Grice, P. (2001) - The Conception of Value.
Grice, P. (2001) - The Conception of Value.
Grice, P. (2001) - The Conception of Value.
PAUL GRICE
With an Introduction by
JUDITH BAKER
This book is sold subject to the condition that it shall not, by way
of trade or otherwise, be lent, re-sold, hired out or otherwise circulated
without the publisher's prior consent in any form of binding or cover
other than that in which it is published and without a similar condition
including this condition being imposed on the subsequent purchaser
J. B.
Con ten ts
Index 1 63
Introduction
Judith Baker
H. P. GR I C E ' S CO N S TR U CT I O N O F V A L U E
'what seems good to the good man is good. ' The principle
may be viewed as itself an application of the metaphysical
principle of supply and demand; it is a procedure for
securing rational demands that is seemingly 'trouble-free'.
As rational beings we demand justification for our projects
and attitudes ; the standards for acceptance do not,
however, come ready-made, but must themselves be
constructed. Persons, who work at their job, who are
concerned to find principles acceptable to rational beings,
get the benefits of their job: what seems good to them is.
Grice was amply aware of the problems left unsolved by
his account. This introduction will address only two
objections it might be natural to raise to the solutions he
offered. The first arises from the procedure of Humean
Projection, the second concerns both construction routines.
One may worry that the application of Humean Projection
involves a dangerous circle: value is a suspect term, hence
has to be put through the mangle to be legitimated; but it
can only be legitimated if we suppose the creature at the
mangle to be of absolute value. The 'Reply' offers the
means to respond: Grice refers to the principle he once
invented, though he did not establish its validity, a
principle he labelled Bootstrap. 'The principle laid down
that when one is introducing the primitive concepts of a
theory formulated in an object language, one has freedom
to use any battery of concepts expressible in the meta
language, subject to the condition that counterparts of
such concepts are subsequently definable or otherwise
derivable in the object-language' (p. 93) . He could appeal
to Bootstrap, to argue that when value as member of a
kind is attributed to persons, the term is taken from the
theoretician'<; language, but is viewed as primitive, and
unanalysed in the language of humans whose concepts are
the object of study. This is legitimate, because it is
redeemed once value has been put through the mangle;
truth conditions or something analogous having been
specified for statements of value.
18 Introduction
The second objection contests the legitimating role
played by a 'theoretical purpose' and maintains that
playing a part in a theory and being objective are quite
separate, and that the fact that, for example, persons might
be needed for a certain theory does not go very far towards
establishing their objectivity. The criticism gets its force
from a position taken in the instrumentalist-realist dispute
within the philosophy of science. Now there are certain
disanalogies in the work and aims of Grice and those
disputants which need to be noted at the start, but none
the less there is a real issue here, namely, what the
difference is between scientific and metaphysical construc
tion, and so what differences with respect to the objectivity
of the constructed entities. First, Grice might have been
happy if theories of value were 'anti-realist' but had as
much objectivity as parts of natural science and mathe
matics.
Second, the kind of entities which are the focus of the
dispute in philosophy of science-unobservable or, better,
unobserved entities, are not really the kind of entities
which concerned Grice. He once noted in a seminar that
some theoretical entities in science, that is, entities inferred
but not observed or thought to be observable, have
become at a given time observable or recognized to be so.
But note that there are two entirely different ways in which
this has been held to come about. There is the naive view,
held by some philosophers and the vast majority of
microscopists, that successive improvements in instru
ments have made whole domains of objects observable,
starting with sperm and cells in the seventeenth century
and, for example, the structure of man-made, integrated
circuits on silicon chips in our own day. Then there is the
idea, entertained by some philosophers, that if certain
theories are true, then objects that we have always been
able to observe are identical with what we formerly
thought of as unobservable. For example, certain visible
crystals are now held to be single molecules, and certain
Introduction 19
flashes of light are held b y NASA to b e high-energy
electrons. If the scientific theories are correct, and a
Kripke-like theory about identity is correct, then we were
always able to see some molecules and some electrons.
Evidently what counts as observable is not plain sailing.
