Conspiracy Theory after Trump
Michael Butter
Social Research: An International Quarterly, Volume 89, Number 3, Fall
2022, pp. 787-809 (Article)
Published by Johns Hopkins University Press
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1353/sor.2022.0054
For additional information about this article
https://muse.jhu.edu/article/867520
[ Access provided at 25 Oct 2022 11:14 GMT from Tuebingen Universitaetsbibliothek ]
Michael Butter
Conspiracy Theory after
Trump
the title of my article may seem premature, as american politics
is not done with Donald Trump, and Trump definitely is not done with
American politics. He may or may not manage to return to the White
House, but it is highly likely that he will try. Still, for the time being
the Trump presidency is history, and it is time to assess its effects
on American politics in general and conspiracy theory in particular.
Accordingly, the “after” in my title does not only indicate a temporal
relationship but is also meant to articulate another meaning—admittedly, long obsolete in English—which the Oxford English Dictionary
describes as “on the authority of, as stated by, according to (an author
or text)” (OED n.d.). In other words, what I am tracing is the impact
that Donald Trump has had (and of course continues to exert) on the
forms and functions of conspiracy theory in American political culture.
Specifically, I am interested in tracing a shift in the status of conspiracist knowledge within the Republican Party and parts of its electorate.
But to assess the impact of Trump we also need to understand what was
going on before he entered the scene. This is why this article begins
even before his ancestors immigrated to the United States. It ends with
a consideration of what might lie in store in the future.
CONSPIRACY THEORY BEFORE TRUMP
For a long time, it was completely ordinary to believe in conspiracy
theories (Butter 2020, 97–99). Most scholars now agree that conspiracy theories emerged during the early modern period (Zwierlein
2020). From then until the 1950s, they constituted what the sociol-
© 2022 The New School
social research Vol. 89 : No. 3 : Fall 2022 787
ogy of knowledge calls orthodox knowledge (Anton 2011, 25–31).
They were both a mainstream and an elite phenomenon, and were
produced, repeated, circulated, and believed by ordinary people as
well as by epistemic authorities in both North America and Europe.
As an integral part of public discourse, they were articulated in political speeches and pamphlets, sermons and religious treatises, newspaper articles, plays, novels, and many other forms of popular writing.
Whereas today we tend to think of conspiracy theories as counternarratives, as challenges to official, non-conspiracist versions of events,
they usually were the official versions in the past. Accordingly, they
often had significant impact on events and developments.
Here are just two examples. The Republican Party was founded in 1854 on the basis of a conspiracy theory, galvanizing activism
against slavery on moral grounds with resistance against what its
members and supporters called the “Slave Power,” that is, the influence of the most powerful slaveholders over national politics. As
Eric Foner puts it, the Slave Power conspiracy theory functioned as
“a symbol for all the fears and hostilities harbored by northerners
toward slavery and the South” (1995, 91) and united diverse groups
such as abolitionists, conscience Whigs, and renegade Democrats. Its
most famous indictment occurred in Abraham Lincoln’s 1858 “House
Divided” speech in which he suggested that Senator Stephen A. Douglas, Chief Justice Roger B. Taney, and Presidents Franklin Pierce and
James Buchanan had orchestrated all major events of the recent
past—in particular the Kansas-Nebraska Act of 1854 and the Supreme
Court’s 1857 Dred Scott decision—to further the goals of the Slave
Power (Butter 2014, 187–201). As the founding ideology of the Republican Party, the Slave Power conspiracy theory was an important
cause of the Civil War. It enabled Lincoln to win the 1860 presidential
election, which led to the secession of the slave states, which, in turn,
resulted in the outbreak of hostilities.
A century later, the fear of a communist conspiracy masterminded in Moscow pervaded American society. In popular memory
the Red Scare is nowadays often reduced to the rants of Joseph Mc-
788
social research
Carthy, but “there was far more to the ‘McCarthy era’ than Senator
Joseph R. McCarthy.” Anti-communism was not a minority phenomenon, and “there existed in Cold War America a broad anti-Communist consensus shared and seldom questioned by most liberals as well
as conservatives, by intellectuals as well as plain folks” (Fried 1990,
vii, 34). Throughout most of the 1950s, it was accepted as a given
that there was a large-scale communist infiltration of schools, colleges, government agencies, and society at large. The Truman and
Eisenhower administrations and their respective congresses took a
variety of measures that ranged from initiating loyalty and security
programs to infringing on the civil rights of suspects and passing legislation that virtually outlawed the Communist Party. This conviction
was only shaken at the end of the decade when conspiracy theories in
general began to be considered as heterodox, that is, illegitimate and
inaccurate knowledge.
As Katharina Thalmann (2019) has meticulously shown, this
process of stigmatization was largely driven by the popularization
of insights from the social sciences. During the 1940s, social scientists began to problematize conspiracy theories in two different ways.
Some scholars, most notably Karl Popper, argued that conspiracy
theories were bad explanations of social and political processes because they overemphasized intentions and neglected unintended consequences and structural effects. Another group of scholars, among
them Theodor W. Adorno and other members of the Frankfurt School,
looked from their US exile to Germany, where the conspiracy theory
of a Judeo-Bolshevist plot for world domination led to the Holocaust.
These scholars claimed that conspiracy theories were not only wrong
but also extremely dangerous.
