Garver On Silence Wittgenstein
Garver On Silence Wittgenstein
Garver On Silence Wittgenstein
1.
Introduction
1. Wittgensteins early masterpiece, Tractatus Logico-philosophicus, culminated in silence. The relentless steps of the search for clarity and meaning
leads to the famous pronouncement of silence in the final sentence, Wovon
man nicht sprechen kann, darber muss man schweigen. Because Wittgenstein returned to philosophy some ten years later and worked persistently at
philosophy for more than two decades until the end of his life, the question
arises whether his return to philosophical work defied his earlier conclusion
or had the effect of canceling it. His later philosophy continued his pursuit
for clarity and meaning, but was dominated by what he called grammar
rather than by logic. In view of this revision in the fundamental tools of his
work, a useful specific form of the issue is whether making grammatical
remarks, as Wittgenstein did in his later work of clarification, is a continuation or a rejection of the silence that his early work had led him into.
The plan of my paper is simple. I will first consider what is included
and what is not included in the key terms silence and grammar as Wittgenstein used them, and then argue that restricting philosophy to grammar
was a way of continuing the silence with which Wittgenstein so dramatically concluded the Tractatus. I will conclude with some reservations about
adopting Wittgenstein as a role-model in this respect.
2.
Silence
8
versial, amply supported by the remarks immediately preceding the proclamation of silence:
The correct method in philosophy would be the following: to
say nothing except what can be said, i.e., propositions of natural
science i.e., something that has nothing to do with philosophy
and then, whenever someone else wanted to say something
metaphysical, to demonstrate to him that he had failed to give
meaning to certain signs in his propositions. Although it would
not be satisfying to the other person he would not have the
feeling that we were teaching him philosophy this method
would be the only strictly correct one.
My propositions serve as elucidations in the following way:
anyone who understands me eventually recognizes them as nonsensical, when he has used them as steps to climb beyond
them. (He must, so to speak, throw away the ladder after he has
climbed up it.)
He must transcend these propositions, and then he will see the
world aright. (TLP 6.53-6.54)
3. Wittgenstein does not make such a clear distinction between philosophical doctrine and philosophical clarification as he does between philosophy
and science. Is there such a distinction? The passage just cited (TLP 6.536.54) suggests it. In response to a metaphysical claim, I am urged to demonstrate to the speaker that he has failed to assign meanings to some of his
terms. Doing this seems to be both pointing out a kind of fact (though perhaps not a kind of fact that Wittgenstein recognizes in the Tractatus) and a
part of the work of clarification.
In the central section of TLP (cited in Note 1) Wittgenstein says that
philosophy is not a doctrine but an activity. What he says in 6.53-6-54 fits
with this earlier description of philosophy. His wording, however, slides
rather mischievously over the fact that this activity involves using words. It
is true that the words are not used to state doctrines, and therefore they do
not involve the sort of nonsense that Wittgenstein mainly objected to. The
words used in the work of clarification have sense in so far as they state
facts. But that a word has or does not have a meaning is not a matter of fact
in TLP; it is something that can be shown but not said. On the other hand, it
is difficult to conceive how the work of clarification can be pursued in
9
silence. So it is difficult to escape the conclusion that the work of clarification is neither something to be spoken of nor something to be consigned to
silence.
The distinction between philosophical doctrine and philosophical activity seems useful in this connection. Wittgenstein seems content to continue
the work of clarification but insists that we cease formulating theories and
doctrines about it.
4. The sanction for violating the silence for attempting to speak about
what we cannot speak about is to utter nonsense, that is, to utter words
and sentences that fail to make sense. Uttering words that make no sense
amounts to not really saying anything. Not saying anything is itself the
same as remaining silent. Here Wittgenstein is playing with us, for in the
ordinary sense of the words, speaking nonsense is quite different from
remaining silent, even though it is not really saying anything politicians
do it everyday. So what looks as though it might be a syllogism, is an
invalid argument, unless we grant Wittgenstein his special meanings for
saying and silence.
