Jan Slaby
1
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
Intentionality’s
Breaking Point
A Lesson from Grief
Abstract: This paper develops elements of a phenomenological
account of how interpersonal care contributes to the structure of
intentionality. It does so by reflecting on a first-person account of
parental grief by the poet and thinker Denise Riley. Her autobiographical notes on the aftermath of the death of her adult son revolve
around a marked experience of altered temporal flow. By relating
what she considers to be an almost unspeakable alteration in her
experience of time, Riley unearths a level of nuanced phenomenological reflection that can inform philosophical studies of lived time
and intentionality. The paper will build on Riley’s observations on
altered temporal experience in grief to explore the entanglement of
temporality and intersubjectivity in the constitution of intentionality.
By doing so, the paper demonstrates that and how a phenomenological study of grief can directly speak to key concerns of the philosophy of mind and of interdisciplinary consciousness studies.
1. Introduction
After losing her adult son to unexpected, sudden death, Denise Riley
describes the immediate aftermath as follows:
Correspondence:
Email:
[email protected]
1
Institute of Philosophy, Free University Berlin, Germany.
Journal of Consciousness Studies, 29, No. 9–10, 2022, pp. 105–27
DOI: 10.53765/20512201.29.9.105
106
J. SLABY
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
The plainest simplest horror from which the mind flinches away: never
to see that person again. The purely cognitive violence of it. Now you
understand those ideas of the migration of spirits, or of reincarnation: to
try to soften that blow. Or no, not to soften it — but to provide something for baffled cognition to grasp at. (Riley, 2019, p. 28)
Besides conveying the unrefined horror of her situation, Riley here
approaches a theme that is common in discussions of the topic: the
inability to take in, to ‘get’, to grasp the death of a loved one. The
definiteness, the infinity, the absoluteness of the phrase ‘He is dead’
marks a vast gap between the processing of a bit of information, a
propositional truth, and the existential reality of what that dreaded
phrase implies. With her considerations on the disruptive, uprooting
character of grief, Riley’s autobiographical reflections align with an
important strand of theoretical work on grief that likewise emphasizes
its destructive impact on the overall experiential perspective — the
lived reality — of the mourner. But over and above this more general,
and by and large familiar, theme of grief’s disruptive character, there
is a specific theme that surfaces in Riley’s reflections: at the centre of
what she reports stands her radically altered experience of time.
Strikingly, she observes a near total cessation of temporal flow. In
the months after she learned of her son’s demise, time for her seemed
to stand still. Riley, no doubt also against the background of her
familiarity with the phenomenological tradition, takes this as a starting
point for reflections on the centrality of parental love — or more
abstractly put, interpersonal care — for the temporal integrity of
experience. What she tentatively calls a ‘maternal temporality’ — an
intertwining of the lived temporalities of mother and child — can thus
form the basis of a consideration on the interpersonal and essentially
temporal foundations of experience.
In this paper, I will assemble elements of a phenomenological
account of the temporal foundation of intentionality — the ‘directedness’ of experience at both world and self — by drawing closely on
Riley’s observations. Her considerations point to a so far underappreciated connection between parental care, the emerging integrity
of a child’s experiential perspective, and the lived time at the base of
the adult’s own perspective on self and world. By reconstructing these
interrelations, I begin to explore the possibility that the temporal
attunement of parent and child might reveal important structural
features of an account of intentionality as socially shared lived time
and thus help advance the phenomenological elucidation of the
conditions of human experience.
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
INTENTIONALITY’S BREAKING POINT
107
The paper is structured as follows. In Section 2, I will briefly consider aspects of the phenomenological literature on grief to focus
especially on the way grief shatters the mourner’s default sense of
world-relatedness and practical coping capacities. This provides the
first general invocation of intentionality as orientation to and in the
world — hence, the title of this text: intentionality’s breaking point. In
Section 3, I will turn to Denise Riley’s observations of altered temporal experience in grief and offer an interpretation of it in terms of
interpersonally shared existential temporality: the temporality of interpersonal care or love. In Section 4, I relate these considerations to the
wider context of phenomenological debates about the temporal
character of intentionality, drawing on ideas from Bergson,
Heidegger, and Levinas. I argue that the altered temporality in experiences of profound parental grief provides a new and important perspective on the temporal structure of intentionality as such. In Section
5, I take up a proposal by Line Ingerslev to illuminate the agentive
dimension of the grieving process — what is sometimes called ‘grief
work’ — in relation to the ideas about temporality developed before.
Section 6 is a brief conclusion and outlook.
2. How Grief Breaks It: Loss of a World
For a start, it helps to recount some themes from the phenomenological literature on grief, to get a sense of the significance of experiences of grief for the broader project of elucidating human experience.
The focus in the following will be on grief’s intentionality, as the
orientation to emotional intentionality has been the guiding thread in
most work in the philosophy of emotion over the past decades.
That grief is an emotional response to a significant loss, usually the
loss of a loved one, is clear. In the common parlance of the philosophy
of emotion, ‘loss’ is understood to be the formal object of grief. More
interesting is what this most parsimonious characterization of grief as
a ‘response to significant loss’ does not yet convey. It fails to get at
the potential depth and significance of profound grief, and it provides
little to make sense of the longer-term unfolding of what might have
started as a shock-like response. In order to get a discussion of
affective intentionality to a level where significant insights might be
gleaned, we have to ensure that a phenomenological characterization
reaches the full extent of the existential devastation that grief might
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
108
2
J. SLABY
bring.2 The focus from the outset is on particularly profound instances
of bereavement-related grief, where grief is the dominant, almost allconsuming experience for a significant amount of time. Empirically,
many instances of grief will certainly be less profound, more shortlived, and not as disruptive or ‘shattering’ as those instances that are
of particular interest to phenomenologists. I note this here to make
sure the following is understood correctly: I do not try to make claims
about the character of many or most actual manifestations of grief, but
rather get at a structural feature that is most clearly on display in the
profound cases.
Grief is obviously different from short flashes of affect or bouts of
emotion. While there might indeed be ‘pangs of grief’, these are only
intelligible as elements occurring within longer lasting sequences of
emotional engagement, of grappling with loss. Grief is the process of
grieving, which is to say it is temporally extended and changeable:
‘there is no single, constant, essential ingredient that we can track
across its whole course’ (Ratcliffe, 2017, p. 158). I won’t go into
details about the arguments against a simplistic ‘mental state’ account
of grief and in favour of complex process perspective (see Goldie,
2012; Rinofner-Kreidl, 2016; Ratcliffe, 2017). I agree with Goldie,
Ratcliffe, Rinofner-Kreidl, and other scholars in or close to the
phenomenological tradition that considerations in favour of grief’s
longer-term processual character should be tied to an understanding of
its affective intentionality. This is a simple way to make the point:
what profound grief is about is a personal loss suffered in the full
thrall of its ramifications and consequences for the emoter’s existence.
