Mind and Being—the Primacy of Panpsychism
Galen Strawson
to appear in Panpsychism: Philosophical Essays ed Brüntrup and Jaskolla (OUP, 2016). Final draft
Introduction
I’ll start with a metaphysical creed—four propositions. I’m confident that the first three are
true, and I suspect that the fourth is true, but I don't think one has to accept any of them to
agree with my principal thesis—the thesis of the primacy of panpsychism, the highly
unoriginal thesis that there are compelling reasons for favouring panpsychism above all
other positive substantive proposals about the fundamental nature of concrete reality.1
I’ll state the four propositions first in German because I like the way they sound in
German. [1] Stoff ist Kraft, [2] Wesen ist Werden, [3] Sein ist Sosein, [4] Ansichsein ist
Fürsichsein. These are identity claims—fully reversible. I’m not going to argue for them
but I’ll provide a few glosses.
1 Stoff ist Kraft
[1] Stoff ist Kraft.
Matter is force or as I will say energy:
[1] matter is energy.
Strictly speaking matter is only one form of concrete being, but I’ll use the word loosely to
mean all concrete stuff: all concrete being is energy—energy-activity, energy-stuff.
I’m using the word ‘energy’ as Heisenberg does when he writes that ‘energy is a
substance, … all particles are made of the same substance: energy’ (1958: 63, 71), and
putting aside the common use according to which ‘energy’ denotes the power of ‘doing
work’ contained in or possessed by a body or system of bodies. ‘All the elementary
particles are made of the same substance, which we may call energy or universal matter;
they are just different forms in which matter can appear …. In the most recent development
of modern physics this distinction between matter and force is completely lost, since every
field of force contains energy and in so far constitutes matter’ (Heisenberg 1958: 160, 149).
Heisenberg finds in this ‘the final proof for the unity of matter’ (p. 160).
I take this general position to be orthodoxy today (no doubt this is unwise). It’s also an
old view, if Aristotelian energeia can be understood as energy: “in Aristotle the concept
energeia coincides with that of reality. And Leibniz, too, declared: ‘quod non agit, non
1
In this paper I’m concerned with concrete being—the universe. I don't know whether it’s helpful to say that
there is abstract being, as opposed to and in addition to concrete being, but I’m going to put this question
aside.
existit’” (Schlick 1918-25, 181): what doesn’t act doesn’t exist. The most fundamental
characterization of substance is that which acts: “activity … is of the essence of substance”
(Leibniz 1714, 65).2
Some may find the equation of force, energy, power, and activity too quick or easy. I
think it’s eminently defensible—the evolution of the old notions dunamis and energeia into
the notions of dynamism and energy is highly significant. I also take it that the existence of
causation—of the “because something is, something else must be” phenomenon as it
concretely exists in nature3—is nothing over and above the existence of energy. One might
say that the causal laws for our universe describe the particular form of energy as it exists
in our universe—the behavioural form of energy as it exists in our universe.4
If spacetime is itself a concrete existent, something substantival, as I’m inclined to
suppose along with many others, rather than a mere container for concrete being, and if it is
in fact the only concrete existent, as a good number of physicists and cosmologists suppose,
if in other words spacetime is the universe, if
[A] Sein ist Raumzeit,
if [A] being is spacetime—then, given [1], spacetime is energy.5 If the existence of
spacetime is the existence of certain fields (electromagnetic, weak and strong nuclear,
gravitational, Higgs), or ultimately only one field, then the existence of the field or fields is
just a matter of the existence of energy.6
We may be wildly wrong about the nature of spacetime, insofar as our conception of
spacetime goes in any way beyond our best equations—even if our best equations are
essentially correct. So be it. I’ll take the word ‘spacetime’ to be a name for the actual
dimensionality of reality, the actual existence-dimension or Existenzraum of concrete
reality whatever its ultimate nature—a term that leaves room for the possibility (the
likelihood) that we are in certain ways bewilderingly wrong about it.
One point is worth noting straight away (I’ll return to it later). We certainly shouldn’t
suppose that having spatial existence entails having some sort of irreducible non-
2
Cf. also, strikingly, Faraday (1844, 140ff), Bohm (1957, §1.6), and many others (when I cite a work I give
the date of first publication, or occasionally the date of composition, while the page reference is to the edition
listed in the bibliography). I’m inclined to include Plato, who holds that “being is nothing other than dunamis”
(Plato c 360 BCE, 247d-e), i.e. potency, power, force. But this would need to be vigorously argued, given the
way in which Plato distinguishes between dunamis, potency, and energeia, actuality.
3
Kant 1781–7: B288. Kant’s formulation is entirely general and can be taken non-temporally.
4
The existence of power can’t be equated with the existence of something ‘merely’ dispositional—given one
common understanding of the word ‘disposition’. Just as there’s no energy without power so there’s no power
without actual, live energy (it would be superficial to think that the existence of vis inertiae doesn’t involve
the existence of energy).
5
I’ll use letters rather than numbers for primary propositions that I don't positively endorse in this paper
although I think some of them may be true.
6
Samuel Alexander endorses [A]: “Space-Time is the stuff of which matter and all things are specifications”
(Alexander 1924, vi). I’m leaving aside the ‘relational’ conception of space because I don't think anyone has
ever managed to make sense of it as a metaphysical position.
2
experiential stuff being, any more than we should suppose something we already know to
be false (given that there is space): that having spatial existence is incompatible with
experiential being.
I’m inclined to think that [1] is at bottom an a priori truth. Aristotle didn't wait for it to
be presented as a scientific discovery. The once popular idea of inert or powerless concrete
being is I believe incoherent,7 and the natural thought that powers require ‘categorical
grounds’ doesn’t require one to think that there is or can be any ‘real distinction’, in
Descartes’s sense, between a thing’s possession of the powers it possesses and the existence
of those powers’ categorical grounds, or that the existence of the categorical grounds can’t
be wholly a matter of the existence of energy. Granted that you can’t have powers without
‘categorical grounds’, so too you can’t have categorical grounds without powers. Imagine
an exhaustive specification of a thing x’s powers P and categorical properties C (the
specification of powers will be—benignly—infinite if it’s given in terms of x’s possible
effects on other things). It’s plausible that only something identical to x in respect of C can
possibly have precisely P and conversely that anything identical to x in respect of C must
have precisely P. In this case neither C nor P can possibly exist apart from the other, so
there’s no real distinction between them in Descartes’s sense, and where there’s no real
distinction between two things it’s plausible that they’re really identical.
So much for the first proposition.
2 Wesen ist Werden
[2] Wesen ist Werden,
i.e.
[2] being is becoming.
This is the essential (Wesen) nature of concrete being, of nature (Wesen). Everything is
process, in other familiar terms. Being is process. Being is doing, activity. A through-andthrough processual view of reality is mandatory. All concrete being is essentially timebeing—whatever exactly time is. Being is being. All being is in Kant’s phrase ‘always
already’ behaving, becoming, and of course conversely (Kant 1781–7, A346/B404).
[1] and [2] are close to
[5] Wirklich ist, was wirkt
—the actual is what has an effect.8 In the case of matter, Schopenhauer observes, “its being
7
8
Cf. Strawson (forthcoming b).
“Wirklich ist, was wirkt, was eine Macht, eine Potenz ist” (Frauenstädt 1840, 341).
3
[Daseyn] is its acting [Wirken]: and it is inconceivable that matter has any other being”.9 To
say this is not to ‘desubstantialize’ matter in any way, or to ‘operationalize’ our conception
of matter, and it is most emphatically not to suggest that matter is really only what we can
possibly observe (as per the fatal modern tendency to epistemologize metaphysics—or
metaphysicalize epistemology). It’s simply to express in a certain way the point that the
nature of concrete being is energy. The point is old, but we periodically lose hold of it.
David Lewis has misled many with his extraordinary view (perhaps a legacy of positivistic
empiricism) that the ‘intrinsic’ or ‘categorical’ nature of matter is or could be independent
of its behaviour.10
So much very briefly for [2]. There is of course a great deal more to be said about this.
3 Sein ist Sosein
[3] Sein ist Sosein.
This is harder to render in a single English sentence. I propose
[3] being is quality.
There’s no metaphysically fundamental distinction between substance and attribute (as
Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz, Kant, Nietzsche, and many others agree). There’s no
metaphysically fundamental distinction between the concrete being of substance, ‘thatness’,
and the concrete being of (intrinsic) propertiedness, ‘howness’, ‘thusness’, qualitativity.
There is no real distinction, in Descartes’s terms, between a concrete entity’s Sein and its
Sosein, when that entity is considered at any particular time. There’s no difference between
bare being (the barest that being can get) and how-being: between being and being-someway. Lewis is wrong to suppose that a thing’s behaviour (in any given context) could fail to
be wholly a function of its intrinsic or categorical nature or stuff being, for a thing’s
behaviour in any given context is simply (and wholly) part of its intrinsic or categorical
nature or stuff being. He is, however, right, on the present view, that concrete reality is “an
arrangement of qualities. And that is all” (Lewis 1986, x).
It’s obvious that there can’t be Sein without Sosein or Sosein without Sein. To be at all is
necessarily to be somehow, and to be somehow is necessarily to exist. The present stronger
claim—that there’s no real distinction, in the case of any particular thing or object o,
considered at any particular time t, between the totality of what constitutes the existence of
9
Schopenhauer 1819–59, §1.4; matter is “causality itself, objectively conceived” (Schopenhauer 1819-59,
§2.1.4); “matter is throughout pure Causality, its essence is Action in general” (Schopenhauer 1813, 97).
10
Two quick points on this view. [1] You can’t vary the nomic circumstances of a thing x—the laws of nature
governing x—while keeping x’s nature constant, because the laws are essentially constitutive of its nature. [2]
Even if you could, there would be no independence of behaviour from intrinsic nature. For x would behave in
the way it did, say W1, in nomic circumstances N1, wholly because of its intrinsic nature, and it would
behave in way W2 in nomic circumstances N2 wholly because of its intrinsic nature; etc.
4
o at t and the totality of what constitutes the existence of the (intrinsic/categorical
instantiated) propertiedness of o at that time—may seem less obvious, but it’s no less
secure. Neither o at t nor o’s (intrinsic/categorical instantiated) propertiedness at t can
coherently be supposed to exist apart from the other in any respect at all, let the
counterfactuals fall as they may. They are metaphysically identical—the same thing. (One
good way to put this is to say that there is a fundamental sense in which all there is is stuff,
substance. This is a truism, rightly heard, but it may not be easily heard by some.)
We can express this as a subthesis of [3]:
[3*] An object considered at any given time t = its (intrinsic instantiated concrete)
propertiedness at t.
The way in which object words and property words operate in everyday thought means that
this outright identity statement can sound plainly incorrect. In particular, the ease and
naturalness with which we use counterfactual idioms when talking about objects and their
properties can mislead us. We may for example be tempted to think that it is a sufficient
objection to [3*] to say something like: ‘This very object considered now at t could have
had different properties now at t from the properties it does in fact have’. In fact this is no
objection to [3*], but it can take a certain amount of effort to rethink one’s conception of
the phenomena that lead us to talk of objects, on the one hand, and the phenomena that lead
us to talk of instantiated properties, on the other hand, up to the point at which [3*] no
longer seems incorrect, but rather evidently true.11
Kant gets this exactly right, I think, when he says that “in their relation to substance,
accidents [or properties] are not really subordinated to it, but are the mode of existing of the
substance itself” (Kant 1781-7, A414/B441). There’s no sort of ontic subordinacy of the
object’s properties to the object itself, no sort of existential inequality or priority or
superiority or inferiority of any sort, no ontic dependence of either on the other, no
independence of either from the other. In the case of any concrete entity, again, its Sosein
(its being the way it is) is identical to its Sein (its being).
I take this claim to be a priori, however much language beguiles us to think otherwise.
There is really no other possible relation of thatness to howness. But it is also perhaps the
hardest of the four claims to grasp. Or rather it’s the hardest to hold on to, in such a way as
to be able to deploy it properly in one’s philosophical thinking. One can lose a theoretically
live grasp of it when one isn’t concentrating even if one endorses it whenever one focuses
on it without trying to do anything else. I think this is principally because of our deep
natural tendency to think of objects and their properties in counterfactual ways. These ways
of thinking are perfectly in order, and crucial for many ordinary purposes, but they pull
11
Cf. Strawson (2008, 279-281). We lose hold of the key point if we take the identity claim in [3*] to be just
a version of the ‘bundle’ theory of objects. The bundle theory of objects as standardly presented will always
seem intuitively unacceptable, and rightly so, because it retains the everyday conception of, and distinction
between, ‘object’ and ‘property’—the very conception that is undermined by insight into the identity claim.
5
against [3] and [3*] in a way that can easily throw us off track in metaphysics.
A good way to avoid philosophical trouble caused by the words ‘object’ and ‘property’
is to use the maximally neutral word ‘being’, which covers both of them. I’ll sometimes do
so. It’s also important to see that [2] and [3] make it as legitimate to talk of experience or
consciousness or experientiality as a kind of stuff as it is to talk of anything else—sugar,
lead, matter, energy—as a kind of stuff. This is another considerable stumbling block,
given current habits of thought; there’s nothing much I can do about this. It takes time to
habituate to the point, in spite of all the work that Russell, Whitehead and others put in, and
in spite of the fading away of the idea that the being of phenomena like spin and charge
requires the being of some further underlying distinct stuff to be the bearer of these
properties.12 Perhaps the best thing to say is that there is certainly no more reason to think
of matter as a kind of stuff than there is to think of experientiality as a kind of stuff. So if
one is comfortable with thinking of matter as a kind of stuff one should be—or needs to
become—equally comfortable with thinking of experientiality in this way.
Certainly experience requires a subject of experience. But this doesn’t mean we have to
fall back to a metaphysics of object and property, with the subject of experience as object
or substance possessing an ontologically distinct property: experience. What we have is the
process phenomenon subject-having-experience; or—in other terms—the process-stuff
experience, which is (necessarily) subject-or-subjectivity-involving process-stuff.
So much for the third proposition.
4 Ansichsein ist Fürsichsein
[4] Ansichsein ist Fürsichsein.
For something to be, to be at all, to be what it is considered wholly in itself or an sich in
Kant’s sense, is essentially for it to be for itself, in the familiar sense of this phrase
according to which for a being to be ‘for itself’ is for there to be something it is like to be it,
experientially. It is for it to be a conscious or experiencing being.13 So
[4] being is mind (experience)
Being is essentially experience-involving—where ‘experience’ denotes any sort of
conscious experience whatever, including the most primitive forms of ‘mere’ sensation. [4]
is a form of panpsychism or panexperientialism (I use these terms interchangeably, taking
the psychical to be essentially a matter of conscious—experiential—goings-on). It’s
12
I use ‘phenomenon’ as a completely general word for any sort of existent that carries no implication as to
ontological category (the trouble with the perfectly general word ‘entity’ is that it is now standardly
understood to refer specifically to things or substances); and suppress its meaning of appearance.
13
There is a basic sense in which all consciousness is a form of self-consciousness, and Fürsichsein may also
be linked more specifically to the notion of self-consciousness.
6
equivalent to
[6] Sein ist Bewusstsein.
It’s a form of pure panpsychism, which I here take to be the view that experientiality is all
there is to the intrinsic nature of concrete reality (note that on this view, the existence of
subjects of experience can’t be supposed to be anything ontologically over and above the
existence of experiencing). The milder version says that this is how things are in this
universe. The stronger version says that this is all that being can be—that panpsychism is
necessarily true.
I think this may be so—that concrete being has in fact no other possible form than
energy, and that energy has in fact no other possible form than experientiality. But it
certainly isn’t a priori viewed from here. We can’t hope to prove that the notion of nonexperiential concrete being is incoherent, even if it’s a priori in God’s physics, or rather his
entirely general theory of being, his ‘concretics’, his necessarily utterly comprehensive
account of what can concretely exist. Still, the great William James holds that “our only
intelligible notion of an object in itself is that it should be an object for itself”, and that “a
thing in itself … must be an experience for itself” (Perry 1935, 446). (See §21 below for a
suggestion about why this might be so.)
Note that I’m understanding experience to entail mind (and conversely). One important
terminological alternative is to define mind more narrowly, taking it that mind entails some
sort of intelligence, and that experience as just defined—the stuff of reality, according to
the present view—may exist without mind.14 This may be what Russell and William James
do, I believe, when they propose that the basic stuff of reality is ‘sensation’ or ‘pure
experience’ respectively, and nevertheless declare themselves to be ‘neutral monists’ who
hold that the stuff of reality is neither mental nor physical. On my view their positions are
forms of panpsychism. But the disagreement is, so far, merely terminological.
5 The Basic Creed
So here’s the basic creed: being is energy, process, quality, mind (experience). These four
things are, in this universe, all the same thing—which may be spacetime (in which case
there is no real distinction between concrete being and its Existenzraum or dimensionality).
Once the restriction to concrete being is in place the four initial terms—Stoff, Wesen, Sein,
Ansichsein—come to the same thing: Wirklichkeit—the actual. That’s the proposal. It’s the
backbone of the metaphysics I favour: identity metaphysics. The principal characteristic of
identity metaphysics is that it finds identity where other metaphysical positions, dancing to
the panpipes of language, find distinctness and difference. In the background stand
14
One may then suppose that mind—mind proper—is always the result of some sort of evolutionary process,
although experience is not.
7
powerful thinkers—Spinoza, Leibniz, James, Nietzsche among others, perhaps also
Whitehead—although none, perhaps, would accept the whole of the basic creed
unreservedly.
Perhaps I should say that I’m not arguing, so I’m not begging questions. I’m offering a
picture—a sketch—of how I think things may be.
6 Natura Non Facit Saltum: No Radical Emergence
Let me first add a version of an old metaphysical thesis to the ontological theses [1]–[6]:
[7] natura non facit saltum.
i.e., roughly, there are no absolute or radical qualitative discontinuities in nature.15 I take
[7]—No Jumps—to be a solid part of any sound naturalism, and from [7], as I understand
it, one can derive the No Radical Emergence thesis as I understand it, i.e.
[8] there is no radical emergence
(some may think that [8] is effectively the same as [7]). And from [8], I submit, we can
derive
[9] the experiential (experiential being) can’t emerge from the wholly and utterly nonexperiential (wholly and utterly non-experiential being)
—because any such emergence would have to be radical in the impossible way.
I’m not going to argue for [8] and [9].16 The general idea is simple. Emergence—emergence, no less—can’t be brute. In all genuine (non-radical) cases of emergence of one
thing from another there’s a fundamental sense in which the emergent phenomenon, say Y,
is wholly dependent on—somehow wholly flows from—that which it emerges from, say X.
Otherwise it simply won’t be true after all to say that Y is emergent from X, for some part
or aspect of Y will have come from somewhere else. (I understand emergence in what I
take to be a standard way as paradigmatically a matter of constitution, not causation: in the
present case, it would be a matter of individually non-experiential phenomena coming to
constitute experiential phenomena simply by coming together or being arranged in a certain
way—as non-liquid H2O molecules together come to constitute something liquid.)
Many will agree. Others won’t. Two things seem worth saying straight away. The first
is that it’s metaphysically far more extravagant and anti-naturalistic to reject [7] the No
Jumps thesis, and postulate radical emergence of the experiential from the non-experiential,
15
On this qualitative construal [7] is wholly compatible with all quantum phenomena and all phenomena cited
in support of ‘saltationism’ in the theory of evolution.
16
For some arguments cf. Strawson (2006, 60-7); cf. also Seager (2012), Chalmers (2016). Compare
Jackson’s arguments for ‘a priori physicalism’ (cf. e.g. Jackson 2003).
8
than it is to postulate non-radical emergence of the human experiential from the non-human
experiential—whatever difficulties the second idea may also seem to raise (e.g. the
‘combination problem’—see §19 below).
Secondly, and more importantly, one doesn’t need to meet those who don't agree with
No Radical Emergence with an argument to support it. All one has to do is ask them
politely why they think anything non-experiential exists; especially when this belief forces
them to endorse radical emergence, given that they’re realists about experience.
On this more later. First, some more declarations.
7 Real Naturalism
Like many, I’m a monist, a stuff monist, an only one-kind-of-stuff monist:
[10] stuff/kind monism is true.
I’m putting aside only-one-thing monism, thing monism, according to which
[B] there is only one thing (object, entity, substance) in concrete reality,
for purposes of discussion, although, like many, I’m attracted to one version of it, i.e. [A]:
the view that spacetime is a single thing—the universe.17
I’m not only a stuff monist. Like many again, I’m a materialist or physicalist monist (I
use the words ‘materialist’ and ‘physicalist’ interchangeably)—someone who holds that
everything that concretely exists in our universe is wholly physical:
[11] materialism/physicalism is true.
I also take it that everything that concretely exists is wholly natural—in no way
supernatural or non-natural. So I’m an outright ontological naturalist.18
I am however a real naturalist, a real materialist—unlike some who call themselves
‘naturalists’. I don’t disagree with them because they believe in the existence of something
I judge to be supernatural. On the contrary: I disagree with them because, overtly or (more
often) covertly, they doubt or deny the existence of a wholly natural concrete phenomenon
we know to exist: the phenomenon of consciousness—conscious experience—experiential
‘what-it’s-likeness’—the phenomenological character of experience—the subjective
qualitative character of experience. I understand all these five common phrases to denote
the same thing, which I’ll call ‘experience’, instead of ‘consciousness’, because the word
17
It is arguable that Descartes holds [B] with respect to concrete material reality; Spinoza holds it with respect
to all concrete reality. Among those who endorse this view today are Horgan and Potrč (2008). Schaffer calls
this view ‘existence monism’ (cf. e.g. Schaffer 2007; 2010).
18
I’m putting aside ethics where I’m not a naturalist—if being a moral realist excludes being a naturalist.
9
‘consciousness’ has been used in too many different ways.
So I’m an outright realist about experience, a real realist about experience:
[12] there is experiential concrete reality.19
Any real naturalist must be a real realist about experience, because experience is the most
certainly known concretely existing general natural phenomenon, and is indeed the first
thing any scientist encounters when they try to do science.
I say that I’m a real realist about experience because some who claim to be realists
about experience aren’t really any such thing. What do I mean by real realism about
experience? The quickest way to say what it is is to say that it’s to hold exactly the same
general view about what experience is (colour experience, say, or pain experience, or taste
experience), considered specifically as experience, that one held before one did any
philosophy, e.g. when one was thirteen or ten or six. One then had an entirely correct view.
If people ask what that view is I’ll ask them to think back to their childhood. If they say
they still don't know I won’t believe them.
It’s important to note here that we not only know exactly what particular conscious
experiences are like, and therefore what they are, considered specifically as such. We also
know what experience is generally considered—even though we have direct experience
only of certain limited kinds of experience available to humans. It’s because we acquire an
essentially general understanding of what conscious experience is, in having conscious
experience and in being the sophisticated concept-exercising creatures that we are, that we
can easily and coherently imagine that there may be creatures—aliens, perhaps—that have
experience quite unlike ours, and perhaps unimaginable by us.
So I’m a real naturalist and a real materialist—a materialist in the sense in which every
materialist was a materialist until some time well into the twentieth century. That is, I’m
someone who thinks that everything that exists is wholly physical and who is also fully
realist about experience or consciousness. At the same time I know that ‘physical’ is a
‘natural-kind’ term, like ‘gold’, or ‘tiger’, and that we may be very ignorant (or plain
wrong) about the nature of the physical in various ways—if and insofar as the physical is
anything more than experience. So really the core meaning of ‘physical’ for me is just:
‘concretely real’.
But in that case why do I say I’m a materialist? Because I believe that
[13] the claims of physics apply to everything that concretely exists
and also that
[14] many of the claims of physics are true of everything that concretely exists
19
One can always substitute the word ‘consciousness’ if one wishes.
10
(e.g. f = ma, the inverse square laws, etc.). And I also know something that was a
philosophical commonplace in the early twentieth century, and indeed earlier, and is
fortunately becoming one again. I know that physics is “just a set of rules and equations”,
in Hawking’s words (Hawking 1988, 174).20 I know that
[15] physics can’t characterize the intrinsic non-structural nature of concrete reality in any
respect at all
and a fortiori that
[16] physics has no terms with which to characterize the intrinsic experiential-qualitative
nature of concrete reality,
whether only part of concrete reality has an experiential-qualitative nature, as we usually
suppose, or whether all of it does, as panpsychists suppose. I know that physics is simply
silent on the question of the intrinsic non-structural nature of reality.
We ordinarily suppose that we have some positive non-structural conception of the intrinsic
nature of space or spacetime. So be it—so long as we’re clear that this conception of space
or spacetime goes beyond anything that the equations of physics tell us. One of the greatest
difficulties that arise in the metaphysics of mind is precisely that we standardly and perhaps
irrepressibly suppose that physics supports the accuracy of our basic imaginative picture (I
mean ‘imaginative’ literally) of what spatiality is—and of what matter is. It doesn’t.
So physics is silent about the intrinsic non-structural nature of reality. The question is
then this (it’s an ancient question, but I’ll give it again in Hawking’s words): “What is it
that breathes fire into the equations and makes a universe for them to describe?” (Hawking
1988, 174). What is it that the equations are true of? What is the fundamental, intrinsic,
non-structural or stuff nature of the concrete reality that the true statements of physics are
true of?
Call this fundamental intrinsic non-structural stuff nature x. The relevant options are (i) x
is wholly experiential (the pure panpsychist option), and (ii) x is partly experiential and
partly non-experiential (as most people suppose). I’m ignoring the third option, (iii) x is
wholly non-experiential, because it denies the existence of experience.21 The central claim
of this paper is that (i) is the best option—that panpsychism is the most plausible theory of
x, given a naturalist—materialist monist—outlook.
20
Cf. also Greg Rosenberg (1999; 2004) and Ladyman et al. (2007). Compare Descartes: “all the properties”
of material things “which I clearly and distinctly understand are … comprised within the subject matter of
pure mathematics” (Descartes 1641, 2.55). Poincaré puts the point very vividly in chapter 10 of Science and
Hypothesis (cf. Poincaré 1903).
21
All theories that claim to give a reductive account of experience in terms of non-experiential phenomena—
e.g. behaviourism in all its forms and all full-on versions of functionalism—deny the existence of experience.
They claim not to on the ground that reduction is not elimination; but reduction is elimination in this case (cf.
Strawson forthcoming a).
11
I’ll now flag an assumption that is built into the question, and then make one more
general metaphysical assumption specifically for the purposes of discussion.
8 Two more Assumptions
The assumption built into the question is that for any concrete entity x one can always
distinguish between x’s structural features and something about x that isn’t just a matter of
structure, something in virtue of which x has or exemplifies the structure it does, something
that is therefore not itself just a matter of structure.
The assumption can seem very secure but it has been questioned. Ontic structural
realists22 claim precisely that structure is all that concretely exists:
[C] concrete being is (wholly a matter of) structure.
And while Max Newman’s claim that “it seems necessary to give up the ‘structure–quality’
division of knowledge in its strict form” (Newman 1928, 147) is an epistemological claim,
it may be thought to point forward to an ontological proposal.
If one takes the structural properties of a concrete thing x to be properties that can be
fully characterized in abstract, logico-mathematical terms, as I do, then I think one can
safely conclude that [C] must be false. One can conclude that there must be more to x than
merely its structural properties, on the seemingly secure ground that there must be more to
concrete being than abstract being.23 If, however, one understands structure in a richer way
as something concrete—as ‘causal structure’ or ‘spacetime structure’ or (in a
Schopenhauerian-Russellian fashion) ‘spacetimecause structure’—then one may be able to
link [C] to [A], and also—via the power-energy-causality equation—to the basic creed [1][5].24
The further assumption that I’m going to make for the purposes of discussion is that
[D] there are a great many ultimate constituents of physical reality.
[D] is sometimes called ‘smallism’.25 It’s very widely accepted, but—as is now clear—I’m
not sure it’s true. It would obviously be false if any version of [B] (thing monism) were
true, and although it seems extraordinarily difficult to understand how any version of [B]
could be true, given the seemingly evident and irreducible plurality of concrete things, it
may yet be, as already remarked, that [A] there is a fundamental sense in which spacetime
22
Cf. e.g. Ladyman et al. (2007).
Ladyman and Ross appear to bite this bullet: “we reject the dichotomy between the abstract and the
concrete, and between the substantival and the structural” (Ladyman et al. 2007, 186).
24
It’s also arguable that [C] entails [B] on the ground that the universe must be correctly describable as a
single structure if [C] is true.
25
Cf. e.g. Wilson (2004), Coleman (2006).
23
12
is indeed the only thing there is, and that all the particle phenomena recognized in the
current standard model are just “various modes of vibration of tiny one-dimensional rips in
spacetime known as strings” (Weinberg 1997, 20). On another thing-monist view, the wave
function is the only thing that exists.
Nevertheless I’ll assume [D] at this point, for many philosophers believe it to be true.
They also take it to give rise to a special and acute difficulty for any panpsychist theory: the
so-called ‘combination problem’. So they might not be impressed by any argument for the
primacy of panpsychism that assumed [B], thing monism, and so assumed that [D] was
false.
9 The Hylal
With this in place, consider the proposal that
[17] experientiality is one possible fundamental kind of stuff and non-experientiality is
another.
This seems unexceptionable at first. ‘Experiential’ and ‘non-experiential’ are mutually
exclusive high-level type terms or ‘kind-determinables’ both of which, we may suppose,
can have very different more determinate values.26 We know this is so in the case of
experiential stuff, in having sound experience, colour-experience, taste-experience, and so
on, and we naturally assume it may also be so in the case of non-experiential stuff. We take
it that there is wholly non-experiential stuff in our universe and the supposition that there
might be radically different kinds of wholly non-experiential stuff (X-stuff, Y-stuff, Zstuff) in other possible universes seems plainly coherent.27
There is however an asymmetry when it comes to our understanding of the experiential
and our understanding of the non-experiential. In the case of experience we have a positive
grasp of the sense in which all possible experience is, simply in being experience, the same
fundamental kind of thing. Even if the particular qualitative character of Martian
experience is radically unimaginable by us we still have a firm positive grasp of the
fundamental kind of thing it is simply in knowing in general what experience is (see §7
above). When we consider the non-experiential, by contrast, we suppose that we could
possibly have a good grasp of the fundamental nature of the local non-experiential stuff
while really having no idea at all about the fundamental nature of X-stuff or Y-stuff or Zstuff in other possible worlds. We know what experience is in an extremely general but still
positively substantive way that allows us to see that experientiality constitutes a single
fundamental kind, a single fundamental natural kind—a single fundamental qualitative
26
Compare ‘colour’, ‘shape’, and ‘animal’, each of which have many more determinate ‘values’—‘red’,
‘blue’, ‘round’, ‘square’, ‘cat’, ‘dog’.
27
It may be, in fact, that non-experiential concrete stuff is not possible. I’ll consider this suggestion at the end.
13
kind, one might say, using ‘qualitative’ in a natural highly general way that has nothing
specially to do with experience. The trouble is that we don't know what the non-experiential
is in the same sort of way, a way that allows us to say that it constitutes a single
fundamental natural kind.
It’s not hard to see why this is so: it’s that we don't have a positive, substantive, general
conception of the non-experiential at all. ‘Non-experiential’ is a merely negative,
maximally general word that can as far as we know sweep up radical qualitative differences
that don't fall under a single qualitative kind in the way that all kinds of experience
knowably do.
How can we adjust the proposal so that it concerns two genuine fundamental kinds? It
suffices to relativize the experiential/non-experiential opposition to a particular universe,
e.g. our own, replacing the maximally general negative term ‘non-experiential’ by a more
specific positive term that denotes the particular fundamental kind of non-experiential stuff
we take ourselves to encounter in our actual world.
Which term will suit? We obviously can’t use the term ‘physical’ or ‘material’, as real
materialists who hold that experientiality is wholly physical. I propose ‘hylal’, derived from
the old Greek word for wood, which came to be used as a general term for matter conceived
of as something entirely non-experiential (consider Berkeley’s ‘Hylas’). All we need to
stipulate for present purposes is that ‘x is or has hylal being’ entails ‘x is or has nonexperiential being’—whatever else is or isn’t true of x.
10 Experiential-Hylal Monism?
With the term ‘hylal’ in place, [17] becomes
[18] experientiality is one possible fundamental kind of stuff and hylality is another.
We can then consider the proposal that
[19] reality may be fundamentally both experiential and hylal in nature
– where this is put forward as a stuff-monist proposal. On this view, the fundamental
natural intrinsic properties of concrete reality include both experiential and hylal (hence
non-experiential) properties, even though [10] stuff monism is true. When we consider
physical stuff, the only fundamental kind of stuff there is, we find both experiential stuff
and hylal stuff.
If [10] stuff monism is true, as we are assuming, [18] rules out [19]. For if [18] is true,
[19] posits two fundamental kinds of stuff and is a version of dualism. So if one wants to
continue to be a monist, and a real realist about experience, and hang on to non-experiential
stuff, in this case hylal stuff, as many do (it’s the only way to resist panpsychism), one has
to suppose that the single fundamental kind of stuff may be fundamentally both14
experiential-and-non-experiential in nature: that experientiality and non-experientiality,
although essentially opposed, can possibly co-exist as a single kind of stuff.28
I’ll call this position ‘experiential-hylal monism’—‘EH monism’ for short: ‘E’ for
experiential and ‘H’ for ‘hylal’. Is EH monism possible? We can see straight away that no
portion of E being can be H being, given that being H entails being non-E. And here I think
we see the gain in clarity of giving up ‘property’ talk for ‘being’ talk.
Objection: It isn’t a gain in clarity. It’s an occlusion of a crucial metaphysical possibility.
Of course H being can’t be E being, but a portion of concrete being can possess both E
properties and H properties. This is plain even when we restrict attention to ‘fundamental
natural intrinsic’ properties, as you are doing here. Look, a human being can possess both E
and H parts and properties.
Well, this could possibly be true of human beings—if there is some H stuff in our
universe (so that pure panpsychism is false). But, first, it directly begs the question to say
that it’s obviously true because human beings certainly have both experiential properties
and spatial properties, if one understands ‘spatial’ in the ordinary way according to which
space-occupying properties are essentially or at least certainly non-experiential properties.
Our ignorance of the nature of the spatial rules out this proposal—even apart from the
tendency among some leading cosmologists to question whether spacetime is
fundamentally real.
Secondly, even if it could be true that things like human beings possess both E
properties and H properties, I don't think it could true in such a way that EH monism is or
could be true. This, I think, is one of the places where property talk leads us grievously
astray. It beguiles us into believing in the coherence of metaphysical possibilities that are in
fact illusory, given Sein ist Sosein. It seems to allow for the possibility that a portion of
concrete being may possess both fundamental natural intrinsic E properties and
fundamental natural intrinsic H properties without being ultimately wholly factorable into
wholly E portions and wholly H portions. In that case, however, some not-furtherfactorable or ultimate parts are both irreducibly E and irreducibly H, i.e. impossibly,
irreducibly both E stuff and non-E stuff.
Sein ist Sosein shows up the impossibility. Whatever one thinks about how properties
may possibly co-exist, concrete being is wholly qualitativity, concrete qualitativity,
according to Sein ist Sosein, and E qualitativity can’t be non-E qualitativity and conversely.
So E qualitativity and H qualitativity can’t possibly coexist in one non-factorable portion of
28
Compare Regius’s suggestion (there is little doubt that he is reporting a view that Descartes also
entertained): ‘some philosophers … hold that mentality/consciousness [cogitatio] and extension are attributes
which are present in certain substances, as in subjects; [and] since these attributes are not opposites but
[merely] different, there is no reason why mentality/consciousness should not be an attribute of some sort coexisting with extension in the same subject, though the one [attribute] is not included in the concept of the
other. For whatever we can conceive of can exist. Now, it is conceivable that mentality is something of this
sort; for it does not imply a contradiction. Therefore it is possible that mentality is something of this sort. So
those who assert that we clearly and distinctly conceive human mentality as necessarily really distinct [in
Descartes’s sense] from body are mistaken’ (Regius 1647: 294–5).
15
being (a portion of being that isn’t ultimately made up of distinct non-overlapping portions
of E qualitativity and H qualitativity). In order to do this they would need something—the
object-as-opposed-to-the-properties, the ‘subject’ or ‘bearer’ of the properties—that ‘has’
them and that is not itself wholly a matter of qualitativity. But there is no such thing—for
Sein ist Sosein.
If this is right, EH monism fails. The attempt to describe it while respecting Sein ist
Sosein pushes us inexorably back to dualism. (I trust that the point doesn't depend
essentially on Sein ist Sosein.)
The picture will continue to appeal—the picture according to which a portion of singlestuff being can have both E and H properties without being factorable into E portions and H
portions. I think this is the way many aspiring real materialists tend to think—in a vague
quasi-pictorial way—about neural goings-on that are experiential goings-on. It’s very easy
to slip back into this, in my experience. One pictures the neural goings-on—the sweeping
nets and waves of electrochemical activity flickering across great connected skeins of
neurons—as having intrinsically irreducibly H (hence non-E) features. One then thinks that
these intrinsically H goings-on are in at least some of their parts or features also E goingson. But Sein ist Sosein blocks this when it’s thought through. For again, and crudely, (i)
things are in the end wholly ‘made of’ qualities (Sein ist Sosein), (ii) and E and H are
incompatible qualities, so (iii) nothing can be made of both at exactly the same place.29
There’s wide scope for missing the point, given the plasticity of property talk. I can’t
hope to meet all objections or convince those committed to the traditional conception of
properties. I think many who count themselves as materialists will be unable to give up the
idea that we know in some fundamental—perhaps Moorean—way what space is. (I was
unable to give it up in Strawson 2003a, §8.) We are confident we know in some deep way
what space is, however wrong we also are about it, and in particular know that having
spatial properties like shape properties essentially involves having non-E stuff properties,
and so know—given that we accept that conscious experiences are brain states—that there
are things that have both E properties and non-E properties.
A first reply might be that a thing’s particular shape isn’t a matter of the intrinsic nature
of the stuff it’s made of, and that we already know that experiential stuff can be spatial
stuff. The main reply targets the presumption that a thing can’t possibly occupy space
29
Objection: we allow that monism—physicalism—may be true even if there are irreducibly different
(perhaps essentially non-interconvertible) ‘fundamental particles’. Why can’t we similarly allow that monism
may be true when there are irreducibly different (essentially non-interconvertible) types of fundamental
stuff—E stuff and H (non-E) stuff?
The first reply is a question: why bother, given that there is no good theoretical reason to posit H stuff? A
further reply is that particles are emergent phenomena according to quantum field theory, plausibly all ‘made
of’ the same kind of stuff. One can also question the non-interconvertibility of fundamental particles (see the
discussion of ‘fungibility’ in §16) and note that the view that the fundamental entities are strings with
different vibrational characteristics creates no evident difficulty for stuff monism. More generally, we take
ourselves to have strong reasons for holding that all the fundamental particles are of the same fundamental
kind. In the case of E stuff and H stuff, by contrast, we know the fundamental nature of E stuff, and H stuff is
defined as non-E.
16
without having without some non-experiential stuff being. This presumption may be deeply
woven into our intuitive conception of space, as remarked, and some may be too deeply
committed to it to take seriously the possibility that it may be false. They will have to face
the fact that it appears to be incompatible with any realistic (genuinely experienceacknowledging) version of stuff monism that retains the idea that concrete reality is spatial.
11 The Untenability of Neutral Monism
EH monism isn’t a version of neutral monism—the view, to quote Russell, that “both mind
[E, on the present terms] and matter [H, on the present terms] are composed of a neutralstuff which, in isolation, is neither mental [E] nor material [H]” (Russell 1921, 25). It’s the
precise opposite—not neutral monism but doubly committed monism, both-and monism as
opposed to neither-nor neutral monism. What the two views have in common as monisms
is that they want to accord the same reality status to E being and H being while remaining
monist.
Can neutral monism do better than EH monism in this respect? Could E and H be
genuinely real properties of things while somehow emerging from some more fundamental
underlying stuff which is neither E nor H but rather—let us say—( عpronounced “ayn”),
where to be fundamentally عis to be fundamentally both wholly non-E and wholly non-H?
The short answer is no, but I’ll spell it out a bit. عcan’t be neither E nor non-E, on pain
of logical impossibility. And it has to be non-E, since it would otherwise be E, and so not
neutral between E and H (it would also be panpsychist). عmust therefore be a kind of nonE stuff which is different from H non-E stuff. There is no other possibility.
But this isn’t a real possibility on the present view. It’s ruled out by [7] No Jumps or
equally [8] No Radical Emergence, which not only lead to
[9] E stuff can’t emerge from wholly and utterly non-E stuff (e.g. )ع
but also to
[20] H stuff can’t emerge from wholly and utterly non-H stuff (e.g. )ع
Objection: How can you rule out the possibility that something is in itself wholly non-E
and wholly non-H but is nonetheless genuinely protoexperiential and protohylal in such a
way that E and H can emerge from it? After all, you yourself allow there are are deep
respects in which we’re radically ignorant of the fundamental nature of things.30
I admit our ignorance, but remain firm in commitment to No Jumps and No Radical
30
Cf. Stoljar (2006a). Stoljar points out that I sometimes appeal to radical ignorance in argument, e.g. citing
‘the silence of physics’ against the view that we have any reason to believe in non-experiential being, and at
other times reject appeals to radical ignorance in arguments made against me, e.g. when standing up for No
Radical Emergence. This is true but it is not I think a difficulty.
17
Emergence. The idea that something can be wholly non-experiential but nonetheless
‘protoexperiential’ will always seem attractive. It is after all the standard view of the
evolution of consciousness like ours, according to which biological experientiality (human
or canine or feline, etc) evolved from wholly non-experiential origins. But No Jumps and
No Radical Emergence are part of the deep structure of naturalism. We have no reason to
believe that nature ever makes ontological jumps of the sort forbidden by [7] and we have
very good reason to believe that it doesn’t.
I don’t, however, need to make this move. All I need to do is to reissue the polite
enquiry I made earlier. Why does anyone think anything non-experiential exists at all? I
think the polite enquiry is devastating and I’ll return to it. I know that some will be
unimpressed by it, and by the commitment to [7] and [8], so it’s fortunate that there’s
another way of showing the inadequacy of neutral monism.
The term ‘neutral monism’ is used in many ways, most of which appear to be ultimately
panpsychist or ‘idealist’. But there’s one central straightforwardly ontological way of
understanding what it is (Russell and James seem driven principally by empiricist
epistemological considerations) which appears to be ruled out by Sein ist Sosein. For
according to genuinely ontological neutral monism, E and H are fully and unqualifiedly
real, natural, categorical features of concrete reality—they’re irreducibly real features, not
just appearances of some sort, even though there’s supposed to be a key sense in which
they’re not fundamental features. Now Sein ist Sosein states that the complete stuff being of
a thing at any time isn’t really distinct from the stuff being of its real, natural categorical
propertiedness at that time. So, given Sein ist Sosein, it seems that we can’t really defend
any sense in which the fundamental nature of concrete reality is ultimately neither E nor H.
The words ‘ultimate’, ‘fundamental’, and ‘intrinsic’ can’t help (one can presumably add
‘intrinsic’ in the sense of ‘non-relational’ to ‘real, natural, and categorical’ above). Nor
does one need to endorse full-blooded Sein ist Sosein to reach this result; it’s enough to
hold that the real, natural categorical propertiedness of x is at least part of what constitutes
the being of x.
It seems, then, that neutral monism can’t help with the ‘mind-body problem’, when it’s
understood in this natural straightforwardly ontological way. So if EH monism is no better,
as I have argued, it looks as if we must either we go back to dualism, which is not I think a
serious option, or head in the direction of panpsychism.31
12 Experience Entails an Experiencer
So here I stand—a naturalist materialist monist who’s wondering about the nature of
concrete reality and who knows that the only general thing he knows for certain about
31
In Strawson (2003a, 50) I argue that we can never have good reason to prefer dualism (or any pluralism)
over monism, so long as we posit causal interaction between the two supposedly distinct substances. Note that
Sein ist Sosein also entails the incoherence of so-called property dualism.
18
concrete reality is that experience exists. I find myself being pushed to acknowledge that
panpsychism is the most plausible form of monism or indeed materialism. I’m aware that
[21] experience entails an experiencer
so I’m going to have to allow that there are as many experiencers as there are genuinely
ontologically distinct portions of experience—even though this may appear to make things
more difficult for me as a fledgling panpsychist.
Some philosophers have questioned [21]—wrongly because all experience is necessarily
experience-for; experience for someone-or-something. Experience is necessarily
experiencing. It’s necessarily had, felt, experienced by something. In this immoveable
sense there is necessarily an experiencer whenever there’s experience. So anyone who
prefers the term ‘panexperientialism’ to the term ‘panpsychism’, on the ground that
‘panexperientialism’ allows for the possibility that there can be experience without an
experiencer, has gone wrong (in a way that isn’t endorsed by Hume, it should be said, or by
Buddhists). Note that to insist that an experience entails an experiencer isn’t to claim that
the experiencer must be irreducibly ontically distinct from the experience or last longer
than the experience. It’s not to favour any particular hypothesis about the actual concrete
realization of the experiencer/experiential-content structure that is attributable to any
episode of experience.
13 A Global Replace
So here I am. I already know that the most parsimonious hypothesis compatible with the
data is that concrete reality—the stuff that realizes the concretely existing structure that
physics picks up on—is wholly a matter of experience, experiencing, experientiality.
Experience like ours certainly exists and it follows, given No Jumps or No Radical
Emergence, that experience must be among the fundamental properties of concrete reality.
(To try to hold on to non-experiential being by holding that reality is non-experiential in its
fundamental nature but is nevertheless and at the same time ‘protoexperiential’ seems to be
to try to paper over a crack in reality with a word. The crack—or chasm—remains
untouched.)
So when it comes to considering the question of the fundamental nature of concrete
reality the choice lies between supposing that both experientiality and some form of nonexperientiality like hylality are among the fundamental properties and supposing that only
experientiality is. I haven’t been able to make sense of the dual option, compatibly with
retaining monism, and I don't think there could ever be a good argument for dualism, so
long as the two stuffs posited by dualism are supposed to interact causally (briefly, I don't
see what argument could undermine the claim that causal interaction is a sufficient
condition of same substancehood). So I seem to be forced into panpsychism.
Can this last position really be said to be a form of materialism? Surely—the point
19
should be familiar by now. Many materialists hold that all concrete being is simply energy
existing in one form or another—i.e. [1]. The panpsychist proposal is simply that the
intrinsic nature of this energy is experientiality. The panpsychist hypothesis performs a
‘global replace’ on the objects of physics as ordinarily conceived. In so doing leaves the
whole of physics—everything that is true in physics—in place. So too for all the other
sciences. I’m a robust realist about physical reality, the theory of evolution, and so on, but I
know of no argument that gives us any good reason to suppose that there is any nonexperiential concrete reality.
The claim that experience is all that exists isn’t the incoherent claim that everything that
exists exists only in or ‘in’ some mind or other (that’s incoherent because a mind can’t exist
only in or ‘in’ itself). It has nothing to do with Berkeleyan idealism, or phenomenalism, and
it certainly isn’t committed to the implausible view that tables and chairs are subjects of
experience. It leaves the physical world untouched, as ‘out there’, relative to each one of us,
as it ever was—however inadequate our idea of its Existenzraum or dimensionality.
Objection: so there’s no distinction between materialism and what amounts to a form of
‘absolute idealism’.
There is a distinction if ‘absolute idealism’ implies [B] thing monism; but not if it’s just
a form of pure panpsychism. I hope you don't think this is comic or absurd, because it looks
as if it’s materialism’s best guess as to the nature of the concrete reality about which
physics says many true things. Eddington and Whitehead saw this clearly nearly 100 years
ago. You don't have to call it ‘materialism’ (‘physicalism’) if you don't want to. I continue
to call it ‘materialism’ (‘physicalism’) because, once again, concrete reality understood in
this way is what physics describes in its own magnificent and highly abstract way and says
many true things about (e = mc2, the inverse square laws, the periodic table, etc.), things
which I take to hold good of everything that concretely exists.
Objection: But still—why not suppose that the basic nature of concrete reality is nonexperiential rather than experiential?
In that case we face again all the problems posed by No Jumps and No Radical Emergence.
Suppose those problems solved. Then I reply to your question—‘Why suppose that the
basic nature of concrete reality is experiential?’—with another question: ‘Why suppose that
it’s non-experiential—either in its basic nature or in any respect at all?’ What evidence is
there for the existence of non-experiential reality, as opposed to experiential reality? None.
There is zero observational evidence for the existence of non-experiential reality—even
after we allow in a standard realist way that each of us encounters a great deal in concrete
reality that is not his or her own experience. Nor will there ever be any. All there is is one
great big wholly ungrounded wholly question-begging theoretical intuition or conviction.
Objection: There isn’t any evidence that the intrinsic nature of reality is wholly
experiential either.
True—but we know that some of it is experiential. We know it for certain because
[22] In the case of experience, the having is the knowing.
20
To have experience is not only to be directly acquainted with the fundamental nature of
experience—at least in certain respects. It’s also of course to know that the experiential
exists. The view that there is any non-experiential concrete reality is, by contrast, wholly
ungrounded. It’s a radically and irredeemably verification-transcendent belief. Hume knew
this. So did many others, including Quine, who famously judged that physical objects that
are assumed to be non-experiential are “posits comparable, epistemologically, to the gods
of Homer” (Quine 1951, 44)
14 Ignorance and Repugnance
Objection: It’s an old point that there’s an evident and fundamental ‘repugnance’ or
incompatibility between the spatial on the one hand and the conscious or experiential on the
other. We encounter things in space, we know them to be in space, and since we have
powerful reasons, given the repugnance, for thinking that spatial things can’t in themselves
be experiential things, or at least can’t be wholly experiential things, we have decisive
evidence that there is non-experiential reality.
This issue arose in §10. One doesn’t have to agree with Kant that space isn’t ultimately
real, but just a ‘form of sensible intuition’, to grant that we may be very ignorant of the
nature of space or spacetime (i.e. ignorant of the reality that underlies our spatial
experience). The intuition of knowable repugnance went south long ago. It was
understandable in the seventeenth century, the age of classical contact mechanics, but it
doesn’t look very good in the twenty-first. We know the experiential is real and we also
know—about as well as we know anything in science—that it’s literally located in the
brain:
[23] human experience is neural activity.
This is by now far beyond reasonable doubt. So we know, about as well as we know
anything in science, that the spatial can be experiential—given that the world is spatial.
And in the present state of our knowledge we have to treat ‘space’ and ‘spacetime’ as
names for some real dimensionality whose nature we aren’t clear about, although we know
that it must be such as to allow the existence of experientiality.
What can we say in general about this dimensionality, given that pure panpsychism is the
most parsimonious hypothesis about the nature of concrete reality? Not much but not
nothing. As pure panpsychists we may take it that (a) the dimensionality of the concrete
real, however ill understood by us, is something that fits smoothly with (b) the nature of the
concrete real conceived of as nothing but experientiality in exactly the same way as the way
in which (c) the dimensionality of the concrete real understood as spatial in the
conventional way is seen to fit smoothly with (d) the nature of the concrete real understood
as good old fashioned non-experientially propertied extended physical stuff (plainly any
21
difficulty lies in the idea of space, not of time).
It may be said that we must retain the idea of dimensional position, even when we figure
the dimensionality of the concrete real as something that fits smoothly with the idea that the
concrete real is wholly experiential, because the idea of position and difference of position
is essentially built into the idea of dimensionality. It may then be said that the property of
having some dimensional position, at least, is something essentially non-experiential. But
this may be readily granted because it raises no difficulty for the idea that the whole
intrinsic nature—stuff nature—of the concrete real is a matter of experientiality.
We find it quite incredibly hard to think clearly about these things, as Russell stressed.
Almost all of us are in his words “guilty, unconsciously and in spite of explicit disavowals,
of a confusion in [our] imaginative picture of reality” (Russell 1927, 382). Even when we
admit and dwell on our ignorance—even perhaps, when we have seen the force of the
argument that all that concretely exists is the wave function—we tend to revert to a
conviction that we have a basic grasp on things that allows us to be sure that the
matter/energy whose spatiotemporal manifestations are all around us couldn't literally be
nothing but experientiality.
15 Pictures of Matter
There’s no direct remedy for this. But there are some mental exercises one can perform. It’s
helpful to keep a few well known physical facts vividly in mind and constantly remind
oneself of them when facing the ‘mind-body problem’. Consider first the fact that the
spatial volume occupied by one’s brain—equivalent to the volume of a sphere about five
inches across—is, intuitively, almost completely empty. (More accurately, it’s almost all
‘quantum vacuum’ and is arguably a plenum, like all spacetime, i.e. the precise opposite of
a vacuum; while still being, intuitively, amost completely empty.) Add the fact that it
contains about 100 billion non-neuronal cells, although it’s almost completely empty, and
an approximately equal number of neuronal cells that have up to a thousand trillion
synaptic connections between them—plus the fact that about 700 billion solar neutrinos
(and heaven knows what else) pass through it every second.
From one intuitively natural perspective matter is quite astoundingly insubstantial, an
intricately shimmering almost-nothing. And this is so even when we consider a pebble or a
mountain. When we go on to consider a brain we find many further layers of staggeringly
intricate organization—in an almost entirely empty space. Such is matter. Such is the
material brain. It helps to maintain this picture when we’re wondering how experience can
be physical. It helps to resist the picture of a mammalian brain as a ‘sludgy mass’, a piece
of meat that can be diced and fried with garlic; although it’s also that.
I think it’s also very important to habituate to Wesen ist Werden—the processual view of
reality. It has to become something more than book learning. The same goes for Sein ist
Sosein. We need to be able to put aside as far as possible the object-property distinction that
serves so well in many other areas of philosophy and everyday life but easily leads us into
22
an intractably misleading picture according to which, when it comes to the ‘mind-body
problem’, we have to think first that we have a thing, a physical thing, and then have to
wonder how such a thing can possibly have experiential properties.
The improved picture represents matter soberly and realistically as an almost
inconceivably sparse shimmering skein of energy, energy-stuff. On one view, this is what
spacetime is. But insofar as this picture has positive imaginative (quasi-pictorial) content
for us, it still builds in some version of our ordinary conception or picture of space. And if
we now try to exert ourselves further imaginatively, in the way philosophy so regularly
demands, in the attempt to put aside any standard conception or picture of space, we’re
returned to the ‘epistemic structural realist’ point that we know nothing at all about the
intrinsic nature of the physical in so far as as its intrinsic nature is more than its
scientifically detectable structure; except of course, and again, and as always, when we
have experience. As Russell says: “we know nothing about the intrinsic quality of physical
events except when these are mental events that we directly experience” (Russell 1956,
153).
We have then to allow again that our picture of space may be profoundly misleading.
This doesn’t prevent us from appreciating the extraordinary insubstantiality of the physical,
even if we can’t shake off the conventional spatial imaginings that come with it. But those
who (like my former self) can’t shake their commitment to the idea that we know what
space is in some truly fundamental and Moorean respect may simply be unable to engage
fully with the ‘mind-body problem’.
16 Fungibility
We know experience exists. We’ve assumed that stuff monism is true and that everything is
physical. It seems that
[24] there is no good reason to believe that anything non-experiential exists32
because there’s zero evidence for the existence of non-experiential reality. One thing
we now need to consider is the idea that
[25] all physical stuff is fungible
in the sense that any form of it can in principle be transformed into any other—so that if for
example one broke hydrogen down into leptons and quarks one could reassemble it as
gold.33 If this is so then it seems plausible to suppose that all physical stuff can potentially
32
This is not the unintelligibility claim made by Berkeley (1710; cf. Foster 1982 and Robinson 2009),
according to which the notion of the non-experiential is wholly unintelligible: I’m happy to allow that the
general notion of non-experiential reality is wholly intelligible.
33
I don't know if this is unrestrictedly true; one contrary line of thought runs as follows. It seems plain that [1]
23
be part of what constitutes—is—experientiality like ours in living conscious brains like
ours, i.e. that
[26] all physical stuff can constitute (be) experientiality, experiential being.
And if so, then—given [8] that there is no radical emergence, given that one can’t get the
experiential out of the non-experiential by any kind of re-arrangement of the nonexperiential—it seems we can advance from [24], according to which there is no good
reason to believe that anything non-experiential exists, to
[27] we have good reason to believe that nothing non-experiential exists.
But never mind [27], which does after all rely on [8]. The weaker [24] is enough for now.
One of the most important experiences that a philosopher brought up in the (recent)
Western tradition can undergo is the realization that [24] is true: the belief in irreducibly
non-experiential reality has no respectable foundation, even given a fully realist
commitment to belief in an external world of tables and chairs—a world that exists wholly
independently of one’s own mind and one’s experiences—and a conviction that physics and
cosmology—and indeed the other sciences—get a very great deal right about the nature and
structure of reality. The experience is life-changing, philosophically.
It’s natural for many to think that it is nevertheless essentially theoretically cheaper to
suppose that the fundamental nature of concrete reality is non-experiential—rather than
splurging on universal experientiality. But this is simply a mistake. The postulation of
fundamental non-experientiality not only commits one to something for whose existence
there is no evidence; it also commits one to belief in radical emergence. It’s far more
expensive, theoretically speaking.
17 No Mystery
Many say that experience (consciousness) is a mystery. But what is mysterious? We know
what experience is. We know exactly what certain types of experiences are simply in
having them. More precisely: we know exactly what certain types of experiences are
considered specifically in respect of what they’re like for us experientially. And, again, we
not only know in this way what particular types of experience are. We also know what
experience is generally considered—even though we have direct experience only of certain
experientiality has something essentially to do with electricality—in our world at least, and perhaps in all
possible worlds. One might accordingly suppose that [2] all electricality is experientiality, and perhaps also
that [3] all experientiality is electricality. One might then hypothesize that [4] ultimate constituents of reality
lacking electricality (chargeless particles—neutrinos, photons, ‘chameleons’) are intrinsically nonexperiential and can’t directly constitute (be) experientiality, and further [5] that fungibility might fail
between ultimate constituents of reality possessing electricality and ultimate constituents lacking it.
24
limited kinds of experience (cf. Sprigge 1999).
‘We know exactly what certain types of experiences are considered specifically in
respect of what they’re like for us experientially.’ The ‘considered as’ qualification makes
room for the idea that our experiences have some further intrinsic nature that transcends
what we know in knowing their phenomenological character in having them. It seems
wise—necessary—to allow for this, given that experiences are neural goings-on, and given
all the wonderfully precise numerical things physics and neurophysiology can say about
them considered as things whose existence involves subatomic particles, atoms, molecules,
individual cells, and so on. We needn’t however suppose that any aspect of the being of our
experiences that transcends what we know of their being simply in having them involves
anything non-experiential. The (pure) panpsychist proposal is precisely that all the
subatomic, atomic, molecular and cellular energy phenomena about which physics and
neurophysiology say true and extraordinarily precise numerical things are themselves
experiential phenomena—microexperiential phenomena.
Call these microexperiential phenomena Es. Es may have phenomenological features of
which we have no knowledge, in having the kinds of experiences we have, even though
they somehow conspire to constitute our experiences. The energy that is an electron is
wholly a matter of experiencing, on the present view, but the specific phenomenological
character of this experiencing may be radically unimaginable by us. This doesn’t change
the fact that we know its nature in a fundamental general way. We do, because we know
what experience is in a fundamental general way simply in having experience. The
psychophysics (to give this term a new use—the point is that physics is psychics) of the
universe is mysterious to us; we don't know how it is that energy is experientiality. But in
God’s physics asking how it is that energy is experientiality may be like asking how it is
that energy is energy; and there is, for all our ignorance, a fundamental sense in which we
know the nature of the stuff out of which everything is made in knowing what
experientiality is.34
I don't know anything about the Laws of Experiential Combination that govern the way
Es constitute macroexperiential phenomena like human and canine experience. On one
view Es undergo radical fusion in such a way that there’s nothing more to their experiential
being—hence their being tout court—than what we experience in having experiences. I
don't see how this can be so, because phenomenological being is all there is to the being of
experiences, according to pure panpsychism, and the complexity revealed by physics and
neurophysiology isn’t phenomenologically given in our experience. On another fusion-like
view the fundents (the fundentia, the elements that fuse) somehow continue to possess
some intrinsic experiential character of their own even as they unite in such a way as to
jointly constitute experience like ours. One hypothesis is that these fusions or unities are
34
It may be doubted whether there is any robust sense in which an electron is a genuinely individual or
persisting thing. On one reading, relativistic quantum field theory has it that the phenomena that lead us to
talk in terms of particles are simply manifestations of the quantization of the energy of fields, and aren’t well
thought of as entities that can be said to endure over any significant period of time.
25
what show up as gusts—waves, bursts—of synchronized activity in the brain. Perhaps they
involve massive quantum entanglement effects or other strongly unificatory phenomena
that can be identified as such by physics even though physics can characterize them only in
non-experiential terms. I don't know. What I do know is that we can’t demand more
intelligibility from the Laws of Experiential Combination (experiential chemistry) than we
demand from quantum mechanics and physics in general.
What remains is the respect in which there is no fundamental mystery if panpsychism is
true—even though we have no idea how the macroexperiential arises out of the
microexperiential. Radical mystery is introduced only by the hypothesis that the intrinsic
non-structural or stuff nature of matter is (i) non-experiential (hylal), at least in part, and
hence radically distinct from anything we know in knowing what experience is, and is
furthermore (ii) of such a nature that we are utterly unable to see how how it relates
ontologically to experience (the ‘explanatory gap’).35 We have, again, no idea of the
intrinsic non-structural stuff nature of the physical insofar as the physical is something
other than the experiential, except insofar as we know that it is something that exemplifies
the structures that physics detects.36 The point is not just that the numbers and equations of
physics don't capture the whole basic or essential nature of reality; it’s that they tell us
nothing about the nature of concrete reality insofar as its nature is more than its structure.
The fact that physics is full of mystery—things we can’t claim to understand at all—is
universally conceded quite independently of this point. Bohr, Einstein, Feynman, Penrose,
Schrödinger, Wheeler all agree. No doubt the experiential is a mystery relative to physics.
But to be a mystery relative to physics is to be a mystery relative to a mystery; and if
something is a mystery relative to a mystery it need not itself be a mystery. It may be that
it’s only relative to a mystery that it looks like a mystery. And the point that physics is
silent about the intrinsic nature of the physical, insofar as the intrinsic nature of the physical
is more than its structure, is entirely general. It has nothing specially to do with experience.
It holds equally on the supposition that the intrinsic (non-structural) nature of the physical
is wholly non-experiential. So there’s no special puzzle or problem in the fact that physics
finds no place for experience (consciousness). It finds no place for any positive
characterization of the intrinsic non-structural features of concrete reality. “If you want a
concrete definition of matter it is no use looking to physics”, as Eddington remarked (1928,
95). And if you look elsewhere you encounter Kant’s point:
Every substance, even a simple element of matter, must … have some kind of inner activity as the
ground of its having an external effect, in spite of the fact that [we] cannot specify in what this inner
activity consists. Leibniz said that this inner ground of all its external relations and their changes
was a power of representation. Later philosophers greeted his (not further developed) thought with
35
Cf. Leibniz (1704, §17); Levine (1983).
Russell writes that “we know nothing about the intrinsic quality of physical events except when these are
mental events that we directly experience” (Russell 1956, 153). Unlike Russell, I take a concrete thing’s
structural nature to be part of its intrinsic nature.
36
26
laughter. They would, however, have been better advised to have first considered the question
whether a substance, such as a simple part of matter, would be possible in the complete absence of
any inner state. And, if they had, perhaps, been unwilling to rule out such an inner state [as
Vorstellungskraft], then it would have been incumbent on them to invent some other possible inner
state as an alternative to that of representations and the activities dependent on representations
(1766: 328 (Ak 2.328)).
It would be anachronistic to think that such representations need not for Leibniz or Kant
involve conscious experience.
18 Occam
So what should we real materialists do—if and when we try to do metaphysics? Like many
I think we should start from something we know to exist and whose nature we know—the
human experiential. It’s beyond reasonable doubt that human experience is wholly a matter
of neural goings-on and it seems no less clear that the most parsimonious scientific
hypothesis about the nature of physical reality is that everything is experiential.
The experiential starting point isn’t chosen for reasons of epistemological or ontological
caution. It's just that it’s usually best to start from something one knows to exist if one
wants to try to give an account of how things are. I’m not particularly cautious when it
comes to metaphysics. I’d postulate non-experiential reality in a flash if I could see how
postulating it could help in any way with any problem in real metaphysics or make a
contribution to any view of how things are that we have any good reason to believe. As
remarked, it’s scientific orthodoxy that concrete reality consists entirely of energy. The
present proposal, once again, is simply that the intrinsic nature of the energy is
experientiality. I’m ready to change my mind if someone can show me that the hypothesis
that the energy phenomena that physics studies have some intrinsic non-experiential nature
is superior to the hypothesis that their intrinsic non-structural nature is wholly
experiential—perhaps by showing some special difficulty in the hypothesis that they are
wholly experiential. As far as I can see, however, there isn’t a scintilla of a reason for
postulating anything non-experiential. Occam’s razor, according to which one shouldn’t as
a theorist posit more entities than one needs to explain the data—
[28] entia non sunt multiplicanda praeter necessitatem
—slices away the non-experiential even if one is an all-out external-world realist.
19 The Combination Problem
This is naturalist monist ‘global replace’ materialist panpsychism. It denies the existence of
something for which there is no evidence, i.e. non-experiential reality (eliminating the need
27
to postulate radical emergence), even as it admits to being clueless about how biological
(e.g. mammalian) experientiality emerges (non-radically) from the overall energyexperientiality of the fundamental constituents of brains.
At this point real-materialist opponents of panpsychism bring up the so-called
combination problem.37 They accept [10] monism, and [11]/[12] real realism about
experience. They believe [13]/[14] that the equations and numbers of physics cotton on
accurately to something real. And they endorse [D] ‘smallism’. They also grant—indeed
insist—that [21] every distinct experience necessarily involves a subject.
It’s the last two claims that directly underlie the combination problem. The central idea is
that a group of distinct experiencings or patches of experientiality, each of which
necessarily has its own subject, can’t possibly interact or fuse or co-resonate in such a way
as to constitute or generate a single experience with a single subject. Why not? Simply
because
[E] a plurality of subjects can’t possibly combine to form or generate a single subject.
If [E] could be proved true, I’d give up [D], which is highly questionable, according to
certain leading conceptions of physics and cosmology. But as things stand I see no good
reason to accept [E] even given [D]. When I figure matter as a shimmering skein of
energy/experientiality as best as I can; when I factor in my imperfect lay grasp of the
phenomena of quantum entanglement and the extraordinary difficulties that arise when it
comes to questions of synchronic and diachronic identity in fundamental physics; when I
factor in my imperfect grasp of the fundamentality of field-theoretic conceptions of those
phenomena that lead us to talk in an arguably misleading way of ‘particles’; when I form an
imaginative picture of small patches of local influence fusing into larger transient local
patches—I can’t feel any deep difficulty in the subject combination problem.38 Once again,
we can’t expect the Laws of Experiential Combination to be more open to human
understanding than the laws of quantum mechanics (although merging droplets of water
provide a nice image: seemingly sharply bounded individual items that merge on contact
into one equally well bounded item).
Nor can I feel any deep difficulty in the ‘grain problem’—the fact that “there seems to be
a profound structural mismatch between the contents of one’s consciousness at any given
time, and what science would tell us is simultaneously going on in the brain” (Lockwood
2003, 453).39 So too, when I consider the two groups of three parameters that account for
all the colours and sounds, or the five that account for all the tastes, or the combinatorial
37
The combination problem was clearly stated by Lucretius two thousand years ago (Lucretius 50, 2.865990). Cf. also Collins and Clarke (1707–1718), James (1890, ch. 6), Goff (2006; 2016), Chalmers (2016), and
Coleman (2016).
38
Cf. Seager’s discussion of ‘combinatorial infusion’ (Seager 2010 and Seager 2016).
39
Cf. also Lockwood (1993). For one interesting form of reply to the ‘grain problem’, cf. Stoljar (2006b, 11718).
28
possibilities of leptons and quarks—the astonishing variety of stuffs (lead, neurons,
marshmallow) they constitute—I feel no difficulty in what Chalmers has called the ‘palette
problem’ (Chalmers 2016): the numerical gap between the relatively small number of
fundamental entities postulated in the standard model of physics and the seemingly vast
number of different types of experiences.40
The basic point is simple. [1] We have no good grounds for thinking that we know
enough about the physical to have good reason to think that these problems are serious
difficulties for panpsychism.41 Kant makes the point well: if someone rejects materialism
[or equally micropsychism] and argues for a simple immaterial soul ‘merely on the ground
that the unity of apperception in thought does not allow of its being explained [as arising]
out of the composite, instead of admitting, as he ought to do that he is unable to explain the
possibility of a thinking nature [einer denkender Natur], why should not the materialist [or
equally the micropsychist], though he can as little appeal to experience in support of his
possibilities, be justified in being equally daring, and in using his principle to establish the
opposite conclusion?’ (Kant 1787, B417–18, my emphasis).42
[2] More positively: we have strikingly good grounds for thinking that many of our
intuitions of irreducible ontological separateness and distinctness are profoundly mistaken.
[3] The problems that arise for a physicalism that postulates fundamental non-experiential
reality and so rejects panpsychism are far greater than the problems that arise for
panpsychism (e.g. zero evidence for non-experiential reality, contravention of No Jumps
and No Radical Emergence).
I also believe (with Descartes, pre-Critical Kant, and many others, including William
James) that there’s a metaphysically primordial way of thinking about what a subject of
experience is given which there is, in the case of any particular episode of experiencing, no
real distinction between the subject of experience or experiencer and the experience or
experiencing (cf. e.g. Strawson 2003b). This may contribute to my failure to feel worried
by the combination problem. I don't, however, think that this particular belief is
indispensable to the lack of worry—except insofar as it’s linked to the Sein ist Sosein claim.
And now a further question arises. The idea that there’s nothing but experiential reality is
supposed to give rise to certain distinctive problems; but how can the supposition that there
is non-experiential reality improve things?43 It may be said that it does remove the
40
I’m mindful, also, of Turausky’s suggestion that particular experiences may be formed by subtraction—
reduction—sculpting—of a base of experiential ‘white noise’ (cf. Turausky unpublished).
41
Remember that these proponents of the combination problem hold that the experiential is wholly physical—
or at least, as monists, that it is wholly of the same stuff as whatever stuff they postulate.
42
Kant undermines the view that we can know that the mind or soul or thinking subject is a single substance
in the Second Paralogism. He grants—stresses—the sense in which the thinking subject is something that is
necessarily single in the activity of thought or experience, and points out that we cannot infer its ultimate
metaphysical simplicity from this fact. He backs up the point nicely in his ‘Refutation of Mendelssohn’ (1787:
B413–15 and n.): even if a mind or soul is an ultimately metaphysically single substance, he argues, we can
imagine its powers being half what they actually are (its ‘degree of reality’ being half what it actually is), and
this is sufficient to show the sense in which a mind or thinking subject that is strongly unified or simple may
nonetheless be composite or have parts.
43
Perhaps the best move at this point is Coleman’s (cf. e.g. 2016). Note, though, that the kind of
29
supposed ‘combination problem’. But I’ve already lost any sense that we have good reason
to think that this is a serious difficulty, and the problem of how pluralities of distinct nonexperiential processes can combine to form necessarily single-subject-involving
experiencings like your and my current experience looms no less large, given that it
requires (among other things) radical emergence of the experiential from the nonexperiential.
20 The Primacy of Panpsychism
I’m not claiming to know that there is no non-experiential reality. I’m just considering the
most plausible scientific hypothesis—‘global replace’ real materialist panpsychism—and
wondering why the self-styled hard-nosed naturalists of our day (a) deny the existence of
something that knowably exists and (b) assume the existence of something for which they
have no evidence: non-experiential reality. My bet is that
[29] everything is experiential
– that the intrinsic (non-structural) nature of the energy that is widely agreed to wholly
constitute physical reality is experientiality.
I can’t prove this, of course. Some will think that the combination of [7] No Jumps and
[28] Occam’s Razor is very close to proof but I’m content to argue for something weaker—
for
[30] the primacy of panpsychism
as advertised at the outset—the view that
[30] we should favour panpsychism over all other substantive theories of the fundamental
nature of reality.
It’s not the only game in town, when it comes to speculating about the ultimate nature of
reality—unless William of Occam is the Sheriff—but it’s the best theory we have.
21 Awareness of Awareness; the World-Knot
I’ll end with a very brief, more positive, and wildly speculative thought. It begins with
Aristotle, at least in the Western tradition, who observes that “if we are aware, we are
phenomenally qualitied non-experiential reality he posits is very far from any standard conception of nonexperiential being—and that the problem posed by No Radical Emergence remains as acute as ever.
30
aware that we are aware” (Nicomachean Ethics 9.9.1170a29-b1).44 I’m going to take this
claim to be correct in saying that all experience, all awareness, as I’ll now also call it—
using ‘awareness’ to refer only to conscious awareness and taking it to be synonymous with
‘experience’ used as above—somehow or other involves awareness of that very awareness.
This can be read in at least two ways, as is well known: in a higher-order way and a
same-order ‘self-intimationist’ way. I favour the same-order view, the view that
[31] all awareness on the part of a subject comports awareness, on the part of that subject,
of that very awareness
where ‘comports’ is used to mean something like (and at least) ‘contains within itself’ (as
in French comporter); so that the awareness of awareness isn’t anything ontically over and
above the awareness considered as a whole.
We can rewrite [31] more simply as
[31] all awareness comports awareness of that very awareness.
I’ll call this the Self-Intimation thesis.
There’s an enormous quantity of discussion of this matter. I’m not going to add to it
here.45 I’m simply going to endorse the Self-Intimation thesis in order to propose a further
Very Large Step: perhaps the self-intimation—the fundamental self-reflexivity, the
Fürsichsein—characteristic of experience is of the essence not only of experience—mind,
consciousness—but of all concrete being. Perhaps it’s only this kind of turnedness-on-itself
that can catapult or bootstrap being into being. This would explain why Sein—
Ansichsein—is Fürsichsein: there is no other possibility:
[32] all concrete reality is necessarily experiential.
Catapulting and bootstrapping are bad metaphors insofar as they suggest that experience
is somehow causa sui—the cause of itself. I don’t think anything can be causa sui. A thing
can be somehow self-sustaining, perhaps, but not self-caused. Slightly better, perhaps, is
the proposal that this sort of self-reflexivity or self-relatedness or self-intimation is an
internal sprungness—a self-sprungness—that characterizes not only awareness but being in
general. It’s what holds off its collapse into nothing (as it were). It is perhaps one good way
to characterize what energy is, and the whole of concrete being is energy in one form or
another: Stoff ist Kraft.
This perhaps is the real ‘world-knot’—Schopenhauer’s term for the point of contact
44
Cf. also De Anima 425b12-25. It is I believe a mistake to read the explicitly propositional formulation
‘aware that we are aware’ in such a way that the claim isn’t also true of non-human animals.
45
Cf. e.g. Zahavi (1999; 2005), Kriegel and Williford (2006). I try to characterize it in Strawson (2013).
31
between subject and world. It really is a kind of knot inasmuch as a knot is essentially
turned on itself. This perhaps is the real remarkableness of experience as it emerges in our
attempt to theorize about it. And it’s nothing other than the remarkableness of concrete
being.
This is entirely speculative. The notion of being self-sprung is metaphorical. But I think
that something about it smells right—the idea that the ‘self-sprungness’ or ‘self-intimation’
of experience is the fundamental form or self-sustaining structure of the energy which is
concrete reality. Self-sprungness makes—constitutes—force, and Stoff ist Kraft. Matter—
more generally, the physical, all concrete being—is force or activity or power or energy.
