Emergent Behaviorism
Author(s): Peter R. Killeen
Source: Behaviorism, Vol. 12, No. 2 (Fall, 1984), pp. 25-40
Published by: Cambridge Center for Behavioral Studies (CCBS)
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/27759042 .
Accessed: 26/06/2013 20:51
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact
[email protected].
.
Cambridge Center for Behavioral Studies (CCBS) is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend
access to Behaviorism.
http://www.jstor.org
This content downloaded from 129.219.247.33 on Wed, 26 Jun 2013 20:51:14 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Behaviorism,
Fall
1984, Vol.
12, Number
2
EMERGENT BEHAVIORISM
Peter R. Killeen
Arizona State University
I conclude that his only valid objections
In this article I examine Skinner's objections to mentalism.
?
that mentalism might afford
the "specious explanations"
that are incomplete, circular, or
explanations
faulty in other ways. Unfortunately, the mere adoption of behavioristic terminology does not solve that problem. It
the nature of "private events," while providing no protection from specious explanations.
I argue that
camouflages
covert states and events are causally effective, and may be sufficiently different in their nature to deserve a name
ABSTRACT:
concern
not force a dualistic metaphysics: Such a distinction can be
call such events"mental"does
by an "emergent behaviorism."
Emergent behaviorism would make explicit use of theories. It
easily assimilated
would be inductive and pragmatic, and would evaluate hypothetical constructs in terms of their utility in clarifying
and solving the outstanding problems of the discipline.
other than "behavior."To
Skinner vacillated in his view on the nature and causal efficacy of events that occur
inside the skin of an organism. In his reply to Blanshard he stated that "ideas, motives, and
feelings have no part in determining conduct, and therefore no part in explaining it"
(Blanshard & Skinner, 1967, p. 325), and several years later "the mental laws of physiological
of William James, the mental
psychologists like Wundt, the stream of consciousness
apparatus of Sigmund Freud have no useful place in the understanding of human behavior"
(Skinner, 1972, p. 19). Why then do thoughts and feelings seem to cause behavior? "They
usually occur in just the place that would be occupied by a cause.... For example, we often
feel a state of deprivation or emotion before we act in an appropriate way. If we say
something to ourselves before saying italoud, what we say aloud seems the expression of an
inner thought" (1972, p. 19). For some reason Skinner never considered that through
classical conditioning, such precursors to action might come to elicit it.
Not everywhere does Skinner deny the efficacy of private events: "It is particularly
helpful to describe behavior which fails to satisfy contingencies, as inT letgo too soon' or 'I
struck too hard.' Even fragmentary descriptions of contingencies speed the acquisition of
effective terminal behavior, help to maintain the behavior over a period of time, and
reinstate itwhen forgotten" (1957, p. 445). How can he admit that "Verbal behavior has
practical effects upon the speaker as a listener"? (1957, p. 440), yet deny the causal efficacy of
ideas, thoughts, and feelings? Part of the reason is that like Bertrand Russell, whom he
admired, Skinner preferred not to use the term "cause" (all mentions of it in the index of
and Human Behavior refer to perjorative discussions) and he found it especially
seem to have given
problematic in referring to intermediate links of causal chains. "Effects"
a
reason
must
that
he
be that
science of behavior
less trouble. Another part of the
recognized
Science
I thank G. Graham, R. J. Herrnstein, and P. Prins for comments on this paper. A number of the issues raised here have
also been discussed by Sober (1983). This article will be published in B. F. Skinner: Consensus and Controversy, 1986,
edited by Drs. Sohan and Celia Modgil, under the Falmer International Master-Minds
Challenged series, Falmer Press,
Sussex, England. The book will contain 24 chapters in a paired-debate
from Professors B. F. Skinner, Willard Day, and Daniel Denett.
Barcombe
format, among
25
This content downloaded from 129.219.247.33 on Wed, 26 Jun 2013 20:51:14 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
them contributions
KILLEEN
is prior to a science of logic, and he respected the laws of conditioning more than the "laws"
of valid inferences. He wished to bring his verbal behavior under the control of his data, even
if that required some inconsistencies given our current state of knowledge. For what we
witness is not a slow shift in position as Skinner's perspective changed. There is no
monotonie relation between the degree of causal efficacy given covert events and the year in
which that opinion was published.
Many of Skinner's objections to "Mental Way Stations" are to ad hoc and untestable
"explanations"
loosely inferred from causal introspection, not to the possibility of "practical
effects" deriving from covert behavior. These and other objections are clearly stated in his
article "Behaviorism at 50" (1963), where he notes that Mental Way Stations (MWS) are
often accepted as terminal data, and thereby abort the search for environmental causes of the
MWS, or, going in the other direction, the existence of itsputative consequences. Even when
the MWS
is anchored to both prior stimuli and consequent responses, "various things
at
the
way station which alter the relation between terminal events.... Mental states
happen
alter one another.... Dissonant cognitions...will not be reflected in behavior if the subject
can, 'persuade himself that one condition was actually different...."(It is leftambiguous as
to whether he believes that such interactions occur, or whether they are precipitated out as
one of the unclean and unnecessary byproducts of a cognitive vocablulary). "The effects
still provide a formidable stronghold for mentalistic theories designed to bridge the gap
between dependent and independent variables" (p. 240).
With what engines does he assault that stronghold? The methodological objections are:
to
the predilection for unfinished causal sequences, b) thatMWS "burdens a science of
a)
behavior with all the problems raised by the limitations and inaccuracies of self-descriptive
repertoires", and c) "Perhaps the most serious objection.... Responses which seem to be
describing intervening states alone may embrace behavioral effects" (p. 241). That is,
inferences about MWS may be based in part on the observation of our subsequent overt
behavior. As we shall see, these are weak objections.
What rule will Skinner establish once the stronghold is breached? He notes that "These
disturbances in simple causal linkages between environment and behavior can be formulated
and studied experimentally as interactions among variables; but the possibility has not been
fully exploited" (p. 240). He deals briefly with multiple causation in Science and Human
Behavior (1953), and much more extensively throughout his monumental Verbal Behavior
(1957). The product was a series of astute observations, but they have not been adopted by
many students as an effective approach to these issues. In part this is because of the
enormous difficulty of the subject; in part because in Verbal Behavior, Skinner
"put the
reader through a set of exercises for the express purpose of strengthening a particular verbal
repertoire.... I have been trying to get the reader to behave verbally as I behave"(p. 455). He
succeeded in that attempt for many of us; what he did not provide was an experimental
analysis of complex cases such as verbal behavior. Itwas all talk, often brilliant talk, and he
leftus talking, often somewhat less brilliantly. His citations are primarily to intellectuals and
men of letters, and this is themodel he provides us, not that of an
experimenting scientist.