The loss suffered is so significant that it is impossible to take in its
facticity and impacts instantaneously, let alone understand and
accommodate it. Rather, such loss requires a gradual, longer-lasting
process of grasping it bit by bit, which likely will occasion timeconsuming learning and adjustment phases (see Rinofner-Kreidl,
2016). Grieving involves an enduring episode of ‘coming to terms’
with the loss and what it means to one. Accordingly, we can assume
that grief is a process of encompassing engagement with existential
loss, likely involving much in the way of confusion, disarray, and
I am skipping a discussion of the character of grief as an extended process instead of a
supposedly short-term internally homogeneous mental state. See Goldie (2012, chapter
3) and especially Fuchs (2018), Rinofner-Kreidl (2016), and Ratcliffe (2017) for
valuable illuminations of these points.
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
INTENTIONALITY’S BREAKING POINT
3
109
disorientation in its course, especially early on. It is an enduring
affective sequence consisting of heterogeneous elements united by
their being jointly oriented towards the gradual realization and ‘processing’ of catastrophic existential loss (cf. Ratcliffe, 2017).
A field-defining insight of phenomenology is that experience presupposes a basic sense of reality which provides the framework in
which things matter to us in specific ways (Ratcliffe, 2008, chapter 2).
In other words, intentional world-directedness has (at least) two
distinct layers. When we relate to certain objects, events, states of
affairs — for instance by perceiving them, thinking about them, or
being angered by them — such mundane experiences unfold against
the backdrop of a more encompassing sense of experiential possibility.
In many of our routine dealings with our surroundings, this pervasive
sense of possibility remains in the background as something we
unthinkingly rely on. But on certain occasions, what we are facing
within the world is such that it reveals cracks within that background
framework, and potentially more than just cracks. Traumatic experiences, bereavement, potentially severe ramifications of the loss of a
job or career, serious illness, and other happenings of a similar magnitude can occasion a change in the otherwise seamless background
structure of experience. What emotional experiences respond to in
these cases is not some mundane matter of concern, but something
that exceeds — or threatens to exceed — the bounds of paramount
reality as hitherto established.3
In her reflections on her condition, Denise Riley provides a stark
image of how worldly significance has been disrupted in the wake of
her son’s death:
An unanticipated and irrevocable vanishing smashes through your
habitual cognitive assumptions that objects and people will continue to
exist, to reappear. The person who says, ‘I keep expecting to hear his
key in the door at any moment,’ isn’t merely falling back on a wellworn trope. She’s issuing a factual report. Once so ferociously shaken
up, cognition can’t readily regroup its forces to reassemble with its old
I think that ultimately all emotions touch upon that background framework of significance in some way, but some do it in a particularly profound manner in so far as their
objects are such that they perturb the presupposed background framework. This sometimes leads to a characteristic choice on part of the emoter: gloss over and effectively
‘deny’ this existential depth and its ramifications (for instance when we instinctively
block out emotions pertaining to our own mortality or bodily fragility) or ‘face up to’
them and begin a process of adjusting the background orientation on which one has
tacitly relied.
110
J. SLABY
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
anticipation intact. The entire stance inside which you’d previously
lived is changed. Not by any disfiguring melancholia on your part, or
even by simple reflective sadness — but by an upheaval of that preconscious topography through which your old apprehension of the
world had once quietly moved. (Riley, 2019, pp. 59f.)
While Riley directs her attention somewhat more to the cognitive side
of the person–world mutuality, phenomenologists tend to foreground
the way in which the world itself seems to change in relation to such
traumatic disruption. But it seems clear that both speak of different
aspects of the same fundamental predicament. Where the very
integrity of the experiential world is concerned, the capacity for
cognition seems to be impaired, not just its exercises on this or that
occasion. This is what Riley speaks of and phenomenologists likewise
assume. Ratcliffe proposes the following elucidation of what may be
the focal point of such disruption:
The person who has died was not only an object within one’s world but
also a condition of intelligibility for that world. Complete acknowledgement of loss therefore involves a disturbance of the world within which
the loss is initially experienced as occurring. (Ratcliffe, 2019a, p. 660)
In fact, as Riley’s observations suggest, ‘complete acknowledgement’
of the loss may not even be necessary for such a wide-ranging
disturbance or breakdown of the familiar world. It is not a neat twostep process of first taking in the loss of the loved one and its irrevocability and then, second, finding one’s familiar experiential reality in a
shambles. The breakdown in the structure of presupposed significance
can well occur instantly, while the bereaved still very much struggles
with grasping what has happened.
The upshot is clear: the lost loved one had been an integral part of
the structure of intelligibility that had heretofore made up the practical
and experiential world of the mourner, their homely sphere of everyday understanding. The assumption behind this is that the realm of a
person’s practical significance is co-constructed in close social interaction, especially in forms of enduring modes of living together, and
that intimate relationships are particularly relevant in establishing
shared ways of inhabiting the world. Death of a child, a parent, or an
intimate partner can thus occasion a partial or near-encompassing
breakdown of this realm of substantive mutuality, this jointly enacted
‘we-space’ of shared significance (cf. Krueger, 2011). In light of the
breadth and depth of this shared realm, it is not surprising that the
‘uptake’ of its breakdown in emotive comportment can take so many
different forms. Speaking of ‘experience’ here is also somewhat
INTENTIONALITY’S BREAKING POINT
111
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
inadequate, given the difficulty, the struggle involved in processing
what has occurred. We seem to lack the terms to relate this condition
at the verge of breakdown or, as Riley has put it, of both ‘knowing and
not knowing that he’s dead’ (2019, p. 23). Ratcliffe, drawing on
Merleau-Ponty, characterized what goes on in the following terms:
4
5
Grief… affects systems of anticipation that both shape perceptual
experience and provide guidance for action, disrupting what was once
presupposed… [I]t is the practically meaningful connections between
things that are eroded — one’s sense of the overall situation in which
things are experienced as appearing and changing. Determinate arrangements give way to haziness. What is lacking here is not merely
epistemic in nature. It is not just that one cannot find a path to follow;
the paths have gone. (Ratcliffe, 2019a, p. 661)
This helps us see clearer that and how many cases of bereavement
imply that the grieving person’s life as such, with its many cares,
concerns, meanings, and possibilities, has been uprooted. With the
deceased partner, parent, child, or friend, a universe of meaning has
been washed away. In light of this, the intentional object of grief could
as accurately be construed as the loss of a world than as the loss of a
person;4 but the point is of course that the person lost just has been
‘the world’, or a key dimension of the world, to the grieving subject.5
3. Denise Riley: Time Without Its Flow
Riley’s account revolves around the experience of lived time coming
to a halt: time without its flow. At the core of Riley’s condition,
beginning upon her learning of her son’s death and continuing for a
period of nearly three years, lies a near-total cessation of experienced
temporal flow. I will take Riley’s observations as phenomenological
evidence and her own reflections on her experience as informing an
interpretation of the temporal dimension of bereavement, upon which
I will then elaborate. Implications for an understanding of intentionality will become visible along the way.