In the first type of case, in which we extend the limits of
observability by making better instruments, it is contingent
that we should have become able to observe the sperm or
make and observe chips. In the second type of case, on one
theory of identity, the flashes are not only identical but
also necessarily identical with electrons, but this is known
only a posteriori. Grice suggested in contrast a quite
different kind of theoretical item, such that it was both
necessary that things of that kind should be observable,
but also that it could be known a priori, in the course of
theory construction, that they should be observable
otherwise they would not fulfil the demands of the theory.
Grice did not propose this curious kind of necessary a
priori observability as the distinguishing feature of meta
physically constructed items. It is however tempting and
an obvious line to pursue if we confine ourselves to the
construction of entities within practical theories. It may be
very important for action that persons are directly known
and are the kinds of creature that we can know a priori to
be directly knowable.
Grice was aware of a need to distinguish scientific from
metaphysical construction-what he referred to in the
'Reply' as, respectively, hypothetization and hypostatiza
tion. In the 'Reply' he emphasized the importance of
construction routines and claimed that we have meta
physical routines of construction, but that there are no
such procedures for science, or that when there are, there is
a move to metaphysical construction. Grice did not
expand on this remark, but it is plausible that the presence
of routines is important because there is a difference in who
does the constructing; not a small scientific elite, or group
of experts, but people in general.
20 Introduction
One might, however, still object: although routines may
distinguish between the two types of construction, the
most we get for our metaphysical entities is justified
acceptance of them, not true belief. The difference between
the two is integral to the dispute. Grice was himself
concerned that transcendental or metaphysical argument
might establish only the first, and weaker, consequence.
Now Grice asserts in the ' Reply' that in some conditions
acceptance may confer truth, namely, within the area of
metaphysical argument. On the supposition of an intoler
able breakdown of rationality if we do not accept a certain
thesis, then the demand for acceptance would be sufficient
to confer truth on what is to be accepted. 'Proof of the
pudding comes from the need to eat it, not vice versa'
(p. 96) .
Why should we agree to this ? We need to see how the
argument might go in specific cases to see just what factors
are at work. Two features of the earlier example of
sheepdogs raise an important question : the new entity,
sheepdog, would serve what Grice called a theoretical
purpose, permitting us, for example, to explain its
behaviour in terms of awareness of its tasks. But at least
some of the characteristics which serve as explanation may
also be viewed as those presuppositions necessary for any
rational agent who works with and trains the animal. They
make the agent's action intelligible. Moreover, the rational
action in question is a common human activity. Both of
these factors help to make it plausible that a new entity has
been constructed. The issue they raise here is whether they
aren't also underpinnings of the metaphysical argument
which threatens a breakdown of rationality. Grice thinks
metaphysical arguments are practical, that they articulate
what are rational demands. The interpretation here is in
line with and, I believe, supports this view: the meta
physical argument for the construction of value is indeed
practical. For the reconceptions of construction routines
arise from our interests and the demands are made from
Introduction 21
within a practice, from the need to make our common
behaviour intelligible. On this interpretation a theoretical
purpose may legitimate construction, but only when the
construction routine itself is part of a common human
activity.
Independently of the appeal to metaphysical argument,
Grice has available a second response to the challenge that
only necessary acceptance, not truth, is required for his
constructions. The routines themselves may be called on to
fill the alleged gap between the two. In the example of
values, it might be argued that we have both a rational
justification for value and the natural tendency to project
our attitudes on the world; here there is no gap between
justified acceptance of a thesis that there are things of
value and belief in its truth. The scientist who accepts a
certain constructed entity may be committed to a research
programme, to thinking in terms of such an entity. But
ontological reservations can have some expression when
she is not on her job, when it is not up to her to act as a
scientist. Whereas if indeed we value something, our
attitude is naturally projected onto the world; it does not
result from a commitment nor is it confined to those areas
in which action is up to us. Whenever we think of what we
value, we have the attitudes and emotions which go with
it. What difference could belief in truth bring?
In the closing paragraph of the 'Reply', Grice acknow
ledged that his defence of value 'bristled' with problems
unsolved or incompletely solved. He was avowedly happy
rather than dismayed to leave his philosophical friends
with work to do.