Matter-force is essentially dynamic, being is essentially becoming: Wesen ist Werden. We
travel smoothly down the chain of terms which—it now appears—forms a circle: a
panpsychist circle. We already know that we neither have nor can have any good reason to
think that anything non-experiential exists in concrete reality and we’ve now noted a
fundamental feature of experience—a kind of self-loopedness that seems uniquely
characteristic of experience—that offers itself as a fundamental feature of any kind of
concrete being at all. With Eddington, Russell, Whitehead, and many others, including
Spinoza and Leibniz, and perhaps Kant, and many others, I suspect we’re wrong to think
that awareness or Fürsichsein is a special—rare—feature of the universe. On the present
view it’s the most common thing there is. In fact it’s the only kind of thing there is. All
being in-itself, i.e. all being, all being period, is being for-itself. This is an essential part of
its intrinsic or ultimate nature. This is what energy is, the energy treated of in physics, the
energy of which matter is one form among others, and about whose intrinsic nature, over
and above its structural nature, physics has, provably and forever, nothing to say.
“Apart from the experiences of subjects there is nothing, nothing, nothing, bare
nothingness” (Whitehead 1929, 167). I don't know exactly why Whitehead came to this
conclusion, but we know—to say it one more time—that experience exists in the universe,
and we don’t know that anything else exists. This isn’t any sort of argument that nothing
non-experiential exists, but all those who are genuinely committed to monism ought to
prefer the hypothesis that everything is experiential to all hypotheses that suppose that the
fundamental nature of reality is wholly non-experiential because all these hypotheses
require that one posit radical emergence. They require experiential phenomena to emerge
from phenomena that are in themselves wholly and utterly non-experiential. Long
familiarity with a picture according to which experientiality emerged from nonexperientiality in the course of biological evolution has softened our thinking in such a way
that we can no longer clearly see what an extravagant hypothesis this is—especially for
someone who is convinced, as I am, of the truth of the theory of evolution.46,47
46
On this last point cf. James (1890, ch. 6). Panpsychism also solves what some see as a major problem for
the theory of evolution—the problem of why experience evolved at all. (Nietzsche expresses this problem
vividly at the beginning of §354 of The Gay Science, although I don't agree with the solution he proposes later
in the paragraph.)
47
This paper is a composite of talks first given at the Towards a Science of Consciousness conference in
32
Bibliography
Aristotle. Nicomachean Ethics. Trans. James Thomson. London: Penguin, c 340 BCE/1953.
Aristotle. De Anima. Trans. Walter Hett. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, c 340 BCE /1936.
Berkeley, George. “Philosophical Commentaries.” Philosophical Works of George Berkeley. Ed. Michael
Ayers. London: Everyman, 1707–1710/1975. 305-412.
Bohm, David. Causality and Chance in Modern Physics. London: Routledge, 1957/2005.
Chalmers, David. “The Combination Problem for Panpsychism.” Panpsychism. Ed. Godehard Brüntrup and
Ludwig Jaskolla. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Clarke, Samuel. The Clarke-Collins Correspondence of 1707-18. Ed. William Uzgalis. Peterborough:
Broadview Press, 1707-1718/2011.
Coleman, Sam. “Being Realistic: Why Physicalism May Entail Panexperientialism.” Consciousness and its
Place in Nature. Ed. Anthony Freeman. Thorverton: Imprint Academic, 2006. 40-52.
Coleman, Sam. “Panpsychism and Neutral Monism: How to Make up One’s Mind.” Panpsychism. Ed.
Godehard Brüntrup and Ludwig Jaskolla. New York: Oxford University Press.
Collins, Antony. The Clarke-Collins Correspondence of 1707-18. Ed. William Uzgalis. Peterborough:
Broadview Press, 1707-1718/2011.
Descartes, René. Meditations and Objections and Replies. Rpt. The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, Vol.
2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1641/1985.
Eddington, Arthur. “Review of ‘The Analysis of Matter’.” The Journal of Philosophical Studies 3.9 (1928):
93-95.
Faraday, Michael. “A Speculation Touching Electric Conduction and the Nature of Matter.” The London,
Edinburgh, and Dublin Philosophical Magazine and Journal of Science 24 (1844): 136-144.
Foster, John. The Case for Idealism. London: Routledge, 1982.
Frauenstädt, Julius. Studien und Kritiken zur Theologie und Philosophie. Berlin: Verlag der Voss’schen
Buchhandlung, 1840.
Goff, Philip. “Experiences Don’t Sum.” Consciousness and its Place in Nature. Ed. Anthony Freeman.
Thorverton: Imprint Academic, 2006. 53-61.
Goff, Philip. “The phenomenal bonding solution to the combination problem.” Panpsychism. Ed. Godehard
Brüntrup and Ludwig Jaskolla. New York: Oxford University Press, 2016.
Griffin, Donald. Unsnarling the World-Knot: Consciousness, Freedom, and the Mind-Body Problem.
Berkeley: University of California Press, 1998.
Hawking, Stephen. A Brief History of Time. New York: Bantam Books, 1988.
Heisenberg, Werner. Physics and Philosophy. New York: Harper and Brothers, 1958.
Tucson in 2010 and a conference in München in 2011, and subsequently at Wollongong University
(Australasian Association of Philosophy conference), New York University, Rice University, Rutgers
University, the University of Mississippi, and the Czech Academy of Sciences in Prague. I am grateful to
many for their comments. I remember in particular Pierfrancesco Basile, Dave Chalmers, Sam Coleman,
Philip Goff, Keith Turausky, Hedda Hassel Mørch, James Ladyman, Pat Lewtas, Anna Marmodoro, Michelle
Montague, and Udo Thiel.
33
Horgan, Terence and Matjaz Potrč. Austere Realism: Contextual Semantics Meets Minimal Ontology
(Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2008.
Jackson, Frank. (2003) “From H2O to Water: The Relevance to A Priori Passage.” Real Metaphysics. Ed.
Halvard Lillehammer and Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra. London: Routledge, 2003. 84-97.
James, William. The Principles of Psychology. New York: Dover, 1890/1950.
Kant, Immanuel. Critique of Pure Reason. London: Macmillan, 1781-7/1933.
Kriegel, Uriah and Kenneth Williford. “Introduction.” Self-Representational Approaches to Consciousness.
Ed. Uriah Kriegel and Kenneth Williford. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2006. 1-8.
Ladyman, James et al. Every Thing Must Go: Metaphysics Naturalized. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2007.
Leibniz, Gottfried. New Essays on Human Understanding. Transl. Jonathan Bennett and Peter Remnant.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. c 1704/1996.
Leibniz, Gottfried. Monadology. Monadology and Other Philosophical Essays. Transl. Paul Schrecker and
Anne Martin Schrecker. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1714/1965.
Levine, Joseph. “Materialism and Qualia: The Explanatory Gap.” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 64.3
(1983): 354-61.
Lockwood, Michael. “The Grain Problem.” Objections to Physicalism. Ed. Howard Robinson. New York:
Oxford University Press, 1993. 271-291.
Lockwood, Michael. “Consciousness and the Quantum World: Putting Qualia on the Map” Consciousness:
New Philosophical Perspectives. Ed. Quentin Smith and Aleksandar Jokic. Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2003. 447-467.
Lucretius. The Nature of Things. Trans. A. Stallings. London: Penguin, c50 BCE/2007.
Newman, Max. “Mr. Russell’s ‘Causal Theory of Perception’” Mind 37 (1928): 137-148.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. The Gay Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1882/2001.
Perry, John. Thought and Character of William James. Boston: Little, Brown and Co., 1935.
Plato. The Sophist. Trans. H. N. Fowler. London: Heinemann, c 360 BCE/1921.
Poincaré, Henri. Science and Hypothesis. London and Newcastle-upon-Tyne: The Walter Scott Publishing
Company, 1903/1905.
Quine, Willard van Orman. “Two Dogmas of Empiricism.” In W. V Quine, From a Logical Point of View,
2nd edn. New York: Harper & Row, 1951/1961.
Robinson, Howard. “Idealism.” The Oxford Handbook to the Philosophy of Mind. Ed. Brian McLaughlin,
Ansgar Beckermann, Sven Walter. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009.
Rosenberg, Gregg. “On the Intrinsic Nature of the Physical.” Towards a Science of Consciousness III. Ed.
Stuart Hameroff, Alfred Kaszniak, and David Chalmers. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1999.
Rosenberg, Gregg. A Place for Consciousness: Probing the deep Structure of the Natural World. New York:
Oxford University Press, 2004.
Russell, Bertrand. The Analysis of Mind. London: George Allen & Unwin, 1921/1978.
Russell, Bertrand. The Analysis of Matter. London: Routledge, 1927/1992.
Russell, Bertrand. “Mind and Matter.” Portraits from Memory. Nottingham: Spokesman, 1956/1995. 145165.
Schaffer, Jonathan. “From Nihilism to Monism.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 85.2 (2007): 175–191.
Schaffer, Jonathan. “Monism: The Priority of the Whole.” Philosophical Review 119 (2010): 31-76.
34
Schlick, Moritz. General Theory of Knowledge. New York: Springer-Verlag, 1918-25/1974.
Seager, William. “Panpsychism, Aggregation and Combinatorial Infusion.” Mind & Matter 8.2 (2010): 167184.
Seager, William. Natural Fabrications. Dordrecht: Springer, 2012.
de Spinoza, Baruch. Short Treatise on God, Man and his Well-being. Repr. The Collected Works of Spinoza.
Ed. Edwin Curley. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1662/1988.
Sprigge, Timothy. “Is Consciousness Mysterious?” The Importance of Subjectivity. Ed. Leemon McHenry.
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999/2010.
Stoljar, Daniel. “Comments on Galen Strawson” Consciousness and its Place in Nature. Ed. Anthony
Freeman. Thorverton: Imprint Academic, 2006a. 170-176.
Stoljar, Daniel. Ignorance and Imagination. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006b.
Strawson, Galen. “Real Materialism.” Real Materialism and Other Essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2003a/2008. 19-52.
Strawson, Galen. “What is the Relation Between an Experience, the Subject of an Experience, and the
Content of the Experience?” Real Materialism and Other Essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2003b/2008. 151-188.
Strawson, Galen. “Realistic Monism: Why Physicalism Entails Panpsychism.” Real Materialism and Other
Essays. Ed. Galen Strawson. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006/2008. 53-74.
Strawson, Galen. “The Identity of the Categorical and the Dispostional.” Analysis 68.4 (2008): 271-282.
Strawson, Galen. “Self-Intimation.” Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 14 (2013/2015): 44-73.
Strawson, Galen. “Consciousness in the 20th Century.” Consciousness. Ed. Alison Simmons. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, forthcoming a.
Strawson, Galen. “Structure and Quality.” Forthcoming b.
Turausky, Keith. “Picturing Panpsychism: New Approaches to the Combination Problem(s).” Unpublished.
Whitehead, Alfred. Process and Reality: An Essay in Cosmology. Ed. David Griffin and Donald Sherburne.
New York: The Free Press, 1929/1978.
Wilson, Rob. Boundaries of the Mind: The Individual in the Fragile Sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2004.
Zahavi, Dan. Self-Awareness and Alterity: A Phenomenological Investigation. Evanston: Northwestern
University Press, 1999.
Zahavi, Dan. Subjectivity and Selfhood: Investigating the First-Person Perspective. Cambridge: MIT Press,
2005.
35