These arguments were initially restricted to the ivory tower of
academia and had no wider repercussions. During the 1950s, however,
they were taken up by a new generation of researchers. Scholars such
as the sociologist Edward Shils and the political scientist Seymour
Martin Lipset switched their attention from totalitarianism in Europe
to the situation in the United States, where many liberal intellectuals
Conspiracy Theory after Trump
789
were suspected of being part of the communist conspiracy. To rebut
these accusations, academics either tackled the conspiracy theorists
in the manner of the Frankfurt School, branding them as “pseudoconservative” or “populist,” or they took the Popperist line, attacking their pattern of reasoning and labeling them “pseudoscientific.”
Unlike the work of Adorno or Popper, these studies attracted notice
beyond the bounds of academia. This was due partly to the efforts of
Shils, Lipset, and others to adopt an accessible style that would reach
a wider public, and partly to the help of multipliers outside universities. Many journalists also regarded the Red Scare conspiracy theories
as a danger to American democracy and seized on the research findings, thereby helping to popularize them.
The effects of this process became quickly apparent. While the
idea of large-scale communist subversion orchestrated from Moscow
was firmly anchored in mainstream American society in the mid1950s, a decade later only members of the far-right John Birch Society
and similar groups continued to believe in a communist plot to undermine American institutions. This, in turn, allowed a new generation of scholars to posit a natural affinity between radical positions at
the margins of society and conspiracist ideology. For consensus historians like John Bunzel, extremist positions were not only antidemocratic but also anti-political, due in large part to the prominence of
conspiracy theories. This stance culminated in Richard Hofstadter’s
famous 1964 essay, “The Paranoid Style in American Politics,” which
took the pathologization of conspiracy theories to extremes by equating them with clinical paranoia and mistakenly claiming that historically such ideas had always been a minority phenomenon on the
fringes of US society.
Accordingly, when Joseph Uscinski and Joseph Parent concluded in 2014 in their quantitative study on the role of conspiracy theories in American public life since the 1890s that “the data suggest
one telling fact: we do not live in an age of conspiracy theories and
have not for some time” (2014, 110–11), they were entirely correct.
There is no similar study for Western Europe yet, but the evidence
790
social research
suggests that conspiracy theories underwent the same shift in status
there (McKenzie-McHarg and Fredheim 2017; Girard 2020). What is
important to note, though, is that the transformation of conspiracy
theories into heterodox knowledge and their relegation to the margins of society did not mean that they became completely unpopular. They were no longer believed by the majority of the population,
but, as many polls and surveys have shown over the past decades,
they remained attractive to a significant minority of the population
in most Western countries (Goertzel 1994; Drochon 2018). But they
now flew mostly under the radar of the public and rather thrived in
subcultures that shared many characteristics with what the sociologist Colin Campbell has called the “cultic milieu” (quoted in Asprem
and Dyrendal 2019, 207–8). These subcultures had their own publications and conventions, but they were rather self-enclosed and not
easily observable from the outside. Their books and magazines, for
example, were often self-published and not available for everybody
(Butter 2020, 125–26).
This is not to say that conspiracy theorizing disappeared completely from the public sphere and never constituted the official version of events anymore. Think, for example, of the Reagan administration’s claim that all international terrorist organizations were
secretly controlled from Moscow (Brunck 2018, 104–16) or the George
W. Bush administration’s allegations about Saddam Hussein having
weapons of mass destruction and ties to al-Qaeda before the 2003
invasion of Iraq (Aistrope 2016). But they could only be articulated in
veiled form—without explicit talk of plots and cabals—and were met
with ridicule and criticism sooner or later. Conspiracy theorists who
positioned themselves against the official version were left with two
options, as Thalmann has demonstrated. They could either pretend
to be just asking questions to gain access to the public sphere or embrace their marginal status by appealing only to the members of the
conspiracist subcultures by explicitly using the language of schemes
and designs.
Conspiracy Theory after Trump
791
This changed with the advent of the internet. Whereas the
popular impression often is that the internet has led to an extreme
rise in the popularity of conspiracy theories, most scholars agree by
now that it has resulted only in a moderate increase in the number
of believers and mostly merely made conspiracy theories more visible
and available again (Butter 2020, 127–29). It has made it far easier
for conspiracy theorists to get their ideas out in the open via blogs,
websites, and videos and posts on social media platforms. Whereas
the traditional media had mostly guarded public discourse from conspiracist intrusions from the late 1960s to the late 1990s, conspiracy
theorists could now simply bypass them. In turn, they became observable from the outside, and it is this visibility that has fueled a lot of
the concern about conspiracy theories in Western countries in recent
decades. In some countries, such as the United States, the concern is
justified, while in others, such as Germany, it is rather exaggerated
(Butter forthcoming).
Drawing on terminology proposed by Nancy Fraser, one could
say that the rise of the internet transformed conspiracist subcultures
into “subaltern counterpublics” (1990, 67; italics in the original). Fraser
developed this concept in a 1990 article and, thus, long before the
internet became a force to be reckoned with in such debates. Nevertheless, I find this and related concepts that she proposes quite appropriate to theorize the shift in status and influence that conspiracy theories have undergone in recent decades. In her article, Fraser
criticizes Jürgen Habermas’s concept of the public sphere, especially
his claim that in a functioning democracy there should only be one
public sphere. Fraser argues that this is not only historically inaccurate but also politically undesirable, as in stratified societies “arrangements that accommodate contestation among a plurality of competing publics better promote the ideal of participatory parity than does
a single, comprehensive, overarching public” (66). Importantly, Fraser is mostly concerned with oppressed groups that are denied (parts
of ) their democratic rights, but she is well aware that some subaltern
counterpublics “are explicitly anti-democratic and anti-egalitarian”
792
social research
(67). This is not to say that publics that revolve around conspiracy
theories are necessarily “anti-democratic and anti-egalitarian,” but
some of them are, and especially in the United States they have become dangerously influential. Fraser may thus have been a bit too
optimistic when she argued that “insofar as these counterpublics [including the problematic ones] emerge in response to exclusions within dominant publics, they help expand discursive space. In principle,
assumptions that were previously exempt from contestation will now
have to be publicly argued out … and that is a good thing in stratified
societies” (67).
