Interpretation and Legal Reasoning in Roman Law
Interpretation and Legal Reasoning in Roman Law
Interpretation and Legal Reasoning in Roman Law
Volume 70
Issue 4 Symposium on Ancient Law, Economics &
Society Part I: The Development of Law in Classical
and Early Medieval Europe / Symposium on Ancient
Law, Economics & Society Part I: The Development of
Law in the Ancient Near East
Article 7
January 1995
This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarly Commons @ IIT Chicago-Kent College of Law. It has been accepted for inclusion
in Chicago-Kent Law Review by an authorized administrator of Scholarly Commons @ IIT Chicago-Kent College of Law. For more information,
please contact [email protected].
The Roman jurists, whose works are excerpted in Justinian's Diare noted for their pragmatic approach to cases and for the subtlety of their casuistic reasoning. They did not generally indulge in
discussions of legal theory. It should not, however, be assumed that
because they did not articulate comprehensive legal theories, they
lacked ideas about the nature of law. For the period of the Roman
republic, these ideas have to be inferred from the bare decisions, but
by the beginning of the empire, differences in the jurists' reasoning
reveal more of their conceptions of the nature of the work in which
they were engaged. The compilers of the Digest, our main source,
were instructed to eliminate disagreements among the jurists whose
works they excerpted. Some traces of these disagreements remain,
however, and there is one text, Gaius's Institutes, 2 which is transmitted separately and contains several references to juristic disputes.
This Article illustrates, with examples taken from the Roman
sources, the methods of interpretation and legal reasoning which characterized the jurists both in the formative period of Roman law and in
its early maturity.
gest,1
From the beginning those who expounded Roman law were well
aware of the difference between unwritten law, which is not stated
authoritatively in fixed texts, and written law, which is so stated. The
distinction was expressly stated by Ulpian at the beginning of the third
century A.D. He indicated that the classification is derived from
Greek thought (D.1.1.6.1), but it was tacitly understood long before
him.
* Emeritus Regius Professor of Civil Law, University of Cambridge and Fellow of
Queens' College, Cambridge. Throughout this article I have provided my own translation for
many of the texts quoted.
1. The Digest of Justinian, Latin text, ed. T. Mommsen, and English translation, ed. A
Watson, Philadelphia 1985 (cited as D.).
2. The Institutes of Gaius, Latin text, ed. B. Seckel and B. Kuebler, and English translation
by W.M. Gordon and O.F. Robinson, Ithaca, 1988 (cited as Gaius, Inst.).
[Vol. 70:1539
Roman law, like most legal systems, began as a set of orally transmitted traditional norms, and written law began as written custom. In
the first century of the Roman republic, in the mid-fifth century B.C.,
the popular assembly enacted the Twelve Tables, 3 which had been prepared by a commission established for the purpose of "writing down
the laws." The contents were not so much new law as authoritative
settlement of doubtful cases which had arisen in the application of the
traditional customary law.
The general word for law was ius and enacted law was lex. Lex
was an express statement of what was ius. It derives from legere, to
read out, and indicates what is read aloud, or publicly declared. These
leges were written down, but their most important characteristic was
not the fact that they were committed to writing, but that their formulation was fixed and incapable of being altered, except by further legislation. The text of a statute was naturally subject to interpretation,
but only within the limits of its wording. In the area of private law,
legislation was rare in the republic after the enactment of the Twelve
Tables (the main exception to this being the lex Aquilia, to be considered later).
Legal development was achieved in the second half of the republic through the creation of new remedies. A legal action had two
stages. The first stage, before the magistrate, the praetor, was
designed to decide whether the parties' dispute raised an issue recognized by the civil law and how it should be settled. In the second
stage, the iudex, a layman chosen by the parties from a list of qualified
citizens, conducted a trial and decided the issue.
By the end of the third century B.C., the praetor set out the issue
in writing in a formula addressed to the iudex and expressed the issue
in hypothetical terms in the following form: "if you are satisfied that
the plaintiff has proved .