OBJECTIONS TO MENTALISM
Random House defines behavior as "the aggregate of observable responses of an
organism to internal and external stimuli." This was the domain of Skinner's early work, as
reported in The Behavior of Organisms (1938). But Skinner was always eager to address the
most sophisticated aspects of human behavior. To do that, he could either devise new
analytical tools, or he could adont those of others, or he could assert that no new tools were
26
This content downloaded from 129.219.247.33 on Wed, 26 Jun 2013 20:51:14 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
EMERGENT BEHAVIORISM
needed. In attempting to extrapolate the laws of conditioning to humans, Skinner clearly
took the last course. Itwas an optimistic gambit; the combination of a few simple principles
can easily generate complex outcomes inany field of investigation. His principles were based
on "movements of an organism or of its parts in a frame of reference provided by the
organism itselfor by various external objects or fields of force"( 1938, p. 6). His independent
variables were reinforcement contingencies defined in terms of
motivational operations defined in terms of deprivation operations,
terms of both physical parameters and the nature of the behavior
Skinner's "generic," or functional, definition of stimuli and responses
schedule parameters,
and stimuli defined in
that they controlled.1
provided a trapdoor to
escape from the problems that would otherwise be posed by attention, elaboration, and
other mental processes. Unfortunately, itwas a route that he seldom took, preferring to
study behavior where physical definitions of stimuli and responses were usually good
enough.
This early history of reinforcement shaped Skinner's approach to the analysis of human
behavior. Skinner recognized that "mental states alter one another," and repudiated them
for that reason.2 But the omission of such states left him with an inadequate vocabulary,
which he then expanded bymoving some stimuli inside the organism ("private stimuli"), and
by treating all other aspects of mental states as responses. Seeing became behavior, and
imagination became "seeing without the thing seen."3 But these are assertions, not
demonstrated facts. They may serve as the axioms of a parsimonious behavioral system, and
that is largely how Skinner used them. But they cannot then also be used as arguments
against other systems, or against behavioral systems with augmented axioms, such as the
assumption that covert events are sufficiently different from overt ones to deserve separate
treatment as a separate category of events. The competition between such systems is in terms
to those who
of explanatory power, not in terms of whose axioms are least objectionable
don't hold them.
Let us, nonetheless, review Skinner's objections to the inclusion of mental events in his
(and anyone else's) system. Keat (1972) summarizes them:
For Skinner, mentalism
is to be rejected because?
(1) It lacks "explanatory
power."
(2) It involves
the employment
(3) It tends to invoke
(4) It distracts
of "theories."
"homunculi"
our attention
(5) It involves a dualistic
regarding man
or "inner agents,"
as an "autonomous
agent."
from the study of behavior.
ontology
of the "mental"
and
the "physical."
(p.55)
To these we may add those mentioned above and not included here: The limitations of a
self-descriptive repertoire, and the contamination of descriptions of internal states by
discriminations based on overt behavior.
What
of these?
Explanatory
Power
Skinner notes that after we have explained a response in terms of mental states or
activities or feelings, we still need to explain themental state. But there is nothing wrong with
that. Experimental analysis of one of the links in a causal chain should not necessarily be
faulted because itdoes not include the previous ones; analysis must inevitably stop at some
27
This content downloaded from 129.219.247.33 on Wed, 26 Jun 2013 20:51:14 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
KILLEEN
point short of the Ultimate Cause. We might infer from a person's pale face, hand over
stomach, and low moan that he is in pain, and thus seek aid for him. We do not attempt to
move his hand, nor silence themoans, nor rouge the face: The inference of an internal state of
distress ismore likely to be useful to him. Nor do we yet need to inferthat itwas something he
ate, or that itwas the flu that is going around, or that he was punched. Such determinations
will certainly help, but we can take immediate and effective action based on our inference
alone. Are we more likely to be helpful ifwe know that he ate strange food, but deny that he is
indistress? Similarly, there are many things thatmight make us angry, and knowledge of that
internal state will be much more effective in explaining subsequent behavior than knowledge
of the (often seemingly innocuous) stimuli that preceded it.We might get by without telling
others of our needs, our goals, our ideas and ideals, and merely be viewed as a "private"
person; were we to convey in their place our reinforcement histories and immediate stimulus
context, unflavored by our subjective evaluations of them, we'd be condemned either as a
tedious obscurant, or, if taken seriously, as an unreflecting pawn of our history.
Theories
Skinner has stated that "whether experimental psychologists like itor not, experimental
psychology is properly and inevitably committed to the construction of a theory of behavior.
A theory is essential to the scientific understanding of behavior as a subject matter" (1969,
pp.vii-viii). What he objects to are particular types of theories: "any explanation of an
observed fact which appeals to events taking place somewhere else, at some other level of
observation, described in different terms, and measured, ifat all, in different dimensions"
(p.vii). But what's wrong with such theories? Although we should not try to model our
scientific discipline too closely on others, for our problems are different,we can evaluate this
general statement by asking whether the condemned types of explanation are used in other
fields. Any reasonable interpretation of Skinner's words shows that theyare not only used,
but that they constitute some of the most powerful and elegant theories that we know!
Newton's theory of universal gravitation explained the tides on the earth by events
"taking place somewhere else"; about as elsewhere as one can get. Skinner should be the last
to want to posit some hypothetical stuff that bridges the spatial gap in order to avoid action
at a distance.
It is not clear how to interpret "at some other level of observation," other than as
observations that employ instruments to aid our senses. But thenwe must include the germ
theory of disease, a theory greatly abetted by themicroscope. Should we give that up for fear
of a behaviorist's censure, and hope that holistic medicine will be ready for us when we need
it?
in different terms" is often a strength of theories. Theories are a map, or
"Described
us by providing a coherent frame of reference within which to view the
serve
and
metaphor,
with
the rules to develop specific models of it. Ifevents are not recondite,
phenomena, along
we seldom think of them in terms of theories. I don't seek theoretical explanation forwhy my
dog barks at cats. But I do generate hypotheses about why he howls at railroad whistles. And
those involve theories that use "different terms"?speculation
about evolutionary
constraints and wolves howling to gather for a hunt. In general, a failed description elicits
another attempt, in other terms ("Let me put itthisway"). We all know thatmany successful
theories involve descriptions in other terms: Chemists explain molar physical properties of
substances in terms of internal states, such as the valence of atoms, polarization of
molecules,
and
so on.