Conspiracy theories of all sorts were definitely contested in the
dominant public sphere in the first years of the twenty-first century.
In fact, they were usually only taken up there to be dismissed and
ridiculed, or to alert the public to their potentially dangerous consequences. This led Jack Bratich, in his study of the public discourse
about 9/11 conspiracy theories (2008), to conclude that the public
had been gripped by a veritable “conspiracy panic”—a slight misnomer, as what he means is conspiracy theory panic. Importantly, most
conspiracy theories circulating at that time were politically neutral
in that they could be and were articulated by the right and the left.
Conspiracy theories that claimed that the 9/11 attacks had been an
“inside job” were articulated on the left to criticize the domestic and
foreign policy of the Bush administration in the years that followed,
as well as on the right where the events were quickly integrated into
an overarching narrative of a New World Order plot (often allegedly
Jewish) against national sovereignty. Even more importantly, these
conspiracy theories were dismissed by liberal and conservative media
alike and by Republican politicians as much as by Democrats. However, this changed with the election of Barack Obama, which in turn
paved the way for Donald Trump.
DONALD TRUMP’S CONSPIRACY THEORIES
On July 2, 2016, the New York Times ran a story titled “Inside the Six
Weeks Donald Trump Was a Nonstop ‘Birther’” (Parker and Eder
Conspiracy Theory after Trump
793
2016). Its authors meticulously reconstructed how Trump had used
the birther conspiracy theory in the spring of 2011 to build on his
image as a successful businessman and TV celebrity and establish
himself in the political arena as a spokesman for concerned citizens.
In a series of tweets and interviews, Trump articulated the allegation
that Barack Obama was not born in the United States and thus was
not entitled to run for president. When this strategy proved successful—and Trump jumped to the top of the field of Republican contenders in some polls—he suddenly dropped the issue entirely. The 2012
election came too early for him, and he had no intention of running
against Obama. But he returned to the tactical deployment of conspiracy theories four years later when he did run. By then the political
landscape had changed to such a degree that this strategy worked
even better.1
Of course, Trump did not invent the birther conspiracy theory,
which emerged over the summer of 2008 and gained more and more
traction in subsequent years (Jardina and Traugott 2019). Fueled by
disappointment and a sense of entitlement, frustrated Republican
voters embraced the conspiracy theory, which became a way to articulate their often racist concerns about the first Black president. Together with related conspiracist accusations that allegedly disqualify
Obama from being elected president—for example, the claim that he
was secretly a Muslim—the birther allegations marked a shift in the
public positioning of conspiracy theory within American political culture. Whereas most conspiracy theories had so far not been aligned
with specific party positions, there was now increasing convergence
between certain theories and the conservative wing of the Republican
Party. As a consequence, there was now also more and more exchange
between news outlets catering to this audience and conspiracist counterpublics. The Glenn Beck Program, for example, premiered on Fox
News in January 2009—the month Obama was inaugurated—after
it had been aired on the considerably smaller HLN for nearly three
years. With the move to Fox, the program’s host, Glenn Beck, became
far more explicitly conspiracist than he had hitherto been. Over the
794
social research
following years, he articulated a plethora of conspiracy theories directed against Obama and his team. Whereas conspiracy theories had
for the past decades been almost universally condemned on national
television, those that targeted Obama could now be voiced on Fox
News. The relegitimization of conspiracy theory in parts of the public
had begun. A few years later Trump would capitalize on this and push
it further.
However, conspiracy theories still retained most of their stigma. Despite the increasing polarization of politics, Republican representatives or those running for office were careful not to endorse such
theories, including the birther claims, in public. For example, in a
conversation with supporters who doubted the legitimacy of Obama’s
election in 2009, former vice presidential candidate Sarah Palin said
that “the public rightfully is still making it an issue” and that “the
McCain-Palin campaign didn’t do a good enough job in that area”
(quoted in Ruta-Franke 2009). When Palin’s statements were picked
up by the media, however, she quickly backpedaled, announcing on
Facebook that she had merely meant to say that voters were entitled
to ask any question they liked. Palin and other Republican politicians,
then, were happy to share the reservations of the so-called birthers
as long as there were no cameras running. A year later, congressman
Ken Buck from Kansas told his staff point blank: “Tell those dumbasses at the Tea Party to stop asking questions about birth certificates
while I’m on camera” (quoted in Amira 2010). At that time, then, Republican candidates and politicians still exercised restraint in public
in order to avoid scaring off more moderate voters.