The Carus Lectures on the
Conception of Value
1. V A L U E A N D O BJECT I V I T Y
2. RE L A T I V E A N D ABS O L U T E V A L U E
3. M E T A PHY S I C S A N D V A L U E 1
whose timely, skilful, and patient piloting the lecture, and so the series
containing it, would not have been written.
70 The Carus Lectures
encounter, it now seems to me, shaped my later philo
sophical life; it seems that I did, indeed, learn in the end.
For first, the metaphysical programme which I shall be
seeking to follow will be a constructivist programme and
not a reductionist programme. The procedure which I
envisage, if carried out in full, would involve beginning
with certain elements which would have a claim to be
thought of as metaphysically primary, and then to build up
from these starting-points, stage by stage, a systematic
metaphysical theory or concatenation of theories. It would
be no part of my plan to contend that what we end up with
'is really only such and suches', or that talking about what
my enterprises produce is really only a compressed way of
talking about the primary materials, or indeed to make any
other claim of that relatively familiar kind. I suspect that
many of those who have thought of themselves, like
Carnap, as engaged in a programme of construction are
really reductionists in spirit and at heart; they would like
to be able to show that the multifarious world to which we
belong reduces in the end to a host of complexes of simple
ingredients. That is not my programme at all; I do not
want to make the elaborate furniture of the world dissolve
into a number of simple pieces of kitchenware; I hope to
preserve it in all its richness. I would seek, rather, to
understand the metaphysical processes by which one
arrives at such richness from relatively simple points of
departure. I would not seek to exhibit anything as 'boiling
down' to any complex of fundamental atoms.
In order to pursue a constructivist programme of the
kind which I have in mind, I will need three things : first, a
set of metaphysical starting-points, things which are
metaphysically primary ; second, a set of recognized
construction routines or procedures, by means of which
non-primary items are built up on the basis of more
primary items ;. and third, a theoretical motivation for
proceeding from any given stage to a further stage, so that
the mere possibility of applying the routines would not be
Metaphysics and Value 71
itself enough to give one a new metaphysical layer; one
would have to have a justification for making that move; it
would have to serve some purpose.
The way I imagine myself carrying out this programme
in detail (on some day quite a bit longer than today) is
roughly as follows. First, I would start by trying to reach a
full-dress characterization of what a theory is ( an exercise
in what I think of as theory-theory); I would be hoping
that the specification of what theorizing is would lead in a
non-arbitrary way to the identification of some particular
kind of theorizing (or theory) as being, relative to all other
kinds of theorizing, primary and so deserving of the title of
First Theory (or First Philosophy) . I would expect this
primary theorizing to be recognizable as metaphysical
theorizing, with the result that a specification of the
character and content of metaphysics would be reached in a
more systematic way than by just considering whether
some suggested account of metaphysics succeeds in fitting
our intuitive conception of that discipline. The implement
ation of this kind of metaphysical programme would, I
hope, lead one successively through a series of entities
(entity-types), such as a series containing at one stage
particulars, followed by continuants, followed by a
specially privileged kind of continuants, namely substances,
and so on. Each newly introduced entity-type would carry
with it a segment of theory which would supplement the
body of theory already arrived at, and which would serve
to exhibit the central character of the type or types of
entity associated with it.
The application of these programmatic ideas to the
determination of the conception of value would be
achieved in the following way. The notion of value, or of
some specially important or fundamental kind of value,
like absolute value, would be shown as occupying some
indispensable position in the specification of some stage in
this process of metaphysical evolution. Such a meta
physical justification of the notion of value might perhaps
72 The Carus Lectures
be comparable to the result of appending, in a suitably
integrated way, the Nicomachean Ethics as a concluding
stage to the De Anima. One would first set up a
specification of a series of increasingly complex creatures;
and one would then exhibit the notion of value as entering
essentially into the theory attending the last and most
complex type of creature appearing in that series. The un
Carnapian character of my constructivism would perhaps
be evidenced by my idea that to insist with respect to each
stage in metaphysical development upon the need for
theoretical justification might carry with it the thought
that to omit such a stage would be to fail to do justice to
some legitimate metaphysical demand.