28
This content downloaded from 129.219.247.33 on Wed, 26 Jun 2013 20:51:14 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
KILLEEN
ifat all, in different dimensions". Differences in the dimensions used to
"Measured,
describe a phenomenon may indicate a basic and insurmountable incommensurability, or
theymay indicate an arbitrary historical decision or a matter of style or convenience. We
may record motion and shape in Cartesian or polar coordinates; we may quantify sound
in terms of their energy over time, or in terms of their power spectrum. In this latter
case, it is the insight provided by Fourier's Law that reveals the equivalence between the two
representations. It is this realization of the unity of phenomena behind the apparently
different dimensional frames that provides some of themost potent rewards for scientists
and inspiration for theiraudience. What more beautiful evidence of this could one want than
waves
that symbol of 20th century physics, Einstein's equation relating energy to mass and the
speed of light?
"Perhaps," you say, "Skinner was merely trying to assert that things like emotions don't
have dimensions that would support conversion to the dimensions of things like running
speed." They don't currently, although some people "Get so mad they could spit," thus
In a similar manner atoms sometimes emit
providing latency and ballistic measurements.
particles, whose latency and trajectory can tell us how "excited" theywere. Of course, one
need not assume that excitation is nothing more than the propensity to emit an electron, nor
that the level of excitation should be characterized only in terms of one type of cloud
chamber tracing. A similar analysis holds for emotions and other types of inner causes. It
may be true that good measures of emotional states and their strengths are not yet available.
However, we should not elevate this current deficiency into a permanent dogma, or we shall
never have them. Let us instead look to theory to suggest new types of dimensions and new
ways of relating them.
Horn uneuli
Skinner objects tomentalism because it leads us to invoke homunculi. But itneedn't do
that, nor is the doing of that necessarily bad. Part of Skinner's objection here is the
argument, for he does not want us to view humans as
unfinished-causal-sequence
"autonomous
agents" (Skinner, 1974). As suggested above, one can defer the analysis of
in
the causal chain without denying their existence. In fact, one can be a
links
prior
or "self
determinist and still believe that it is useful to treat humans as autonomous,
governing" (Audi, 1976). The governors (e.g., traits and values) may have been aligned by
nature and nurture, but the individual's interactions with his or her current environment may
be treated more effectively by a theory of internal rules and set-points than by untested
reference to histories of reinforcement. Not that such behavior is uncaused, but that more
might be gotten out of focusing on the internal, self-reflective dialogue as cause than by
focusing
on
bells,
whistles,
and
cumulative
records.
In fact,
histories
of
reinforcement
are
often reconstructed through verbal reports of individuals who are less than disinterested
observers, and they thus suffer some of the same liabilities as introspective reports. "History
of reinforcement" is a critical construct in Skinner's theory, but has received little critical
analysis. In study of human behavior, it often serves as generic explanation, of the same
order
of "inner
man."
Skinner's problem with homunculi is that he never took then seriously enough. What he
seems to mean by them are small creatures with all the capacities of larger ones, who live
ex machina. Clearly, there would be a problem
inside and make the decisions?homo
packing them in. All themore a problem since theywould need their own homunculi. And
they theirs. The implication is that an infinitenumber would be needed, thus forestalling any
specification of themachinery thatmight actually get the job done, and thereby reducing this
29
This content downloaded from 129.219.247.33 on Wed, 26 Jun 2013 20:51:14 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
EMERGENT BEHAVIORISM
type of explanation to absurdity. Skinner is objecting to the hypostatization of a solution, in
themanner ofMoli?re's doctor who explained the soporific properties of opium as being due
to their virtus dormitiva: "The function of the innerman is to provide an explanation which
will not be explained in turn" (Skinner, 1971, p. 14). If this is its only function, then it is
certainly counterproductive.
But not all infinite series are regresses, nor do all of them carry us infinitelyfar from the
starting point. If enough tasks are accomplished by each homunuculus before itpasses its
output to the next higher demon, then the job will get done with a finite number of levels; the
series will converge, and itmay converge quickly.
But why bother with such a hierarchy? Simon ( 1973) provides themost eloquent answer,
and Dawkins (1976) discusses hierarchies ingreater detail. Just as computer programs based
on subroutines are easier towrite, to troubleshoot, and tomodify, behavioral programs are
more
effective when arranged hierarchically (Dennett, 1978). Cognitive psychologists
analyze the role of "scripts," "sch?mas," and "prototypical actions" in the control of
behavior (Abelson, 1981); behaviorists speak of higher-order stimulus control, but seldom
attempt to explain that in turn.
The computer subroutine metaphor is useful, not only because such programming
shares features with behavioral programming, but because of the way in which people
characterize the actions at each level. As Dennett (1978) has observed, a single line of code is
discussed mechanistically. So might be a single subroutine. But for sufficiently large systems,
whether they control petroleum refineries or play chess, programmers revert to functional
("in order to") and intentional ("it is attempting to") discourse. (Of course, this could be
folly, responsible in part for the high costs of gasoline and our inability to write a grand
master chess program!) Similarly, for reflexive or automatized behavior, it is natural to
speak mechanically, in terms of short chains of cause and effect. But why believe, against the
everyday evidence afforded by the ordinary verbal behavior of even themost sophisticated
radical behaviorists, that the emergent language of function and intention is not a superior
mode of discourse concerning complex human behavior?
Distraction
from the Study of Behavior
an organism isobserved
Patently a behaviorist's complaint. But since behavior is "what
an
to
be
another
organism may be doing many
doing" (Skinner, 1938, p. 6),
organism
by
be
fit for scientific study. Ifwe
as
that
don't
behavior, yet may
qualify
interesting things
broaden the definition by annexing private events, ithas to be demonstrated why "response
than "image." If
produced private stimulus" is a better label for the object of your mind's eye
the answer is that we don't have a "copy" in our head, then we must ask clarification of the
nature of "private stimuli"; either they carry themeaning of copy/image, or an important
images, and our ability to inspect them?will be leftunaccounted for.
phenomenon?our
Behaviorism has helped us to focus on the environmental context of actions, and that
has been all to the good. It isall too easy to inventunverifiable "mental"causes even when the
behaviorism
precipitating environmental events are obvious to any who would look. Radical
should
not
scientists
it
is
like
excellent
major
But,
something
discipline,
discipline.
provides
in. The world is bountiful with substantive issues, to which behaviorism can contribute
It is by focusing on these issues that the
important perspectives and methodologies.
will
be
and
improved. We should study behavior, but we should
methodologies
perspectives
is a theoretical
also study what goes on inside organisms. To call that "behavior"
in most Skinner boxes; labelling it
commitment; it certainly isn't what gets measured
"behavior" is a least a metaphorical extension, ifnot a magical mand. Perhaps other terms
30
This content downloaded from 129.219.247.33 on Wed, 26 Jun 2013 20:51:14 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
KILLEEN
for itwould be better. "The decision as towhether to limit psychological theory to stimulus
response relationships...or to admit non-behavioral theoretical termswould seem to depend
(Zuriff, 1976, p. 51).
only on the heuristic values of the two approaches"
Dualism
Not a simple issue. But neither is itone that is solved by claiming that "my toothache isas
physical as my typewriter" (Skinner, 1972, p. 384). How can that be? Is not a toothache in
in different terms, and
that limbo of "some other level of observation, described
measured...in
different dimensions," along with theories and other embarrassments?