To a lesser degree, the same can be said about Trump in
2015 and 2016 during his first run for the presidency. Trump flirted
throughout with conspiracy theories, including the birther claims he
had first articulated four years earlier, but contrary to popular lore,
it took him a long time to articulate conspiracy theories openly and
in detail. Throughout the almost year-long primaries within the Republican Party and the five months of the election campaign proper,
Trump drew on an array of conspiracy theories that ranged from the
Conspiracy Theory after Trump
795
claim that vaccinations cause autism to accusations that his rival Ted
Cruz was born in Canada and therefore not eligible for the presidency. These allegations served two functions: firstly, to discredit political opponents like Cruz; secondly, to present himself (however paradoxical this may sound) as a champion of truth, as somebody who
was not afraid to embrace the conspiracist discourse frowned upon
by the elite.
Characteristically, Trump almost always left himself a loophole
in order to distance himself from any accusation that he was spreading conspiracy theories. In his speeches, interviews, and tweets, he invariably introduced conspiracist tropes with expressions such as “I often hear it said that” or “a lot of people are saying.” Russell Muirhead
and Nancy Rosenblum see such phrases as signs of a new conspiracism popularized by Trump: “The new conspiracism—all accusation,
no evidence—substitutes social validation for scientific validation: if
a lot of people are saying it, to use Trump’s signature phrase, then it
is true enough” (2019, 3; italics in the original). However, I would
suggest that such phrases functioned in Trump’s rhetoric less as validations and more as disclaimers. He was not providing evidence by
numbers, but was making it seem that he was not actively spreading
conspiracy theories, merely repeating what others were saying.
This strategy of referencing conspiracy theories without actually embracing them was most apparent in Trump’s interview on the
Alex Jones Show in December 2015. During the half-hour conversation,
which Trump joined remotely from Trump Tower in New York, Jones
repeatedly tried to get him to endorse the New World Order conspiracy theory by putting words in his mouth. But Trump evaded all these
attempts. He used the opportunity to get Jones to corroborate his own
claim that New Jersey Muslims had cheered the collapse of the World
Trade Center on September 11, 2001, while he also indulged at length
in a critique of elites and the system. But he refused to engage with
Jones’s explicitly conspiracist claims. The reason for this, I would suggest, is simple: Trump’s campaign was aimed at appealing to multiple
audiences, or, to employ Fraser’s terminology, publics: those who be-
796
social research
lieved in conspiracy theories and those who did not. Simply by appearing on Jones’s show, Trump signaled to conspiracy theorists that
he was one of them; he did not need to endorse any specific theory
explicitly. At the same time, not committing to specific conspiracist
claims was designed to avoid alienating potential voters who were
skeptical of such theories.
Whereas Muirhead and Rosenblum suggest that Trump’s “pairing of conspiracism and a populist style” is “awkward” (2019, 64), it
is actually quite typical of how populist leaders employ conspiracist
rhetoric in political cultures in which conspiracy theories are more or
less stigmatized. As Eiríkur Bergmann and I have argued elsewhere,
“conspiracy theories … offer a specific explanation as to why the elites
act against the interests of the people” that “tends to co-exist within
a populist movement or party with other explanations such as negligence or personal enrichment.” In countries where conspiracy theories underwent a process of stigmatization it is usually a significant
minority within a populist movement that believes in them. Populist
leaders therefore customarily try to cater to this part of the electorate
by confirming their suspicions without doing it too openly and too
frequently (Bergmann and Butter 2020, 334). Trump acted accordingly
until a few weeks before the election. After all, he was not only trying to keep together a populist movement in which many believed
in conspiracy theories and even more did not; he was also working
to secure the votes of traditional supporters of the Republican Party
that were rather unreceptive to conspiracism and populism as well
as those of undecided voters. Thus, he repeatedly suggested that the
election was being “rigged” but never elaborated on his claim (Trump
2016a).
However, in October 2016 Trump changed his approach. The
race seemed lost: he was still behind in the polls, the debates were
over, and the audiotape in which he discusses sexually assaulting
women had just been made public. Most probably, he and his advisers understood that there was now no way for him to win over still
undecided moderates. He could count on those supporters of the Re-
Conspiracy Theory after Trump
797
publican Party who would, even grudgingly, vote for the Republican
nominee, and so Trump and his team focused on mobilizing those
particularly receptive to his populist and conspiracist rhetoric. Accordingly, in a campaign speech in West Palm Beach, Florida, on October 13—his first public appearance after the release of the tape—
Trump moved from allusions to conspiracy theory to developing such
a theory in detail by accusing the Democratic nominee Hillary Clinton of conspiring with the international financial elite against the
American people. His accusations culminated in the claim that “the
Clinton machine is at the center of this power structure. We’ve seen
this firsthand in the WikiLeaks documents, in which Hillary Clinton
meets in secret with international banks to plot the destruction of
US sovereignty in order to enrich these global financial powers, her
special interest friends and her donors” (2016b). We do not know exactly what impact this and similar speeches that Trump gave in the
days that followed really had. But apparently his openly conspiracist
rhetoric did not appall those who had already decided to vote for him.
By Election Day he had won more voters, and thus the strategy seems
to have paid off. Trump was carried into office by those open to the
rhetoric of the Florida speech, as well as traditional Republican voters
who did not desert him despite his explicit conspiracist claims. It is
this “Trump coalition,” as one might call it, that the Republican Party
is relying on to win back Congress in 2022 and the White House in
2024—with the important difference, discussed below, that conspiracist convictions are now even more important.