Ratcliffe construes it thus: ‘the unity of grief instead consists in what it recognizes,
reacts to, and responds to: an all-enveloping, dynamic disturbance of life possibility’
(2017, p. 157).
Accordingly, when people in throes of grief claim the bottom has been knocked out
from under their feet or that the world has collapsed for them, these remarks can be
taken at face value. That is indeed what has happened. In his meditation on his grieving
the death of his wife, C.S. Lewis wrote: ‘Her absence is like the sky, spread over
everything’ (Lewis, 1966, p. xx).
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
112
J. SLABY
Riley reports finding herself sealed in a perpetual present. With the
passage of time halted, there is no transition forward, no anticipation
of what’s to come, no sense of futurity. Riley speaks of this as a
‘freezing of time’ (2019, p. 13); as the ‘extraordinary feeling of atemporality’ (p. 14); as a ‘private non-time of pure stasis’ (p. 15); as a
‘condition of being “outside time”’ (p. 17). She moreover ponders that
the dead ‘give us… a grip on the present instant in which we’re now
relentlessly inserted. Not in a contemplative sense, but vigorously. A
carnal sensation’ (p. 29). And furthermore, she expounds: ‘Simply,
you are no longer in time. Only from your freshly removed perspective can you fully understand how our habitual intuitions of time
are not without their limits, and can falter’ (p. 42).
There are several things to unpack and reflect about here. The first
thing to note is how this dramatic change to lived temporality is
related to the experience of practical significance. The capacity to
navigate one’s world as a sphere of familiar objects and projects relies
on temporal structures of anticipation and recollection. A sense for the
regular passing of time, sequences of past, present, and future in their
concrete entwinement, is required for everyday practical coping. This
is the temporality of habit. Riley points this out herself when she links
the alteration in lived time to a breakdown of routine induction:
Unanticipated death does such violence to your ordinary suppositions,
as if the whole inductive faculty by which you’d previously lived has
faltered. Its textbook illustration was always ‘Will the sun rise
tomorrow?’ But now that induction itself is no more, the sun can’t any
longer be relied on to rise. (ibid., p. 33)
A central part of Riley’s account concerns how she herself attempts to
make sense of her condition of arrested temporality. Her initial gloss
sounds somewhat fantastic. Riley speculates that this peculiar atemporality might be a kind of sharing in the condition of the dead. Death,
after all, could be thought of as a form of falling out of time:
You share the death of your child, in that you approach it so closely that
you sense that a part of you, too, has died that instant. At the same time,
you feel that the spirit of the child has leaped into you. So you are both
partly dead and yet more alive. You are cut down, and yet you burn
with life. (ibid., p. 20)
This appears less fantastic when we consider the full interpretation of
the condition that Riley presents. Her son was integral to her own
world-orientation, an active partner in her elementary engagement
with worldly significance. Upon his death, this pole of her world-
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
INTENTIONALITY’S BREAKING POINT
113
orientation ceases to be active and recedes into the past. Continued
attachment to her son then ‘drags’ Riley into a realm of temporal
stasis: ‘For if timelessness is the time of your dead, you will go with
them in their timelessness… They draw you across to their side, while
you incorporate them on your side’ (ibid., p. 46). Riley now basically
inhabits two separate worlds, where the atemporal, futureless ‘world’
she shares with her son dominates her sense of time (see Fuchs, 2018,
pp. 50f., for elaboration).
This points to a temporal reinterpretation of attachment, here
especially in the context of the mother–child relationship. Somewhat
reluctantly but with a clear purpose, Riley invokes the notion of a
‘maternal temporality’ (2019, p. 83). Besides this focus on the
maternal, which requires a separate discussion, Riley’s interpretation
brings out how lived time is at the root of sustained affectionate
relatedness to another person. Attachment to another, caring for them,
requires ‘making time’ for the other person, and this is only possible
on condition of an intact capacity to, as it were, give time — in the
sense of devoting a portion of one’s own lifetime to the other. Caring
for someone means, at its practical minimum, to spend one’s own time
with and for the other: giving time — a (ful)filled phase of coexistence that will thereby become the other’s lifetime, while it
thereby also changes one’s own temporal experience from solitarily
spent or ‘endured’ time to shared time. It is clear that not ‘any time’
will do here. Merely going through the motions with another, just
‘hanging in there’, or nervously busying oneself with other things will
not count as giving time in this rich sense. What is required is
attentive, engaged ‘lived’ life time — time that is spent with and for
the other, in which one’s ‘being together’ with the other takes
precedence over one’s own individual matters and manners of engagement. It is what the trivializing lore of our day, but in this case rather
aptly, would designate as ‘quality time’.
Especially in its connection with interpersonal relatedness, this
mode of existential temporality has received little attention on part of
phenomenologists. For instance, Heidegger’s reflections, in Being and
Time (1927), on the original temporality of Dasein as ‘ekstatic’ come
across as a rather solitary affair, although they are likewise built on a
notion of devotional co-temporalizing. That lived time can be ‘ekstatic’, that is, that in temporalizing one is driven ‘out of oneself’ and
towards something worth one’s while, is of course a helpful gloss on
interpersonal co-temporalizing in the sense of giving and sharing time
with another. Yet Heidegger’s account of shared time is a far cry from
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
114
J. SLABY
privileging interpersonal relatedness, as for him there is no privileged
role for the other: anything that might ‘fulfil one’ will do, as long as
one’s commitment to it is deep enough.