Skinner's verbal behavior here appears to be more under the control of formal properties
(alliteration) than physical properties. We may wish to avoid the long, usually dense,
sometimes tedious, philosophical analyses of the mind/body issue by such a fiat. But the
difference between toothaches and typewriters remains. Now we must invent some new
dimension along which to differentiate them.Whatever we label that dimension, itwill have
two ends (or at least directions), and thus support a new charge of dualism.
"
Mental" need not be equated with angels, uncaused causes, and other superstitions. It is
a convenient rubric for many of the phenomena that led most of us into the field of
psychology, and which remain fit subjects for study, despite our years of neglect. The act of
faith that such phenomena are best treated as behavior threatens to overextend our primary
the clock
construct, and to jeopardize it in the eyes of critics even where it is secure?when
strikes thirteen, the previous twelve become suspect. Natsoulas
(1983) concluded that
was not in a
"Skinner has not got the problem of conscious content right. Moreover...he
position to get this problem right because of the impoverished conceptual apparatus...given
the philosophy of psychology to which he stands committed" (p. 19). Can we not
countenance a variety of constructs as requisite to the variety of events in our purview? I
suggest thatwe can, and thatwe can do so without loss of our soul, and even without the loss
of our identity as behaviorists.
Limitations of Self-Descriptive Repertoires,
and Their Confounding by Overt Behavior
objections may be treated together. The first is based on two accurate
observations; We are not "wired" to be able to observe all of our covert processes. And, we
rely on a verbal community to shape our verbal repertoire, but that has only restricted access
to our internal events, and is thus able to afford only imperfect tutelage. For both reasons, we
These
often
rely on
observations
of our
overt
in our
behavior
attempts
to clarify
our
internal
events
or states. Thus, we might offer "I'm hungry" as an explanation for a second helping,
although that utterance isbased more on the public stimulus of refilling the plate than on any
internal stimulus. This is often a useful thing to do. Of course, not infrequently such post-hoc
explanations are mere fabrications, social conventions that are difficult to disapprove, and
which thus function to stifle further probes (or to facilitate further interactions; Goffman,
1971). They are "lines", and if theywork well on our audience, we may even be taken in by
them ourselves (Nisbett & Wilson,
1977; Sabini & Silver, 1981).
Of course, "there are good reasons why a speaker should turn his verbal behavior upon
himself," and establishing stimulus control by internal stimuli, calibrated by the observation
of public stimuli (and by such helpful labels as "I guess Iwas hungrier than I thought"), isone
reason. Such statement should not be taken as absolute assertions of causality so much as
31
This content downloaded from 129.219.247.33 on Wed, 26 Jun 2013 20:51:14 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
EMERGENT BEHAVIORISM
hypotheses that may lead to self-knowledge, however uncertainly. They also may lead to
frames of reference that exert continuing control over our subsequent overt behavior (Bern,
1972).
Because our introspections can be unreliable does not mean that they, and the private
events that they label, do not function as links in a causal chain. The private events may
control overt behavior even when not introspected. Introspection may supply labels that
amplify the control of private events?even when the labels are inaccurate, and even when
they are incorrect, and thus block control by the stimuli on which they are based. In their
review of attitude and attitude change, Cialdini, Petty and Cacioppo
(1981) note that "no
longer are researchers questioning ifattitudes predict behaviors, theyare investigating when
attitudes predict behaviors....
have] found that attitudes had causal
[Researchers
predominance over behaviors" (p.366).
In fact, Skinner acknowledges the existence of inner causes. Zuriff (1979) lists ten inner
causes invoked in the writings of Skinner, and suggests that Skinner's objection is not to
inner causes, per se, but to the kinds of theories that both postulate them and that are also
incomplete, ad hoc, not measurable, and so on (cf. Creel, 1980). Apparently, it is not
mentalism that is a problem, just bad mentalism.
In summary, inner causes need not be introspected to serve as causes. Our fallibility in
overt
describing them, and our attempts to improve those descriptions by calibration with
behavior, should provoke interested, even intense, study of the relation between inner and
outer causes. It is Skinner's inconsistency in stating his position on these matters that has
scared off young researchers, for no matter what theydo, theyare liable to be condemned by
a mentalist if they study inner causes, as a methodological
their sophisticated peers?as
behaviorist if they ignore them.
HYPOTHESES, THEORIES, EMPIRICS
have often gotten poorly sorted in Skinner's metaphysics. Hypotheses are
scientific guesses; both behaviorists and mentalists make them. They may be hard to notice
in Skinner's writings because of the certitude with which he states them, but ask yourself,
wherever he makes an assertion, "What are the data underlying that statement?" You will
find many unsupported. For example, in discussing the process by which a community
answer questions such as "Do you intend
shapes us to observe our own behavior in order to
not involve mediating processes" such as
"do
to go?" he emphasizes that such contingencies
not
a
properly documented (See the interchange
feelings (1972, p. 19). If this is fact, it is
between Zajonc(1980,
1984) and Lazarus (1982, 1984) on this issue). If it is an opinion, it is
unfair to dress it in the italics of a fact. By avoiding calling his ideas hypotheses, Skinner
These
avoids having to test them.
Because theydefine
Theories are ways of organizing bodies of data and empirical laws.
and expanded,
modified
the nature of appropriate data, and because they are continually
come
after our data
cannot
as useful or useless. But theories
theyare not so much true or false
must
grow together with the
collection is complete, as Skinner suggests they should; they
turn
in
so
that
may be modified by the
they
data, so that theymay guide their collection, and
evidence.
that some
a theory is rightly regarded with some respect, it is inevitable
tomake,
hard
often
is
distinction
scientists try to elevate their speculations into theories (the
not
have
however,
Most
speculations,
since, at their inception, new theories are speculative.
to
called
be
and
thorough enough,
worked through existing data, are not broad enough
for such a shortcut to the top motivated much of
disdain
a
that
I
believe
righteous
theories).
Because
32
This content downloaded from 129.219.247.33 on Wed, 26 Jun 2013 20:51:14 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
KILLEEN
Skinner's (1975) disparagement of theory. But the theoretical road is not itself easy.