But in 2016 we were not quite there, and after he had won the
election, Trump immediately resorted to his earlier strategy of “simultaneously affirming his belief in … conspiracy theory and qualifying” it (Thalmann 2019, 199). For example, when asked about his
earlier allegations of voter fraud in an ABC interview a few days after
the inauguration, he employed the same strategies that he had used
throughout most of the campaign: “You have a lot of stuff going on
possibly. I say probably. But possibly” (ABC 2017). He positioned himself similarly vis-à-vis the QAnon conspiracy theory—in many ways
798
social research
the postelection version of the Pizzagate allegations—and neither
endorsed nor dismissed it explicitly. Occasionally, he would draw on
other popular conspiracy theories. For example, on October 5, 2018,
as the Senate was voting to end the debate about his controversial Supreme Court justice nominee Brett Kavanaugh, Trump connected the
Kavanaugh case with the upcoming midterm elections. “Look at all of
the professionally made identical signs. Paid for by Soros and others.
These are not signs made in the basement from love! #Troublemakers,” he tweeted (2018), harking to the—implicitly antisemitic—conspiracy theory that the Democrats pay protesters with money provided by exactly those international banking elites he accused Hillary
Clinton of conspiring with two years earlier. But he never followed
up with another tweet, so as not to commit himself to the conspiracy
theory too explicitly.
Accordingly, assessing the status of conspiracy theories in
American culture halfway through Trump’s presidency, Thalmann
concluded that “conspiracy theory remains illegitimate [but] that
might not matter anymore” (2019, 192). Such theories, she argued,
were still derided in large parts of the public sphere. But this did
not prevent them from finding their audiences because of the internet—the subaltern counterpublics, as Fraser would call them—and
the increasing conspiracy peddling of news outlets such as Fox, fueled by the ever-intensifying polarization of the political landscape.
Moreover, Thalmann suggested convincingly, Trump and others who
spread conspiracy theories were not at all interested in returning
them to the hegemonic position in the hierarchy of knowledge that
they had occupied until the late 1950s because their status as stigmatized knowledge allowed them to “[embrace and market] their
opposition to mainstream culture” (197). In other words, conspiracy
theories were useful to Trump because of—not despite—their still
relatively marginal status and the wholesale dismissal with which
epistemic authorities and elites reacted to them, because this enabled
him to fashion himself as oppressed and a champion of the people.
Conspiracy Theory after Trump
799
However, when Trump lost the 2020 election, this changed.
Conspiracy theory became a way to contest the defeat, but the status
of conspiracy theory as illegitimate knowledge proved problematic
in turning the result around. Trump had been talking about possible
election fraud, particularly in connection to mail-in ballots, since the
spring of 2020. But he had done the same in 2016, and until election
night on November 3, 2020, he stuck to his usual pattern of vague
claims and ambivalent allegations on Twitter and in his campaign
speeches. Once it became clear that he had lost, however, he began to
spread explicit conspiracy theories—just as he had done in October
2016 when defeat seemed certain. He was supported in his effort to
cast the election as stolen by Fox News hosts such as Tucker Carlson,
who fell in line after some initial hesitation and amplified his allegations, as well as by other branches of the conservative media ecosystem. These concerted efforts were successful. As many polls have
shown, many Republican voters still believe that Joe Biden’s victory
was the result of a sinister plot. A few days after the election, a Reuters poll found that 52 percent of Republicans believed that Trump
was the rightful winner (Kahn 2020). By January 2022, 40 percent of
Americans overall believed that Biden was an illegitimate president
because the election had been stolen (Yang 2022).
Trump and his allies, then, were quite successful in convincing much of the public that their conspiracist allegations were true,
but this was not enough to overturn the election. The attempts by
Trump and his inner circle to pressure Georgia Secretary of State Brad
Raffensperger and other officials at the state and county level to recount, not certify, or discount certain ballots have been well-documented by journalists and others. In addition, the Trump campaign
filed more than 60 lawsuits in several states to contest the election
process, the counting of ballots, and of course its results. None of
them were successful, as the courts refused to accept the conspiracist
logic most of them were based on as a legitimate form of legal discourse and dismissed them quickly. To resort to Fraser’s terminology
once more: Trump and his allies had managed to construct a weak
800
social research
public, one “whose deliberative practice consists exclusively in opinion-formation,” but failed to transform it into a strong one, a public
“whose discourse encompasses both opinion-formation and decisionmaking” (1990, 75). They were successful in making conspiracy theory a legitimate form of knowledge (again) in the public formed by
conservative media and its audience but did not manage to achieve
the same for the strong public that is the US legal system. Their conspiracy theorizing was successful in a court of public opinion, but not
in a court of law.
Accordingly, as the investigation of the United States House
Select Committee on the January 6 attack—whose public hearings are
taking place as I write this text in June 2022—has conclusively shown,
Trump instigated his supporters to storm the Capitol and attempt a
coup d’état on January 6, 2021. Before they attacked the building,
many of his supporters gathered outside the White House to listen to
his hour-long conspiracist rant. He claimed that the election had been
stolen by a conspiracy of the radical left, big tech companies, the media, and Republican traitors. In typical conspiracist fashion he bombarded his audience with numbers, half-truths, questionable eyewitness accounts, and suggestive questions (Naylor 2021). What had not
worked for the judges worked for this audience, and they went down
to the Capitol. Whereas Trump had for a long time headed a populist
movement in which a significant minority believed in conspiracy theories, it had now been transformed into one glued together by such a
theory. Luckily, the coup d’état failed. Congress certified the election
result eventually, and on January 20, 2021, Biden was inaugurated.
But the story does not end here.