Granting the special meanings of saying and silence, the conclusion
of the Tractatus is less a moral injunction than a logical necessity. That my
words fail to make sense when I attempt to speak about what we cannot
speak about is a logical consequence rather than a moral duty. The must in
the final sentence is a logical rather than a moral must, in spite of the mystical tone and undeniable ambiguity of these words.2
5. It is useful to think of TLP 7 as a platitude or tautology, that is, as nothing
more than a logical truth. The first implication of this reading is that the
work of a philosopher will have no more relevance to matters of life and
death than do modus ponens, modus tollens, and the principles of syllogistic
inference. It is by recognizing and accepting these limits that philosophy
becomes possible at all. This aspect of the Tractatus seems not only to flesh
out but also to revise radically Wittgensteins pre-war remark that Philosophy consists of logic and metaphysics: logic is its basis. (NB 106) What
happened between the Notes on Logic of 1913 and the completion of the
Tractatus is that Wittgenstein came to realize that logic, being senseless,
cannot be the basis for anything, so that any metaphysics presumed to be
based on it must be nonsense.
10
6. The mysticism of the Tractatus is palpable and inescapable. It seems
clear enough in his remark about seeing the world aright (TLP 6.54) but is
more explicit in TLP 6.522: There are, indeed, things that cannot be put
into words. They make themselves manifest. They are what is mystical.
7. There is a powerful tension, but no contradiction, between the logical
analysis and mysticism in the Tractatus. There is, after all, even an element
of the mystical in logic. Logic is not a science, the so-called proofs in logic
are really psychological aids, and we can really only show, not say why (not
even say that), a proposition is a logical truth. Whereas in the scientific philosophy of Russell and the Vienna circle logic serves as a tool for combating mysticism, in TLP logic and mysticism reinforce one another.
Wittgenstein thought the quest of philosophy was for clarification rather
than for knowledge. His yoking together logical tautologies and moral principles, in that they both lack sense, suggests that he thought of the clarification provided by logic as closely identified with the clarification required
by moral integrity, and hence that logical confusion was not only a sin but
the most significant sort of sin.3 This is not a common perspective on either
logic or morals, so it is no wonder that it disconcerted Russell. Being a philosopher meant adopting an unusual stance towards the world, assigning
facts to scientists and morals to moralists, while as a philosopher remaining
silent about both what is the case and what to do.
8. So Tractarian silence is both a logical truth and a moral commitment. It
does not mean an absence of verbal utterances but rather abstention from
truth-claims in domains other than the natural sciences. It is based on the
insight that logic is not a science4 as well as on a deep understanding of
how logical analysis leads to the clarification of the sense of propositions.
3.
Grammar
9. Near the beginning of his second career, Wittgenstein wrote (CV 9) that
his goal was clarity as an end in itself Klarheit als Selbstzweck5 and he
proceeded to lay out over the years a conception of clarity radically different from the conception of analytic clarity developed in the Tractatus.
11
10. Being interested in clarity as an end in itself entails being disinterested
(as a philosopher) in scientific and moral truth. Thus, as is well known, he
steered clear of metaphysics and rational ethics (whether Kantian or consequentialist). Wittgenstein did make allowance in his work for certain factual
truths that he came to regard as part of grammar. In Grammatical Remarks
and Philosophical Investigations these truths were primarily remarks about
language-games, and since mastering the use of a language is a feature of
our complicated form of life, they also included remarks on the natural history of human beings (PI 25, 129). In On Certainty the range of allowances was broadened to include both the expressions that Moore thought he
knew for certain and analogous platitudes, such as that his name is Ludwig
Wittgenstein and that he has spent his whole life on or near the surface of
the earth. With respect to metaphysical and moral truth, however, he made
no such allowance. The distinction between seeking clarification and seeking knowledge, prominent in the Tractatus, is thus retained with emphasis
in his later work.
In his later work he adopts a radically different conception of clarification (based on grammar and uses of language), a significantly different conception of science (based on knowledge and method rather than on the
totality of factual truth), and a different conception of knowledge (excluding certainty but including theories and explanations). The new approach
also features sharp distinctions between knowledge (which invites doubt)
and certainty (which excludes doubt) and between science (which involves
testing, explanation, and progress) and natural history (which is limited to
description of plain facts).