I propose to start today's extract from this metaphysical
story at a point at which, to a previously generated stock
of particulars which would include things which some,
though not all, would be prepared to count as individual
substances, there is added a sequence of increasingly
complex items, which (as living things) would be thought
of by some (perhaps by Aristotle) as the earliest items on
the ascending metaphysical ladder to merit the title of
substances proper. My first metaphysical objective, at this
stage of my unfolding story, would be to suggest a
consideration of the not unappealing idea that the notion
of living things presupposes, and cannot be understood
without an understanding of, the notion(s) of purpose,
finality, and final cause. In my view this idea is not only
. appealing but correct; I recognize, however, that there are
persons with regrettable deflationary tendencies who
would insist that while reference to the notions of finality
or final cause may provide in many contexts a useful and
illuminating manner of talking about living things, these
notions are not to be taken seriously in the metaphysics of
biology and are not required in a theoretical account of the
nature of life and of living things. A finalistic (or
" vitalistic") account of the nature of living things might
take as a ruling idea (perhaps open to non-vitalists as well)
Metaphysics and Value 73
that life consists (very roughly) in the possession of a no
doubt interwoven set of capacities the fulfilment, in some
degree, of each of which is required for the set of
capacities, as a whole, to be retained; a sufficiently serious
failure in respect of any one capacity will result in the
currently irreversible loss of all the rest; and that would be,
as one might say, death. The notion of finality might be
thought to be unavoidably embedded in the notion of life
for more than one reason. One reason would be that if it is
in one way or another of the essence of living creatures
that one has, instead of an indefinitely extended individual
thing, an indefinitely long sequence of living things, each
individual being produced by, and out of, predecessors in
the sequence, then to avoid having individuals which are of
outrageous bulk because they contain within themselves
the actual bodies of all their descendants, it will be
necessary to introduce the institutions of growth and
maturity; and with these institutions will come finality,
since the states reached in the course of growth and
maturity will have to be states to which the creatures
aspire and strive, though not necessarily in any conscious
way. Another way in which it might be suggested that the
notion of finality has to enter will be that at least in a
creature of any degree of complexity, the discharge of its
vital functions will have to be effected by the operations of
various organs or parts, or combinations of such; and each
of these organs or parts will have, so to speak, its job to do,
and indeed its status as a part (a working functional part,
that is to say, and not merely a spatial piece) is determined
by its being something which has such-and-such a job or
function (eyes are things to see with, feet to walk on, and
so forth); and these jobs or functions have to be distin
guished by their relation to some feature of the organism
as a whole, most obviously to such things as its continued
existence. The organism's continuance, though not ordin
arily, perhaps, called a function of the organism, will
nevertheless be required as something which the organism
74 The Carus Lectures
strives for, in order that we should be able to account for
the nature of the parts as parts ; it will be that thing, or one
of the things, to which in their characteristic ways the parts
are supposed to contribute. It is worth noting, with regard
to the first of these reasons for the appearance of finality
on the scene, that for the idea of actual containment of a
creature within its forebears there is substituted the idea of
potential containment, an idea which can be extended
backwards (so to speak) without any attendant inflation of
the bodies of ancestral creatures.
Perhaps I might at this point make two marginal
comments on the scheme which I am proposing. First, if I
allow myself in discussing the notion of life to ascribe
purpose or finality to creatures, parts of creatures, or
operations of creatures, such purposes or finalities are to
be thought of as detached from any purposers, from any
creature or being, mundane or celestial, which consciously
or unconsciously harbours that purpose or finality. If the
walrus or the walrus's moustache has a purpose, that
purpose, though it would be the purpose of the walrus, or
of its moustache, would not be the walrus's purpose, its
moustache's purpose, or even God's purpose. A failure to
appreciate this point has been, I think, responsible for
some of the disrepute into which serious application,
within the philosophy of biology, of the concept of finality
has fallen. Second, if one relies on finality as a source of
explanation (if one does not, what is the point of appealing
to it? ) , if indeed one wishes to use as modes of explanation
all, or even more than one, of Aristotle's " Four Causes " ,
one should not b e taken to b e supposing that there i s a
single form of request for explanation, a proper response
to which will, from occasion to occasion, be now of this
type and now of that type, and maybe sometimes of more
than one type. It is not that there would be just one kind of
"Why ? " question with alternative and possibly at times
even rival kinds of answer; there would be several kinds of
"Why ? " question, different kinds of question being perhaps
Metaphysics and Value 75
linked to categorially different kinds of candidates for
explanation, and each kind calling for its own kind of
'cause', its own type of explanation. And it might even be
that, so far from being rivals, different types of 'cause'
worked together, or one through another; it might be, for
example, that the operation of final causes demanded and
was only made possible by the operation, say, of efficient
or material causes with respect to a suitably linked
explicandum; the success of a " finality " explanation to a
question asking why a certain organ is present in a certain
kind of organism might depend upon the availability of a
suitable "efficient cause" explanation of how that organ
came to be present.