CONSPIRACY THEORY AFTER TRUMP
The most worrisome aspect of the story I am telling is not that Trump’s
peddling of conspiracy theories has paved the way for the election
of figures such as congresswoman Marjorie Taylor Greene, who has
repeatedly expressed belief in far more outlandish and explicitly antisemitic conspiracy theories, such as QAnon. This is a phenomenon
Conspiracy Theory after Trump
801
long familiar in Western democracies. There is probably no national
or regional parliament in Europe or North America that does not have
such figures. The most worrisome aspect of the story is also not the
attack on the Capitol. Rather, it is the degree to which the Republican
Party and the media that support it have not only not distanced themselves from Trump and his conspiracist allegations about the stolen
election but also appropriated them and rewritten the story of what
happened on January 6, 2021. I explained above that the Republican
Party was founded on a conspiracy theory in the 1850s; now a conspiracy theory is foundational for the party once again.
Whereas some Republican representatives spoke out against
Trump immediately after the attack on the Capitol, the party has
since then embraced his conspiracy theories. Representatives like Liz
Cheney, who called the attack on the Capitol what it was and held
Trump responsible, were demoted in Congress and often lost to primary challengers supported by Trump during the summer of 2022.
What happened on January 6 is either dismissed as completely exaggerated or—in yet another conspiracist move—blamed on the radical
left, which allegedly staged the attack disguised as Trump supporters.
This conspiracy theory is by now believed by half of those who identify as Republicans, according to a recent poll (Lange 2022). By the same
token, the conspiracy theory of the stolen election is by now virtually
uncontested within the party, with only those whose careers are effectively over, like Senator Mitt Romney, daring to disagree openly.
Whereas elected officials and candidates did not want to be publicly
associated with birther claims 10 years ago, they now either openly
embrace this theory or at least do not explicitly distance themselves
from it. Some of them might be genuine believers, others merely selfserving, and yet others are maybe just afraid to speak their mind. All
of them, it is safe to assume, are aware that the conspiracy theory
goes well with Republican voters, many of whom, as polls show, believe it themselves. Those who do not adhere to conspiracy theories
often vote for candidates who do because party affiliation trumps other considerations in the extremely polarized climate of contemporary
802
social research
American politics. What I termed the Trump coalition still stands,
and conspiracy theories are more central to it now than a few years
ago, as evident in the more open way in which they are articulated
and the larger number of coalition members who uphold them today.
Conspiracy theories, then, have indeed been relegitimized to
a considerable degree in American political culture because many
genuinely believe them and the Republican Party has recognized
their strategic value as a tool of mobilization and weaponization.
This does not mean that the term “conspiracy theory” can now be
openly embraced—it is always the other side that is spreading “conspiracy theories”—but that the logic of conspiracy theory has become
more accepted again. When I wrote the conclusion to my book on
the history of American conspiracy theories, I already suspected that
such a development might be in the making. Back then, I suggested that what appeared to be happening was either that conspiracy
theories were entering the mainstream again or that the margins of
society, to which conspiracist discourse had been largely relegated
since the 1960s, were becoming broader (Butter 2014, 300–301). In
light of recent events, I think there is a third and better explanation:
the fragmentation of the public sphere. Whereas Fraser in 1990 was
thinking of a dominant public sphere and a number of different subaltern counterpublics, we are now faced with at least two different
publics—one Democratic and one Republican—that span both politics and the media and that need to be distinguished from a number
of less influential counterpublics that of course continue to exist. It
is currently impossible to say which of these publics is in the hegemonic position. Since one of these publics has embraced conspiracy
theories and the other has not (which is not to say that such theories
are entirely absent there), conspiracy theory is now both stigmatized
and relegitimized. Depending on the public, it functions still as heterodox or again as orthodox knowledge.
This is worrisome not only because such fragmentation makes
meaningful public debate on topics such as climate change impossible (and it is no coincidence that this topic, too, is increasingly seen
Conspiracy Theory after Trump
803
as a conspiracy in one of the publics); it is also worrisome because the
partial relegitimization of conspiracy theories poses a more immediate threat to American democracy. Trump’s conspiracy theorizing
with regard to the election was reactive. Before he lost, he restricted
himself to rumors and hints. The full-blown theories only followed afterwards. They were dismissed in the courts but sparked the attack on
the Capitol. Republican politicians, however, are now being proactive
with regard to upcoming elections. They have been using the specter
of voter fraud in general and the “stolen election” in particular to
introduce voting restrictions of all kinds that are allegedly meant to
make voting securer but are in effect making it more difficult for
groups that tend to support the Democrats, most notably people of
color (Brennan Center 2021). And while Brad Raffensperger managed
to keep his job and fended off the challenge by a Trump loyalist in the
2022 primaries, other officials in key positions for certifying election
results who did not give in to Trump have by now been replaced. The
Republican Party’s embrace of the conspiracy theory of the stolen
election means that conspiracy theories are now part of what Fraser
called a strong public, one with decision-making power. Thus, if the
2024 election results are contested with the claim that the election
was rigged, it might play out differently than in 2020.