Presenting its negative mirror image of fulfilled existential temporality, namely the disrupted temporality of grieving, Riley’s observations bring the temporality of profound interpersonal care into view.
What is thereby brought into relief are two closely connected insights
into the structure of experience. First, that devotional interpersonal
care is a matter of ‘giving’ another time and thus of a co-temporality,
practically enacted, so that lived time becomes essentially shared time.
And second, as evidenced by cases of breakdown, that is, loss of the
loved one, the centrality of this intimately lived co-temporality for the
integrity of the subject’s own temporal perspective, the temporal
coherence of one’s individual outlook on the world and self. This very
temporal coherence of subjective experience gets shattered in and
through parental bereavement. Riley contends that, ‘with the death of
your child, your own experience of time might be especially prone to
disturbance because the lost life had, so to speak, previously unfurled
itself inside your own life’ (2019, pp. 49f.). It is worth quoting from
this passage at some length:
If you had once sensed the time of your child as quietly uncoiling inside
your own, then when that child is cut away by its death, your doubled
inner time is also ‘untimely ripped’. Yours, and the child’s. The
severance of the child’s life makes a cut through your own. You as its
mother can no longer be present to yourself in the old temporal way. A
sculptural imagination rises to grip you; the hollow of the old shelter for
the living child has now been gouged out of you. It was the space of the
child’s past, which used to lie like an inner shell enveloped by your own
time. That child you had, alone, when you were young yourself, a child
you grew up with, nested like a Russian doll whose shorter years sat
within yours, gave you a time that was always layered. Then you held
times, in the plural. (ibid., p. 50)
I have called this a temporal reinterpretation of attachment; one could
also say it outlines the temporality of care, of which the mother’s care
for her child is a pronounced instance. Yet I think the main point
expands to other forms of interpersonal care-giving, especially in
child-rearing contexts. It would be misleading to read Riley’s textual
emphasis on her own position as a grieving mother as a naturalization
of a culturally specific form of motherhood. In fact, it would be more
to the point to read it the other way around: a substantive notion of
care has been culturally realized in a certain conception of the
INTENTIONALITY’S BREAKING POINT
115
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
mother–child relationship; this is compatible with a broad range of
different childcare arrangements across epochs and cultures, and it
allows for people other than biological mothers to assume the position
of caregiver (accordingly, I favour speaking of ‘caregiver’ rather than
‘mother’). The emphasis here lies on the relational and generous
aspect of ‘giving’ — on the endowing and sheltering nature of care, in
the temporally rich sense expounded above, not on a specific concept
of motherhood.6
Riley’s interpretation is not finished with the act of untimely
severance of the two nested temporalities of mother and child. Indeed,
their temporal bond continues after death:
6
Yet after this scooping-out by the death, a fresh incorporation arrives:
the child gets reanimated in your effort to embody its qualities and carry
them onwards. Perhaps this is the peculiar fate of mothers of dead
children: still to contain that other life, and to shelter it twice over. Once
before the child’s birth, and once after the death when you’re left with
an impression of a spirit internalized. (Riley, 2019, pp. 50f.)
Arrested time, time without its flow: that might indeed be construed as
a sharing in the dead’s temporality, a sharing conditioned by care or
love. What used to be a living flow entangled with your own lived
time is now an eternal temporal block, a ruptured flow, a suddenly
frozen ‘past tense’ that continues to be nested within the endogenous
temporality of the grieving parent. In view of this, it indeed rings true
that ‘a part of me has died’, as many a bereaved is prone to exclaim.
We can see what this means in terms of lived time: the other’s life has
abruptly ceased, yet it is still ‘contained’, in its altered condition, as a
salient residue within my own expanded temporal existence. My lived
time, the qualitative, existential time that ‘I am’, and that used to be so
These considerations could be the beginning of a discussion on the status and reach of
Riley’s reflections. While she herself is silent on these matters, one may read her
analysis of the entangled temporalities in the mother–child dyad as an outline of a
feminist existential analytic. This would provide a counter-image to Heidegger’s tacitly
masculinist approach in Being and Time, which seems to be modelled after heroic
individuals bravely facing their own death (modelled, that is, after soldiers fighting at
the front lines, bravely facing death at each instant). It would be problematic to assume
that Heidegger’s approach was universally applicable while blaming Riley’s for cultural
parochialism. Indeed, the interesting meta-thought here is that there is no universality to
be had, not even at the most general ontological level, just culturally specific models of
existence that might be ‘put on offer’ through philosophical elaboration (see Being and
Time, 1927, pp. 266f. and 313–16 for brief passages on methodology where Heidegger
seems to come close to admitting as much).
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
116
7
J. SLABY
thoroughly absorbed in my co-existence with the child, continues to
‘make time’ for the dead child. This highlights again the temporal core
of care as making, giving, and sharing time. The caring still goes on,
the grieving person continues to share their time with the other who
himself has fallen out of that temporal conjunction. No longer alive,
the other has ceased to drive on the flow of jointly lived time, and has
instead turned into a frozen, static element within the joint sphere of
intimate relatedness. This might stand behind the experience of a
ruptured flow, a blockade in one’s sense of temporal unfolding. The
more the bereaved individual tries to ‘stay with’ the lost loved one, in
the sense of continuing to share time with them, the more lived time
might come to a halt.
Riley’s ‘sculptural’ metaphors, even outside the obvious context of
the physicality of birth, seem apt. Such ways of speaking are familiar
from many reports of grief, where those afflicted claim that something
has been ripped from their own flesh, that a part of themselves has
been cut away.7 Riley insists on a sense in which the dead come to reinhabit their old position within the existential temporality of those
left behind: ‘the dead one, although now sheared away from your old
conjoined temporality, now comes to re-inhabit your newly arrested
time vividly, as an incorporated presence’ (Riely, 2019, pp. 82f.).
Thereby, the grieving subject’s lived time appears ‘augmented’ (ibid.,
p. 83), enhanced by a shadowy presence that is sometimes quite
vividly felt.
With these reflections, Riley sketches a way to expand her nested
temporalities account of affectionate attachment into a ‘continued
bonds’ perspective on grief and bereavement (cf. Klass and Steffen,
2018). For as long as the altered condition of lived time endures, this
peculiar temporal fusion between mother and child is ongoing, if in a
form very different from the previous relatedness of the two interwoven but autonomous lifelines.