Nevertheless, these assuaging and anodyne representa
tions are, I fear, unlikely to appease a dyed-in-the-wool
mechanist. Such a one would be able to elicit from any
moderately sensible vitalist an admission that the mere fact
that the presence of a certain sort of feature or capacity
would be advantageous to a certain type of creature offers
no guarantee that the operation of efficient causes would
in fact provide for the presence of that feature or capacity
in that type of creature. So a vitalist would have to admit
that a " finality" explanation would be non-predictive in
character; and at this point the mechanist can be more or
less counted on to respond that a non-predictive explana
tion is not really an explanation at all. While a mechanist
might be prepared to allow that survival is a consequence
(in part) of those features which, as one might say, render a
type of creature fit to survive, and perhaps also allow that
this consequence is a beneficial consequence, or pay-off,
arising from the presence of those features, he would not
be ready to concede that the creature comes to have those
features in order that it should survive. To refine the terms
of this discussion a little: one might try to distinguish
between the question why a certain feature is present, and
the question why (or how) that feature comes to be
present; the mechanistically minded philosopher might be
76 The Carus Lectures
represented as doubting whether the first question is
intelligible if it is supposed to be distinct from the second,
and as being ready to maintain that if, after all, the two
questions are distinct and are both legitimate, the provision
of an answer to the first cannot be held to require the
existence of an answer to the second, and indeed is
possible at all only given independent information that
that feature has come to be present.
Furthermore, in respect of other areas where a vitalist
(or finalist) is liable to invoke finality as a tool for
explanation, the mechanist will say that one can quite
adequately explain the phenomena which lead the vitalist
to appeal to finality, without having recourse to such an
appeal; one will use a particular kind of explanation by
efficient causes, one which deploys such cybernetic notions
as negative feedback and homoeostasis; as one mechanistic
philosopher, David Armstrong, has suggested, people will
be like guided missiles.
At this the vitalist might argue that to demand the
presence of biological explanation as embodying finalistic
apparatus casts no disrespect on the capacity of "prior"
sciences (such as physics and chemistry) in a certain sense
to explain everything. In a certain sense I can explain why
there are seventeen people in the market-place, if in respect
of each person who is in the market-place I can explain
why he is there, and I can also explain why anyone else
who might have been in the market-place is in fact
somewhere else. But there is an understandable sense in
which to do all that does not explain, or at least does not
explain directly, why there are seventeen people in the
market-place. To fill the " explanation-gap " , to explain not
just indirectly but directly the presence of seventeen people
in the market-place, to explain it qua being the presence of
seventeen people in the market-place, I might have to
introduce a new theory, perhaps some highly dubitable
branch of social psychology; and I suspect that some
scientific theories, like perhaps catastrophe-theory, have
Metaphysics and Value 77
arisen in much this kind of way on the backs (so to speak)
of perfectly adequate, though not omnipotent, pre-existing
theories, in order to explain, in a stronger sense of
"explain " , things which are already explained in some
sense by existing theory.