It is difficult to hold all these conceptions and distinctions together in a
coherent picture, and therefore no wonder that Wittgenstein crisscrossed the
same territory again and again from different directions.
11. The conception of clarity that Wittgenstein developed in his later work
was never made fully explicit, more often being shown than articulated. I
will therefore try to highlight some of its prominent aspects.
12. One important aspect is that it is contextual rather than analytic.6 Clarity
is rarely to be achieved by analyzing a complex into its constitutive elements and their distinctive arrangement. Reliance on context rather than
analysis is shown most emphatically by Wittgensteins repeated focus on
the use or uses of words and sentences.
12
13. There are different sorts of use. Wittgenstein uses five German words
that are translated as use in English versions: Gebrauch, Nutzen, Benutzung, Verwendung, Anwendung. In some instances the reference is to quite
general usage (Gebrauch in der Sprache) and in others to the employment
(Anwendung) of a word or sentence in specific circumstances. In every
case, however, there is at least implicit reference to some context or other,
rather than to analysis, for the work of clarifying meaning.
Wittgenstein begins his discussion with the most general, not with the
most specific. His focus is on whole expressions; if these expressions are
individual words, they stand alone as expressions rather than as elements in
sentences.
14. The early sections of Philosophical Investigations culminate in 23:
How many kinds of sentences are there? Perhaps assertions,
questions, and commands? There are countless kinds: countless different kinds of use of all that we call signs, words,
sentences. And this multiplicity is not something fixed, something given once and for all; rather new types of speech, new
language-games, as we may say, come into existence and others
wither away and are forgotten. (We can get a rough picture of
this from the changes in mathematics.)
The word language-game is meant to bring into prominence
that speaking a language is part of an activity, or of a form of
life. . . . .
It is interesting to compare the multiplicity of the tools of language and the ways of their being used, the multiplicity of kinds
of words and sentences, with what logicians have said about the
construction of language. (Including the author of the Tractatus
Logico-philosophicus.)
15. Here we see a focus on what we might call complete expressions, ones
that stand alone as everyday utterances. They are different kinds of sentences, different uses of language, and their differences from one another
are basic in the sense that they are not to be understood through analysis of
their components. They are not ultimate wholes, about which nothing further can be said, but taking these wholes rather than their parts as basic constitutes a radical break with the mainstream of analytic philosophy.7
13
16. The focus on language-games, that is, on uses of language, is evident
from the manner in which Wittgenstein begins the Investigations and is
confirmed in later texts. At PI 656 he writes, Look on the language-game
as the primary thing. In Part II (p. 226) he makes the intriguing observation, What has to be accepted, the given, is so one could say forms of
life. This observations contrasts with usual conceptions of the given,
which understand the given to be particulars or universals rather than anything so broad and undefined as forms of any kind.8
It is useful to conceive our human form of life, comprising as it does the
mastery of the use of a language, as the large vague context within which
the various language-games make sense. That large vague context makes
possible an amazing range of human understanding. As Wittgenstein says
(PI 206): The common behavior of mankind is the system of reference by
means of which we interpret an unknown language.
17. It is difficult to see the distinctions among these uses of language, these
language-games, as constituting a part of grammar.9 It is not grammar in the
most common sense, since that consists of morphology and syntax. To
understand him, therefore, we must see how his grammar differs from morphology and syntax.
18. The Swiss linguist Ferdinand de Saussure made a distinction that can
help us. It is characteristic of morphology and syntax that they have to do
with langue rather than parole, in the terminology of Saussure. That is to
say, they concern the structure of language isolated from its use. Since language-games concern context and use rather than structure, they do not
seem to be a matter of grammar in the common sense. That is one aspect of
the difficulty.
Phonology, however, is also part of the general description of a language, and one branch of phonology, phonemics, focuses on parole rather
than langue.10 Wittgensteins insistence on distinctions among languagegames as fundamental to his work of clarification also involves primarily
parole rather than langue. If we can see Wittgensteins work as having features in common with phonemics, it will be easier to see that it is a form of
grammar.