Yet at some point, even the most intense, most enduring existential
alteration occasioned by bereavement begins to wane. At the end of
her account, about three years after her son’s death, Riley observes her
‘re-entry to a communicable social life and its familiar chronology’.
And as one might expect, this moment arrives with much sadness of
its own, because it marks yet a further separation from the dead: ‘The
Resemblances between the pain of grief and the experience of a phantom limb have
been discussed quite a bit (see, for example, Fuchs, 2018; Ratcliffe, 2019b).
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
INTENTIONALITY’S BREAKING POINT
117
cost of recovering your conventional apprehension of flowing time is
intolerably high. The dead slip away, as we realize that we have
unwillingly left them behind us in their timelessness’ (Riley, 2019, p.
80).
Riley’s contention that ‘the dead slip away’ should not be misunderstood: while it might reflect the experiential sense of losing one’s
formerly firm grip on the dead loved one, this is likely not an all-ornothing affair. There is a more complex story to be told about possibilities of holding onto the dead after the primal experience of altered
temporal flow has subsided. This is the point of commemoration
practices and grieving rituals that aim to re-establish a livable bond
with the dead while acknowledging the loss, and here it might help to
focus attention on the worldliness of intimate co-temporalizing: as
attachment is never to the other person in isolation, but to the other as
co-embedded in a shared lifeworld, the residual relations, contexts,
possessions of the deceased might be harnessed to prevent the slipping
away of the dead to be both total and inevitable. I will come back to
this in Section 5 below. But first, let us venture into the analysis of the
temporal and interpersonal structure of intentionality.
4. How Love Makes It:
Intentionality Reassembled
Some of the perplexity that surrounds the philosophical debates on
intentionality is evoked by the utter simplicity of its predominant
characterization as directedness or aboutness — terms bordering on
lexical malformation. To describe the mind, or a mental state, as
directed to an object is painfully coarse, given that in practice we are
not punctually focused on isolated objects, but engaged episodically or
near continually with broader segments of reality. And the term
‘aboutness’ really doesn’t give us much more than a bad word. We
have to do better in glossing what is meant, as even a merely verbal
starting point orients enquiry and prefigures the questions we ask of a
topic.
In fact, we are in touch with the matters around us by way of
enduring modes of practical engagement, and so whatever acts or
comportments we are picking out for analytical purposes is part of an
expanded sequence of world- and self-relatedness. This more natural
way of construing what is meant by intentionality is different from
simplistic ideas of ‘directedness’ or ‘aboutness’ in virtue of the fact
that it adds a temporal dimension. Instead of hinting at a timeless or
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
118
J. SLABY
instantaneous link between subject and object, as if two snapshots
were conjoined by a mysterious beam or ‘noetic ray’, as Husserl
suggestively called it, what terms such as ‘involvement’, ‘engagement’, ‘coping’, ‘dwelling’, or ‘care’ denote makes sense only if
understood as temporally extended sequences. Abstractly, these terms
denote processes; concretely, they evoke an experienced duration,
qualitative time that unfolds in one’s being (engaged) with some
matter or some person. Accordingly, approaches to intentionality
construed in a way that foregrounds the role of lived time seem
phenomenologically appealing.
In this section, I tentatively assemble elements for a perspective on
intentionality as lived time, an approach that culminates in an attempt
to interpret the substance of Riley’s reflections on grieving and her
notion of a ‘maternal temporality’.
Henri Bergson’s reflections on durée provide a fitting starting point.
According to Bergson (1907/1944), human consciousness is at root
the transpiring of existential temporality — a lived duration — yet it is
near-impossible to apprehend this experiential immediacy of time’s
unfolding as such. In our routine comportment we tend to objectify
lived time by projecting bits of our experience onto items placed
within an external spatial framework. Such engagement with spatially
located ‘things’ taken as individually enduring bits of stuff makes us
gloss over the characteristic experience of durée, at least for the most
part. Lived time is thereby consumed by tangible objects that occupy
our attentive engagement and impose their own temporal order of
linear, objective time. Only on rare occasions — some forms of
leisurely relaxation, certainly boredom, or the dreamy condition
between wakefulness and sleep — will we get a more immediate
sense of the unique ‘melody of duration’, if only fleetingly (see
Schweitzer, 2008). The part of Bergson’s proto-phenomenology of
lived time that is relevant for present purposes is the idea of a dynamic
mutuality between experienced time and the endogenous temporality
of whatever we are currently dealing with. The term ‘attunement’,
later mainly associated with Heidegger as the English translation of
his term-of-art Befindlichkeit, seems to capture this idea well: there is
a dynamic entwinement between lived time and various dimensions of
‘world’ time, where such worldly time is not yet socially imposed
clock time, but so many endogenous temporalities of entities in their
native surroundings (‘everything has its own time’). To use one of
Bergson’s (1907/1944) own examples: waiting for a lump of sugar to
dissolve in a glass of water, we are for a phase of our own time in the
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
INTENTIONALITY’S BREAKING POINT
8
119
thrall of that object’s temporal unfolding. The sugar’s dissolving
imposes a characteristic, if in this case unremarkable, sequence upon
our own temporal awareness. For as long as the process lasts, the
dissolving lump ‘attunes’ us to its own temporality, which, as Bergson
suggestively writes, ‘coincides with my own impatience’ (ibid.).8
More complex examples are provided by Heidegger (1929–30/2008)
in his analysis of boredom: waiting for the train to arrive, we are stuck
with the mind-numbing routines at the village train station (here,
certainly, much determined by schedules and their delays). Absorbed
by such goings-on, ‘our’ time is wrapped up in — and at the mercy of
— that barren place with its monotonous routines (cf. Slaby, 2017).
What this gives us is the idea that intentionality is temporal attunement, a coming to ‘share time’, to resonate with something other than
oneself, in the form of being absorbed and fulfilled or left empty by
whatever happens to ‘be there’. In a situation of waiting, this can be
rendered salient to reflective awareness, sometimes painfully so.
Waiting is a state of suspension occasioned by something we want
or need having not yet materialized. Because of this we are temporarily stalled and thereby brought back upon our own, now conspicuously empty and thus potentially obtrusive, time. What harasses
us in waiting is the very time, as it then may dawn on us, that we
ourselves are: a bit of our lifetime. And this annoyingly conspicuous
time is so exactly because it is ‘empty’ — the absence of what we wait
for, the interval that marks its delayed arrival, reveals the condition
that lived time is usually filled time, time that we in some way or other
spend through our being engaged, busy, occupied, involved. Situations
in which we are bored, nervously seek distractions, are thus limit
cases of intentionality, as a notable emptiness now occupies the place
of a proper temporal ‘something’ — of something that, as we tend to
say on such occasions, would be ‘worth our while’. Thus, crudely put,
our lived time provides a dynamic ‘slot’, so to speak, for intentional
objects to occupy, or rather: to temporalize.
