39
After Nietzsche: Notes towards a philosophy of ecstasy
By Jill Marsden
Palgrave Macmillan, 2002
Reviewed by Christopher Branson, University of Warwick – Humboldt Universität zu
Berlin
Nietzsche’s thought of eternal recurrence is at once immediate and maddeningly distant.
In almost any one of its presentations it strikes the reader as though the demon were there
with him. ‘Here is something,’ one feels: mysterious, enormous, tempting, dangerous.
And yet the task of interpreting it is of great difficulty. Anyone who has discussed this
thought in an undergraduate seminar knows just how quickly the sensation of deep
insight can be lost through pithy extrapolation. The problem seems to be that of capturing
the scale of the thought, of attempting to locate just why Nietzsche wrote of it with such
gravitas. Perhaps we are guilty of assuming that our felt sympathy towards the thought
automatically qualifies us to conceptualize it. As Jill Marsden writes in the preface to her
inspiring book, After Nietzsche, “Eternal return is above all else a thought of the supreme
affirmation of life but what it actually means to affirm life is highly questionable, a
phrase too easily uttered and then abandoned unthought” (xiii).
Nietzsche himself warns us that we must take the thought in the correct spirit if we are to
know the true weight of it. When Zarathustra experiences his vision of eternal return,
Published in The Agonist—Vol. III, issue 2, July 2008
40
finding himself at the gateway called ‘Moment,’ his arch-enemy, the dwarf-spirit of
gravity, makes a mockery of the thought by reducing it to a safe, empty cognition:
‘All that is straight lies,’ murmured the dwarf contemptuously. ‘All truth is
crooked; time itself is a circle.’
‘You Spirit of Heaviness’ I said angrily. ‘Do not make it too light and easy for
yourself!’ (Z:3 ‘On the Vision and the Riddle’)
It is a peculiar mode of thought that resists our cognitive powers and depends instead on
something more akin to a musical sensibility—the ability to hear the ‘tone,’ or ‘pitch’ of
the thought. This is a queer type of knowledge, paradoxically emerging at the eclipse of
our reflective faculties. Marsden’s claim is that such an experience of sensitive knowing
entails ‘ec-stasis’ or the exceeding of the self, of passing beyond the form of identity
given by the ‘I,’ and thus that ecstasy “is the necessary condition for thinking eternal
return” (xi). It is only in the throes of rapture, she writes, that one can feel equal to the
demonic call for supreme affirmation: “Amid the dazzlement of erotic love, of sublime
entrancement, of visionary and hallucinatory bedazzlement, there is a joy that wills itself
so intensely that it wants itself more and again” (8).
Whilst the thought of eternal recurrence is perhaps the inspiration behind this book—and
an elucidation of the thought is certainly one of its goals—it is not its overarching theme.
As the subtitle suggests, Jill Marsden is primarily concerned with developing a
philosophy of ecstasy, of investigating what we can learn from the experience of rapture.
This is not a phenomenological or descriptive project, however, which would render
ecstatic joy an object of knowledge. Rather, it is to pursue the type of thought generated
by experiences of transfiguration. This, Marsden argues, is one of the unique tasks
provided to us by Nietzsche’s philosophy in the wake of the death of God. This
event—the collapse of our belief in the principle of identity—brings with it a new
trajectory for philosophy. This is to communicate with that which had previously been
banished from thought, the realm of experience lying beyond the fictional ‘conditions of
possibility’ that the human animal has fabricated and progressively incorporated. This
Published in The Agonist—Vol. III, issue 2, July 2008
41
cannot involve the mere broadening of the thought of the same to include such extreme
states, but necessitates a radical turn in our interpretation of what ‘thinking’ entails.
Conceptual thinking “will of necessity inhibit any genuine contact with alterity, for
specific difference will always be mediated by representation within a concept of
identity” (4).