To this, the mechanist might reply that there is (was)
indeed good reason for us to strengthen our explanatory
potentialities by adding to the science(s) of physics and
chemistry the explanatory apparatus of biology, thus
giving ourselves the power to explain directly rather than
merely indirectly such phenomena as those of animal
behaviour; but it does not follow from that that the
apparatus brought to bear by biology should include any
finalistic concepts or explanations; explanations given in
biological terms are perfectly capable of being understood
in cybernetic terms, without any appeal to concepts whose
respectability is suspect or in question.
In response to this latest tiresome intervention by the
mechanist, I now introduce a reference to something which
is, I think, a central feature of the procedures leading to the
development of a cumulative succession of theories or
theory-stages, each of which is to contain its predecessor.
This is the appearance of what I will call overlaps. In
setting out some theory or theory-stage B, which is to
succeed and include theory or theory-stage A, it may be
that one introduces some theoretical apparatus which
provides one with a redescription of a certain part of
theory A. I may, for instance, in developing arithmetic,
introduce the concept of positive and negative integers;
and if I were to restrict myself to that part of the domain of
this 'new' concept which involves solely positive integers, I
would have a class of formula: each of which provides a
redescription of what is said by a formula relating to
natural numbers; and since the older way of talking (or
writing) would be that much more economical, if it came
to a fight the natural numbers would win; the innovation
would be otiose, since theorems relating solely to positive
78 The Carus Lectures
integers would precisely mirror already available theorems
about natural numbers. But of course, to attend in a
myopic or blinkered way only to positive integers would
be to ignore the whole point of the introduction of the
'new' class of positive and negative integers, which as a
whole provides for a larger domain than the domain of
natural numbers for a single battery of arithmetical
operations, and so for a larger range of specific arithmetical
laws. That is the ratio essendi of the newly introduced
integers, to extend the range of these arithmetical opera
tions. Somewhat similarly, if one paid attention only to
examples of universal statements which related to finite
classes of objects, one might reasonably suppose the
expressions of universal statements to be equivalent to a
conjunction of, or to be a 'compendium' of, a set of
singular statements ; and indeed, at times philosophers
have been led by this idea, notably in the case of Mill. But
of course, at least part of the point of introducing universal
statements is to get beyond the stage at which one is
restricted to finite classes, and therefore beyond a stage at
which one can regard universal statements as being simply
compendia of singular statements.
In the present connection, one might suggest that
discourse about detached finality might be regarded as
belonging to a system which is an extension or enlarge
ment of a system which confines itself to a discussion of
causal connections (efficient or material), including the
special kind of causal connections with wh ich cybernetics
is concerned ; and that this being so, not only is it not
surprising but it is positively required, for the extension to
be successfully instituted, that finality should enjoy an
overlap with some special form of causal connection, like
that which is the stock-in-trade of cybernetics. To test the
relation between these two conceptual forms ( finality and
" cybernetical " causal connection) , it will be necessary to
see whether there is an area beyond the overlap, in which
talk about finality is no longer mappable onto talk about
Metaphysics and Value 79
caual connection; and the place where it seems to me that
it would be natural to look for this divorce to occur, if it
occurs at all, would be in the area to which attributions of
absolute value belong, and in which talk about finality
goes along with attributions of absolute value. If one then
denies, as Foot and others have done, that there is any
metaphysical region in which absolute value is a lawful
resident, one seems to be cutting oneself off, maybe not
without good reason, from j ust that testing-ground which
is needed to determine the conceptual relationship between
finality and causal connection. To this point I shall return.
As I am talking, in this lecture, about finality, I am
always referring to what I am calling detached finality,
that is, to purposes which are detached from any purposer,
purposes which can exist without there being any conscious
being who has, as his purpose, whatever the content of
those purposes may be. Now there are some distinctions in
relation to finality which I want to make. First, it may be
either an essential property of something or an accidental
property of it that it has a certain finality. My conception
of essential property is of properties which are defining
properties of a certain sort or kind and also, at one and the
same time, intimately bound up with the identity conditions
for entities which belong to that kind. [It might indeed be
taken as a criterion of a kind's being a substantial kind that
its defining properties should enter into the identity
conditions for its members.] The essential properties of a
thing are properties which that thing cannot lose without
ceasing to exist (if you like, ceasing to be identical with
itself).
