Wittgenstein's Tractatus: True Thoughts and Nonsensical Propositions
Wittgenstein's Tractatus: True Thoughts and Nonsensical Propositions
Wittgenstein's Tractatus: True Thoughts and Nonsensical Propositions
ISSN 0190-0536
© Blackwell Publishing Ltd. 2003, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA
02148, USA.
Andrew Lugg 333
suspect since Wittgenstein was not at all reluctant to brand his propo-
sitions as nonsensical and was unwavering in his opposition to think-
ing of philosophy as a body of doctrine. The second is problematic
because he did not hesitate a decade or so later, when he returned
to philosophy, to criticize and reformulate what he had said in the
Tractatus.3
Nor is it easy to rest content with the suggestion that Wittgen-
stein took himself to be expressing ineffable truths by means of non-
sensical propositions.4 This way of understanding the remarks of
the Tractatus harmonizes with the supremely confident tone of the
Preface and the uncompromising character of the declaration at 6.54
as well as with Wittgenstein’s recognition of ‘things that cannot be
put into words’, things that ‘make themselves manifest’ (6.522). But it
has the disadvantage of attributing to him the dubious conception
of important nonsense, a conception he does not invoke (indeed he
never speaks of nonsense as conveying truths or as being important).5
Worse still, there is the awkward fact that in his Preface Wittgen-
stein not only speaks of ‘the truth of the thoughts that are here set
forth’, he twice avers that thoughts are ‘expressed [ausgedrückt]’ in the
book.
The difficulties besetting these approaches can doubtless be eased
to a certain extent. There is little likelihood, however, that they can
6. Though now rarely stressed, this aspect of Wittgenstein’s thinking did not escape
his contemporaries’ notice. See, e.g., the letters quoted in the editor’s introduction
to B. Russell, The Collected Papers of Bertrand Russell, volume 6, ed. J.G. Slater (London:
Routledge, 1992), pp. xxvii, xxxi and xxxvii, and R. Carnap, ‘Intellectual Autobiog-
raphy’, in P.A. Schilpp (ed.), The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap (La Salle: Open Court,
1963), p. 25.
7. For the shift in the use of the word ‘tautology’ prompted by the Tractatus see B.
Dreben and J. Floyd, ‘Tautology: How Not To Use A Word’, Synthese 87 (1991),
23–49. Interestingly the old sense of tautology is still often invoked. See, e.g., W.V.
Quine, The Pursuit of Truth, revised edition (Cambridge: Harvard University Press,
1992), p. 55, where Quine avails himself of ‘the intuitive notion of tautology, the
notion that comes into play when we protest that someone’s assertion comes down
to “0 = 0” and is an empty matter of words’.
8. Also see H.O. Mounce, Wittgenstein’s Tractatus (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1981), p. 102: ‘[T]he propositions of the Tractatus are not tautologies but they
belong to roughly the same category’. On my view Wittgenstein’s ‘propositions’ are
tautologies – and were regarded as such by him. They are genuine thoughts; they
are not out-and-out gibberish with ‘an appearance of sense’ (p. 104).
9. Wittgenstein was well aware that the tautologous character of his remarks is not
so easily recognized as the tautologous character of ‘If A then A’. He writes in the
Preface: ‘Perhaps this book will only be understood by someone who has himself
had the thoughts that are expressed in it’, and later observed that ‘every sentence in
the Tractatus should be seen as the heading of a chapter, needing further exposition’.
M. Drury, ‘Conversations with Wittgenstein’, in R. Rhees (ed.), Recollections of
Wittgenstein (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1984), p. 159.
10 L. Wittgenstein, Notebooks 1914–1916, trans. G.E.M. Anscombe, 2nd edition
(Oxford: Blackwell, 1979), p. 86 (entry for 20 October 1916): ‘Aesthetically, the
miracle is that the world exists. That there is what there is’.
11 Ibid., p. 18 (entry for 24 October 1914). It is no objection that ‘was der Fall ist’
introduces the non-trivial idea that the world consists of facts, not of things (compare
1.1). On the present interpretation Wittgenstein also took ‘The world is the totality
of facts’ to be tautologous and ‘The world is the totality of things’ to be contradic-
tory (i.e. unassailably and definitively false). Frege seems to have understood what
Wittgenstein was saying – though he doubtless missed the point – when he wrote
to him regarding the first few remarks of the Tractatus: ‘At the beginning I find the
expressions “to be the case” [der Fall sein] and “fact” [Tatsache] and I conjecture that
to be the case and to be a fact are the same. The world is everything that is the case
and the world is the totality of facts. Is not every fact the case, and is not that which
is the case a fact? Is it not the same when I say, Let A be a fact, as when I say, Let
A be the case? What is the point of this double expression?’. Letter dated 28 June
1919, quoted in J. Floyd, ‘The Uncaptive Eye’, in L.S. Rouner (ed.), Loneliness (Notre
Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1998), pp. 88–89. The translation is by B.
Dreben and J. Floyd. Also compare Frege’s letter of 3 April 1920 to Wittgenstein
(ibid., pp. 96–97).
12 Notebooks 1914–1916, op. cit., p. 62 (entry for 17 June 1915), and ‘Some Remarks
on Logical Form’, op. cit., p. 32.
13 Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics, op. cit., III, §33.
14 Also compare 6.35: ‘Laws like the principle of sufficient reason, etc, are about
the net and not about what the net describes’. On the interpretation being pro-
posed, the central remarks of the Tractatus are likewise about the net rather than what
it describes.
15 Also like the axioms of mechanics, the thoughts in the Tractatus are comparable
to ‘the number-system [with which] we must be able to write down any number
we wish’ (6.341). Incidentally, Wittgenstein did not hesitate to write at a time when
the main ideas of the Tractatus were already in place: ‘My whole task consists in
explaining the nature of the proposition’ (Notebooks 1914–1916, op. cit., p. 39, entry
for 21 January 1915).
21 Compare Anscombe, op. cit., p. 163: ‘[A]ttempts to say what is “shewn” produce
“non-sensical” formations of words’. Where I part company with Anscombe is over
her claim that in Wittgenstein’s eyes only logical truths ‘are . . . “tautologies” ’ and
her insistence that there is a distinction ‘in the theory of the Tractatus between logical
truths and the things that are “shewn” ’. Also see L. Wittgenstein, ‘Notes Dictated to
G.E. Moore’, Notebooks 1914–16, op. cit., p. 110: ‘Even if there were propositions of
[the] form “M is a thing” they would be superfluous (tautologous) because what this
tries to say is something which is already seen when you see “M” ’. In my view what
Wittgenstein says about the law of causality applies to his own remarks (with obvious
changes): ‘If there were a law of causality, it might be put in the following way:There
are laws of nature. But of course that cannot be said: it makes itself manifest’ (6.36).
22 Ogden renders the passage as: ‘My propositions are elucidatory in this way: he
who understands me finally recognizes them as senseless’. Also it is worth noting
that Wittgenstein accepted Ogden’s translation of ‘unsinnig’ as ‘senseless’ at 4.124 and
5.473 as well as at 6.54.
23 The reading of the Tractatus I am proposing is in some respects close to Carnap’s
view of how it ought to be read.The main difference is that Carnap saw the remarks
of the Tractatus as analytic propositions, i.e. propositions that are assertable despite
their being devoid of ‘material content [inhaltsleer]’. It is, I think, wrong to complain,
as Carnap does, that Wittgenstein failed to recognize that ‘the logic of science can
be formulated, and formulated not in senseless, if practically indispensable pseu-
dosentences, but in perfectly correct sentences’ (R. Carnap, The Logical Syntax of Lan-
guage, London, Routledge, 1937, p. 283). For more on the difference between
Carnap’s and Wittgenstein’s conception of tautologies, see B. Dreben, ‘Quine’, in
R. Barrett and R. Gibson, Perspectives on Quine (Oxford, Blackwell, 1990), especially
p. 86.
Department of Philosophy
University of Ottawa
65 University Street
PO Box 450, Stn. A
Ottawa, Ontario KIN 6NS
Canada