The question is, then, how one is to describe thoughts which reach beyond what is
generally taken to be “knowledge.” Jill Marsden’s response is to pursue philosophy as
aesthetics, as a science of sensitive knowing, which is taken not to be “a region of
philosophy delimited from supposedly non-sensual areas of thought” (31). She argues
that the notion of thought as affective is developed by Nietzsche all the way from The
Birth of Tragedy right through to his later works. By ignoring the unfortunate
metaphysical vocabulary that he borrows from Schopenhauer in his early work, Marsden
reinterprets Nietzsche’s development of Apollinian and Dionysian forces, along with the
relationship between philosophy and art, in terms of a “Physiology of Art.” This was the
prospective title Nietzsche gave to a series of notes on art and physis in the 1880s, which
connected his later concerns of embodiment and incorporation with the Apollinian and
Dionysian, which are here referred to as “fundamental types”.1 The relationship between
the body and aesthetic experience on the one hand, and the body and knowledge on the
other, drives Marsden’s thought.
Whilst Nietzsche’s thought of eternal return may be described as the caesura of
Marsden’s philosophy of ecstasy, marking the birth of new adventures in thought, the
problems that it seeks to re-think invariably arise in Kant. Indeed, the Kantian concept of
the self haunts this book, representing in its multifarious implications the intellectual
errors that a philosophy of ecstasy seeks to overcome. Marsden approvingly cites
Deleuze’s argument that Nietzsche’s development of the concept of genealogy can be
understood as the culmination of the critical project (15-16). Whilst Kant’s conditions of
1
Friedrich Nietzsche, KSA 13: 17[9], translated by Jill Marsden, After Nietzsche, 191n2. Many of the notes
on the ‘physiology of art’ are collected in The Will to Power, Ch.IV, ‘The Will to Power as Art’ (794-893).
Published in The Agonist—Vol. III, issue 2, July 2008
42
thought always remained external to the conditioned, Nietzsche’s critique of the value of
values represents an internal critique, a concern with the creation of values such as
knowledge and truth. In other words, Kant failed to apply his own dictum—that the ‘initself’ is unknowable—to our value judgements. It was through his concern with the
genesis of values that Nietzsche’s thought was led ultimately to the body as the site of
this genesis and the material condition of thought.
In The Gay Science Nietzsche presents an account of the development of identity-based
‘knowledge’ in evolutionary terms. “Over immense periods of time,” he writes, “the
intellect produced nothing but errors. A few of these proved to be useful and helped
preserve the species” (GS 110). These errors, such as the notions that there are enduring
things, substances and bodies, and that a thing is what it appears to be, proved to be of
use in the practical life of the organism, servicing its basic needs of survival, and were
thus continually inherited down the generations. It is in this sense that Nietzsche defines
the strength of knowledge: “[it] does not depend on its degree of truth but on its age, on
the degree to which it has been incorporated, on its character as a condition of life”
(ibid.). The power of knowledge is given by the degree to which it has become instinctive
for the organism. The Kantian notion of the self can be understood as the condensation of
these errors. This is to relativize the result of Kant’s ingenious transcendental deduction:
that the unity of the self and the perceived objectivity of the world are in a reciprocal
relationship of determination. By understanding this quasi-stable “Self” as the product of
a genesis through the incorporation of errors by the body, however, one is able
distinguish between the self, which is given for thought, and the body, which is not. As
Marsden puts it:
[I]t is questionable whether the conditions under which ‘representations’ can
relate to ‘objects’ are themselves invariant. If becoming lacks a subject distinct
from itself, the body ‘as such’ is not to be regarded as a given. If the body is as
much a constellation of the rhythm of things as the items in the perceptual
horizon, then its status as a form of the same is as illusory as the things it surveys.
(25)
Published in The Agonist—Vol. III, issue 2, July 2008
43
Thus, the possibility of thinking beyond the form of the same seems to rely on our ability
to perceive beyond the self, by attending to the affective experience of the body.