Theoreticians may labor harder over data than those who collected them, and may
understand them more profoundly. Good theory is to be admired. It guides research. It
summarizes and simplifies manifolds of data. It is the lietmotif that provides continuity and
harmony to empiricism.
The Insidious Nature of Covert Hypotheses
Skinner was correct in noting that premature hypothesis formation and testing may
preclude a more open-minded and fruitful exploration of phenomena. But even more
dangerous is a premature closure that isattained by not treating one's insights as hypotheses,
and therefore in need of testing. Thinking of a speculation as a hypotheses helps us to
disengage from it if it turns out wrong. If we think it as an assumption or take it to be
its invalidation would threaten thewhole system, and we are more likely to cling
tenaciously to it,and to become doctrinaire. Or worse, bellicose. Witness the recent review of
Gibson's work by Costali (1984), who questions the existence of cognitive structures, and
seeks "an alternative scheme that does not merely question the solutions put forward by
cognitive psychologists but converts their very problems from implicit to conspicuous
nonsense." Cognitive psychologists are not innocent of confusion and error, both of the
types that Skinner has identified, and others as well (Sampson, 1981). But denigration such
as Costall's ismore likely to hurt the behaviorist movement than the cognitivist, for itplaces
us in the roles of confounder, critic and saboteur, in all less seemly and less productive
postures than that of originator. Science must be self-correcting, but since so much is
provisional and since all systems contain flaws, the demonstration of a superior approach is
much more effective in bringing about correction than is fault-finding. Let us agree with
axiomatic,
(1981) that "it is premature to depict cognitive accounts as inherently flawed and
unworthy of the serious, dispassionate attention of radical behaviorists" (p. 167).
Wessells
THE POSSIBILITY OF EMPIRICAL MENTALISM
success was not due to the fact that itwas atheoretical (itwas not?it was
merely inchoately theoretical), nor that itwas anti-mentalistic (spitting into that wind has
Its success was due to its
kept us from studying some of themost intriguing phenomena).
not get too far removed
that
discourse
its
and
insistence
for
data,
respect
empiricism?its
from it.The Queen told Alice that she could believe as many as six impossible things before
breakfast; when analysis is stacked onto more than one or two tenuous assumptions,
behaviorists lose their taste for themeal. This isnot to say that theory is thereby denied them.
Anyone current with the discussions of maximizing versus matching in the analysis of
Behaviorism's
choice, of economic behaviorism, of optimal foraging, of behavioral momentum, will
recognize that the name of the primary journal may soon have to be changed to the Journal
of theExperimental -andTheoretical Analysis of Behavior. I think this is excellent progress.
and
The study of mind has proceeded from the opposite direction?speculative
some
a
word.
not
With
four-letter
that
it
involves
is
its
That
practice,
problem,
unempirical.
it is possible to say "mind" without a shudder of revulsion, and even to consider that itmight
be preferable to "covert behavior," the first term of which has the synonyms "clandestine,"
"surreptitious," and "furtive," suggesting the overthrow of elected governments and the
same experimental
mining of harbors. The second term seduces us into believing that the
events at some other
for
will
do
behavior
overt
of
in
the
served
have
that
study
techniques
level of observation, described in different terms, and measured in different dimensions.
They may, but why limit ourselves?
33
This content downloaded from 129.219.247.33 on Wed, 26 Jun 2013 20:51:14 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
EMERGENT BEHAVIORISM
"The objection to inner states is not that they do not exist, but that theyare not relevant
ina functional analysis"(Skinner,
1953, p. 35). "The major behaviorist objection to cognitive
or mental explanations
is not that they are not objective, or that they are based on
the probability of investigation of
...but rather that they...decrease
introspection,
"Mentalistic
ideas are so seductive that one is
variables"
(Branch, 1982, p. 373).
manipulable
of being led by them down
the garden path of introspection and
can afford to entertain the seductress"
a
behaviorist
minded
only tough
mysticism....Perhaps
Is
that
all that Skinner and other radical
in
Catania,
1982, p. 375).
(Pavio, quoted
behaviorists have been objecting to then, a dalliance with unproductive ideas? (Do not
dismiss that objection by noting that ideas, as collateral by-products, cannot themselves in
in danger
any case produce behavior. It is the texts inwhich you read them, and what you say about
them to yourself and to others, that has the behaviorists worried, not ideas themselves). But
what if this concern ismisplaced? What if invocation of inner states and mental explanations
turns out to be useful? What ifSkinner was rightwhen he said that "part of human progress
has been the improvement of our description of these things [internal states]"(1964, p. 106)?
We know the importance of chains of conditioned reinforcers: "Unless the gap between
behavior and the ultimate reinforcer is bridged with a sequence of conditioned reinforcers,
other behavior will occur and receive the full force of reinforcement" (Skinner, 1958, p. 95).
about the gap between stimulus and response? How do humans mediate long gaps
there, if not by talking to themselves, visualizing objects in familiar locations, and
performing other mental gymnastics? Behaviorists accept such feats, preferring only thatwe
call them behavior: seeing behavior, choice behavior, imagining behavior. But that
qualification must take some of the fun out of it, for few behaviorists study those covert
chains that mediate so much of human behavior.
What
Other researchers, less certain about the irrelevance of internal states, have attained
insights about them that even behaviorists must applaud, if that be only briefly before they
attempt to "translate" them, or with Costali, "reduce them to explicit nonsense." Posner
(1982) has outlined the rich interaction ofmodels and data in thedevelopment of attentional
theory. E. R. John, a critic of the behavioristic minimization of research on mental
phenomena, has traced stimuli into the brain bymeasuring the evoked responses to rhythmic
stimuli, tagged by its own rhythmicity. Among his findings: localization of the areas
responding to the stimuli, and their spread during conditioning; upon introduction to the
experimental chamber the rhythmic brain activity commences, "as if the animal were
rehearsing the experience of themeaningful stimulus"; activization of that evoked response
when the event is expected but absent; in differential conditioning, errors preceded by the
rhythm appropriate to the incorrect (and not displayed) stimulus (John, 1976).