It is clear that the essential properties of a sort are not to
be identified with the necessary properties of that sort, the
properties which things of that sort must have; for those
properties whose presence is guaranteed by logical or
metaphysical necessity, given the presence of the essential
properties, would not thereby be constituted as essential
properties of the sort, that is, as properties which are
80 The Carus Lectures
constitutive of the sort. Moreover, attention to the words
of Terry Irwin and Alan Code leads me to suspect that in
the case of sorts of living things, properties which are
essential to a sort might not be invariably present in
instances of the sort, and so might fail to be necessary
properties of that sort. This possibility, if it is realized,
would arise from the fact that membership in a vital sort
may be conferred not (or not merely) by character but by
ancestry ; so a freakish or degenerate instance of such a sort
might even lack some essential feature of the sort, provided
that its parents or suitably proximate ancestors exhibited
that feature.
The link between the two strands in the idea of essential
property, that of being definitive of a kind and that of
constituting an identity condition for members of that
kind, becomes eminently intelligible if one takes Aristotle's
view that to exist and to be a member of a certain kind are
one and the same thing (with appropriate consequences
about the multiplicity contained within the notion of
being) . Now my idea, and I think also the idea of Aristotle,
is that the range of essential properties of this or that kind
of thing would sometimes, or perhaps even always, include
what I might call finality properties, that is, properties
which consist in the possession of a certain detached
finality.
A second distinction which I want to make is between
active and passive finality, a distinction between what it is
that, as it were, certain things are supposed to do, and (on
the other hand) what it is that certain things are supposed
to suffer, have done to them, have done with them, and
such-like, including particularly uses to which they are
supposed to be put. One might, as a bit of j argon, label the
active kind of finality property as metiers or roles. It would
of course be possible, within the area of active finality, to
allow for different versions of activity : the activity of a
tiger, for example, while legitimately so-called, might be,
as one would be inclined to say, activity in a different
Metaphysics and Value 81
M E T A P HY S I C S , P HI L O S O P H I C A L P S Y C H O L O G Y ,
A N D VA L U E
Preamble
3 This topic will be touched upon somewhat more fully in Section VIII.
1 28 American Philosophical Association
Ramsified naming: 'There is j ust one J and j ust one V such
that L, and let J be called " judging" and V be called
"willing " . ' On this alternative, the uniqueness claim is
essential, since "judging" and "willing" are being assigned
as names for particular instantiables. The second altern
ative, which I may call the way of Ramsified definition,
can dispense with the uniqueness claim. It will run : ' (a) x
judges just in case there is a J and there is a V such that L,
and x instantiates ]; ( b) x wills j ust in case there is a J and
there is a V such that L, and x instantiates V. '
We now have available a possible explanation of the
ambivalence we may feel with regard to the status of
certain psychological principles, which was the subject of
Problem B . The difference between the two alternative
procedures is relatively subtle, and if we do not distinguish
them we may find ourselves under the pull of both. But the
first alternative will render certain psychological principles
contingent, while the second will render the same principles
non-contingent. Let me illustrate by using an even simpler
and even less realistic example. Suppose that a psycho
logical law tells us that anyone in state P hollers, and that
we seek to use this law to introduce the term "pain " . On
the first alternative, we have : there is just one P, such that
anyone in state P hollers, and let us call P "pain " . Since on
this alternative we are naming the state P "pain " , if the
utilized law is contingent, so will be the principle 'anyone
who is in pain hollers. ' If we use the second alternative, we
shall introduce "pain " as follows : x is in pain j ust in case
there is a P such that anyone in state P hollers and x is in
state P. On this alternative it will be non-contingently true
that anyone who is in pain hollers. (For to be in pain is to
be in some state which involves hollering.) While this
suggestion may account for the ambivalence noted, it does
not of course resolve it; to resolve it, one would have to
find a reason for preferring one of the alternatives to the
other.
In a somewhat devious pursuit of such a reason, let us
Method in Philosophical Psychology 1 29
enquire further about the character of the postulated
psychological instantiables-are they, or could they be,
identifiable with physical (physiological) instantiables ?