. . ,
1995]
1541
terpreting the law. They did not give reasoned opinions but "unmotivated" rulings, which carried authority because of their authors'
standing in the community. They had been accustomed to giving rulings on the scope and extent of the unwritten rules and, like the common law judges, could reformulate those rules with an eye to the facts
of a particular case. The existence of a text must have constrained
their freedom of decision making, as indeed it was probably intended
to do, but they soon gained confidence in their task. Indeed, they
were capable of creating new legal institutions in the guise of giving
meaning to the text of the Twelve Tables.
For example, the Twelve Tables contained a provision designed to
penalize a paterfamiliasfor abusing his power over his sons. 4 He was
entitled to sell his son into forced labor to another, but the legislation
provided that if he sold him three times, the son was to be free of his
father's power. Three sales were regarded as an abuse of the power of
the family head. At the time of the Twelve Tables, it was not contemplated that a father might voluntarily wish to free his son, who constituted an important economic asset to the family unit. Later,
circumstances made it desirable that the father should have the power
to emancipate his son and the pontiffs advised that, provided the father went through three successive sales to a compliant friend, the son
would be freed from paternal power by virtue of the Twelve Tables'
rule (Gaius, Inst. 1.132). Thus, an entirely new institution of voluntary
emancipation from paternal power was created by interpretation.
Pontifical interpretation went further. The Twelve Tables referred only to sons, and where daughters and grandchildren were concerned, the paterfamilias could apparently sell them as much as he
liked. Once the three sale rule was interpreted to refer to voluntary
emancipation, the pontiffs declared that, whereas three sales were required in the case of sons, one sale was sufficient for the emancipation
of daughters and grandchildren.
It should be noted that this pontifical innovation, while giving a
family head a power that he previously did not enjoy, did not interfere
with the interests of anyone outside the family. In most cases the pontiffs and the secular jurists, who succeeded them from the middle of
the third century B.c., had to be more cautious. The way they expounded the law differed according to whether the law was in written
or in unwritten form. If it was unwritten, they could gradually de4. Jolowicz and Nicholas, op. cit., 88ff.
CHICAGO-KENT
LAW REVIEW
[Vol. 70:1539
velop it on a case-by-case basis without any objection. If it was written, they had to keep within the terms of the lex.
This point may be illustrated by comparing the development of
theft of property and of damage to property, both of which gave the
victim a civil action for penal damages. Theft was recognized by the
customary law before the enactment of the Twelve Tables and was
regulated by that legislation, 5 whereas damage to property was wholly
a creature of statute.
Two kinds of theft were recognized: (1) manifest theft, where the
thief was caught in the act of theft, and (2) non-manifest theft, where
the thief was apprehended later. The penalty was a function of this
distinction. In manifest theft, the thief was scourged and handed over
to work for the victim. In non-manifest theft, the penalty was monetary with the thief paying double the value of the thing stolen. A
monetary penalty was later substituted for corporal punishment in the
case of manifest theft with the thief paying quadruple the value of the
thing stolen. These sums were penalties payable to the victim, irrespective of whether the victim recovered his property. What made the
grant of such a remedy to the victim realistic was the existence of
noxal surrender. If the thief was a slave or a son in the power of his
family head who would not have funds of his own from which to pay
the penalty, the action would be brought against the slave's owner or
the son's family head. The latter then had the option of either paying
the penalty or surrendering the delinquent noxally into the ownership
or power of the victim.
The Twelve Tables did not, however, define theft (furtum). The
idea was well-established and a definition was unnecessary. As the
etymology from ferre, to carry, suggests, theft originally indicated taking away someone else's property. By the end of the republic, theft
had been expanded to the extent that the jurists were granting the
victim's remedy, the actio furti, for any dishonest interference with
another's property, even if the thing stolen was not moved. In addition, the jurists were ready to give this remedy to non-owners who
found themselves the victims of theft. As Buckland put it, "with the
single word furtum to interpret, the lawyers had a free hand and there
is probably no other institution in which the shaping hand of the jurist,
untrammelled by legislation, is so evident as it is here."'6
5. Jolowicz and Nicholas, op. cit., 167ff.
6. W.W. Buckland, The Main Institutions of Roman Private Law, Cambridge 1931, 327.
1995]
1543
[Vol. 70:1539
Two
At the beginning of the empire, there were two contrasting movements at work among the Roman jurists.9 On the one hand, there was
pressure for more rationalism in the law, for identifying a coherent set
8. P. Stein, "The Development of the Institutional System," Studies in Justinian's Institutes
in memory of J.A.C. Thomas, ed. P.G. Stein and A.D.E. Lewis, London 1983, 151ff.