Bergson writes: ‘If I want to mix a glass of sugar and water, I must, willy nilly, wait
until the sugar melts. This little fact is big with meaning. For here the time I have to
wait is not that mathematical time which would apply equally well to the entire history
of the material world, even if that history were spread out instantaneously in space. It
coincides with my impatience, that is to say, with a certain portion of my own duration,
which I cannot protract or contract as I like. It is no longer something thought, it is
something lived’ (Bergson, 1907/1944, pp. 12–13).
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
120
J. SLABY
What is — or, at any rate, should be — always worth our while are
the lives of those we love. This is where the present considerations go,
and it here where they link up with Denise Riley’s reflection on grief’s
conspicuous temporality.
With Bergson and Heidegger we can say that the temporality at the
core of our awareness and engagement amounts to a temporal construal of selfhood: the self coincides with its time — and this means a
temporal entwinement of self-relatedness, endogenous rhythmic or arhythmic sequence, with extant temporalities — those inherent
dynamics of what the self is involved in and engaged with. What
Riley adds, or makes explicit, in her recounting of her experience of
bereavement is the way that parental love is a paradigmatic form of
this temporal entwinement of self with non-self: the attunement
between caregiver and child, self and other, is constitutive not only of
the child’s (or infant’s) own emerging sense of self (this much is a
staple in developmental psychology: think of Daniel Stern’s, 2010,
work on affect attunement in the infant–caregiver dyad), but it is also
constitutive of the caregiver’s own sense of temporal coherence and
self-presence. Parental love, according to Riley, amounts to the enactment of nested temporalities, those of caregiver and child. And this is
not just a matter of corporeal attunement, as if two partners joined to
perform a unique song or melody. Rather, parental love immediately
encompasses historical time, as it relates as much, and as intimately,
to the child’s biographical life: ‘it’s historical time, the times of the
child are contained and sheltered within your own’ (Riley, 2019, p.
81).
What Riley calls ‘maternal temporality’ is a sharing or joining of
historical lifelines, the affectionate incorporation of another’s lifetime
into one’s own sense of time. Riley calls this entwinement of lifetimes
affective history, invoking the double sense of, first, the shared history
of mother and child, and second, the maternal investment in the
child’s own historical existence. Accordingly, it is an expanded,
world-involving sense of time that does not curtail the child’s
independent existence while it is still entwined with it. With this, we
can once more appreciate Riley’s interpretation of her radically altered
sense of time after her son’s death:
This affective history will extend your usual scope of felt time well
beyond your own skin. In the past you had sensed your living child’s
time, including the physically interior time of its gestation as well as its
early growing and independent life, as if it were internal to your own.
You had aged in tandem with it. But now the time of the vanished child
INTENTIONALITY’S BREAKING POINT
121
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
has been cut away from your impression of your interior time. As I’d
noted, it’s as if, from a set of nested Russian wooden dolls, the innermost one’s had fallen out. (ibid., p. 82)
I read this as an expanded explication of the temporality of care, as a
paradigmatic articulation of the entwinement of two temporal beings.
Parental love is dedicated co-temporalizing with the child. This process not only endows the child with a temporal sense of self anchoring
their own composed perspective on the world, but it also reconfigures
the caregiver’s own temporal existence, providing coherence and
fulfilment: relatedness towards meaningful matters whose significance
comes about only in so far as it is jointly lived through in a shared
sequence of being-together. What is called for, in the light of these
considerations, is a more detailed development of a conception of
affective intentionality as essentially temporal and as essentially intersubjective. This will help the present debate on the nature of intentionality catch up with the important considerations by Emmanuel
Levinas (1961/1969). He attempted to derive an account of the conditions of intentionality from an ethics of alterity, thereby reversing
the philosophical order of priority between the practical/ethical and
the theoretical. Riley’s considerations on grief invoke a similar
reversal of priorities in the personal sphere of motherhood or parenthood: it is the child that crucially partakes in providing and sustaining
the experiential coherence of the caregiver’s perspective, the child’s
initially tenuous, fleeting, unstable temporal perspective joins a
temporal entre-deux from which both the parent’s and the child’s
mature experiential capacities emerge. Obviously, these hints towards
what might revive a rigorously interpersonal existential analytic can
only be a starting point for what has to become a much more thorough
investigation.
5. Relearning to Be Alone
Riley’s account of her grief is, among much else, also meant to provide an alternative to the familiar discussions of grief focused on grief
work, readjustment, and recovery, of ‘getting back on track’ or
‘moving on’. Likewise, it is not interested in putative ‘stages of grief’
and the like. However, to connect with somewhat more copingoriented approaches, it makes sense to consider work that focuses on
the practices, rituals, and discursive elaborations that attempt to render
grief livable, while steering clear of the facile tropes of self-help
literature. Riley, for her part, flips the social world’s directive that
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
122
J. SLABY
‘you should be moving on’ into an idea of continued companionship:
‘If there is ever to be any movement again, that moving will not be
“on”. It will be “with”. With the carried-again child’ (2019, p. 42).
Within the recent philosophical work on grief, there are approaches
that try to outline complex perspectives on the continued bonds idea. I
single out one such account that I find particularly helpful. It is by
Line Ingerslev, and revolves around the following proposal: ‘grief can
be understood as an open-ended rehearsal of our capacity to be alone
in the company of an absent other’ (Ingerslev, 2018, p. 343).9 Among
the many ideas this single phrase crystallizes, three deserve particular
attention in the context of the present discussion. First, Ingerslev
considers grief to be an existential crisis in so far as the death of
another puts the subject radically in question, in an existential or
vocational sense: ‘a mode of existing while not knowing how to go
on.’ In this manner, the experience pushes the individual to the limit
of their responsiveness, occasioning a profound existential reorientation. Second, Ingerslev invokes the ‘capacity to be alone’ as discussed
in some currents of psychoanalytic thought, for instance by Donald
Winnicott (1958). And third, that this capacity has to be calibrated
anew in relation to the now absent other. Especially this last aspect, if
properly developed, distinguishes Ingerslev’s proposal from an individualistic orientation towards coping and adjustment. The deceased
remains in the picture, as an active pole of affective relatedness and as
the ongoing source of ethical and existential demands. The absent
other is at the centre of the process of grieving both practically and
normatively. But let us unpack these three aspects successively.