Curiously, one way in which we may begin to pursue this idea is provided by Kant
himself in his writings on aesthetic experience. In perhaps the most exhilarating chapter
of her book, Jill Marsden traces the Kantian concept of ‘disinterestedness’ in aesthetic
experience, through Schopenhauer’s anti-humanist interpretation, to its revaluation in the
Nietzschean ideas of Apollinian and Dionysian rapture (Ch.3: ‘A Feeling of Life, 47-72).
What marks the experience of beauty from desire-based satisfactions is that the pleasure
it gives us is “useless, gratuitous and literally good for nothing” (50).2 That Kant attempts
to align beauty not only with embodiment, but also with the Ideas of reason, and thus
wants to give it an inspirational role in the supersensible vocation of moral goodness,
should not deter us from the conclusion that beauty is itself purposeless: “[I]f beauty is a
humanising power it must sustain the rift in order to bridge it” (ibid.).
The key insight with regard to aesthetic experience is of the form of judgement it
involves. Insofar as it is without purpose, it is disinterested, removed from the self:
To say that such a judgement is ‘free’ from interest means that I cannot choose
whether to have a liking for beauty, it chooses me, it compels me. In a curious
sense aesthetic judgement is of me (is grounded in sensations of pleasure and
pain) without being obviously peculiar to me (‘interested’). (54)
It is through philosophy pursued as aesthetics that the inhuman or ecstatic form of
thought emerges. A normal, ‘interested’ judgement is referred to the presentation of an
object’s existence. In his transcendental deduction, Kant suggests that this knowledge of
the object is the result of three transcendental syntheses of presentations by the
imagination: the synthesis of sense impressions into a single manifold; the reproduction
of past impressions in a present manifold; and the recognition of past and present
2
The notion of the purposeless expenditure of energy plays an important role in Marsden’s philosophy of
ecstasy, being associated with active forces in general (the need for life to squander in its self-overcoming,
see 17-18) and sacred experience in particular (125-127).
Published in The Agonist—Vol. III, issue 2, July 2008
44
representations as connected. What is unique about the representations of aesthetic
experience is that they reproduce themselves without any acts of the imagination (54-5).
“We linger in our contemplation of the beautiful, because this contemplation strengthens
and reproduces itself.”3 Intentionality is in thrall when we are captivated by the beautiful.
Whilst Kant describes interested engagement with an object as the product of desire,
meaning that it is empirical, pure disinterested contemplation is transcendental in nature
and hence ‘free’ of reality (51-2). This is because contemplation of beauty entails making
a ‘reflective judgement.’ Kant defines judgement in general as “the ability to think the
particular as contained in the universal.”4 Since the universal, or rule, is not given in the
experience of the purposeless artwork, the judgement made is a reflection on the
particular, and is not determined from without. This reflection is referred by Kant to the
question of how the subject feels itself affected by the presentation, which he calls a
‘feeling of life’ [Lebensgefühl].5 It is this aspect of ‘disinterested’ experience that
Marsden finds crucial to Nietzsche’s project:
It is particularly significant that Kant should propose that representations be
referred to this Lebensgefühl because this implies that aesthetic judgement always
entails an evaluation of life—a consideration of its pains and pleasures. Pleasure
is aligned with a sense of life enhancement (‘the furtherance of life’) whereas
displeasure signifies a sense of its inhibition or restriction. (52)
Marsden compares Kant’s description of the beautiful with Apollinian rapture, in terms
of the way the intuition of the flow of time (given by the syntheses of the imagination) is
stalled and intensified (55).6 It is in her alignment of Kant’s analysis of the sublime with
Dionysian pathos, however, that she suggests a link between ‘disinterested’ experience
and the supreme affirmation of eternal return. Unlike the experience of the beautiful,
3
Immanuel Kant, Critique of Judgement, translated by W.S. Pluhar (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1987): 68.
4
Immanuel Kant, Critique of Judgement: 18-19.
5
Cf. Imannuel Kant, Critique of Judgement: 44.