9. P. Stein, "The Two Schools of Jurists in the Early Roman Principate," 31 (1) Cambridge
Law Journal (1972), 8ff; D. Liebs, "Rechtsschulen und Rechtsunterricht im Prinzipat," Aufstieg
und Niedergang der Rbmischen Welt, ed. H. Temporini and W. Haase, Berlin-New York 1976,
11.15, 197-286; G.L. Falchi, Le Controversie tra Sabiniani e Proculiani, Milan 1981.
1995]
1545
of rules and remedies, each with precisely defined limits, and for the
use of logic in the application of those rules. On the other hand, there
was a counter-movement to avoid too many precise rules, with a view
to preserving as much flexibility as possible, to avoid logic as being too
remote from experience, and to concentrate on the decision in the
individual case.
These contrasting movements were represented by two schools of
jurists, known as the Proculians and the Sabinians. The former was
founded by Labeo and the latter by Capito and they "first made, as it
were, two sects: for Ateius Capito held fast to what had been handed
down to him, whereas Labeo, a genius, with confidence in his own
scholarship, who had studied several other branches of knowledge, set
out to make many innovations" (Pomponius in D.1.2.2.47).
Although Labeo is described as an innovator, a comparison of the
substantive doctrines of the two schools does not show either the
Proculians as reformers or the Sabinians as especially conservative. It
seems that the differences were of method rather than doctrine and
that Labeo used his expertise in other disciplines, particularly grammar and dialectic, to introduce into Roman juristic discourse more rigorous techniques of interpretation and argument than those of the
republican jurists. His views are well represented in our sources.
Capito's views are not, but we have many texts from his successor,
Sabinus, and can draw comparisons between Labeo's methods and
those of his opponents.
INTERPRETATION OF LEGAL TEXTS
[Vol. 70:1539
way to his land and had then abandoned it, without waiting to be expelled physically (D.4.2.9pr.).
With respect to the first chapter of the lex Aquilia, which seems to
have caused little difficulty in the republic, Labeo held that the etymology of the word for kill (occidere, from caedere, to cut) covered
only killing by violence and with a weapon. Therefore, in a case
where a midwife gave a drug to a slave-woman, who then accepted it,
consumed it, and died, Labeo argued that the action under the statute
was not applicable and that the praetorshould grant a special actio in
factum (D.9.2.9pr.). Whenever the circumstances of a case could not
be subsumed under the terms of the formula of a particular action, the
praetor could grant an actio in factum. In it were set out the particular
circumstances of the case, which the plaintiff had to prove at the trial
if the lay judge was to find in his favor.
Celsus, a later Proculian, had to confront the fact that previous
practice had already extended the word rumpere in the third chapter
of the lex Aquilia to mean corrumpere. He engaged, however, in some
damage limitation. How far did corrumpere extend? Celsus argued
that it was not enough for the owner to be deprived of the thing by the
defendant's act. In addition, it was necessary that the defendant
should have caused some change in the thing itself. Celsus explains
the interpretation of rumpere as corrumpere (to damage) in a typically
Proculian way. Referring to its place in the text following "burn" and
"smash," he added that "there is nothing new in that a statute, after
enumerating some cases specially, should add a general term which
embraces those specific things" (D.9.2.27.16).
With respect to the interpretation of contracts, Labeo held that
what mattered was quod actum est (literally "what was transacted,"
D.18.1.77), and it is clear that by this phrase he referred to the objective agreement of the parties, as expressed in the formulation of the
contract. For him certainty was all-important and if the parties were
not prepared to exploit the potentials for certainty that language offered them, they should not expect the law to bail them out.