CONCLUSION
Very often—and often entirely justifiably—the United States is seen
as the future of Europe. Developments in America—from the rise of
neoliberalism to the possibility of ordering one’s coffee to go—are
said to take place in Europe a little later. Accordingly, and especially in
what Donald Rumsfeld called “old Europe,” many observers worry that
conspiracy theories will become a danger to democracy in those countries as well. To my mind, this is exaggerated. Conspiracy theories need
to be taken seriously because they can be a catalyst for radicalization
and thus lead to violence (Butter 2020, 154–55), and as the COVID-19
pandemic has shown, they can also tear families apart (Butter forthcoming). But democracy in the German-speaking countries, Nordic
804
social research
countries, and Western and Southern Europe is not threatened. Their
political systems are far less polarized than the American one because
they are built on proportional representation, and competing parties
are usually forced to cooperate or even form coalitions. This makes
it far more unlikely to see another party as conspiring, as conspiracy
theories thrive when supporters of different political parties see no
common ground and perceive the other party as a threat to the country (van Prooijen and Douglas 2018). These countries also have for the
most part far less polarized media landscapes, which works against
fragmentation and keeps conspiracy theories at the margins. What is
more, in Central and Eastern Europe, especially Poland and Hungary,
conspiracy theories are already a danger to democracy and have been
for a much longer time than in the United States. In this region of the
world, conspiracy theories never lost their status as an orthodox form
of knowledge (Butter 2020, 105); the PiS Party in Poland and the Fidesz
Party in Hungary have been using them systematically to consolidate
their power bases and cut back on civil liberties.
Accordingly, it might be time to turn the perspective around
and ask, as the Daily Show recently did (Kurtz 2022), whether Hungary
might be the future of the United States—an illiberal democracy that
retains the semblance of a proper democracy but wherein one party
has “rigged” the system in such a way that it has become almost impossible to vote it out of power. There is no voter fraud in the sense
of ballots being forged or destroyed, but the election laws that Fidesz
passed after it came into government favor the strongest party disproportionally and that party is invariably Fidesz. Moreover, all TV stations are by now controlled by Fidesz, which means that the party’s
candidates and platforms receive much more airtime and attention
than those of the opposition. Importantly, both Fidesz politicians and
the media attached to the party feed it a constant stream of disinformation and conspiracy theories, thus mobilizing the party’s supporters and misrepresenting and disqualifying the opposition (Krekó and
Enyedi 2018).
Conspiracy Theory after Trump
805
It is unlikely that such complete control could be established
in the United States, but it is also not necessary. The Electoral College
already gives the Republican Party an unfair advantage. In a way, the
system is already “rigged.” All that is needed is to make sure that the
party comes out on top in a number of key states. And the party is
working hard to ensure this—based on a conspiracy theory that it has
inherited from Donald Trump.
NOTES
1. To say that Trump deployed conspiracy theories strategically is not
to say that he did not and does not genuinely believe (some of) them.
This question—just as that of authorial intention in literary criticism—is impossible to settle.
REFERENCES
ABC. 2017. “Transcript: ABC News Anchor David Muir Interviews
President Trump.” ABC News, Jan. 25. https://abcnews.go.com/Poli
tics/transcript-abc-news-anchor-david-muirinterviews-president/st
ory?id=45047602.
Aistrope, Tim. 2016. Conspiracy Theory and American Foreign Policy.
Manchester: Manchester U. Press.
Amira, Dan. 2010. “Kansas Congressional Candidate Just Can’t Stop
Accidentally Being a Birther.” New York Magazine, July 23. https://
nymag.com/intelligencer/2010/07/kansas_congressional_candida
te.html.
Anton, Andreas. 2011. Unwirkliche Wirklichkeiten: Zur Wissenssoziologie von
Verschwörungstheorien. Berlin: Logos.
Asprem, Egil, and Asbjørn Dyrendal. 2019. “Close Companions?
Esotericism and Conspiracy Theories.” In Handbook of Conspiracy
Theory and Contemporary Religion, ed. Asbjørn Dyrendal, David G.
Robertson, and Egil Asprem, 207–33. Leiden: Brill.
Bergmann, Eiríkur, and Michael Butter. 2020. “Conspiracy Theory and
Populism.” In The Routledge Handbook of Conspiracy Theories, ed.
Michael Butter and Peter Knight, 330–43. London: Routledge.
806
social research
Bratich, Jack Z. 2008. Conspiracy Panics: Political Rationality and Popular
Culture. Albany: State U. New York Press.
Brennan Center. 2021. “Voting Laws Roundup: October 2021.” Brennan
Center for Justice, Oct. 4. https://www.brennancenter.org/our-work
/research-reports/voting-laws-roundup-october-2021.
Brunck, Annika Carolin. 2018. “Fighting ‘the Evil Scourge of Terrorism’:
From ‘Jewish Terrorism’ to ‘Islamic Terrorism’ in the United States,
1940–2017.” PhD diss., U. Tübingen.
Butter, Michael. 2014. Plots, Designs, and Schemes: American Conspiracy
Theories from the Puritans to the Present. Berlin: De Gruyter.
———. 2020. The Nature of Conspiracy Theories. Trans. Sharon Howe.
London: Polity.
———. Forthcoming. “Covid Conspiracy Theories in Germany, Austria
and Switzerland.” In Covid Conspiracy Theories in Global Perspective, ed.
Michael Butter and Peter Knight. London: Routledge.
Drochon, Hugo. 2018. “Who Believes in Conspiracy Theories in Great
Britain and Europe?” In Conspiracy Theories and the People Who Believe
Them, ed. Joseph E. Uscinski, 336–46. New York: Oxford U. Press.
Foner, Eric. 1995. Free Soil, Free Labor, Free Men: The Ideology of the Republican
Party Before the Civil War. Oxford: Oxford U. Press.