That a loved one’s death, as responded to by grief, amounts to an
existential crisis is not in question. Yet in terms of understanding the
actual unfolding of grieving it helps to get at the exceptional,
unresolvable, catastrophic, and often utterly incoherent character of
this mode of emotional comportment:
[T]he vocational aspect involved in grief is not one that you master, it
makes the death of the other the active voice in grief while not allowing
9
I chose Ingerslev’s account not only because it is so generally convincing but because it
fits so well to the specific considerations on the temporality of attachment offered here.
I also learned a lot from Sonja Rinofner-Kreidl’s careful considerations on grief’s
ambiguous nature, and especially from her comprehensive rebuttal of coping-oriented
approaches to ‘overcoming grief’ (see Rinofner-Kreidl, 2016, especially pp. 191–202).
Fuchs (2018) likewise develops a noteworthy perspective on the gradual reorganization
of the bereaved’s identity in relation to the lost loved one.
INTENTIONALITY’S BREAKING POINT
123
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
you to find neither words nor narratives and while fundamentally not
allowing me to enter into a meaningful future. (Ingerslev, 2018, p. 353)
10
Ingerslev is adamant that grief cannot well be captured by narrative
accounts of emotion, as narrative evokes and requires too much in the
way of coherence, sequence, emplotment, and that it presupposes an
auctorial perspective that is usually more resolved and collected than
anyone will likely be in the throes of acute grief. At best, she holds,
narrative gets a foothold towards the end of the grieving process,
when the chaos and incomprehension of the condition have by and
large given way to more composed modes of comportment.10
The second important aspect in Ingerslev’s ‘grief formula’ is her
invocation of the capacity to be alone. The background to this is a
psychoanalytic understanding of childhood emotional development.
The point is that a child’s capacity to be alone, understood as a stage
in emotional maturation, is a relational capacity that is both developed
and mainly exercised in relation to a primary caregiver. I spare us the
details of the classic psychoanalytic account (reductive and sexist as
they are) and only state the upshot: the capacity to be alone depends
on an ‘internalized’ relation to a caregiver, whose sheltering presence
continues to affectively imbue the child’s comportment in the physical
absence of that significant other. In the context of the interpersonal
constitution of intentionality, this capacity can be glossed as a selfsustained comportment, a sufficiently oriented and coherent self-pole
in the self–world dynamic. It is a capacity for ongoing engagement
with the world in the absence of the stability-providing, calm- and
coherence-enabling caregiver, whose lived temporality had initially
scaffolded the child’s. In effect, it is about ‘finding one’s flow’ amidst
the dynamics of the surrounding world: one’s own rhythm of awareness and engagement as it develops out of the initially shared
synchronicity with the caregiver. This capacity to be alone has to be
learned during early childhood, and in the case of death of the caregiver (or death of whomever had occupied a position of comparable
affectionate attachment later in life), its mature iteration will have to
be relearned, reconstituted, often painstakingly — a process that will
encompass a retrieval of that original joint sense-making capacity that
has been lost with the death of the other. But it is more than that. At
any rate, this is what Ingerslev means by her idea of ‘rehearsal’: the
Like Ratcliffe (2017), Ingerslev devotes a lot of space to a critique of Peter Goldie’s
(2012) narrative approach to grief.
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
124
J. SLABY
capacity to be alone is practised — rehearsed — as a form of
attempted togetherness with the deceased other. This is what grief
work, on Ingerslev’s account, mainly consists in. This fits quite well to
what was developed so far: intentionality as scaffolded through an
intimate caring relationship, where the capacity to individually and
autonomously engage with world and self, in the manner of an
integrated orientation in and to the world, is derivative, both
structurally and developmentally, from a primary mode of togetherness, of a span of time — an affectively imbued duration or ‘lived
time’ — jointly lived through with another.
What is particularly interesting is how the relationship to the absent
other figures in this process of relearning:
In our rehearsal of being alone, the other is neither animated, internalized nor brought back to life by certain rituals or objects. Rather, the
mode of relatedness can be understood as a form of lived dedication or
evocation. (Ingerslev, 2018, p. 356)
Evocation and dedication are ways in which the survivor’s life
remains oriented towards the deceased in projecting a newfound
future. One could say that it is about continuing ‘the legacy’ of the
deceased, which might take many different forms. One could also say,
as Ingerslev does, that this orientation to the absent other is the form
that love takes when the loved one no longer dwells among the living:
‘grief as a work of love’ (ibid., p. 358).11 It is a form of ongoing care
in the sense of continuing to heed the other’s demands, respond to the
other’s concerns. Love, as long as it holds, is open-ended, in fact,
infinite — which belies accounts that construe unresolved, ongoing
grieving as pathological. It might be a triviality that grieving for loved
ones can be a continuation of love, but it is a triviality that is often
forgotten, glossed over, misconstrued, and certainly fallen short of in
practice. It is fitting that Ingerslev at this point also invokes Denise
Riley:
What Riley described… as the arrested flow of time can equally be
understood as an ongoing repetition of remembering one dead, however
only if we accept that in grieving as an ongoing activity we can find a
way of not moving ‘on’, but moving ‘with’ the absent other. (Ingerslev,
2018, p. 357)
11
As Michael Cholbi (2021) has convincingly argued, not all forms of grief presuppose a
loving relation to another person.
INTENTIONALITY’S BREAKING POINT
125
This ‘moving with’ the absent other, the continuing affectionate bond
that grounds it and, in particular, the temporality of these interpersonal
entwinements, helps us to better understand human world- and selfrelatedness as an essentially interpersonal engagement. If it is true that
profound grief might break intentionality, as we have seen it does, this
is so on the grounds that the affectionate interpersonal bond at its base
had enabled human-level intentionality in the first place: if grief can
break it, love has made it.
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
6. Conclusion and Outlook
The aim of this paper was to begin an exploration of the interpersonal
conditions of intentionality by starting from the marked breakdown of
world-relatedness in parental grief. The main point was to take Denise
Riley’s observations of arrested temporal flow that she experienced
when grieving her son as a basis for probing into the possibility that
human intentionality might depend in part, both constitutively and
developmentally, on interpersonally shared temporality. While the
considerations offered on this highly complex theme had to remain
provisional and sketchy, they have connected the phenomenology of
bereavement with the long-standing philosophical endeavour of
analysing the conceptual foundations of the mind’s capacity to relate
to the world. In particular, the line of thought that I took from Riley’s
book has inspired a partial transformation of phenomenological considerations on the role of temporality as a condition of experience, by
suggesting that intimate interpersonal relatedness is more fundamental
to the temporal coherence of experience than the groundworks of
Bergson, Husserl, and Heidegger suggest.