19. Identification of elements of parole requires methods different from the
primarily analytic methods of morphology and syntax. Two methods used
14
in phonemics to replace analytic definitions are contrast and distinctive feature analysis. Both these methods, which are not entirely independent, are
prominent in Wittgensteins later work.
The contrasts that matter in phonemics are not ones that could be made
but ones that actually are recognized by speakers of the language in question. In English, for example, the phoneme /p/ is contrasted with /b/, and we
recognize the difference between pet and bet and between sup and
sub, as well as that between limper and limber, even when they are
pronounced as isolated words rather than in context. In Arabic, on the other
hand, this distinction is not phonemic, and the Arabic phoneme /be/ sounds
sometimes like the one and sometimes like the other, so that Pepsi is
likely to come out as Bepsi. Similarly, we do not notice that our phoneme
/p/ is phonetically different in different contexts: its two occurrences in
pop and its still different occurrence in spot are phonetically distinguishable and would likely be heard as different sounds in some Turkic languages.
What matters in this method is contrasts that are in fact significant in a
given language rather than ones that could be significant. This focus on fact
rather than possibility as primary is congenial with a strain in Wittgensteins
thought that is evident at the beginning of the Tractatus and continues
throughout his work.
20. Wittgenstein once emphasized the importance of contrast by saying that
he could use the line Ill teach you differences! (from King Lear) as a
motto for his work. He made this remark in the context of commenting on
the difference between Hegel and himself: Hegel seems to me to be always
wanting to say that things which look different are really the same. Whereas
my interest is in showing that things which look the same are really different.11 It is obvious contrasts that he refers to in PI 23; and again in
PI 78:
Compare knowing and saying:
how many feet high Mont Blanc is
how the words game is used
how a clarinet sounds
If you are surprised that one can know something and not be
able to say it, you are perhaps thinking of a case like the first.
Certainly not of one like the third.
15
Note that here, as elsewhere, Wittgenstein not only presents the extreme
contrast between the first and third examples but also provides an intermediary case.
21. Sometimes Wittgenstein refers to distinctive features in order to make a
contrast obvious. In distinguishing expressions of emotion from expressions of sensation, for example, he notes that although a pain might last
only five minutes, one could not say that same thing about grief.12 In this
case the distinctive feature concerns what might be said next, as well as
what is characteristic of emotions as contrasted with sensations. Possibilities of discourse continuation, and recognition that in some contexts a certain continuation is nonsense, are distinctive features of the grammar of language-games. I christen this ship the Mary Belle is a declarative sentence,
but the response I doubt that would be nonsense in the normal circumstances of its use a distinctive feature that shows that this declarative sentence is not a truth-claim.
Distinctive features help in recognizing and remembering contrasts.
22. Wittgensteins grammar thus differs from traditional grammar by
extending the study of language from langue into parole and by focusing on
context and use rather than on structure and analysis. Contrasting various
kinds of utterances and inscriptions through distinguishing the different circumstances of their use and their different possibilities for discourse continuation is indeed part of a general description of language, and hence a part
of grammar in the most general sense. Wittgenstein makes use of methods
of grammar, especially methods of phonemics, but he applies them where
grammarians and linguists have not commonly done so. Grammar lessons
are perhaps normally somewhat therapeutic, and this is emphatically true
for Wittgenstein, but modern linguistics aims at science rather than therapy.
Although the confusions upon which Wittgenstein hopes to work his therapy of clarification are grammatical confusions embedded in the use of language, his remarks are philosophical rather than linguistic.
23. Wittgensteins later work makes use of grammar rather than logic, and
context rather than analysis, in order to pursue his work of clarification.13
Grammar cannot be foundational in any sense. It is necessarily secondary
rather than primary, since it depends on the prior existence of the language
it describes. Nor can it lay the groundwork for wisdom about either the
16
physical world or our human world, since its subject-matter is language
rather than the world or our behavior in it. In these respects Wittgensteins
later work of clarification is a refinement of the silence of the Tractatus.