Fraser, Nancy. 1990. “Rethinking the Public Sphere: A Contribution to the
Critique of Actually Existing Democracy.” Social Text 25/26: 56–80.
Fried, Richard M. 1990. Nightmare in Red: The McCarthy Era in Perspective.
Oxford: Oxford U. Press.
Girard, Pascal. 2020. “Conspiracy Theories in Europe during the
Twentieth Century.” In The Routledge Handbook of Conspiracy Theories,
ed. Michael Butter and Peter Knight, 569–81. London: Routledge.
Goertzel, Ted. 1994. “Belief in Conspiracy Theories.” Political Psychology 15
(4): 731–42.
Jardina, Ashley, and Michael Traugott. 2019 “The Genesis of the Birther
Rumor: Partisanship, Racial Attitudes, and Political Knowledge.”
Journal of Race Ethnicity and Politics 4 (1): 1–21.
Kahn, Chris. 2020. “Half of Republicans Say Biden Won because of a
‘Rigged’ Election: Reuters/Ipsos Poll.” Reuters, Nov. 18. https://www
.reuters.com/article/us-usa-election-poll-idUSKBN27Y1AJ.
Conspiracy Theory after Trump
807
Krekó, Péter, and Zsolt Enyedi. 2018. “Explaining Eastern Europe: Orbán’s
Laboratory of Illiberalism.” Journal of Democracy 29 (3): 39–51.
Kurtz, Judy. 2022. “‘Daily Show’ Correspondent Sees Hungary as
‘Cautionary Tale’ for US.” The Hill, April 20. https://thehill.com/bl
ogs/in-the-know/3274165-daily-show-correspondent-sees-hungary
-as-cautionary-tale-for-us/.
Lange, Jason. 2022. “Half of US Republicans Believe the Left Led Jan. 6
Violence: Reuters/Ipsos Poll.” Reuters, June 9. https://www.reuters
.com/world/us/half-us-republicans-believe-left-led-jan-6-violence-re
utersipsos-2022-06-09/.
McKenzie-McHarg, Andrew, and Rolf Fredheim. 2017. “Cock-Ups and
Slap-Downs: A Quantitative Analysis of Conspiracy Rhetoric in
the British Parliament 1916–2015.” Historical Methods: A Journal of
Quantitative and Interdisciplinary History 50 (3): 156–69.
Muirhead, Russell, and Nancy Rosenblum. 2019. A Lot of People Are Saying:
The New Conspiracism and the Assault on Democracy. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton U. Press.
Naylor, Brian. 2021. “Read Trump’s Jan. 6 Speech, a Key Part of Impeachment
Trial.” NPR, Feb. 10. https://www.npr.org/2021/02/10/966396848/re
ad-trumps-jan-6-speech-a-key-part-of-impeachment-trial?t=165530
8615356.
Oxford English Dictionary. n.d. S.v. “after (adv., prep., and conj.).” https://www
.oed.com/view/Entry/3661?rskey=EXM3yQ&result=3&isAdvanced=
false#eid.
Parker, Ashley, and Steve Eder. 2016. “Inside the Six Weeks Donald Trump
Was a Nonstop ‘Birther.’” New York Times, July 2. https://www.nytim
es.com/2016/07/03/us/politics/donald-trump-birther-obama.html.
Ruta-Franke, Garance. 2009. “Palin Flirts with Obama Birth Certificate
Questions.” Washington Post, Dec. 4.
Thalmann, Katharina. 2019. The Stigmatization of Conspiracy Theory since the
1950s: “A Plot to Make Us Look Foolish.” London: Routledge.
Trump, Donald (@RealDonaldTrump). 2016a. “This election is being
rigged.” Trump Twitter Archive, Oct. 15, 7:45 a.m. EST. https://www
.thetrumparchive.com/?results=1&searchbox=%22This+election+i
s+being+rigged%22.
808
social research
———. 2016b. “Remarks at the South Florida Fair Expo Center in
West Palm Beach, Florida.” American Presidency Project,
Campaign Documents, Oct. 13. https://www.presidency.ucsb.edu
/documents/remarks-the-south-florida-fair-expo-center-west-palm
-beach-florida.
——— (@RealDonaldTrump). 2018. “The very rude elevator screamers
are paid professionals.” Trump Twitter archive, Oct. 5, 9:03 a.m.
EST. https://www.thetrumparchive.com/?results=1&searchbox=
%22at+all+of+the+professionally+made+identical+signs.+Paid+for
+by+Soros+and+others.+These+are+not+signs+made+in+the+base
ment+from+love%21+%23Troublemakers%22.
Uscinski, Joseph E., and Joseph M. Parent. 2014. American Conspiracy
Theories. New York: Oxford U. Press.
Van Prooijen, Jan-Willem, and Karen M. Douglas. 2018. “Belief in
Conspiracy Theories: Basic Principles of an Emerging Research
Domain.” European Journal of Social Psychology 48 (7): 897–908.
Yang, Maya. 2022. “More than 40% in US Do Not Believe Biden Legitimately
Won Election—Poll.” Guardian, Jan. 5. https://www.theguardian
.com/us-news/2022/jan/05/america-biden-election-2020-poll-vic
tory.
Zwierlein, Cornel. 2020. “Conspiracy Theories in the Middle Ages and the
Early Modern Period.” In Routledge Handbook of Conspiracy Theories,
ed. Michael Butter and Peter Knight, 542–54. London: Routledge.
Conspiracy Theory after Trump
809