By making time for the child, the caregiver establishes and upholds
a jointly lived temporality that contributes to the temporal coherence
of both the child’s and the parent’s experiential perspectives,
rendering them mutually dependent. Thus, devotional care, in the
sense of ‘giving’ one’s time to and sharing it with a loved one, is
among the enabling conditions of intentionality. With this result —
that is more reflective of insights by Emmanuel Levinas than of those
by the founding fathers of phenomenology — the analysis offered
here confirms and reinvigorates John Haugeland’s rendering of the
upshot of his interpretation of Heidegger on intentionality, namely that
‘love is the mark of the human’ (Haugeland, 1998, p. 2). While
Haugeland arrived at this by way of considerations that do not give
pride of place to intimate interpersonal relations, his choice of the
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
126
J. SLABY
term ‘love’ for what Heidegger calls authentic care or resoluteness
seems all the more convincing in the light of the reflections offered
here. Haugeland’s settling on ‘love’ as a designator for original
intentionality, a term he tellingly places alongside ‘faith’ as another
conceptual option, is supposed to emphasize the existential depth of
commitment — a devotional mode of staking oneself unreservedly on
an endeavour or project that will thereby come to define, condition,
and orient one’s life, so that failing at that endeavour, or losing one’s
grip on it, would threaten to undermine or even bring to an end one’s
personal existence and the whole framework of intelligibility it rests
on (indeed, this would be a kind of ‘death’, see Rouse, 2017).
If considered alongside Riley’s reflections on the temporality of
attachment between mother and child, one’s inchoate sense that there
is something amiss with Haugeland’s proposal finds a clearer articulation. While Haugeland follows Heidegger in an essentially individualistic construal of existential commitment, Riley’s account suggests a
profoundly interpersonal perspective on the foundational dimension of
human experience. What Riley reluctantly calls a ‘maternal temporality’ could thus anchor a robust alternative to the influential account
of authentic Dasein as individual being-towards-death. Not so much
one’s own looming death provides the orienting horizon for a devoted
existence enabled by authentic care, but the potential death of — or
profound peril suffered by — a significant other, notably one’s child.
I hope this article has succeeded in showing that a resolutely interpersonal existential analytic and its integration with contemporary
consciousness studies is an endeavour worth pursuing further.
Acknowledgments
I thank Fabian Bernhardt, Laura Candiotto, Millicent Churcher, Carol
A. Kidron, Matthew Ratcliffe, and two anonymous reviewers for a
host of helpful comments and suggestions in response to earlier
versions of this paper.
References
Bergson, H. (1907/1944) Creative Evolution, Mitchell, A. (trans.), New York:
Random House.
Cholbi, M. (2021) Grieving our way back to meaningfulness, Royal Institute of
Philosophy Supplement, 90, pp. 235–251.
Fuchs, T. (2018) Presence in absence: The ambiguous phenomenology of grief,
Phenomenology and Cognitive Science, 17, pp. 43–63.
Goldie, P. (2012) The Mess Inside: Narrative, Emotion, & the Mind, Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic
For personal use only -- not for reproduction
INTENTIONALITY’S BREAKING POINT
127
Haugeland, J. (1998) Having Thought: Essays in the Metaphysics of Mind,
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Heidegger, M. (1929–30/2008) Die Grundbegriffe der Metaphysik. Welt,
Endlichkeit, Einsamkeit, Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann. (English translation
(2008) The Fundamental Concepts of Metaphysics: World — Finitude —
Solitude, McNeill, W. & Walker, N. (trans.), Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.)
Heidegger, M. (1927) Sein und Zeit, Tübingen: Max Niemeyer.
Ingerslev, L. (2018) Ongoing: On grief’s open-ended rehearsal, Continental
Philosophy Review, 51, pp. 343–360.
Klass, D. & Steffen, E.M. (2018) Continuing Bonds in Bereavement: New
Directions for Research and Practice, London: Routledge.
Krueger, J. (2011) Extended cognition and the space of social interaction,
Consciousness and Cognition, 20 (3), pp. 643–657.
Levinas, E. (1961/1969) Totality and Infinity: An Essay on Exteriority, Lingis, A.
(trans.), Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press.
Lewis, C.S. (1966) A Grief Observed, London: Faber & Faber.
Ratcliffe, M.J. (2008) Feelings of Being: Phenomenology, Psychiatry and the
Sense of Reality, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Ratcliffe, M.J. (2017) Grief and the unity of emotion, Midwest Studies in
Philosophy, 41, pp. 154–174.
Ratcliffe, M.J. (2019a) Towards a phenomenology of grief: Insights from MerleauPonty, European Journal of Philosophy, 28 (3), pp. 657–669.
Ratcliffe, M.J. (2019b) Grief and phantom limbs: A phenomenological comparison, in Hopkins, B. & Crowell, S. (eds.) The New Yearbook for Phenomenology
and Phenomenological Philosophy, vol. 4, New York: Routledge.
Rinofner-Kreidl, S. (2016) On grief’s ambiguous nature, Quaestiones Disputatae,
7 (1), pp. 178–207.
Riley, D. (2019) Time Lived, Without its Flow, London: Picador.
Rouse, J. (2017) Love and death, in Adams, Z. & Browning, J. (eds.) Giving a
Damn: John Haugeland’s Philosophy, pp. 131–157, Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press.
Schweizer, H. (2008) On Waiting (Thinking in Action Series), London: Routledge.
Slaby, J. (2017). Living in the moment: Boredom and the meaning of existence in
Heidegger and Pessoa, in Feger, H., Dikun, X. & Ge, W. (eds.) Yearbook for
Eastern and Western Philosophy, vol. 2, pp. 235–256, Berlin/New York: de
Gruyter.
Stern, D.N. (2010) Forms of Vitality: Exploring Dynamic Experience in
Psychology, the Arts, Psychotherapy, and Development, New York: Oxford
University Press.
Winnicott, D.W. (1958) The capacity to be alone, International Journal of
Psychoanalysis, 39, pp. 416–420.