Just as the silence was a logical conclusion rather than a moral exhortation, so also the remark that grammar is necessarily secondary, and hence
philosophy can never be foundational, is a grammatical rather than a metaphysical or epistemological or moral observation. It is not that one ought
not to lay philosophical foundations, but simply that if you are laying foundations you are, willy-nilly, playing some other game than that of philosophy.
4.
24. The silence with which the Tractatus concludes is not broken in Philosophical Investigations, nor in other later work. The silence consists in
focusing on the work of clarification and refusing all temptations to contribute to quests for knowledge or for causal or moral judgments or explanations.
Wittgenstein was adamantly opposed to the spirit of his times, that is,
our times. He conceived our times as centered on progress and growth (CV
9) and dissociated himself and his work from moralism, scientism, and
problem solving (CV 5-10 passim). He chided Renan for apparently supposing that science might enhance wonderment (CV 7) and certain architects for succumbing to temptations (CV5); and for those who think they
have discovered solutions to problems of life, his contribution will be to
show them how to see that they are wrong (CV 6). For philosophers the recommended asceticism consists in eschewing explanations, deductions, and
theses, and limiting our work to assembling reminders and presenting
descriptions of what is open to view before all new discoveries and inventions (PI 126-128).
Since modern philosophy has focused on explanations, deductions, and
overall solutions, Wittgensteins stance on these matters is rightly seen as
an effort to silence academic philosophers. Basing his work either on tautologies (TLP) or on grammar (PI) is a dramatic alternative and a rebuke to
the search for certain knowledge characteristic of modern philosophy. This
rebuke is a main feature of Wittgensteinian silence.
17
25. It is no surprise that few philosophers have accepted this rebuke without
protest. To review the varieties of objections to Wittgensteins philosophy is
out of the question here, but it will be useful to take note of one rather
friendly objection. Arnulf Zweig rebukes Wittgenstein for remaining silent
about the Holocaust (Zweig 1997). Zweig makes this criticism not as a hostile critic but as an anguished friend. Others have pointed out that there are
criticisms of Hitler and other moral judgments in Wittgensteins notebooks
and correspondence, and perhaps Zweig exaggerates. Nevertheless he has a
point, and others concur that Wittgensteins philosophy, and in particular
his steadfast adherence to a search for clarity rather than for truth and justice, is unacceptably remote from the urgent problems of real lives.
This anguished criticism is cogent, but I hesitate to agree that it implies
moral failure on the part of Wittgenstein. The silence might better be seen
as philosophical integrity than as moral failure. Wittgensteins mission was
to work in philosophy, as an artist, and if he succumbed to the temptation of
also (or thereby) being a moral beacon, he would be in the same position as
the poor architects mentioned above (CV 5).
26. Clarity as an end in itself is something like the Holy Grail, radically
removed from the problems of daily life and providing an almost impossible ideal. It is absolute, and not in any way conditional. This is in conformity with what Wittgenstein took to be the nature of philosophy (and logic).
In continuing to pursue this ideal, Wittgenstein seems to have continued to
see obscurity as a sin. His commitment to his work of clarification has an
unmistakable religious dimension, a continuation of the mystical/prophetic
dimension McGuinness identified in the Tractatus.14 When Wittgenstein
remarked that he could not help approaching every problem from a religious point of view,15 he may well have been referring to this persistent
dimension of his work.
27. As much as I admire Wittgenstein, as clearly as I see his later work as
both continuing and revising the earlier work in its search for absolute
unconditioned clarity, as certain I am that sound philosophy seeks clarification rather than knowledge, and in spite of the power and consistency of his
continued Tractarian silence, I do not feel easy about joining Wittgenstein
in either the absolutism of his commitment or the abstinence from moral
and political comment.
18
In my book Wittgenstein & Approaches to Clarity one main theme is
that in the course of my own work in philosophy I have always sought clarification for some other purpose, not as an end in itself. Those other purposes generally take the form of exegesis, advocacy, or criticism, for all of
which rigorous clarity separates a thoughtful philosophical approach from a
more passionate one. Perhaps all of this work of mine is applied philosophy,
rather than philosophy proper. Nonetheless it remains heavily indebted to
Wittgenstein, and in particular to his focus on language-games.