The elegant work of Shepard and his students on mental transformations should by now
be well known to all psychologists. In an accessible introduction to his work, Shepard (1978)
notes the important role that imagery has played in the physical and life sciences. Shepard
and Podgorny (1978) document and demonstrate many of the pervasive parallels between
In his paper "Psychophysical Complementarity"
cognitive and perceptual processes.
he
that
argues
(Shepard, 1981)
evolutionary constraints have shaped the nature of our
and
and that these achieve a rapid "mesh" with the
processes,
perceptual
cognitive
environment via certain predispositions that guide our inferences in uncertain situations.
arguments, perhaps, but he makes exceptional use of them. This view is
Unexceptional
parallel with that of Land (1978), a most practical scientist, who argues that animals evolved
in a "polar partnership" with theworld around them,with an inner order related to an outer
order; related, Shepard would say, as a key to a lock. Many of Shepard's critical papers are
34
This content downloaded from 129.219.247.33 on Wed, 26 Jun 2013 20:51:14 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
KILLEEN
in Shepard and Cooper
discussed
(1982). There one finds scores of
demonstrations such as: The time taken to decide whether two figures are the same depends
not only on how many degrees one must mentally rotate them to get them aligned, itdepends
also on whether one rotates them the short way or the long way; when the subject is given a
head-start on rotating an image before a second figure is presented, if it is presented when the
collected
and
subject should have reached that orientation with their image, reaction time is uniformly
short and independent of that orientation; subjects can rotate an image of a concrete object,
but not of a frame of reference; rotation is either continuous or, ifnot, the size of thediscrete
steps must be less than 30 degrees. Other transformations, such as dilation, contraction,
translation, and translation of attention to different parts of the image, are also reported (see
also
the work of Kosslyn; e.g., 1980). The wealth of creative experiments and systematic
analyses thwarts simple summary. More than Skinner ever did, Shepard and his associates
are treating seeing as behavior. They seem not at all hampered by their resolution that the
"thing" to which "seeing without the thing seen" refers isan image, and that subjects need not
do without it. To the contrary.
But behaviorists have never been very much interested in
perception (Kantor, 1970);
perhaps we should leave imagery to those who have a head start on us, both experimentally and
conceptually (for the latter, see Block, 1981). Our interests have been pragmatic, concerning
"manipulate variables of which behavior is a function"?Behavior Modification. Of course
even there imagery will sometimes intrude. Covert sensitization and desensitization involve
imagery, but except for the inconvenience, those procedures could be effected overtly. And,
presumably, covert behavior "behaves" in the same fashion as overt behavior. But perhaps not
always: Meichenbaum
(1974) reviews studies where the covert processes do not respond to
contingencies in the same fashion as overt behavior. Given theuntoward overt responses of some
animals to contingencies of reinforcement, and their recalcitrance to
ordinary conditioning
procedures (Breland & Breland, 1966),we should not be surprised to find that there are special
constraints on cognitive conditioning. But, with few exceptions (e.g., Catania, Matthews, &
Shimoff, 1982;McGuigan,
1978;Neuringer, 1981), behaviorists have not been looking. "If those
espousing a so-called radical behavioristic approach to cognition are to convert thosewhom they
label cognitivists, then theywill have to do so with experimentation and data"
(Wasserman,
1983). If,and when, we assay that shiftfrom rhetoric to research,we may be infor some surprises
(Longstreth, 1971).
But, finally, does not the study of mental phenomena, in cognitive terms, force us into a
dualistic metaphysics? No, itdoes not. As Bunge (1980) notes,
the thesis that
dualism does not force us to adopt eliminative or vulgar materialism...i.e.,
rejecting psychophysical
mind and brain are identical, that there is no mind.... Psychobiology
i.e., the thesis that
suggests...emergentism,
is an emergent property possessed
only by animals endowed with an extremely complex and plastic
mentality
nervous system.... [This] is not saying thatminds constitute a level of their own, and this simply because
disembodied
[One] can hold that themental
(or even embodied) minds, but only...minding animals...
relative to the merely physical without reifying the former, (pp.216-217)
Emergent materialism. What
there are no
is emergent
is the difference between this and mentalism?
difference boils down to this: whereas mentalism has (simple)
terms alone, materialism gropes for (usually complex) explanations
possibly social circumstances as well. (Bunge, 1980, p. 214)
The
for everything mental in mental
explanations
of the mental in terms of brain processes and
It appears, then, that what I have been calling empirical mentalism Bunge would call
emergent materialism. Call itby either name, it is time for "tough minded behaviorists" to
entertain the notion. It is time for them to become "emergent behaviorists."
35
This content downloaded from 129.219.247.33 on Wed, 26 Jun 2013 20:51:14 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
EMERGENT BEHAVIORISM
PRINCIPLES OF EMERGENT BEHAVIORISM
What would Emergent Behaviorism be like? It would not be a "methodological
behaviorism" that draws a boundary for its subject coextensive with the skin. Nor would itbe
a cognitive psychology that, at itsworst, draws the same boundary but stays inside of it.Nor
would it be a radical behaviorism that has been short-sheeted by its own parsimony,
contorting its basic theoretical terms to cover areas that are out of their reach.
It would be behavioral. Our roots are in the study of animal behavior, and in the
rejection of introspective mental models for its explanation. An impressionistic theory of
human motivation provides a poor foundation for a theory of animal behavior. But,
conversely, a theory of the behavior of non-verbal animals provides a problematic basis for
the study of human behavior, including that covert behavior called mental activity. Our
behaviorism would be emergent because it recognizes the causal relevance of mental states,
and thus the utility of having theoretical terms within the system to refer to those states.
Itwould be inductive. But its induction would be Peirce's(Rescher,
1978), not Skinner's
on observed
based
It
the
of
would
involve
1954).
generation
hypotheses
(Verplanck,
on
based
those
the
of
modification
and
empirical tests
hypotheses
regularities ("abduction"),
concern
as
events
"at
another
Insofar
these
level," this
may
("retroduction").
hypotheses
constitutes a rejection of Skinner's positivism.
Like Skinner's behaviorism, itwould be pragmatic (Platt, 1973). Itwould recognize that
"the rationality and progressiveness of a theory are most closely linked?not with its
confirmation or itsfalsification?but ratherwith itsproblem solving effectiveness"(Laudan,
1977, p. 5). The same is true of research traditions; those that are successful are those that
lead to the solution of an increasing range of empirical and conceptual problems. Emergent
behaviorism would result from a cumulation of successful theories and the problem domains
that they have addressed?not
by fiat, nor by aping the traditions of other sciences, nor by
certain
proscribing
techniques on doctrinal grounds. This may seem unexceptional, but I
believe that the commitment of op?rant behaviorists to description rather than problem
solving has thwarted such development.5
Emergent behaviorism would be prudent with its resources, but not parsimonious.
Parsimony is a better criterion for choosing competing theories than for generating new
ones. The conceptual stinginess that it entails impoverishes exploration and thus stifles
progress. It puts all the the emphasis on cost, rather than cost-effectiveness. New constructs
should be viewed as new parameters in a regression equation; they involve a real cost, for
they decrease the degrees of freedom in the data/theory system. But, if the data are
sufficiently strong and numerous, such constructs may greatly improve our ability to
comprehend them. Gratuitous and ad hoc explanations are to be rejected, whether they are
mentalistic or behavioral, simply because they don't pay their way (Rescher, 1978). They
dilute the explanatory power of the theory by introducing a "parameter" that can account for
only a small domain of the data under purview.