One possible position of a sort which has been found
attractive by some slightly impetuous physicalists would
be to adopt the first alternative (that of Ramsified naming)
and to combine it with the thesis that the J-instantiable is
to be identified with one physiological property and the V
instantiable with another such property. This position at
least appears to have the feature, to which some might
strongly object, of propounding a seemingly philosophical
thesis which is at the mercy of possible developments in
physiology; and, one might add, the prospects that such
developments would be favourable to the thesis do not
seem to be all that bright. The adaptiveness of organisms
may well be such as to make it very much in the cards that
different creatures of the same species may, under different
environmental pressures, develop different sub-systems
(even different sub-systems at different times) as the
physiological underlay of the same set of psychological
instantiables, and that a given physiological property may
be the correlate in one sub-system of a p articular psycho
logical instantiable, while in another it is correlated with a
different psychological instantiable, or with none at all.
Such a possibility would mean that a physiological
property which was, for a particular creature at a
particular time, correlated with a particular psychological
instantiable would be neither a necessary nor a sufficient
condition for that instantiable; it would at best be
sufficient (and perhaps also necessary) for the instantiable
within the particular kind of sub-system prevailing in the
creature at the time. The unqualified identification of the
property and the instantiable would now be excluded.
Faced with such a difficulty, a physicalist might resort to
various manoeuvres. He might seek to identify a particular
psychological instantiable with a disjunctive property,
each disjoined constituent of which is a property consisting
130 American Philosophical Association
in having a certain physiological property in a certain kind
of sub-system ; or he might relativize the notion of identity,
for the purpose of psycho-physical identification, to types
of sub-systems ; or he might abandon the pursuit of
identification at the level of instantiables, and restrict
himself to claiming identities between individual psycho
logical events or states of affairs (e.g. ]ones's believing at t
that p) and physiological events or states of affairs (e.g.
]ones's brain being in such and such a state at t) . But none
of these shifts has the intuitive appeal of their simplistic
forebear. Moreover, each will be open to variants of a
familiar kind of objection. For example, ]ones's j udging at
noon that they were out to get him might well be a case of
j udging something to be true on insufficient evidence ; but
(to use Berkeley's phrase) it 'sounds harsh' to say that
]ones's brain's being in such and such a state at noon is a
case of j udging something to be true on insufficient
evidence. For my part, I would hope that a much-needed
general theory of categories would protect me against any
thesis which would require me either to license such
locutions as the last or to resort to a never-ending stream
of cries of 'Opaque context !' in order to block them. If the
prime purpose of the notion of identity is, as I believe it to
be, to license predicate-transfers, one begins to look a little
silly if one first champions a particular kind of identifica
tion, and then constantly jibs at the predicate-transfers
which it seems to allow.
Such considerations as these can, I think, be deployed
against the way of Ramsified naming even when it is
unaccompanied by a thesis about psycho-physical identities.
However unlikely it may be that the future course of
physiological research will favour any simple correlations
between particular psychological instantiables and par
ticular physiological properties, I do not see that I have any
firm guarantee that it will not, that it will never be
established that some particular kind of brain state is
associated with, say, judging that snow is white. If so, then
Method in Philosophical Psychology 131
V. Creature Construction
4 Let me illustrate with a little fable. The ve ry e minent and very dedicated
neurophysiologist speaks to his wife. " My (for at least a little while longer)
dear, " he says, "I have long thought of myself as an acute and well-informed
interpreter of your actions and behaviour . I think I have been able to
identify nearly every thought that has made you smile and nearly every
desire that has moved you to act. My researches, however, have made such
progress that I shall no longer need to understand you in this way. Instead I
shall be in a position, with the aid of instruments which I shall attach to you,
to assign to each bodily movement which you make in acting a specific
antecedent condition in your cortex. No longer shall I need to concern
myself with your so-called thoughts and feelings. In the meantime, perhaps
you would have dinner with me tonight. I trust that you will not resist if I
bring along some apparatus to help me to determine, as quickly as possible,
the physiological idiosyncracies which obtain in your system. "
I have a feeling that the lady might refuse the proffered invitation.
5 I am indebted to George Myro for the tenor of this remark, as well as
for valuable help with the su bstance of this section.
Index