28. Wittgenstein writes, There is only logical necessity. I take that to be a
logical or grammatical remark, grounded on the insight that genuine necessity is unconditioned in a way that only logic is unconditioned. If I echo this
remark of Wittgensteins in the face of necessities asserted every day by
politicians and moralists, is my utterance still a logical remark? or has it
become preaching? or political commentary? That query is, in his terms, a
grammatical question, on which he offers little guidance except perhaps
through the example of his persistent refusal to engage moralists and politicians, an example which I find breath-taking, but which, like Zweig and
Russell, I do not find edifying. Nor does it seem required of a philosopher,
unless a philosopher must have a singular public identity (such as Wittgenstein seems to have allowed himself16) and so cannot also publicly be a citizen or an essayist.
There seems no final answer to the questions of grammar and silence,
any more than there is a final solution to the problems of life.
References
Garver, Newton. 1994. This Complicated Form of Life: Essays on Wittgenstein. Chicago: Open Court
2006. Wittgenstein & Approaches to Clarity. Amherst NY: Humanity
Books.
Harris, Roy. 1988. Language, Saussure and Wittgenstein: How to Play
Games With Words. London: Routledge.
Kross, Matthias. 1993. Klarheit als Selbstzweck: Wittgenstein ber Philosophie, Religion, Ethik, und Gewissheit. Berlin: Akademie Verlag.
Malcolm, Norman. 1994. Wittgenstein, A Religious Point of View? Edited
with a response by Peter Winch. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
19
McGuinness, Brian. 1988. Wittgenstein: A Life-Young Ludwig, 1889-1921.
London: Duckworth. Republished as Young Ludwig: Wittgensteins Life,
1889-1921, London/New York: Oxford University Press 2005.
2002. Approaches to Wittgenstein: Collected Papers. New York: Routledge.
Pike, Kenneth. 1947. Phonemics: A Technique for Reducing Language to
Writing. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.
Rhees, Rush, ed. 1981. Ludwig Wittgenstein: Personal Recollections.
Totowa NJ: Rowman and Littlefield.
Shields, Philip R. 1993. Logic and Sin in the Writings of Ludwig Wittgenstein. Chicago/London: University of Chicago Press.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1961. Tractatus Logico-philosophicus. Translated by
David Pears and Brian McGuinness. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
(= TLP)
1968. Philosophical Investigations, Third edition. Edited and Translated
by G. E. M. Anscombe. Oxford: Blackwell. (= PI)
1969. On Certainty. Edited by G.H. von Wright and G.E.M. Anscombe.
Translated by Denis Paul and G.E.M. Anscombe. New York: Harper &
Row. (= OC)
1979. Notebooks 1914-1916. Second edition. Edited by G.H. von Wright
and G.E.M. Anscombe. Translated by G.E.M. Anscombe. Oxford:
Blackwell. (= NB)
1998. Culture and Value. Second edition. Edited by Georg Henrik von
Wright in collaboration with Heikki Nyman. Revised Edition of the
Text by Alois Pichler. Translated by Peter Winch. Cambridge, MA:
Blackwell. (= CV)
1993. Philosophical Occasions, 1912-1951. Edited by James Klagge and
Alfred Nordmann. Indianapolis: Hacket. (= PO)
Wolgast, Elizabeth. 2004. A Religious Point of View. Philosophical
Investigations 27:2 (April).
Zweig, Arnulf. 1997. Wittgensteins Silence; in Current Issues in Political Philosophy: Justice and Welfare in Society and World Order, Proceedings of the 19th International Wittgenstein Symposium. Vienna:
Hlder-Pichler-Tempsky.
20
Notes
1.
See TLP 4.11: The totality of true propositions is the whole of natural science (or the
whole corpus of the natural sciences. The distinction between science and philosophy is
presented in the following sections, 4.111-4.112. The key points are: Philosophy aims at
the logical clarification of thoughts. / Philosophy is not a body of doctrine but an activity.
/ A philosophic work consists essentially of elucidations. / Philosophy does not result in
philosophical propositions but rather in the clarification of propositions. [My slashes
represent new paragraphs in Wittgensteins text.]
There are problems with Wittgensteins way of making the distinction between science
and philosophy (e.g., whether theoretical statements can have sense on his terms), and
even issues (raised by Quine among others) whether any such distinction can be made.
These are interesting issues and might usefully be discussed on another occasion. For my
present purposes what matters is that Wittgenstein insisted on such a distinction in TLP,
and in his later work held to there being a dichotomy, though he expressed it rather
differently. See PI 109: It was true to say that our considerations could not be scientific
ones and OC 308: Knowledge and certainty belong to different categories.
2.
So Wittgensteins apparent injunction to silence is a logical rather than a moral point, and
therefore not an injunction at all. This comment depends on distinguishing logic from
morals, and logical necessity from moral necessity, seemingly obvious distinctions that
Wittgenstein may not have accepted at the time. The final pages of the Tractatus (from
about 6.37 on) are full of cryptic and apparently edifying remarks that seem intended to
give a perspective on life, what we naturally consider a Weltanschauung. This powerful
rhetoric is integral to the power and mystique of the Tractatus and depends in part on not
distinguishing logic from morals, as well as not distinguishing morals from religion.
3.
4.
See TLP 4.0312, where Wittgenstein characterizes this point as his fundamental idea.
There is a useful discussion of this as the fundamental idea of Wittgensteins early work in
McGuinness 2002, chapter 10.
5.
Matthias Kross used this pregnant phrase as the title of his Habilitationsschrift (Kross
1993), which discusses these matters in depth. Wittgensteins own phrase is slightly but
insignificantly different: Mir dagegen ist die Klarheit die Durchsichtigkeit Selbstzweck.
6.
For further discussion of this point see Garver 2006, chapter 10.
7.
But not necessarily with the Tractatus itself, where a name has meaning only in the context of a proposition (TLP 3.3).
8.
It is not clear what Wittgenstein means by forms of life. I believe the term is
intentionally vague and incapable of definition see Garver 2006, chapters 10-12. It is
nearly certain that he did not always mean language-games see my discussion in chapter
15 of Garver 1994. With regard to the present text, there is an alternative wording in
Wittgensteins notebooks, with forms of life [Lebensformen] replaced by facts of
living [Tatsachen des Lebens], which makes it more likely that he meant to refer at least
in part to language-games in this text. He certainly did think of language-games as facts of
the natural history of human beings (see PI 25, 415, 654-656, page 174c).
21
9.
Moore, for example, did not understand it. See PO, 69: I still think he was not using the
expression rules of grammar in any ordinary sense, and I am still unable to form any
clear idea as to how he was using it. On the same page Moore reports Wittgenstein as
having said that he was making things belong to grammar that are not commonly
supposed to belong to it.
10. The work of Ferdinand de Saussure (see Saussure 1959) made it possible to describe
phonemes and to distinguish phonemics from phonetics, the latter but not the former
being amenable to methods of physics. For a more practical and more readable account of
phonemics, see Pike 1947, and for a good discussion of parallels between Saussure and
Wittgenstein, see Harris 1988. I know of no reason to think that Wittgenstein had any
familiarity with the work of Saussure or other modern linguists. Parallels between his
work and that of linguists are fascinating as well as instructive, but they should not be
carried too far. Linguistics is a science, a quest for knowledge, and Wittgenstein held
himself aloof from every science, every quest for knowledge.
11. The remarks are reported by Maurice Drury (Rhees 1981, 171).
12. See, for example, PI page 174.
13. For a more extended discussion of philosophy as grammar, see chapter 13 of Garver 2006.
14. See McGuinness 1988, chapter 9.
15. He is quoted as having made this remark by Maurice Drury (Rhees 1981, 94). Malcolm
discusses it in his last work (Malcolm 1994), which includes comments by Peter Winch.
See also the comments by Elizabeth Wolgast in Wolgast 2004 and my comments in
chapter 14 of Garver 2006.
16. One might construe Zweigs criticism as lodging the complaint that Wittgenstein,
although identifying himself as Jewish, did so only privately; that is, that his singular
public identity as a philosopher evaded publicly identified himself as a Jew, which would
have obliged him to speak out about the Holocaust.