In sum, emergent behaviorism would focus on behavior, not on para-scientific theories
about it such as those derrogated by Skinner in the first lines of this paper. Its goals are to
develop successful theories of behavior, and it recognizes that those theories may involve
mental terms. Its methods would include hypothesis generation and testing. It would be
pragmatic, not parsimonious, asking firstwhat we can do, and only second, what itwill cost.
Finally, because itopens the door to new freedom in theory construction, requiring only that
the products pay theirway, it should restore the excitement that some in our field have been
searching for at the back door of cognitivism.
36
This content downloaded from 129.219.247.33 on Wed, 26 Jun 2013 20:51:14 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
KILLEEN
REFERENCES
status of the script concept. American
R. P. (1981). Psychological
Abeison,
Audi, R. (1976). B. F. Skinner on freedom, dignity, and
Bern, D.
J. (1972). Self-perception
B. & Skinner, B. F. (1967). The
27, 317-337.
Block, N.
(1981).
Blanshard,
N. (1982). Misrepresentating
Branch, M.
Breland, K., &
Bunge, M.
Breland, M.
MA:
Catania, A. C,
with nonverbal
The MIT
163-186.
4,
1-62.
6,
debate. Philosophy
and Phenomenological
Row.
and Brain Sciences,
The Behavioral
5, 372-373.
A psychobiological
New York:
approach.
The Behavioral
Pergamon.
and Brain Sciences,
5, 374-375.
Matthews, B. A., & Shimoff, E. (1982). Instructed versus shaped human verbal behavior,
responding. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 38, 233-248.
Cialdini, R. B., Petty, R. E., & Cacioppo,
357404.
A. P. (1984). Are theories of perception necessary? A review of Gibson's
Perception". Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 41, 109-115.
(1980). Radical
epiphenomenalism:
B. F. Skinner's account
"The Ecological
of private events. Behaviorism,
8, 31-53.
R. (1976). Hierarchical organization: a candidate principle for ethnology. In P. P. G. Batesonand
(Eds), Growing Points in Ethology (pp. 7-54). New York: Cambridge University Press.
D. C.
to Visual
Approach
R. A. Hinde
Dawkins,
Dennet,
interactions
J. T. ( 1981). Attitude and attitude change. Annual Review of Psychology, 32,
Costali,
Creel, R.
Behaviorism,
Psychology,
New York: MacMillan.
Behavior.
(1982). Antimisrepresentationalism.
36, 715-729.
Press.
behaviorism.
problem:
Psychologist,
of behavior.
Social
problem of consciousness?a
New York: Harper &
(1966). Animal
(1980). The mind-body
A. C.
Catania,
Imagery. Cambridge,
(1967). Theory of Motivation.
Bolles, R. C.
in Experimental
theory. Advances
Research,
the explanation
(1978) Brainstorms. New York: Bradford Books.
Goff man, E. (1971). Relations
in public: Microstudies
(1976). A model of consciousness.
regulation (pp. 1-50). New York: Plenum.
John, E. R.
order. New York:
of the public
and D.
In G. E. Schwartz
Basic Books.
(Eds.), Consciousness
Shapiro
and
Kantor, J. R. ( 1970). An analysis of the experimental anaylsis of behavior (TE AB). Journal of the Experimental
13, 101-108.
self
Analysis
of Behavior,
Keat, R. (1972). A critical examination
of B. F. Skinner's
objections
to mentalism.
I, 53-70.
Behaviorism,
Killeen, P. R. (1981). Learning as causal inference. In M. L. Commons & J. A. Nevin (Eds.), Quantitative analysis of
behavior (Vol. I): Discriminative properties of reinforcement schedules (pp. 89-112). Cambridge, MA: Ballinger.
Kosslyn, S. M.
(1980).
MA:
Image and mind. Cambridge,
Harvard
Land, E. H. (1978) Our "polar partnership" with the world around
Loudan,
L. (1977). Progress and itsproblems:
Toward
University Press.
us. Harvard Magazine,
January/February,
23-26.
a theory of scientific growth. Berkeley: University of California
Press.
Lazarus, R. S. (1982). Thoughts
Lazarus,
R. S. (1984). On
on the relations between emotion and cognition. American Psychologist.
the primacy of cognition. American
Psychologist,
39,
Longstreth, L. E. (1971) A cognitive interpretation of secondary reinforcement. In J. K. Cole
on motivation (pp. 33-80). Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press.
Lowe, C. F. (1983). Radical behaviorism and human psychology.
behavior (pp. 71-93). New York: John Wiley & Sons.
McGuigan,
Hall.
Meichenbaum,
Michael,
Natsoulas,
D.
(1974). Cognitive
behavior modification.
J. (1980). Untitled presentation. Behaviorism,
T.
(1983). Perhaps
In G. C. L. Davey
Principles of covert behavior.
F. J. (1978). Cognitive psychophysiology:
8,
the most difficult problem
Morristown,
37,1019-1024.
124-129.
NJ: General
(Ed.) Nebraska
(Ed.), Animal models
Press.
161-163.
faced by behaviorism.
Behaviorism,
37
This content downloaded from 129.219.247.33 on Wed, 26 Jun 2013 20:51:14 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
of human
Cliffs, NJ: Prentice
Englewood
Learning
symposium
II,
1-26.
EMERGENT BEHAVIORISM
A call for change. Behaviorism,
Neuringer, A. J. (1981). Self-experimentation:
T. D.
Platt, J. R. (1973). The
Francisco: Freeman.
Skinnerian
I. (1982). Cumulative
Posner, M.
development
Rescher, N. (1978). Peirce's philosophy
of attentional
the punitive
(Ed), Beyond
theory. American
society (pp. 22-56). San
Psychologist,
168-179.
37,
IN: University Press.
of science. Notre Dame,
in the pigeon. Journal of the Experimental
Reynolds, G. S. (1961). Attention
Sabini, J.& Silver M.
In H. Wheeler
revolution.
9, 79-94.
than we know: Verbal reports on mental processes. Psychological
(1977). Telling more
Nisbett, R. E., & Wilson,
Review, 84, 231-259.
of Behavior, 4, 203-208.
Analysis
( 1981). Introspection and causal accounts. Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology, 40,171
179.
psychology as ideology. American
Sampson,
E. E. (1981). Cognitive
Shepard,
R. N. (1978). The mental
Shepard,
R. N.
organization
Shepard,
image. American
Psychologist,
In M. Kubovy
Psychophysical
complementarity.