6
For Marsden’s excellent discussion of Apollinian rapture and its relation to the Dionysian, see 30-47.
Published in The Agonist—Vol. III, issue 2, July 2008
45
where the subject is rapt in an ‘inhuman’ perception of form, the sublime experience
involves the confrontation with that which cannot be rendered harmonious. This involves
a far more ambiguous ‘feeling of life’ than the straightforward response of pleasure
before beauty. Pleasure in the face of the sublime arises only indirectly from the
momentary inhibition of the vital forces, followed by an outpouring of them that is all the
stronger (56). In other words, in the experience of the sublime pleasure and pain engage
in a dynamic of perpetual overcoming, which leads Marsden to the conclusion that, in
spite of Kant’s attempt to reel in the destructive power of the sublime, where it would
only inspire in us a transcendental purposiveness, a darker thought might have been
sewed. “Maybe beauty only emerges as a supremely pure and idealizing power when reenergised by the Sodom of ‘our’ destitution and despair” (ibid.).
The revaluation of suffering is central to Nietzsche’s critique of values, but its relation to
the concept of affirmation is not always given due thought by commentators. It is a
truism to say that if we wish to affirm life, and life contains suffering, then we must
affirm suffering too. In Marsden’s interpretation of affirmation, where affirmation is not
given by cognition but by the lived flourishing of active (i.e. vital) forces, suffering plays
an essential, constitutive role in this flourishing. And if affirmation is accompanied by the
feeling of joy in the organism, then the affirmation of life per se, as opposed to human
life, would come with an unbounded pleasure, the ceaseless augmentation of pleasure by
its antagonism with pain, and thus a constant overcoming. For Marsden, the most
powerful experience of this exquisite paroxysm of joy in pain is given in Apollinian
rapture. In Ch.2, ‘The Tempo of Becoming’ (24-46), she argues that, whilst the selfdifferentiating power of the Dionysian is the more fundamental force, since “the
difference between Apollinian and Dionysian ecstasy is already thought within the
Dionysian” (42), it is in Apollinian ecstasy that the vital energy inherent in both is
concentrated and contracted, forming an eternalised image of this activity. With regard to
the antagonism of pleasure and pain, she writes of the “secret violence” of Apollinian
rapture:
Published in The Agonist—Vol. III, issue 2, July 2008
46
It attenuates the moment, retards the feeling of space and time, stalls the orgasm
of Dionysian frenzy, refuses to let go. This is not the conservative activity of the
functional body, eternally sheltered against desires which would delight to death.
It is a far more subtle yet highly charged knowledge, an eroticism which palpably
‘knows’ its bounds, presses tantalizingly up against its carefully retained limits.
(72)
If I find a flaw in Jill Marsden’s reading of Nietzsche, it is precisely in the privileging of
ecstasy as the site of affirmation. It strikes one as akin to remarking that it was only in
their orgiastic frenzy that the Greeks loved life. Nietzsche describes the “craving for the
ugly” of the best Greeks as an example of “neuroses of health” (BT ‘Attempt at a SelfCriticism,’ 4). If affirmation is to be given a physiological sense, in the sense of the
active flourishing of life, then I believe that it should not be reduced to the extreme
moments in the individual in which the Self is overcome in ecstasy. It should also, I
believe, have a historical and communal dimension that refers to the flourishing of a
people: “the youth and youthfulness of a people” (ibid.). It is in this broader sense of
affirmation that the “weight” of the thought of supreme affirmation is revealed.
From his first sketch of eternal recurrence, Nietzsche associated the thought with specific
tasks, perhaps the central one of which pertains to knowledge, and more specifically, the
incorporation of truth.7 In section 110 of The Gay Science (the first part of which,
concerned with the emergence and incorporation of the errors of knowledge, we
discussed above), Nietzsche writes that it was only very late in the development of the
organism that truth emerged, as a different form of knowledge to that which had
previously been experienced. He writes that “the ultimate question about the conditions
of life” has now been posed: “To what extent can truth endure incorporation? That is the
question; that is the experiment” (GS 110). In a rich and instructive discussion of this
thought, Keith Ansell Pearson argues that ‘truth,’ obviously a problematical term for
Nietzsche, should here be understood in two senses. On the one hand, truth should be
taken to mean the practices of truthfulness, such as “doubt, suspicion, critical distance,
7
See KSA 9: 11[141], translated by Keith Ansell Pearson in ‘The Eternal Return of the Overhuman: The
Weightiest Knowledge and the Abyss of Light,’ the Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Issue 30 (2005): 2-3.
Published in The Agonist—Vol. III, issue 2, July 2008
47
subjecting all things to scrutiny, and so on”.8 On the other hand, it refers to the ultimate
“truth” which Nietzsche understands modern science as entropically indicating. This is
“the knowledge that all things are implicated in a perpetual and eternal flux […that] we
are not what we take ourselves to be either as moral agents or as thinking subjects”.9
The specific historical event that we find ourselves living through is that of the death of
God. Jill Marsden is right to point out that this collapse in our faith of “the eternally
transcendent One” does not announce “a new beginning or starting point for thinking but
a return” (7). We do not start again from nothing. God is dead, but his shadow is still
shown in the caves of men. The will to truth, the critical drive which has undermined the
form of identity, is still to be pursued to its limit. Whilst in our moments of rapture, be
they erotic, aesthetic or religious, we may experience a joy so great that we will it again,
the lightness of these moments casts the rest of our lives in shadow. This is the flipside of
the thought of eternal recurrence, the great weight of its challenge. Whilst the ‘Self,’ in
all of its reactive evaluations, persists in us, the thought that there is no redemption still
carries the power to crush. Who can bear this thought? Perhaps a people yet to come. The
incorporation of truth is the transformative task Nietzsche designates for those who will
to bear it. And for this task we must also acquire a passion for the knowledge we wish to
incorporate, which means to pursue knowledge as an experiment in gay science.
If, in spite of our best endeavours to appear good Nietzscheans, we are sometimes
horrified that there is no redemption, that the universe is without purpose, then this
indicates that we are still some way from acquiring the great health that wills the ugly and
terrible, that sees beauty in horror. Nietzsche writes of his will to such health: “I want to
learn more and more to see as beautiful what is necessary in things; then I shall be one of
those who make things beautiful” (GS 276). With this thought he introduces Book Four
of The Gay Science, which culminates in the thought of eternal return and the
8
Keith Ansell Pearson, ‘The Eternal Return of the Overhuman: The Weightiest Knowledge and the Abyss
of Light,’ the Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Issue 30 (2005): 7.
9
Keith Ansell Pearson, ibid.
Published in The Agonist—Vol. III, issue 2, July 2008
48
introduction of the figure of Zarathustra. The development of an aesthetic taste for
necessity (“Amor fati: let that be my love henceforth” (ibid.)) is thus deeply bound up
with the thought of affirmation. Nietzsche tells us that the changing of a taste is
dependent on the development of new habits, which may then be experienced as needs
(GS 39). And, as we know, our habits are deeply connected with knowledge. To repeat,
the strength of knowledge depends “on the degree to which it has been incorporated, on
its character as a condition of life” (GS 110).
Thus we come to an understanding of why affirmation is to be pursued through
Wissenschaft, and the incorporation of “truth” in particular. By teaching ourselves the
truths of life, we may come to develop a taste for this naturalised understanding, and
eventually a love of fate and necessity. Nietzsche emphasises that love always has to be
learned. He describes this in terms of the development of appreciation of a strange form
of music. First we must learn to detect and distinguish the elements of a melody. This
requires the good will and the exertion to tolerate it in spite of its strangeness. (This good
will may be understood in terms of the cheerfulness of gay science; the exertion in terms
of our instinctive resistance to certain truths.) The final result is, however, glorious:
Finally there comes a moment when we are used to it, when we wait for it, when
we sense that we should miss it if it were missing; and now it continues to compel
and enchant us relentlessly until we have become its humble and enraptured
lovers who desire nothing better from the world than it and only it. (GS 334)
The result of immersing ourselves in the truths of knowledge will be their incorporation,
and our eventual affirmation of them. This is the process of making truth a condition of
life. In Jill Marsden’s terms, we may say that this is to make the “feeling of life” one
experiences before this knowledge the joyful sensation of life’s enhancement, as opposed
to the pain of its hindrance, of confronting ideas that our instincts react against. Even if
the thought of eternal return that Nietzsche experienced near Lake Silvaplana was borne
in ecstasy, the thinker was nevertheless faced with the task of learning to love it:
Published in The Agonist—Vol. III, issue 2, July 2008
49
What shall we do with the rest of our lives—we who have spent the majority of
our lives in the most profound ignorance? We shall teach the teaching—it is the
most powerful means of incorporating [einzuverleiben] it in ourselves. (KSA 9:
11[141], translated by Keith Ansell Pearson)10
It is through the consideration of the task of incorporating truth that we can situate and
appreciate Jill Marsden’s explorations of the philosophy of ecstasy. Her commitment to
the pursuit of thinking beyond identity, which is suggested in the experience of ecstasy, is
itself an experiment in the pursuit and incorporation of “truth” (as the ultimate truth of
the flux of eternal becoming). Furthermore, her development of the “physiology of art” as
a philosophy of affectivity provides us with great insight into how thought and the body
are related, and thus furthers our understanding of the mechanism of incorporating
knowledge.
I should also point out that, whilst the content of Marsden’s book is largely concerned
with what type of knowledge is communicated in the throes of rapture, the self-body
relation which it describes by no means excludes affirmation (as self-overcoming)
outside of these extreme states. To think that the case would be to deny Marsden’s insight
that the body is not given for thought, and thus to make of ecstatic rapture a difference
experience in kind from ‘normal’ life (a transcendental experience, à la reflective
judgement in Kant), rather than a privileged intensification of it, in which the libidinal
undercurrents of life are revealed. And, finally, I should also warn against the impression
that, for Marsden, the thought of eternal recurrence is readily given in the experience of
ecstasy. Hers is, after all, also a philosophy of experimentation and transformation. The
thought of eternal return certainly is ecstatic, but, as she warns us, “What eternal return
will be for us is a matter of what we shall be for it—what we shall be capable of
embodying” (121).
This is only to describe and begin to engage with some of the thoughts that Jill Marsden
pursues in her book. One cannot adequately introduce all of its adventures here, which
10
Keith Ansell Pearson, ‘The Eternal Return of the Overhuman: The Weightiest Knowledge and the Abyss
of Light’: 2.
Published in The Agonist—Vol. III, issue 2, July 2008
50
also include the exploration of the idea of rapture as the precondition of artistic creation,
the notion that extreme states of health and sickness are the material conditions for
overcoming the form of the same, and the interpretation of mystical experience as the site
of thinking union without unity. As its modest subtitle suggests, the book does not
attempt to provide a finalised system of thought, but consists of interrelated
investigations into aspects of ecstatic experience. In doing this, using Nietzsche as the
site of multiple vectors of thought, Marsden also engages with the works of Deleuze and
Guattari, Bataille, Irigaray and Bergson amongst others.
Whilst I find an ultimate flaw in Marsden’s interpretation of affirmation, this book
demands to be read. It is a work of original and often highly incisive scholarship, which
contributes much to the task of thinking beyond the human condition. And what is truly
remarkable—an all-too-rare delight in academic writing—is that the book reads as
though it were conceived and written in ecstasy. It communicates, like an artwork,
something of the conditions of its genesis: the joy borne of rapture. The reader may be
‘affected’ by its thought for some time.
Published in The Agonist—Vol. III, issue 2, July 2008