Sabinus and his followers favored a looser and less rigid approach
to the interpretation of texts. For example, Sabinus held that the rule
of the Twelve Tables that required three conveyances for a son to be
freed from paternal power, referred only to voluntary conveyances,
even though there was no such limitation in the statutory text. Therefore, when a paterfamiliassurrendered the son noxally to the victim of
1995]
1547
As we have noted in the case of the slave who died after consuming poison, Labeo was unwilling to assimilate under an action facts
which did not strictly fall under the terms of the relative formula.
Rather, he advocated the creation of a separate action for the special
circumstances. Sabinus, on the other hand, preferred to squeeze new
[Vol. 70:1539
1995]
1549
[Vol. 70:1539
republican jurists regarded both the person who took the thing and
the person who helped him as equally guilty as thieves. There had
been a tendency to treat as a thief anyone who did something which
resulted in making the victim lose his property to another, if he should
have known that he was acting against the owner's will, whether he
was subjectively dishonest or not.
Labeo held that the words should be read disjunctively as meaning "either by the physical act or by the design" of the defendant
(D.50.16.53.2). Thus, he distinguished the principal who took the
thing from the accomplice who helped him and, in the case of the
latter, required specific, dishonest advice (malignum consilium) directed to the taking. Labeo was consistently scrupulous in requiring
proof of actual subjective dishonesty on the part of the defendant.
Sabinus accepted that the republican jurists' views on theft
needed tidying up but was reluctant to limit the scope of the delict.
He adopted a broad definition, and did not insist on actual subjective
dishonesty: "anyone commits theft who has handled another's thing,
when he ought to know that he does so against the owner's will" (cited
by Aulus Gellius, Attic Nights, 11.18.20). Sabinus held it to be theft
where a stakeholder in a competition received the prize and then refused to hand it over to the winner (D.19.5.17.5).
Although the majority view was that theft was confined to moveables, Sabinus held that land could be stolen and that a tenant farmer
who sold the land that he was renting committed theft against the
owner, who was thus deprived of its possession (Aulus Gellius, id.
11.18.13). (In Roman doctrine the landlord was held to "possess"
through his tenant.)
UNWR
EN LAW
When they were not dealing with the interpretation of a fixed text
or the limits of actions, the Proculians recognized the existence of an
unstated structure of basic principles. They sought to apply those
principles in circumstances where their rivals saw no connection.
They looked for a logical structure to the law, whereas the Sabinians
stressed custom and practice. Labeo held that one could use analogy
to discover the law applicable to a problem which had not been the
subject of a previous ruling. He was familiar with the dispute among
grammarians between analogists, who viewed language as a structure
of rules, and anomalists, who considered language as based exclusively
1995]
1551
[Vol. 70:1539
was void, and the Sabinians argued that the same rule must apply also
to the nomination of a guardian.
The Proculians asked what was the reason for the rule and found
that both legacies and manumissions of slaves reduced the amount of
the residuary estate, which went to the heir. Therefore, it was logical
that they should appear in the will after the institution. But this reason did not apply to the nomination of a guardian, and so the Proculians held such a nomination to be valid, even when it preceded the
institution.
THE CRITERIA OPPOSED TO RATIONALITY
1995]
1553
the too legalistic reasoning (civilis ratio) of his opponent. The phrase
is used in lay literature to explain, as natural, unusual events which
have been attributed by others to supernatural causes. It has been
noted that in the dispute over specification, Sabinus justified his view
that the new thing belonged to the owner of the material by an appeal
to natural reason.
In another dispute, there are traces of similar arguments
(D.17.2.83). When a stone was embedded in the ground, partly in A's
land and partly in B's land, A and B each owned that part of the stone
which lay in his land. For when it was in the ground, it was not distinguishable from the ground. What is the position when the stone was
removed from the ground? Some jurists (the Proculians?) argued that
then the stone, as an object distinct from the ground, was owned in
common by A and B in undivided shares, which bore the same relation to each other as the former separate portions. Others (the
Sabinians?) differed. How, they asked, could the mere removal of the
stone from the ground alter its ownership? The solution suggested by
nature was that A and B each retained absolutely the same part of the
stone as they had when the stone was in the ground. The law cannot
alter what nature has settled.
Later Sabinians substituted "the general convenience" (utilitas
13
communis) for nature as a criterion to set against Proculian logic.
Justifying a ruling that some might consider "absurd," Salvius Julianus
remarked, a century after Sabinus, that "it can be proved in innumerable cases that many rulings have been accepted by the civil law contrary to logic for the general convenience." As an example, he set
forth the case of several persons, intending to steal, who carried off
another's timber beam, which none of them could have carried alone.
They are all liable for theft, "although by subtle reasoning (subtili ratione), it might be argued that none of them is liable because no one
person actually removed the beam" (D.9.2.51.2).
THE NATURE OF LEGAL RULES
There are traces of a dispute over the nature of legal rules.14 The
late republican jurists, particularly Quintus Mucius Scaevola, tried to
state the civil law in a series of definitiones, which were seen as summary descriptions of the law as revealed in practice. Labeo intro13. V. Scarano Ussani, L'Utilita e la certezza: compiti e modelli del sapere giuridico in
Salvio Giuliano, Milan 1987, 3ff.
14. P. Stein, Regulae luris: From Juristic Rules to Legal Maxims, Edinburgh 1966, 67ff.
[Vol. 70:1539
DEFINITION OF LAW
1995]
1555
The two schools of jurists, as representatives of two opposing approaches to law, did not survive much more than a hundred years
among practitioners. By the beginning of the second century A.D.,
there was a tendency to merge the methods of both schools. As consultants, the jurists could deal with the cases that came their way individually, but as teachers they had to take a broader view.
Evidence for the existence of the schools as teaching institutions
is sparse, but it is not difficult to believe that the differences between
the schools survived in law teaching after they had ceased to have
much significance in practice. Debates between teachers and students
and alumni loyalty to their institutional attitudes would have ensured
their survival in the academic environment. Even in the second half
of the second century A.D., Gaius, who was exclusively a law teacher,
treated the school disputes as alive and flourishing.
The lasting influence of those disputes was the creation of a tension between two ways of looking at law. This tension formed the
parameters within which the later giants of classical jurisprudence operated. It is through their writings, particularly those of Paul and Ulpian in the early third century, as excerpted in Justinian's Digest, that
later generations learned about the nature of law itself.
[Vol. 70:1539
The famous aphorism of Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr. in his lectures on The Common Law, "the life of the law has not been logic; it
17
has been experience," was itself derived indirectly from Roman law.
Holmes went on to say, "it is something to show that the consistency
of a system requires a particular result, but it is not all.... The law...
cannot be dealt with as if it contained only the axioms and corollaries
of a book of mathematics.' 1 8 Two years before he wrote those words,
Holmes had been reading (in a French translation) Rudolph von Jhering's Der Geist des rdmischen Rechts ("The spirit of Roman law"). In
this work Jhering says, "the desire for logic that turns jurisprudence
into legal mathematics is an error and arises from misunderstanding
law. Life does not exist for the sake of concepts but concepts for the
sake of life. It is not logic that is entitled to exist but what is claimed
by life, by social relations, by the sense of justice,-and logical necessity, or logical impossibility, is immaterial."' 19
In their debates, the Roman jurists were caught in the two contrasting characteristics that society still expects from law: certainty and
rationality on the one hand, and a satisfactory solution of the individual case on the other.
17. P. Stein, "Logic and Experience in Roman and Common law," 59 Boston University
Law Review (1979), 433; reprinted in P. Stein, The Character and Influence of the Roman Civil
Law: Historical Essays, London-Ronceverte, 1988, 37ff.
18. O.W. Holmes, The Common Law (1881), 1.
19. 4 L'Esprit du Droit Romain, translated 0. Meulenaere (3rd ed.1888), 311.