(pp. 279-341). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
R. N., & Cooper,
L. A. (1982). Mental
R. N., & Zare, S. (1983). Path-guided
Sidman, M.
(1958). By-products
Sidman, M.
(1979). Remarks.
Simon, H. A.
&
J. R.
(1973). The organization
Pomerantz
images and their transformations. Cambridge,
(Eds.),
MA:
Perceptual
The MIT
Press.
that resemble perceptual processes. InW. K. Estes (Ed.),
189-237). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
apparent motion.
Science,
220, 632-634.
of aversive control. Journal of the Experimental
Behaviorism,
36, 730-743.
125-137.
(1981).
Shepard, R. N., & Podgorny, P. (1978). Cognitive processes
Handbook
of learning and cognitive processes (vol. 5) (pp.
Shepard,
Psychologist,
33,
Analysis
of Behavior,
I, 256-280.
7, 123-126.
of complex
systems. In H. H. Pattee (Ed.), Hierarchy
theory.
Skinner, B. F. (1938). The behavior of organisms. New York: Appleton-Century.
Skinner, B. F. (1953). Science
Skinner, B. F. (1957).
and human behavior. New York: Free Press.
Verbal behavior. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
Skinner, B. F. (1958). Reinforcement
today. American
at 50. Science,
Skinner, B. F. (1963). Behaviorism
13, 94-99.
Psychologist,
140, 951-958.
Skinner, B. F. (1964). Comments at symposium. In T. W. Wann (Ed.), Behaviorism
bases for modern psychology (pp. 97-108). Chicago: The University Press.
Skinner, B. F. (1969). Contingencies
of reinforcement: A
and phenomenology:
Contrasting
theoretical analysis. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
Skinner, B. F. (1971). Beyond freedom and dignity. New York: Knopf.
and behaviorism.
Skinner, B. F. (1972). Humanism
Skinner, B. F. (1974). About
Skinner, B. F. (1975). The
behaviorism.
The Humanist,
New York: Knopf,
steep and thorny way
July/August,
18-20.
1974.
to a science of behavior. American
Psychologist,
30, 42-49.
Sober, E. (1983) Mentalism and behaviorism in comparative psychology. In D. W. Rajecki (Ed.), Comparing
Studying man studying animals (pp. 113-142). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
to action: The allocation
Staddon,
J. E. R.
(1980). Limits
Staddon,
J. E. R.
(1983). Adaptive
of individual behavior. New York: Academic
behavior and learning. New York: Cambridge
behavior:
Press.
University Press.
P. E. Meehl, W. S. Verplanck, W. K.
Verplanck, W. S. (1954). Burrhus F. Skinner. In S. Koch, K. MacCorquodale,
Estes, C. G. Mueller, Jr.,& W. N. Schoenfeld, Modern
learning theory (pp. 267-316). New York: Appleton-Century
Crofts.
Wasserman,
E. A.
(1983).
Is cognitive psychology behavioral?
Psychological
Wessells, M. G. (1981). A critique of Skinner's views on the explanatory
9, 153-170.
Zajonc,
R. B. (1984). On
the primacy of affect. American
Psychologist,
Record,
33, 6-11.
inadequacy of cognitive theories. Behaviorism,
39,
117-123.
38
This content downloaded from 129.219.247.33 on Wed, 26 Jun 2013 20:51:14 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
KILLEEN
Zuriff, G. E. (1976). Stimulus
Zuriff, G. E. (1979). Ten
equivalence,
grammar, and
inner causes. Behaviorism,
internal structure. Behaviorism,
4, 43-52.
7, 1-8.
NOTES
and some are
?Some of these constructs are operationally defined (contingencies and motivational
operations)
1000 schedule that is ineffective inmaintaining
functionally defined (stimuli and responses). Thus, a Fixed Ratio
behavior remains a Fixed Ratio 1000 schedule, but a "stimulus" that is ineffective in controlling behavior is not a
stimulus. This is a curious mix of types. Certainly motivational constructs can be defined functionally (see, e.g., Bolles,
1967). So can reinforcement contingencies, although that ismore difficult and requires a feedback/control
language
Skinner and subsequent
1980, 1983). And stimuli and responses can be defined operationally?as
(Staddon
Experimental Analysts of Behavior routinely reported experiments using lights of some color, counting lever-presses of
some force and so on. Unless we designed explicit experiments (e.g., as did Reynolds [1961]), we couldn't know that
responses of a slightly different topography were under the control of different aspects of the same stimulus. No matter
admired, such analyses are usually undertaken only when the experimenter runs into trouble (see, e.g.,
1958). Thus while the op?rant in theory isan act (i.e., it is defined functionally), in practice it is usually defined
of the cue, the operand urn, and the feeder.
operationally as the closure of three switches in sequence?those
how much
Sidman,
2Without such interaction, there would be little need for the constructs. In cases where behavior becomes habitual or
automatized, and thereforemore resistant tomodification, themore complex control provided by internal events such as
self-instruction has given way to simpler chains of behavior; guidance by mental events vanishes, and with it the need for
corresponding theoretical terms. But there are many occasions, themost characteristically human, where such control is
present: the ability to guide, speculate, calculate and evaluate. Skinner discusses these different sources of control in his
important article on rule-governed vs. contingency-shaped
him in this venture to terra cognita.
behavior
(1969). Unfortunately,
few behaviorists
followed
3This arresting assertion is like a Zen koan, involving the nice contradiction that transitive verbs need not have predicates.
Just why Skinner should deny that "private stimuli"can be "seen" is unclear. He denies the name "image" to an ensemble
of them for fear of our seduction by the belief that there is a physical copy present in the brain. However, experiments to
be cited below suggest that functionally the best way to treat such private events may be as images, because of themany
properties they share with the referents of that term in its natural language use.
that optimize learning in animals also satisfy Hume's conditions for inferring causality?contiguity
in
space, precedence in time, and constancy of conjunction (Killeen, 1981). But these are transcended and modified by
mental activity, just as Korte's laws for perceived motion of flashing lights are modified by placing an arched "path"
above the lights (Shepard & Zare, 1983).
4The conditions
introduction of the construct "establishing stimulus*
5One of the few such elaborations I have seen recently isMichael's
(1980; see also Sidman, 1979). I believe that itwas Skinner's contempt for (other people's) theory that lefthis students
unprepared to develop his own.
39
This content downloaded from 129.219.247.33 on Wed, 26 Jun 2013 20:51:14 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
40
This content downloaded from 129.219.247.33 on Wed, 26 Jun 2013 20:51:14 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions