; or
(ii) the primary intent of the communication is for
service and/or administrative announcements from
the sender to its existing users, subscribers or
customers; or
(iii) the following conditions are present:
(aa)
the
commercial
electronic
communication contains a simple, valid, and
286
287

Id. at 728-729.
Rep. Act No. 10173, otherwise known as the Data Privacy Act of 2012.

Dissenting & Concurring

89

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion
reliable way for the recipient to reject
receipt of further commercial electronic
messages (opt out) from the same source;
(bb)
the
commercial
electronic
communication does not purposely disguise
the source of the electronic message; and
(cc)
the
commercial
electronic
communication does not purposely include
misleading information in any part of the
message in order to induce the recipients to
read the message.

On the origins of this provision, the Senate Journals reference to the


deliberations on the Cybercrime Law 288 states:
Unsolicited Commercial Communications in Section
4(C)(3)
This offense is not included in the Budapest Convention.
Although there is an ongoing concern against receiving
spams or unsolicited commercial e-mails sent in bulk
through the computer or telecommunication network,
Section 4(C)(3) is too general in the sense it can include a
simple email from one person to another person, wherein
the sender offers to sell his house or car to the receiver.
Therefore, to avoid such acts of injustice, Section 4(C)(3)
should be narrowed.
Senator Angara accepted the recommendation as he
clarified that what the bill covers is unsolicited emails in
bulk. 289

VIII (B)
Section 4(c)(3) Has No Chilling Effect
on Speech of Lower Value
Section 4(c)(3) of Rep. Act No. 10175 on unsolicited commercial
communication has no chilling effect. It is narrowly drawn. Absent an actual
case, it should not be declared as unconstitutional simply on the basis of its
provisions. I dissent, therefore, in the majoritys holding that it is
unconstitutional.
Commercial speech merited attention in 1996 in Iglesia ni Cristo v.
Court of Appeals. 290 In Iglesia ni Cristo, this court stated that commercial

288
289
290

Session No. 17, September 12, 2011, Fifteenth Congress, Second Regular Session
Id. at 279.
328 Phil. 893 (1996) [Per J. Puno, En Banc].

Dissenting & Concurring

90

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

speech is low value speech to which the clear and present danger test is
not applicable. 291
In 2007, Chief Justice Reynato Puno had the opportunity to expound
on the treatment of and the protection afforded to commercial speech in his
concurring and separate opinion in Pharmaceutical and Health Care
Association of the Philippines v. Duque III. 292 Writing to elucidate another
reason why the absolute ban on the advertising and promotion of breastmilk
substitutes x x x should be struck down, 293 he explained the concept of
commercial speech and traced the development of United States
jurisprudence on commercial speech:
The advertising and promotion of breastmilk substitutes
properly falls within the ambit of the term commercial speech-that
is, speech that proposes an economic transaction. This is a separate
category of speech which is not accorded the same level of
protection as that given to other constitutionally guaranteed forms
of expression but is nonetheless entitled to protection.
A look at the development of jurisprudence on the subject
would show us that initially and for many years, the United States
Supreme Court took the view that commercial speech is not
protected by the First Amendment. It fastened itself to the view
that the broad powers of government to regulate commerce
reasonably includes the power to regulate speech concerning
articles of commerce.
This view started to melt down in the 1970s. In Virginia
Pharmacy Board v. Virginia Citizens Consumer Council, the U.S.
Supreme court struck down a law prohibiting the advertising of
prices for prescription drugs. It held that price information was
important to consumers, and that the First Amendment protects the
"right to receive information" as well as the right to speak. It ruled
that consumers have a strong First Amendment interest in the free
flow of information about goods and services available in the
marketplace and that any state regulation must support a
substantial interest.
Central Hudson Gas & Electric v. Public Service
Commission is the watershed case that established the primary test
for evaluating the constitutionality of commercial speech
regulations. In this landmark decision, the U.S. Supreme Court
held that the regulation issued by the Public Service Commission
of the State of New York, which reaches all promotional
advertising regardless of the impact of the touted service on overall
energy use, is more extensive than necessary to further the state's
interest in energy conservation. In addition, it ruled that there must
be a showing that a more limited restriction on the content of
291

292
293

Id. at 933. Presently in the United States, the clear and present danger test is not applied to protect low
value speeches such as obscene speech, commercial speech and defamation.
561 Phil. 386 (2007) [En Banc].
Id. at 449.

Dissenting & Concurring

91

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion
promotional advertising would not adequately serve the interest of
the State. In applying the First Amendment, the U.S. Court rejected
the highly paternalistic view that the government has complete
power to suppress or regulate commercial speech.
Central Hudson provides a four-part analysis for evaluating
the validity of regulations of commercial speech. To begin with,
the commercial speech must "concern lawful activity and not be
misleading" if it is to be protected under the First Amendment.
Next, the asserted governmental interest must be substantial. If
both of these requirements are met, it must next be determined
whether the state regulation directly advances the governmental
interest asserted, and whether it is not more extensive than is
necessary to serve that interest. 294 (Citations omitted)

In his separate concurring opinion in Chavez v. Gonzales, 295 Justice


Antonio Carpio, citing Pharmaceutical and Health Care Association of the
Philippines, stated that false or misleading advertisement is among the
instances in which expression may be subject to prior restraint, 296 thus:
The exceptions, when expression may be subject to prior
restraint, apply in this jurisdiction to only four categories of
expression, namely: pornography, false or misleading
advertisement, advocacy of imminent lawless action, and danger to
national security. All other expression is not subject to prior
restraint. As stated in Turner Broadcasting System v. Federal
Communication Commission, [T]he First Amendment (Free
Speech Clause), subject only to narrow and well understood
exceptions, does not countenance governmental control over the
content of messages expressed by private individuals. 297
(Citations omitted)

Further in his separate concurring opinion, Justice Carpio reiterates


this point. Making reference to the norm in the United States, he states that
false or deceptive commercial speech is categorized as unprotected
expression that may be subject to prior restraint. 298 Conformably, he also
cited Pharmaceutical and Health Care Association of the Philippines and its
having upheld the constitutionality of Section 6 of the Milk Code requiring
the submission to a government screening committee of advertising
materials for infant formula milk to prevent false or deceptive claims to the
public.
In his twelfth footnote, Justice Carpio made reference to the state
interest, articulated in the Constitution itself, in regulating advertisements:

294
295
296
297
298

Id. at 449-450.
569 Phil. 155 (2008) [En Banc].
Id. at 237.
Id.
Id. at 244.

Dissenting & Concurring

92

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion
Another fundamental ground for regulating false or misleading
advertisement is Section 11(2), Article XVI of the Constitution
which states : The advertising industry is impressed with public
interest, and shall be regulated by law for the protection of
consumers and the promotion of the general welfare. 299

As acknowledged by the majority, [c]ommercial speech is a separate


category of speech which is not accorded the same level of protection as that
given to other constitutionally guaranteed forms of expression but is
nonetheless entitled to protection. 300
I agree that the basis of protection accorded to commercial speech
rests in its informative character: [t]he First Amendment's concern for
commercial speech is based on the informational function of advertising: 301
Commercial expression not only serves the economic interest of
the speaker, but also assists consumers and furthers the societal
interest in the fullest possible [447 U.S. 557, 562] dissemination of
information. In applying the First Amendment to this area, we have
rejected the "highly paternalistic" view that government has
complete power to suppress or regulate commercial speech.
"[P]eople will perceive their own best interest if only they are well
enough informed, and . . . the best means to that end is to open the
channels of communication, rather than to close them. . . ." Id., at
770; see Linmark Associates, Inc. v. Willingboro, 431 U.S. 85, 92
(1977). Even when advertising communicates only an incomplete
version of the relevant facts, the First Amendment presumes that
some accurate information is better than no information at all.
Bates v. State Bar of Arizona, supra, at 374. 302

Since it is valuable only to the extent of its ability to inform,


advertising is not at par with other forms of expression such as political or
religious speech. The other forms of speech are indispensable to the
democratic and republican mooring of the state whereby the sovereignty
residing in the people is best and most effectively exercised through free
expression. Business organizations are not among the sovereign people.
While business organizations, as juridical persons, are granted by law a
capacity for rights and obligations, they do not count themselves as among
those upon whom human rights are vested.

299
300
301

302

Id.
Page 14 of Justice Roberto Abads February 7, 2014 draft.
Central Hudson Gas & Electric v. Public Service Commission, 447 U.S. 557 (1980) <
http://caselaw.lp.findlaw.com/scripts/getcase.pl?court=US&vol=447&invol=557> (visited February
13, 2014).
Id.

Dissenting & Concurring

93

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

The distinction between commercial speech and other forms of speech


is, thus, self-evident. As the United States Supreme Court noted in a
discursive footnote in Virginia Pharmacy Board: 303
In concluding that commercial speech enjoys First Amendment
protection, we have not held that it is wholly undifferentiable from
other forms. There are commonsense differences between
speech that does "no more than propose a commercial
transaction," Pittsburgh Press Co., v. Human Relations Comm'n,
413 U.S., at 385, and other varieties. Even if the differences do
not justify the conclusion that commercial speech is valueless, and
thus subject to complete suppression by the State, they nonetheless
suggest that a different degree of protection is necessary to
insure that the flow of truthful and legitimate commercial
information is unimpaired. The truth of commercial speech, for
example, may be more easily verifiable by its disseminator than,
let us say, news reporting or political commentary, in that
ordinarily the advertiser seeks to disseminate information about a
specific product or service that he himself provides and
presumably knows more about than anyone else. Also, commercial
speech may be more durable than other kinds. Since advertising is
the sine qua non of commercial profits, there is little likelihood of
its being chilled by proper regulation and forgone entirely.
Attributes such as these, the greater objectivity and
hardiness of commercial speech, may make it less necessary to
tolerate inaccurate statements for fear of silencing the speaker.
Compare New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254 (1964),
with Dun & Bradstreet, Inc. v. Grove, 404 U.S. 898 (1971). They
may also make it appropriate to require that a commercial message
appear in such a form, or include such additional information,
warnings, and disclaimers, as are necessary to prevent its being
deceptive. Compare Miami Herald Publishing Co. v. Tornillo, 418
U.S. 241 (1974), with Banzhaf v. FCC, 132 U.S. App. D.C. 14,
405 F.2d 1082 (1968), cert. denied sub nom. Tobacco Institute,
Inc. v. FCC, 396 U.S. 842 (1969). Cf. United States v. 95 Barrels
of Vinegar, 265 U.S. 438, 443 (1924) ("It is not difficult to choose
statements, designs and devices which will not deceive"). They
may also make inapplicable the prohibition against prior restraints.
Compare New York Times Co. v. United States, 403 U.S.
713(1971), with Donaldson v. Read Magazine, 333 U.S. 178, 189 191 (1948); FTC v. Standard Education Society, 302 U.S.
112 (1937); E. F. Drew & Co. v. FTC, 235 F.2d 735, 739-740
(CA2 1956), cert. denied,352 U.S. 969 (1957). 304 (Emphasis
supplied)

303

304

Virginia Pharmacy Board v. Virginia Consumer Council, 425 U.S. 748 (1976) <
http://caselaw.lp.findlaw.com/cgi
bin/getcase.pl?friend=llrx&navby=volpage&court=us&vol=425&page=765> (visited February 21,
2014).
Id.

Dissenting & Concurring

94

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

It follows, therefore, that the state may validly suppress commercial


speech that fails to express truthful and accurate information. As emphasized
in Central Hudson:305
The First Amendment's concern for commercial speech
is based on the informational function of advertising. See First
National Bank of Boston v. Bellotti, 435 U.S. 765, 783 (1978).
Consequently, there can be no constitutional objection to the
suppression of commercial messages that do not accurately
inform the public about lawful activity. The government may
ban forms of communication more likely to deceive the public than
to inform it, Friedman v. Rogers, supra, at 13, 15-16; Ohralik v.
Ohio State Bar Assn., supra, at 464-465, or [447 U.S. 557, 564]
commercial speech related to illegal activity, Pittsburgh Press Co.
v. Human Relations Comm'n, 413 U.S. 376, 388 (1973).
If the communication is neither misleading nor related to
unlawful activity, the government's power is more circumscribed.
The State must assert a substantial interest to be achieved by
restrictions on commercial speech. Moreover, the regulatory
technique must be in proportion to that interest. The limitation on
expression must be designed carefully to achieve the State's goal.
Compliance with this requirement may be measured by two
criteria. First, the restriction must directly advance the state interest
involved; the regulation may not be sustained if it provides only
ineffective or remote support for the government's purpose.
Second, if the governmental interest could be served as well by a
more limited restriction on commercial speech, the excessive
restrictions cannot survive. 306

Section 4(c) (3) of the Rep. Act No. 10175 refers only to commercial
speech since it regulates communication that advertises or sells products or
services. These communications, in turn, proposes only commercial or
economic transactions. Thus, the parameters for the regulation of
commercial speech as articulated in the preceding discussions are squarely
applicable.

305

306

Central Hudson Gas & Electric v. Public Service Commission, 447 U.S. 557 (1980) <
http://caselaw.lp.findlaw.com/scripts/getcase.pl?court=US&vol=447&invol=557> (visited February
13, 2014).
Id. There are contrary opinions, but their reasoning is not as cogent. As explained by Justice Clarence
Thomas in his concurring opinion in 44 Liquormart, Inc. v. Rhode Island, 517 U.S. 484 (1996): I do
not see a philosophical or historical basis for asserting that "commercial" speech is of "lower value"
than "noncommercial" speech. Indeed, some historical materials suggest the contrary.
As noted by Aaron A. Scmoll, referring to the United States Supreme Court Decision in 44
Liquormart,: While Stevens and several other Justices seemed willing to apply strict scrutiny to
regulations on truthful advertising, a majority seemed content to continue down the path Central
Hudson created. The strongest reading drawn from 44 Liquormart may be that as to complete bans on
commercial speech, the Court will strictly apply Central Hudson so that in those cases, the analysis
resembles strict scrutiny. Schmoll, Aaron A. (1998) "Sobriety Test: The Court Walks the Central
Hudson Line Once Again in 44 Liquormart, but Passes on a New First Amendment Review, "Federal
Communications Law Journal: Vol. 50: Iss. 3, Article 11.

Dissenting & Concurring

95

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

Definitely, there is no occasion for Section 4(c)(3) to chill speech of


fundamental value. Absent an actual case, judicial review should not go past
that test. Hence, this provision should not be declared unconstitutional.
VIII (C)
The Provision has a Valid Purpose
As noted by the majority, Section 4(c)(3) refers to what, in
contemporary language, has been referred to as spam. The origin of the
term is explained as follows:
The term spam, as applied to unsolicited commercial
email and related undesirable online communication, is derived
from a popular Python sketch set in a cafe that includes the canned
meat product SPAM in almost every dish. As the waitress
describes the menu with increasing usage of the word spam, a
group of Vikings in the cafe start singing, Spam, spam, spam,
spam, spam, drowning out all other communication with their
irrelevant repetitive song. 307

Spam is typified by its being unsolicited and repetitive as well as by


its tendency to drown out other communication. Compared with other forms
of advertising, spam has been distinguished as a negative externality. This
means that it imposes upon a party a cost despite such partys not having
chosen to engage in any activity that engenders such cost. Thus:
How does spam differ from legitimate advertising? If you
enjoy watching network television, using a social networking site,
or checking stock quotes online, you know that you will be
subjected to advertisements, many of which you may find relevant
or even annoying. Google, Yahoo!, Microsoft, Facebook, and
others provide valuable consumer services, such as search, news,
and email, supported entirely by advertising revenue. While people
may resent advertising, most consumers accept that advertising is a
price they pay for access to content and services that they value.
By contrast, unsolicited commercial email imposes a negative
externality on consumers without any market-mediated benefit,
and without the opportunity to opt-out. 308

The noxious effects of spam are clearly demonstrable. Any email user
knows the annoyance of having to sift through several spam messages in a
seemingly never ending quest to weed them out. Moreover, while certain
spam messages are readily identifiable, a significant number are designed (or
disguised) in such a way as to make a user think that they contain legitimate
content.
307

308

Rao, J. M. and D. H. Reiley, The Economics of Spam, JOURNAL OF ECONOMIC PERSPECTIVES, 26(3):
87-110 (2012).
Id.

Dissenting & Concurring

96

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

For instance, spam emails are given titles or headings like, Please
update your information, Conference Invitation, Please Confirm,
Alert, Hello My Dearest, and Unclaimed Check. Spam messages also
make reference to current events and civic causes.
Similarly, spam messages disguise themselves as coming from
legitimate sources by using subtle or inconspicuous alterations in sender
information. Thus, a letter i, which appears in the middle of a word, is
replaced with the number 1, a letter o may be replaced with the number
zero; a spam message may be made to appear to come from the legitimate
online financial intermediary PayPal, when in fact, the sending address is
paypol.com. At times, entirely false names are used, making spam
messages appear to come from relatively unfamiliar but ostensibly legitimate
senders such as low-key government agencies or civic organizations. As
noted by Cisco Systems: The content in the message looks and sounds
much more legitimate and professional than it used to. Spam often closely
mimics legitimate senders' messagesnot just in style but by spoofing the
sender information, making it look like it comes from a reputable sender. 309
The damage cost by spamming is manifest in calculable financial and
economic costs and not just in the nebulous vexation it causes users. IT
research firm Nuclear Research found that as far back as eleven (11) years
ago, in 2003, an average employee receives 13.3 spam messages a day.
Moreover, a person may spend as much as ninety (90) minutes a day
managing spam. This translates to 1.4% lost productivity per person per year
and an average cost of US$ 874 per employee per year. 310 A 2012 study also
noted that some US$20 billion is spent annually to fend off unwanted email
with US$6 billion spent annually on anti-spam software. 311
Apart from being associated with the vexation of users and costs
undermining productivity and efficiency, spamming is also a means for
actually attacking IT systems. The 2000 attack of the I Love You Worm,
which was earlier noted in this opinion, was committed through means of
email messages sent out to a multitude of users. While defensive
technologies against spamming have been developed (e.g., IP blacklisting,
crowd sourcing, and machine learning), spammers have likewise improved
on their mechanisms. The present situation is thus indicative of escalation,
an arms race playing out in cyberspace. As is typical of escalation, the
capacity of spammers to inflict damage has significantly increased. In 2003,
309

310

311

The Bad Guys from Outside: Malware,


http://www.ciscopress.com/articles/article.asp?p=1579061&seqNum=4 (visited February 14, 2014).
Spam: The Silent ROI Killer, < http://www.spamhelp.org/articles/d59.pdf> (visited February 14,
2014).
Rao, J. M. and D. H. Reiley, The Economics of Spam, JOURNAL OF ECONOMIC PERSPECTIVES, 26(3):
87-110 (2012).

Dissenting & Concurring

97

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

spamming botnets began to be used, thereby enabling the spread of malware


(i.e., malicious software):
Blacklists gradually made it impossible for spammers to
use their own servers (or others open relay servers) with fixed IP
addresses. Spammers responded with a Whack-a-Mole strategy,
popping up with a new computer IP address every time the old one
got shut down. This strategy was observed and named as early as
1996, and eventually became considerably cheaper with another
major innovation in spam: the botnet.
A botnet is a network of zombie computers infected by a
piece of malicious software (or malware) designed to enslave
them to a master computer. The malware gets installed in a variety
of ways, such as when a user clicks on an ad promising free
ringtones. The infected computers are organized in a militaristic
hierarchy, where early zombies try to infect additional downstream
computers and become middle managers who transmit commands
from the central command and control servers down to the
frontline computers
The first spamming botnets appeared in 2003. Static
blacklists are powerless against botnets. In a botnet, spam emails
originate from tens of thousands of IP addresses that are constantly
changing because most individual consumers have their IP
addresses dynamically allocated by Dynamic Host Control
Protocol (DHCP). Dynamic blacklisting approaches have since
been developed; Stone-Gross, Holz, Stringhini, and Vigna (2011)
document that 90 percent of zombie computers are blacklisted
before the end of each day. However, if the cable company
assignsa zombie computer a new IP address each day, that
computer gets a fresh start and can once again successfully send
out spam. 312

Spams capacity to deceive recipients through false and misleading


headers, content, and senders likewise makes it a viable means for phishing
and identity theft, thereby enabling spammers to gain control of user
accounts (e.g., online banking, social networking). This is demonstrated by
the case of Jeffrey Brett Goodin, the first person to be convicted under the
United States Controlling the Assault of Non-Solicited Pornography and
Marketing Act of 2003 (more briefly and popularly known as the CANSPAM Act). Goodin was found guilty of sending emails to users of America
Online (AOL). Posing as someone from AOLs billing department, his
emails directed users to go to websites operated by Goodin himself. On the
pretense that information was necessary to prevent the termination of their
AOL services, these websites prompted users to supply personal and credit

312

Rao, J. M. and D. H. Reiley, The Economics of Spam, JOURNAL OF ECONOMIC PERSPECTIVES, 26(3):
87-110 (2012).

Dissenting & Concurring

98

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

card information. This, in turn, enabled Goodin to engage in fraudulent


transactions. 313
There can be no more direct way of curtailing spamming and its
deleterious effects than by prohibiting the transmission of commercial
electronic communication with the use of computer system which seek to
advertise, sell, or offer for sale products and services, 314 unless falling
under any of the enumerated exceptions, as Section 4(c)(3) does. The
preceding discussion has clearly demonstrated the extent to which spamming
engenders or otherwise facilitates vexation, intrusions, larceny, deception,
violence, and economic damage. Spamming represents a hazard, and its
riddance will entail the concomitant curtailment of the perils it entails.
VIII (D)
The Provision is Narrowly Drawn
Section 4(c)(3) is phrased in a manner that is sufficiently narrow. It is
not a blanket prohibition of the transmission of commercial electronic
communication with the use of computer system which seek to advertise,
sell, or offer for sale products and services. 315 Quite the contrary, it
recognizes instances in which commercial information may be validly
disseminated electronically. It provides multiple instances in which such
communications are not prohibited.
First, when there is prior affirmative consent from the recipient.
Second, when it is primarily in the nature of a service and/or
administrative announcement sent by a service provider to its clients.
Third, when there is a means to opt out of receiving such
communication, such communication not being deceptive in that it
purposely disguises its source or does not purposely contain misleading
information.
The first exception, far from curtailing free commercial expression,
actually recognizes it. It vests upon the parties to a communication, albeit
with emphasis on the receiver, the freedom to will for themselves if the
transmission of communication shall be facilitated.

313

314
315

California
Man
Guilty
of
Defrauding
AOL
Subscribers,
U.S.
Says,
<http://www.bloomberg.com/apps/news?pid=newsarchive&sid=a3ukhOXubw3Y> (visited February
14, 2014). On spam laws, < http://www.spamlaws.com/aol-phishing.html> (visited February 14,
2014).
Rep. Act No. 10175, sec. 4 (c) (3).
Rep. Act No. 10175, sec. 4 (c) (3).

Dissenting & Concurring

99

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

The second exception recognizes that there are instances when a


service provider must necessarily disseminate information (with or without
the recipients consent) to ensure the effective functioning and clients use of
its services.
The third exception directly deals with intentionally deceptive spam
that intends to ensnare users by not allowing them to opt out of receiving
messages.
Section 4(c)(3) merely provides parameters to ensure that the
dissemination of commercial information online is done in a manner that is
not injurious to others. For as long as they are not vexatious (i.e., prior
affirmative consent and opt-out requirement) or misleading, to the extent
that they are not intrusive on their recipients, they may continue to be validly
disseminated.
The opt-out provision provides the balance. Others may have as much
right to speak about their products and exaggerate as they offer to make a
commercial transaction. But that right is not an entitlement to vex others by
their repetitive and insistent efforts to insist that others listen even if the
customer has already declined. Commercial speech is protected only until it
ceases to inform.
A FINAL NOTE
Section 4. No law shall be passed abridging the freedom
of speech, of expression or of the press x x x

Rather than act with tempered but decisive vigilance for the protection
of these rights, we have precariously perched the freedoms of our people on
faith that those who are powerful and influential will not use the overly
broad provisions that prohibit libel, cyber libel, and cybersex against their
interests. We have exposed those that rely on our succor to the perils of
retaliation because we stayed our hand in declaring libel provisions as
unconstitutional. By diminishing the carefully drawn jurisprudential
boundaries of what is obscene and what is not, we have allowed the state to
unleash the dominant patriarchal notions of lascivious to police sexual
expression.
On the other hand, the majority has opted to strike down what appears
to be narrowly tailored protections against unsolicited commercial
communication through cyberspace. I decline to endow this kind of speech
the commercial and the corporate with more value. The balance struck
by the majority in this case weighs more heavily towards those who have

Dissenting & Concurring

100

G.R. Nos. 203335, et al.

Opinion

more resources and are more powerful. We have put the balance in favor of
what is in the hegemony. Legitimate dissent will be endangered.
That, to me, is not what the Constitution says.
The Constitution protects expression. It affirms dissent. The
Constitution valorizes messages and memes at the margins of our society.
The Constitution also insists that we will cease to become a democratic
society when we diminish our tolerance for tp.e raw and dramatically
delivered idea, the uncouth defamatory remark, and the occasional lascivious
representations of ourselves.
What may seem odd to the majority may perhaps be the very kernel
that unlocks our collective creativity.
ACCORDINGLY, I vote to declare as unconstitutional for being
overbroad and violative of Article III, Section 4 of the Constitution the
following provisions of Republic Act No. 10175 or the Cybercrime
Prevention Act of 2012:
(a) The entire Section 19 or the "take down" provision;
(b) The entire Section 4(c)(4) on cyber libel as well as Articles 353,
354, and 355 on libel of the Revised Penal Code;
( c) The entire Section 4(c )( 1) on cybersex; .
(d) Section 5 as it relates to Sections 4(c)(l) and 4(c)(4);
( e) Section 6 as it increases the penalties to Sections 4( c)(1) and
4( c)(4);
(f) Section 7 as it allows impermissibly countless prosecution of
Sections 4( c)( 1) and 4( c)( 4 ); and
(g) Section 12. on warrantless real-time traffic data surveillance.

I dissent with the majority in its finding that Section 4(c)(3) on


Unsolicited Commercial Advertising is unconstitutional.
I vote to dismiss the rest of the constitutional challenges against
the other provisiqns in Republic Act No. 10175 as raised in the
consolidated petitions for not being justiciable in the absence of an
actual case or controversy.
4

Associate Justice

You might also like